Seifert1 20
Seifert1 20
Seifert1 20
Josef Seifert
Translated by Oliver Heydorn
Ten years after writing the Logical Investigations, Edmund Husserl, in his famous
and sole Logos essay, 1 defended the thesis that philosophy ought to be a
‘rigorous science’ and described this goal of philosophy as an “ideal” that ‘has
never been completely abandoned,’ but also as an ideal that has never been even
roughly or partially realized. Husserl considers it as evidently tragic that up until
now philosophy has never lived up to this claim.2 In this regard, Husserl asserts it
is not only philosophy, which is not, yet a perfect or complete science. He rightly
emphasizes this is also true for all the so-called exacts sciences, since they are
Dr. JOSEF SEIFERT, Professor, International Academy of Philosophy Spain–Instituto de
Filosofía Edith Stein Granada, Spain. Email: jseifert@iap.li.
1
This first essay (which was disregarded by some reviews and a short encyclopedic
contribution) that Edmund Husserl, the founder of the phenomenological movement, had
published after the drafting of the Logical Investigations (1900/01), was called
“Philosophy as a Rigorous Science” and appeared in 1911 in the first volume (H 3) of
Logos (Logos I, 1911, S. 289-341), in whose publication Husserl was involved as Henrich
Rickert had promised. Cf. Edmund Husserl, Aufsätze und Vorträge (1911-1921), Editors
Thomas Nenon and Hans Rainer Sepp, Husserliana Volume XXV
(Dordrecht/Boston/Lancaster: M. Hijhoff, 1987), p. 3-62. The essay was drafted between
December 1910 and January 1911, revised in February and appeared in March 1911.
Husserl considered it as a general exposition of his views in a popular style.
2
Ibid., p. 4: So philosophy in its historical disregard for the highest and most rigorous of
sciences, which supports the inevitable claim of mankind to a pure and absolute
knowledge … does not manage to form a real science.
also imperfect and incomplete. Rather, he wants to claim that philosophy has
never even begun to be a science such that it would follow no dogmatic system in
which ‘all things and each thing in particular are controversial’, and is nothing
more than the product of mere individual prejudices and perspectives.3 Now
Husserl claims that philosophy, for the very first time, ought to fulfill this ideal
and become a rigorous science.
In looking at Husserl’s analysis and considering the reasons behind his
devastatingly harsh judgement of the entire history of philosophy (excluding his
apparently less than modest claim that for the first time in the whole history of
philosophy someone has wanted to make philosophy a strict science) one thing in
particular stands out. It is that several of Husserl’s fundamental claims are
sometimes acknowledged as presuppositions, while at other times they are more
implicitly assumed. Some could be defended while others could not be expressly
put forward let alone defended, and as well, others could be easily confused with
one another. Let us consider, in detail, the theses Husserl presupposes and asserts.
In the first place, Husserl openly presupposes that a scientific philosophy must be
preferred over any system, that it not be controversial, and that it possess a broad,
virtually universal consensus, as is the case in physics or mathematics. Secondly,
he emphasizes that it cannot be any kind of ‘Weltanschauung Philosophie’, by
which term he understands at least two radically different things. On the one hand,
a scientific philosophy, which he sharply contrasts with a ‘Weltanschauung
Philosophie’, may not attempt to answer the important questions of metaphysics;
above all it may not claim that it has access to those things that exist in
themselves as they are in themselves or, in particular, to the really existing
world.4 Every transcendent act of cognition that grasps an essence that rules over
3
Ibid., p. 5 also Cf. ibid., p. 53, 55 Cf. the similar explanation of Husserl in “Pure
Phenomenology, its Field of Research and its Methods (Introductory Talk in Freiburg)”,
in: Edmund Husserl, Aufsätze und Vorträge (1911-1921), Editors Thomas Nenon and Hans
Rainer Sepp, Husserliana Volume XXV (Dordrecht/Boston/Lancaster: M. Nijhoff, 1987),
p. 68-81, p. 69.
4
Husserl speaks in a similar sense in “Phenomenology and Psychology”, in: Edmund
Husserl, Aufsätze und Vorträge (1911-1921), Editors Thomas Nenon and Hans Rainer
Sepp, Husserliana Volume XXV (Dordrecht/Boston/Lancaster: M. Nijhoff, 1987), p.
82-124, especially p. 83, where the bracketing of “the naïve belief in the world” and of
“the real existence of the given things” is required from philosophy.
the existing world, as well as every cognition of the real world, lies beyond the
reach of scientific philosophical knowledge. As a result, a rigorously scientific
philosophy must remain expressly within the realm of consciousness, its
intentional acts and its corresponding purely intentional objects, in order for it to
be a rigorous science.5 In addition, a scientific philosophy ought not to entertain
any of the most fundamental and deepest problems, as every metaphysical
question is supposed to lie beyond its competency. 6 On the other hand,
philosophy ought not to find its origin in a mere Weltanschauung or in a religious
faith. This is the case with every kind of fideistic philosophy, which attempts to
answer the most fundamental questions, and in so doing takes as its basis the
personal opinion of a Weltanschauung philosophen. The results in answers, which
5
So writes Husserl in the essay “Philosophy as a Rigorous Science”, in: Edmund Husserl,
Aufsätze und Vorträge (1911-1921), Editors Thomas Nenon and Hans Rainer Sepp,
Husserliana Volume XXV (Dordrecht/Boston/Lancaster: M. Nijhoff, 1987), p. 3-62, p.15:
Whenever a theory of knowledge would nonetheless like to investigate the relation
between consciousness and being, then it can only have being as the correlate of
consciousness as a consciously conditioned “meaning”: as perceptions, remembrances,
expectations, pictured images … etc. Cf. also the clear capturing of this position in “Pure
Phenomenology, its Field of Research and its Methods (Introductory Talk in Freiburg)”,
in: Edmund Husserl, Aufsätze und Vorträge (1911-1921), Editors Thomas Nenon and Hans
Rainer Sepp, Husserliana Volume XXV (Dordrecht/Boston/Lancaster: M. Nijhoff,
1987)p. 68-81, p. 72-75, where phenomenology is characterized as a “science of
consciousness as such” and above all where all objects that are foreign to consciousness
(transcendent) objects are excluded from the domain of phenomenological philosophy. On
this cf. also, Josef Seifert, “Critique of Relativism and Immanentism in E. Husserl’s
Cartesian Meditations. The Equivocation in the Expression ‘Transcendental Ego’ as the
Baisis of Every Transcendental Idealism.” – “Kritik am Relativismus und Immanentismus
in E. Husserls Cartesian Meditations. Die Aequivokationen im Ausdruck, transcendentales
Ego’ an der Basis jedes transzendentalen Idealismus.” Salzburger Jahrbuch für
Philosophie XIV, 1970.
6
Ibid., p. 59, where Husserl demands: “…that philosophy takes on the form and
language of a genuine science and recognizes as incompleteness that which in it is often
praised and is quite imitated – depth. Depth is a sign of Chaos, that genuine science wants
to transform in a cosmos, in a simple, fully clear, dissolved order. Genuine science knows,
as far as its real doctrines reach, no depth … depth belongs to essence…”
only have appeal for this or that particular personality. Such a Weltanschauung
Philosophie ought never – in spite of its undisputed value according to Husserl –
to confuse people by appearing to be a science. 7 Genuine science and a
rigorously scientific philosophy must especially not assume anything as a given,
must not validate anything handed down as a starting point, and must not allow us
to be blinded by influential authorities. 8 Behind this stands the unspoken, but in
itself the most important thought of Husserl concerning philosophy as a rigorous
science. In other words, philosophy can only be a science if it does not concern
itself with mere personal opinions. Instead, it should deal with the objective
knowledge of truth and the attainment of the appropriate evidence, as well as if it
seeks a systematic construction based on principles and an inner, logical order of
knowledge. Philosophy in the strict sense must be a “science from its very
beginnings, from the origin” “of all things (pantón rhematón)”.9
Husserl rightly ascertained to achieve this goal (that is in order to arrive at an
objective, evident and from the beginning progressive knowledge) philosophy
must first fight against the kind of naturalism and psychologism, which led him in
his Logical Investigations to the castigation of that relativism and reductionism,
that completely falsify the object and knowledge of philosophy. Since necessarily,
a scientific philosophy is only possible through a return to the ‘Things
Themselves’, it must further overcome Dilthey’s historicism, which makes it
particularly impossible to return to the things and problems themselves by
insisting one be held captive by historical understandings and feel oneself into
past epochs. We are in such perfect agreement concerning this last and third point,
namely that a strict scientific philosophy can be differentiated from theology and
from every system which springs from some Weltanschauungs belief, that we
cannot fail to credit Husserl with being right with respect to the first two theses.
For this reason, I would like to turn towards the establishment of a new
foundation, which will partially constitute a sharp critique of Husserl’s view. In so
doing, I ought to present him as Socrates says in the Phaedo with a veiled face.
Although I do not consider Husserl to be a god, before whom a Socrates must veil
7
Edmund Husserl, “Philosophie als Strenge Wissenschaft”, in Edmund Husserl, Aufsätze
und Vorträge (1911-1921), Editors Thomas Nenon and Hans Rainer Sepp, Husserliana
Volume XXV (Dordrecht/Boston/Lancaster: M. Nijhoff, 1987), p. 3-62, ibid., p. 58ff.
8
Ibid., p. 60.
9
Ibid., p. 61.
his face,10 I am so indebted to him (as is philosophy) that the sharp critique,
which I think necessary, makes me feel ashamed. Nevertheless, for the sake of
truth, I feel a duty to develop such a critique. I present the following claims to
evidence:
1) The first of the four named presuppositions, namely that philosophy has
not yet begun to be a strict science, because “all things and each thing in it is
controversial”,11 is highly doubtful. It springs from a thoughtless application of
the conditions of natural science to those of philosophy, an application that is
taken by Husserl to be self-evident but is in truth an untenable position. Not only,
therefore, must we refuse to give our assent to Husserl’s first thesis, as it is
obviously illusionary to assume the perfection of a philosophy should always be
judged by whether or not it can secure the universal consensus of all philosophers.
Rather, we hold that each consensus that in the natural sciences leads unavoidably
to objective scientific knowledge can, in philosophy, since it requires a particular
talent and philosophical vision, as well as countless further presuppositions in
order to achieve evident knowledge. In whose way obstacles such as sophisms of
all kinds as well as sins against the spirit stand, in no way be interpreted as a
necessary consequence of evident knowledge. It is, therefore, by no means true
that in philosophy a greater or almost universal consensus is a condition of its
scientific character. How is it that Husserl’s own lucid refutation of psychologism
and of that more fundamental relativism and skepticism in the Prolegomena of
the Logical Investigations be considered unscientific? Is it only because not all of
his colleagues shared Husserl’s results? And while one may want to find a partial
ground in a certain incompleteness of Husserl’s analysis for the lack of such a
consensus, the objection is nonetheless valid: even the evident and most lucid
examples of scientific philosophical knowledge has not once produced in
philosophical logic, let alone in ethics, a universal consensus. In fact, even if an
all-knowing and divine version of philosophical science ̶ in its pure and evident
ideal structures ̶ were lucidly explained, it too, without a doubt, would be produce
all kinds of controversies. The claimed and at first glance certainly peculiarly
appearing unrealisability of universal consensus in philosophy has very plausible
grounds that Husserl not once raises let alone refutes. Of course will we, we who
10
Socrates veiled himself before the god Eros, when he relates a speech that another had
written against love.
11
Ibid., p. 5.
claim that a “pure philosophical science” does not require universal consensus,
have to find a new foundation and be able to explain how an evident and
systematically built up scientific knowledge is possible without being able to
have a universal or even a broad consensus12. We will return to this point later.
2) Husserl’s second thesis condemns his own objective position that he held
in the Prolegomena to his Logical Investigations. There he had described the
logical objects of cognition as being equally valid for men, angels, and gods. With
the diametrically opposed claim that a scientific philosophy may only deal with
the noemata of consciousness, Husserl rejects his former objectivism and turns
toward transcendental phenomenology. Accordingly, a rigorously scientific
philosophy may not deal with the existing world, but rather, may only handle pure
essences, and not their being or validity in themselves. Consideration is given to
the noemata of intentional acts as pure and immanent objects of consciousness.
We will hope to show that this position proves itself false for a number of reasons,
and even as the very dissolution of the specifically scientific character of
philosophy. Scientific philosophy can and must reach both the existing world as
well as the recognition of those fully transcendent and for each being decisively
important necessary essences in order to be a rigorous science.
3) The third Husserlian presupposition is in itself unclear and is only in one
of its meanings justified, namely that philosophy may accept no presuppositions
based on faith; in this respect I am in complete agreement. Although I cannot
develop this further in the present context, it neither follows, as Husserl was later
to hold, that all faith-claims are incapable of being rationally grounded.
Additionally, there can be no rigorous science, in a theological sense, which
would take its starting point in rational faith, which could then be systematically
developed and grounded by reason.
4) The fourth thesis, which Husserl defends, is that philosophy must attain to
an evident knowledge that is free of preconceived notions and that it must reject
12
Cf. my extensive defense of this point of view in: Josef Seifert, “Zur Begründung
ethischer Normen. Einwände auf Edgar Morschers Position. Ein Diskussionsbeitrag”; also
cf. “Und dennoch: Ethik ist Episteme, nicht blosse Doxa. Ueber die wissenschaftliche
Begrünbarkeit und Ueberprüfbarkeit ethischer Sätze und Normen. Erwiderung auf Edgar
Morscher’s Antwort” in: Vom Wahren und vom Guten, Festschrift zum achtzigsten
Geburtstag von Balduin Schwarz. (Salzburg: St. Peter Verlag, 1983), Editors, Edgar
Morscher, Josef Seifert and Fritz Wenisch.
every historicism and psychological naturalism; this thesis will also by defended
by us. Husserl, through his critique of psychologism and historicism, has
undoubtedly contributed in a very essential way to the fulfillment of philosophy
as a science in this sense. So impressive and correct is the ideal of an evident,
critical, analytical and preconception-free knowledge which Husserl places before
us, and yet in terms of his own explanation and grounding of this claim
concerning philosophy as a rigorous science, it becomes impossible to really
make or to show how philosophy can be a “pure science.” This is rather only
possible through a renewed extraction and continuation of many classical and
preceding insights (including those of Husserl’s Logical Investigations). It is the
task of realistic phenomenology to provide a new foundation and to enlarge this
classical philosophy. By means of this new foundation for the rigorously
scientific character of genuine philosophy, realistic phenomenology managed to
free it from Husserl’s basic errors concerning philosophical methodology. Freed,
in particular, from his immanentism and his pure essentialism,13 which betray his
own principle of a ‘conditionless’ return to the things themselves.
Before Husserl, Kant was also occupied with the question of the scientific
character of philosophy. He formulated an additional thesis as a condition of this
‘scientific-ness’: that philosophy or metaphysics can only appear as a science
when it is capable of grounding synthetic a priori propositions. Philosophy and
logic, as well as mathematics, pure physics, etc., as a priori sciences, were
contrasted by both Husserl and Kant with the empirical and experimental sciences.
The kind of knowledge, which we are calling ‘a priori’, allows itself to be
characterized in general by two marks: strict necessity and apodictic certainty 14.
13
On this cf. Edmund Husserl, “Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft”, cit., p. 26, p. 36,
where Husserl says that as a science a pure phenomenology can only be “of essential
research and not existential research at all”; cf. also ibid., 41, where the a priori character is
emphasized, as on p. 62.
14
Under apodictic certainty I understand here an indubitable “absolute” certainty, that
Bonaventure – in an objective and adequate description – also calls ‘infallible certainty’,
Neither of these marks is present in the essential features of a lion, the knowledge
of such facts having to be obtained by biology through observation. With Kant
(and with Husserl), we must add another note to the two marks of philosophical a
priori knowledge: necessity and apodictic certainty. Instead of the probability of
the general forms of empirical knowledge – namely, the note that it has a content
that goes beyond what is contained in mere definitions or tautological formulas
such as “all old men are old”, or “every cause produces an effect”. For the
necessary truth ‘All triangles are triangular’, or ‘All old men are old’ is surely
characterized as well by the two aforementioned marks, but their predicates
follow solely because of the principles of identity and contradiction, simply out of
the definition of the subjects. These truths are most certainly necessary, but empty.
They tell us nothing new in that only general and formal ontological and logical
basic principles, such as that everything is itself (the principle of identity) and
nothing can both be itself and not be itself (the principle of contradiction).
Additionally, the logical laws, which follow from this with respect to the truth
and falsehood of propositions, as applied in a particular case, or better put, the
predicate only claims what was already contained per definitionem in the concept
of the subject.15
Since Kant, these propositions are seen as analytical judgements. The
proposition “Every effect has a cause” tells us nothing new in its predicate: for
“effect” is already defined as a definite result of a cause. Quite different is the
case of those informative propositions, which express something new and are
characterized by necessity and apodictic certainty: “Every change and every
non-necessary being requires an effective cause.” This so-called principle of
causality is in no way tautological or analytic. The predicate of this proposition
adds something new to the subject ‘Every change and every contingent being’.
Kant refers to such a proposition therefore, as synthetic. All of those judgements,
the truths of which are only knowable through empirical observation, are
synthetic. We only need then experience and perception in order to achieve
knowledge of them. Whenever I say something such as that lions in contrast to
hyenas first kill their prey before consuming it, the proposition is synthetic.
and which justifies the positing of the absolutely maintained apodictic judgement in the
logical sense.
15
Cf. for a deeper discussion of this question and for the justification of the fact that this
formulation is not sufficiently precise, Fritz Wenisch, (1988) and J. Seifert (1976, II. Teil).
While there are many propositions of this type, that is, propositions which
can be verified or falsified only through experiments or single observations; in the
same way there are also other amazing propositions, which are synthetic. They
are neither justified through empirical observations, nor do they lack absolute
necessity and apodictic certainty. There appears to be such legitimate and by no
means arbitrary apodictic claims concerning axioms, principles, and other general
states of affairs. Only if such propositions exist can philosophy be grounded as
the rigorous science that Kant emphasized. In keeping with Kant, the question
concerning the rigorously scientific character of philosophy can first be identified
with the question concerning the possibility of synthetic a priori propositions.
How can we know, for example, that every change requires a cause? If
philosophy is supposed to be both possible and justifiable, this kind of
proposition, which can be found in both mathematics and philosophy, must be
capable of being grounded. The problem of the so-called synthetic a priori
knowledge, with whose help we understand for example the Pythagorean theorem,
has belonged since Plato’s dialogue Meno, where the problem of the possibility of
a priori knowledge is first to be formulated, to the most fascinating of all
philosophical problems. How can we explain general knowledge claims that tell
us something new, and which are not dependent on empirical experience but are
rather distinguished through apodictic certainty and necessity? This fundamental
question of Kant, “how are synthetic a priori judgements possible?” is also
fundamental question of philosophy and of phenomenological realism in
particular. The question is simple and yet terribly difficult to answer. How can
one derive from the given temporal objects something timeless? Does it come
from the experience of contingently existing objects’ necessary and unchanging
states of affairs, from uncertain and non-evident sensory perceptions apodictically
certain and evident states of affairs, or from the experience of imperfection
something perfect?
Plato had thought that such a knowledge could only be accounted for in
relation to the eternal ideas, which the soul must have beheld before its birth. St.
Augustine thought that such an astonishing form of knowledge could only be
explained through an immediate divine illumination. This insight would permit us
to have a cognitive share in the eternal and divine ideas. Descartes tried to ground
the same kind of knowledge in innate ideas and Leibniz assumed as an
explanation that God had established a harmony between subjectively held ideas
and the objective nature of things. The first modern philosopher who wishes to do
16
Rudolf Lüthe, 12th of May, 1992 in Schaan (Liechtenstein).
Firstly, the kind of necessity which characterizes the states of affairs in the
Pythagorean Theorem or in the principle of causality, is not just any kind of
necessity. It is rather a necessity of a very particular kind, one whose peculiarity
does not allow us to reduce it to anything else. This necessity is not a mere
linguistic convention, nor a mere language game; it is also not a necessity of
having to think in a certain way. There is no subjective necessity that renders it
impossible, for example, to think differently than in accordance with the principle
17
Cf. Adolf Reinach, “Über Phänomenologie”, p. 531-550. Max Scheler (1966, p. 71, 175).
Cf. further Dietrich von Hildebrand (1991); Josef Seifert (1987).
of causality. We can argue for this based on the facts of experience by pointing
out that there is no necessity of thought here because we can in fact deny it. The
necessity which the philosopher and mathematician investigates lies rather in the
things themselves, it has the character of having to be in a certain way and not
being able to be in a different way. In addition, this a priori necessity is the same
whether men, angels, or gods think about them, as Husserl said. This insight,
which was obtained particularly through Husserl, Reinach, Scheler, and
Hildebrand, that a priori knowledge does not distinguish itself by means of a mere
necessity of thought, as Kant and psychologism held, but rather through an
objective necessity of the things themselves, is perhaps the central contribution of
realist phenomenology. Thus, philosophy discovers again the nature and structure
of the things themselves: the objective world and its structures that since Hume
and Kant were believed to have been lost. In this way, realistic phenomenology,
through a return to that particular necessity of the things themselves, rejects every
subjectivization of the a priori and establishes once again classical philosophy
and metaphysics.
Secondly, this necessity of the objects of philosophy is not blindly posited by
realistic phenomenology but instead is knowable through insight and deduction,
and is thereby linked with the highest form of knowability and intelligibility
(understandability). All talk of mere innate ideas, forms of perception and of
thought that lie ready made in the mind, but also any variation on Plato’s teachings
regarding anamnesis, cannot do justice to the inner knowability and intelligibility
of essential states of affairs that must be a certain way and cannot be otherwise.
Consequently, Husserl’s claim concerning the nature of philosophy as a rigorous
science which limits philosophy to the mere noemata of intentional acts shows
itself as invalid, yes even absurd. For the datum of absolute necessity is in its
absoluteness fully independent from every thinking consciousness, unconstitutable
by God or men and therefore a limitation of the object of philosophy to noemata is
unnecessary. When, of course, one does not see the distinction between contingent
essences (with respect to which we obtain only probable knowledge concerning
their reign over the existing world) and necessary ones, as is the case with Husserl,
then his error is quite understandable. For then a rigorous philosophical science
could only investigate essences as inhabitants of a possible world and could not
know if the existing world is formed according to them.
Thirdly, this necessity is predominately accessible to us in immediate
cognition through the Wesensschau (insight) or indirectly through syllogistic or
other forms of deductive proof. We achieve in both cases that indubitable and
infallible knowledge (spoken of by Augustine and Bonaventure and from which we
can only deviate and fall into error when we begin in our judgements) to bypass the
evident objects of cognition. Instead of their faithful analysis to construct, to
reduce, and in so doing we deviate from the light of the things themselves.
Yet, how can we know such synthetic a priori states of affairs? Are they
simply innate ideas? Do we hold that a priori knowledge must be independent of all
18
experience, as Kant thought? It is precisely on this question that
phenomenological realism manages, as Scheler expresses it, to be more positivistic
than any positivism, more empirical than Hume does, while still defending the a
priori in its strictly objective interpretation. According to empiricism, only the
material for ideas is supplied by experience; the linking of ideas and their
association is a contribution of the subject. The general essence is not itself given in
experience; above all no necessary essence is thus given. Realistic
phenomenology, on the other hand, understands experience in a much more
extensive way than empiricism, whereby it returns to Husserl’s notion of
‘categorical intuition’ as the experience of the general essences of things. At the
same time, it rejects every kind of mere immanentism, conceptualism, or
constructivism. Obviously, we cannot recognize the law that the color purple in the
order of similarity must lie between blue and red without the experience of sight –
and yet the law is necessary19. In the same way the Kantian thesis that the a priori,
because of its necessity, cannot be given in any experience is not to be blindly
accepted. Rather we must make a distinction, as Hildebrand above all has done,20
He posits the distinction between empirical experience, which takes it starting
point in the simple observation of real existing objects and a completely different
pure such-being experience. This experience of ‘essence.’ can have its origin in
‘sense perception,’ in the psychic experience of one’s judgement or cognition, or in
the moral experience, wherever intelligible and necessary essences are
18
Plato assumed a certain experience before birth. Cf. Balduin Schwarz (1970, 33-51). Cf.
also Reale (1993, chapter 6 ff.)
19
Concerning this experience in which the knowledge of essence is given, Husserl wrote
quite beautifully in Edmund Husserl, “Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft,” cit., p. 32 f.,
where he says that the insight into essences is neither a mystical act nor is less of an
experience than sense-perception.
20
Cf. above all Hildebrand (1976, chapter 4).
21
Cf. Seifert (1977), chapter 1.
22
Cf. Hildebrand (1991, chapter 4)
23
With the truth of this proposition we do not wish of course to deny the possibility of a
wishing or willing that in a certain sense is unconscious, in so far as it remains unclear to
the person willing that he wills and what he wills.
It has often been said that the call to return to immediate cognition (a priori
insight) is the most basic form of philosophical and rational cognition. As such, (a
call which incidentally can be traced back to Plato as well as to the Posterior
Analytics and the Metaphysics of Aristotle) for which no proof can be given or
required and of which there can be no higher criterion, implies the neglect of
dialectic and argument and with it rigorous scientific method. That this does not
follow can be seen from the fact that every logical argument presupposes the most
important logical principles. Additionally, the difference between valid and
invalid forms of drawing a conclusion which themselves can only be known
through insights and cannot be grounded by means of other proofs and without
which all other demonstrations would be worthless. No view of rationality that
does not recognize this highest form of rational knowledge that lies in the
intuitive grasping of intelligible and necessary essences and states of affairs is
capable of being conceptualized. This does not indicate a rational deficit, nor a
repudiation of all forms of argument as ways to insight. On the contrary, there is
the dialectic of the question in relation to the answer; there is the uncovering of
the presuppositions of an opponent in which he is shown to presuppose himself
what he is denying and so on. All forms of philosophical argumentation and
platonic dialectics are, in the light of the phenomenological insight, not only
permissible, but also receive from it their ultimate justification. Reinach has also
shown that insight does not mean obviousness or an easy accessibility to every
24
Cf. Hildebrand, “Das Cogito und die Erkenntnis der realen Welt. Teilveröffentlichung
der Salzburger Vorlesungen Hildebrands: Wesen und Wert menschlicher Erkenntnis”,
Aletheia VI, 1994. Cf. also Seifert, Erkenntnis objektiver Wahrheit, II, chapters 1-2.
25
Cf. Josef Seifert (1977), chapters 1-2.
26
I have also tried to show this in Back to Things in Themselves, 1987, chapter 2.
27
There is, already in ancient philosophy, also a kind of cogito to be found in Parmenides
28
Cf. in particular Hildebrand (1964) and Seifert (1987, chapters 3-4). Through his
radically different interpretation of the subject as a transcendental ego, which allows for no
archimedian point for the knowledge of an objectively existing world (no ‘piece of the real
world’, as Husserl in his Cartesian Meditations put it), and which, moreover, is responsible
for the constitution of all meaning and all real being, the phenomenology of the later
Husserl distinguishes itself from phenomenological realism in perhaps almost as radically
a way as through its assumption of the dependency of the eîde and necessary essences on
the subject.
29
Cf. also, Rocco Butiglione (1989, p.9-75); and Josef Seifert (1989, chapters 1-4, 9-15).
30
Cf Balduin Schwarz (1934).
31
Cf. for example, Plato, Crito. cf. concerning the idea of value-blindness, Hildebrand
(1982).