Beyond Structural Listening PDF
Beyond Structural Listening PDF
Beyond Structural Listening PDF
EDITED BY
Andrew Dell’Antonio
13 12 11 10 09 08 07 06 05 04
10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
The paper used in this publication is both acid-free and totally chlorine-free
(TCF). It meets the minimum requirements of ANSI/NISO Z39.48–1992
(R 1997) (Permanence of Paper).
contents
preface / vii
2. Musical Virtues
Mitchell Morris / 44
bibliography 303
index / 323
preface
This project probably has its roots in a long conversation I had with Rose
Rosengard Subotnik at the 1990 AMS/SMT/SEM meeting in Oakland, Cal-
ifornia. Through the ensuing decade and a half, other conversations with
many friends and colleagues—among them the authors of this collection—
brought about a collective interest in exploring the formulations on struc-
tural listening that Rose had first articulated in the Meyer Festschrift. When
the essay was republished in Rose’s second collection, Deconstructive Varia-
tions, the topic took on new urgency; shortly thereafter, my conversations
intensified, and eventually led to my approaching the University of Califor-
nia Press with a proposal for a collection of essays.
In the process of its formation, the collection has changed (developed?):
the cast of characters is slightly different than that originally envisioned, the
title—and even the content—of more than one of the essays has metamor-
phosed beyond the expectations of its author. . . or its editor. These are
probably consequences of the dialogical (dare one say dialectical?) nature
of the project, of which this collection is one synchronic manifestation. Most
gratifying to me is the fact that our collective dialogue has expanded beyond
the boundaries of these essays—we have learned from each other, and have
found much common ground, and many fruitful points of disagreement. In
the process, I have gained even more respect for my fellow authors than I
had before, and I thank them again for their articulateness and willingness
to engage in this continuing discussion.
In a collection such as this, it is most appropriate to let the authors make
their own acknowledgments, and we have done so in each individual essay.
However, I will take the editor’s prerogative to give some much-deserved
overall thanks.
The University of Texas Cooperative Society provided a crucial subven-
vii
viii preface
tion grant, without which the collection could not have been published in
this form. Mary Francis supplied unwavering editorial guidance and invalu-
able support in navigating the shoals that invariably face editors of complex
collections such as this one. Ruth Solie and Nicholas Cook took time to offer
detailed and constructive suggestions on an earlier version of the typescript,
and much credit for the resulting improvements goes to them. Without Rob
Walser’s backing and enthusiasm for the project, the collection would not
have come to fruition as you see it today. Adam Krims’s wise counsel and
insight carried me through many a rough spot. My colleagues’ encourage-
ment—especially that of Elizabeth Crist, David Neumeyer, Jim Buhler, Sarah
Reichardt, and Dennis Rathnaw—made balancing this venture with other
professional duties a pleasure. And the contribution of my family—Lella,
Lester, Gianfausto, Ian, Barbara, and especially Susan and Miriam—to my
emotional and intellectual balance can never be quantified.
None of this would have been possible without Rose Rosengard Subotnik.
This collection is not the Festschrift she still amply deserves, but perhaps its
dialectical spirit—and, yes, unresolved conflicts—are a worthy tribute to the
influence she has had on us, and on the discipline of musicology.
Andrew Dell’Antonio
Austin, Texas
December 2003
introduction
The concept of structural value offered by Schoenberg and Adorno, like their
concept of the structural listening that can discern such value, is at once exact-
ing and generous. Demanding an unflagging intelligent concentration on the
part of the listener, these men require of the composer, and more generally of
themselves, a no less stringent standard of discipline. For Schoenberg these two
[structural rigor and expressive capacity] are virtually synonymous: the deep-
est emotional satisfaction in music arises precisely through the achievement of
an intensely expressive structural integrity (which is “independent of style and
flourish” and communicable at least to those whose “artistic and ethical culture
is on a high level”). (155)
ous self-discipline; such training and self-discipline, in their turn, are the
mark of an aesthetically prepared and culturally elevated individual.
But, as Subotnik observes, the notion of “listening” that emerges from this
paradigm is potentially detachable from the sense of hearing:
Even more important, perhaps, is the secondary status that [structural] listen-
ing accords to the musical parameter of sound . . . Certainly, to an important
extent, structural listening can take place in the mind through intelligent
score-reading, without the physical presence of an external sound-source . . .
By Adorno’s account, in fact, “mature music,” which concerns itself with that
“subcutaneous” structure where individual integrity can hope to resist or even
transcend social ideology, “becomes suspicious of sound as such.” [Adorno
imagines] a time when “the silent, imaginative reading of music could render
actual playing as superfluous as speaking is made by the reading of written
material.” (161–62)
Some common threads in our essays seem to resonate strongly with these
“postmodern” approaches to knowledge (and our readers will doubtless find
other threads when reading these essays as a group):
control 1: questioning mastery. [Maus, Morris, Levitz, Dubiel,
Scherzinger; strong resonances in Fink, Attinello] What is our goal when we
listen, structurally or otherwise? Echoing Subotnik’s characterization of the
“ideal structural listener,” Maus offers us a snapshot of Allen Forte self-con-
sciously “modeling” the ideal theorist, who organizes time though analysis in
much the same way that a composer organizes time through music; music
and analysis are both “the product of a controlled, rational, masterful
agency,” and in this way working through an analytical chart “feels like” com-
posing, helping us connect to the truth of the compositional process and the
persona of the composer (see also Power and Personas, below). As Maus
observes, mastery is key for Forte since the field of music theory must pre-
sent itself as scientifically valid and deserving of high estimation during its
formative period, a time when high modernist valuing of science was still at
a peak. As Morris points out, the mastery of structural listening and/or analy-
sis has a clear moral value: such a practice reflects autonomy and internal
development, but also originality and expressivity, drawing explicit parallels
with two of the ideals of modernist selfhood: “atomistic individualism” and
“disengaged instrumental reason.” According to Morris (who is drawing on
Subotnik’s characterizations), in the modernist structural model “music
occupies itself with moral thought and action in ways that strongly resemble
the ways in which human beings occupy themselves with thought and action”
(see p. 51). Levitz comes to similar conclusions about the importance of
static models and comprehensive explanatory gestures in analyses of the
danse sacrale from Stravinsky’s Sacre du printemps by Boulez, Forte, and van den
Toorn. Departing from Subotnik’s characterization of structural listening as
score-bound, Dubiel argues that the most productive way to approach struc-
ture is through the listening experience itself, rather than through fulfill-
ment of pre-existing organicist models; he finds that listening for structural
events is not about mastery, but about “responsiveness along unforeseen
lines,” or “elusiveness of perception” (see p. 176). Rather than following the
established tradition of placing high value and emphasis on musical details
that are developed or “fulfilled” in the unfolding of the musical work,
Dubiel tries dwelling on “unfulfilled” or unexplainable musical events, and
6 andrew dell ’ antonio
his analyses reflect his experiments with the release of intellectual mastery
in the analytical process. The notion of “structural listening,” Dubiel sug-
gests, can best be thought of as a way of thinking about listening rather than
a way of listening; he examines examples in which he has difficulty “hearing”
specific details despite his ability to recognize them on the musical score, and
pointedly questions what it might mean to “hear” or to “listen” given these
paradoxical circumstances; indeed, listening for specific details might result
in confusion or disorientation rather than mastery, and this might be a valu-
able interpretative strategy to learn to deploy. In any case, the lack of coher-
ence in an analytical endeavor should not be seen as a weakness, but rather
as a potential opening for new insights. Scherzinger comes to a similar con-
clusion; seeing Subotnik’s definition as too limiting, and wanting to define
musical structure more broadly as the “opening of possibilities,” he suggests
that “open-ended” approaches to structure can be effectively used in desta-
bilizing established notions of the canon “from within”; he suggests that such
critiques are no less politically progressive than critiques “from without” that
dismiss structure as a progressive tool.
control 2: pleasure, pain, and the sublime. [Fink, Attinello;
strong resonances in Dubiel, Maus] Like Dubiel, Fink specifically challenges
the notion of control, finding potential in the pleasure-through-pain of the
sublime, and specifically in the potential for the “revelation of unspeakable
content” behind the moments when a formal process can be perceived as
hurtling toward failure; returning to the now-infamous image evoked by
Susan McClary of the recapitulation of the first movement in Beethoven’s
Ninth Symphony as akin to a “rage of a rapist incapable of attaining release,”
Fink traces a long tradition of controversy surrounding that musical episode,
and argues that the “beautifiers” who wish to hear that moment as non-prob-
lematic are at least matched, and perhaps out-argued, by those “sublimators”
who feel the frustration and pain of the musical gestures as inherent in the
sublime power of Beethoven’s approach. We can hear the passage as unprob-
lematic, Fink suggests, but what do we lose by such a decision? Has modernist
criticism, in its search for organic solutions, dismissed the power of disrup-
tion that many listeners experience as supremely meaningful in this and
other music? Attinello argues that the disruptive power of the sonic sublime
is a key component of much postwar avant-garde music, and suggests that the
scientific metaphors of control and organization deployed by Boulez and
composers of the Darmstadt school can mask the crucial preoccupation in
this music with the power of the “violent ineffable”—of sound that threatens
to “crack open the sky.” He proposes that listeners try to focus on the sonic
disruption that is created by such ostensibly detached procedures, and to
dwell on the paradox created by those two apparently opposed affective
states, rather than on the more explicit rhetoric of compositional mastery.
introduction 7
notes
1. Rose Rosengard Subotnik, “Toward a Deconstruction of Structural Listening:
A Critique of Schoenberg, Adorno, and Stravinsky,” in Subotnik 1996, 148–76; a pre-
12 andrew dell ’ antonio
vious version of this essay appeared in Narmour and Solie 1988. Much of the discus-
sion of Subotnik’s argument that follows owes its articulation to an earlier version of
Tamara Levitz’s article for this collection; I would like to thank her for her incisive-
ness and insight.
2. Subotnik 1996, 158. Subotnik traces the principle of work autonomy so essen-
tial to structural listening back to a passionate eighteenth-century debate that found
its most influential resonance in Kant’s Kritik der Urteilskraft. She believes that it was
Kant who convinced scholars for over two hundred years of the importance of judg-
ing the art work in itself, according to its own Zweckmäßigkeit and independently of
other realms of knowledge. This led to what is often almost casually, and sometimes
incorrectly, labeled “formalism” in music theory in the twentieth century. See also
Subotnik 1991.
one
strange echo
Allen Forte’s essay “Schenker’s Conception of Musical Structure” comments
on a graphic analysis by Heinrich Schenker, in order to exemplify
Schenker’s approach to tonal music. In a typical remark, he paraphrases
Schenker’s sketch: “Schenker then shows how this initial prolongation is fol-
lowed by a restatement.”
Then he does something odd. In the next sentence, Forte writes: “To reca-
pitulate, there are two prolongational classes shown in this background
sketch” (12–13). The odd part is the echo between “restatement” and “reca-
pitulation,” and the way the words resonate across the obvious distinction
between the music and Forte’s own text. The music, interpreted by Schenker,
restates; immediately after, Forte the theorist recapitulates. The words have
almost the same meaning, though they refer to different things—one a musi-
cal event, the other an event in Forte’s text. Curiously, Forte applies the con-
cept “restatement” to the music and “recapitulation” to his own words. This
reverses the more natural pairing, as though to emphasize (through the
rhetorical figure of chiasmus) a symmetry or mirroring between media.
Why would this echo or mirroring occur? Many people, reading the essay,
might not be puzzled by this: it is easy to ignore such a detail of language,
13
14 fred everett maus
not allowing it to distract from the “content” of the essay. You might not reg-
ister it consciously or, perhaps, you might enjoy it as a rather subdued form
of wit, as decoration. But what if you want to take that bit of matching more
seriously, rather than setting it aside? What if you want to include it as part
of the message of the essay? What context of other passages in Forte’s essay,
and of broader considerations about music theory, could make this play of
“restatement” and “recapitulation” more than a mishap or a small joke?
expresses hope that, “as Schenker’s work becomes more widely recognized,
serious music theorists will make further applications of his ideas” (23).
These passages evoke music theorists as people who reflect and converse. But
in many other passages, a reified music theory floats free from any particu-
lar social embodiment. Forte writes of “certain problems which stand before
music theory today” (4); he identifies “five unsolved problems in music theory”
(24); he suggests that “music theory is responsible for developing new con-
cepts and new analytical procedures” for contemporary music (33). (Here
and in subsequent quotations throughout, I add italics to draw attention to
wording.) Music theory itself. Is anybody home?
Yes: at several points Forte invokes an abstract, generalized figure, “the
music theorist,” whose behavior contributes to this field. “From the view-
point of the present-day music theorist,” he suggests, Schenker’s achievement
“may be likened to a particular kind of high-level achievement in science”
(7). Extant writings on rhythm, he claims, “have little significance to the the-
orist whose proper concern is with the structural role of what we ordinarily
designate as ‘rhythmic’” (24). His concluding paragraph states that “in many
respects Schenker’s work provides us with a model of what the work of the
music theorist should be” (34). This last sentence lays some of Forte’s cards on
the table: the essay is not merely about some interesting ideas of an intrigu-
ing historical figure, Heinrich Schenker; rather, it is meant to articulate a
particular model of a normative subjectivity, a way to be a musician. By fol-
lowing the model, you can discipline and transform your existing self to
become a specimen of “the music theorist.”
Of course, as I already suggested, Forte’s own writing contributes to the
model. While admiring and emulating the repetitiously named Schenker, a
reader should also want to emulate the agent or self constructed in Forte’s
essay, the subject of its many first-person pronouns. Given the common con-
ception of professional music theory as impersonal and science-like, you
might not expect to see so much self-reference, so many first-person pro-
nouns, but there they are. Surely this personal self-referring subject offers an
exemplary instance of “the music theorist,” the agent of music theory.
So who is this music theorist—who, in Forte’s essay, says “I”?
The music theorist of Forte’s essay is conspicuously a writer, concerned to
dispose the words of the essay in the allotted time or space. Sometimes the
presence of these words, these items that the writer disposes, becomes reflex-
ively explicit. Introducing an account of Schenker’s musical activities outside
music theory, Forte writes that “I should like to devote a few words to a
description of them” (7). In suggesting possible applications of Schenker’s
views, he writes that “I should like to devote the following paragraphs to a dis-
cussion of five unsolved problems in music theory” (23–24). From the words
on the page, you construct a voice or a subjectivity, and then you find that this
subjectivity is addressing you about the acts of arranging those very words.
16 fred everett maus
mirroring
Indeed, within much of the essay, as you read the confident account of
Schenker’s thought and of the structure of a song (“Aus meinen Thränen
spriessen,” from the Schumann/Heine Dichterliebe), misunderstanding does
not seem to be a live possibility. The sense of rapport among Forte,
the disciplined subject of musical analysis 17
Schenker, and the music results partly from an extraordinary feature of the
essay, the same feature I pointed out in my opening comments: repeatedly,
details of language create patterns in which the behavior of Schumann’s
music, as depicted by Schenker, and the behavior of Forte’s essay mirror one
another within the space of a sentence or two. The relationship seems unde-
niable, but bizarre—not just the broad relation of mimicry, but the place-
ment of musical and textual mirror-images in such close proximity. Here are
more examples:
(1) Forte expands a point: “In amplification of this, example 1.9 shows how
the inner-voice component A is stated at the beginning of the song, pro-
longed by the lower adjacent 7 tone, G-sharp, in the middle section, then in
m. 12 begins the descent to C-sharp.” And in the next sentence, Forte con-
tinues: “In Schenker’s terms, this linear progression is the composing-out of an
interval” (28). The theorist amplifies a point, the piece composes out an
interval.
(2) Commenting on Schenker’s sketch, Forte writes that “the adjacent-
tone D recurs in m. 14, where Schenker assigns more structural weight to it,
as indicated by the stem. I reiterate that conventional durational values are
used in the analytic sketches to indicate the relative position of a given com-
ponent or configuration in the tonal hierarchy” (14). A tone in Schumann’s
piece recurs, and the theorist reiterates.
(3) Forte discusses the Schumann song’s use of a particular secondary
dominant. He indicates parenthetically that this point does not continue his
explication of Schenker’s analysis: “(To avoid misunderstanding, I point out
that this discussion is not directly related to Schenker’s sketch.)” After break-
ing continuity to offer this special explanation, he writes that “the A7 chord
seems abrupt, has the effect of a discontinuous element, and therefore
requires special explanation” (27).
(4) Writing about the notion of interruption, Forte comments that “the
idea of the interrupted fundamental line provides the basis for Schenker’s
concept of form.” After a few sentences of explanation, Forte continues:
“Before explaining the middleground, I should like to direct attention again
to the diminution which spans the third below C-sharp” (13). Like a com-
position, the theorist proceeds by interrupting his structure, delaying the
continuation.
Indeed, such interruptions or delays, basic to Schenker’s conception of
musical time, occasion many of Forte’s first-person pronouns: “I shall return
to this often neglected facet of Schenker’s work later” (7); “further on I shall
provide a commentary upon an analytic sketch” (9); “I shall explain the black
noteheads shortly”(12); “I shall return to this further on when I consider the
general problem of constructing a theory of rhythm for tonal music” (15).
(5) Forte completes his account of the Schumann sketch by showing the
form of the complete song: “One final aspect of the foreground sketch
18 fred everett maus
deserves mention: the form” (17). Closure and completeness in song, sketch,
and Forte’s commentary align.
(6) At several points Schenker is also drawn into this pattern of matching.
Forte identifies a passing chord, and writes: “it belongs only to the fore-
ground and therefore is to be distinguished from the initial tonic chord, a
background element. Two of Schenker’s most important convictions underlie
this treatment of detail” (15). Convictions underlie a particular analytical
treatment, as background elements underlie a foreground chord.
(7) Writing of Schenker’s motivic thought, Forte notes that “throughout
his writings he demonstrates again and again that tonal compositions abound
in hidden repetitions of this kind” (14). Schenker repeatedly identifies musi-
cal repetitions.
(8) A more complex transfer of qualities, brought about by a conjunction
of temporal references involving Schenker, the composition, and the writer
of Forte’s essay, appears in the following sentences: “Here we have an
example of the careful distinction which Schenker always draws between
major bass components, or Stufen, which belong to the background level,
and more transient, contrapuntal-melodic events at the foreground and mid-
dleground levels. A brief consideration of three additional events will com-
plete our examination of the middleground level” (14). “Always,” “tran-
sient,” “brief”: the distinction between endurance and transience appears in
dazzling succession for Schenker’s thought, musical structure, and Forte’s
exposition.
How strange that Forte’s essay, beyond making assertions about musical
structure, should also mimic procedures of Schenkerian musical structure.
I doubt that Forte consciously formulated such a project, or that his readers
have typically perceived the pattern consciously. Nonetheless it adds to the
sense of authority in the essay: music theory seems to find something like a
musical voice. Or perhaps the essay, and the theory it promotes, gives music
the prosaic, reasonable, well-organized voice of an academic essay, placing
music within comfortable reach of Forte’s writing and concepts.1
control
Beyond the specific moments where Forte’s language creates parallels
between music and theoretical discourse, there is a more general resem-
blance between the theorist and the composition in the essay. At the begin-
ning of the explication of Schenker’s analysis of Schumann’s song, Forte
identifies the foreground, middleground, and background levels of the
sketch, and meanwhile employs the terms “subordination” and “control.”
Indicating the middleground level, he states that “it should be evident now
that the analytic procedure is one of reduction; details which are subordinate
the disciplined subject of musical analysis 19
supplication
Forte’s essay describes the patterning of musical sound in time, and mirrors
it with a patterning of words in the essay. Forte offers the essay to his read-
ers, and permits himself an isolated moment of pathos near the beginning,
when Forte steels himself for anticipated incomprehension. Now let’s turn
to Heinrich Heine’s text for Schumann’s song. You will not learn from Forte’s
essay that the famous poet has anything to do with this music—the word
“Heine” is absent (the word “Schumann” barely appears).2 Nonetheless
Heine’s text is apposite:
From my tears spring up
many blooming flowers,
and my sighs become
a chorus of nightingales.
And if you love me, child,
I give you all the flowers,
and before your window shall sound
the song of the nightingale.3
Heine Forte
transformed into/symbolized by
Obviously this relationship between song and essay is different in its effect
from the mirroring that I described before. I suggested that the mirroring
creates matched images of music and theorist and, however subliminally,
enhances the authority of the theorist. But Forte’s structural rhyme with
Heine’s text occurs in an essay that omits any mention of the poem. It is as
though, rather than showing the parallel, Forte prefers to substitute his own
new text to go with the music of the song, concocting a loose translation of
the original.
the disciplined subject of musical analysis 21
But after all, what advantage would Forte’s stance derive from attention
to the words of the song? As Forte depicts it (drawing upon Schenker), Schu-
mann’s song is a display of structural mastery, a disciplined deployment of
repetition, delay, interruption, and so on, all subordinated to the back-
ground that controls everything. In contrast, Heine’s character is mostly out
of control, in the grip of strong emotions, the symptoms of which turn
miraculously into beautiful natural objects, useful perhaps as gifts; and this
lover is dependent, asking for reciprocity, hoping for the mutuality of shared
love. The hope for love brings a need for response from the interlocutor,
whereas Forte, in his essay, seems secure in his knowledge of Schenker: he
doesn’t need the readers, though he hopes to benefit them by sharing his
knowledge.4
It is intriguing to find, a generation later, another Schenkerian analyst,
Arthur Komar, directly expressing his disdain for Heine’s protagonist: “The
words [of Dichterliebe] actually impede my enjoyment of the whole cycle—
to the extent that I heed them. The moping, distraught lover portrayed in
German song cycles bores me, but this feeling in no way detracts from my
enthusiasm for the music of the great song cycles of Beethoven, Schubert,
and Schumann” (Komar 1971, 11, note 20). As this implies, Komar’s
extended essay analyzes the music of Dichterliebe while disregarding the
words. Asking in what way the whole cycle is “an integrated musical whole”
(63), he replies by identifying a “tonal plan” and “modal plan” established
in the first five songs; taken together, these plans “essentially control the
remaining course of the cycle” (78). Once that mopey lover is out of the pic-
ture, Komar can display the control that gives wholeness to the cycle and
purpose to his own analytical writing. I suppose Forte’s evasion of Heine’s
poem has a similar point.5
Heine’s lover addresses the second half of the poem to the beloved, end-
ing in suspense as the lover awaits a reply. Forte’s essay uses the second per-
son pronoun twice, with uniform rhetoric: Forte anticipates a question,
which he promptly answers. “But, you ask, what about the books and
articles . . .” (5). “You may ask how one accounts for a motion of this
kind . . .” (22). Forte ventriloquizes the reader, creating a dependent inter-
locutor who elicits his own authoritative responses. Rather than “I need your
love,” we read that “I know what you need to know just now, and here it is.”
In these approaches—of Heine’s lover to the beloved, of Forte to his read-
ers—the trajectories of need and potential satisfaction are opposite. Heine’s
lover supplicates the beloved, who might return his love; the projected
reader supplicates Forte, who offers satisfaction promptly.
The song text is about erotic desire and the transformation of feeling into
symbols. Psychoanalysis specializes in such topics. It is interesting, given the
omission of such a text, that Forte’s essay mentions psychoanalysis promi-
nently. While Forte does not say that music theory is a science, he seems to
22 fred everett maus
your own? But, despite obscurity, to make the persona’s utterance your own
must be, somehow, to feel the persona’s power and control as your own, and
this idea has, one might feel, a general affinity with Forte’s procedure of mir-
roring between the controlling musical forces and his own linguistic control.
Cone’s account is complex. Alongside descriptions of identification, other
passages emphasize the domination of listeners by music. I already indicated
a flow of power within the music, depicted in both Cone’s and Forte’s
accounts: some powerful force, the background or the persona, controls all
the subordinate events of the composition. To this, Cone adds that the music
exerts control over the listener.7
Elaborating the psychology of listeners’ experiences, Cone cites the fact
that many people have imaginary musical sound in their minds much of the
time, involuntarily, and he defines composing and listening in relation to
this musical stream of consciousness. “To compose is to control this inner
voice, to shape it into new forms, to make it speak for us. To listen to music
is to yield our inner voice to the composer’s domination” (157). You might
have an ongoing stream of musical thoughts, in which case you can simply
let it continue. As a composer, you might take your existing stream of musi-
cal thoughts and exert conscious control over it: composers make a distinc-
tive use of control in their own mental lives. As a listener, you can yield the
stream to the influence of something outside, letting the composer’s control
(or, as Cone might put it at his most precise, the persona’s control) extend
to your own mental life.8
I want to reflect a bit on this interesting idea of an inner musical voice,
offering a more differentiated description than Cone provides. The inner
activity can vary widely, ranging from aimless sonic doodling, to full-fledged
inner performance of familiar music, to vivid inner improvisation; it can
fluctuate from periphery to focus of one’s awareness; it can be uncontrolled
and spontaneous, or one can shape it in various respects. And, beyond Cone’s
alternatives of the composer’s and listener’s roles, the inner stream can flow
out into performance, solo improvisation, or musical interaction, and can
also emerge in such half-externalized forms as humming, rhythmic fidget-
ing, finger-tapping, and so on. For me and, I assume, for many people, this
ongoing musical stream, and the various fluctuations in its character, are
important aspects of what it is to be conscious! Cone’s descriptions of the
composer, who forcefully directs this inner stream with the goal of produc-
ing a score, and the listener, who completely relinquishes control and allows
someone else’s music to take over, are extremes in a complex range of pos-
sibilities. Perhaps Cone’s selective account reveals that, despite the calm, affa-
ble surface of his writing, he is drawn in some way to these extremes of con-
trol and domination. Or, at least, he has not developed the account beyond
what he needs to give his description of the classical concert setting.
Cone’s conception, in which we experience music by encountering pow-
the disciplined subject of musical analysis 25
erful forces that control everything in the piece, and that also control our
own inner musical voice, has a complex relationship to his other idea about
identification. The listener is dominated by, and also identifies with, the per-
sona, seeming to maintain relations of subordination and identification
simultaneously. Listeners are, on Cone’s account, at once subjected to con-
trol that comes from outside, and empowered by taking on that control as
though it were their own. Here is Cone’s way of putting it, in sentences that
conclude the main argument of the book: “To listen to music is to yield our
inner voice to the composer’s domination. Or better: it is to make the com-
poser’s voice our own” (157). These sentences conjoin the two aspects of dom-
ination and identification, without clarifying their relationship.9
This account of listening reminds me of a useful general concept formu-
lated by the psychoanalyst Christopher Bollas. Bollas (1987) writes of a phe-
nomenon that he calls “extractive introjection”: sometimes two people inter-
act so that some mental content or process, originally belonging to one
person, seems to be taken away from that person, subsequently belonging
only to the other one. Bollas illustrates the concept through a series of anec-
dotes. For instance, he describes a four-year-old, B, at play, “engaged in a pri-
vate drama that is nonetheless realized through actual objects. The space is
entered by A, who creates such distraction that B loses his playfulness.” A
might be a parent, who “appropriates the playing by telling the child what
the play is about and then prematurely engages in playfulness.” With repeti-
tion of such interruptions, the child’s “sense of spontaneity would diminish”
and B “will come to experience an extraction of that element of himself: his
capacity to play” (1987, 159). Something that was in the child, an ongoing
activity, is now gone, replaced by something outside; the playfulness has
been extracted from the child and introjected into the adult. Bollas describes
a number of similar interactions, many of them between adults. He goes on
to suggest that “a child who is the victim of consistent extractive introjection
may choose to identify with the aggressive parent and install in his person-
ality this identification, which then functions as a false self” (164). That is,
the response to a theft of part of oneself might be, not exactly a recovery of
what was taken, but an imagined identification with the other person and the
act of theft.
Similarly, in Cone’s account of listening, many people usually have music
passing through their minds; but when you listen attentively, you experience
a displacement or extraction of the source of musical thought, from your
own stream of inner music to the activities of external sound sources. In per-
formance settings that strictly limit sonic participation, such as modern clas-
sical concerts, the musical source is entirely outside the listener. However, as
Cone describes it, this “extraction” leads immediately to an act of identifi-
cation, in which the listener somehow identifies herself with the external
source of musical activity.
26 fred everett maus
scores in theory and analysis, on the grounds that they distract from, or
replace, musical sound—as though analysts are, in some way, thinking about
scores rather than musical sound. Such a blunt criticism seems ill founded or,
at best, undeveloped. The idea that score-readers replace sound with sight
is too simple. Experienced score-readers do not just look at visual symbols;
we use them as a starting point for remembering or imagining sound. The
Composer’s Voice gives a more helpful point of departure for thinking about
score-reading, by considering scores in light of power relations and subject
positions.
A score contains the composer’s instructions. Therefore, Cone suggests
that it can serve as a symbol of the all-powerful persona, and this can give
value to its visible presence in live performance settings. “The physical pres-
ence of the score (or of its parts) is a constant reminder—for both per-
formers and audience—of the control of the complete musical persona” (64).
And Cone describes score-reading in terms of identification: “Score-reading
. . . permits a musician (the reader) to identify himself fully and intimately with
the complete persona, and . . . gives him total control over the direction of the
persona’s musical activity” (136). Score-reading, it seems, is the best way to
feel like the persona. It even, somehow, gives you control over the persona’s
activity! How can this be?
As Cone explains, score-reading is “a kind of abstract performance”
(136); a performer has the task of bringing musical events into being, and a
score-reader does this too, at least in imagination. Performance and score-
reading occupy complex positions, neither fully creative nor fully receptive.
The performer or score-reader must respect the composer’s instructions but,
by so doing, can assume responsibility for the creation of musical events, in
actual or imagined sound.
In fact, the score opens a wider range of subject-positions for a score-
reader than Cone indicates. (Again, as in his account of “our inner voice,”
Cone seems drawn to a somewhat simplified account.) You can use the score
to imagine hearing a performance, in a kind of imaginative listening. Or you
can imagine yourself following the composer’s notated instructions in a per-
formance, taking the role of an imaginary performer. Or you can imagine
choosing the symbols that constitute the score, as though making the deci-
sions that compose the music. Or, less literally, you might imagine creating
all the musical gestures of the piece from your own musical initiative, like a
composer, but in the ordering and time of a performance; this is probably
closest to Cone’s conception of identifying with the persona. And of course
your imagination might do things that remain a little vague about these dis-
tinctions. The most powerful positions, identifying with the composer or his
imaginary reconfiguration as the persona, are readily available to a score-
reader, probably more available than to a listener. But also, even if you imag-
ine yourself in the least powerful role, as a listener, your own imagination has
28 fred everett maus
to conjure up the musical sounds that you imagine yourself hearing. Imag-
ining oneself listening is different, in that way, from just listening. In general,
it seems that an emphasis on score-reading is likely to diminish the subordi-
nation that listening may bring. So, to the extent that analysis is based on
score-reading rather than listening, it may be able to evade issues about the
dependency or receptiveness of listening.
But, whatever you think about the general tendencies of analytical prac-
tice, it would be too simple to say that Forte’s essay emphasizes score-read-
ing and ignores listening. The truth is stranger and more complex: Forte
places very strong emphasis on listening experience, but does so at just five
scattered points, with no perceptible effect on the rest of the essay. There is
a pattern: each reference to listening occurs within a single sentence, after
which he drops the topic immediately.
Forte cites Schenker’s belief that a performer could play well only “if
he had developed an aural sensitivity to the hierarchy of tonal values
which [the score] expressed” (8). Forte also mentions Furtwängler’s em-
phasis on Schenker’s discovery of “Fernhören (literally, ‘distance-hearing’)”
(19), and he explains Brahms’s curiosity about parallel fifths and octaves
by the “contradiction” between pre-Schenkerian theory and Brahms’s
“own highly-refined sense of hearing, which encompassed large spans”
(30). Apart from their paradoxical combination of emphasis, brevity, and
lack of consequences, these remarks about listening share other traits.
They are all about someone else’s hearing, not Forte’s. And they concern
the listening experiences of good performers, or of those imposing
authorities Furtwängler and Brahms, not the experiences of mere listen-
ers as such.
Forte’s most important reference to listening comes in a general discus-
sion of methodology. He asserts that Schenker’s theory derives from “the
organization of the music itself,” and explains: “Schenker consistently derived
his theoretical formulations from aural experiences with actual musical com-
positions, and verified them at the same source” (7). Evidently, for Forte, the
appropriateness of Schenker’s theoretical work depends on the founda-
tional role of those listening experiences. Schenker’s valuable contributions
rest on his listening. Can we discuss and ponder his listening experiences?
No: they are not otherwise acknowledged in Forte’s essay, and consequently
they occupy a curious position as something crucial that, nonetheless, one
barely mentions. In the essay, Schenker’s experiences as a listener are both
the source of his musical wisdom and, it seems, something private.
Schenker’s secret life.
In one more passage, Forte suggests that Schenker teaches a particular
kind of hearing. Someone who encounters Schenker’s thought must learn
many new things—“a new terminology, a new set of visual symbols, and, most
important, a new way of hearing music” (6). As you might expect from the other
the disciplined subject of musical analysis 29
seduction
In using Cone’s writing to interpret Forte’s, I have treated Cone as, in cer-
tain ways, the more explicit of the two writers. I have looked to his text for
relatively direct statements of ideas that can then be read back into Forte’s
essay. In particular, while Forte does not do much to describe listeners, I
have suggested that Cone’s account provides an account of listening that
works well with Forte’s account of control and subordination.
Now, though, I want to change tactics and start teasing out some less
explicit aspects of Cone’s position. In particular, I want to identify an implicit
eroticization of musical experience in The Composer’s Voice. Just as I have used
Cone’s views to fill in gaps in Forte’s account, now I want to interpret Cone’s
1974 book by drawing on a more recent musicological tradition, from about
1990 on, that directly explores relations between musical experience and
sexuality.17 In The Composer’s Voice, an eroticization of musical experience
sometimes comes close to the surface, but Cone’s habitual discretion nor-
mally keeps sexual issues in the realm of implication and connotation.
Recently, Philip Brett has drawn attention to passages in The Composer’s
Voice about four-hand piano performance, passages that evoke, not quite
directly, the eroticism (and, in male–male performance, homoeroticism) of
that ensemble. Brett (1997, 154) observes how close Cone’s writing comes
to raciness, and asserts that “This is surely as close as musicology of a per-
fectly respectable kind can come to exploring the (deviant) sexuality sur-
rounding music without advertising what it is doing.” A few years after The
Composer’s Voice, Cone published “Schubert’s Promissory Note” (1982), his
most direct treatment of music and sexuality, linking certain passages in
Schubert to sensuous pleasures and their horrifying consequence of syphilis.
That essay confirms my sense that Cone himself sometimes experiences
music as sensual or seductive, and also shows that he is likely to be circum-
spect in his descriptions.18
Closer to the main concerns of this paper, an intriguing passage implies an
eroticized power relation between personas and their listeners. In order to clar-
ify his account of identification, Cone contrasts a listener’s relation to music
with a reader’s or listener’s relation to language. The contrast concerns the sep-
aration between the musical or linguistic “voice” and its audience: according to
Cone, it is far easier for an addressee to maintain a sense of independence in
perceiving linguistic communication. Music has an invasive aspect, a way of dis-
solving a listener’s control, that distinguishes it from language. After empha-
sizing this “extraordinary power that music seems to exert over our inner life,”
and stating that “music can speak to us only as it speaks through us,” Cone offers
a model, stating that Zerlina, in the duet “Là ci darem la mano” from Mozart’s
Don Giovanni, “admirably symbolizes the situation” (155). Who is Zerlina, and
how might she symbolize you, or me, as a music-listener?
32 fred everett maus
In “Là ci darem la mano” Don Giovanni approaches the peasant girl Zer-
lina, drawing her away from her impending wedding to suggest that he,
rather than her fiancé, the peasant Masetto, will marry her. The duet shows
his seduction of her—his wooing, her initial resistance, and her eventual
assent just before the two start off for Don Giovanni’s house. Though the
opera is all about Don Giovanni’s successes and failures in seduction and
rape, this is the only seduction depicted onstage.19 The subject matter of the
duet—Don Giovanni’s destructive, manipulative use of his prestige and
charm—is unpleasant, but the duet is widely known and loved, a favorite bit
of the opera.
Cone mentions this familiar duet in order to make a specific, delimited
point. He brings out a subtle contradiction between textual and musical pat-
terning at the beginning of the duet. Don Giovanni addresses Zerlina invit-
ingly. Zerlina replies by describing her indecisiveness, but while her words
seem to resist his invitation, she sings them to the melody of Don Giovanni’s
invitation. According to Cone, “her melody, her subconscious reaction,
reflects his. Already, long before she gives in verbally, she has identified her-
self with his music” (155). Zerlina’s words can keep their distance from the
content of Don Giovanni’s words. She does not reply by saying back to him
what he just said to her (it would be odd if she did!), but that is exactly what
happens musically. Cone goes further, interpreting her use of his music as a
sign that a part of her, which Cone identifies as her “subconscious,” is already
beginning to give in to the attempted seduction.20 It is clever of Cone to cite
this example where the musical repetition and the verbal non-repetition
seem equally natural, and where the onstage interaction can model a rela-
tion between musical persona and audience.
But, while Cone cites this duet to illustrate that music creates identifica-
tion more irresistibly than words, the example overflows the boundaries of
his explicit purpose, in a manner typical of indirect, connotative communi-
cation. For one thing, it complicates the politics of identification. In identi-
fying with Don Giovanni by repeating his music, Zerlina models her behav-
ior on his, but the sense of equality or participation that she gains from this
mimicry is delusive. By the end of the duet, she feels that she is choosing Don
Giovanni, electing to share his prestige and power, but in fact the sensation
of choice is part of his snare. Her identification with Don Giovanni’s pur-
poses is the mechanism through which Don Giovanni achieves domination.
How much of this could one carry into Cone’s account of musical identifi-
cation? Does musical identification, rather than countering the persona’s
domination of the listener, instead somehow deepen and disguise that dom-
ination? “Là ci darem la mano” has sinister implications as a model of musi-
cal identification.
The example also raises issues about gender. Cone’s analogy offers a
banal, predictable alignment between gender and the persona/listener
the disciplined subject of musical analysis 33
opposition: the active, powerful persona resembles the masculine Don Gio-
vanni, the more passive listener the feminine Zerlina. Cone’s use of the duet
brings closer to the surface the potential association between listening and
femininity.
Cone’s analogy also draws in the notion of seduction. If listeners resem-
ble Zerlina, does that mean that music acts as a lover to its listeners, seduc-
ing them in some way? In fact, the choice of example makes it hard to avoid
thoughts of musical seduction, for this duet that depicts seduction is itself
quite beautiful, an especially seductive composition. You don’t need to take
my word for it; analogies between Don Giovanni’s seduction of Zerlina and
Mozart’s seduction of the listener recur in commentaries on the duet. Crit-
ics often notice that the duet delights its listeners into a suspension of their
better judgment, just as Don Giovanni’s flattery delights, confuses, and per-
suades Zerlina.
For instance, Nino Pirrotta (1994, 127) emphasizes the music’s capacity
to persuade listeners of the reality of the seduction: “Up to this point the
recitative dialogue has been convincing in its declamation but not in the
seduction, even if we grant that Zerlina needs little convincing; the magic of
the duettino that follows convinces us.” Like Zerlina, we succumb to a magic
that produces the effect of conviction. Wye Jamison Allanbrook (1983, 262)
emphasizes that listeners enjoy the depicted seduction, rather than judging
it sternly: “ ‘Là ci darem la mano’ is the sweetest imaginable of love duets . . .
all irony and cynicism must be suspended in the fact of the sheer beauty of
this dialogue of seduction and acquiescence.” Allanbrook’s account brings a
listener’s cognitive condition especially close to Zerlina’s: intellectual resis-
tance, one’s conscious evaluation of the situation, is undone by the pull of
sensuous attraction. Paul Henry Lang (1971, 87), again, spreads the seduc-
tive qualities from Don Giovanni to Mozart: he asks, “Was there ever set to
music a more delightful, a more tender, a more ravishing and enticing acqui-
escence to a tryst than ‘Là ci darem la mano’?” Zerlina’s acquiescence, as
Mozart shows it, ravishes and entices the audience. Otto Jahn’s version of the
same idea is more graphic (1882, 3:187): “[Don Giovanni’s] seductive pow-
ers are first practised towards Zerlina . . . that which can neither be analysed
nor reproduced is the effect of the tender intensity of the simple notes,
which penetrate the soul like the glance of a loving eye.” Mozart’s notes pen-
etrate you, as though someone were gazing at you in just the right way. The
vocabulary of these passages—magic, sweetest, sheer beauty, delightful, rav-
ishing, enticing, tender intensity—shows clearly the non-rational allure that,
for these critics, undoes any more distanced or reflective judgment.
So Cone is not the only critic to sense, in the relation between Don Gio-
vanni and Zerlina, a model for the relation between the music (or some cre-
ative force, a persona or composer) and its listener. But these other writers
make the analogy specifically in terms of seduction. Cone’s discussion of “Là
34 fred everett maus
batti, batti
Nonetheless, if “Là ci darem la mano” implicitly eroticizes the relationship
between persona and listener, the notion of seduction still does not offer the
most precise account of the erotic qualities of that relationship. In “Là ci
darem la mano,” Don Giovanni talks Zerlina into going away to have sex;
subsequently, were they not interrupted, they would move along to his
house and do the act. But Cone’s analogy likens Don Giovanni’s and Zerlina’s
preparatory conversation to the act of listening, which is itself, for a listener,
a consummation, not a negotiation about some future event. Listening,
then, would resemble both seduction and sex act, the two occurring simul-
taneously. But a more exact sexual analogy is possible, one that matches
many aspects of Cone’s account of listening.
To see this other analogy, let’s begin by remembering embodiment: in
sexual activities, bodies interact, and so one might ask how the bodies of lis-
teners affect these analogies. As it happens, Cone’s book—which really is
remarkably comprehensive—addresses the embodiment of listeners. In sug-
gesting that a listener “mentally performs the work he is hearing,” Cone spec-
ifies that a literal performer shapes the course of musical events, while “the
listener has no such opportunity: he must submit to the direction of others.”
This submission includes a suppression of bodily movements. Some listen-
ers might “hum, or beat time, or make other physical gestures,” but “most
sophisticated music lovers . . . frankly recognize the limitations of their roles
and sublimate their desires for physical activity” (136–37). A simpler account of
listening might deny the relevance of embodiment; Cone’s account, on the
contrary, identifies a particular bodily experience—an inhibited or “subli-
mated” desire for movement, linked to submission—as a constituent of
sophisticated musical love. As one might expect, Cone complicates this sub-
the disciplined subject of musical analysis 35
when we [acting as bottoms] give up our power, we feel more powerful. When
we give up control, we feel freer (27). When we bottom we feel fabulously pow-
erful . . . When I’m being flogged, . . . I struggle and wonder if I can take it all.
That struggle seems to make me stronger, and soon I feel intense energy run-
ning through me, as if all the force with which the whip is thrown at me is
injected into me, becomes my energy to play with. While my tops throw the
whips at me as hard as they can, I take in their power and dance in the center
of their storm (17).
These violent images are, of course, outside the range of The Composer’s Voice;
it is remarkable that they replicate Cone’s psychology of listening so closely.
As Cone might have put it, to listen to music is to grant the persona “power-
over” our inner voice; or better, it is to make the persona’s power into the
“power-with” that we share.
In relation to my present argument, the match between Cone’s account
of listening and this account of masochistic subjectivity suggests, at the least,
that Cone has developed his views in a plausible, non-arbitrary way. Starting
with an extreme contrast between the power of the persona and the sub-
mission of the listener, Cone attributes to listeners the same mingling of sub-
ordination and identification that some S&M bottoms report in their own,
similarly-structured experiences, and in a way this confirms Cone’s
account.22
I have argued that Forte and Cone share a starting point in treating each
composition as the product of a powerful controlling force, and I observed
the disciplined subject of musical analysis 37
that Forte’s text has little to say about listening, despite proclaiming its
importance. If you want to add an account of listening to the shared con-
ception of musical compositions, The Composer’s Voice offers such an account.
Cone describes sharply contrasting roles. The powerful agency of the com-
positional persona finds its complement in the submission of the listener;
simultaneous identification with the persona complicates that submission.
Given the shared starting point, Cone’s book shows where Forte might end
up if he gave direct, sustained attention to the listener’s role. In particular,
Cone’s account describes a passivity, perhaps masochism, in listening, bring-
ing out traits that are commonly devalued and associated with femininity.
They are traits that some writers would surely wish to deny or disavow.
fort/da
In a well-known formulation, Anna Freud describes a common “defensive
mechanism”: someone who experiences aggression from outside may
respond by imitating the aggressive behavior. For instance, she tells the story
of a little boy who had been hurt by the dentist. He came to Freud’s home
and tried to cut various items—a piece of rubber, a ball of string, some pen-
cils (Anna Freud 1966, 111–12). As Anna Freud puts it, “by impersonating
the aggressor, assuming his attributes or imitating his aggression, the child
transforms himself from the person threatened into the person making the
threat” (113). One active/passive pairing gives way to another; in the first,
the subject is passive and then, repudiating the passive role, the same subject
becomes active instead. This account resembles Sigmund Freud’s descrip-
tion of the game of “fort” and “da” that a small boy played. As Sigmund Freud
interprets it, the child responded to his inability to control the disappear-
ance of his mother by inventing a game in which he threw away his toys, say-
ing “fort” (“gone”); with one toy on a string, he was able afterward to pull it
back and say “da” (“there”). He was “staging the disappearance and return
of the objects within his reach . . . At the outset he was in a passive situation—
he was overpowered by the experience; but, by repeating it . . . as a game, he
took on an active role” (Sigmund Freud 1961, 8–11). More broadly, Freud
identifies the active/passive antithesis as one of three basic “polarities” of
mental life. The goal of avoiding passivity is central to masculinity, which
routinely seeks the active role in active/passive complementary relationships
(Sigmund Freud 1963, 97).
These narratives, in which mastery comes through reversal of active and
passive roles, give a helpful model for understanding Forte’s essay. Forte’s
conception of a masterful, controlling force at the heart of each composition
tends to imply a subordinate, submissive role for listeners. The event of lis-
tening seems to bring together an active, controlling, perhaps aggressive
composition and a submissive, receptive listener. Cone writes about listeners
38 fred everett maus
notes
I presented versions of this paper at New York University (November 2000) and the
University of Virginia (February 2001), and benefited from stimulating discussion on
those occasions. I am especially grateful to Suzanne G. Cusick, Andrew Dell’Antonio,
Nadine Hubbs, and Katharine Eisaman Maus for reading drafts and responding with
insightful comments. Epigraph: Forte 1977, 7. The article appeared first in Journal of
Music Theory 3, no. 1 (April 1959): 1–30. I give page references to the 1977 version.
1. It is important, here and throughout, that I am writing about Forte’s essay,
rather than directly addressing Schenker’s ideas. Study of Schenker’s self-conception
and positioning of music theory is a separate, demanding enterprise, with a growing
literature. See, for instance, Dubiel 1990 or Snarrenberg 1997.
2. Snarrenberg (1994, 53), in his interesting treatment of the essay, notes that
40 fred everett maus
Forte mentions Schumann only once. For another discussion of Forte’s essay see
Kerman 1980. Marion A. Guck (1994) offers pertinent comments on another essay
by Forte.
3. Translation from Komar 1971, 16.
4. My description of the poem simplifies a little. Heine’s poem shows the lover’s
passivity and dependence but also shows, by describing the beloved as a “child” with
whom one might bargain (trading love for flowers and birds), a defensive attempt to
reverse roles, making the beloved seem dependent instead. Near the end of this essay
I will place such reversals at the center of my account of Forte. If my interpretation
of Forte’s essay is correct, the depiction of such a defensive reversal in the poem
would hardly make it more appealing to him.
5. Of course, I understand that Forte is commenting on a sketch by Schenker, and
that the omission of text is already present in the original analysis. Still, I think it is
fair to ask why he repeats this omission, especially since the music of this particular
song is odd and, in certain ways, mysterious without the words. Kerman (1980)
emphasizes the role of the poem in understanding the music. It is interesting, too, that
Forte chooses a song as his main example to introduce Schenker’s theories, as though
making a special point of Schenker’s, and his own, willingness to disregard verbal text.
6. Snarrenberg (1994, 51) states succinctly that Forte’s “reading of Freud seems
more colored by his reading of Schenker than vice versa.” However, ideas of psy-
choanalysis in the 1950s were often scientistic, and Forte’s general conception of psy-
choanalysis as, ideally, an objective, impersonal science would have been widely
shared. Much later twentieth-century psychoanalytic thought has worked to dimin-
ish this scientific allure.
7. A third kind of control comes from the obligatory nature of music’s power.
Cone is not content to say just that someone might choose to yield control to the com-
poser, as one possible relation to music: obscurely but insistently, he states that you
must yield control. (Must? Why? What if you don’t?) “When we listen to music, whether
with words or not, we must follow it as if it were our own thought. We are bound to it”
(156). His account of performance is similar: “The ‘convincing’ interpretation is the
one that forces its listener to follow it, no matter whether he knows the piece by heart
or has never heard it before” (138–39). And, in a passage I already quoted, Cone
asserts that operatic unity “forces us to look for a wider intelligence at work.”
8. It is not quite clear in Cone’s text whether the persona is the force that acts on
listeners: various passages seem to identify the music (145), the performers (137), or
the composer (in the passages just cited) as exerting this control. On the other hand,
Cone disparages listeners who experience music through imaginary relationships to
real performers rather than fictional agents or personae (119–21). An interesting
account emerges if you think of the imaginary persona as dominating the listener,
but the text leaves Cone’s intentions unclear, and perhaps he did not think the issue
through. A more intricate account, with which I shall not burden the present essay,
can acknowledge and interpret Cone’s unclarity on this issue.
9. The lack of clarity comes partly from verbal ambiguity: “domination. Or bet-
ter . . . to make the composer’s voice our own.” What does Cone mean when he
says that the second alternative is “better”? Does he mean that the formulation in
terms of identification is more accurate? Should it replace the formulation in
terms of domination? Or is Cone describing two different possibilities, two rela-
the disciplined subject of musical analysis 41
tionships to the composer’s voice, and saying that the second is preferable? Or
should the two relationships be taken together somehow? In this essay I suggest
that domination and identification co-exist in the experiences Cone describes,
but exploration of alternative readings would be fruitful, in ways I have set aside
for present purposes.
10. The background-to-foreground approach, characteristic of Schenker’s essays,
is less characteristic of Forte’s pedagogical writings. The textbook Introduction to
Schenkerian Analysis by Forte and Steven E. Gilbert (New York: W. W. Norton, 1982)
emphasizes reduction, the elimination of detail to move toward middleground and
background levels. The review by Dubiel (Musical Quarterly 70, no. 2 [Spring 1984]:
269–78) notes this departure from Schenker’s procedures.
11. Recently Benjamin has offered an alterative to this view; see W. E. Benjamin
1999, 112.
12. And Benjamin, in the heat of anti-modernist polemic, suggests that the com-
position of middlegrounds satisfies an otherwise frustrated desire for tonal compo-
sition: “If one subscribes to the notion of Schenkerian analysis as a kind of traditional
composition, it follows that many creative musicians will turn to it as a way of grati-
fying their impulses to work in a language which is natural to them” (168).
13. I am drawing on the useful vocabulary of Walton 1990.
14. Notice, by the way, that this conception of imaginary composition is in ten-
sion with another aspect of Forte’s language that I emphasized before, the specifica-
tion of certain musical elements as controlling or subordinating others. That is, one
conception treats musical elements as fictional characters, the other describes a fic-
tional creator who stands outside, and controls, all the musical material. I have iden-
tified similar tolerance of apparently contradictory descriptions in Maus 1988; Guck
(1994) also makes this point about imaginative language in analytical writing.
15. In referring to the persona in a Schenkerian analysis, then, I am not referring
to that other all too audible voice, Schenker’s own violent, vivid self-depiction—a
creature that could also be referred to, in a different usage, as the “persona” of a
Schenkerian text.
16. Cone (1989) acknowledges that analysis takes you out of the fast-paced,
sequential time of listening. But he emphasizes that the goal of analysis lies in the
return to an enhanced experience of music in real time. Unlike Cone, Schenkerian
analysts seldom try to tell this story to the end.
17. The crucial contributions are McClary 1991 and Brett, Wood, and Thomas
1994.
18. Cone’s own abstract of the essay in RILM is chastely technical, and summa-
rizes the sexual content thus: “As a final conjecture, an attempt is made to connect
this meaning with specific events of Schubert’s life” (RILM No. 82–01540-ap).
19. Curtis 2000 is valuable for its unusually direct and politically committed
account of Don Giovanni’s relation to the women in the opera.
20. There is a bit more in Cone’s interpretation. The interaction continues as the
two characters trade inconclusive, briefer phrases in a middle section. Then, when
they return to the opening material, they trade material back and forth rapidly, com-
pleting each other’s musical thoughts, while the text shows Zerlina on the verge of
assent. At the same time, when either one falls silent, an instrument continues in the
same vocal register, a subtle touch. “When the flute doubles Don Giovanni’s voice . . .
42 fred everett maus
performer and music (with no clear role for the audience). Marion Guck makes a
similar shift. She writes eloquently of the power of music: “Experience of music’s
power is definitive of music loving. The powers I’ve described seem to me genuinely
part of close involvement with music. I can understand intellectually how they might
seem so disturbing that one would want to deny them. However, I cannot say that
these experiences feel dangerous to me, nor can I endorse denying them” (1997,
347–48). But, in moving to a sustained example, a passage from a Mozart piano con-
certo, Guck suddenly places herself in the role of pianist, thereby taking on agency
in the production of the music (1997, 348–50). Again, as in Cusick, the audience dis-
appears from this scene of performance.
26. Recent publications cover an enormous methodological range, including psy-
chological and psychoanalytical theory, ethnography, social history, literary criticism,
political advocacy (pro and con), and fiction. Hanly 1995 includes a selection of
important psychoanalytical papers. The volume Masochism, trans. Jean McNeil
(1989), joins Leopold von Sacher-Masoch’s short novel Venus in Furs and an influen-
tial essay, “Coldness and Cruelty,” by Gilles Deleuze. Other recent work includes Cal-
ifia 1988; Stoller 1991; “A Poem is Being Written,” in Sedgwick 1993, 177–214; Noyes
1997; Hart 1998; Savran 1998; and much more. It is an especially active area of
research and writing.
27. I presented early versions of the interpretation of Forte (the origin of the first
four sections of this essay) at the joint meeting of the American Musicological Soci-
ety, Society for Music Theory, and Society for Ethnomusicology, Oakland, 1990, and
at the conference Feminist Theory and Music, Minneapolis, 1991. Other material
dates from 2000–2001.
two
Musical Virtues
mitchell morris
i
“Lamah ragashu goyim?”
Musicological tempers were short in the ’90s, and only recently seem to have
settled into a sullenness that still occasionally flares into rancor. Many
thoughtful and serious scholars hold incommensurate points of view with
great conviction and vehemence, and find little success in persuading oppo-
nents or often even in eliminating smaller disagreements between their own
positions and those of their philosophical allies. Journals, newsletters, inter-
net sites, even some of the (quasi-)mass media, all register this intellectual
conflict, and AMS presidents and others have frequently spoken out in
attempts to reconcile the various segments of the field, or at least to establish
more moderate tones of discussion. As society has gone, so has the Society:
everyone’s feelings, it seems, are especially delicate around the turn of the
millennium.
But why should it be that disagreements in musicology (not to mention
many other fields and areas of cultural endeavor) are so often vexed and vex-
ing? Sociologist of philosophy Randall Collins (1999) has argued that con-
flict in intellectual domains is a necessary stimulus to creativity, and orga-
nized by particular structural features of that intellectual field: the
composition and history of institutions; cultural capital derived from earlier
intellectual work; ideological and personal ties (friendly or hostile) among
scholars; a necessarily limited attention-field within which competition takes
place; and the contingencies of the larger history that itself defines the
course and prospects of intellectual fields. This model is enormously instruc-
tive and leads to fascinating and productive ways of thinking about the his-
tory and shape of musical scholarship—and of particular interest is its
44
musical virtues 45
that in this essay I do not discuss in any detail the ways that my project
inevitably resonates with those ongoing in the work of a number of other
scholars, in both philosophy and in music; aside from a very few notes that
gesture toward work with which my own project must in the future engage,
I will proceed as if from relatively bare discursive ground. By way of a con-
clusion, I will move to several short discussions that lay out some examples
of the starting places from which the kinds of criticism I have in mind might
begin to flourish.
One of the problems with such a notion arises from the way that it inevitably
favors only a narrow range of possibilities among various musics—those are
specifically the panromanogermanic canon of the eighteenth and nine-
teenth centuries, with a few stragglers in the twentieth century.2 Most music
has never aspired to the autonomy demanded in the model of structural lis-
tening, and so it must be consigned to a lesser position.
Second, although the kind of music elevated by structural listening must
demonstrate its rationality by subordinating itself to some unifying principle
(in practice the principle of motivic development), this kind of subordina-
tion is characteristic of only a limited range of works within the panro-
manogermanic canon itself. Furthermore, this rationality, while a powerful
criterion for success as determined by structural listening, seems to require
balance by the musical establishment of a complex sonic-intentional domain
that can be interpreted as signs of individuality, but it is exactly such indi-
viduality that can be spoken of within models of structural listening only with
the greatest difficulty. This leads us as scholars into poor and misleading
arguments. (Simply consider our notorious failure to provide convincing
analytical accounts of the music of Ockeghem.) All in all, such difficulties
seem in Subotnik’s understanding to limit unacceptably our abilities as
scholars and listeners to engage with a wide variety of musics, a wide variety
of interpretive possibilities.
philosophers. But MacIntyre goes to great lengths to point out that not only
are these two solutions vulnerable on many logical grounds, they also have
no historical record of effectiveness at all. He dramatically proposes that for
such reasons, they be discarded in favor of ethical thinking that employs the
older concept of “virtue.” But such a concept can only be understood
through historical accounts.
comprehensive synthesis of the two models took place. The specifics of this
synthesis matter less for MacIntyre’s overall narrative than his idea that, how-
ever briefly, a coherent picture of moral reasoning was established. It is this
synthesis that was rejected during the Reformation and the Enlightenment,
resulting in the confused moral landscape within which MacIntyre’s enquiry
begins.6
If we accept MacIntyre’s argument that the models of moral reasoning
that took hold in the Enlightenment were in the end internally incoherent,
and that our most plausible hope of making sense requires the restoration
of the notion of virtue in its Classical sense, how are we to do so without
recourse to clearly superseded ideological accompaniments? (I am thinking
here of Aristotle’s “metaphysical biology,” and his damaging unhistorical
assumptions that the polis, as the highest political organization established by
natural law, demands the exclusion of numerous human beings, notably
women, slaves, and anyone at all who works.) MacIntyre proposes that we
substitute highly specific forms of social telos for the biological telos charac-
teristic of Aristotle’s account. The substitution requires definitions of the
terms “practice” and “tradition” so that virtue can be understood to operate
within them, as well as an emphasis on the notion of the self as narratively
constituted.
A practice is
The circularity of this definition is crucial: in our attempts not only to hold
to the standards of a practice but also to surpass them, we interrogate and
gain space to improve those very standards. The grounding of this definition
in MacIntyre’s description of virtue from Homer to Aquinas is apparent. The
account in After Virtue goes on to outline the difference between the general
concept of a practice and more specific activities that we could call “tech-
nique,” and to make clear that the range of practices is wide enough to
encompass music and farming, teaching and some understandings of poli-
tics. To be engaged in the practice of music—any of a number of practices
of music—requires skill in producing the appropriately “organized sounds,”
but producing sounds does not encompass the whole of what we mean by the
practice of music. I take it that we acknowledge this when we praise or blame
specific performances on grounds larger than those of particular errors of
execution, including those difficult to articulate sensations and intuitions we
54 mitchell morris
this Good also requires that it present itself as universal and not open for
debate. This complex sequence of assumptions establishes an image that has
as much potential imaginative power, it seems to me, as Plato’s myth of the
cave: call it the myth of the sounding noumenon, maybe. But I fear that few
of these assumptions may be true. The power of the image may chiefly come
from a poignant sense that it cannot be sustained.
ii
Johannes Brahms, Intermezzo, op. 118, no. 2
It is most true, stylus virum arguit,—our style betrays us.
robert burton, Anatomy of Melancholy
with several more general musical features, from which we might begin a
consideration of the ethics of lateness in this Intermezzo. Listening to the
opening gesture of the piece, I am always struck by how close it is to ending
by the second measure, and yet how reluctant it is to close. The affective ten-
sion at the beginning is mostly the result of the extended D-major triad in
second inversion, which is audibly “unreal”: the ear (well, my ear) pulls vainly
at the upper-hand Dn and Fs at the beginning of measure 1 in the hopes that
they will follow the lead of the initial right-hand notes and fall to Cs and En,
and when Brahms intensifies this desire by pushing on to the expansive tenth
of An and Fs at the downbeat of measure 2, the push to ending seems inten-
sified. And yet the music carries on. If we must think in structural terms, we
can note that the tonic triad of A major is only genuinely resolved at the very
ends of the A sections, and thus we are able to hear the need for resolution
in the opening two bars as partially satisfied by the music’s fall to the domi-
nant in measure 4, by changing inversions and assisting the tonicization of
the dominant in the following phrase.16 Was this chord a functional but
strangely placed subdominant, or was it a temporarily unresolved melodic
shape? Both, of course, and movingly unsatisfactory either way.
It’s no great art to begin a piece in the German canonical tradition with a
gesture of farewell, and its quality of commonplaceness is part of the point.
The emotions that ought to accompany a phrase such as “there is nothing
new under the sun” will most clearly appear when even the threat of newness
seems to be excluded. It follows as well that we are summoned to assume stock
emotional responses at the very beginning of this piece, but as the music con-
tinues, we might realize: (1) that the very ordinariness of stock emotional
responses, though usually regarded as the source of their unsatisfactoriness,
can be understood as on the contrary part of what makes them worthy of as
much attention as those rare and thrilling “original” responses—the
omnipresence in life of stock emotions, treated here artistically, might begin
to suggest something of their intrinsic value within the frames of human lives;
(2) that, in any case, stock emotional responses can be understood as much
more nuanced than we are ordinarily inclined to think, such that their typo-
logical nature ought not to preclude them from being taken seriously. The
music of this Intermezzo in this way begins to be reminiscent of the poetry of
someone like Thomas Hardy, in which verse after verse reveals how conven-
tional poetic emotions turn out to be immensely rewarding and subtle.
Pessimism and its attendant emotions are multifarious, perhaps always
more so than simple happiness, and this is again apparent in the Intermezzo
in places such as the lovely sad melody that opens the B section of the piece.
One of the most affecting points in the melody occurs at measure 54; this is
the second measure of a phrase that acts as both a very weak consequent and
also amplification of the initial phrase in the B section. The affective weight
is for me concentrated in the right-hand minor sixth, Gs/En, an appoggiatura
musical virtues 61
that clearly means to sink down by step to Fs/Dn, but never does so. There
are several larger reasons to care about this unresolved appoggiatura. First,
the unresolved Gs sits a tritone away from the root of the chord, and this
sonority often tends to appear in situations of longing (cf. the famous first
resolution in the Prelude to Tristan as an obvious example), and tritone
appoggiaturas appear in a number of places in this Intermezzo. Moreover, the
antecedent phrase of the B section is importantly out of kilter metrically, and
measure 54 is ironically the moment when the metrical planes seem to be
coming back into alignment. The hanging appoggiatura can begin to stand
in for numerous other moments in the Intermezzo where what is implicitly
promised, what is so nearly immediate that longing begins to be replaced by
satisfaction, in the end falls away into lack. Even the deliberately weakened
final cadence—a resolution oddly “inauthentic” in its voicing—sounds hol-
low. It begins to seem as if lack is the normal state of affairs in this piece, as
indeed it is in human life, and we can push this line of thought further in
connection with the piece by coming to interpret it as a way of teaching us
what it means to live with reduced expectations, to learn to reveal this
poverty as partially (though only partially) compensated for by art, and thus
to find a way of showing that regret, like death, is the mother of beauty.
iii
Steve Reich, Come Out
We flinch and grin,
Our flesh oozing towards its last outrage.
That which is taken from me is not mine.
geoffrey hill, “I Had Hope When
Violence Was Ceas’t”
Steve Reich’s 1966 piece Come Out begins with a real voice. To quote Reich’s
own program notes:
it was originally part of a benefit presented at Town Hall in New York City for
the re-trial, with lawyers of their own choosing, of the six boys arrested for mur-
der during the Harlem riots of 1964. The voice is that of Daniel Hamm, now
acquitted and then 19, describing a beating he took in Harlem’s 28th precinct
station. The police were about to take the boys out to be “cleaned up” and were
only taking those that were visibly bleeding. Since Hamm had no actual open
bleeding he proceeded to squeeze open a bruise on his leg so that he would be
taken to the hospital. “I had to like open the bruise up and let some of the
bruise blood come out to show them.” (Reich 1987)
Reich deserves credit, certainly, for his desire to account for the social and
personal particulars of his piece, but such specificity is also clearly necessary
62 mitchell morris
to the aesthetic or ethical trajectory of Come Out. It matters a lot that we are
listening to Hamm’s voice in all its grainy individuality, with its accent and
idiosyncrasies of pace and pronunciation intact, and that his voice is describ-
ing a specific assault not only on his bodily integrity but also and more
importantly on his claims to dignity. There’s no question of us understand-
ing the text, because it’s repeated in full three times before Reich’s musical
processes begin their work (this takes up the first 20 seconds of the piece).
When the music launches into its sequence of repetitions of the final
phrase, “come out to show them,” however, interpretation must take
multiple but probably incompatible directions. By approximately thirty rep-
etitions of the phrase (up to around 1'8") we can hear that some slow trans-
formation is taking place: Hamm’s speech acquires more and more rever-
beration, and after the first minute of the piece gradually dissociates into first
two vocal layers, then more and more fragments of sound, panning between
speakers. Within three minutes the pitch centers of each syllable (approxi-
mately between Dn/Bn/Cs and Ef/Cn/Dn according to my piano) become
more distinct, and the specific syllables fade increasingly into the back-
ground, sibilants, dentals, then finally guttural. That is, the words “come out”
stay in the texture until around 8'40" in part because C, the only guttural con-
sonant and the first consonant of the phrase, can retain its individuality
under the pressure of Reich’s tape manipulations far longer than the nasal
M or the sibilants S and TH, and even longer than the dental T.
To return to the relentless progress of the music, by minute 4 Daniel
Hamm’s words are increasingly submerged in musical process, and even the
residual presence of the words “come out,” which begin to seem like a bass
part, fades by about 8'40". The remaining approximately four minutes of the
piece are a ferocious continuation of abstract procedures.
Critics who have written on Come Out have mostly concentrated on the way
it was made—the kind of account most likely to persuade readers who are
committed to the tenets of structural listening.17 But Reich’s own words on
the technique of composition are much more relevant for a consideration
of ethics: “By using recorded speech as a source of electronic or tape music,
speech-melody and meaning are presented as they naturally occur. By not
altering its pitch or timbre, one keeps the original emotional power that
speech has while intensifying its melody and its meaning through repetition
and rhythm” (Reich 1987). Reich furthermore mentions his interest in the
poetry of William Carlos Williams, Charles Olson, and Robert Creely as a way
of connecting Come Out to his other work, presenting the piece as a problem
in the setting of American speech as well as invoking the poets’ interest in
the connection between art and distinctively American ways of world-
making. But the central point to be taken up in an ethical hearing of Come Out
might best begin from Reich’s claims that the locus of meaning in speech
comes from its connotative dimensions, so that emotion is the province of
musical virtues 63
speech as music. Note that his comments suggest a model in which music
and speech shade into one another, and speech itself is internally divided
such that meaning is to “speech-melody” as thought is to emotion, or per-
haps idea is to body. We might conclude, then, that Reich would wish us to
hear the development of sound in Come Out as retaining the emotional con-
tent of Hamm’s narrative all of the way through the piece.
The problem is, content matters, and its gradual attenuation in Come Out
is difficult to interpret. But it is not that hard to provide exegetical possibil-
ities, and here is a short list:
object lost. What has been lost is not only the dignity of Daniel Hamm as a
human being, but also the dignity of his oppressors and the dignity of all
bystanders, and in fact this is an object that cannot be released without dev-
astating moral consequences. Reich’s obsessive repetitions take the structure
of mourning and allow it to shape the piece in such a way that Come Out acts
as a reliquary for pain and an attempt to offer it as recompense for what is
lost. That it can only fail makes the offer more moving.
iv
Trent Reznor/Nine Inch Nails, “Reptile”
If thou were to see in liknesse of fleisch and blood that blessed sacrament, thou
schuldest lothen and abhorren it to resseyve it into thy mouth.
john wycliffe, Elucidarium
In 1994, Trent Reznor, the author of the group Nine Inch Nails, released The
Downward Spiral, a remarkably grim work that nevertheless achieved notable
critical and commercial success; the song “Reptile” appears as track 12. Even
for an album permeated by revolting verbal and musical metaphors as well
as horrific violence, this song retains a striking ability to disgust. The open-
ing verse, for instance, combines repellent imagery that evokes contami-
nation, hybridity, decay, and putrescence, all in the service of vicious misog-
yny directed toward an ex-lover:
v
It is also true, lectio virum arguit: the examples I have chosen to discuss clearly
bespeak a particular set of moral interests and encourage reflection on var-
ious sets of virtues. These do not reduce to the overly simple kinds of fables
compiled by would-be Aesops such as William Bennett, because there are
multiple sets of potential virtues (and vices) in each piece I have offered up.
Nevertheless, it would be disingenuous not to acknowledge that I have
favored minor-mode affects and dispositions in my interpretations. In
Brahms’s Intermezzo, I tend to hear musical evocations of qualities such as
modesty and restraint, I contemplate the connection of these qualities to
feelings of reduced expectation and belatedness, and I remain impressed
musical virtues 67
that so much beauty can be wrung out of sadness. Reich’s Come Out also
works nearby with grief and violence, but in my hearing its interpretive tra-
jectory moves toward a more abstract intersubjectivity rather than the con-
struction of individualized, exemplary interiority. With Reznor’s song “Rep-
tile,” the hatred of self and other that drives the disgust at the heart of the
ascetic process offers, among other things, a location in which I note how the
difference between virtue and vice becomes a little harder to see.
In each case, my account is extremely partial, and were discussion to stop
there, the possibility of listening to and for virtue and vice would be stymied.
MacIntyre observes that it is only within the context of human relationships
that we can speak of morality; abstract principles of universal application
make a poor place from which to view the moral life precisely because they
are insufficiently attentive to the contingencies that make up human condi-
tions. I have suggested that structural listening is subject to similar criticisms.
If music—writing it, playing it, listening to it, talking about it—is to recover
its capacity to be recognized as a kind of moral activity with an important role
in shaping our understandings of what is good, then we must be able to speak
with one another about just those qualities, contentious, partial, and difficult
of definition, which are at present the ground of our disagreements. If we lis-
ten to the virtues of our music, perhaps we can listen to the virtues of the
music and speech of others. In some sense, music becomes like our Torah:
we are not required to complete the work; neither are we allowed to aban-
don it.
notes
1. Subotnik 1996, 150. See the introduction to this volume for further discussion
of Subotnik’s characterization of “structural listening”.
2. The term is of course Richard Taruskin’s. See the discussions in Taruskin 1997.
3. This supplementation can also lead to power relations that are (perhaps by
accident) morally suspect. Consider, for instance, the pedagogical problems posed
by I. A. Richards’s notorious New Critical primer Practical Criticism (1964). Assuming
that his task is to promulgate a quasi-Kantian view of poems, Richards in fact sys-
tematically withholds crucial contextual information from his test subjects, then
mean-spiritedly chides them for not being able to deduce the information from the
poems themselves. By a sleight of hand, the critic’s authority is thus placed beyond
question, hence beyond dialogue.
4. On this point see Williams 1993.
5. MacIntyre 1984, 122. The following summary depends on MacIntyre 1984,
chapters 10–13.
6. There is an interestingly ironic resonance between MacIntyre’s Aquinas and
Adorno’s Beethoven with respect to their crucial but poignantly brief synthesis of
moral worlds.
68 mitchell morris
20. Of particular importance here is Rimbaud’s concern with the artist as voyant,
plainly including all that term’s religious connotations. Also resonant are works such
as Bataille 1986. And Mario Praz’s classic work, The Romantic Agony (1970), could be
considered a basic guide to this tradition.
21. I have examined some aspects of the nineteenth-century sublime in Morris
1998. An especially interesting discussion of the affect of disgust is found in Miller
1997. A set of concerns closely related to the French and German traditions men-
tioned informs the work of writers such as Kathy Acker, J. G. Ballard, or Dennis
Cooper, all of whom have been cited in the contexts of Industrial music. And to
return to grotesqueries such as the marriage of corpses and machines, this kind of
fusion is a widespread thematic interest in much Industrial culture, and may be
thought of as another way of approaching the kinds of issues discussed in academic
contexts under the rubric of the Post-Human or the Cyborg.
three
In her critique of what she calls structural listening, Rose Subotnik departs
from the premise that music can be defined in terms of a binary opposition
between rational, abstract structures and sound or style, which in her account
includes aspects of music as diverse as medium, history, and corporeality.1
She argues that structural listeners have focused too adamantly on the struc-
turalist pole of this key binarism, thereby neglecting crucial aspects of musi-
cal experience. With the expression “structural listeners” she is referring in
particular to Arnold Schoenberg, Igor Stravinsky, and Theodor Adorno,
whose extensive theoretical writings she does not aim to analyze in detail
(especially in terms of contradictions, modifications over time, and
nuances), but rather to summarize conceptually, explicating them in terms
of broad common denominators. This focus leads her to define Schoen-
berg’s and Adorno’s differentiated approaches to listening “for present pur-
poses” “as one,” and to summarize Adorno’s contribution as that of
“locat[ing] musical value wholly within some formal sort of parameter, to
which it is the listener’s business to attend,” even though one of his central
Marxist arguments concerned the immanent historicity of musical material
(Subotnik 1996, 150 and 152–53). Her discussion of Stravinsky is similarly
focused: rather than investigate the practical considerations involved in
Stravinsky’s work as a ballet and theater composer, she defines his approach
to listening on the basis of his ghostwritten Poetics of Music of 1936, conclud-
ing that Stravinsky “celebrated the activity of musical construction and
would confine musical meaning within the boundaries of the individual com-
position, exclusive of contextual relationships and (at least in theory) of
intent” (152–53). Thus distilled to their essence, the principles of structural
listening can function ideally as one pole of Subotnik’s primary conceptual
binarism of form versus content/style.
70
the chosen one ’ s choice 71
I study Le Sacre from the perspective of musical gesture and dance not only
as a means of overcoming Subotnik’s dualistic approach, but also because I
feel that the neglect of this aspect of the work has led to misinterpretations
72 tamara levitz
astating consequences for his analysis of Stravinsky’s Le Sacre and for the
twentieth-century practice of ideologically critiquing music.
As is well known, Adorno countered the positive example of Schoenberg
with the negative model of Stravinsky. As Schoenberg’s dialectical opposite,
Adorno’s Stravinsky necessarily rejected organic musical development. In
works like Le Sacre, he renounced any attempt to “redeem or fulfill that which
had appeared in the immanent dynamic of the musical material as an expec-
tation or demand” (Adorno 1978, 138, note), and reduced his melodies to
“rudimentary successions of notes” or “cut off, primitivist patterns” that did
not develop and thus lacked the unfolding of a subjective being (139 and
note). Diatonic, folkloristic, and chromatic melodic particles bled together,
as if they had been randomly inserted, creating a contradiction between the
“restrained horizontal” and the “daring vertical” that resulted in chords
becoming coloristic rather than constructive (140). In many spots, pedal
points replaced “genuine” harmonic unfolding and harmonic development.
Yet Le Sacre most egregiously rejected the subject by ignoring “the dialectical
confrontation with the musical course of time . . . which has constituted the
essence of all great music since Bach” (171).10
Adorno’s perspective on musical subjectivity had little influence in North
America until Subotnik’s courageous critiques of the 1980s. They resurfaced
indirectly in Richard Taruskin’s work, however, especially as he attempted to
reintegrate ideological critique into the traditional discourse of music theory
throughout the 1990s.11 Chastising North American theorists for blindly
embracing music’s aesthetic autonomy, Taruskin campaigned for new inter-
pretive approaches that would take into account social, historical, and politi-
cal context. By asserting that what he called Stravinsky’s “fascism and anti-Semi-
tism” were an immanent aspect of his musical compositions, he hoped to
prove false the claim of his opponents that political attitudes and social cir-
cumstances existed parallel to, yet independent of, the music.12 In so doing, he
hoped to give Le Sacre back its history and to demand for it a moral reckoning.
Although Taruskin distanced himself from North American practices of
music theory, his interpretation of Le Sacre remained firmly grounded in a
“structural” theoretical approach. Frustrated by what he called the North
American obsession with composers’ lives, experiences, and intentions, and
by the “poietic fallacy,” the popular belief that the meaning of music was
exhausted in the story of its making, Taruskin based his work on what he
called “immanent criticism,” the study of musical structures as embodiments
of their maker’s political and social allegiances.13 Such analysis departed
from the premise that the “artistic qualities of the music, however narrowly
they may be defined or evaluated, are decisively—indeed internally —con-
nected with its conceptual metaphors” (Taruskin 1997, 461). Taruskin’s
“immanent criticism” of the music revealed a surprising intellectual turn: in
the chosen one ’ s choice 75
more specifically, to the story of the Chosen One. She remains the most dis-
turbing figure for both of them, and so it is to her that I now turn.
The cultural image of the Chosen One as a helpless victim without indi-
viduality, corporeality, or choice is so persistent in the secondary literature,
that one is compelled to ask where it came from. The best source seems to
be Stravinsky himself, who described how he understood the Chosen One in
a revealing dream that he claimed inspired Le Sacre and that is quoted rev-
erently in all accounts of its history: “One day, when I was finishing the last
pages of L’Oiseau de feu in St. Petersburg, I had a fleeting vision which came
to me as a complete surprise, my mind at the moment being full of other
things. I saw in imagination a solemn pagan rite: sage elders, seated in a cir-
cle, watched a young girl dance herself to death. They were sacrificing her to
propitiate spring.”18 Stravinsky made sure everybody knew that the ballet was
about this sacrifice of a chosen victim by originally calling his work Velikaya
zhertva [The Great Victim].19 His envisioned choreography suggested that
the Chosen One would not show any resistance to her fate: he planned “a
series of rhythmic mass movements of the greatest simplicity which would
have an instantaneous effect on the audience, with no superfluous details or
complications such as would suggest effort.”20
Taruskin often lamented the fact that so many scholars gave Stravinsky’s
comments ultimate authority in defining the meaning of his works. Given
Taruskin’s worries, it is surprising that both he and Adorno chose to adopt
wholesale Stravinsky’s vision of the Chosen One, without considering or
comparing it to Roerich’s or Nijinsky’s interpretations of that role. They both
defined the Chosen One, to a certain extent with Stravinsky, as lacking indi-
vidual choice, dancing vacuously, and ready to sacrifice herself without the
slightest hint of conflict with her community.
Adorno understood the Chosen One’s death, like Petruschka’s, as an
“antihumanistic sacrifice to the collectivity: a sacrifice without tragedy,
offered not to the image that was gradually arising of mankind, but rather
the blind confirmation of a condition that was recognized by the sacrificed
one herself, whether through self-ridicule or through self-effacement”
(Adorno 1978, 135–36). Solely on the basis of the synopsis of the ballet,
Adorno assumed that the Chosen One agreed to the collective will imposed
on her without showing resistance, opposition, subjective will, or tragic
incongruity. He concluded that “there is no aesthetic antithesis between the
sacrificed one and her tribe, rather, her dance carries out the unopposed,
direct identification with the latter. The subject exposes as little conflict as
the musical structure delivers” (147). Even the musical shocks in Le Sacre,
which Adorno understood as essential to avant-garde music (because of the
way in which they made the individual aware of his “futility against the gigan-
tic machine of the whole system”; 144), have been reduced to mere effects,
and thus create no sense of antagonism or conflict: “In Stravinsky there is
the chosen one ’ s choice 77
neither a readiness for fear nor an opposing ego; rather, it is accepted that
the shocks cannot be adopted by the musical subject, which gives up trying
to maintain itself and thus remains content with participating in the thrusts
(shocks) as reflexes” (145).
Adorno’s interpretation of the Chosen One was shaped by his under-
standing of dance, which he defined as “the static art of time, of turning itself
in circles, of movement without progress” (179). In his opinion, the music
of Le Sacre allowed only purely physical, almost ecstatic movement, separated
from emotional and intellectual thought:
[The body] is treated by the music as a means, as a thing that reacts exactly to
it; it obliges the body to perform at its maximum, as is drastically displayed on
stage in the “Jeu de Rapt” and the “Jeux de Cités Rivales.” The severity of Le
Sacre, which makes itself as insensitive to any stirring of subjectivity as the rit-
ual does to the pain of its initiates and sacrificial victims, is at the same time the
supreme command that forbids the body from expressing pain by permanently
threatening it, and which trains it to do the impossible as in the ballet, which
is the most important traditional element of Stravinsky’s work. Such severity
and ritual driving out of the soul contributes to the impression that Le Sacre as
a product has not been subjectively brought forth and is not reflective of
human beings. Rather it exists as a thing in and of itself. (Adorno 1978, 159)
Adorno concluded that the subject had been alienated from bodily sensation
in Le Sacre, resulting in a ballet that centered on a dancing body foreign to
itself (161). Haunted by the fear of communal and round dancing that dom-
inated in Germany in the post-Nazi years, Adorno condemned the Chosen
One’s dance as primitive, and based on a notion of collectivity that denied
the individual subject:
The Chosen One dances herself to death, in the same manner as anthropolo-
gists report that savages who have unknowingly broken a taboo actually die
thereafter. Nothing of her as an individual being is reflected in her dance than
the unconscious and coincidental reflex of pain: according to its inner orga-
nization, her solo dance is, like all others, a collective dance. It is a round dance
void of any dialectic of the general and the particular. Authenticity is obtained
through the denial of a subjective pole. This occupation of the collective stand-
point in the manner of a surprise attack causes the following to occur: at the
moment when an agreeable conformity to an individualistic society is dis-
missed, a conformity of a secondary and indeed highly disagreeable kind,
namely with a blind integral society, the same as one of castrated or headless
people, takes its place. (Adorno 1978, 147)
Stravinsky’s music showed little concern either for its own fate or for that of
the Chosen One: “The abomination is watched with some pleasure, and
shown not in a transfigured, but rather unalleviated fashion” (136). The sub-
ject ceased to exist musically: “The choreographic idea of the sacrifice
78 tamara levitz
shapes the musical treatment of the subject itself. In the music, and not on
the stage, everything is eradicated that distinguishes itself as individuated
from the collective” (145). The composition of Le Sacre thus equals a “dele-
tion of the self, unconscious skillfulness, fitting in to the blind totality”
(156).21 Dance “from the start forces the composition into a subservient posi-
tion and into renouncing its autonomy,” turning Le Sacre into a “parasite”
(179).22
This is a remarkable conclusion from someone who had probably never
seen Nijinsky’s original choreography of Le Sacre, and gave no indication of
having studied or seen any of the subsequent choreographies of the work
either.23 With striking confidence Adorno defined as objective truth the
visual fantasy he had dreamed up.24 Having never examined in any detail the
dynamics of the dancing body, he was probably not entirely aware that he
had reduced the Chosen One to a mechanized, abstract vision of human
corporeality.25 In his world, the body lacked the concrete presence of the
musical score he so cherished; it was an abstract idea without physicality and
subjectivity, whose movements necessarily remained meaningless.
Like Adorno before him, Taruskin defined Le Sacre’s politics on the basis
of the fact that “the ‘petty I’ [was given up] in the interests of . . . the absorp-
tion of the individual consciousness in the collective” (Taruskin 1995, 17).
His Chosen One became the individual (or non-individual) who had to sub-
jugate herself to the masses or collective subjectivity (das Volk) for the fascist
politics of Le Sacre to work. By adopting a subjectivity of the masses, or col-
lective ego, she allowed herself to be controlled from the outside by a leader
or Führer, who Taruskin hinted was Stravinsky or the conductor. Stravinsky
just has to put pen to manuscript paper in order to transform sensible
human beings into jerking, kicking automata.
Rather than explore the philosophical consequences of an imagined
dancing Chosen One, as Adorno did, Taruskin supported his claims about
her lack of choice by returning to immanent musical meaning. His study of
the score led him to conclude that Stravinsky, and not some false collectiv-
ity, had killed the Chosen One. The “terrible dynamism” of his “crashing
orchestra” in the “Danse sacrale” embodied the “opaque, constraining”
force of society, which inhumanely killed her, and coerced the audience into
sharing its point of view (Taruskin 1995, 20). Stravinsky had organized his
“cells” or “motivic tesserae” in her dance to heighten the antihuman effect
of “hypostatization—[or] extreme fixity of musical ‘objects’,” that repre-
sented the Chosen One’s lack of subjectivity (Taruskin 1996, 1:962–64). By
including a facsimile sketch for the music of this scene, he offered visual
proof for the authority of his interpretation. The reproduction emphasized
the physical presence and thus historical truth of the document. Taruskin
invited the reader to notice the age of the paper, the personal feel of the writ-
ing, and the impatience of Stravinsky’s scrawl, which could easily convince
the chosen one ’ s choice 79
him or her that the Chosen One’s death had resulted from an arbitrary and
somehow viciously unsympathetic compositional game on Stravinsky’s part.
Although dance is hardly central to Taruskin’s analysis, he does refer to it
when arguing about the Chosen One’s lack of choice and conflict. Instead of
analyzing existing choreographies of the work, however, he followed Adorno
in describing the Chosen One as dancing an ecstatic “whirling dance”
(Taruskin 1996, 1:886–87), inspired by a music that elicits “a primitive, kines-
thetic response.”26 He supported his argument by referring to anthropolog-
ical research on the whirling dances in Slavic ritual, which interested
Roerich and Stravinsky, and which he could associate with Le Sacre, in spite
of the fact that it was not danced that way.27 Taruskin found the ritualistic
dance he uncovered foreign to his sensibilities, and viewed its emotional
ecstasy, primitivism, and lack of rationality with suspicion.28 He lamented
that the choreography envisioned for the Chosen One was “devoid of plot
in the conventional sense,” and that it was a ritual with primitive immediacy,
rather than a represented narrative (1996, 1:865). In Adorno’s spirit he con-
cluded that “the maiden herself does not perform a culminating dance [at
all]; rather, one is done around her—in the presence of the Elders, as all ver-
sions of the Rite scenario specify” (1996, 1:886).
The image of a spinning female body was useful to Adorno and Taruskin,
because it allowed them to understand the Chosen One as lacking subjective
choice and corporeality. Their vision, so contrary to most actual danced ver-
sions of Le Sacre, says much more about them than about her. Like many oth-
ers before and after them, they have donned the bearskins and joined the
elders, to sit in the circle with Stravinsky and watch the Chosen One dance
herself to death. Using the authority of structural listening and the brilliant
wit of their lucid pens, they erase the Chosen One’s individuality from the Le
Sacre with dashing final strokes. She is not a subject, but rather a twirling
image, a silent victim, an empty canvas, a wispy curl of smoke, a spinning
arabesque, thin air.
In spite of their shared ideas about spinning female bodies, Adorno and
Taruskin came to different conclusions about Stravinsky’s Le Sacre. Adorno
accused Stravinsky of having tried to achieve an authenticity that was no
longer possible in his time. He glorified the negation of the individual sub-
ject, thereby neglecting the critical role of art and betraying his mission as
an avant-garde artist. His regressive music entertained, lulled, and mollified
its audiences, preventing them from developing their critical potential. Yet
what was most pitiful was that Stravinsky had pretended that this “retrogres-
sion of musical language and of the state of consciousness appropriate to it
was up to date” (Adorno 1978, 137).
In contrast to Adorno, Taruskin is neither a Marxist nor a historical mate-
rialist, and has no allegiance to either the Hegelian objective spirit or
Geschichtsphilosophie. Instead of backing up his claims about Le Sacre with a
80 tamara levitz
over seventy years and may have begun with Stravinsky himself. Although the
composer at first admired Nijinsky’s choreography,31 by 1921 he had rejected
it as too bound to the “tyranny of the barline.”32 Stravinsky’s reasons for con-
demning Nijinsky may have been partly financial (in that he may have been
trying to get Nijinsky’s share of one-quarter of Le Sacre’s royalties), and partly
aesthetic (in that by 1921 he had adopted what was to become his neoclassi-
cal aesthetic). Whatever the case, the damage he did to Nijinsky, and the
degree to which he distorted the original Sacre, was considerable. This legacy
of violent refusal is still felt in Pieter van den Toorn’s Stravinsky and “The Rite
of Spring”: The Beginnings of a Musical Language (1987). Van den Toorn inves-
tigates the origins of Le Sacre in dance in the introduction to his book. But
rather than enrich his analysis with the information he finds, he proceeds to
reject the very interpretative path he has dared to open up: “the scenario
itself, the choreography, and, above all, the close ‘interdisciplinary’ condi-
tions of coordination under which the music is now known to have been
composed—these are matters which, after the 1913 premiere, quickly passed
from consciousness,” van den Toorn writes, “like pieces of scaffolding, they
were abandoned in favor of the edifice itself and relegated to the ‘extra-musi-
cal.’ They became history, as opposed to living art” (van den Toorn 1987, 2).
He implies through his use of passive voice that unseen and unknown forces
rather than developments in contemporary music, philosophy, and the dis-
cipline of music theory stripped Le Sacre of its history. He feels confident in
reducing Le Sacre to “the music itself” because he had the support of Stravin-
sky himself, whose process of rejecting Le Sacre’s original staging and chore-
ography he describes in careful historical detail. His well-researched and
informative history of the reception of the Le Sacre leads him to the disturb-
ing conclusion that the new sources linking the work to its original chore-
ography were “enlightening as commentary, [but] in no way undermine the
integrity of The Rite as ‘musical construction’ ” (21). Stravinsky may have
remembered the original choreography fondly in his late years and desired
a revival, but van den Toorn considers this a slip in judgment (16–17).33
There are several reasons why van den Toorn and many others have
rejected Nijinsky’s contribution to Le Sacre. First of all he was a dancer, and
thus the creator of an ephemeral art that could not be captured in rational
analysis or linked ontologically to music. Second, he was also mentally ill, suf-
fering from what Peter Ostwald later clinically categorized as both manic-
depressive psychosis and schizoaffective disorder in a narcissistic personality,
which caused him to be hospitalized in 1919 (Ostwald 1991, 349–50). This
illness, from which he never recovered and which kept him in and out of
institutions until his death in 1950, lead many commentators from the 1920s
on to assume tacitly that he had always been “crazy” and that his choreo-
graphic work was thus somehow invalid.34 Finally, Nijinsky was a bisexual
whose sexuality frightened and confused many people, during his time and
82 tamara levitz
long afterwards. One need only read Acocella, Garafola, and Greene’s vivid
description of who caused the sexual violence in Le Sacre:
The notion of an “art plastique” that would combine drama, music, and
dance into a new form of artistic communication was very much on the minds
of French critics at the time of Le Sacre’s premiere, and found its intellectual
and visual formulation six months later in a special issue of the journal Mont-
joie.38 Ricciotto Canudo, Auguste Rodin, André Biguet, and others described
a new type of dance that they associated with the Futurist dancer Valentine
de Saint-Point, and with a composer who wrote for her, Erik Satie.39 “Meta-
chorie” (as Saint-Point called her invention) originated in the spirituality of
ancient myth and yet was realized in the modern forms of geometry.40 It
required “equivocal bodies,” which had neither the female nor male attri-
butes, and which acted in space according to “the relation of body mass.”41
Although Isadora Duncan had initiated this dance revolution by recreating
“plastic Greek myths,” she had made the drastic mistake of trying to dance
to sentimental and expressive nineteenth-century music. In contrast, the pro-
moters of “metachorie” envisioned a music that would itself embody the idea
of the dance, and found such an art form first realized in Le Sacre:
Expressive music needs conventional, banal, and even anti-artistic mime.
Dance does not succeed in translating artistic emotions with facial expressions.
What is really deep is the spirit, the gesture, the line that unrolls simultaneously
in depth and breadth. It is the dynamism of the two dimensions that creates the
marvelous beauty of dance and that nostalgically haunts the minds of painters.
Choreographic music must also develop in spatial depth. It must be con-
structed architecturally and rhythmically, in broad values and plans, like the
groups of Rodin, in order to mix with the geometric schemes of the choreog-
raphy and to penetrate it. This music was born with Le Sacre du Printemps.
Before that, there was dramatic music, descriptive music, and even so-called
pure music: since then there is choreographic music, fashioned in a certain
sense plastically according to the rhythm of the idea, in order to form with the
dance a new synthetic communion . . . For this to happen the essential idea
must encrust itself simultaneously in the being of the musician as musical
rhythms, and in the being of the choreographer as plastic rhythms. There has
to be an absolutely intimate penetration. (Chennevière 1914)
Although the contributors to the journal did not seem to think that Nijinsky
had been as successful as Saint-Point at realizing such music in dance, they
comment frequently on the importance of his choreography as “art plas-
tique.” The editor of Montjoie, Ricciardo Canudo, accompanied the reprint
of his manifesto on “art cérébriste,” as well as other articles in the issue, with
Valentine Gross-Hugo’s illustrations of the choreography of Le Sacre. In their
minds, Stravinsky’s Sacre was inextricably intertwined with Nijinsky’s chore-
ography as plastique animée.42
By January 1914, Stravinsky no longer agreed with the authors writing for
Montjoie. In 1912, however, he had been delighted to work with Nijinsky, to
whom he referred as “the ideal plastique collaborator.”43 From March to
84 tamara levitz
November 1912 they had met on more than five occasions (including a trip
to Venice), to work on Le Sacre.44 For a short time, their opinions on how
dance should express meaning corresponded.
one arm in 3/4 and the other in 4/4. Diaghilev had been so inspired that he
had hired Jaques-Dalcroze’s student Marie Rambert to supervise the
rehearsals of Le Sacre in Monte Carlo in winter 1913.51 According to Nijinska,
Nijinsky himself performed such rhythmic counterpoints with ease. She
reported that he was so precise in translating rhythm into movement that he
could perform a 5/4 bar in midair. He first leapt into the air. “On beat 1 he
bent one leg at the knee and stretched his right arm above his head, on count
2 he bent his body towards the left, on count 3 he bent his body towards the
right, then on count 1, still high in the air, he stretched his body upwards
again and then finally came down lowering his arm on count 2, graphically
rendering each note of the uneven measure.”52 Nijinsky understood such an
approach to dance, in the spirit of Jaques-Dalcroze’s followers, as “plastique
animée,” and as a means of linking movement to feeling and training the
spirit through the body.53 He drew on these lessons when designing the
“Danse sacrale,” in which he gave the Chosen One an individual movement
for every event in Stravinsky’s music, translating it note for note into dance.
The “Danse sacrale” thus offers the rare example of a choreography in which
musical cells or motives are directly, literally associated with the specific ges-
tures of a dancing body. By using Dalcroze’s approach (which also appealed
to Stravinsky) Nijinsky gave each of the Chosen One’s gestures expressive
power and symbolic significance.54 Together, these gestures constituted her
identity as she danced through time. Through such detailed movement she
expressed her opposition to the people who had chosen her to die. Her
movements were immediate, yet not primitively void of subjective will and
choice, as Adorno and Taruskin imagined.
How does one begin to recover the lost movements Nijinsky felt commu-
nicated so much about how he understood Le Sacre and the choices of its Cho-
sen One? Perhaps the answer lies in the very real, twisting, tense, springing,
angry body of Nijinsky, as it moved in a humid practice room in Vienna or
London in winter 1913. Nijinsky, intense and concentrated, is teaching his
sister Nijinska the movements of the Chosen One’s “Danse sacrale.” Frus-
trated, he asks the rehearsal pianist, Steiman, to play over and over again
individual passages of the handwritten score that Stravinsky had sent him.55
Mesmerized by the tragedy of Nijinsky’s movements as he performs the
dance for her, Nijinska tries to visualize the dark clouds gathering in
Roerich’s painting The Call of the Sun, and to imagine what he has described
to her as the “awakening of the spirit of primeval man” (Nijinska 1992,
449–50). The room is filled with physical tension and conflict—the tighten-
ing of muscles that we will have to learn to remember if we are going to do
justice to the Chosen One.
What was Nijinsky expressing through the movements he created in that
forgotten practice room over eighty years ago? The dominant emotion, from
all accounts, seems to have been exactly what Adorno and Taruskin find miss-
86 tamara levitz
ing in Le Sacre: fear and a deep antagonism between the Chosen One and her
surroundings.56 Nijinsky experienced Stravinsky’s music in Taruskin’s spirit
as “some kind of monster, breathing evenly as it got nearer and nearer, a
monster with many hands, many legs, many eyes” (Krasovskaya 1979, 234).
He wanted the Chosen One to react to this horror with terror and outrage—
over her tragic fate and her helplessness in face of it. She would express her
anger through body tension, which Nijinsky created by choosing positions
and movements that contained the energy of the moving body, such as turn-
ing the feet inwards or holding the elbows close to the torso.57 No matter how
jagged and distorted Nijinsky’s movements became, he would never lose the
sense of rooting them in his “extraordinarily profound sense of his own cen-
ter,” creating a tornado of contained energy.58 This movement would not be
casual or light, but rather “conscious right down to its last detail” (Krasovskaya
1979, 244). In order to communicate to his sister how to express the emotion
he associated with such an intense exaggeration of body tension, he told her
that her body had to “draw into itself . . . and absorb the fury of the hurricane”
(Garafola 1989, 71; Nijinska 1992, 470). His performance of the Chosen
One’s dance expressed this tragic confrontation with fate: “With clenched fist
across his face, he threw himself into the air in paroxysms of fear and grief.
His movements were stylized and controlled, yet he gave out a tremendous
power of tragedy.”59
Nijinsky expressed the Chosen One’s painful confrontation with her com-
munity in Le Sacre by creating physical tension within her very body. This
choreographic practice contrasted starkly with “academic ballet [that]
emphasized effortless surface tension to obliterate any hint of energy
expended” (Kirstein 1976, 145). Through her knotted, tense body, the Cho-
sen One expressed all the conflict missing in Adorno and Taruskin—a con-
frontation between her own subjective will and the crushing threat of her
community and her fate.
One can speculate widely on the sources of Nijinsky’s angry passion for
the Chosen One. If Lynn Garafola is correct in arguing that she is a “creation
of twentieth-century male sexual anxiety,” and that she “takes the place of
the feminized artist,” than it would not be entirely misguided to interpret her
as representing Nijinsky himself, in which case his investment in her would
be self-explanatory.60 By the time of Le Sacre, audiences in France had
marked Nijinsky as a feminized artist or androgynous, exotic, foreign and
mysterious Other—an image Diaghilev had promoted, perhaps at Nijinsky’s
expense, by casting him in roles such as the Golden Slave in Schéhérezade or
in the Spectre de la rose. With Nijinsky, ballet had also become overnight a
“privileged arena for homosexuals as performers, choreographers, and spec-
tators”—a gay revolution that forced the women who had traditionally dom-
inated the ballet into the back seat.61 Nijinsky later struggled with this sexu-
ality, especially in his diary of 1919. It is possible that the community’s threat
the chosen one ’ s choice 87
in Le Sacre reminded him of the hostility toward his sexuality that he experi-
enced in his own life and subsequently internalized. He also created Le Sacre
in a hostile atmosphere, albeit of a very different kind, in which most of the
dancers rejected what he was doing (Nijinska 1992, 462). By not dancing the
role himself, but rather forcing his sister and then, when she got pregnant,
Maria Piltz, to dance it exactly as he wished, Nijinsky may have been experi-
menting with expressing his own desires through a female body.62 This may
explain why he was so passionate about the role, and why he did not want the
Chosen One to submit to the violence perpetrated on her. He expressed his
feeling of victimization by depicting the Chosen One in one of the episodes
of her dance as a maimed bird, as Nijinska remembered:
Suddenly, spontaneously, Nijinsky jumped. It was an awkward jump, as if he
were a wounded bird, one leg folded beneath him. He raised a clenched fist to
the sky and held the other to his body. Then he squatted down, touched the
ground with one hand, and began to stamp, beating his hands against his bent
knees. Now he resembled a bird busily building its nest. Still in his squatting
position, he took long paces off to the side and then covered his head with his
arm. As if in a low arabesque, he stretched out his leg, stuck out his arms and
banged them against the floor—as if they were wings.63
In his diary, Nijinsky links this bird symbolization to Diaghilev and himself:
Diaghilev is a terrible man. I do not like terrible men. I will not harm them. I
do not want them to be killed. They are eagles. They prevent small birds from
living, and therefore one must guard against them. . . . Eagles must not prevent
small birds from carrying on with their lives, and therefore they must be given
things to eat that will destroy their predatory intentions.64
1 ère
– Période.
1.
gi ? gi g g
C C TU C C C C TU C C C C C
jh jh jh
(2+3)
A3 A5 B7 (3+4)
Γ15 (3+12)
2. gi g g g
C C TU C TU C C C C C C C
hj
Α5 (2+3) Β7 (3+4)
hjA
3
ème
2 – Période. Γ ′15(12+3)
1.
g gi gi g
C C C C C C C C C C C C C C C C
hj hj (2+2)hj jh
C 8(3+3+2) A4 B7
Γ11
2.
gi gi g g
C C C C C C C C C C C C C C C C C C TU C
jh jh jh
C 5 (3+2) Α′5 A4 (2+2)
B7 A3
ÁC ′5Ë
Γ ′19 (5+11+3)
3ème
– Période.
1.
gi gi gi gi gi gi
C C C C C C C C C C C C C C C C C C C C C C C C C C C
jh h jh jh
A5 B4 A 2 B4 A3 A5 B4
Γ9 Γ6 Γ12
2.
gi
C C C TU C C C C TU C TU C
jh jh
C5 C7
Exemple XVII.
1. — A3 A5 B7 , A5 B7 A3 , ce qui donne:
I Γ15 Γ ′15
II . — A5 B4 , A2 B4 , A3 A5 B4 , C5 , C7 :
Γ9 Γ6 Γ12 C5 C7
90 tamara levitz
contracted to A4 (four beats), while cell B7 remains the same. C5 and A5 are
inserted before the repeat of A4 and B7, giving a clear example of Stravinsky’s
additive practice. The third period again involves the manipulation of all
three cells.
When the refrain returns after the first “couplet,” it does not use cell C at
all. In the coda on the refrain that appears at rehearsal no. 187, however, C
is used extensively and even exclusively from rehearsal no. 196 forward.
Boulez makes one nod to the choreography, by noting that the coda ends
with “an obvious movement dialectically tied to an implied immobility.”70
Otherwise, his approach flattens and detemporalizes the piece in a visual
representation that emphasizes subtraction and addition rather than the
continuous flow of time and movement. His geometrical representation sup-
presses the bodily action that could disrupt the static architectural con-
struction of the piece.71 His repeated rhythmic units cannot suggest forward
dynamic movement, and seem alienated from any sense of a bodily rhythm.
The analytical methodology, for all that it purports to focus on the rhythmic
dimension, actually abstracts this rhythm from the danced bodily continuity
that gave the piece its rhythmic life.
Boulez’s legacy left its mark on Allen Forte’s The Harmonic Organization of
“The Rite of Spring” (1978). Whereas Boulez concentrated on rhythm, Forte
focuses exclusively harmony, with the now familiar aim of securing Stravin-
sky a place in the musical canon next to Schoenberg by proving his newness
(Forte 1978, 19). His lack of interest in the historical, social, and cultural con-
text of Le Sacre is reflected in his inability to create a narrative for his book.
He replaces the richness of literary prose with a list-like description of the
pitch-class sets used throughout the piece, which drains the piece of all its
rhythmic vitality. The Chosen One is no longer mentioned, her fate deemed
as secondary as the timbres, rhythms, musical gestures, and melodies that
surround her. His sanitized structural approach retains at least one histori-
cal trace, however, that of Stravinsky’s sketches, which help Forte to prove
that Stravinsky intended to use the pitch-class sets found in the score.72
In Stravinsky and “The Rite of Spring”: The Beginnings of a Musical Language,
Pieter van den Toorn, like Forte, brackets out in his interpretation of the
“Danse sacrale” all “extra-musical” elements except the sketchbook, which
he also accepts as part of the musical score.73 He divides his analysis between
different chapters of his book, on issues ranging from re-barring Stravinsky’s
music and rhythmic structure to and pitch structure. In this manner, the
reader loses all sense of the dance as a unified piece; the Chosen One like-
wise disappears behind an analysis that emphasizes systematic regularity. Van
den Toorn criticizes Boulez for having “taken the irregular or shifting meters
[in Le Sacre] at face value” and for having ignored “the role of steady metric
periodicity” (van den Toorn 1987, 67). He argues that “if the shifting accents
or stresses are to have meaning, then this can come only to the extent that
the chosen one ’ s choice 91
142 1 2 3
1 2 1 2>g 1 2
gi ? ' gi 'g
3 T U W CCC C TU 2 T U W CCC C 3 T U W CCC C T U W CCC C 28 CC C Y CCC C X YY CC C X CC 2
! 16 C 16 C 16 C C CC C Y CC W X CC C 16
? gi Y C YY C C YY C C C C YY C C XX C C YY C C
# 3 gi YY CC TU 2 C Y jC 3 TU h TU h 28 2
16 C hj 16 C h 16 16
a5 b7
143
1 2 3
1 2 1 2>g 1 2
' gi 'g
2 T U W CCC C 3 T U W CCC C T U W CCCC C 28 CC C Y CCC C X YY CC C X CC
! 16 C 16 C CC C Y CC W X CC C
gi Y C YY C C YY C C C C YY C C XX C C YY C C
# 2 C YC 3 TU h UT h 28
16 C jh 16
a5 b7
144 +2
1 2 3
1 2 1>g 2 1
! 28 T U CC U
W CCC T
CC C
CC 3 TU W CCC
CC 28 CCC C Y CCCC C X YY CCC C W X CCC
16 C YC X C C
g YY C C gi YY C C CC Y Y C C X X C C Y Y C C
# 2 Ci YY CC T U 3 C h 28
8 C 16 C
a4 b7
145 +2
3 1 2
1 2 1 >g 2 1 2
! 28 T U
C
W CCC C T U
CC C
CC 3 T U W CCC C 28 CCC C Y CCCC C X YY CCC C W X CCC
16 C C YC X C C
g Y CC
Y Y
Y C C C Y C X C C YY C C
C Y C X
# 2 Ci YY CC TU U
3 T h 28
8 C 16
a4 b7
the chosen one ’ s choice 93
“wild martial” dance.79 She was not glorified, but rather ostracized, cruelly
chosen for her sacrifice because of the simple fact that she trips just before
rehearsal no. 101. Marie Rambert indicated the violent reaction of the
women around her: they stomp their feet at rehearsal no. 103, and rush at the
Chosen One with fists “as though they want to hack her” at rehearsal no.
107.80
The community’s hateful response in Nijinsky’s choreography is more
clearly put in perspective if compared with Mary Wigman’s feminist pro-
duction of Le Sacre in 1957. Wigman choreographed the very same music and
yet allowed the Chosen One to be part of a caring and respectful community
led by a group of older priestesses. At the moment when she would have
tripped in Nijinsky’s choreography, Wigman’s Chosen One is just about to
meet a young man—an event that will emphasize her humanity. She is
thwarted in this attempt by the three older priestesses, who know she must
be saved for the sacrifice. When Nijinsky’s amazons would have stomped in
anger, Wigman allows men to come on stage with rope, in order to tie the
Chosen One as the maidens around her sway in devotion. Finally, at
rehearsal no. 107, where Nijinsky’s women rush at the Chosen One with their
fists, Wigman allows them to sway and vibrate while she prepares to receive
her crown—surrounded by the three old priestesses who accompany and
guide her to her death.81 The Chosen One’s ritual sacrifice in Wigman’s Le
Sacre takes place within a (albeit ideologically problematic) community with
venerated traditions and a sense of its own future. In Nijinsky’s choreogra-
phy, on the other hand, it is an act of sheer terror and panic.
Suddenly, at rehearsal no. 142, Nijinsky’s Chosen One leaps vigorously
into the air, timing her movements to occur on each off-beat sixteenth-note
chord of cell A. The light attack Stravinsky required on these offbeat chords
facilitates her leap toward the sky, as an expression of her desire to live and
to escape her fate and the clutches of the ancestors who surround her.
Stravinsky further underscored her physical move away from the earth by
having these chords played pizzicato.82 This movement is in extreme con-
trast to the rest of the ballet, which has been primarily about the body’s
attachment to the earth. The astonishing optical allusion of these leaps is
that they are not actually at regular intervals, as they at first seem to be.
Rather, the Chosen One respects the addition of the sixteenth-note to the
sixteenth-note off-beat chord in measure 3, and thus delays her leap so that
it coincides with the next off-beat eighth-note chord in measure 4. In mea-
sure 10, when Stravinsky omits part of cell A, the Chosen One omits her
leap; when he allows cell A to return in measure 13 with a sixteenth-note
missing, the Chosen One shifts her leaps so she lands on the ground on the
downbeat of measure 14.
Nijinsky follows the cell structure of Stravinsky’s music, by having the
Chosen One perform a new, distinct gesture for cell B. According to Mil-
94 tamara levitz
licent Hodson, the Chosen One bends painfully backwards from the waist
here, ending her phrases in a twisted turn in which something coming
from above appears to crush her. This movement symbolizes vividly the
weight of the oppressive forces she has upon her, and her inability to free
herself from them. This expression of weakness is followed immediately,
however, by the surprise interruption of cell C at rehearsal no. 144. Here,
a startling new symbol of resistance is inserted into the choreography: the
Chosen One “makes a convulsive jump on one leg, having crossed and
raised the other in front of her; squeezing one hand into a fist, she threat-
ens the heavens while the other hand is held close to her body” (see fig.
3.1).83 This moment marks a surprising break and hardly has the neutral
character of an “insertion” sought in both Boulez’s and van den Toorn’s
analyses: it pierces the musical fabric, disrupting any notion of a unified
voice in the work.84
As the sacrificial dance proceeds, the opposing gestures associated with
cells B and C become more prominent. The refrain returns four times,
accompanied by the same movements to cells A, B, and C, yet varied to
reflect the Chosen One’s exhaustion and dejection over the inevitability of
her fate. The fact that she dances this refrain each time to the same fast
tempo, which is otherwise not maintained throughout, and especially not in
her final episode, emphasizes how important this section of the music is to
the Chosen One’s assertion of her will.85 Between the refrains, during her
episodes, the Chosen One succumbs more to her community, by acting like
a maimed bird, spinning ever so briefly like a top, and banging her straight-
ened leg on the ground.86 She repeatedly emerges from these moments, how-
ever, to return to her initial phrase, most strikingly at rehearsal no. 180, when
all the ancestors gather to watch her. This refrain is an abrupt interruption
of five measures, containing only cells A and B. After this startling interrup-
tion, the Chosen One gathers the strength to return to this position of defi-
ance one last time, from rehearsal no. 186 onward, when the refrain returns
as a coda. Stravinsky originally scored this section lightly to emphasize the
Chosen One’s leaps into the air.87 The conflict she feels between defiance
and oppression is best expressed after rehearsal no. 192, when the music is
reduced to the alternating gestures of cells B and C. Stravinsky was dismayed
at how most interpreters missed this moment, which he called a “dialectical
structure of phrases.”88 At rehearsal no. 197, cell B is suddenly left out, in
what Stravinsky called a turning point in the music (Vera Stravinsky and Rob-
ert Craft 1978, 514). The Chosen One is left to end her dance with an inces-
sant hammering out of her most powerful physical motive of defiance (on
cell C; see fig. 3.1). Her driving music successfully destroys the static back-
ground of the ancestors. She will die, but not without making her final defi-
ant gesture. Cell C will prevail.
the chosen one ’ s choice 95
bered the movements Nijinsky had taught them, and passed them on. Most
spectators did not quickly forget Nijinsky either, or the statement he had
made in his Sacre. In this manner an unwritten tradition was created, which
developed momentum as the century moved on. Social codes of behavior
changed, allowing Mary Wigman by 1957 to create the first “feminist” Sacre.
And by 1976, Pina Bausch would use the role of the Chosen One to define
“women [a]s the subject rather than the object, experiencing her feelings
from the inside, intent on her own events,” as Christy Adair has eloquently
commented.97 The Chosen Ones they created had vibrancy, social meaning,
and cultural relevance and created a tradition for the piece that was distinct
from, but hardly inferior to, its tradition as a concert piece. Frequently, the
soloist dancing the Chosen One argued and disagreed with the choreogra-
pher, thus replicating the spirit of dissension that characterized the collab-
oration between Stravinsky, Nijinsky, and Piltz.98 Their historically contin-
gent work demonstrated the limitations of any project that tried to define Le
Sacre as an expression of an objective spirit, essentialist politics, or of pure
reason based on structural listening. With his Sacre, Nijinsky stood up to
Stravinsky, and held strong. The tension of their physical and creative strug-
gle, transformed into the passionate, contained but defiant gestures of the
Chosen One, strains against all totalizing readings of the music. At that infa-
mous premiere in Paris over eighty years ago, Nijinsky opened a door, not to
inhumanity and fascism, but rather to a new form of dance for the twentieth
century. As Nijinska (1992, 470) concluded: “An awareness of the need for
fearless self-expression—of the original, of the individual, of the unknown in
art—awakened that night.”
notes
I am grateful to the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada for
a three-year research grant that enabled me to begin work on this project in archives
in Germany and Switzerland. I would like to thank in particular Werner Grünzweig
at the Akademie der Künste in Berlin, and Ulrich Mosch and Felix Mayer at the Paul
Sacher Stiftung in Basel for their kindness and permission to view materials in their
archives. Finally, I want to extend my deepest gratitude to the Stanford Humanities
Center, a remarkable institution where I had the good fortune to complete my work
on this topic as a fellow in fall 1999.
1. Subotnik 1996, 149; 162–63; 168. See the introduction to this volume for some
of my further remarks on Subotnik’s argument.
2. In recent years, Nicholas Cook has published some of the most illuminating
arguments on why and how musicologists are moving toward performance studies.
See Cook 1998 and 2001.
3. I have chosen to use the French titles of the piece, because they accompanied
its first publication in a four-hand piano version in 1913, and are well established. The
the chosen one ’ s choice 99
English titles were only added to the published score in 1967. See van den Toorn
1987, 25–27 and Taruskin 1996, 1:861.
4. Subotnik mentions the dancing body only briefly, in note 75 of her chapter.
Characteristically she quotes a source that describes modern ballet as “abstract.” In
other words, she evokes an image of modern ballet that negates or tries to tran-
scend the dancing body, revealing in this way her own tendency to view dancing
bodies as distinct from the visuality of the musical experience. See Subotnik 1996,
251.
5. Adorno 1978, 39. All translations from German and French to English in this
essay are my own.
6. See Witkin 1998, 144; and Adorno 1978, 40.
7. See Witkin 1998, 129; 130.
8. Dennis 1998, 53–56. See also Paddison 1993, 48.
9. See Adorno, “Stravinsky: Ein dialektisches Bild,” Forum ( June/July/August
1962); republished in Adorno 1997, 208.
10. This argument remains an important part of Adorno’s later “Stravinsky: Ein
dialektisches Bild” (Adorno 1963).
11. See Taruskin 1995, 6–7. This article was republished, in a modified version,
in Taruskin 1997, 360–88.
12. Taruskin 1995, 3. In the late 1990s, Taruskin’s main opponents were Kofi
Agawu and Pieter van den Toorn. In Music, Politics, and the Academy, the latter ques-
tioned the “musical significance” of Taruskin’s historical and analytical studies of
Stravinsky’s Russian roots (van den Toorn 1995, 196). Van den Toorn claimed that
“once individual works begin to prevail for what they are in and of themselves and not
for what they represent, then context itself, as a reflection of this transcendence,
becomes less dependent on matters of historical placement.” Van den Toorn con-
fused the notion of music as a form of communication necessarily invested with soci-
etal and historical meaning with the idea of music as representation of something
outside itself (van den Toorn 1995, 144). Kofi Agawu likewise judged Taruskin’s his-
torical work on the octatonic scale to be of “dubious” significance, consisting of noth-
ing more than “a corroborative evidence for patterns observed in Stravinsky’s scores”
(Agawu 1993, 92). The fact that Agawu demands that historians provide a “technical
demonstration” of how context relates to music shows how unwilling he likewise is to
accept a hermeneutical approach in the cultural sciences as a viable alternative to sci-
entific inquiry.
13. Taruskin 1992, 197; and 1993, 288–89. See also Taruskin 1995, 2–3.
14. Adorno differed from Taruskin in offering an alternative to music that was
ideologically tainted, namely music that mirrored the most progressive state of con-
sciousness and thus contained philosophical truth. Taruskin offered no such model
to counter the negative image provided by Stravinsky, leading us to the conclusion
that the affirmative music he envisioned may be utopic in Paul Ricoeur’s sense,
although I think Taruskin would adamantly deny such a proposition. (See Ricoeur
1986.)
15. Taruskin confirms his sympathy for Adorno’s conclusions about Stravinsky on
occasion, and links his own interpretation to Adorno’s theory of permanent regres-
sion. See Taruskin 1995, 20; 1993, 287; and 1997, 385–86; 424.
100 tamara levitz
16. Taruskin 1997, 344; 424. See also 1995, 17. I am not sure why Taruskin uses
the German word “Individuum” here, which is quite distinct from Adorno’s “Subjekt.”
17. Taruskin describes such a transcendence of the individual ego in Scriabin’s
use of the six-tone, symmetrical mystic chord. See Taruskin 1997, 344.
18. Igor Stravinsky, Chroniques de ma vie, vol. 1 (Paris: Les Éditions Denoël et
Steele, 1935), 69; translated into English in Stravinsky 1962, 31. Taruskin (1996,
1:849–66) gives a remarkable history of Stravinsky’s fabrication of this dream.
According to his account, Stravinsky originally reported this dream to his first biog-
rapher, who described it as “a young maiden dancing to the point of exhaustion
before a group of old men of fabulous age, dried out practically to the point of pet-
rifaction” (André Schaeffer, quoted in Taruskin 1996, 1:862). Note how the issue of
a pagan rite is not included in the original dream, which emphasizes rather the oppo-
sition between the sexual potency of the young girl and the impotent older specta-
tors surrounding her. Note also that Roerich did not envision such a sacrifice in his
original version of Le Sacre (see Taruskin 1996, 1:861).
19. The term “zhertva” means simultaneously sacrifice and victim in Russian. Nev-
ertheless, this title is most often translated as “The Great Sacrifice.” See the libretto
for Le Sacre in Stravinsky’s hand reprinted in Vera Stravinsky and Robert Craft 1978,
78; and Stravinsky’s letter to Alexander Benois from 16 November 1910, ibid., 82. See
also Taruskin 1996, 1:871.
20. Stravinsky 1935, 1:105; 1962, 48. Stravinsky described the adolescents in Le
Sacre as “not fully formed: their sex is unique and double, like that of a tree” in “Ce
que j’ai voulu exprimer dans Le Sacre du Printemps,” Montjoie, 29 May 1913; reprinted
in Lesure 1980, 14.
21. In spite of Adorno’s suspicions that Le Sacre was neither a critical nor an
enlightened work, he shied away from identifying its absence of subjectivity with fas-
cism. Rather, he believed that the work could never have been performed in the
Third Reich, because the National Socialists would not have stood such an expression
of their own barbarism. Adorno saw the roots of Stravinsky’s inhumanity not in fas-
cism, but in liberalism. See Adorno 1978, 137.
22. Adorno uses the word “parasite” on p. 178.
23. In spite of the intensive critical attention that has been focused on Adorno’s
Philosophie der neuen Musik, I have not been able to find a single account that takes into
consideration his definition of dance. In that it is highly unlikely that Adorno saw
Nijinsky’s original performance of 1912 (when he was nine years old), or Massine’s in
Paris in 1920, one can assume he probably saw Marion Hermann’s choreography
in Frankfurt am Main in January 1931 (or, less likely, Lasar Galpen’s choreography in
Cologne in May 1930). He did not arrive in Hollywood early enough to have witnessed
Lester Horton’s Americanized version of the ballet. There is all but no information on
Marion Hermann’s choreography and performance of the work. See Manning 1991,
129–58. See also Berg 1988. For a list of choreographies of Le Sacre to 1991 see Aco-
cella, Garafola, and Green 1992, 68–100.
24. In focusing on Adorno’s subjective experience and imagination, I am not
ignoring the fact that he defined his Philosophie der neuen Musik specifically as an
objective Geschichtsphilosophie of modern music that did not reflect his own subjective
opinions, but rather his insight into the Hegelian objective spirit (objektiver Geist) of
the chosen one ’ s choice 101
the musical works he analyzed. (See Adorno, “Missverständnisse,” Melos 17, no. 3
[1950]; republished in Adorno 1975, 203–6.) In contrast to Dahlhaus and other crit-
ics, however, I do not think Adorno’s claims for his philosophy should stop us from
examining its roots in his own experience. I believe looking for objective spirit in a
dancing body is a highly problematic enterprise. See Dahlhaus 1987a, 9–15.
25. Dominique Dupuy notes that the body can frequently turn into a body-
machine in the minds of those who have forgotten it. He urges his readers to think
of the living body in other terms than as an object made to express something. See
his comments, quoted in Launay 1993. See also Dupuy 1995, 165–66.
26. Taruskin 1995, 19. Taruskin admitted at one point that he thought audiences
created “tremendous” stagings in their imaginations of how Le Sacre would be danced,
and that their actual visual exposure to the work thereafter was “often disappointing.”
See ibid., 8.
27. It is interesting that Taruskin did not find it relevant to examine Nijinsky’s
choreography for Stravinsky’s work, especially in view of the fact that he completed
such a thorough investigation of the work’s genesis. In no fewer than 117 pages on
the composition of Le Sacre, Taruskin mentions Nijinsky only once, in passing
(Taruskin 1996, 1:875). In Defining Russia Musically, Taruskin dismisses Nijinsky’s
work as playing a “negligible role in the ballet’s history” (Taruskin 1997, 380). See
also Taruskin 1995, 16.
28. Milan Kundera has lamented the fact that so many critics have been fright-
ened by the ecstasy expressed in Le Sacre, rather than enjoying and reveling in it. See
Kundera 1991.
29. Taruskin 1996, 1:865; for Blok’s involvement, see 849–51.
30. A survey conducted by Dance Magazine in 1998 concluded that Nijinsky was the
most loved dancer of all time, although the vast majority of people have never seen
him dance (in that no film documentation exists). How powerfully Nijinsky must
have danced himself into our historical consciousness and creative imaginations, to
have achieved such a status over seventy years after he last danced on stage! And what
a strong will it must have taken to have barred him from the history and analysis of
his most famous work, Le Sacre.
31. Stravinsky, letter to Max Steinberg, 5 June 1913, reprinted in translation in
Vera Stravinsky and Robert Craft 1978, 102. In this letter, Stravinsky writes that “Nijin-
sky’s choreography was incomparable. With the exception of a few places, everything
is as I wanted it.” See also Lesure 1990, 16; and van den Toorn 1987, 16. Charles M.
Joseph concludes that Stravinsky was worried about Nijinsky’s well-being at the time
of preparing Le Sacre, and arranged diversions for him. See Joseph 1999, 194–96.
32. Stravinsky, “Interview with Stravinsky,” The Observer, 8 July 1921; reprinted in
Lesure 1990, 76–77. Some of the most devastating criticism of Nijinsky is included in
Stravinsky 1935, 80–106 (Stravinsky 1962, 36–48). Stravinsky complained most often
about Nijinsky’s lack of musical knowledge and skill. Although this has proven to be
an unfair judgment, Pieter van den Toorn continues to promote it (see van den
Toorn 1987, 8). For more positive assessments of Nijinsky’s musical abilities, see Nijin-
ska 1992, 458; and Denby 1977, 18.
33. I am not sure why van den Toorn and others feel they have to choose between
Le Sacre as music and Le Sacre as a ballet. Why were they not able to let the two tradi-
102 tamara levitz
tions of Le Sacre peacefully coexist, as they surely have historically throughout the
twentieth century?
34. When Stravinsky was completing Memories and Commentaries, he planned to
undermine Nijinsky further by remarking that “Everyone who knew Nijinsky
expected he would relapse into insanity; he had a mad brother, a blind uncle, a deaf
cousin, Diaghilev said that the family was syphilitic.” Nijinska asked him to omit this
passage, and he subsequently did. These documents are held in the Stravinsky
Archive at the Paul Sacher Stiftung. I am curious why Stravinsky felt compelled to lash
out at Nijinsky in this manner.
35. Stravinsky called the work a “choreodrama” in a letter to N. F. Findeizen,
translated into English by Robert Craft in appendix II to Stravinsky 1969, 32. See also
“Le Sacre du Printemps,” in Vera Stravinsky and Robert Craft 1978, 512.
36. Stravinsky to Nicholas Roerich, 13 (26) November 1911; translated into
English by Robert Craft in appendix II to Stravinsky 1969, 30.
37. Stravinsky to Nicholas Roerich, 6 March 1912, translated into English by Rob-
ert Craft in appendix II to Stravinsky 1969, 30.
38. Montjoie 1–2, Numéro consacré à la Danse Contemporaine ( January–Febru-
ary 1914). There has been so much focus on Stravinsky’s article for Montjoie on 29
May 1913 that this later issue has been overlooked.
39. For information on Saint-Point, see Berghaus 1993 and Satin 1990. See also
Brandstetter 1995, 366–85; and Franko 1995, 21–24.
40. Saint-Point 1914. There are several articles in this issue about ritual dances of
peoples outside Europe, which the writers associate with a spirituality required for the
new art of dance. See, for example, Kharis, “La danse d’orient”; Jean-Paul d’Aile, “Les
danses sud-américaines”; and Henri Siégler-Pascal, “La religion de la danse.”
41. Postel du Mas 1914. Stravinsky’s vision of using adolescents for Le Sacre whose
“sex was not fully formed” can be related to attempts at blurring gender identity in
modern dance in this period.
42. There are several sources that are helpful in gaining a preliminary insight into
the nature of the “art plastique” and abstract dance Canudo and other were propos-
ing. I would mention: Copeland and Cohen 1983; Franko 1995; and even Acocella
and Garafola 1991.
43. Stravinsky, “Ce que j’ai voulu exprimer dans Le Sacre du Printemps,” in Lesure
1980, 14.
44. The best chronology of the genesis of Le Sacre is still provided in Vera Stravin-
sky and Robert Craft 1978, 84–92. See also Hodson 1987, 53–66.
45. Nijinsky 1995, 24. In this passage Nijinsky continues: “Scholars will ponder
over me, and they will rack their brains needlessly, because thinking will produce no
results for them. They are stupid. They are beasts. They are meat. They are death.”
46. Nijinsky, letter to Stravinsky from 25 January 1913, quoted in English in
Garafola 1989, 68.
47. Jacques Marnod in Mercure de France, 1 October 1913; quoted in Lesure 1990,
21–22; rpt. in Lesure 1980, 35–38.
48. Jacques Rivières, “Le Sacre du printemps,” Nouvelle revue française, November
1913; rpt. in Rivières 1947, 90.
49. Émile Vieillermoz, quoted in Jameux 1990, 25.
the chosen one ’ s choice 103
50. Odom 1997, 29–39. See also Nijinska 1992, 451; and Rambert 1972, 53–54.
51. Marie Rambert thus began her work with Nijinsky on Le Sacre after the first
rehearsals had begun in late fall 1912. It is likely that Nijinsky’s choreography
changed under her guidance. See Nijinska 1992, 457–58.
52. Nijinska 1992, 460. Hodson assumes that these moves would have been
danced by the Chosen One, and yet gives no evidence to support this claim. See Hod-
son 1996, 168.
53. On Dalcroze’s method as “plastique animée” see Giertz 1975, 59 and Levitz
2001. Concerning Jaques-Dalcroze’s teachings at this time, see Jaques-Dalcroze
1912/1913; Jaques-Dalcroze 1912 and 1965.
54. Stravinsky’s correspondence with Dalcroze is documented in Stravinsky 1984,
77–83.
55. Bronislava Nijinska remembers practicing the “Danse sacrale” before Novem-
ber 1912, using a “score” sent by Stravinsky (Nijinska 1992, 448–49). This seems to
contradict other evidence that exists about the work. First, Stravinsky only finished
the work on 17 November 1912. He commented in a letter to Roerich on 14 Decem-
ber 1912 that Nijinsky had only begun the staging on 13 December 1912. On 18
December, Serge Grigoriev wrote that Nijinsky had still not started the rehearsals,
and was waiting for Roerich’s costumes. By the end of January, Nijinsky had still only
had five rehearsals of the ballet (since Stravinsky left Vienna that month), and made
no mention of having done the “Danse sacrale.” Most remarkably, Nijinsky wrote
Stravinsky on 24 March 1913, requesting the music for the “Danse sacrale” (see Vera
Stravinsky and Robert Craft 1978, 92–95). I trust van den Toorn’s argument that
Nijinsky would have used a four-hand arrangement of the piece that did not include
the “Danse sacrale” for almost all or all of these early rehearsals, because the full score
was only finished on 8 March 1913. (See van den Toorn 1987, 35–36.) Robert Craft
claims, however, that Nijinsky used a “sketch-score” of the “Danse sacrale” as early as
November 1912 (Craft 1988, 173). In view of the fact that his article consists of so
many erroneous facts and misplaced quotes, I can only take it as a complete fabrica-
tion on his part. (See also Taruskin 1988b, 385.) Concerning the extant manuscript
copies of Le Sacre, see Cyr 1982, 98–114. If Nijinsky started the “Danse sacrale” in win-
ter 1913, rather than in November 1912, then Millicent Hodson errs in assuming that
it was choreographed first, and that it formed the basis for the movement vocabulary
of the rest of the ballet. Hodson also claims that Irina Nijinska reported that Nijin-
ska rehearsed the part of the Chosen One with her brother by hearing the synopsis
of the ballet read aloud over and over again, and not by hearing the music. (See Hod-
son 1980, 43 and 1996, 167.) It is clear from many accounts that Roerich’s libretto
had a deep influence on how Nijinsky designed his ballet (see, for example, Nijinska
1992, 457–61). Nevertheless, I remain convinced that Nijinsky was not listening to a
synopsis, but rather to the music played by the rehearsal pianist when he created the
dance. See Rambert 1972, 56–57. For an accurate chronology, see Hill 2000, 26–34.
56. Taruskin comments (in reference to Whittall 1982) that it is “sentimental” to
identify with the Chosen One, or to find conflict or tragedy in her role. I am not sure
why he finds this sentimental. See Taruskin 1995, 20.
57. Hodson 1986, 67. She notes the similarity between this posture and the figures
on Russian totems, which Nijinsky probably became familiar with through Nicolas
104 tamara levitz
Roerich. Nijinsky wanted the dancers to achieve the concentrated focus of such
carved figures. This again shows his affinity for the “art plastique” being promoted
by his French contemporaries.
58. Acocella 1987, 65. Denby (1977, 18) commented in detail on Nijinsky’s
emphasis on the center of weight in his body, which allowed him to perform partic-
ularly meticulous movements. See also Kirstein 1976.
59. Description provided in Hargrave 1985, 93. It is important to note that Nijin-
sky expected the emotion of the dance to be communicated through movement, and
not through facial expressions. Dancers who showed emotion in their face infuriated
him (see Rambert 1972, 62). Edwin Denby (1977, 19–21) has called him a “classical”
dancer for this reason.
60. Garafola 1989, 72. Nijinsky’s sister believed that the Chosen One’s dance was
“his [Nijinsky’s] own dance, inspired by the music.” Nijinska 1992, 450.
61. Garafola 1999, 247. Burt Ramsey has offered valuable insight into Nijinsky’s
public role around 1912, and his homosexuality, in Ramsey 1995, 74–100.
62. Kopelson 1997, 190. This would partly explain Nijinsky’s violent reaction
to and intense anger over his sister’s news that she was pregnant and could not
dance the part. Nijinsky afterwards feared that he had been on the verge of killing
his sister’s husband at that moment. See Rambert 1972, 58; and Nijinska 1992,
461–63.
63. Krasovskaya 1979, 238–39. She describes Nijinsky’s “sacrificial dance” based
on a letter from Bronislava Nijinska of 11 December 1967, and on a conversation with
Maria Piltz on 28 March 1968. Hodson has attempted to match Nijinska’s general
description to specific points in Stravinsky’s music in Nijinsky’s Crime against Grace. I
find this problematic for three reasons: (1) Nijinska’s account was given over fifty
years after the fact; (2) Nijinska did not dance the final part of the Chosen One; and
(3) her account is general and not accompanied with indications of how the move-
ments coordinated with the music.
64. Nijinsky 1995, 37. It is important to remember, however, that these comments
were written after Diaghilev and Nijinsky had broken contact, and thus do not reflect
the state of their relationship in 1912–13. Nevertheless, I believe they demonstrate
how remarkably Nijinsky and Stravinsky differed in their degree of empathy for the
victims of violence. Whereas Stravinsky loved bullfights, for example, they terrified
Nijinsky, who felt sorry for the tortured animals. See Nijinsky 1995, 43–44.
65. On the notion of representing corporeality through the fall, see Varilio 1994,
35–60, esp. 43–44.
66. In an earlier interview in the Pall Mall Gazette on 15 February 1913, Nijinsky
claimed that the dance had no human beings in it. This comment is frequently cited
in studies of the ballet. Note, however, that this remark was made before he com-
pleted work on the Chosen One’s dance. I believe that he probably started training
Nijinska as the Chosen One only around February 1913, in spite of reports that he
began the dance in November 1912. Nijinska gave birth in October 1913, which
means she would only have found out she was pregnant around March 1913. Surely
she had not been working on the dance for five months before finding out she was
pregnant. It is also not clear that Nijinsky even had the music for the “Danse sacrale”
before this time. See note 55.
the chosen one ’ s choice 105
67. Boulez shares Adorno’s opinion that Le Sacre failed in its form, development,
and harmony. See Boulez 1966, 142–45.
68. Boulez mocks the only visual realization of Le Sacre that he considers, namely
Walt Disney’s Fantasia. He remarks sarcastically that whereas Le Sacre was once the
object of scandal, it was now used for animated cartoons (Boulez 1966, 75). It is cul-
turally interesting to note that Boulez even saw Fantasia, let alone felt it worthy of
commentary.
69. Boulez does not indicate which score he used, thereby bypassing the thorny
issue of Stravinsky’s revisions of Le Sacre. This is not surprising, in that the idea of a
score being revised would not have fit into his notion of what constituted the musi-
cal work. The rhythmic examples he uses in his article indicate that he was using the
1929 score or a copy thereof. On the issue of editions and revisions of Le Sacre, see
Cyr 1982, 89–148; Cyr 1986, 157–73; van den Toorn, “Sketches, Editions, Revisions,”
in van den Toorn 1987, 22–56; and Fink 1999b, 299–362.
70. Boulez 1966, 136.
71. Concerning the philosophical consequences of music theory’s use of two-
dimensional graphic representation in the twentieth century, see Gilmore 1995 and
Koozin 1999. Koozin makes the mistake of proposing three-dimensional represen-
tations that fail to depart from two-dimensional thinking.
72. As sketch studies became popular, the sketch emerges as a significant form of
visual representation in musical analysis. The sight of etchings, sketches, or scribbles
evoked the palpable presence of a real composer with tired fingers, broken pencils,
spilling ink, and the very real presence of pens, lead, paper, and other materials
required in order to compose. It is interesting that the body found its way back into
music studies in this way, even in a period that wanted nothing to do with it, and
which favored heightened intellectual rationality.
73. Van den Toorn 1987, 19 and all of chapter 2.
74. I am referring to this dance as it was reconstructed by Millicent Hodson for
the Joffrey Ballet in 1987. I refer only to gestures for which we have historical docu-
mentation, and thus avoid the issue of the validity of her reconstruction. She used the
following sources for her reconstruction: (1) Marie Rambert, Le Sacre du Printemps,
Piano Score for Four Hands, choreographic notes (1913), introduction (1967) (Lon-
don: Ballet Rambert Archives); (2) Nijinska’s letter about this solo to Vera
Krasovskaya in December 1967; published summary in Krasovskaya 1971, 440–42; (3)
Valentine Gross-Hugo’s drawings; (4) the reconstruction of the dance by Olga Stens
in France and by Nicholas Zverev (see Stanciu-Reiss 1957); (5) Stravinsky 1969. The
appendix consists of the notes. For a review of these sources, see Hodson 1987.
75. See Stravinsky 1969, appendix, 42. Stravinsky indicated that the Chosen One
should stay in this spot from rehearsal numbers 142 to 149.
76. Jann Pasler (1981) develops this thought in convincing detail. The scenery for
scene 2, which depicted a vast Slavic sky, enchanted rocks, and the magic mountain
of sacrifice, also contrasted sharply with the dance. See Garafola 1989, 67–68.
77. Nijinska 1992, 448–49; see also Stravinsky’s letter to Nicholas Roerich, 1(14)
December 1912, translated into English by Robert Craft in Stravinsky 1969, appen-
dix, 31.
78. Gabriele Brandstetter (1998, 48–49) argues that the circle structure in Le Sacre
106 tamara levitz
has the multiple function of shutting out the audience while also shutting it in, and
of acting as an index for the representation of ritual.
79. Taruskin (1996, 1:890) traces the roots of this dance to Herodotus’s The Per-
sian Wars. Stravinsky labels the dance this way in his sketchbook. He calls it a “wild
martial dance” in his letter to N. F. Findeizen, 2(15) December 1912, translated into
English by Robert Craft in Stravinsky 1969, appendix, 33.
80. Marie Rambert’s notes are given in Hodson 1996, 135–40.
81. Mary Wigman’s extensive drawings and notes for her choreography of Le Sacre
are kept in her archive at the Akademie der Künste, Berlin. These documents
include the 1926 piano reduction of Stravinsky’s work with her meticulous com-
ments, as well as extensive drawings. Wigman fought with Dore Hoyer over the Cho-
sen One’s dance, however, and left no indication in writing or images of how she envi-
sioned that part of the piece. See also Steinbeck 1987.
82. Stravinsky only later removed that indication because he thought string play-
ers would be too incompetent to play it that way. See van den Toorn 1987, 42–44. A
weightless, precise performance of these chords best embodies the motion of leap-
ing into the air, which both Nijinsky and Stravinsky envisioned. In spite of this,
Stravinsky was one of the few conductors ever to perform these chords that way. Most
conductors perform these chords with enough crashing intensity to stifle anybody’s
attempt at escape.
83. Nijinska, quoted in Hodson 1996, 166. Hodson associates this gesture with
cell A, but I believe she is mistaken, especially in view of Valentine Gross-Hugo’s draw-
ings. I find there are many errors in Hodson’s reconstruction, and in this book. (For
a highly insightful critique of Hodson’s reconstruction, see Acocella 1991.) Jacques
Rivières described this gesture as an “arm raised to heaven and waved straight above
her head in a gesture of appeal, threat, and protection” (Rivières 1947, 93). The Cho-
sen One learned this gesture from her tribe, who demonstrate it for her in the “Evo-
cation des ancêtres.” This fact lends support to Nijinska’s thesis that in her “Danse
sacrale,” the Chosen One is protecting the earth against the heavens, and that the
ancestors had taught her the gesture she needed to win that battle. Such an inter-
pretation makes the ancestors less hostile than they otherwise appear to be.
84. I am keenly aware of the dangers inherent in trying to analyze dance by cre-
ating a narrative out of individual gestures. Nicholas Cook warns against such
approaches, which can be equated with constructing the body as text. Cook prefers
to understand the body as “sound,” as a “site of resistance to text”: “Instead of seeing
the relationship between work and performance in terms of a transparent revelation
of underlying structure, as epitomized by the Schenkerian concept of performing
from the middleground, a variety of terms come into play which thematize the opac-
ity of the relationship: quotation, commentary, critique, parody, irony, or travesty, for
example” (Cook 2001). I, nevertheless, analyze the dancing body of the Chosen One
in this way, because I believe this is how Nijinsky, following Jaques-Dalcroze, under-
stood and conceived of it. I would not support such an analytical approach for all cho-
reographed works of music.
85. See Fink 1999b.
86. Nijinsky never allows the Chosen One to spin freely as Adorno and Taruskin
want her to do. When she spins from rehearsal numbers 164 to 173, her movement
the chosen one ’ s choice 107
is “desperate and ecstatic at the same time,” and when she spins again after rehearsal
no. 181, she spins with “feet almost on the points striking the ground like daggers,”
according to Valentine Gross-Hugo (Hodson 1996, 177; 191). Her spinning is also
always stopped or interrupted by the return of her refrain.
87. On the original scoring of this moment, see Fink 1999b.
88. Stravinsky to Ansermet, 30 January 1926, reprinted in Vera Stravinsky and
Robert Craft 1978, 513. Boris Asaf’yev (1982, 53–54) discusses the tension between
cells B and C. Remember that Boulez intuitively understood this moment (see note
70).
89. There was much opposition to Jaques-Dalcroze’s approach to dance before
World War I. See Giertz 1975, 47–59. Opponents of Jaques-Dalcroze included
Claude Debussy, Rudolf Bode, and Hans Brandenburg. Adorno’s later interpreta-
tion of the dance movement of Le Sacre as mechanical may have resulted from his
knowledge of this body of criticism. This debate on mechanical versus conscious
dance also finds an analogy in the controversy over vitalist versus geometric inter-
pretations of the music of Le Sacre—a topic analyzed in Fink 1999b and, initially, in
Taruskin 1988a.
90. Nicholas Roerich, The Realm of Light (New York: New Era Library, 1931),
185–91; quoted in French in Hodson 1980, 41.
91. Krasovskaya 1979, 243–44. A large number of critics commented on the fact
that Piltz looked like she was being tortured in the “Danse sacrale.” This was not nec-
essarily Nijinsky’s original intention. See Bullard 1971 and Lesure 1980.
92. Brandstetter speaks of Le Sacre as “not only . . . an attack on the representative
code of the body in classical dance, but also . . . an affront against the norms of the
reigning body aesthetic in general” (Brandstetter 1988, 46).
93. Rivières 1947, 91. I think historians in general have tended to focus too exclu-
sively on the last few pages of Rivières’ extensive analysis (pp. 95–97).
94. Hodson erroneously indicates that these drawings were published in June
1913, at the time of the ballet’s premiere. She also uses drawings that were not actu-
ally ever published in Montjoie (Hodson 1996, 170). Many reprints of Gross-Hugo’s
actual drawing for Montjoie are included in Stravinsky’s archive, Paul Sacher Stiftung.
Gross-Hugo completed about twenty sketches of the Chosen One’s solo, and twenty-
five refined pictures of Piltz in the part. These drawings are kept in the Theatre Col-
lection at the Victoria and Albert Museum in London. The collection also includes a
diary in which Gross-Hugo talks about her drawings. The pages of her sketchbooks
are detached and the original sequence is not intact. Marie Rambert found Gross-
Hugo’s drawings too Duncanesque and refined, and not as prehistoric as they should
be. (See Hodson 1980, 45 and 1987, 57). A large selection of these drawings is pub-
lished in Hugo 1971.
95. Hodson 1996, 171. This example is only one of many showing that Gross-
Hugo is not accurately depicting the movement as Marie Rambert described it in her
piano reduction of the piece.
96. Ibid., 183. In the better-known version of these drawings used by Millicent
Hodson, Gross-Hugo uses a different movement for this measure! See Hodson 1996,
170.
97. Adair 1992, 210. See also Goldberg 1989 and Cody 1998.
108 tamara levitz
98. It would be interesting to study why this dance in particular has led to such
violent disagreements between dancers and choreographers—perhaps because
dancers seem to embrace it as an intense vehicle for their own, personal forms of
expression. Concerning Nijinsky’s original arguments with Stravinsky over Le Sacre,
see Marie Rambert 1972, 59.
four
Beethoven Antihero
Sex, Violence, and the Aesthetics of Failure,
or Listening to the Ninth Symphony
as Postmodern Sublime
robert fink
The postmodern would be that which, in the modern, puts forward the unpresentable
in presentation itself; that which denies itself the solace of good forms . . .
jean-françois lyotard, The Postmodern Condition
Yada, yada, yada. After the drubbings in the New York Times, the slashing
attacks from neo-conservative dinosaurs like Robert Bork and Roger Kim-
ball, the brutal caricatures of “postmodern radical feminist” musicology that
graced the pages of journals as divergent as U.S. News and World Report and
Lingua Franca—one might well ask: Wouldn’t it have been better for all of us
if Susan McClary’s gloss on the moment of recapitulation in the first move-
ment of Beethoven’s Ninth Symphony had simply never been written? I
think this is Cusick’s wish—her discussion of Feminine Endings never men-
tions the Minnesota Composer’s Forum Newsletter, the 1987 source where
McClary actually did deploy her infamous metaphor. What thoughtful musi-
cologist (old or new) would not want to erase the thuggish reception those
few words unleashed—even at the cost of erasing the words themselves?
But Susan McClary did in fact consciously compare the effect of one of
Beethoven’s most famous passages to a failed rape; and I for one would hes-
itate before consigning her audacious image to critical oblivion. For it was
this stark passage, and no other, that reached out and slapped a young, some-
what disillusioned doctoral candidate upside the disciplinary head and set
him on the path that would eventually lead to a vocation in the “new” musi-
cology, and the writing of this determinedly celebratory essay. When, in
1988, I first heard McClary quoted on the Ninth, I had no feminist context
within which to appreciate her sexual politics. I had no context at all, hav-
ing read none of her work, when a renowned male musicologist dropped
that one fateful sentence into his subtly disparaging talk—and waited for the
inevitable snickering to begin.2
It did not occur to me then that McClary’s quote was an attack on
Beethoven himself, nor did I understand her words as the opening salvo in
a musicological gender war. I just thought she was reporting her own expe-
rience of listening to Beethoven. I want to recapture and argue strenuously
for this “beginner’s” reading of McClary in the argument to come.3 It now
beethoven antihero 111
The music may well achieve sublime intensity . . . when notes are sustained for
unusually long periods of time and when the sheer volume of sound is shatter-
ingly intense, when the music’s progress is frequently interrupted, or when the
textures are so complex that the imagination is stretched to its limits in an
effort to follow what is going on. When we feel that we are poised over a bot-
tomless chasm, when the imagination encounters the limitless and the immeas-
urable, then the experience may be described as sublime. (le Huray 1979, 98)
We cannot credibly assert that Romantic critics did not appreciate con-
fusing, overpowering musical experiences like this one; abjection before the
sublime is one of the things they valued most about listening to Beethoven’s
music. Yet the rhetorical violence of his Ninth Symphony is extreme even
within the sublime, the built-in masochism of the aesthetic category harder
to ignore. We would do well to remember the physical bluntness of Edmund
Burke’s famous epigram: the beautiful is founded on pleasure, but the sub-
beethoven antihero 113
lime is founded on pain. Such pain may well underpin the increasingly neg-
ative metaphors, extending to war, catastrophe, and violent rape, that the
more erhabene moments of the Ninth have accumulated over time.
Though the Ninth is now the canonical masterwork of abstract instru-
mental music, a nagging hermeneutic anxiety quickly crystallized around
measures 301–15 of its first movement. The ff D major of the recapitulation
and its immediate aftermath have fascinated and troubled almost every
commentator since the middle of the nineteenth century. This was not
always so; early descriptions of the symphony concentrated on the famous
opening, the thematic content of the first movement’s exposition, and of
course discussed the propriety and success of the choral finale.4 Yet the pas-
sage has loomed increasingly large in criticism, interpretation, and analysis
of the Ninth, so that for many twentieth-century scholars it is the pivot of the
movement, if not the entire work. There is clearly something intrinsic to this
spot that has attracted increasing aesthetic attention, perhaps because it
combines to an extraordinary degree the “violence and signification” that,
in Joseph Kerman’s view, singled out Beethoven’s Fifth as the “paradigmatic
‘work of musical art’ for the nineteenth century” (1988, 484). That signify-
ing violence, whether acknowledged openly or not, seems to have drawn to
itself scholarly prose, both analytic and impressionistic.5
For the most part, hermeneutic approaches to this unexpected blast of
tonic major followed by tonal chaos define two (dialectically opposed)
strategies. The sublimating strategy, which attempts to focus on and interpret
its extremity, gives rise, dialectically, to the beautifying, which attempts to
deny or minimize any disturbing aspects, usually by exalting technical
description over exegesis. Beautifiers want to convince us that there is no
hermeneutic problem; they explain to us that the passage makes perfect for-
mal sense. Sublimators revel in the problem, and are often delighted to hint
through tone and imagery that the passage is problematic: that it is extreme,
overpowering, at the limits of musical discourse. Sometimes, they move
beyond the modern sublime—and anticipate postmodern hearing—as they
intimate that the Ninth does not make formal sense.
The distinction is neatly thematized in the first extended description of the
recapitulation, a remarkable passage in Robert Griepenkerl’s 1838 novel The
Music Festival, or the Beethovenians (Die Musikfest, oder die Beethovener). Years before
analysts and critics homed in on it, Griepenkerl described the exact moment
of recapitulation in impressive technical detail, as a moment of high drama:
“Crescendo! Sforzato! Every man for himself!” cried Vicarius, loudly slamming shut
the score he had been keenly following up until that point. And then began the
most sublime passage in the entire first movement. Pfeiffer saw in it the battle
between Old and New, the crucial gigantic and titanic battles of our times.
...
114 robert fink
Everyone attacked the open fifths in fortissimo, except the bassoons and
double basses, who once having achieved Fs refused to let it go; they held it out
in thirty-seconds against the mass of the orchestra hastening back into Chaos—
thus turning the entire passage, if you like, into a single first-inversion triad.
The previously-heard fifth-motives of the violins wandered fortissimo like angry
ghosts in and around the thunder of the drums, the blasts of the trumpets, and
the firmly anchored Fs of the basses. (Griepenkerl 1838)
always be a beautifier, someone who has kept his control, kept his score
firmly open, to tap the wild-eyed sublimator on the shoulder and point out
a thematic or formal connection. And if in 1838 it was Vicarius who ulti-
mately dominated the discussion, in the twentieth century it has been beau-
tifying criticism that has, until recently, had the last word.
Of course, there has always been a small and not particularly influential
minority who make an overt denial of any hermeneutic problem: they take
the D-major tutti at its “triumphant” face value. The most famous was prob-
ably Sir George Grove: “[the first theme] is now given with the fullest force
of the orchestra and the loudest clamour of the drum, and ending unmis-
takably in D major. Its purpose is accomplished, its mission fulfilled, its tri-
umph assured; no need now for concealment or hesitation!” (Grove 1884).
Grove’s bluff good humor was followed by the authors of many English-lan-
guage concert guides before Tovey (see below).
Another, vastly more influential group uses Adalbert’s more subtle beau-
tifying tactic—they look for the theme. This involves “hard” analysis: care-
fully avoiding emotional display, one presents the passage as a set of purely
technical-compositional conundrums to be unraveled. One of the first to do
this sort of thing was Hugo Riemann, in his Grundriß der Kompositionslehre
(Riemann 1889), but at the same time he allowed himself wild flights of sub-
limating description in less formal venues, such as program notes (see
below). Probably the first to undertake severely technical analysis of the
Ninth as an explicitly polemical act was Heinrich Schenker in his book-
length study of 1912—and it would not be unfair to say that ignoring all
questions of meaning in Beethoven’s Ninth has remained a polemical act to
this day.
Schenker’s 300-page study, undertaken years before the transcendental
concept of the Ursatz heated up his prose, is so matter-of-fact and detailed as
to be almost unreadable at length. He approaches measures 301–15 as a tra-
ditional Stufentheorist, providing a careful linear rationalization of its root
succession. An “ideal” Is3–sIV–V bass progression in D minor explicitly disci-
plines Schenker’s hearing of the passage (see Example 1b, below). He uses
it to dismiss any implication of D major other than as a chromatically-altered
tonic (V/iv), and to give “organic necessity” (organische Notwendigkeit) to the
sudden and apparently arbitrary appearance of the chord Bf–D–F–Af. In
general, Schenker prefers this complex chromatic root progression to the
looser concept of “mode mixture” between D major and D minor, a dialec-
tic all too susceptible to promiscuous interpretation in terms of joy-pain, tri-
umph-defeat and so on. As he points out, “[in the context of this functional
progression] the fundamental color change gains a sort of causality that
mode mixture totally fails to give” (“enthält doch das chroma prinzipiell
eben eine Art von Kausalität, wie sie der Mischung durchaus fehlt”; p. 123).
Schenker’s rigidly neutral tone, and his overt use of analysis to control and
116 robert fink
Wallowing in the syntactic disruption that theorists would later explain away,
Marx foregrounds irrationality and incoherence—the “unnatural” persis-
tence of frozen D major and the sudden, offbeat shift to a seemingly unre-
lated key. Note in particular the melodramatic reference to the apparition
of the Erdgeist in Goethe’s Faust, scene 1. (This is the kind of thing that drove
Schenker crazy.) In the poem, Faust calls up a figure of raw and elemental
power that overwhelms his intellect and disappears as abruptly and arbitrar-
ily as it came.9
Marx’s “terrifying specter” (Schreckensphantom) is a generational descen-
dant of the “angry ghosts” (zürnende Schatten) that appeared in Griepenkerl’s
1838 description, of which Marx may well have been aware. But the
beethoven antihero 117
The interpretive link between Beethoven’s Ninth and Goethe’s Faust was
to prove immensely attractive to the critical descendants of Vicarius. In tra-
versing the discourse around this work, one quickly learns to read any men-
tion of Faust as an overt or covert sublimating gesture. But the nineteenth-
century predilection for Faustian metaphor at the moment of recapitulation
also betrays a covert fear that the passage, exciting as it, may go a little too
far. Or perhaps it is exciting just because it goes too far. After all, isn’t the fig-
ure of Faust one of the archetypal human symbols of the pleasures and per-
ils of overreaching genius? Did Beethoven transgress here?
Most significant in this context is Marx’s last observation (“Conclude?—
that is not within the power of this troubled Giant-Spirit”), which begins to
hint that the passage is to be heard as a dramatic mimesis of formal and har-
monic failure. The first theme, though it has achieved provisional “sover-
eignty” in D major, does not have the power to “conclude,” that is, to cadence,
in any convincing way. In direct opposition to Schenker, whose chromati-
cized root progression provides a way of hearing (“eine Art von Kausalität”)
that allows this chord sequence to succeed, Marx’s account simply accepts
the momentary sense of mystification and failed progression.10
Corroborative evidence can be adduced from Wagner’s 1846 description
of the emotional progression within the movement as a whole: “Thus force,
revolt, defiance, yearning, hope, near-success, fresh loss, new quest, repeated
struggle, make out the elements of ceaseless motion in this wondrous
piece . . .” (p. 247). Map this progression of emotional states onto sonata
form, and it appears that the moment of recapitulation and its aftermath cor-
respond to “near-success” (Fast-Erreichen) and “fresh loss” (neues Verschwinden)
respectively. One might well ask why this passage only rates as a near success:
could it be the failure to cadence—a purely formal failure—that Wagner is
hearing?
118 robert fink
heart of the hurricane. Masses of sound collide violently. The winds set them-
selves up in contrapuntal opposition to the strings; and the lightning bolts
intertwine, both from the heights and depths.12
couldn’t take the physical violence of the Fifth (Kerman 1988); a year after
that, Richard Taruskin lambasted pseudo-historical theses about perfor-
mance practice that allowed performers to resist the unfashionably “cosmic”
idealism of the Ninth (Taruskin 1989).
But—perhaps inevitably—McClary’s Beethoven-based feminist criticism
was read as a feminist criticism of Beethoven, and it struck a painful nerve.
That first tangential aside in the Minnesota Composer’s Forum Newsletter caused
such furor that when the essay was reprinted in book form (McClary 1991)
she evidently felt it necessary to expand her discussion and explain some of
the structural assumptions that gave rise to her earlier impressionistic
account. The general tone of this second description is quite controlled.
McClary situates the passage as the climactic, “horrifyingly violent” moment
in an Adorno-esque conflict between the musical subject (the first theme)
and the pressures of a tonal narrative that relentlessly threatens its individu-
ality:
But for the subject of the Ninth, to return to the beginning is to actually regress
to a point further back than its own conscious beginnings: it is to be dissolved
back into the undifferentiated state from which it originally emerged. And if
its hard-won identity means anything, the subject cannot accept such dissolu-
tion, even if it is toward that conventional moment of re-entry that the whole
background structure of the movement has inexorably driven. (1991, 128)
The point of recapitulation in the first movement of the Ninth is one of the
most horrifying moments in music, as the carefully prepared cadence is frustrated,
122 robert fink
damming up energy which finally explodes in the throttling, murderous rage of a rapist
incapable of attaining release. The ‘triumphal’ end of the symphony—in which
promised cadences repeatedly are withheld at the last moment—finally simply
forces closure by bludgeoning the cadence and the piece to death. (McClary
1987, 12–13—emphasis mine, following that of posterity)
This image of “Beethoven the rapist” is, of course, painful in the extreme—
and scandalizing to many readers. But if we examine the rape image in light
of the descriptions of earlier sublimating critics, we can see its origin:
McClary makes exactly the same imaginative cathexis as Marx, Kretzschmar,
et al.—but she reinterprets the violent, confusing, overpowering physicality
of the experience from her female subject position.
The inherent sadomasochism of the sublime now takes on a new, threat-
ening aspect. When Beethoven’s “demonic intentions” (Kretzschmar) and
his “overwhelming demonic fantasies” (Riemann) are redirected, when the
relation between the masculine composer and the masculine critic is
replaced by that between a masculine composer and a feminine critic—what
other gendered image carries as much force as rape?
The pain suffered by the imagination in judgments upon the sublime has lead
some critics of Kant to denounce the tyranny of reason, to which the imagina-
tion submits itself in judgments upon the sublime. Undoubtedly, Kant’s refer-
ences in this context to subjection (Unterwerfung), violence (Gewalt), depriva-
tion (Emphasis Beraubung), and sacrifice (Aufopferung), encourage such an
interpretation. The notion of Beraubung Emphasisis particularly significant
here, since in addition to its usual meaning of “being robbed,” it can also sug-
gest rape.18
Push just a little bit on Marx’s 1859 description and sexual violence is
exactly what you will get. As we have seen, it was Marx who first linked
Beethoven’s recapitulation to a specific moment in Goethe’s Faust, the
apparition of the Erdgeist. For fin-de-siècle playwright Frank Wedekind, this
“Earth-Spirit” was a frankly sexual being, a fact so self-evident that he could
appropriate it as just another name for Lulu, his avatar of sexual destruction.
(The first published part of Wedekind’s “Lulu-play” was called simply
Erdgeist.19) The scene Marx recalls reads easily as a barely-disguised episode
of homosexual rape, as Faust evokes the (at that point male) Earth-Spirit in
a flood of feminized, sexualized longing:
Reveal yourself!
Ha! How my heart is gored
By never felt urges,
And my whole body surges—
My heart is yours; yours, too am I.
You must. You must. Though I should have to die.
beethoven antihero 123
self was painfully aware of: that other possessors of the Y chromosome,
respected critics like Marx, Riemann, and Kretschmar, had previously expe-
rienced Beethoven’s Ninth not only as prolongations and scale steps, but as
“the overwhelming, demonic fantasy of the Master’s creative impulse.” Out
of that collective fantasy they constructed not only Beethoven Hero, the man
who freed music, but Beethoven Antihero, the Faustian purveyor of sublime
eroticized violence. In the discourse around the Ninth, McClary is hardly out-
side the pale, and to dismiss her as a man-hating feminist (see below) is to
repress large swaths of reception history. When it comes to sublimating crit-
icism, she is just one of the guys.
And yet, for all its continuities in tone and imagery with a long line of
male accounts, the value judgment implied by McClary’s feminist critique
(yet not overtly levied within it, I hasten to add) does appear to open up a
radically new and negative hermeneutic, at least within high art music criti-
cism. Where male critics felt only masochistic pleasure, McClary allows for
the possibility of dread.
Drawn into greater and more explicit detail, the one side could only disappoint
the other, become the distraction of the other. It would be diminished,
reduced to a form of silliness. This happens with McClary’s analysis of the
Ninth . . . additional detail undermines the alleged relationship between
music and sex or sexual politics; the two sides are pulled further apart. (van
den Toorn 1995, 36)
If all that was at stake was the acknowledgment within the Ninth of the
romantic-modern sublime, of unpresentable content mediated by the power
of formal presentation, we might attempt to make a separate peace with van
den Toorn. Lyotard’s conception of the modern sublime does allow for a
kind of appreciation that, moving away from a sense of powerlessness and
pain, identifies with the intelligence that empowers a composer like
Beethoven to present the unpresentable through formal abstraction: “the
emphasis can be placed on the increase of being and the jubilation which
results from the invention of new rules of the game” (1992, 147). In other
words: one can beautify the sublime, one can “look for the theme.”
But what if one reads McClary’s failed rapist as an avatar of the presence
within Beethoven’s Ninth of the postmodern sublime, of the traumatic
moment where the unpresentable breaks through into presentation itself?
In that case beautifying criticism’s defensive focus on formal innovation
(“new rules of the game”) would provide little protection, since the collapse
of the masterwork’s “organic” form would be precisely the issue. But to grasp
the totality of that collapse, we must take up van den Toorn’s challenge to
work the rape metaphor deeply into the detail of Beethoven’s music, the
detail he so confidently assumes will make a mockery of it, that he assumes
is unproblematically on “his” side.
How then to unravel the confusing welter of details at measures 301–15
of the first movement of the Ninth?
Most critics look to the bass of this passage: they are trying to come to terms
with an essential failure of functional root progression at a pivotal moment
in the harmonic drama. The dynamics of sonata form demand a major har-
monic arrival on the home tonic at this point: if not a perfect V–I closure, at
least some easily recognizable transformation. The general consensus is that
measures 295–301 do not provide that closure: the dominant is too weak and
abrupt, and the first-inversion major tonic too unstable for such an important
formal juncture. Indeed, the Fs in the bass of the tonic triad at measure 301
introduces another, conflicting harmonic imperative, for it sounds very much
like a leading tone to G minor. Thus as we wait for the immobile D major to
move in measures 301–12, expectation builds for the basic cadential pro-
gression that will neatly resolve both local and global harmonic needs:
I6–iv–V–i, as in example 4.1a. This tonic–predominant–dominant–tonic is the
126 robert fink
# Yc W A A A
A c
∏ I6 iv V i
# Yc W A WA A A c
∏ I6 ∏ iv7 V i6
is in fact the case in every one of van den Toorn’s counterexamples. But, as
I pointed out above, the single most disruptive fact about measures 312–13
is that the G6 “resolves” not to a common dominant substitute, but to an
extremely uncommon first-inversion tonic, forcing the Bf in the bass not to
A, but to F. That is why Beethoven can keep the tonic D pedal sounding in
the timpani underneath this G6 and its resolution, underscoring the fact that
there is actually no dominant functionality in the passage at all. This is, to my
mind, the difference between “shortchanging a cadential cliché” and a much
more radical compositional gesture: destroying any sense of comprehensi-
ble cadential syntax. Van den Toorn’s comparisons covertly beautify: they put
back in the structural dominant that Beethoven so disruptively left out.
But identifying the “deviation” (however extreme) is merely the first step;
as van den Toorn quite rightly points out, the focus of analysis should be the
significance of the deviation, how it functions in a particular context. In fact,
of course, analysis creates that context, and this van den Toorn now proceeds
to do. He rationalizes the irregular resolution of Bf by pointing out that it is
part of a local motivic relationship: the F–Bf–F in the bass is to be heard as
an imitation of the preceding D–A–D in the strings, and thus, we assume, a
thematic echo of the basic material of the movement (ex. 4.2). (“The theme,
listen for the theme!”) A more global context explains the “dramatic Fs–F
slip” as an echo of another prominent half-step slip in the movement, the
beginning of the development at measure 160. The loud Fs itself echoes mea-
sure 186, cementing a symmetrical formal relationship between the begin-
ning and the end of the development section.
One might quibble with some of the details of this context. The relation-
ship between D–A–D (4th + 5th) and F–Bf–F (5th + 4th) is more complex
than simple imitation, and surely the passage most echoed by measures
312–15 is not the opening of the development but the counterstatement of
the first theme at measures 48–50, with its own sudden drop from D–A–D to
F–Bf–F. But it is not my aim to “tyrannize” van den Toorn by forbidding him
contextual hearing and the power of his analytical insights. It is certainly pos-
sible to hear this moment of recapitulation van den Toorn’s way if one
desires; the issue is not one of right or wrong. Rather, the questions that need
to be asked are: What do we gain by hearing measures 301–15 only this way?
Conversely, what must we give up?
Van den Toorn is forthright in describing the benefits he gains by hear-
ing within the context he has constructed: “[the Fs–F slip] projects a large-
scale formal association that tends to dampen, at least for this observer, its
potential for alarm, the effect of ‘horror’ or ‘murderous rage’ felt by
McClary” (1995, 34). Here is the clearest possible statement of the defensive,
distancing aim of beautifying analysis. Over 150 years after Griepenkerl’s
novel, van den Toorn is still playing Adalbert to Susan McClary’s Vicarius,
using purely musical intuitions to call her back from dangerous hermeneu-
beethoven antihero 129
BB CC OO YC B
ff Y CC BB
BB CO
! Y 42 B
CO
CO C C C hC B
ff X C
C C C ff C C C
C jh C TU C C C UT C C S C C C
! Y 42 C C C C
ff hj WC
# Y 2 ___ W_ C ___ W C C C C X C C C C ___ __
4 WC __ YC C_
ff ff
X
BB X BB CC CC OOOO
B XB C C OO C
C
! Y B BB
C C C C C OO C
! Y C
C C T U U jhl C OO C CO C C
C C
_
# Y C __
C C C C C C C XC C OO C C C OO C C
tic excess, his analytical counterargument not much more than a more
sophisticated and extended version of . . .
“The theme, listen for the theme!”
reassuring certainties? In the second part of this essay, I intend to use the
first-movement recapitulation as the touchstone in a wide-ranging analytical
discussion that incorporates all the richness of musical detail I can muster.
The burden of the argument will be that, far from offering us salvation from
the symphony’s unpresentable content, the form of Beethoven’s Ninth is
itself not salvageable, shattered at its critical structural turning points by the
irruption of the unpresentable into the act of presentation. I believe, pace
van den Toorn, that the deeper we delve into the specific musical and formal
tensions this work enacts, the more “potential for alarm” we will find.
Let us begin by taking McClary’s infamous evocation of the postmodern
sublime not as a simplistic statement about content, but as a complex intu-
ition about form. It might be schematically unpacked as follows. The thrust-
ing drive of tonal music, the intertwining of harmonic and formal necessity,
is physical, and gives rise to a physical desire—analogous to sexual desire. In
measures 301–15, Beethoven focuses all the potential desire of a large-scale
symphonic form onto a single cadential moment (McClary: “damming up
energy”), and then proceeds to botch it unforgettably in a passage of terri-
fyingly violent orchestral kineticism (McClary: “which finally explodes in the
throttling, murderous rage of a rapist”) that is thereby frustrated, which is to
say reconverted into potential (McClary: “unable to attain release”).
It is worth pointing out how far this is from a man-hating condemnation
of “Beethoven the Pornographer” (van den Toorn 1991, 291). We the lis-
teners are both raped and rapists. It is both our desire that is frustrated by the
botched progression, and our bodies and minds that are overwhelmed by the
“noise” of the orchestra and the irrationality of the passage. McClary does not
just “cry rape”: she evokes the complex mimetic image of a rapist who is unable
to attain release. And in this she provides a precise echo of previous male crit-
ics like A. B. Marx (“To conclude?—no, that is not within the power of this
troubled Giant-Spirit”). She introduces them to Adrienne Rich, whose poem
on the Ninth begins: “A man in terror of impotence . . .”
Thus the first step toward understanding the larger structural implications
of this traumatic passage is to hear it as a violent acting out covering up a
more fundamental formal impotence; this reading of the musical surface
becomes increasingly insistent as we survey critical responses from Marx to
McClary. To go any further, we must break new ground, and investigate in a
more detailed and unconventional way just what it is that this passage was try-
ing—and so conspicuously failing—to do.
C f CC O C C f BC C C
f C C C fB WC C
# YY 3 C O C C C C C C
C C S CO WC C C
4 h CO C C C
fff
Y WC C C C Y CC B OO B OO B OO XB
! Y C
C S S B B B XB C
C C BO
De - us, De - us, pa- ter o mni - po - tens.
W CC CC XCWC C C C C BO BO BO XB
C C XC W C WC
C C BO BO BO XB C
# YY WC C C C BO
YC C
fff
bass, but on what the bass denies: the soprano line, which it flatly refuses to
support, specifically the Af(Gs) A in the first flute. Physical extremity and
rhythmic surprise mark this Gs–A as a significant melodic climax; the non-
progression of the bass marks it (makes it) unequivocally a failure. In this
case, Beethoven has annihilated his climax so thoroughly that little more
than the indecipherable fragments from some kind of rising line are left
behind. To reconstruct this ascent, and ascertain its place within some larger
formal mechanism, we can attempt to read it through another failed ascent,
analogous in structure, but less extreme and thus less distorted. Example 4.3
reproduces what I feel is a functionally identical spot in the Missa Solemnis:
measures 176–90 of the Gloria (“Domine Deus, Rex coelestis, Deus pater
omnipotens”). This passage displays a striking identity of surface detail, local
harmonic progression, and large-scale formal function with measures
301–15. Once we determine how this earlier failed climax works, we can use
that knowledge to comprehend the later and significantly more disrupted
passage.
Simple enumeration will document a telling repetition of compositional
detail: both climaxes are built around the same loud, off-balance anticipa-
tion of the Bf–D–F–Af sonority (ff in the Ninth, fff in the Gloria). Both sur-
prise chords support a long Af in the flutes that progresses directly and
enharmonically to A. Both passages are sonically extreme: the prolonged
orchestral battering of the Ninth is matched in sheer violence by the Gloria’s
132 robert fink
overwhelming and isolated blast (fff tutti with chorus, trombones) on the
crucial Bf7 —a truly awesome depiction of the “pater omnipotens.” Even the
drumroll on a non-fundamental D is the same.
The convergence of sound is the visceral clue to an identity of function.
Both of these passages attempt a piece of modulatory trickery very charac-
teristic of Beethoven: they reinterpret a dominant-seventh chord
(Bf–D–F–Af) as a German sixth (Bf–D–F–Gs) to force an enharmonic short-
cut out of a long flat-side excursion and back home to D major. The har-
monic functions map quite neatly from one piece to the other (see ex. 4.4).
Both passages come from the flat side of D—the Gloria from Ef (locally
IV/Bf; m. 174), the Ninth from F (measures 287 ff.). In both cases the sud-
den intrusion of an Fs instead of the expected F creates a D-major triad,
which functions locally as V/gm (Gloria, mm. 182–84; Ninth, mm. 301–11).
At this point, the Gloria, composing out van den Toorn’s “cadential cliché,”
gives us fully and explicitly what the Ninth elides and distorts beyond recog-
nition. V/gm actually resolves to G minor in measure 185 of the Gloria, fol-
lowed immediately by the pivotal Bf–D–F–Af, whose enharmonic resolution
to a unison A ( = V/D, resolving in the next measure) this time makes per-
fect voice-leading sense.
Yet this modulatory progression, though more syntactically correct than
its counterpart in the Ninth, is no less a failure to establish D major as tonic.
Beethoven immediately undermines his seemingly “omnipotent” climax.
Measures 192–95 provide an exceptionally vivid piece of mime in which the
fff tutti falls apart before our eyes: fading shards of the movement’s opening
motive disintegrate into aimless woodwind chattering while the energy of
rushing unison scales in the strings audibly droops and dissipates, section by
section. And, just as in the Ninth, we realize retroactively that the big D-major
chord at this climax was not a tonic, but a dominant. By allowing Bf and Ef
to reassert themselves, Beethoven turns the omnipotent D into a somewhat
querulous V9/gm—and we fall back to the flat side again. The final clue,
though inaudible, is unequivocal in its symbolic import. The written key sig-
nature after the climax is the same as it was before: two flats. In terms of real
modulatory activity, nothing has happened—just as in measures 301–15 of
the Ninth, where the implied key signature both coming in (F major) and
going out (D minor) is one flat.22
So it appears that no amount of physical (or rhetorical) force will convert
this enharmonic trick into a true modulation; in retrospect, the brutal
excess of both these G6 chords only betrays a foreknowledge of failure, the
awareness that the rules are being broken, that this shortcut between third-
related triads ultimately won’t work. Indeed, the significance of this particu-
lar and complicated mimetic gesture (stressed G6 leads to instantaneous
modulation up by third; premature arrival on major tonic; immediate dis-
integration) was being established by Beethoven as early as 1807. In mea-
beethoven antihero 133
#4 – 5
Gloria, mm. 174–200
YA AAA W AA A Y AA A
A A
! Y AA A A A A
# Y YA A A A
A A A A A
flat side F∏ ! “G6” V I
sures 73–91 of the slow movement of the Fifth Symphony, there is an abrupt
“modulation” from the flat side (Af) to the tonic major of the entire work (C
major) accomplished by an unexpected and assaultive G6; this highly
unstable tonic then fades away, evaporating back into the flat side through
an amorphous chromatic passage.
The “G6 cadence” in this mimetic context becomes a signifier of har-
monic failure; its similar appearance provides a convincing link between
measures 185–89 of the Gloria and measures 312–15 of the first movement
of the Ninth. As we know from tonal theory, G6 is primarily a linear chord,
and it is as a signifier of linear failure that I ultimately want to consider it. It
is in terms of long-range dramatic voice leading that reading the Ninth
through the Gloria begins to pay off most spectacularly. These passages both
use local harmonic failures to undermine the large-scale linear structures
that aim to climax above them. But the linear ascent that was shattered
beyond reconstruction in the Ninth is merely negated, after the fact, in the
Gloria. In fact, the Lydian ascent that is momentarily achieved in measures
174–89 of the Gloria, together with the bass line that ultimately undermines
it, gives us the basic outline of a complex linear-harmonic template that
functions on a large scale in both the Ninth and the Missa Solemnis.
One can see the melodic significance of the Gs–A that is common to both
failed climaxes more clearly in the more coherent linear context of the Glo-
ria: there it functions as the powerfully stressed last step in a chromatic
ascent from D to A that spans measures 173–89 (see the soprano line of ex.
134 robert fink
4.3). This ascent to scale degree 5 (in the high soprano register) by way of a
dramatically highlighted sharp fourth scale degree is the basic prototype of
successful linear motion in the Ninth and the D-major sections of the Missa
—thus the descriptive term “Lydian.”
The Lydian Ascent, the Missing Dominant, and the Subdominant Collapse
A cursory look at the D-centered movements in the Missa Solemnis and the
Ninth Symphony will uncover plentiful attempts at this climactic Lydian
march up to the fifth scale degree (Gloria, measures 38–42, 303–12; 335–45,
509–25, 530–42; Dona nobis pacem, measures 350–74; Ninth I, measures
31–35, 55–63, 301–15, 531–39; Ninth IV, measures 325–29, 832–41; see Fink
1994). But what does it mean to argue that this melodic mannerism encodes
some kind of possible formal success—and, conversely, that diatonic cli-
mactic progressions more firmly “in D” are to be heard as “failures”? How is
it that the diatonic scale steps of D major are somehow not good enough for
the Ninth?
I have discussed what Leo Treitler once called “the phenomenology of key
relations” in the Missa Solemnis and the Ninth Symphony at length elsewhere
(Fink 1994, 167–71). I will simply recall here what Treitler and others have
noted: that large-scale tonal relationships in the Ninth Symphony are
plagued by a pull toward the flat side, “down” toward “darker” keys like B-
flat and E-flat, a pull that has the effect of derailing, time and again, the move
“up” and sharpwards to the dominant (Treitler 1989, 57–63).23 This seduc-
tive pull, if indulged, threatens to usurp the tonic–dominant polarity that is
an absolute necessity if a traditional sonata form (which the Ninth still
emphatically tries to be) is to make sense.
The battle against this flat-side pull lies behind two of the most com-
mented-upon narrative threads in the Ninth’s symphonic plot: the drive to
move from D minor to D major; and the equally compelling need to exor-
cise B-flat so that it can no longer compete as a tonal center with D. The dra-
matic coups de théâtre are familiar to anyone who has studied the piece: sud-
den unmotivated drops by third to F, Bf, and even Ef triads at critical
moments in the form; systematic displacement of secondary key areas in the
dominant or relative major with moves to the flat submediant; increasingly
violent attempts to banish Efs and Bfs from crucial cadential gestures; the
final achievement of a hushed and radiant B major, followed by the heedless
rush of a (seemingly) unsullied D-major corroboree.
Thus for most commentators, the story of the Ninth is about getting rid
of the tonal intrusions that undermine the stability of the D-major tonic. But
simply banishing “wrong notes” and “wrong keys,” sharping all the Fns and
naturalizing all the Bfs, does not actually solve the fundamental tonal aporia
of the work: the fatal absence, especially in the D-centered outer movements,
beethoven antihero 135
directly on the heels of a previous failed attempt to avoid flat-side collapse and
stabilize D major as tonic.
I consider the linear-dramatic significance of the famously “darkly blaz-
ing” D-major chord itself, voiced with a prominent A on top, to be the des-
perate attempt to avoid an incipient subdominant collapse, to progress
directly from an unsharped fourth to a stable fifth scale degree. The first
horn’s seventh at measures 293–300 does not fall to the third; it rises to the
fifth in direct and visceral contravention of voice-leading rules—in effect,
against tonal “gravity.” (Contrary to his received image as a brutal and
heedless orchestrator, Beethoven could be exquisitely considerate of
instrumental needs when it suited his dramatic purpose. So the hornists
are the only players given rests on the last beat before D major crashes in;
they alone have time to breathe and prepare a true ff attack. We need that
high A.)
This to me is what is so terrible about the “terrible” D major: the sheer
violence channeled into supporting the doomed D–A fifth—an interval
whose imminent collapse will call into question a basic axiom of
Beethoven’s tonal harmony. The perceptual precision of A. B. Marx’s Faus-
tian fustian now becomes impressively clear: he is exactly right to focus on
the way that Beethoven makes Fs–A–D sound as if unnaturally (and precar-
iously) frozen in place: “er . . . steht . . . zwölf Takte lang, unbeweglich wie
ein Schreckensphantom, auf Fis-A-D . . .” And Faust’s cry of horror in the
face of this “terrifying phantom” could double as Beethoven’s cry of despair
when the horns collapse down to low [D] in measure 312: “Weh! Ich ertrag
dich nicht!” (The English equivalent that best captures the linear double
meaning is “I cannot bear you”—both “I cannot endure you” and “I cannot
hold you up”; the root of ertragen is tragen = “carry.”) The open fifth, so cos-
mically weightless in the Ninth’s opening bars, now carries all the weight of
tonic–dominant polarity, and is literally insupportable without some dra-
matic reinforcement.
The crucial fifth scale degree is so unstable that Beethoven immediately
resorts to a brutal G6 cadence in hopes of generating a dramatic Lydian pro-
gression to shore it up. When that cadence collapses in a welter of voice-lead-
ing mistakes, the double failure extinguishes all hope for the strong push
through sharp 4 to 5 that would buttress tonic–dominant polarity and in so
doing, at least partially compensate for the movement’s lack of a structural
dominant. Beethoven’s “inability to attain release” at this pivotal formal
moment—he tries to get it up (to A), and fails twice!—threatens the global
collapse of tonal logic. The unspeakable content (“A man in terror of impo-
tence . . .”) leaves its trace on the music itself: a failed recapitulation; a lin-
ear collapse; a shattered tonic–dominant polarity; ultimately, an unsalvage-
able form.
beethoven antihero 137
Example 4.5 Beethoven, Ninth Symphony I, Coda, mm. 531–38: Lydian ascent
returns.
∏3 ∏4 5
WC C OO C WC C OO C XW C C C C OOOO CC CC CC OOOO CC
C C OO C C C OO C
! Y 42
ff π6
# Y2 XC C C C XC C WC C
4 XC C XC WC
ff [I C C C C
°V/V V]
∏3 ∏4 5
WC C OO C WC C OO C WC C OO C C C OO
C
WC C OO C WC C OO C WC C OO C C C OO
! Y
sempre ff
XC C C C XC C WC C
# XC C WC
Y XC
C C C C
sempre ff
Aftermath
Flutes and horns grasp desperately for the dominant A while the bass line
that spiked their G6 cadence continues to wreak havoc: metrically out of step
with both winds and strings, it gnaws away at the tonic pedal, gradually forc-
ing it flatwards with grinding Cns and Fss. By measure 325 we have arrived,
not at the hoped-for dominant, but at a root-position subdominant that
quickly plunges to a Neapolitan Ef.
We must wait over 200 measures for a partial retrieval of the recapitula-
tion’s titanic collapse onto the subdominant; this is the function of the very
last harmonic progression of the first movement (mm. 531–38; ex. 4.5). The
Lydian ascent Fs–Gs–A blared out by the ff woodwind (the second time in
brutal unison) is clear enough; it should also be pointed out that the har-
monic progression taking place over the tonic pedal is an implicit recom-
position of the failed G6 cadence of measures 312–15. D major as possible
V/iv is now followed by a “corrected” predominant sonority: Bn–D–F–Gs as
° V/V, instead of Bf–D–F–Af as G6/V (see the reductions in ex. 4.6).25 With
the (momentary) purging of Bf, Beethoven can finish the ascent, progress-
ing directly to the missing root-position V and thence to the tonic.
There are no more Bfs in the first movement, but that is only because
Beethoven deploys the ascending melodic version of the D-minor scale to
138 robert fink
AA AA AA AA A
! Y A A A ! Y A X AA W AAA
Schenker’s
scale-step
# Y WA WA A analyses # Y WA WA A
I∏3 ∏IV [ ∫ 7/3] V [6/4] (I) I∏3 ∏IV 7 V (I)
Scale steps: ∏III ∏IV V Scale steps: ∏III ∏IV V
f∏ – g∏ – a
close. The first movement’s final cadence, martial as it is, cannot “fix” the fail-
ure of the recapitulation by establishing D major as tonic. The second move-
ment tries to further a Lydian agenda, moving immediately from D minor to
C major (the dominant of the relative major, a “sharper” key than we might
expect); it also, as van den Toorn points out, re-stages the crucial G6 cadence
of the first movement at its own moment of recapitulation (mm. 248–83)
with slightly better local results. But the ultimate outcome is yet another col-
lapse onto B-flat as submediant (m. 304). This scherzo has a bad habit of
spinning ever flatter through cycles of falling thirds (mm. 144–71); these dis-
orienting descents prepare us for the topsy-turvy world of the slow move-
ment, where D major is made to serve as secondary key to the submediant-
as-tonic, B-flat.
That same B-flat is jammed like a dissonant splinter into the opening D-
minor sonority of the last movement. This submediant-infected minor tonic
is in first inversion, and “progresses” through a German-sixth chord to the
dominant: with horror (nineteenth-century German critics dubbed this the
beethoven antihero 139
epilogue
. . . yelling at Joy from the tunnel of the ego
music without the ghost
of another person in it, music
trying to tell something the man
does not want out, would keep if he could
gagged and bound and flogged with chords of Joy
where everything is silence and the
beating of a bloody fist upon
a splintered table.
adrienne rich, “The Ninth Symphony
of Beethoven Understood at Last as
a Sexual Message”
142 robert fink
Beethoven Antihero
Noise is the trace the unpresentable leaves in a musical presentation, the
high-decibel, high-distortion edge of the postmodern sonic sublime. And it
seems in the late twentieth century it has mostly been women listening to
Beethoven’s Ninth as noise. They are the only ones who are willing to talk
about it, at any rate; and their reaction has been uniformly troubled. After
all: the sixteen-fold trochaic repetition of a fortissimo D-major triad I just fin-
ished celebrating—wasn’t that the exact passage in the Ninth that inspired
Adrienne Rich to the brutal trochaic pentameter of “Gagged and bound and
flogged with chords of Joy” (Rich 1973, 205–6)? There are sixteen trochees
from “gagged” to the end of her poem; you could sing her words to
Beethoven’s music. (Go on—I dare you.)
It was Susan McClary who introduced most of us to Rich’s poem, and
McClary is well aware of the insoluble dilemma that this Prestissimo repre-
sents:
The “triumphal” end of the symphony is likewise problematic, for how could
any configuration of pitches satisfactorily ground the contradictions set
forth over the course of this gargantuan composition? As the conclusion
is approached, the promised (though by definition, inadequate) cadences
repeatedly are withheld at the last moment; and finally Beethoven simply
forces closure by bludgeoning the cadence and the piece to death. (1991,
129)
Beethoven’s overwhelming desire for the tonic major strides forth, “naked
and powerful.”
“Seid umschlungen”? Maybe not.
The title of Rich’s poem is “The Ninth Symphony of Beethoven Under-
stood at Last as a Sexual Message.” Understood that way, as we have under-
stood it here, the message really is profoundly dystopic and disturbing, a mes-
sage totally at odds with the work’s utopian Enlightenment surface. But it
would be a serious mistake to think that the feminist demurral in the face of
the Ninth’s triumphal ending is merely an artifact of their sexual reading,
and can be erased by refusing to hear the piece “their way.” The doubts they
raise resonate with other radical critiques of music and society—even those
untainted by sexual hermeneutics. For example, it’s easy to link this musical
violence to actual social and political structures. There could hardly be any
simple, unambivalent approach to “alle Menschen werden Brüder” in Met-
ternich’s Austria, after the Napoleonic Wars and the Congress of Vienna.
(Nicholas Cook puts it well: “can Beethoven really have been so unthinking,
so dumb, as to remain unaffected by the history of his own time, holding true
to the beliefs of the 1780s in the Vienna of the 1820s, with its censorship,
secret police, and network of informers?” [1993, 102]) One could point out
that by 1825, Beethoven himself had experienced (if vicariously) the dialec-
tical relation between Enlightenment reason, violence and totalitarian con-
trol. The canceled dedication of the Eroica is a famous example of
Beethoven’s sensitivity to the failure of revolutionary politics. Is the Ninth his
Sinfonia anti-eroica? Did he, twenty years later, compose a little bit of the Ter-
ror and the Restoration into his belated paean to the ideals of the French
Revolution? (The Ninth, by the way, is dedicated to one of the founding
members of the counterrevolutionary Holy Alliance, King Friedrich Wil-
helm III of Prussia, “in tiefster Ehrfurcht.”)
Explicit political metaphors for musical violence—anarchy, class war, civil
insurrection—already appear in Greipenkerl’s 1838 account of the first-
movement recapitulation. “Old Hitzig,” the principal bassist, is under no
illusions that, in the midst of music like this, “all men are brothers”:
Through the entire passage the double basses held on to D, once again in
thirty-seconds. Old Hitzig, who completely understood the gigantic pedal
point of which he was the Atlas, leaned into his instrument and counterbal-
anced the storm breaking over his head with all his God-given strength of arm.
He pulled notes out of his old Luizi that cut through the orchestral mass like
the pedal tones of an organ.
“Stand firm,” he encouraged the other double-bassists. “The rabble above us
is really going crazy. [Das Gesindel über uns treibt wahrhaftig zu toll.] Don’t let go,
and it will all pass right over us. The scoundrels have a good mind to toss us bass
players in the pan and make pancakes of us. Damn, those triplet-sixteenths in
the flutes and violins whistle like bullets through dry grass, I’ll soon take one
144 robert fink
A bystander like Vicarius (thus his name?) can afford to indulge in sub-
lime affirmations of this welter of sound (“this is no street brawl”). Hitzig is
in the thick of it. Trying, like any good bass player, to preserve the remnants
of orderly root progression, he hears above him only the threat of a mob riot-
ing dangerously out of control (“Das Gesindel über uns treibt wahrhaftig zu
toll”). History tells us that we unleash this revolutionary force at our peril;
there is only a short step from brotherhood to blood-brotherhood. When D
major returns at the end of the piece, is it because all men are brothers—or
just that they all, finally, love Big Brother?
For a dialectician like Adorno, the choice is moot. Rose Subotnik intro-
duced many of us to Adorno’s “diagnosis” of Beethoven’s late style, a style
that for Adorno was inconceivable in isolation from the successive political
disillusionments of the years 1789–1824. Confrontation with the funda-
mental truth of modern society—that individual freedom and social order
are not reconcilable—rendered the affirmative critique inherent in
Beethoven’s “heroic” second-period style impossible to sustain. Earlier,
Beethoven had created optimistic musical narratives in which individual sub-
jects (themes) enacted struggle and synthesis with society (form). But by
1824 this utopian synthesis was no longer a believable prospect:
Thus Adorno finds “authenticity” in the late style’s refusal of the heroic
manner, its denial of synthesis. Musical works now act out the impossibility
of synthesis: the battle between the individuality embodied in themes and
the necessity inherent in forms shatters the musical discourse. Form either
fragments into anarchy, or becomes overtly conventional and oppressive;
subjectivity flees behind equally fragmented or conventional musical mate-
rial.
From this point of view, the embattled first movement of the Ninth is bril-
liantly negative, and the “sublime” moment of recapitulation is actually its
most tragic and authentic denial of synthesis (this Adorno-esque subtext is
particularly strong in McClary 1991). But the heavy-handed utopianism of
the Ode to Joy is out of touch, dangerously close to “false consciousness.”
Indeed, Adorno had problems with the Ninth as ideology: choosing between
the late choral works, he spurned the Ninth in favor of the Missa Solemnis, a
beethoven antihero 145
When utopia, which provided the French Revolution with its content of hope,
entered German music and philosophy (effectively and ineffectively), the
established civil order wholly functionalized reason, which became a purpose-
less purposiveness which might thus be attached to all ends. In this sense, rea-
son is planning considered solely as planning. The totalitarian State manipu-
lates the people. Or as [the Marquis de] Sade’s [police chief,] Francavilla puts
it: “The government must control the population, and must possess all the
means necessary to exterminate them.” (Horkheimer and Adorno 1991,
88–89)
From utopia to the death camp. And if Furtwängler could conduct the Ode
to Joy and then reach down to shake Goebbels’s hand, how can Adorno or any
of us exonerate Beethoven’s Ninth from its portion of guilt?
But we can, if we choose, leave the National Socialists out of it; there are
even more fundamental critiques available if we draw back from orgiastic cel-
ebrations of (Strength through) Joy. Consider Jacques Attali, for whom the con-
cept of “noise” is the foundation of a unique and brilliantly post-structural
“political economy of music.” Revisit the end of Beethoven’s Ninth with
Attali’s basic premise in mind:
Both the feminist and the post-structuralist deal in basic instincts: for
McClary music constructs and disciplines sexuality, for Attali music con-
structs and disciplines aggression. And Attali, like McClary, is well aware of
how far this combination of sublimated sex and violence is from our ideal-
ized picture of musical appreciation:
The hypotheses of noise as murder and music as sacrifice are not easy to accept.
They imply that music functions like sacrifice; that listening to noise is a little
like being killed; that listening to music is to attend a ritual murder, with all
the danger, guilt, but also reassurance that goes along with that; that applaud-
ing is a confirmation, after the channelization of the violence, that the specta-
tors of the sacrifice could potentially resume practicing the essential violence
(Attali 1985, 28).
1896 Grove, George, Beethoven and His Nine Symphonies, 3d ed. (London:
Novello, 1898).
1912 Schenker, Heinrich, Beethoven Neunte Sinfonie (Leipzig, 1912).
1920 Ernest, Gustave, Beethoven (Berlin: G. Bondi, 1920).
1927 Nef, Karl, Die Neun Sinfonien Beethovens (Leipzig, 1928).
1935 Downes, Olin, Symphonic Masterpieces (New York, 1935).
Tovey, D. F., Essays in Musical Analysis II (London: Oxford University,
1935).
1936 Riezler, Walter, Beethoven (Berlin: Atlantis, 1936).
1941 Rolland, Romain, Beethoven: Les Grandes Époques Créatrices, vol. 4 (La
Cathedrale Interrompue), 1 (La Neuvieme Symphonie) (Paris: Sahler,
1943).
1958 Sauer, Wilhelm, Beethoven und das Wesen in der Musik (Berlin: Hesse,
1958).
1980 Treitler, Leo, “History, Criticism, and Beethoven’s Ninth Symphony,”
in Music and the Historical Imagination (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 1989).
1981 Hopkins, Antony, The Nine Symphonies of Beethoven (London: Scolar
Press, 1981).
1982 Treitler, Leo, “ ‘To Worship that Celestial Sound’: Motives for
Analysis,” Journal of Musicology 1 (1982): 524–58.
1987 McClary, Susan, “Getting Down Off the Beanstalk,” Minnesota
Composer’s Forum Newsletter (February 1987).
1989 Taruskin, Richard, “Resisting the Ninth,” 19th-Century Music 12/3
(spring 1989): 241–56.
1991–95 Van den Toorn, Pieter. “Politics, Feminism, and Contemporary Music
Theory,” Journal of Musicology 9/3 (summer 1991): 1–37. Revised and
reprinted in van den Toorn, Music, Politics, and the Academy (Berkeley
and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1995).
1991 McClary, Susan, “Getting Down Off the Beanstalk,” in Feminine
Endings: Music, Gender, and Sexuality (Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press, 1991).
notes
This essay is—obviously—inspired by and dedicated to Susan McClary. In the nearly
ten years it has been in gestation, it has benefited immensely from the direct input
and the indirect example of Joseph Kerman, Richard Taruskin, Mitchell Morris,
Judith Peraino, Gretchen Wheelock, Ralph Locke, Rose Subotnik, David Levy, Fred
Maus, Suzanne Cusick, Marion Guck, Cecilia Sun, Elisabeth Le Guin, Raymond
Knapp, Robert Walser, and Andrew Dell’Antonio.
1. “Artyfacts,” Guardian, 1 December 1995, p. T9. The anonymous sarcasm of the
Guardian reviewer is all the more depressing in that it repackages seminal misinfor-
mation from that most “respectable” of sources, Edward Rothstein of the New York
Times. It was Rothstein who, a few days before, in discussing (among other “new musi-
cological” publications) Feminine Endings, had allowed himself to reuse as if it came
beethoven antihero 149
from the book the infamous quote he had attacked several times before (“Musicologists
Roll Over Beethoven,” New York Times, 26 November 1995). The most charitable
explanation is that he had not yet actually read McClary’s work, a full four years after
its publication.
2. The talk in question, “The Feminist Critical Perspective on Musicology,” was
later published by Leo Treitler as “Gender and Other Dualities of Music History”
(Treitler 1993). To give Treitler credit, he seemed genuinely troubled by the effect
his decontextualized use of McClary’s words had on audiences in 1988, and made
significant and salutary changes in the way he framed her in his 1993 argument.
3. Suzanne Cusick might see this “effortless” moment of trans-gender intersub-
jectivity as rather less than innocent: “It is easy to understand why McClary’s work
would have seemed, at first, comprehensible to traditional musicologists in a way that
more explicitly women-centered musicology had not. . . . Because such an enterprise
can be immediately understood to rescue both women and men from disciplinary
practices that rigidly channel our relationships to sensual and bodily pleasures,
McClary’s feminist scholarship promises a kind of liberation for all of us. Thus it
promises a space for feminist men with a clarity that some other feminist musicolo-
gies do not have” (Cusick 1999, 487). As a once-traditional male musicologist radi-
calized by McClary’s writing, I would not deny that Cusick (whose work is no less
admirable than McClary’s) has my number. My only disclaimer is that I am just as
conscious of the equivocal position of “men in (musicological) feminism” as I intuit
her to be. I have tried to make some of my post-McClaryite gender allegiances clear
in the opening and closing pages of Fink 1998.
4. The critical reception of this recapitulation is treated at greater length, with
extensive selections from primary sources, in Fink 1994, 132–60. For a compendious
collection of early critical references to the Ninth, see Solie 1988. Contemporary ref-
erences to the Ninth in German musical periodicals are reproduced in Wallace 1986;
and a more general survey, covering some of the same ground as this study, is in the
Cambridge Handbook on the Ninth by Nicholas Cook (1993).
5. A short list of the accounts of the recapitulation passage (Beethoven, Ninth Sym-
phony, I, 301–99) on which the following discussion is based is provided in the appen-
dix at the end of this essay. The full text of these descriptions, in the original lan-
guages, can be found in Fink 1994, appendix A; all translations in the following
section are my own, except where otherwise noted.
6. Virtually all the emotion in Schenker’s study comes in the appendices to each
analytic section, where he brutally chastises the “Schwärmerei” of earlier critics. He
carries both Hugo Riemann and Hermann Kretschmar along with him to be ritually
beaten up at the end of each analytical section. Riemann he often dignifies by dis-
puting the earlier critic’s harmonic readings; he quotes Kretschmar’s descriptions
merely to ridicule what seemed to him a total lack of content.
7. By contrast, Schenker only mentions the timpani as an afterthought—because
their rhythm intermittently reinforces that of the theme (“In kompositorischer Hin-
sicht beachte man endlich noch den Rhythmus der Pauken in den Takten 304, 308,
310, die thematisch mitwirken”).
8. “Jetzt ist die Herrschermacht des Gedankens entschieden; er . . . steht . . .
zwölf Takte lang, unbeweglich wie ein Schreckensphantom, wie der trübflammendes
Erdgeist vor Faust stand, der ihn heraufbeschworen und nicht ertragen konnte, auf
150 robert fink
group in the recapitulation. One might quite reasonably doubt the experiential valid-
ity of this long-range connection. For I am not only claiming that the Is–° V/V–V–i
progression of mm. 531–39 is a provisional correction of the gnomic Is6–G6–(V)–i6
of mm. 312–15. I also need to assert that the actual melodic line Fs–Gs–A in those
later measures is heard as a straightened-out and successful version of the failed
Fs–Gs–A ascent in mm. 301–15—even though the earlier ascent’s very existence
depends on our perception of a highly abstract melodic link between Fs in the bass
and Af–An in the soprano.
But the skeptic need not rely on the evidence of my ears alone. We can call
another witness, disinterested, and perhaps even hostile: the Stufentheorist Heinrich
Schenker, as he is on record in his 1912 monograph. As example 4.6 attempts to
show, his harmonic analysis of these two passages implies this linear connection,
which he evidently at that time had no theoretical interest in pursuing.
Here is Schenker’s harmonic explanation of mm. 301–15:
[The tonic’s] major third Fs does not arise, as it might at first glance seem, from mode
mixture, but from a chromaticization leading to the soon to appear scale-step IV:
D minor: Is–IV
In effect: G minor: Vs–I
This last (IV) then actually appears in m. 312, although it is itself—as before—immedi-
ately chromaticized, as if scale-step V were actually what we were waiting for:
D minor: sIV–(V)
28. The original version of this sentence (Fink 1994, 206) lacked quotation
marks around the word “success.” At that time I was much more heavily invested in
Beethoven’s ability to create a viscerally exciting—and thus “successful”— form
based around dramatic moments of harmonic-linear failure (as I freely admitted; see
1994, 213–16). The goals of that earlier study were somewhat different than the pres-
ent one (I was more interested in Beethoven the Master of musical “Energy”); but the
intervening years have also brought a greater degree of critical distance from the
piece itself—and a more mature sense of what is culturally interesting about form in
a postmodern musical episteme.
five
This discussion is intentionally split in two: the first part is an essay about the
subjective hearing of a particular body of music; the second is about the subjectivity of
writing that essay, refracted through the personal and social contexts that led to its cre-
ation. I’m not sure anyone can fairly examine the first without examining the second:
the subjectivity of listening always ought to remind us of the unavoidable subjectivity
of musicology itself.
composers such as Barraqué, Boulez and Maxwell Davies, looking for the way
in which impatience with the world as it is and a horror of the predictable
result in shattered sounds that force the listener to imagine a world beyond
the known. Such a world may be a common modernist trope: one that may
be suggested in sound, but which can only be inhabited by terrifying angels.
This, the beginning of Rilke’s Duino Elegies, is a poem that causes the earth
to crack open. Historically, this first stanza of a set of extraordinary poetic
experiments is the point where Rilke leaves behind the merely beautiful pic-
tures of his Symbolist work to create an image that is both a summary of
many aspects of nineteenth-century poetry and at the same time convinc-
ingly modern. It is thus tied, both chronologically and conceptually, to the
first of his Sonnets to Orpheus, with its then shocking venture into proto-Sur-
realism. The historical move is, however, only a part of the important shift
represented in the poem; Rilke, powerfully taking over a space of being that
is only obliquely suggested in his earlier poems, creates a vision of possible
existence that demands the demolition of everyday experience. The com-
plex, allusive world established in this new approach to the sublime thus
becomes an existential earthquake. The poetic earthquake is teased out into
verbal explanation, as it must be; but in music we have a more succinct, more
exact expression of such an earthquake: the explosive, apparently instanta-
neous accented chord that opens Boulez’s Pli selon pli.
This earthquake is characteristic of both of the times when modernism
shattered the existing landscape, first in the years before World War I and
then again after World War II. Rilke’s difficult language, hinting at realities
that are not quite accessible in words but which nevertheless insist on being
understood, opens up a future that will include both Pound and Wittgen-
stein, while the passionate demand for a new way of being invokes the sub-
sequent Heidegger. Although we are accustomed to separating out the time
spans of the figures and works involved, I need to breach period divisions in
order to tease out a shared vision that, I suggest, spans most of the century:
a vision of destroying the world to transcend it, of discovering a ‘passionate
ineffable’ beyond any normal experience. In that context, Rilke’s metaphors
156 paul attinello
may seem historically distant from the work of Boulez, and not a part of the
same cultural movement that produced the brittle explosion at the begin-
ning of Pli selon pli; but I assert that, at an imaginative level, they represent
the same relationship to reality. It should be clear that I am not terribly inter-
ested in tracing a chain of influences—either particular words or particular
images—that result in a series of directly comparable artistic products. I am
certainly not tracing images of angels that appear in the poetry of early mod-
ernism or the music of high modernism. I instead hope to define an impor-
tant constellation of desires, those passionate wishes to crack open the sky
and pass through to whatever may be on the other side.
The cluster of works that most clearly express such desires include some
of the classic works of musical high modernism. I suggest that it would be
useful for readers to go and hear the pieces I cite—even those they know
well—in order to remind them of the sensual impact of their experience as
sound, rather than as score, abstract memory, or theoretical construct. In
choosing these works I am aiming at characterizing, not the composition
degree zero aspect of works like Boulez’s Structures Ia, but the development
of a style of passionate violence that occurs on both sides of that zero point.
Accustomed as we are to the homily that the music of the 1950s was intended
to project an absence of meaning, I believe that we have ignored the evident
expressive results that are composed into such works, especially when they
are considered collectively. Indeed, so much avant-garde music of the 1950s
and 1960s, which was said to be designed to leave behind the past (whether
the past of music, the past of Europe, or the past of bourgeois stability), is
more a constantly refashioned attempt to blow up that past. It is easy to speak
of the fearsome or transcendent implications of specific staged or texted
works by Berio, Barraqué, Nilsson, and many others; but it also seems impor-
tant to acknowledge that many untexted musical works of high modernism
share a remarkably specific common sensibility. Although the invocation of
Rilke and Benjamin may seem historically inappropriate when speaking of
Boulez or Maxwell Davies, I believe I am justified in using their language; not
because they could be seen as specific influences on these composers, but
simply because they said it best.
To paraphrase the Rilke quoted above: if I suffer and cry out, it is hard to
believe that any infinite beings, caught up as they are in the structures of a
radically different reality, would even notice me. What is worse, if one of
them did notice, any intended help from such a being, symbolized in an
embrace, would destroy rather than save me. This sensually personal image
is used by Rilke to insist that what we call beauty—what, in fact, most of his
earlier poems celebrate—is really the edge of the sublime, and that the sub-
lime is the destructive but full-fledged form of beauty. So these terms, usu-
passion / mirrors 157
Not only are we helpless against existence, but we are embarrassed even in
facing the animals, who are, however humbly, part of a real, immanent kind
of existence. Language, as well as the habit of speaking, art and representa-
tions of beauty, are merely attempts to stave off existence. This is also, of
course, a demand that we aim for the zero point of existence; although Rilke
does not try to express this by reaching a zero point of poetry (which could
be said to have been reached in Surrealist and Dadaist texts before the war,
and long before it was approached in music), he insists that endeavors out-
side that zero point are always essentially inadequate. Of course, one of the
advantages of musical expression is its ability to bypass the verbal, which
helps to distance us somewhat from our usual interpretations: although we
may still be lost in our minds rather than aware in the world, musical expres-
sion can sometimes point, with somewhat more virtual “reality” than poetry,
towards “real” experience.
Certain phrases in the next few stanzas present real understanding as just
as unavoidable as it is impossible: “there is night, when a wind full of infinite
space / gnaws at our faces,” or the lines on being unable to preserve the
image of the beloved because of “all the huge strange thoughts inside you /
going and coming and often staying all night” (Rilke 1984, 151). The second
elegy again flings terror into our faces, as it begins with the conclusion of the
first stanza of the first elegy: “Every angel is terrifying.” The end of the first
stanza of the second elegy moves it all ruthlessly closer:
But if the archangel now, perilous, from behind the stars
took even one step down toward us: our own heart, beating
higher and higher, would beat us to death. Who are you?
rilke 1984, 157
This is an earthquake again, or perhaps (it can be imagined) still the same
earthquake in an infinitely extended moment: but, this time, the earthquake
happens inside of us.
158 paul attinello
The immense crack in the world that begins Pli selon pli is repeated at the
end of the piece, suggesting not so much any ABA structure as that the entire
work happens in a single instant. Both the first and last such ‘cracks in the
sky’ are associated with brief, aphoristic lines from Mallarmé, sung by the
soprano solo. In both cases, its detachment from the original poem makes
the action of each line—in the first case the gift of a poem, in the last the bit-
ter, surreal chaos of death—almost incomprehensible, and more of a magi-
cal invocation than a meaningful statement of any kind. Once again, in his-
torical terms, the linking of Boulez in 1957, Rilke in 1912, and Mallarmé in
1865 may seem unworkable; but I continue to claim that, in poetic and imag-
inative terms, it makes a kind of sense that is more important—and which
explains more of our need for, and usage of, these pieces—than any histor-
ical sense.
This frequently cited paragraph is a sensual shock among the complex asser-
tions of Benjamin’s Theses on the Philosophy of History —which were written in
1940, in the midst of a storm that would make such feelings relatively famil-
iar, especially in European artistic expression.
The painting itself, which was painted in 1920, purchased by Benjamin in
1921, and which hung in his various studies until he fled Paris in June 1940,
does not really illustrate Benjamin’s complex image in a definite or allusive
way. Klee’s angel floats in space, staring in a way that may be unsettling, but
which does not suggest any detailed metaphor of catastrophe, storm, or
debris. It is important to register the rhetorical shift in Benjamin’s third sen-
tence away from the description of the painting to a separate train of thought
only inspired by it. On the other hand, art historian and Klee specialist Otto
Werckmeister points out that the “angel of history” can be seen as a devel-
oped form of a meditation written twenty-five years earlier by Klee himself:
Today is the passage from yesterday to the present. In the great mine of forms
lie ruins from which one still partly hangs. They offer material for abstraction.
passion / mirrors 159
This suggests that Klee and Benjamin may have communicated with each
other about these feelings and ideas. Werckmeister analyzes the same paint-
ing from a different point of view, pointing out the hand-like wings and
apparent suspension in midair; but unexpectedly, after this physical descrip-
tion, he reaches a surprising conclusion: “with the Angelus Novus, the effort
to fly succeeds. . . . It may be taken as an image of the artist’s exaltation, by
means of abstraction, into a spiritual counterworld” (Werckmeister 1989,
241–42). Certainly, some kind of “counterworld” is common to all of the
texts and interpretations resonating out from this painting. Benjamin also
referred to Klee’s painting in writing at an earlier date, but despite the much
calmer political circumstances of the time, he interpreted it as representing
something that was terrifying without being evil. In his lengthy 1931 essay on
Karl Kraus, Benjamin celebrates the destructive instinct as a valid, even a
Promethean, foil to the creative instinct. This destructive instinct is at its
most valuable when life has become habitual:
And therefore the monster stands among us as the messenger of a more real
humanism. . . . He feels solidarity not with the slender pine but with the plane
that devours it, not with the precious ore but with the blast furnace that puri-
fies it. . . . One must have followed Loos in his struggle with the dragon “orna-
ment” . . ., or seen Klee’s New Angel, who preferred to free men by taking from
them, rather than make them happy by giving to them, to understand a
humanity that proves itself by destruction. (Benjamin 1979, 289)
“progress,” makes the whole even more chilling, implying that we are always
already caught in this situation as our (modern) temporal reality. The frac-
tured, tangled mess of tradition and progress becomes an eschatological trap
that prevents the angel from either controlling or slowing his movement into
the future, or on the contrary returning to Paradise (where the past is per-
haps not merely wreckage). He is always already moving forward in time, as
are we.
The terrifying explosion that forces us forward in time, or at least a
response to the feelings created by such an image, suggest the eschatologi-
cal world of Barraqué with its resistance to movement and frozen, perpetual
reaction to awaited death and failure. While completing his famous piano
sonata in 1952, Barraqué wrote, angrily and satirically, of the trap he was
thereby creating for himself:
You see, in our time, what the “serial principle” actually means: a two-fold
abstraction, which both constructs and destroys. The creative act in its aesthetic
necessity remains incomprehensible, for one knows full well that it is not suf-
ficient to employ rows and place f and p signs in order to produce a valid work;
but in the moment when the spark ignites, one sets foot in a region which is
just as absurd as that where a rock turns into a man, where a man takes leave
of rationality against his will, and falls prey to irrationality and becomes insane.
As I wrote to Boulez, all of the present experiments are not very satisfying,
because all of these people are content when they have written a row and
placed a f or p and (the pinnacle of on the other hand) an accent or portato
on every note. Almost no one has RECOGNIZED the disturbing temperature
of our times, our historic truth. They don’t know that more than ever an under-
standing of the world in its totality is the only Possibility, and that outside of this
everything is not just incomplete, but totally Useless.2
The best example of Barraqué’s “historic truth” is the entire second move-
ment of the Sonata wherein, as Hodeir says,
Music cracks under the unhuman strain, disintegrates and is sucked into the
void. Whole slabs of sound crumble and vanish beneath the all-engulfing ocean
of silence, until only the twelve notes of the row remain, and even these are
plucked off, one by one (Hodeir 1961, 195).
A musical image of such tension can be found in the ending of the last move-
ment of Maxwell Davies’ First Symphony. Although the work is “permeated
by the presence of the sea and the landscape of this isolated place [Orkney]
off the north coast of Scotland,”3 the effect is not in any way pastoral, but is
instead eerie and vastly transcendent. The texture of the symphony is fast,
complex and—like that of the Barraqué Sonata—frequently on the edge of
perceivable coherence; if this is indeed a natural world, it is one that is
already too infinite and too dangerous for us to possess, or even fully to
grasp. In such a context, the extraordinary drive of the final passage, which
follows a long passage of slow but increasing movement, suggests to me an
attempt to reach beyond the world toward something far beyond physical
experience; the tangled line rising from the basses up through the orchestra
explodes through the ceiling of audible sound to progress to some other
inconceivable place, past the limits of time and mere understanding. Why
162 paul attinello
can always operate at different angles to each other, and the resultant super-
structure heads off in different, and sometimes unexpected, directions.
And, just as every live performance of the paper is somewhat different, so is
every reading of any “final” published version—all of the complex or unpre-
dictable experiences that constitute reality contribute to the discussion of a
particular body of music and my understanding of it.
Various such contributions led to the creation of part 1, which in part 2
becomes an object of study—the discussion is itself subject to discussion. My
youthful fascination with the dark sensuality of high modernist music, which
included such works as Le marteau sans maître and Blomdahl’s Aniara, a fas-
cination rediscovered after years of study, is the original foundation of the
article “A Passion for the Violent Ineffable.” Indeed, my desire to tease out
that particular quality led to my dissertation on some of the more chaotic
and bizarre works of the 1950s and 1960s. The original impulse should, ide-
ally, be the pure source of part 1; but the source is muddied, unpredictably
altered, not only over time but by peripheral circumstances such as the con-
ditions of writing—a dorm room in Surrey, another in Turku, my expecta-
tions of a British audience and a Scandinavian one, and the imagined or real
reactions of various listeners or readers, who may or may not have been, at
the time, thinking of something else entirely.
We are accustomed to discounting many of these circumstances but, in my
imagination, which is of course where the writing occurs, these aspects remain
acutely present. And we do work with our imaginations, there’s no doubt
about it: although I often explain the object of our subjectivities to my stu-
dents as “cultural products,” that is a disappointingly cold, and therefore inac-
curate, phrase. What we are working on is an art form, and one that impels
an inner world of feelings and dreams. I suggest that that is why we started
working with music in the first place, way back before we entered graduate
programs, got degrees, or dug ourselves into jobs. Indeed, as we are educated
into academe, in a discipline that has been heavily influenced by the sci-
ences—that is, by a discipline that still prefers to lean toward what is pejora-
tively called “positivism”—we learn to control our various imaginings. We
don’t entirely ignore them, of course, except in very few cases—one might
consider the graduate student forced to write a dissertation documenting
music in which he or she has no interest as an extreme example. We sublimate
our imaginative impulses and ideas, sneakily arranging topics and projects to
allow ourselves to talk about things that fire us up, all the while pretending to
be purely scholarly and coolly objective. More broadly, we become socialized
into subgroups that encourage agreement on certain permitted infractions of
the norm: thus the attachment to arcane mystery that one sees in many
medieval scholars, the passionate and slightly guilty liberalism expressed by
many ethnomusicologists, and—of course—the mathematical formalities
affected by scholars of my own period, the period of high modernism.
164 paul attinello
consistent. This is also affected by our view of the linearity of a given argu-
ment. In reading and listening, we repeatedly ask ourselves: what’s missing
in this paper, or in that paper? When has too much that is important been
excluded, or too many tangents been included? Chances are that we will
judge rigor more exactingly than any other parameter of value—such as
interest, involvement, contribution to the culture (or merely to the existing
literature). Sometimes this judgment is unfair, as when scientific parameters
are imposed on contexts where they are inappropriate (such as, frequently
enough, in music).
Rigor, and its implied correlate consistency, is of course not only a
method of controlling ideas and arguments. It is also a means of avoiding
boredom on the part of the reader or listener: after all, how many people
have disconnected or inconsistent ideas that are actually interesting? Not
many, that’s certain. But is this merely human nature, a common aspect of
the human condition, or is it our modernist education hampering us in our
work? Has our training made it impossible for us to think freely—has it
reduced us to two alternatives, the rigorous and the lazy (with a bow to
Deleuze and Guattari, as these can be reinterpreted as the paranoid and the
schizoid), with the latter always inadequate? Certainly, we allow composers
a certain leeway that isn’t allowed to scholars, the idea seeming to be that the
creative mind can’t be bothered with consistency. Why, then, should the
scholarly mind be so concerned about it? And, to bring the argument back
to part 1: what is our relationship to rigor, and what can it be, if we are reflect-
ing on an era where avant-garde scientism is the fashion, such as the 1950s?
Do we pretend not to notice the short haircuts and dark suits in all the group
photographs from Darmstadt?
gusted reactions to them by others, impacted upon many of the crucial aes-
thetic decisions and schisms of the 1950s and 1960s.7
This conflates several uncomfortable problems in subjectivity: how much
am I allowed to talk about this? It’s a dangerous topic, after all, and some of
the wealthier composers have lawyers. And can I manage to remain cool and
unattached, and manage to seem cool and unattached, in relation to this sub-
ject matter? Can I avoid the impulse to play “IMRU”—the game of claiming
about almost any famous figure, “Oh, you know he’s gay”? Is everything
infected by possible motives and agendas, such that any statement on a topic
that matters to the speaker is always suspect?
Many schizophrenic patients “delightedly believe that they have grasped the
profoundest of meanings; concepts such as timelessness, world, god and death
become enormous revelations which when the state has subsided cannot be
reproduced or described in any way—they were after all nothing but feelings.”
It is understandable that such concerns might often reduce a person either to
silence or to oblique and vague attempts at description. . . . At least some of the
statements that strike observers as woolly or empty philosophizing . . . may
thus be attempts—sometimes inept but sometimes not—to express concerns
that are just too all-encompassing or too abstract to be stated in clear and spe-
cific terms, even by the most clear-minded of speakers. (Sass 1992, 191)
passion / mirrors 171
notes
Versions of part 1 were read in July 1999 at the Third Triennial British Musicological
Societies 1999 Conference in Surrey; in October 1999 at the Skagerak Network sem-
inar Självreflexivitet i musikforskningen (Self-reflexivity and Musicology) in Turku,
Finland; and in April 2000 at the annual national conferences of the Musicological
Society of Australia and New Zealand Musicological Society in Sydney. A version of
part 2 was given as a continuation of part 1 at the Skagerak Network seminar; I am
grateful for their invitation to write it.
1. Quoted in Werckmeister 1981, 98; my translation. “Heute ist der gestrige-
heutige Übergang. In der großen Formgrube liegen Trümmer, an denen man noch
teilweise hängt. Sie liefern den Stoff zur Abstraktion. Ein Bruchfeld von unechten
Elementen, zur Bildung unreiner Kristalle. So ist es heute. . . . Ich habe diesen Krieg
in mir längst gehabt. Daher geht er mich innerlich nichts an. Um mich aus meinen
Trümmern herauszuarbeiten, mußte ich fliegen. Und ich flog. In jener zertrüm-
merten Welt weile ich nur noch in der Erinnerung, wie man zuweilen zurückdenkt.
Somit bin ich ‘abstrakt mit Erinnerungen.’ ”
2. Quoted by Heribert Henrich, translated by Mark Bruce, in booklet for Boulez:
Troisième Sonate / Douze Notations / Barraqué: Sonate pour Piano / Pi-Hsien Chen (Telos
Records TLS 006), 7.
3. [N.a.], booklet, Maxwell Davies: Symphony no. 1 (Collins 14352), 1995.
4. Karl Birger Blomdahl and Erik Lindegren, I speglarnas sal/In the Hall of Mirrors
(Caprice [LP]), 1972.
5. Music from 2001: A Space Odyssey/Suite from Aniara (Columbia MS 7176), 1968.
This album was apparently taken off the market as a result of Ligeti’s lawsuit against
Columbia for using his music without permission; a Deutsche Grammophon record-
ing, for which Ligeti did receive royalties, replaced it on the American market. The
DGG recording had no Blomdahl on it.
6. Nirvana, “Smells Like Teen Spirit,” Nevermind (DGC), 1991.
7. These ideas are greatly expanded in an essay I have co-written with David
Osmond-Smith, “Gay Darmstadt: Flamboyance and Rigor at the Summer Courses for
New Music,” which will appear in the Proceedings of the Second Biennial International
Conference on 20th-Century Music, ed. Keith Potter, Arnold Whittall, and Christopher
Mark, published by Ashgate in 2004.
six
Uncertainty, Disorientation,
and Loss as Responses to
Musical Structure
joseph dubiel
What I like best about the problematic notion of musical “structure” is the
attention it can direct to the constructedness of musical identities. By the
identity of a musical thing, I mean principally how it sounds; by saying that
such an identity is constructed, I mean that how a musical thing sounds is
engendered by relationships in which we understand that thing to partici-
pate. And by relationship I mean any kind of juxtaposition, contrast, or affin-
ity—that is, my idea of musical relationship is not constrained by connota-
tions of orderly or logical progression. An unprepared departure from what
a passage has been doing is every bit as relational as the fulfillment of an
implication; so, for that matter, is an event that resists characterization in the
terms that have previously been in play, and invites reconceptualization of
everything heard so far.
With a notion of “structure” as inclusive as this, it is not clear that any par-
ticular kind of listening experience can usefully be picked out as the hearing
of “structure.” Anything we hear might be—must be—significantly the result
of “structure” in the inclusive sense. If such a thing as “structural” listening
is to be reified at all, then perhaps it is not to be defined by any characteris-
tic of the listening; perhaps it could better be identified as a certain way of
thinking about listening. It might be a kind of listening that involves wanting
to make the way in which one’s experience is elicited an object of apprecia-
tion in itself. The distinctive feature of such listening might be a certain kind
of self-monitoring, motivated by a certain kind of wonder—wonder that
sounds can do that. As a composer, I always have a specific interest in notic-
ing how it’s done, alongside noticing it done; but even when I’m off duty I
like having room in my listening mindset to marvel at the fact that such mul-
tifarious experience can be elicited by arrangements of noises. To prevent
misunderstanding, I should specify that I do not want to set up a dichotomy
173
174 joseph dubiel
tions that I set up to support them. That is, the experiential reports do not
necessarily have the qualities, or the dynamics, or concern themselves with
the same entities, as the technical reports that I develop alongside them. So
even if you’re already with me in being over the idea of “structure” as order,
there is something this essay can offer you, namely a particular look at the
possible discrepancy between an attribution of “structure” and the experi-
ence, presumably of this “structure,” that the attribution is meant to account
for. In a way, what this essay offers you is a problem: Why build into your the-
oretical account of a passage a distinct character that is different from that
of the experience you want to capture? Why tolerate such a difference, or
why bother? How should we expect a theoretical model to resemble the
experience it is set up to account for?
I am not going to try to answer those questions, especially not in any prin-
cipled or general way. I state them here in an effort to define the contexts in
which my examples might matter. Probably the most I can offer in the way
of generality will not be any general proposition at all, but a demonstration
of the workability of a few attitudes. One is an attitude of unprincipled prag-
matism about the relationship between analytical constructions and the
experiences to which they respond: unprincipled in that I am willing to
accept almost any kind of incongruity between the terms of an analysis and
the experiences that go with it; pragmatic in the sense that I am tolerant of
almost any kind of suggestiveness or resonance, but completely inflexible in
the expectation that there be some articulable relationship between analy-
sis and hearing. Even though my overt point is going to be that we cannot
insist on any particular parallelism between a theoretical formulation and its
experiential correlate, the last thing I want to do is offer comfort to the kind
of analysis that just identifies a pattern (any pattern) and then helps itself to
the assurance that this pattern (because it is such a lovely pattern) must be
working on us somehow—“unconsciously,” as people often say. If the pattern
matters to the music, then there must be some way we hear the mattering, and
what we hear, we’re conscious of! (We might at the same time not be con-
scious of how the configuration of sounds is provoking this experience; we
may well not be conscious of some concepts that would help us to report and
explain this. But those are different issues.)1
This is why I am not completely at ease with the (in many ways useful)
image of unperceived “structure” being responsible for perceived “effect.” I
would rather think of music being perceptible in a variety of different ways,
and of the coordination of different kinds of observation as being a useful
topic of inquiry—and of the effort to coordinate different kinds of observa-
tion as itself a useful mode of inquiry. My procedure, in most of the musical
analyses that follow, will be to begin with some “structural” fact that I know
by some means other than hearing, which I am for some reason unsure how
to hear (to put it less crudely, whose relation to experience, actual or pos-
176 joseph dubiel
sible, I do not yet know), and to try to find out what it might mean to hear it.
In all of these cases, I find myself developing an account that does not much
resemble my initial account of the fact; part of what I would claim to have
learned in each case is what might count as hearing this fact, that I would not
have expected.
With not very many presuppositions about what kinds of musical experi-
ences to discuss, and especially not the presupposition that these experi-
ences are going to resemble theoretical discourses, the main thing that I am
ever going to be able to say in favor of an analysis is that it can stimulate a
great deal of specific observation—or, to put it another way, it allows a lot of
the particulars of a musical passage to matter, and even creates kinds of par-
ticulars and kinds of relevance for them. It follows that I’m going to be pre-
senting a lot of analytical detail. What I hope to demonstrate is not an all-on-
top-of-it mastery, so much as the potential for responsiveness along
unforeseen lines.
It was a quite unforeseen lapse in mastery that got me thinking along the
lines of this essay. In a work that I thought I knew well—the Tristan prelude—
I one day came across a structural fact that I didn’t think I’d ever been hear-
ing and that, at the same time, I couldn’t imagine not hearing, so that I had
to do some work to figure out what would count as hearing it.
What I realized is that the big tune that enters at the deceptive cadence,
after the introductory fragments, doesn’t maintain a consistent relationship
to its bass line when it recurs. (See ex. 6.1.) The first time (m. 17), the tune’s
upbeat comes in over F in the bass, and on the downbeat the bass starts an
ascent, Fs–G–A. The next time (m. 32), the bass gets underway first, with F
already rising to Fs at the first upbeat. The tune even changes to adapt to this
difference: its big downward swoop, occurring over G in the bass instead of
Fs, is C–E instead of C–D. Eventually the difference between these two set-
tings fades: the bass of the second version includes a chromatic passing tone
that the first one doesn’t, Gs between G and A, and so the bass line’s high
point A coincides with the same point in the tune both times, and its subse-
quent descent to Cs fits the tune the same way. (The descending step from
A to G is also filled chromatically the second time, but in such a way that the
overall alignment of bass and tune is unchanged.)
The difference fades: but still—what a thing not to have noticed! I don’t
know many tonal melodies that can be displaced by half a measure against
their bass lines without at least some effect of powerful transformation being
wrought upon them. (Or maybe I do, and just don’t realize it.) And it isn’t
only that I hadn’t noticed; it is also that, once I was aware of this, I still had a
hard time noticing, even with the evidence right before my eyes, and under
my fingers. To this day, I have a hard time noticing, in a sense: the theme
uncertainty, disorientation, and loss 177
Example 6.1 Wagner, Tristan und Isolde, Act I, Einleitung: two occurrences of the
theme, with the melody in different relations to the bass.
17
g g
! 68 S T g
C O C C C C C O C C C Y C C C O C C C O C Y C C OX C C W C 68
C CO C C C
ff p C f dim. p
# 6 g g
8 CO CO WCO CO CO C C CO CO 68
C C WCO CO
32 g C YC C CO C C
g C CO C C C C CO C C
! 68 S T C CO C C
C C CO C C C C CO C
C
C C YC C CO C C C
C CO C C
C h
p cresc. f dim. p
# 6 g g g
8 CO WCO CO WCO C YC C XC C C WCO CO
doesn’t sound that different to me, one way and the other, certainly not as
different as I think I should expect. (Try it—even if you know the passages
well, and are in the habit of glossing over the examples when you read about
music. Play the melody with one bass line, then with the other.)
Or perhaps—the point I have been preparing—I am not listening for the
relevant sort of difference. Perhaps I do hear some difference, have been all
along, only it is not the kind of difference I have thought to listen for, or
thought to connect to the contrapuntal rearrangement of the theme. In any
event, here is something to investigate. I have a contrast that I can reason-
ably call structural, even in a very conventional sense: it’s a matter of how the
notes are arranged. In this instance, I recognize its structural status in the
very uneasiness I feel about not clearly noticing it. A lot of facts that might
be veraciously pointed out in a score, I wouldn’t be at all surprised to find
inaudible; and in the right context I would be prepared to question whether
such facts should be considered music-structural at all. But this one can’t not
be significant, somehow. So there it is, and I need to do some work to say
what it means for my hearing. Even for something as macroscopic—as bla-
tant—as a melody and its bass going out of phase for a while, it is not obvi-
ous what sort of experience ought to count as “hearing it.”
Now I can be more specific about what I am not hearing that I might have
expected to: in the second (and later) occurrences of the theme, I am not
getting any very strong sense of departure from a norm or prototype pre-
sented by the first occurrence. I suppose that the first version must be, in
178 joseph dubiel
some sense, the normal one, if any one is. It is the version that recurs later
in the opera—for instance, when Isolde narrates her first meeting with Tris-
tan, and when the two of them have their drink together later in the first
act—and it and Tristan eventually expire simultaneously in the third act. It
probably is the way I vaguely and inaccurately thought all the thematic state-
ments went, when I thought they all went the same way.
Statistics aren’t exactly to the point, but as a matter of fact this first con-
trapuntal arrangement is the exception in the prelude. The second arrange-
ment is the one reproduced at the next occurrence of the theme (m. 55),
and at another occurrence shortly after that (m. 58). (The first recurrence
is transposed up a major third and moved to the opposite metrical position,
but the relation between melody and bass is the same.) That these statements
match the second one may not be so remarkable, since their textural sur-
roundings are essentially the same as those of the second statement. More
interesting is what happens at the next occurrence of the theme, when a
return to the first version seems explicitly called for by another approach to
the deceptive cadence (m. 74), proceeding from a reconstitution of the pre-
lude’s opening. (See ex. 6.2.) Here the original counterpoint does recur, but
also does not. It does, in that the melody does begin over Fn in the bass, and
the bass has (and needs) no passing Gs between G and A. It does not, in that
the melody is out of its normal metrical position, and the interval of its first
big descent is again altered (this time to C–Ds)—this even though the leap
still occurs over Fs. The metric repositioning is easy to notice, because the
melodic entrance overlaps, instead of waits for, the resolution of the appog-
giatura in the deceptive cadence. Because the entrance is thus vividly “too
early,” the restoration of the original contrapuntal alignment sounds not
quite like a restoration—sounds more like a new realignment on top of the
old realignment. And these accumulated changes make this fifth statement
seem, of all the statements, the most obvious departure from some inferred
norm, despite the return of the original counterpoint.
Without overestimating the relevance of such a survey to the hearing of
events locally, I can acknowledge the difficulty of identifying any “normal”
version of the theme. Accordingly, it might be best to characterize the “orig-
inal” version of the theme as (simply) the particular version that follows the
deceptive cadence (not only in the prelude, but in its later occurrences as
well).2 It might be thought of as the version adjusted to the deceptive cadence,
and the second version, similarly, as the one adjusted to the contrasting cir-
cumstances of its entry, and the idea of norm and departure might be dis-
pensed with. Taking this point completely to heart, the way to respond to the
difference between the versions might after all be not to hear the theme as
different on these various occasions, but to hear (as if) the same theme,
embedded in various contexts, and to assimilate the differences, insofar as
they are noticeable, to this embedding. It may even be a good interpretive
uncertainty, disorientation, and loss 179
Example 6.2 Wagner, Tristan und Isolde, Act I, Einleitung: another occurrence of
the theme, with another relation between melody and bass.
g
C C Y C YY CC C
74
! 68 C CO C C g C CO C C C C CO C
C C WC C CO C C C C CO C C
C CO YC
WC g g
# 6 CO WCO CO CO C C C C
8 CO WCO CO CO C C C
C C C
less “linear,” more “harmonic” (as well as generally descending, and some-
what slower). Accordingly the bass of the second thematic statement, though
no longer the first stirring of bass motion, still does represent revival after a
kind of lull. Compared to this, the entrance of the melody is a less decisive
event, for which the bass does not wait: the bass moves from F to Fs at once
in the first measure, and the melody comes along after. Soon enough, the
extra chromatic passing tone will allow the original alignment to be restored,
and the theme will run its course.
Actually the story is subtler than this. The theme’s bass does not simply ini-
tiate rising motion; rather it makes more vivid, by accelerating it, a rising
motion that, at least in retrospect, takes in the preceding E (m. 31)—the E–F
succession even vaguely recalling the environment in which the theme first
arose, after the E–F of the deceptive cadence. For that matter, this ascent
reaches back still further, to Ds (m. 29). (See ex. 6.3.) While the ascent from
Ds to E does not seem to be driving the music in which it occurs (for a vari-
ety of reasons, notably a certain obscurity in the harmonic rhythm and pro-
gression), this ascending step is nonetheless available for eventual assimila-
tion into an ascent gradually accumulating toward the rising bass of the
theme. There are two measures from Ds to E, one from E to F; and one-half
measure per step thereafter. Unless the bass moved from F to Fs within the
measure, no acceleration would occur; and so it moves.
The interpretive strategy that has now emerged is to portray the bass, in
each of the theme’s occurrences, as moving when and how it does for reasons
of its own—essentially reasons of textural pacing, independent of the
theme—and then to hear the melody fitted in to each of these contexts as
smoothly and neatly as it can be. This might be how it makes sense for me
not to be struck by the change of contrapuntal alignment as a phenomenon
in itself.
From one point of view, there is nothing especially original in this. I’ve
worked myself around to a conclusion that I might have started with, that
smoothly worked transitions—concealment of the seams—might be an
important aspect of Wagner’s technique. Why have I had to work myself
around to it? It is not normal for an analysis to take the elusiveness of a per-
ception as a topic, and to try to order some observations around, and in sup-
port of, the difficulty of making a particular expected observation. The
admission of difficulty—in both senses of admission: owning up to it, and let-
ting it into the discussion—is an unusual analytical maneuver, if not indeed
the opposite of the work analysis tries to do. I end up having elaborated a
sense in which not hearing the difference between the two contrapuntal
arrangements might be counted as gaining access to the prelude’s struc-
ture—as much as anything might.
That said, I think it is possible to give a more characterful account of how
the difference between versions can be noticed (while not being noticed).
uncertainty, disorientation, and loss 181
Example 6.3 Wagner, Tristan und Isolde, Act I, Einleitung: the slow bass ascent
preceding the second occurrence of the theme.
28 g g
g g g
! 68 W C C C C C C OO C C W C W C W C C C C C W C OO C C W C X C W C C C C O C
WC C C C C C C CWCWC WC C C C CWC C CWCXC WC C C COC
p cresc. f p cresc. f p etc.
# 6 O CO CO WCO
8 C WBO BO CO WCO
p sf p sf p
Example 6.4 Wagner, Tristan und Isolde, Act I, Einleitung: the counterpoint from
which a six-four chord emerges over G.
32 S T
CO C C g C CO C
! 68 W C C CC
CC B O C CO C
h C C OC Y C C C
C
g h etc.
g g
C WC C C C WC XC C
# 6 WW CC C WC C CO C WC XC C
8 CO WCO C WCO
6
4
Example 6.5 Wagner, Tristan und Isolde, Act I, Einleitung: voice-leading interpre-
tations of the first occurrence’s bass, on different temporal scales.
a.
#
C WC C
Ì
pt
uncertainty, disorientation, and loss 183
b.
#
C WC C C C
and even
c.
#
C WC C C C XC C
5 4 6
3 2 3
So the six-four here lacks the news value of the one in the second ver-
sion—a difference completely compatible with what I have already proposed
about the character of the theme’s first entrance. The news value of the first
entrance is concentrated right at the beginning.
The first time, the theme is presented to us on a silver platter; the second
time it sneaks up on us, but is then no less decisive in its effect (in fact, it is
perhaps even more so, at least tonally). Put another way: the first time seems
like the well-prepared entry of an agent, the second more a glimpse or rec-
ollection of it, now in the coils of something powerful but impersonal. And
I don’t see anything “unstructural” about these attributions: I can’t imagine
what the Tristan prelude is built to do, if not something like this. So I have
come around to a sense of “the same thing, somehow striking me differently”
that I can believe is (in part) the perceptible effect of the contrapuntal
realignment and that is compatible with, and even to some degree may
depend on, my not noticing the realignment as a feat of “convertible coun-
terpoint.”
And that is how I wasn’t being just dumb, or inattentive, all those years
when I didn’t catch on to this. Perhaps I was responding wonderfully to it all
along. Truth be told, I can’t say: I never really tried to articulate this until I
was provoked by my confusion over the counterpoint. I am convinced that
the beginning of wisdom here, in this case, was my learning to live with, and
then learning to celebrate, a state of affairs that might seem to epitomize the-
oretical failure. I refer not only to my initial sense that a difference clear in
the score was difficult to recover, but also to a residual sense that the con-
trast of character I have ended up with still may not as definite as the place-
ment of F or Fs in the bass under the theme’s upbeat. This doesn’t bother me
any more.
One reason is that the definiteness of any report of hearing such as I have
just given is bound to be spurious, beyond a certain point. Obviously I can-
not just now have been reporting any single real occasion of my hearing.
184 joseph dubiel
My next example takes a further step along this line. If, in the Tristan pre-
lude, it ends up being debatable whether noticing various differences in
character between instances of the theme should count as hearing changes
in the counterpoint or not, Morton Feldman’s Triadic Memories presents a
case where I’m happy to concede that I don’t hear the thing that Feldman
has notated, at least in the terms in which he (appears to have) notated it.
At the beginning of the piece, the rhythmic notation is quite remarkable:
a division of each 3/8 measure into four parts, against which are set synco-
pated figures that entail further subdivision of those four parts. (See ex. 6.6.)
What is not notated, that is, is the simple 8/16 measure that would suffice to
specify the durations, or even, assuming that an underlying triple meter mat-
ters somehow, the subdivision of the 3/8 measure into, in effect, a 24/64
measure, that would allow those rhythms to be written directly in relation to
the beat. In fact, the ostensible triple meter is not expressed in any way for
more than twenty pages of score, lasting many minutes.
Is triple meter a “structural” feature of the passage, then? Is four against
three? Syncopation against four against three? Should we admit as “struc-
tural” a feature that we do not hear and do not know how to hear, just
because it is notated? Do we have any use for a concept of structure like that?
(There is, I suppose, a tradition of retreating from perceptual questions in
situations like this and aligning “analysis” with some kind of reconstruction
of the composer’s decisions; but, aside from the general evasiveness of this
strategy, it is specifically useless in this case: precisely the perceptual obscu-
rity of the notation makes it hard to understand as a compositional choice.)
On the other hand: is there no way to hear the notated rhythm? That is, is
there nothing to hear that is plausibly a consequence of the peculiar nota-
tion? Suppose that the result of the passage being written the way it is, is—
though not any sense of these rhythms laid against a triple pulse—a sense of
uncertainty, disorientation, and loss 185
!
3 ppp H H H H H H
#8 TO TO T TU TU T TU TU
WCO C C C OW C O CO C OW C O CO
1⁄
WCO WCO WCO
2
d Ì
!
H H H H H H
# TO TO T TU TU T TU TU
WCO C C CO CO
WCO C OW C O WCO
WCO CO
WCO
tural” with what was done by the composer (perhaps even done “intention-
ally,” if we have an idea of what that means), we may think of it as something
that we can intelligibly imagine someone doing for the sake of the effect it
(perhaps) produces. Our analysis may say, in effect: it is as though the piece
were contrived to do such-and-such; we may conceive of it as so contrived,
whether this is a biographical fact about the composer or not.
And—more important—what the “such-and-such” is may take some imag-
ination to figure out. As a corollary, “do you hear that?”, asked with reference
to a structural feature, may be a bad question, at least without sufficient
attention given to the necessarily prior question “what would it be to hear
that?” And the answer to this question cannot be counted on to sound like a
report of the seizing of some information. Who knows what kind of sensation
it might be? Actually, a good reason to carry on music-analytic investigations
is that they may help us to recognize sensations that we didn’t realize we were
having. The effort to figure out what the effect could possibly be of some fea-
ture of the sonic configuration may lead to a raising of consciousness.
Think of this untypical example as chosen to illustrate these two points in
a relatively uncomplicated context. What it is to hear something may take
some imagination to figure out (enough to disconcert a yes-or-no approach
to the question of whether you hear something). Hearing something—
responding to it intensely and relevantly—may not involve mastering it,
being (or becoming) able to give it back in the terms in which it was set up;
may involve specific sorts of confusion or loss of information.
From the first of these points it may follow that a music-structural propo-
sition may not have (have to have) a one-to-one audible correlate to be audi-
bly relevant. (This is a lax position; behind it is a strict interest in holding the-
oretical propositions to a standard of audible relevance, but the ways of
meeting this standard are meant to be multiple, even beyond anticipation.)
From the second it follows that some of the connotations of “structure”—
those of logic, pertinence, comprehensiveness—may limit our imaginations
for the first point; may even actively lead us away from good possibilities. Let
us say at least that the thing we hear, the thing we put together in experience,
in reaction to, in consequence of, our encounter with a musical “structure”
need not be expected to have those connoted characteristics. And in that
case, why should we even take the trouble to expect the thing encountered
to have those characteristics?
mented by E, the most lusted for: how do the relative strengths of the lusts
account for that? So perhaps the transformational reading of the piece
should not be called on to predict or explain what happens in the piece. Per-
haps its role is to elaborate the meaning of things that do happen, along the
lines of “should Cs come along, it may do so with an air of filling out Fs–B into
a complete transposition or inversion of G–C–F.”
Which probably is as it should be. After all (as Martin Scherzinger once
pointed out in a discussion of Lewin’s article), this is about the least lustful-
sounding piece anyone has ever heard. The sense of earlier events driving
later ones to happen, which Lewin has so productively synthesized in this
atonal context, may not carry over directly from the realm of abstract trans-
position and inversion to the temporal flow of this composition.
Here is another way to read the technical information. The fact that Ds is
compatible with only one of the many possible transformational relations
between the two chords, means that Ds does as much as any note could to
differentiate one relationship from the others, thus at least momentarily to dis-
ambiguate the cloud produced by the chords’ combination. In this sense, Ds
is the most eloquent note that could have been chosen to come first—as it
does, alone, and scored to pierce the haze—the single note that can do most
to define the relationship between the chords. And then E, the note that
ornaments Ds (in one of the two registers in which Ds occurs), is the most
neutral note that could be chosen for this role—the one that, in itself, does
least to diminish the ambiguity of the original combination, and therefore
does least to counter the clarifying effect of Ds.6
To appreciate this alteration of imagery, it helps to direct your auditory
attention away from the two chords as they are attacked, toward the sound of
all six notes (and fifteen intervals) ringing together, a state that persists for
quite a long time. Elaine Barkin encourages this move in her writing about
this piece: most concisely in Barkin 1979b, with the word “INTER ACT” writ-
ten out vertically, interlaced with the ties that sustain the two chords, and
later (even after Ds) with the ties (rearranged as they are in the score) fol-
lowed by a vertical “intermit”, but also throughout Barkin 1979a, which
makes a theme of “not . . . ‘letting go’ ” (21) when it would be tempting to
say that nothing is happening. What happens, while the chords fade away
together, is that an initial unclear configuration—unclear in that it is full of
suggestions—remains unclarified, and even blurs further; and then is recre-
ated, before anything else is added. This is not the dynamic that Lewin’s
unfulfilled transpositions and inversions might immediately suggest; but it
is one to which his technical information can productively be harnessed. We
simply have to notice that attacks of notes are not the only kind of event in
the piece.
Theorists may be interested to note that this interpretation of Lewin’s
material, though on the face of it less “deterministic”—that is, less concerned
190 joseph dubiel
Example 6.7 Schoenberg, Sechs kleine Klavierstücke, op. 19 no. 6: Ds added to the
second chord completing T6 of the first; then an extension of T6 between two
sonorities, both including Ds.
? WA W AA ? WA
T6 of
W AA =
WA
and/or T6 of
WW AA =
W AA
! A AA A AA
this? At the very end, the same registral configuration—the original high and
low chords, and then something below them—occurs in a more extreme
form, with the new low thing lower, and therefore with both of the original
chords recharacterized as high, the distinction between them not sounding
as it once did. My suggestion is that the ambiguous registral situation of Ds
is the first step in this process.
I find it encouraging that a percept as macroscopic and (relatively) unthe-
oretical as a gradual reconfiguration of our sense of registral location should
turn out to be so thoroughly intertwined with a sense of intervallic differen-
tiation and character developed in (and from) a context where none seems
to be given a priori—a story of the tritones, to put it simply. I feel that, after
some effort, I have really found something in the sound that I can believe is
significantly a consequence of the transformational configuration con-
structed by Lewin.
It is interesting that I had to work away from an “implicative” account of
the music (at least a little) to find this. It is as though a certain, not-alto-
gether-thought-through image of what analytical-perceptual success would
look like had to be to some degree overcome to reach this conception of the
sound. The ambition to say why things happen—to represent events as caused
within the piece—is in this case worth setting aside, in favor of the ambition
only (only!) to say what things are when they do happen. And the analysis
includes, as a central feature, a long passage of music that is hard to char-
acterize in the terms of the analysis. For me, the key thing to find here (or to
let myself accept) was the unclarity of the coexisting chords—the constructed
unclarity. Here, I gained by allowing myself not to be on top of events.
by the beginning of a thematic statement in that key early in the piece (m.
8). This E major does not even last the full length of the figure, from one
downbeat to the next: the Bn that would complete the figure is supplanted by
Bs, and C-sharp minor easily reabsorbs the whole thing. A hopeful event is
swallowed up, and the music goes on remarkably as though it never hap-
pened. It’s a sad moment.
It’s the vanishing to which I want to do justice, analytically—including the
sadness. I’d like to find something to say about how a composition isn’t just
going astray if it puts something behind it, but that does let a loss sound like
a loss. In a way, this shouldn’t be hard. Why can’t a composition do that, if it
wants to? But even if am I hyperconscientious on this point, still the weight
of analytical tradition is against portraying the progress of a piece in this way.
The most traditional thing to do about a passage like this is precisely to deny
that a modulation takes place, to deny it precisely for the reason that it is not
sustained. The view is obvious almost beyond discussion in our Schenker-
influenced analytical world, but we hardly need Schenker to appreciate it;
in fact, the most conventional and limited harmony book is likely to make
precisely this sort of distinction, between “real” and merely “apparent” mod-
ulations, its topic of greatest intellectual intensity.
More specifically and interestingly, analytical culture places a high value
on the identification of details that follow up, refer to, and in that sense sus-
tain the sound of, unusual events, with a certain extra cachet given to events
that do this unobviously. So the routinely “sophisticated” way to handle an
unrealized modulation would be to acknowledge that lesser minds might
ignore it and then counter that, if we do recognize it—recognize it as unre-
alized, that is—then we can find such-and-such interesting reflections of it
later in the piece; and in that sense, the modulation turns out not to be lost
at all, as nothing in a great piece is allowed to be lost. A prime candidate for
such an unobvious reflection ( just to show I know my business) would be the
(deservedly) celebrated dissonant clash, late in the piece, between Bs in a
chord and Bn in a descending scale—thus, between the diagnostic pitch
classes of C-sharp minor and E major (at the end of m. 29—a favorite
moment of Schoenberg’s). But I rather like a hearing of this piece in which
E major just goes lost after the early adumbration of it; in which the prelude’s
tone changes, as it proves to be in many ways a looser and more obscure com-
position than it initially seemed it was going to be. And no matter the mer-
its of this hearing, I ought to have the capacity to construct it; maybe some-
one else would prefer a different story, but it ought not to be the theory that
decides for us.
In retrospect, there will be plenty of reasons not to have trusted in E
major, even as the thematic statement begins. The preceding sequence does
not lead to a cadence in this key, only to the triad; the dominant preceding
194 joseph dubiel
this triad is not even in root position; and this dominant represents essen-
tially the first harmonic occurrence of Bn,8 and not, as a fully elaborated mod-
ulation would require, the resituation in E major of a Bn already introduced
within C-sharp minor. And although there is a familiar Baroque pattern com-
prising a few statements of the motive in the tonic key (mm. 1–4), a modu-
lating sequence (mm. 5–7), and an arrival at a new key, marked by the
motive again, all the features of the prelude just cited are departures from
the pattern’s ideal form—to which familiarity with the form paradoxically
sensitizes me.
In this sense, perceiving an E-major key, even at the prompting of a the-
matic entrance, is getting ahead of myself—allowing myself to get ahead of
myself (or is that the way it always happens?). It’s not making up a new key
out of whole cloth; it’s not even ignoring contradictory evidence, really (evi-
dence doesn’t seem like quite the right concept, although some music the-
ory might talk of it this way); it’s just going quite far on the strength of some
understated suggestions. Is it or isn’t it wishing a new key into existence?
The first thing I have to work with—even before the motive unfolds—is
the harmonic clarity of the E-major triad, in contrast to the airy dissonance
of the sequence. Over and above this clarity, the E-major measure is much
richer harmonically than any measure of the opening: besides the gentle
expression of the subdominant on the last quarter note (a precedented
detail),9 the transitory combination of Ds and Fs on the way to this quarter
note even suggests the dominant; and in the piece so far, any major-triad
sonority stands out, let alone a mutually reinforcing combination of them.10
The exposure of the neighboring subdominant, intensified further by the
ornament, prepares the particular cruelty of its capture by C-sharp minor in
the place of its resolution: warmth and fineness of detail turn out to be vul-
nerability.
The music that comes with Bs does not even act to erase E major, really,
so much as carry on as though E major had never happened. Its most chill-
ing aspect may be its reimposition of a pattern of strong and weak measures
that seemed to have faded away. The metrical regularity of the opening mea-
sures (like their harmonic sobriety) is suspended during the sequence, or at
least not reinforced: a series of parallel measures, as clearly articulated as
these are by suspensions and resolutions, can easily be taken “one, one, one,”
with the strong–weak pattern promising to reemerge at the time of the new
motivic statement. And with respect to the reemergent pattern, the Bs chord
that cuts off the statement makes a surprising accent—in effect a syncopated
one; but it can also be heard as simply strong, as falling back into the origi-
nal two-measure rhythm, which had been displaced only so briefly and
inconclusively that its recovery is easy.
The psychology of the hypermeter is all of a piece with that of the tonal-
ity. Nothing in the sequence actively interferes with the original pairing of
uncertainty, disorientation, and loss 195
two times, the complete motive is not really attempted again, even though
the prelude has almost half its time yet to run; and for that matter none of
these near attempts is in the upper voice.
What is it like to hear this? I’d have to be analytically on edge to notice the
motive’s not recurring, let alone its not recurring as a reaction to something
that happens to E major early on. I would expect the fact to strike me, not at
any particular point, but perhaps as something about the tone of the contin-
uation, the way the prelude spends the rest of its time in flux, thematically
and to some degree harmonically. Apart from the incipits of the principal
motive, the thing that the prelude comes nearest to “recapitulating” is its
modulating sequence; and it is remarkable how strangely placed and blurred
this is. Its beginning overlaps the Fs-minor motivic statement (perhaps even
takes over from it), half a measure out of its original metric position; only the
upper voice is parallel to the earlier passage; and the newly composed lower
voices are only intermittently sequential (the second half of m. 22 is approx-
imately parallel to the second half of m. 21). Nowhere can the prelude work
itself up to a decisive large-scale dominant: what seems to happen is that the
dominant triad is laid over the root of the subdominant, as a big 42 chord (this
happens in m. 29, after one more start on the motive in an Fs triad, and it
eventuates in the scale that produces the Bn against Bs), and then the piece
goes into its most extreme state of textural flux, in effect a written two-voice
cadenza, reeling further and further from its motives until the cadence.
It is hard to describe hearing what the piece does not do. I suppose this
must involve infusing my hearing of what the piece does do with a sense of
“instead of” or “when it might have”; and it would be difficult to identify this
sense with particular times (when does the piece not go to the dominant?).
It would be difficult to make it part of my listening to tot them up as evidence
that E major must have been really important, as I have (more or less) been
doing analytically. Most of what there is to hear from them, I have been sug-
gesting, is a change in the prelude’s tone, a loss of clarity of articulation.
This is the attitude I would take, as well, toward the dissonant Bn of mea-
sure 29, to which I referred earlier: insofar as I recognize the pitch as a ref-
erence to E major at all, I want to interpret the reference as an indication of
just how far we are from a recovery of E major. Theorists often use the idea of
reference very casually, often running it together with “resemblance” and
leaving it at that. But a reference doesn’t always have to be a positive one; an
event can take its meaning in significant part from its relation to E major but
not necessarily sound like E major. A particularly delicate instance of this
occurs in the passage that revisits the modulating sequence (mm. 20–24).
Supposing that a diatonic circle of fifths is a relevant model for the passage—
certainly its last few steps (mm. 23–24) clearly express the roots Gs, Cs, Fs—
then its first few roots, after the Fs from which it begins, could well have been
B, E, A. Of course they aren’t allowed to be: the details of the (nonsequen-
198 joseph dubiel
notes
I thank Christopher Bailey, Marlon Feld, Jason Freeman, Marion A. Guck, Richard
Plotkin, Martin Scherzinger, and Melanie Schoenberg for valuable comments on var-
ious aspects of this essay.
1. I want to acknowledge my indebtedness, throughout this discussion, to several
writers, and this may be the point when specific connections are easiest to draw. Mark
uncertainty, disorientation, and loss 199
DeBellis, in Music and Conceptualization (1995), shows how the idea of perceiving
something under one concept and another, or perhaps under none, more efficiently
does much of the theoretical work that is usually attempted with the ideas of con-
scious and unconscious perception or, even more vaguely, with background and fore-
ground. Kendall Walton (1993) and Marion A. Guck (1993) describe and illustrate
the possibility of a cause of one’s experience becoming, through analysis, another
object of appreciation.
2. It is interesting to notice, incidentally, how, in the second act (less obviously
characterized by unfulfilled longing), this theme pointedly and repeatedly does not
enter to continue any of the very many references to the deceptive cadence.
3. By pointing out that the bass notes Ds and E that precede the thematic entrance
occur within inchoate versions of the theme—up a small interval, down a big one,
B–C–Ds, C–Cs–E—Richard Plotkin suggested to me a still more complex story, in
which the theme’s agency cannot be discounted, even though its identity is still blurry.
4. There is no metronome mark; but if the speed of the measure were set at
q = 63–66—practically the default tempo of Feldman’s late music, as Paul Nauert
has pointed out to me—then a sixty-fourth note would last something like 1/26 or
1/25 of a second, only slightly longer than the period of the vibrations of the low-
est A on the piano, which come twenty-seven and one-half to the second. It seems
safe to say that this duration is not perceptible as a duration.
5. No one is more scrupulous than Lewin about the difference between an elab-
orated analysis and the assembly of technical material to inform such an analysis—
even here, where he has done such a remarkable job of building qualities of move-
ment and implication into the technical material. And therefore I wish to be very
clear that my subsequent reflections on this material are not intended as criticism of
Lewin’s ingenious proposals; rather, they represent my continuation after the point
where his article turns to other matters.
6. Of course, E itself represents another moment of incompletion under the
transformation that Ds reinforces, T6; its counterpart under this transformation, Bf,
is the next new pitch class to enter the piece.
7. For an extended discussion of listening to single notes in this way, and, more
generally, of treating “structure” as a way to confer characteristics upon individual
elements, see Hirata 1996. The influence of ideas developed by Hirata in her disser-
tation about Feldman (Hirata 2002) is too pervasive for me to identify (it is by no
means limited to my discussion of Feldman, and indeed may be more prominent in
all the other examples), and I gratefully acknowledge it throughout.
8. There is a Bn on the downbeat of the second measure of the sequence, and it is
good enough to make the bass Fs dissonant; but either it is absent by the time the bass
resolves to E or it is dissonant against Cs in the tenor, which moves in parallel with
the bass.
9. The last quarter note of the measure is a moment of subtle harmonic interest
through the opening statements of the theme, expressing an ostensibly neighboring
harmony that, a little more each time, shows the potential to do something more—
prepare a dissonance (m. 2), displace the main harmony (m. 3)—and then recedes.
10. It is obvious how one would go about dismissing these consonances as zufäl-
lig, in Schenker’s sense; but it is more interesting to recognize the relevance of their
200 joseph dubiel
Collective Listening
Postmodern Critical Processes and MTV
andrew dell ’ antonio
1.1 Structural listening strategies imply a model of one-to-one communication: the lis-
tener, in understanding the structural development of a musical text, is made privy to the
composer’s creative processes. Under this model, the composer’s intentions are tied up
with an individual’s understanding of the unfolding of a musical work.
This is the model that Rose Rosengard Subotnik outlines in her essay
“Toward a Deconstruction of Structural Listening” from her recent collec-
tion Deconstructive Variations:
1.2 This is the kind of authorial presence and individual interpretative engagement that
modernist critics such as Adorno, Horkheimer, and Jameson have bemoaned as lacking
in popular music.
is aimed in this case at motion pictures, but such critiques are regularly
applied to other commercially-driven artifacts, including popular music.
Jameson explicitly draws a comparison between the “authenticity” of the
experience of “popular” versus “classical” music, to the clear detriment of
the former:
I will argue that we never hear any [contemporary pop works] “for the first
time”; instead, we live a constant exposure to them in all kinds of different sit-
uations . . . this is a very different situation from the first bewildered audition
of a complicated classical piece . . . the passionate attachment one can form
[to pop works] are fully as much a function of our own familiarity as of the work
itself . . . what we listen to is ourselves, our own previous auditions. ( Jameson
1979, 129–30)
tural forms that break from an ideal of “high art,” particularly those that
place less emphasis on the creative primacy of a single author of a stable text.
Pace Jameson, I would argue that critical engagement does not presuppose
“high art” repertories; indeed, as Simon Frith observes,
people bring similar questions to high and low art, that their pleasures and sat-
isfactions are rooted in similar analytic issues, similar ways of relating what they
see or hear to how they think and feel. The differences between high and low
emerge because these questions are embedded in different historical and
material circumstances, and are therefore framed differently. (Frith 1996, 19)
As we will see below, music videos do not match Jameson’s modernist model
of autonomy, hence an exploration of music videos must find a different
conceptual framework for the interaction between texts and their appraisal.
2.1 Semiotician Umberto Eco has instead argued for an “intention of the text”: the text
itself, providing clues as to how it “wants” to be read, may present sufficient intentional-
ity to create its own “Ideal Reader” (or perhaps, in the case of music, “Ideal Listener”). This
model opens up the interpretative field and might provide a useful alternative to the
search for a composer’s original intentions.
Italian semiotician and critic Umberto Eco, attempting to work around the
need for stable and verifiable authorial subjectivity while still retaining the pos-
sibility of predictable signification, focuses on the notion that a text itself
(rather than its author’s intended message) may contain the locus of meaning.
“A text,” Eco suggests, “as it appears in its linguistic manifestation or surface,
represents a chain of expressive devices that must be actualized/deployed by
its recipient” (Eco 1998, 50). Furthermore,
A text is in any case woven up with “white spaces,” gaps to be filled . . . because,
the more its function is aesthetic rather than explanatory, a text wants to leave
the interpretative initiative up to its reader, even if it usually wants to be inter-
preted within a certain margin of unequivocality. A text wants someone to help
make it work. (Eco 1998, 52)
to predict one’s Ideal Reader means not only to “hope” that he exists, it means
shaping the text so as to create him. A text not only rests upon, but also con-
tributes to the production of a competence. Thus perhaps a text is less lazy, its
request to cooperate less liberal than it may want to make us believe. (Eco
1998, 56)
One of the principal ways by which the text shapes the reader’s interpre-
tative decisions is by leading the reader to develop a hypothesis about what
Eco calls the topic of the text:
The topic is a hypothesis that depends on the initiative of the reader, who for-
mulates it in a rather crude way, as a question (“what the hell is this about?”)
which translates itself into a tentative proposed title (“this is probably about
X”). The topic is thus a meta-textual instrument that a text can either imply or
contain explicitly in the form of topic markers, titles, subtitles, guiding expres-
sions. On the basis of the topic, the reader will decide to magnify or minimize
the semantic properties of the terms at hand, establishing a level of interpreta-
tive coherence, which we shall call isotopia. (Eco 1998, 92)
2.2 Eco’s discussion still, however, works within the framework of individual communi-
cation: a text creates an ideal recipient.
3.1 Expanding on Eco’s lead, this essay explores the idea of the “intention of a musical
text” in the context of music videos and MTV. These are complex sources, comprising
multiple layers of media and hence authorship.
In moving from a literary to a musical text, the most direct way to translate
Eco’s notion of the Ideal Reader might seem to be a notion of an “Ideal Lis-
tener.” Yet the term “listener” is not entirely suited to my purpose, especially
in the context of a discussion of music videos, which involve multimedia con-
sumption. Indeed, the notion of “listening” is itself problematic: it implies
that the sense of hearing can—or should—be detached from other senses
when encountering a multimedia work.4 For the sake of this discussion, I will
use the term Ideal Appraiser, derived from a cross-pollination of Eco’s
model with Gracyk’s notion of “appraisal” as the process of responding to a
multimedia work.5
208 andrew dell’antonio
Music videos, then, are multimedia works resulting from the intersection of
multiple authors and artistic personas. It is perhaps a self-evident point, when
dealing with rock/pop repertories, that the author of the lyrics of a rock/pop
song is often not the same as the composer of the tune (or, indeed, that differ-
ent elements of the tune—melody, harmony, orchestration/arrangement—
may be contributed by different individuals), and that the lead singer is often
yet another individual (not to mention other band members and additional
performers, such as dancers, a prominent feature in many pop and hip-hop
videos). The songwriters/performers may have control over the video’s sound
and overall musical structure (videos are, after all, supposed to match “their”
song rather closely, though different styles of video do so in a variety of ways,
many avoiding or disrupting linear narrative), but directors generally are
known (and sought out by performers) for bringing their own specific “look”
or visual style to a video. The question of the relative “weight” of visual and
sound parameters as perceived by the video appraiser is a tricky one, and for
the moment I shall sidestep it, limiting myself to observing that both elements
can certainly be appraised simultaneously, even if to varying degrees of con-
sciousness and attention. Ultimately, then, music videos are a prime example
of a multimedia work produced by a large number of authors, with differing
(possibly competing) expressive/semiotic agendas.6
3.2 Music videos are also consumed in ways that differ from Eco’s model of detached
critical reading, and thus construct their “ideal viewer/listener” (or Ideal Appraiser)
through significantly different procedures.
The essential element of pleasure in viewing the clips must involve more than
purely visual pleasure . . . the clips must encompass a delivery of pleasure that
relates visuals to the music that is being sold, that provides an experience of
collective listening 209
A video must be able to function as a “commercial” for the song with which
it is associated, especially since videos do not make up a significant source
of income for either the artist or the record company (indeed, record
companies tend to consider videos to be unfortunate but necessary
expenses, as Goodwin points out). Yet a video cannot serve only that func-
tion, since MTV (in selling its commercial time, which can take up as much
of 30 percent of each broadcast hour) needs to be able to rely on its view-
ers’ willingness—indeed, eagerness—to watch a video repeatedly (I shall
refer to this phenomenon as iterative viewing/appraisal), and indeed to
tune to the channel in the hopes of seeing a favorite video. Thus, the video
must be able to deliver pleasure (and hence signify) in its own right, in a
way that supplements the song, and must offer meanings that rely on
repeated pleasure in the course of successive appraisals. A desirability of
iterative consumption (both of the video as a whole and of its primary com-
ponent, the song) must thus be built into the video’s construction of an
Ideal Appraiser.
One further characteristic of the genre (which is shared by all time-con-
tingent cultural forms, including film and of course heard—as opposed to
score-read—music) is that appraisers cannot interrupt their “reading” of a
video to review the meanings of a previous passage, and hence to refine their
understanding of the video’s topic. This immersive condition is in direct con-
trast to the detached/detachable nature of textual reading; as Eco remarks,
“The more complex a text is, its reading is never linear; the reader is forced
to look back and re-read the text, perhaps several times, even in some cases
beginning from the end” (Eco 1998, 91). Despite the undeniable complex-
ity of a video’s layered signification, however, the video appraiser lacks this
resource available to Eco’s text reader. (While it is possible to pause or
rewind a recording, music videos are seldom consumed on videotape.) If a
video signified like a complex written text, one would assume that repeated
viewings/hearings would be needed in order for appraisers to form a coher-
ent isotopia. Indeed, it may well be that the iterative phenomenon of “heavy
rotation” (MTV’s repeated showing of a video in different time slots, espe-
cially in the few weeks following its introduction) is meant to offer the
appraising public repeated opportunities to assimilate the information that
the video provides. I have speculated elsewhere (see Dell’Antonio 1999,
72–73) that iterative exposure to a text/performance can replace “critically
distant” reflection for the purposes of immersion-based critical processes;
this may be what MTV is trying to achieve.
But does the appraiser require multiple rehearings/viewings in order to
understand a video, or (pace Jameson) can videos signify strongly enough to
210 andrew dell’antonio
enable the consumer to shape meaning (topic, isotopia) the first time around?
And how much of the video must be appraised in order for the appraiser to
engage the topic/isotopia dialectic? We should note here that seeing a video
from beginning to end is not a given on MTV: introductions by the network’s
“video jockeys” (VJs) often overlap with the first few seconds, and on many
shows (particularly the popular call-in show Total Request Live, on which more
below) only portions of videos are shown. The fact that these fragmented ver-
sions make up a substantial part of MTV’s schedule implies that videos do not
require structural integrity—a marker, one would presume, of Horkheimer’s
“autonomous necessity”—in order to be effectively appraised.
If videos are frequently appraised in versions lacking structural integrity,
it would seem that structural appraisal (hence structural listening) is not cru-
cial to the process of understanding music videos. The Ideal Appraiser that
music videos envision is not a structural appraiser. But then, Eco is careful
to distinguish what he calls the fabula of a text (the linear sequence of events
that make up its structure) from the topic (which is, as we saw above, “what
the text is about”). And if the two elements are strongly linked in the textual
examples Eco provides (and, certainly, in a structural/formalist notion of
musical meaning), they need not be—cannot be, I will argue—in an
appraisal of a music video and a concomitant understanding of its topic.
Indeed, Goodwin has observed that the “multilayered text” of a popular
song (which, following McClary and Walser, he sees as composed of a “stack-
ing up” of different components of social meaning; Goodwin 1992, 94) does
not work according to the linear correspondences and connections of real-
ist narrative, and hence cannot be read (we might say appraised) employing
the same techniques. This is all the more true of videos, which combine the
“meaning stack” of a song with a visual “meaning stack” that can further
break down any tendency toward linear narrative progression.7 This is not to
say that videos inherently exemplify Jamesonian assemblages of empty sig-
nifiers; as Goodwin has rightly pointed out, the blanket description of MTV
as a postmodern phenomenon, and of videos as quintessentially postmodern
texts, has relied on mistaken assumptions about the predominance of visual
and cinematic components in the structure of music video.8 All the same, the
lack of dependable integrity discourages a structural/teleological appraisal
of fabula in music videos. Appraisal techniques must turn elsewhere to
develop the topic, and we shall return to this issue shortly.
One final important issue differentiating the video appraisal process
from Eco’s model is the thorny question of whether videos are “texts” at all,
or whether they should best be understood as recorded performances, and
what the distinction might mean for the collective appraiser. “Before trying
to make sense of performance as a way of working with a text,” suggests Frith,
“we should first be sure we understand how performance is different, how it
is ‘non-textual’. What makes something a performance in the first place?”
collective listening 211
(Frith 1996, 204). For our purposes we might ask, to what degree is a music
video “performative” and to what degree is it “textual”? Frith cites anthro-
pologist Richard Bauman in observing that “a performance is ‘an emergent
structure’: it comes into being only as it is being performed . . . Bauman
[also] suggests that performance is an ‘enhancement’, involving a height-
ened ‘intensity’ of communication: it makes the communicative process
itself, the use of language and gesture, the focus of attention” (Frith 1996,
208). “Sincerity” or essential meaning. Frith argues, “cannot be measured by
searching for what lies behind the performance: if we are moved by a per-
former we are moved by what we immediately hear and see” (215).
Frith and Bauman’s characterization above hinges on immediacy as a nec-
essary component—even a defining trait—of the aesthetic experience of a
performance (as opposed to something perceived as a “text”).9 An experi-
ence that requires or foregrounds immediacy will necessarily require differ-
ent strategies for consumption than one that requires distancing or reflec-
tion. Of course, immediacy does not preclude awareness (conscious or
otherwise) of such structuring aspects as form: after all, listeners always bring
a panoply of generic expectations to a musical work, and those expectations
can include specific types of structural “milestones.” A foregrounding of
immediacy does, however, entail an ideal of (at least partial) surprise, a will-
ingness to release the kind of control over the workings of a musical event
that is implicit in an ideal of detached structural listening.
If process is foregrounded, focus on text and its completeness is not nec-
essary. Indeed, since completeness of a text can only be assessed through dis-
tancing, and performance (as theorized above) gains meaning through
immediacy and immersion, assessment of completeness cannot play any role
in appraising a performance. The notion of a complete/stable text is thus
rejected, or at best marginalized; and as we have speculated in Section 1.2
above, the idea of structural listening seems best suited for—arguably,
requires—an identifiable and stable text. Thus, structural listening would
seem unsuitable for understanding musical events that can be deemed “per-
formances” rather than “texts.”
Frith (1996, 225) suggests that music videos display the characteristics of
performance outlined above. It can be argued, however, that videos also dis-
play one of the primary characteristics of texts: they are fixed, not variable,
and can be recognized (and marketed) as stable entities. If videos are not
texts but performances (or, I would argue, text/performance hybrids), and
if the most crucial aesthetic aspect of a performance of rock/pop/rap music
(and, by extension, the performative aspect of a music video) is its immedi-
acy of signification, and if critical distance is impossible or undesirable when
appraising a performance (rather than a text), what other critical options
are available?
We might think of this another way, triangulating Eco’s textual model
212 andrew dell’antonio
with the notion of structural listening and the distinction between text and
performance explored above. If a text calls attention to its unfolding mean-
ing (by asking its reader to arrive at a stable isotopia through postulating a
topic), a performance calls attention to the process of meaning-production
(the postulation of the topic) itself. If so, a performance is a quintessentially
social activity, since the members of the group witnessing a performance are
connected by their shared processing of the codes/signs generated by the
performance (their shared negotiation between topic and isotopia), much
more self-consciously than solitary readers of the same text can ever be. In
other words, the specific message of a performance (and, I would contend
with Frith, a music video) is not as crucial as the way the performance/video
reinforces understandings about what is collectively meaningful—whether
politically, socially, or aesthetically—and how the collective arrives at such
meanings. Indeed, the semantic codes that the video text/performance pro-
vides to its appraisers may serve (and, as we will see below, frequently do
serve) specifically to reinforce a topic that is explicitly collective.
The idea of the collective is, indeed, part and parcel of the sensibility sur-
rounding late twentieth-century popular music. As Lawrence Grossberg sug-
gests, “the consumption of rock constructs or expresses a ‘community’ ”;
Grossberg connects this with the “authenticity” of hard/folk rock culture,
which “assumes that authentic rock depends on its ability to articulate private
but common desires, feelings and experiences into a shared public lan-
guage” (Grossberg 1993, 202). The authenticity of rock depends on perme-
ability between public and private emotions: the boundaries between the
individual and the collective are not as clearly drawn as in the modernist par-
adigm of critical distance. The creative process itself is often portrayed as a
collective effort: as Frith observes,
since the mid-sixties the group (rather than the solo singer) has dominated
Anglo-American popular music (at least in terms of male voices), and if such
groups more often than not have a “lead” singer we rarely hear his voice com-
pletely unaccompanied. We are, that is, accustomed to the idea of a “group
voice.” (Frith 1996, 201)
If a collective expressive “voice” has long played a role in the “authentic” cre-
ative impulse of rock/pop, it is reasonable that this should be so for critical
approaches to the repertory as well. Along these lines, Frith suggests that
“dancing in public—listening in public—thus seems to be more expressive of
how we feel about our music, more truthful, than dancing, listening alone”
(Frith 1996, 240). Such a construct of authentic experience through collec-
tive rather than solitary enjoyment in rock and pop music culture is evident
in music videos, which often appeal to collectivity, each genre doing so in a
somewhat different way: heavy metal or punk/grunge bands incorporate
concert scenes with ecstatic, dancing/moshing/screaming fans; rap videos
collective listening 213
often have street scenes with the rappers surrounded by dancing fans and/or
gesturing, stone-faced homeboys; pop artists incorporate complex choreo-
graphed group dance sequences. The video appraiser is encouraged to see
her/himself as one of the collective of fans, or perhaps even (by sing-
ing/dancing along with the stars) “in sync” with the performers.
I would thus suggest that the critical model that music videos establish
is one of collective negotiation; thus the Ideal Appraiser they construct
is a collective, not an individual. The topic/isotopia of a video is negotiated
not according to Eco’s one-to-one model of a text and a solitary reader/
appraiser, but rather between a group of appraisers who collectively process
the semantic information provided by the video; and further, that process of
meaning-negotiation (i.e., the collective creation of a topic) is assumed to
be as crucial as final agreement on a stable set of meanings (or isotopia), if
not more so. Thus, in working toward a notion of the Ideal Appraiser of
music videos, one of the key elements is the breakdown of a single, stable
subject position—whether from the standpoint of the video or that of its
appraiser.
3.3 Most importantly for this essay, I will argue that the Ideal Appraiser for such texts is
not individual but collective: music videos on MTV appear to be meant to be consumed
not by an individual but by a group. Indeed, in those occasions in which MTV displays crit-
ical reactions to videos, such reactions are collective rather than individual: MTV portrays
collectivity and group participation as crucial to the listening/viewing experience.
then would change time slot or be discontinued until another special event
came along). When paired with music videos, Yack Live resulted in a format
remarkably similar to the collective commentary seen in B&B. MTV would
announce a time and a specific IRC chat room for its video-based Yack Live,
show a number of videos (either from its regular rotation or specially fea-
tured videos), and then monitor the chat room and broadcast the dialogue
on the chat rooms simultaneously with the videos.12 While the Yack Live chat
was ostensibly about the videos, and a number of the broadcasted comments
did indeed reflect on the video’s content, the dialogue between the chat par-
ticipants (sometimes up to fifteen or twenty interweaving individuals) was
anything but focused on video commentary. Like B&B, the interlocutors
moved freely from specific commentary to sparring/flirting with other
“chatters” to commenting on their state of mind. Still, the Yack Live chat was
by no means unconnected to the videos: in some sense, the entirety of the
exchanges entailed the negotiation of meanings and emotions surrounding
the appraisal of a video, instances of an immersion-based collective critical
process akin to the one seen in B&B.
Collective critical processes were again at stake in a short-lived MTV show
called Twelve Angry Viewers (hereafter 12AV), which aired in the period
between autumn 1997 and spring 1998. Through a process implicitly por-
trayed as random, each week MTV chose twelve “jurors” to represent its view-
ers.13 Each daily half-hour show presented three videos, each followed by dis-
cussion and each juror voting on a 1 to 5 scale; the video that received the
most points was declared the day’s winner. At the end of each week, jurors
voted on the winners of the four previous days, and the weekly winner was
put into “heavy rotation” (i.e., MTV pledged to show it on an especially fre-
quent basis) for an unspecified period of time.14
While offering an image of the critical process, MTV focused instead on the
ostensible results of that process; when jurors cast their votes, they were asked
to give only a number, and not a rationale for their choice (though often jurors
did provide a one-sentence explanation of their vote). Unlike B&B (which pre-
sented short excerpts of each video, thus foregrounding the protagonists’
commentary rather than the video), 12AV initially presented videos (almost)
in their entirety, perhaps with the ostensible goal of providing the jurors (and
the MTV viewership) a full “text” by which to judge the video. In later episodes,
as the commentary/discussion portion of the show was increased by one or
two minutes, smaller portions of the videos were shown.
Especially interesting for the purposes of this study was MTV’s depiction
of the critical process in 12AV: during the course of each video, a small but
well-visible “picture within the picture” provided the television viewer with
a silent image of the 12AV jurors sitting on couches and on the floor in front
of the TV (a visual link to the world of B&B, and probably yet another appeal
to “real-ness” on the part of MTV, on which more below), appraising the
collective listening 215
4.1 The idea of a collective listener/reader for a collective text is incompatible with
Adorno and Horkheimer’s formulations of artistic autonomy or Jameson’s ideal of stable
collective listening 219
subjectivity, but it does seem to mesh with recent theories (such as those of Deleuze and
Guattari) that characterize postmodern subject positions as multiple and shifting.
But through the impasses and the [oedipal] triangles a schizophrenic flow
moves, irresistibly . . . a stream of words that do not let themselves be coded, a
libido that is too fluid, too viscous: a violence against syntax, a concerted
destruction of the signifier, non-sense erected as a flow, polyvocity that returns
to haunt all relations. . . . language is no longer defined by what it says, even
less by what makes it a signifying thing, but by what causes it to move, to flow,
and to explode—desire (Deleuze and Guattari 1977, 133).19
The origin of packs is entirely different from that of families and states: they
continually work them from within and trouble them from without, with other
forms of content, other forms of expression (Deleuze and Guattari 1988, 242).
4.2 Collective listening strategies may be not so much postmodern as non- modernist;
their presence and premises certainly call into question an idealization of structural lis-
tening as normative practice.
What we have examined so far suggests that the performative texts of music
videos are not suited to a model of structural listening, and that collective lis-
tening strategies (which, I have argued, show traits of subjectivities and
approaches to “objects/phenomena”—texts, performances, etc.—that have
been theorized as “postmodern”) seem to be (or at least are portrayed as
being) uniquely suited to these late twentieth-century multimedia phenom-
ena. Furthermore, Frith argues that incomplete and fragmentary appraisal
is fast becoming the norm for all repertories:
We certainly do now hear music as a fragmented and unstable object. . . . All
music is more often heard now in fragments than completely: we hear slices of
Beatles songs and Bach cantatas, quotes from jazz and blues. Such fragmentary
listening may have as much to do with—may be particularly suited to—indus-
trialization and urbanization as with recording technology as such. (Frith
1996, 242)
mode of presentation: just a few seconds are enough to establish the coher-
ent system of signs (isotopia) that it inhabits, and thus what it is “about” (topic).
Once the topic/isotopia are established, the video’s role is to prolong and reit-
erate those signs, through musical, visual, and (to a much lesser extent) spe-
cific textual or structural means. To be sure, there are meanings in most
music videos that can be lost if the video is not appraised attentively and/or
in its entirety, and the same can be said for popular songs, which create
meaning through structural unfolding as well as through immediate signifi-
cation. However, attentive and thorough appraisal is by no means essential
to the topic/isotopia of the video/song; otherwise most manifestations of
videos/songs, being fragmentary, would be meaningless, powerless to create
an Ideal Appraiser—and this is clearly not the case.
But here we come to another quandary: the same could be argued about,
say, a Mozart symphony as well. Certain musical gestures or devices in the
course of any of Mozart’s symphonies provide immediate signification to a
listener familiar with eighteenth-century musical conventions, whether by
the associative nature of the instrumentation or tone color used, the place
of specific harmonic or melodic gestures within normative/accepted prac-
tice, irregularity/regularity of adjacent phrases, and so on. We do not need
to hear an entire movement to recognize a dominant pedal as a “flag” to spe-
cific kinds of events, or to mark a musical idea that features flutes as possibly
“pastoral” in character, or to perceive an antecedent/consequent pair as
oddly configured, as long as we are familiar with the semiotic codes (whether
explicitly “musical” or not) of late eighteenth-century Europe. We cannot,
however, focus on the “uniqueness” of a specific Mozartean symphonic
movement without listening to it in its entirety—and preferably with the con-
stant attention and focus, not to mention critical distance, that structural lis-
tening would seem to require.
Thus, I would argue that only specific, limited repertories—repertories
that have traditionally been seen as requiring self-isolation within the col-
lective in order to achieve the goal of critical distance and individualized sub-
jectivity—have demanded a focused (hence non-collective) listening strat-
egy. Or better yet: such a “requirement” of self-isolation may be in no way
inherent in the musical work—pace Adorno and others who would seek aes-
thetic worth in organic/internal necessity—but may rather be a construction
of a type of subjectivity that requires the “performance” of isolation for its
own aesthetic self-validation.20 And here we are back at the modernist para-
digm outlined at the beginning of this essay: a stable, discrete, and complete
musical “text” resonates well with a similarly defined ideal of subjectivity on
the listener’s part; while one could view the sonic experience of the type of
musical phenomenon currently regarded as a “stable text”—say, a
Beethoven string quartet—as a fluid multimedia negotiation of meanings
steeped in immediacy, following the characterization of “performance” in
222 andrew dell’antonio
section 3.2 above, models that have chosen structural unfolding as their pri-
mary focus have chosen not to do so. Thus the concept of wholeness,
uniqueness, and “fixed-ness” of a text may be not only the goal, but
arguably—and more fundamentally—the creation of the “structural listen-
ing” process.
In other words: the element of the “structural listening” dyad most sus-
ceptible to deconstruction may be not the adjective (pace Subotnik’s tour-de-
force), but the gerund: a modernist definition of listening (one that entails
focus, uniqueness, and the ability to parse small changes in unique
melodic/harmonic configurations over a long span of time) is required for
the concept of “structural listening” to even make sense in the first place.21
For, assuredly, the fragmented nature of musical/multimedia experience
described by Frith above is by no means unique to twentieth-century cul-
ture: accounts of eighteenth- and early nineteenth-century appraisal of
opera, for example, are remarkably similar. Operas themselves would be
heard repeatedly and piecemeal, as audience members came and went
based on their favorite performers’ stage appearances; popular songs from
operas would be printed as broadsheets, sometimes even with different
words; and composers would then publish variations on such popular tunes.
Interestingly, the work that is seen as launching Schumann’s pioneering
approach to musical criticism (Chopin’s op. 2, which causes Eusebius
famously to exclaim “hats off, gentlemen, a genius”) is a set of variations on
the duet “Là ci darem la mano,” from Mozart’s Don Giovanni; not a “great
work of absolute music” but a fetishized excerpt from a popular multimedia
show.22
If Subotnik’s deconstruction of the notion of “structural” listening was an
important stage in the reassessment of modernist ideals of musical experi-
ence, the above (brief) challenge to the notion of “[attentive] listening”
itself (which, as I argue, hinges on modernist notions) may open the way for
alternative perspectives on Subotnik’s “replete,” “stylistic” listening. Struc-
tural listening and its requirements (critical distance, stable subjectivity, well-
defined object of “music itself,” differentiated notion of “listening” as an
activity separable from generalized appraisal of multimedia) appear to be
best suited to a controllable, already known repertory; the fluidity of devel-
oping repertories requires immersion and constant negotiation about what
produces meaning. It makes sense that this should be a collective process,
because meaning is produced collectively; an individual responding to a
text/performance can only place that text/performance in a context of
meaning that s/he already has in place. Thus, structural listening can only
tell us what we already know about musical meaning; collective listening is
about negotiation, and its language must necessarily be tentative and
unformed.
collective listening 223
This is not to say that the kinds of discourse MTV portrays should be
accepted as the most representative versions of collective listening; clearly
MTV has a stake in the acceptance of its offerings as valid, and thus any crit-
ical engagement must be tempered and controlled, lest it reject portions of
MTV’s programming that are financially successful for the company. Thus,
MTV representations of the collective critical process can probably best be
understood as simulating critical processes and appealing to them, rather
than transparently reflecting them—all the more so since the high noise-to-
signal ratio and gradual development inherent to the collective listening pro-
cess does not fit a format that seeks to show, comment, and pass judgment
on three videos in roughly twenty minutes. Even when collective critical
strategies are less mediated by MTV than 12AV (as, for example, in the Yack
Live chat room conversations), the level of critical observation is relatively
low, and one could foresee a more subtle and discerning (dare one say artic-
ulate) approach; but the phenomenon of the chat room is still in its infancy,
and I would venture that new modes/standards of articulateness will gradu-
ally form around this medium.23 After all, what is articulate to the structural
listener (or the academic) may seem inarticulate to those who are partici-
pating in the collective listening process, and vice versa.
But finally, we should briefly speculate on the origin and nature of the col-
lective appraisal model: is it a creation of MTV, or is MTV responding to and
attempting to shape/develop a broader phenomenon?
5.1 Since the idea of a collective critical process seems to resonate with MTV’s public,
this raises the question whether MTV has fostered this tendency or responded to it (or
possibly both): Gramsci’s concept of “organic intellectual” activity will be brought to bear
on this issue.
We have explored how MTV has enlisted the internet and its increasing
opportunities for virtual reality (“you are really there”), whether real or
apparent, to construct a sense of collective participation; such participation
is seen as crucial to the image of “authenticity” that the network seeks to proj-
ect. As Goodwin succinctly puts it, “MTV, like pop music, needs to display its
creativity, its ability to change, its refusal to stop moving. It is not just that
MTV must be seen as hip and irreverent, but that it must seem always to be
hip and irreverent in new ways” (Goodwin 1992, 132). MTV has very good
economic reasons for wishing to construct “hipness,” and we shall return
shortly to the question of whether its “authenticity” can usefully support a
genuine collective appraisal process. First, however, a useful observation on
the nature of popular culture, and its connection to the concept of “authen-
ticity”: Antonio Gramsci, in theorizing on the nature of “folk” and “popular”
culture, focuses on the category of songs “written neither by nor for the
224 andrew dell’antonio
people, but adopted by the people because they conform to the people’s way
of thinking and feeling.” This, Gramsci concludes, is the only truly “popular”
type of music, because “what distinguishes popular song, in the context of a
nation and its culture, are not its artistic traits, nor its historical roots, but its
way of conceiving life and the world, in contrast with ‘official’ society; in this,
and in this alone, can we look for the ‘collectivity’ of popular song, and of
the people themselves (Gramsci 1975, 1:679–80). More important than the
“authenticity” of the sources of popular cultural artifacts in the historical past
of a specific group, according to Gramsci, are the ways in which those arti-
facts are perceived by a group to reflect their social/aesthetic position, in
contrast to the positions of others, particularly those perceived to be “esta-
blishment” figures. Note also Gramsci’s focus on the ideally “collective”
nature of popular song, which we might usefully compare with Grossberg’s
characterization of rock culture (see section 3.2 above). We might say: if
MTV succeeds in creating a space for the formation of groups that are able
collectively to negotiate cultural meanings, then MTV may be operating in
a role that Gramsci defined as that of the “organic intellectual”: one who
does not impose cultural ideals, but acts as a catalyst to organize the cultural
ideals of a group.
In describing the role and cultural products of organic intellectuals,
Gramsci further suggests that “[the new popular genre] must elaborate that
which already exists, whether polemically or otherwise; what matters is that
it must sink its roots in the humus of popular culture as it is, with its tastes,
tendencies, etc., with its intellectual and moral world, even if it is backwards
and conventional” (Gramsci 1975, 3:1822). In other words, the organic intel-
lectual’s role is to accept the cultural premises of her/his popular culture, to
facilitate its development, and not necessarily to question or resist its prem-
ises (as Gramsci puts it, “whether polemically or otherwise”); we shall return
to this crucial point below. Eco remarks that Gramsci’s model “does not rule
out the presence of an educated group of producers and of a mass of con-
sumers; but the relationship becomes dialectical, rather than paternalistic:
the former interpret the needs and circumstances of the latter” (Eco 1997,
51). This seems to be exactly the role that MTV is playing: it must be per-
ceived as the authentic mouthpiece and servant of its public, and in a very
real sense it is, within the premises of consumer capitalism; and we shall
return to this point as well.
It may be paradoxical to talk about Gramscian organic intellectuals oper-
ating within late capitalist culture, but what is happening with MTV seems
to work along similar lines. Frith observes that “the [record company’s]
product is laid out for us so as to invite assessment. The record company
works to define the evaluative grounds, thus ensuring that we make the right
judgment” (Frith 1996, 61). Likewise, MTV welcomes the notion of critical
process, especially when that process is meant to reinforce a notion of rock
collective listening 225
’n’ roll “authenticity,” on which the network relies for its own authenticity.
MTV has thus attempted to depict critical process as dependent on the
group/collective nature of “authentic” rock ’n’ roll experience.
A constructed version of the Gramscian concept (in Eco’s words) of a
“dialectical, rather than paternalistic” relationship between the “organic
intellectual” producer of culture and the mass consumers seems to be what
is at play here. MTV doesn’t want to give its consumers what it thinks is good
for them, it wants to appear to give them transparently what they want;
indeed, it makes a show of asking them what they want, and of showing the
consumers’ own “authentic” participation in the process. This is to a large
extent a construct, but it cannot be completely fictional, otherwise MTV
risks losing the perception of “authenticity” on which it founds its legiti-
macy.
Goodwin has remarked that, since music videos are geared to the success
of another product (i.e., hit songs), audiences “become the ‘product’ to be
‘delivered’—to advertisers” (Goodwin 1992, 44); he thus characterizes con-
sumers as pawns in the economic maneuvers between MTV and record com-
panies. Goodwin is especially keen to debunk what he perceives a pernicious
notion of “consumer sovereignty” integral to MTV’s propaganda ( 45–47);
but his characterization may be overcompensating. Although videos are cer-
tainly conceived by the record companies as advertisements for their com-
modities, MTV has control over how the videos are packaged for appraisal.
Because of its need to portray authenticity, MTV creates spaces which,
though carefully orchestrated, still provide room for individual listeners’
input and creativity, and in any case depict collective critical engagement as
an ideal for its audiences. As Frith observes, “[music] producers are seen to
‘interfere’ in the proper communication of musicians and audience. But this
is not necessarily the case: they may, in fact, make that communication pos-
sible” (Frith 1996, 62). Likewise, MTV opens a space for the collective criti-
cal process, even as it tries to shape it to its economic needs. In any case,
while MTV may not be the institution that Gramsci envisioned in his for-
mulation of the organic intellectual (it certainly does not participate in the
explicit class struggle that Gramsci advocated), I would suggest that Gram-
sci’s model provides a useful key into the nature of MTV’s relationship to the
ideal of collective appraisal. While collective appraisal processes are
independent of MTV, the network has fostered them in an “organic intel-
lectual” sense inasmuch as they serve both its audience’s needs and its own.
To be sure, MTV has to walk a fine line between opening up a collective
space and limiting the critical enterprise to something it can control or
defuse, depending on its economic needs; the network thus reveals the
potential of collective criticism, takes advantage of its outward manifesta-
tions, but must be careful not to grant its collective critics too much indepen-
dence or critical latitude.
226 andrew dell’antonio
5.2 MTV’s portrayals of collective critical response to music video are undoubtedly
shaped by the network’s commercial considerations, but they also create spaces for
active participation on the part of MTV’s public.
Goodwin has mined the social implications of MTV’s cultural efforts as “an
instance in the shift of power away from public service institutions” and
toward “free market institutions.” MTV, Goodwin argues, attempts to
“restructure the subject-as-citizen (the public service model) along the lines
of the subject-as-consumer (the free market model)”; its cultural message
“may constitute an ideology to the extent that it implies marketplace solu-
tions to all social problems” (Goodwin 1992, 169). “Politically speaking,”
Goodwin concludes, “music television must be seen as an ideological phe-
nomenon through its capacity to extend the social relations of the market-
place and erode public service notions of culture” (171). Goodwin is here
arguing against an idealization of MTV as embodiment of postmodern cul-
ture, locus of free and unbounded signification; and he is absolutely on tar-
get in this regard.
But Goodwin’s (quasi-)Marxist analysis is not entirely dismissive of MTV
as a valid cultural phenomenon; ultimately, its ideology does not seem
inherently more pernicious than modernist ideals of artistic autonomy. In a
truly schizophrenic fashion, “MTV is . . . simultaneously involved in the
incorporation and the promotion of dissent” (Goodwin 1992, 155). All cul-
tural formation and critical process, after all, is based on contexts and frame-
works of premises; the fact that MTV does its cultural work on the model of
“subject-as-consumer” does not negate the possibilities for effective and sig-
nificant cultural participation on the part of the MTV viewer. For while Jame-
son reminds us that
talist social life. At that point, to say that the group exists and that it gener-
ates its own specific cultural life and expression, are one and the same”
( Jameson 1979, 140).
Within this quasi-Gramscian formulation, Jameson (from the modernist
perspective we have seen above) would probably assume that an “organic
group” must be self-consciously stable, aware of its own existence (and dif-
ference from other groups) and its clearly drawn boundaries. But if we com-
bine Jameson’s insight about emerging collective cultural expression with
the fluidity and constructedness of late-capitalist groups theorized by
Deleuze/Guattari and embodied in the collectives portrayed on MTV, then
the image of culturally empowering “organic group formation” is implicit in
the collective listening scenarios suggested above. MTV is certainly trying to
harness the cultural power of the organic groups it fosters, and in many ways
it succeeds in doing so; but its ability to harness is dependent on the “authen-
ticity” (or at least perceived authenticity) of such organic groups in reality.
While the groups created by collective appraisal efforts tend to lack a self-
conscious cultural or political agenda, and indeed frequently lack even a
stable group consciousness, the collective appraising process nevertheless
provides a space for collective cultural negotiations that continuously color
and reshape the appraiser’s notions of pleasure and power.24
Collective, “organic” expression, Jameson continues, “is the third term
missing from my initial picture of the fate of the aesthetic and the cultural
under capitalism; yet no useful purpose is served by speculation on the forms
such a third and authentic type of cultural language might take in situations
which do not yet exist” ( Jameson 1979, 140). Some twenty years after Jame-
son’s formulation, perhaps such situations now do exist. To be sure, the
notion of “authenticity” of cultural language is now more fluid and renego-
tiable than a more thoroughly modernist notion of authenticity, one requir-
ing stable subject and object positions, would assume. And perhaps, as Jame-
son himself suggests, this authenticity cannot define itself as entirely separate
from capitalist hegemony. Indeed, Goodwin has rejected a simple Marxist
view that “mass culture is the extreme embodiment of the subjection of cul-
ture to the economy; its most important characteristic is that it provides
profit for the producers,” pointing out that “few cultural texts are today pro-
duced as pure commodities” (Goodwin 1992, 45). It may well be that a pre-
sumption of commodity-value underlies all late twentieth-century cultural
products, in a way analogous to the status of representation as the unques-
tioned basis of visual art in the Western tradition from the Middle Ages until
the early twentieth century. But commodity-value does not exclude other val-
ues to the appraiser; and in portraying videos/songs as desirable commodities,
MTV must engage with notions of artistic/aesthetic value: videos/songs will be
desirable if they are aesthetically satisfying to the potential appraiser/con-
sumer.25 MTV must therefore encourage its audience to operate critically, and
228 andrew dell’antonio
5.3 Collective critical processes may therefore well be a viable example of “organic intel-
lectual” practices within late-capitalist culture.
notes
I would like to thank Patrick McCreless, James Buhler, and the students in my Fall
1999 graduate seminar at the University of Texas for their crucial feedback on pre-
liminary versions of this essay.
1. For a more extensive discussion of Subotnik’s characterization of “structural lis-
tening,” see the introduction to this volume.
2. I will use the term “appraisal” to describe the process of experiencing multi-
media, since the separate terms “listening” and “viewing” are inadequate to the task.
Theodore Gracyk recently postulated an important distinction between stages of
“appraisal” and “evaluation” in the listening process, with particular reference to
230 andrew dell’antonio
selection and voting. For example, one week the jurors voted for the “worst video
ever,” with the winner to be taken off MTV rotation; on another instance, viewers’
mothers were recruited as jurors.
15. E. Ann Kaplan, in her groundbreaking study of MTV, connects the notion of
“musical background” with the collective appraisal experience in her account of stud-
ies of teenage habits: “The experience [of watching MTV] is then often a group one,
people responding loudly to their likes and dislikes as part of the fun. Often, however,
the program provides the background for casual partying rather than being watched
concentratedly by teenagers.” She goes on to remark that “MTV is ‘consumed’ in a
variety of settings, ranging from the lounge or cafeteria of the college student center
. . . to the dance club scene . . . to the large department store” (Kaplan 1987, 20). The
clear distinction that she draws between concentrated watching and casual partying
is, I believe, an artificial dichotomy: rather, the collective appraisal process is likely
to involve a continuum of attention span, from occasional focused moments to com-
plete disregard, on the part of each member of the collective. This type of “unfo-
cused” appraisal is by no means limited to contemporary pop music contexts; see
note 21 and section 4.2 below.
16. Three recently updated examples include Holoman’s Masterworks, Yudkin’s
Understanding Music, and Kerman/Tomlinson’s Listen; “listening guides” in these text-
books are predicated first and foremost on structure, and opening chapters stress the
importance of focused, undistracted listening.
17. Before we deplore such lack of focus, it might be worthwhile to point out that
the idea of combining music and text (common in the West since at least Aristo-
phanes) implies parallel and simultaneous—and hence “unfocused” (cross-eyed?)—
appraisal strategies, one for the sounds, and one for the words. This may indeed be
why structural listening is so frequently invoked as most congenial to untexted music
. . . and the fact that this type of music makes up a minority of even nineteenth-cen-
tury “art” repertories (not to mention earlier or later repertories) has not prevented
the idealization of the structural listening paradigm.
18. This is evident especially in Yack Live and B&B, since the discussion in 12AV
is more regimented, but it also surfaces in the latter.
19. For additional discussion of Deleuze and Guattari’s “de-Oedipalized/anti-
Oedipal” model and its application to the collective critical process in a specific MTV
show, see Dell’Antonio 1999, passim.
20. An excellent unpacking of the lasting influence of the modernist/late
Romantic notion of self-isolation as a requirement for a “high art” experience can be
found in Small 1998, esp. 39 ff.
21. The very fact that this technique needs to be carefully taught (through
“music appreciation” courses) to individuals who otherwise very capably appraise
multimedia events that have significant musical components should give us pause
about its suitability for understanding of a broad range of musical phenomena.
22. For more on Schumann’s criticism as a parallel to collective listening/critical
strategies, see Dell’Antonio 1999, especially 75 ff.
23. Historians of science have speculated that periods of empirical “scarcity” (or
“sloppiness”) and/or apparent incoherence are characteristic of conceptual or sci-
entific paradigm shifts; see, for example, Feyerabend 1978, 10–15 and passim. With
232 andrew dell’antonio
specific reference to musical issues, see Carl Dahlhaus’s discussion of the concept of
“New Music” in Dahlhaus 1987b, 1–13.
24. Robert Walser phrased a similar point well in his analysis of the socio-political
import of Prince as “gender/culture-bender”: “If [Prince] seems to lack the social rel-
evance of self-consciously ‘political’ artists, it is because he is a rhetorician who deals
with aspects of social intercourse that seem—perhaps must seem—most private and
natural. To engage, disrupt, and rearticulate those affective engagements can be as
consequential as any more overt struggle over signification or ideology” (Walser 1994,
87). A collective appraisal of a Prince video could well result in renegotiation of what
are acceptable/effective erotic images (whether visual or sonic) for the members of
the group, thereby perhaps significantly changing the appraisers’ attitudes toward
behavior formerly considered “deviant,” with concomitant social consequences.
25. I believe it is irrelevant to speculate whether videos can be “aesthetically sat-
isfying” within the modernist standards of artistic autonomy discussed above. With
Frith (1996, 19), I am defining aesthetics broadly, tying it to the notion of pleas-
ure/gratification/satisfaction that videos and pop songs unquestionably create for
their public.
eight
It starts, appropriately enough for Debussy, with a dream. The way I remem-
ber it now, some years after dreaming it: I was interviewing to be hired by a
congregation of a church as their minister. This interview was really a sort of
audition, in that I was to give a sample sermon. It took place in a paneled
room with mullioned windows, a very solemn and official place, containing
a large table surrounded by chairs—like a seminar room. Various church el-
ders were in the chairs; I was at the head of the table. I felt discomfort
because I am not a religious person; was I a charlatan to attempt this? But
the unsureness dissolved in a sudden perception of what I would say. I began,
in this dream, to describe a dream. I knew with total certainty that the act of
describing this dream would become, if I did it right, profoundly sacred, and
that my listeners would have no trouble recognizing it as such. I had only to
make my description completely apt, entire, so that nothing was not
described, and nothing said that did not participate in the transport of this
image and experience. The words had only—only!—to perfectly match
their object, and I would have achieved the sacred.
The image in the dream-within-a-dream was of a white horse, grazing on bright green
grass, sloping slightly toward the point of view, which was some distance above the plane
of the ground. Some yards beyond the white horse, the ground sloped away steeply, so that
a crest or ridge line appeared behind him; beyond that, indeterminate distance. The sky
was blue but shot with cloudiness or mistiness. In front of the grazing horse was a small
pond, surrounded by the vivid green, reflecting the whitened blueness of the sky. The horse
was a somewhat heavy older animal. It grazed quietly.
I have tried more than once, as above, to recapitulate the act of description
that I performed in that dream. I cannot do so, will never remember the exact
words; but I recall vividly the triumphant sense that my description was capable
233
234 elisabeth le guin
of becoming perfect, the growing, exultant sense that, if I but chose my words
with enough attention, I could equal creation through description. It is in this
memory, and in the faith in description that underlies it, that this essay had its
genesis.
In his letters, reviews, and essays Debussy exhibits a strong and entertaining
character, parts of which—the sarcasm, the love of ellipsis and allusion—are
familiar through association with his music, and other parts of which—the
vehemence, the occasional sloppiness—come as quite a surprise. On few top-
ics is that vehemence more consistently on display than in his opinions on
reception, and most especially on any receptive practice that might partake
of the analytic or academic. The strain is a familiar one:
Du goût (S.I.M., 15/2/13)
La Portia du Marchand de Venise parle d’une musique que tout être port en soi
. . . «Malheur, dit-elle, à qui ne l’entend pas . . . » Paroles admirables, sur
lesquelles devraient méditer ceux qui, avant d’écouter ce qui chante en leurs
âmes, se préoccupent de savoir la formule qui les servira le mieux. Ou, très
ingénieux, juxtaposent des mesures, tristes comme des petits cubes. Musique
qui sent la table et la pantoufle . . . Méfions-nous de l’écriture. Travail de taupe,
où nous finissons par réduire la beauté vivante des sons à une opération où,
péniblement, deux et deux font quatre. . . . (Debussy 1971, 223)
On taste
Portia in The Merchant of Venice speaks of a music that everyone carries
within: “The man that hath no music in himself . . . let no such man be
trusted.” Admirable words, and a necessary meditation for those who, before
listening to that which sings within their souls, become preoccupied with the
formula that will serve them the best, or who, very ingeniously, juxtapose mea-
sures, sad like little cubes. Such music smells of the table and of house slippers.
Let us distrust writing. Moles’ work, where we end up by reducing the living
beauty of sounds to a sum where, laboriously, two and two make four.
There are only a very few places in which Debussy’s critical statements keep
better pace with the complexity of his musical thinking, by suggesting some-
thing more challenging than a retreat from description and analysis. One is the
famous remark, “Search for the discipline within freedom!” This was directed
at writers of, not about, music, but it is most intriguing when musicologically
appropriated. Another, longer statement is directed toward the listener:
Du respect dans l’art (S.I.M., 12/12)
En verité, nous regardons souvent très mal—les paysages qui ne sont pas
célèbres en savent quelque chose et jusqu’où peut aller la fantaisie des appré-
ciations—nous entendons peut-être plus mal encore?
one bar in eight 235
Ainsi restons persuadés qu’il y a des personnes très honorables qui n’en-
tendent qu’une mesure sur huit . . . — cette arithmétique n’est pas infallible,
elle doit même varier avec chaque individu, — il est donc naturel qu’à la fin
d’un morceau il leur manque des mesures et que leur compte ne soit pas juste!
Ce manque est difficile à avouer, à moins d’employer cette ruse habituelle qui
consiste à dire, l’air préoccupé : «J’ai besoin d’entendre cela plusieurs fois . . . »
Rien n’est plus faux! Quand on entend bien la musique — écartons l’en-
traînement, les études appropriées — on entend tout de suite, ce qu’il faut
entendre. Le reste n’est qu’une affaire de milieu, ou d’influence extérieure.
(Debussy 1971, 216)
Of respect in art
In truth, we often see very poorly—landscapes that are not celebrated know
something about how and where our fantasy of appreciation goes. Do we per-
haps listen even more poorly?
Thus we remain persuaded that there are very honorable people who hear
but one bar in eight. This arithmetic is not infallible, it must vary for every indi-
vidual, but it is only natural that at the end of the piece they will be missing
some measures, and that their summing-up will not be correct! This failure is
difficult to admit, except by means of that habitual ruse that consists of saying,
with a preoccupied air, “I need to hear that several times.” Nothing is more
false! When one really listens to music—let us set aside training or appropri-
ate study—one hears at once what should be heard. The rest is nothing but a
matter of environment and exterior influence.
This statement, “When one really listens to music . . . one hears at once
what should be heard,” is exasperatingly breezy. It does rather seem to be
sloppy rhetoric, for he asserts the opposite elsewhere; writing a decade ear-
lier about Dukas’s difficult piano sonata, Debussy had acknowledged, with
apparent approval, that such remote and rigorous music demanded being
played “over and over again at the piano,” while in a 1914 interview con-
ducted by Calvocoressi, he is paraphrased as saying, “To believe that one
can judge a work of art at first hearing is the strangest and most dangerous
of delusions.”1 Nonetheless I want to explore here the ways in which, taken
seriously, this statement points to a kind of trope in musical reception, in
which aural experience is approached through analogy to the visual mode.
Debussy’s music encourages this tendency particularly seductively, and in
the process asks contradictory things of us that are still in need of sorting
out.
The piece on which I chose to begin this exploration was the song “Soupir,”
first of the Trois Poèmes de Stéphane Mallarmé of 1913—music as aphoristic and
gnomic as any he produced, and, as such, a pretty unwise choice; but, as
Debussy may well have intended, I was needled by his challenge, and wished
to put both him and myself to the test. At the same time, there is some bet-
236 elisabeth le guin
hedging in such a choice, for this piece is also a poem, and a poem’s exis-
tence might reasonably be expected to tether the auditory experience to
some kind of semantic one. However, disentangling the knot with which the
music and semantics are tied is always fraught, and here exceptionally so,
Mallarmé and Debussy being each so dedicated to the confounding of deno-
tational relationships.
the poem
A tracing-through and demonstration of the various possibilities and real-
izations for this music’s relationship to this poem—tone painting, mood set-
ting, symbolism, subversion—could easily consume the rest of this essay, and
in so doing represent a turning aside from “hearing at once,” into an engage-
ment with writing. What I propose to do here is to introduce the poem and
point the way to a listening familiarity with it as a spoken event—one
intended to approximate the degree of familiarity that Debussy’s 1913 audi-
ence would, by and large, have had. Thus the relationship to the poem that
I wish to establish for this experiment is deliberately inexplicit, one in which
the poem forms an implicit, half-articulate frame of sound-meaning for sub-
sequent listening.
Soupir
Mon âme vers ton front où rêve, ô calme soeur,
Un automne jonché de taches de rousseur,
Et vers le ciel errant de ton oeil angélique
Monte, comme dans un jardin mélancolique,
Fidèle, un blanc jet d’eau soupire vers l’Azur!
Vers l’Azur attendri d’un Octobre pâle et pur
Qui mire aux grands bassins sa langueur infinie
Et laisse, sur l’eau morte où la fauve agonie
Des feuilles erre au vent et creuse un froid sillon,
Se traîner le soleil jaune d’un long rayon.
Sigh
My soul toward your brow, where dreams, oh calm sister,
An autumn scattered with freckles,
And toward the errant heaven of your angelic eye,
Mounts, as in a melancholy garden,
Faithful, a white fountain sighs toward the azure!
Toward the tender azure of an October pale and pure
That mirrors in the great basins its infinite langour
And lets, on the dead water where the fawn agony
Of leaves strays with the wind and ploughs a cold furrow,
The yellow sun be trailed by a long ray.
one bar in eight 237
The act that will be of most importance here will be to speak the poem
aloud, preferably many times, savoring it; this act assumes a special impor-
tance for the English-speaking reader with less than excellent French (a
group in which I belong). Some of Mallarmé’s resonances—the rhymes, the
other similarities of timbre from line to line (“ton front . . . automne jonché
. . . Monte,” “langueur . . . Laisse”)—can be heard and felt in the mouth this
way. Others—homonyms and assonances with absent words that do not
appear on the page, but whose possibility haloes the heard text with other,
unrealized, imaginary meanings—are surely lost. Speaking the poem is a
good way to get some sense of Mallarmé’s syntactical extensions, the
stretched and torqued constructions that put the poem into tension with the
traditional alexandrine, or twelve-syllable line (another imaginary reso-
nance, lost on most English-speakers, since syllabic meters do not really func-
tion in English)—and into a very exaggerated tension with any sort of nor-
mal sentence structure. Note, for instance, how the main verb (“monte”) of
the first statement does not appear until the beginning of the fourth line,
when it has already been loaded down with two complex and delicate
descriptive clauses; and, mirroring the mirroring evoked in the text, how the
object of the second statement (“un long rayon”) is separated by another
active and evocative descriptive ellipsis from its verb (“laisse”). One may
become aware of a slow rising motion (the speaker’s gaze, the fountains,
vague expectation), in the first half of the poem, followed by an equally slow
subsidence into cool nostalgia (the autumn, abandonment, a setting sun)
the second. In my translation I have attempted to reproduce both Mal-
larmé’s peculiar syntax, and to use as many cognates as possible, in order to
retrieve, at some remove, these tensions and resonances (while, inevitably,
losing the rhymes). However, the Anglophone’s relation to the poem’s lan-
guage as soundscape is in this context not wholly disadvantageous: for such
a listener, French will tend to lose its transparency and become a sonic
object, no longer fully semantic, impenetrable but for the beautiful shadings
of vowel sound, so challenging and sensuous to the foreign palate: further
along the continuum from poetry to music.
the song
From the very first moments of “Soupir”: a low chord, arpeggiated on the
piano leisurely in time and widely in interval: it sounds cool, “neutral,” archi-
tectural. And then, oh triumph of many years of hard-won ear-training! a
framework kicks in: I think, “That chord starts somewhere around low E,”
and internally I “see” a bass stave, on which the E and the ensuing pitches
“write” themselves.4 I think, “Ah, it sounds neutral because I can ‘see’ that it
is made of stacked-up fifths.” Eschewing the physical score has not prevented
me from creating a virtual one and mentally annotating it.
I try another time, with the admonition in place: avoid thinking about
pitch, since it is the aspect of listening most freighted by the academic con-
ventions Debussy deplores; concentrate on other things—time, timbre, reg-
ister, articulation.
I can still “allow” the coolness, the spaciousness, I think. They are colored
by a brassiness in the piano’s low register on this recording that is peculiarly
attractive. A little later, the singer (Hugues Cuenod)5 makes some plangent
vowel sounds (I am especially fond of the three different sounds taken by the
vowel “i” in infinie), which are a source of pleasure to me, subliminally evok-
ing the peculiar sensations that arise in my American palate and throat when
I try to pronounce French. (Here, it seems, I invoke a virtual, participatory
body.) Vocal timbres seem in every way apposite to piano timbre: warm,
immediate, utterly personal, intrinsically different from it; the idea of the
singer producing the “same” pitch as the piano (or of participating in the
“same” chord with it) seems superficial, artificial. The interest and the char-
acter of timbres seems to inhere almost entirely in their differences, which
rise to my attention at moments of transition or contrast between them, and
one bar in eight 239
again and again, from its object; but with the added vexation of my knowing
I am supposed to be far from a novice at listening to music. I am acutely
aware of how well I fit the bill of Debussy’s “honorable people who hear but
one bar in eight,” that awareness (and the chagrin it causes me) becoming,
in fact, one of the chief points of continuity between listenings; I worry and
worry at certain vague but compelling matters, like timbral recurrence and
metamorphosis, like vocal-register-in-relation-to-surrounding-harmony, over
successive listenings, and the worry becomes part of my “score,” in the
unhappy sense of a score I am trying to settle.
The desire for something to look at is acute: I want a means to winnow
these wayward perceptions, confirm the “good” ones, dismiss the embar-
rassing ones, and salve my musicological ego in the process. I want a sense
of how to shape and interpret heard experience that acknowledges that
experience’s immediacies; and I look to historical context for guidance.
One must see . . . the movement of the spectator around the statue or the archi-
tectural monument as a plastic or view-absorbing execution, which unfolds in
order the various aspects which are held within the physical frame, and which
are the aesthetic reason for that frame as it was planned.
Are there profound and basic differences between this “plastic execution”
and a musical performance? In a musical, theatrical or choreographic work,
the order of successive presentation is set, constant, precisely measured and
determined. In painting, sculpture, or architecture, this order is not deter-
mined: the spectator is [at least relatively] free. (Souriau 1958, 123–24)
as one remains open to the possibility that what ends up getting interpreted
may not be what one set out to prove! For one thing, I think there may be
some argument to be made for the operation of synopsis as we encounter it
on the level of biological survival. Humans can take in a great deal of com-
plex information very quickly indeed by a single glance, or even a peripheral
“take,” especially when the object of the glance is another human; we see,
more or less instantly, a great deal more about others than we are generally
called upon to make conscious. This is also true of certain auditory infor-
mation, especially timbre (and the combinations of timbre with pitch), ambi-
ence, and the micro-temporal operations of articulation, and again, espe-
cially when what is being heard is another human. Tone of voice, breathing,
delivery all give us far more instantaneous information than we generally
think about: one has only to reflect on how automatically and how accurately
we gauge sex, age, body size, state of mind, state of health, ethnic/cultural
background, social class (these last two verging into vocabulary), the type of
space (indoor, outdoor, large, crowded . . .) from which we are being
addressed: all this and more, in the first five words a stranger speaks to us
through the small and distorting microphone of the telephone. Such tim-
bral/ambient/articulational perception seems to be inherently symbolic or
referential; all of these momentary perceptions point “outward,” toward con-
crete signifieds—people, places, emotions, old memories. In a musical con-
text, they will consequently tend to exceed the boundaries of what a piece of
music is usually considered to be.
In music the positing of a synoptic model can represent a way of flash-
freezing the fluid nature of temporalized perception, thereby making expe-
rience into an object, and thereby also rendering it available to description.
Thus not only a fallacy but a conundrum, for what has happened to imme-
diacy in this process? Debussy himself was certainly aware of this difficulty:
privilege of capturing all the poetry of the night and day, of the earth and sky,
of reconstituting its atmosphere and giving rhythm to its immense palpitation.
Here Debussy evades consideration of the arts of the shadow-play and of cin-
ematography, nascent in Paris during his prime, and said to be a source of fas-
cination to him.6 The cinema, a facsimile of continuity created through the
extremely rapid sequencing of innumerable synoptic moments, was certainly
a new way for the visual artist to give “rhythm to [the] immense palpitation” of
experience. In the passage above, Debussy offers music as a kind of cinematic
alternative to the “fragmentary” synoptic process; but the listener gets no
advice about how to go about capturing the poetry so encoded, and remains
in danger of appreciating (perhaps) one immense palpitation in eight.
If, as I have suggested, by synoptically “appreciating” or “capturing” the
motion of music through time is meant a process of rendering it susceptible
to description, then it is a contemporary of Debussy who cast the most seri-
ous doubt on the possibility of this venture. Through his books and his pub-
lic lectures at the Collège de France, Henri Bergson had by 1913 established
a popular reputation unusual for a professional philosopher in any day or
age. This was built in part upon his considerations of the nature of time as a
perceptual rather than a conceptual field, and in particular his idea of durée,
duration. Bergsonian duration is a rejection of the Newtonian idea of time
as analogous to space, that is, a “repetitious, homogeneous, paradoxically
static” (Gunter 1983, xxi) neutral field, in which temporal experiences take
place: an idea that is essentially a figure–ground separation, and as such,
markedly visualistic. This separation was collapsed by Bergson, in an effort—
one which he was to refine and labor over his entire life—to make the
embodied experience of time the arbiter of the concepts and language we
use in assessing it. Bergson did not live to write exhaustively or systematically
about music, but in one of his best-known passages he used musical recep-
tion as a central metaphor for true durational awareness:
Pure duration is the form which the succession of our conscious states assumes
when our ego lets itself live, when it refrains from separating its present state
from its former states. For this purpose it need not be entirely absorbed in the
passing sensation or idea: for then, on the contrary, it would no longer endure.
Nor need it forget its former states: it is enough that, in recalling these states,
it does not set them alongside its actual state as one point alongside another,
but forms both the past and the present states into an organic whole, as hap-
pens when we recall the notes of a tune, melting, so to speak, into one another.
Might it not be said that, even if these notes succeed one another, yet we per-
ceive them in one another, and that their totality may be compared to a living
being whose parts, although distinct, permeate one another just because they
are so closely connected? The proof is that, if we interrupt the rhythm by
dwelling longer than is right on one note of the tune, it is not its exaggerated
one bar in eight 243
length, as length, which will warn us of our mistake, but the qualitative change
thereby caused in the whole of the musical phrase.7
[W]ith these successive states . . . you will never reconstitute movement. Call
them qualities, forms, positions, or intentions, as the case may be, multiply the
number of them as you will, let the interval between two consecutive states be
infinitely small: before the intervening movement you will always experience
the disappointment of the child who tries by clapping his hands together to
crush the smoke (Bergson 1983, 308).
Bergson’s work labors uphill against the human reliance on the inevitable
stabilities and immobilities of words. Not only mistrusting analysis and
description, he ends up effectively disallowing language as any kind of
acceptable bearer of meaning—a bad position for a philosopher to be in.8
Bergson’s understanding of language is interesting, however, in its invo-
cation of kinesthesis; his concept of a “motor-diagram,” evolved by human
beings as they learn to use language, makes very clear some of the neural and
muscular pathways by which the heard may become the understood.9 Of
course similar pathways evolve as humans learn to use music; I have men-
tioned the involuntary responses of my palate and throat to the vocal sounds
on my recordings. If I were a pianist, doubtless many more elements in the
“motor diagram” would emerge. But I am not a pianist, and they do not,
which is a demonstration of the extremely contingent usefulness of kines-
244 elisabeth le guin
Les monuments, la mer, la face humaine, dans leur plénitude, natifs, conser-
vent une vertu autrement attrayante que ne les voilera une description, évo-
cation dites, allusion je sais, suggestion . . .10
Monuments, the sea, the human face, in their native plenitude, retain a virtue
that charms differently than that revealed in a description; call it evocation, or
allusion, suggestion.
And then there is the little issue of silence. This perfected metaphorical
Music simply must not trouble us with any messy, non-denotational sounds:
[C]e n’est pas sonorités élémentaires par les cuivres, les cordes, les bois, indé-
niablement mais de l’intellectuelle parole à son apogée que doit avec pléni-
tude et évidence, résulter, en tant que l’ensemble des rapports existant dans
tout, la Musique (Mallarmé 1985, 278).
[I]t is undeniably not the elementary sonorities of brass, strings, woodwinds,
but of the intellectual word at its apogee that must result, with plenitude and
evidence, as the combination of connections existing in everything, in Music.
out of date in 1913; with Debussy we are already generations into the artis-
tic and critical cultivation of the Romantically indescribable. Why, then,
make such heavy weather of an anachronistic critical process? If one were
not to so insist on the availability of receptive experience to description, this
“crisis” would evaporate. But of course, insist I do, furiously, doggedly, and
of necessity. While description may not be everyone’s epistemological moor-
ing, as the opening of this essay shows it to be for me, I do firmly hold it to
be mandatory on the part of anyone who is serious about making sense of the
experience of art: with musicology’s modest pretensions to science come cer-
tain unavoidable obligations to Enlightenment practices and values, of
which description is the linchpin.
Perhaps not surprisingly, some of the most helpful thinking and writing
on this crisis comes from the French Enlightenment’s own endless discur-
sive anxiety over it. Synopsis as a kind of epitome of visuality, visuality as a
kind of epitome of unmediated (and therefore genuine or inarguable)
experience, and appearance as that quality of the object which summons
the whole complex in the viewer, are a central concern of eighteenth-cen-
tury French aesthetics and criticism. This concern spills over from art into
music criticism, driving the numerous and overlapping musical Querelles.
Critics and pamphleteers worry and worry at the nature of music’s imme-
diacy, at determining where that operates and how it works; and typically,
these exegeses of music as a signifying art take visuality as their model and
starting point. Rousseau in the Essay on the Origin of Languages (Rousseau
n.d. [1754]) calls the instantaneous visual language of gesture the “most
vigorous,” and locates it as the primary language. He even uses this to
explain the power of narrative, as a cumulation of apparitions or tableaux,
which “strike a redoubled blow” to the senses, producing a more emotion-
ally and morally intense effect than that possible through the single glance.
(One has to wonder what Rousseau would have made of the “redoubled
blows” of the cinema.)
The frequent insistence in the Encyclopédie that music must paint, not just
things, but sentiments, can be read as a kind of evolution toward an under-
standing of music as expressive rather than “merely” representational; by
these lights, the sophisticated composer, the painter of sentiments, paints
not only toward what we see, but what we think and feel in the seeing of it.
However, this seems to be simply a relocation of the synoptic moment, rather
than a supersession of it, from the plane of figural to that of emotional recog-
nition. In his considerations of the act of seeing and of recognition, Diderot
asserts that
[Q]u’on n’est affecté, dans les premiers instants de la vision, que d’une mul-
titude de sensations confuses qui ne se débrouillent qu’avec le temps et par la
réflexion habituelle sur ce qui se passe en nous . . .11
246 elisabeth le guin
Autre chose est l’état de notre âme; autre chose, le compte que nous en ren-
dons, soit à nous-même, soit aux autres; autre chose, la sensation totale et
instantanée de cet état; autre chose, l’attention successive et détaillée que nous
sommes forcés d’y donner pour l’analyser, la manifester, et nous faire enten-
dre. Notre âme est un tableau mouvant, d’après lequel nous peignons sans
cesse: nous employons bien du temps à le rendre avec fidelité: mais il existe en
entier, et tout é la fois: l’esprit ne va pas à pas comptés comme l’expression. Le
pinceau n’exécute qu’à la longue ce que l’œil du peintre embrasse tout d’un
coup.12
The state of our soul is one thing; another, the account we make of it, whether
to ourselves or to others; another, the total and instantaneous sensation of that
state; yet another, the successive and detailed attention we are forced to pay in
analyzing it, manifesting it, and making ourselves understood. Our soul is a
moving tableau, after which we paint without ceasing; we spend much time in
rendering it with fidelity: but it exists, entire, all at once: the spirit does not
move step by step, as does its expression. The paintbrush can only execute at
length that which the eye of the painter embraces in an instant.
The art historian Michael Fried has explored at length the preoccupation
of eighteenth-century painters with images of this very process. Jean-Baptiste
Greuze is merely the best-known of the many who depicted scholars and
maidens and patriarchs (and, of course, artists) absorbed in their various
objects of contemplation; these images are themselves only appearances,
icons, even fetishes of the reflective process, of “spending much time.”
Diderot’s Salons, the essays in which he treats of the biannual exhibitions at
the Louvre (and in which he lionized Greuze during the 1760s) are among
the great monuments of this act of “successive and detailed attention” that
grounds the descriptive art. They are also a site of its crisis, for no matter how
lucid, sensitive, and perceptive the prose, transparency is never achieved. In
fact, at a fairly early point, its very vividness serves to move description away
one bar in eight 247
from its object and make it an independent act, at best parallel to the thing
described, sometimes freely diverging from it in flights of visualistic fancy
intended to incite readers into their own independent, sympathetic envi-
sioning of the absent canvas. In Norman Bryson’s words, “[T]he image itself
is no longer made to emanate from the information supplied by the writing,
but on the contrary writing is only the score by which the reader’s percep-
tual apparatus must realise [the image]” (Bryson 1981, 189).
This kind of description unpacks the visualizing, concretizing, freeze-
frame synoptic process, and “musicifies” reception through description,
determining sequence and duration (and even content!) of what is “seen.”
Such readerly reconstitution of the art object is, as Bryson suggests, really a
kind of performance, the description really a kind of score. It functions just
as well in musicological description as in art-historical, and we take it for
granted as a basic performative mode for reading literature in our discipline.
(Souriau’s account of listening, quoted above, fits the reception of such
descriptions much more aptly than it does the first-hand reception of the
music described.) How many of the readers of this essay, after all, listened to
the Debussy song as they read my accounts of it? Is transparency really ever
the object here?
His own realization that the pursuit of descriptional transparency had led
him full-tilt into fiction and persuasion caused Diderot, in his later writings,
to retreat from description in moral dismay.13 Among those in the ensuing
century who were most fruitfully to take up the challenge was another con-
temporary of Bergson’s and of Debussy’s, Edmund Husserl. Husserl’s prin-
cipal strategy for the rendering of perception into the conceptual currency
of language is what he calls the epochê, or “bracketing,” of perceptions. This
maneuver is exceptionally easy to misunderstand and misuse; in particular,
some followers of Husserl have made it serve as an expedient exclusionary
gambit whereby inconvenient facts, such as social and political contexts, may
be deliberately omitted from a critical stance. However, in its ideal (and
rather idealistic) form, the epochê allows, even mandates, any and all contin-
gent phenomena in the assessment of experience; they must only be
approached with infinite attention and caution as to their nature and source
as perceptions, and as to their inflection through, or possible origins in,
beliefs, convictions, associations, etc., etc. Any assumptions we make about
these perceptions automatically become subject to the same scrutiny. This is
not a disallowal, but a radical defamiliarization, of experience. An experi-
ence so regarded, “plays . . . the role of ‘transcendental clue’ to the typical
infinite multiplicities of possible cogitationes . . . that, in a possible synthesis,
bear [it] within them . . . ” (Husserl 1960, 50). In this view, the phenome-
non—in our case, the musical work as heard—is a clue to the range of its pos-
sible appearances within the hearer, which can be further teased forth by
processes such as memory, association, and reflection.
248 elisabeth le guin
Baudelaire spends the first part of this essay praising Guys’s ability to cap-
ture and render the fleeting, volatile play of visual sensation, characterizing
it in one place as a return to a childlike way of seeing, and in another as a
kind of artistic inebriation with immediacy: Guys is, in other words, a master
synopsist. Not until late in the essay does Baudelaire reveal that Guys painted
always after the fact, always by memory. He goes further, to declare that this
is the ideal mode for producing all art, and all accounts of art: for in his view,
memory is a purifying and controlling influence, the dividing line between
an indiscriminate inventory of impressions (he uses the terms “myope” and
“de bureaucrate”) and something true, vivid, valuable.
Ainsi, M.G., traduisant fidèlement ses propres impressions, marque avec une
énergie instinctive les points culminants ou lumineux d’un objet (ils peuvent
être culminants ou lumineux au point de vue dramatique,) ou ses principales
caractéristiques, quelquefois même avec une exagération utile pour la
mémoire humaine; et l’imagination du spectateur, subissant à son tour cette
mnémonique si despotique, voit avec netteté l’impression produite par les
250 elisabeth le guin
choses sur l’esprit de M.G. Le spectateur est ici le traducteur d’une traduction
toujours claire et enivrante. (Baudelaire 1949, 122)
And so partiality, in both senses, reigns. Did I ever really think it could be
otherwise? Only in my dreams. Yet I do wonder about Debussy, whose arch
wryness about the inefficient listening of “honorable people” seems to mask
a real, Diderotic regret, an insuperably melancholy longing for the unity of
interpretation with experience; perhaps he too is a victim of “the will to see
everything and forget nothing.”
notes
1. This interview appeared in English in The Etude, vol. 32, no. 6 (1914), 407;
reprinted in Debussy 1977.
2. In his recent work on Debussy’s Faune, David Code argues very persuasively
that “the piece must be read as well as heard,” as there are too many perceptual and
one bar in eight 251
A few rungs down. One level of education, itself a very high one, has been reached
when man gets beyond superstitious and religious concepts and fears and, for
example, no longer believes in the heavenly angels or original sin, and has stopped
talking about the soul’s salvation. Once he is at this level of liberation, he must still
make a last intense effort to overcome metaphysics. Then, however, a retrograde move-
ment is necessary; he must understand both the historical and the psychological jus-
tification in metaphysical ideas. He must recognize how mankind’s greatest advance-
ment came from them and how, if one did not take this retrograde step, one would rob
oneself of mankind’s finest achievements.
friedrich nietzsche, Human All Too Human
at ultimate truth—exclaimed, ‘So the universe rests on that turtle!’ ‘Oh, no,’
replied his mentor. ‘From there it’s turtles all the way down’ ” (1).
But, contra McClary, the wisdom of the tale may not be that the world
rests on many, many turtles (a.k.a. “cultural practices”) instead of only one,
but that the sage cannot quite say this. The sage’s pause marks the limit (or
what Gayatri Spivak might call the “perhaps-structure”) of all knowledge, and
the statement about turtles, framed as a negation of the youth’s hasty con-
clusion, marks the eternal return of the same that haunts all efforts to deter-
mine knowledge of the world once and for all. The point is that the world
only becomes “turtles all the way down” when the desire for knowledge
becomes absolute; when becoming becomes a world-picture. So, not only does
McClary’s text elevate the moment that the sage utters his most empty for-
malism, but it overlooks the beautiful tiger (and the elephant) upon whose
backs we are hanging in dreams. After all, how beneficial to life, how beau-
tiful, is the giant turtle upon whom our perspective is narrowed to endless
turtles? And in what darkened waters does it swim?
In musical terms, what I am saying is that the observation that all musical
processes (including “purely musical” ones) are so many cultural conven-
tions is a preamble to knowledge passing as a conclusion. This observation
does not register the irreducible metaphysical step required to institute any
form of political commitment; still less does it register the role that those
musical processes that do not take themselves to be reducible to cultural
practice might play in these commitments. According to Friedrich Nietz-
sche, after overcoming metaphysics, the possibility of advancing depends on
a “retrograde movement” (1986, 27). That is, to inhibit the maelstrom of
radical skepticism from becoming an absolute formula, an imaginative leap
of faith is required. I want to advance a series of faithful leaps (or retrograde
musicological movements) that idealize music as a purely aesthetic phe-
nomenon, but that simultaneously rein back its imaginative flight, like a
trout on a line, to the project of productive political intervention and social
upliftment in the social world.
To sum up, in this paper I want, first, to elaborate various means of resist-
ing the ideological closure and programmatic constraint of recent trends in
musicology—especially those that emphasize social and political issues over
close reading and other formal techniques associated with musical analysis;
and second, to elaborate new kinds of closure and constraint produced by
music analysis that may be politically beneficial in various quarters. Let me
turn now to a more sustained critique of the new musicology. To avoid reduc-
ing this remarkably rich field of discourse to a checklist of essential features,
I will launch my critique of it in the context of a particularly impressive,
indeed exemplary, case of new musicological writing, namely the work of
Rose Rosengard Subotnik. In fact, Subotnik’s awareness of the dialectical
relation between work and world confounds the simplistic distinctions
256 martin scherzinger
between these two realms to which I have alluded. Also, she recognizes the
necessity of a moment of faith in all scholarly discourse and thereby reduces
the essentialized methodological grip of the metaphorics of “cultural prac-
tice.” It is hoped, therefore, that my critique of Subotnik’s quite complex
position has implications beyond the context of her project.
turalism. Following that, I will offer perspectives on the way these fields of
discourse intersect with politics and strategies for the progressive use of for-
mal analysis.
Lewin surmises that the temptation to place musical things in unique spatial
locations is “prompted by the unique vertical coordinate for the . . . note-
head-point on the Euclidean/Cartesian score-plane” (360). Indeed, suc-
cumbing to this temptation by rendering conclusive analytic verdicts strikes
him as “fantastically wrong” (359).
260 martin scherzinger
quate to capture these distinctions because it assumes that a single event can
emerge only within a single temporal frame. When the events of measure 15
confirm the sequential reading, a new connection is established with the Af
in the bass in measure 9 (the former possibly an expanded recapitulation of
m. 9) and the span from measures 9 to 15 sounds like an elaboration of dom-
inant harmony in C major instead of C minor. This permits us to revisit the
blues-perception of G minor once again, albeit from a different phenome-
nological space and time. In other words, it is not that we rehabilitate this
perception, because, as Lewin says, it is “not necessarily ‘really’ dead,” even
if some perceptions took it that way.
For Lewin, the point is to hear the musical work as a complex structure of
interrelationships, weaving different threads of perceptual meaning in
different temporalities. Elsewhere he draws on Edmund Husserl’s distinction
between understanding the work as “Gegebenheit and Dasein” instead of as
“Sinn and Anwesenheit,” as “given and there (regardless of the temporal situat-
edness of the listener), not just sensible and present” (1986, 375). Although
they are described in a style quite remote from Derrida, Lewin’s irreducibly
temporalized perceptions approximate the workings of Derrida’s decon-
structive phenomenological inquiries, especially his discussion of the sign’s
temporization (or the becoming-time-of space)—a notion that he also borrows
from Husserl.1 At the very least, Lewin’s project resembles that of Derrida in
the terms that Subotnik interprets the latter. It is wholly compatible with Sub-
otnik’s general description of an ideal way of listening. That is, while it might
eschew the radical polyvalence of a genuine deconstruction (if only because
of the conceptual limits it places on its “poetic” apparatus or the certainty
with which it regards the horizons of the work), Lewin’s analysis resists “fix-
ing” musical structures (in the narrow manner that Subotnik associates with
“structural listening”) and precisely concerns itself with the “diverse,
unstable, and open-ended . . . multitude of contexts in which music defines
itself” that characterize “stylistic listening” (1996, 173; 175). I could also
make the point that Lewin, like Derrida, asserts a kind of linguistic compo-
nent for his model of listening, which irreducibly enmeshes these percep-
tions in socio-cultural forces that exceed the work’s temporal enclosures.
However, it should suffice here to note that, far from constraining the terms
of listening in a pedantically technical vocabulary, Lewin puts a high pre-
mium on the task of raising perceptual possibilities, or even inventing cate-
gories of musical listening.
The general point I am trying to make is that Derrida, a crucial philo-
sophical underpinning for the new critical musicology, shares various prem-
ises with Lewin, whose work is sometimes identified as formalist. In a com-
mentary to Music and Text: Critical Inquiries, Hayden White, for example,
writes that Lewin’s reading of a phrase in Mozart’s Figaro is “a rigorously for-
the return of the aesthetic 263
the (identical) pattern of attack points were the sole determinant of musical
“rhythm,” there would be no telling these examples apart.
On the other hand, it is plausible to think that other principles—not pro-
vided by the notions of “toleration” or of “rhythm” in themselves—can cap-
ture the necessary discriminations in these examples. This would solve the
problem of what should and should not be tolerated with an appeal to some
kind of limiting claim, perhaps a normative principle; and of what counts as
a “ ‘transcription of the [Sacre] passage . . . with respect to ‘preserving the
rhythm,’ ” (Boretz 1971, 150) with an appeal to various limiting functional
events in the non-rhythmic auditory dimensions of the piece. Boretz demon-
strates how the rhythmic quality of any musical passage is inevitably
beholden to aspects of timbre, dynamics, registral locutions and dispersions,
polyphony, modes of articulation, concepts of pitch relation, tonal function,
and extramusical predisposition. So, if these categories are to avoid the situ-
ation (issued forth by a self-grounded definition) of becoming their oppo-
site, we must appeal to independent, or supplemental, contents that func-
tionally guide our understanding of them. Both writers provisionally reverse
the priority of the pure concepts and these seemingly infelicitous contents:
the prior identification of supplemental normative criteria would disam-
biguate what should and should not be tolerated; and the prior identification
of functionally significant non-durational events would specify which dura-
tions are relevant to a rhythm.
But this structural dependence on events outside of the categories’ felic-
itous denotation confronts each writer with a second vanishing point: Laclau
asserts that the terrain dividing the tolerable from the intolerable has been
qualitatively transformed into one between “the morally acceptable and the
morally unacceptable” (1996, 51). Thus grounding toleration “in a norm or
content different from itself dissolves it as a meaningful category” (51). Like-
wise Boretz claims that grounding rhythm in non-rhythmic dimensions
“deprives rhythm of its independent status as a musical stratum,” and the
concept ends up denying “the very intuition on which it is principally
founded and by which it is principally motivated” (1971, 153).
Now, for both writers, this seeming deadlock also points to a solution,
albeit not of the Hegelian sort. Laclau argues that, from the point of view of
the content, toleration is meaningful only insofar as one accepts that which
one finds morally disagreeable. Why should this matter? Perhaps because
one has a political interest in a society that can cope with a certain degree of
internal differentiation. From the point of view of the concept itself, tolera-
tion cannot be entirely without limit because of the necessary relation tol-
erance has to intolerance. That is, intolerance conditions the possibility and
the impossibility of tolerance—it is an inevitable accomplice. Again the
grounds for deciding what is and is not tolerant is a matter of political com-
mitment: a “radical democrat” might want to cope with more differences
the return of the aesthetic 267
than a supporter of the “moral majority” would (Laclau 1996, 51). Indeed,
the struggle concerning the contents of toleration in any given society is
made possible by the very lack of a necessary content in the term.
Boretz argues slightly differently: from the point of view of the content,
rhythm is meaningful only insofar as it “subsum[es] every dimensional and
inter-dimensional substructure” of the music under investigation (1971,
154). Why should this matter? Perhaps because one has a musical interest in
a rhythmic theory that can cope with a certain degree of internal differenti-
ation between different inter-dimensional settings. From the point of view
of the concept itself, rhythm cannot be a mere matter of “timelength pat-
tern[s] exhibited by an (auditory) succession” because of the necessary rela-
tion this has to any auditory event whatever (1971, 150). Again, the grounds
for deciding what is and is not pertinently rhythmic is a matter of musical
commitment: one theorist might want to say that rhythm is the least system-
atic of parameters, irreducibly contingent on particularities like pitch,
polyphony, concepts of harmony, and extramusical predispositions, while
another may want to say that not so many of these factors count in a discus-
sion of rhythm itself. Perhaps the former orientation also prefers to focus on
particular instances of rhythmic activity while the latter prefers the context
of a general theory. Indeed, the debate concerning the contents of rhythm
in any music-theoretical community is made possible by the very lack of a
necessary content in the term.
The point of this comparison is to show that Boretz and Laclau share the
same basic argumentative strategy. Both read deconstructively: a category of
thought is placed under context-free investigation precisely in order to
identify the conditioning grounds of its emergence. Both achieve this by way
of a kind of Freudian “talking cure” that insists on articulating, or bringing
to linguistic expression, the meaning of the concept. This illuminates the
inadequate handle the expression seems to have on what the term takes itself
to be. Where the line dividing the poles of the term and its opposite is drawn,
is (speaking in terms of the duality itself) logically undecidable. (The oppo-
sition turns out to be more basic than either of its poles in itself; indeed the
duality is the undecidable ground of possibility for both terms.) Finally, both
accounts want to resist a general abstract theory of the respective concepts
and to open the horizon of possibility for their coming to mean.
This is where the aesthetic imagination of music analysis can be produc-
tively set against the largely demystifying work of the new critically-oriented
musicology. Indeed, the mere presence of poststructuralist premises in musi-
cological discourse does not assure that these are productively implemented.
Sometimes musicologists who explicitly reckon with such premises even
close down their imaginative horizons. One might expect, for example, that
a psychoanalytic inquiry into the subject of listening—whether this focuses
on the listening subject or on the subjection of/through listening—would
268 martin scherzinger
melancholy. Like the house at which he is staring, the narrator (still) finds
himself standing “auf dem selben Platz” (“in the same place”) in Heinrich
Heine’s poem. Harmonic activity is kept to a minimum and the melodic line
circles tirelessly around Fs1. Finally in measure 25, the melody begins on a
note other than Fs1. This is the moment in which another person enters the
scene: the moment in the text plausibly suggestive of the drama of the gaze.
This is the stanza in which the melodic line is unhinged from its repeti-
tiousness and becomes energized in an upward sweep into measure 42.
Thus, far from “signifying the gaze,” Fs seems to signal a kind of brooding
stasis that precedes the imagined presence of another. And this presence is felt
precisely by departing from Fs.
Given the social emphasis on the structuring activity of the gaze, it may be
inappropriate to explain this romantic experience of a double in these
terms. While the registral sweep from measure 25 to measure 41 ultimately
settles on the pitches Fs and G again, as if to lay bare the structure of the nar-
rator’s fixation, the process seems more narcissistic than social. After all, the
gaze of the narrator’s double is diverted (staring at the sky), while the Lacan-
ian gaze is directed at the subject from a multitude of perspectives. More
importantly, can the Lacanian gaze appropriately be signified by a pitch class?
If the gaze is a kind of presentiment that lies behind conscious experience,
the effect of which is manifested in that experience without itself being read-
ily accessible to consciousness, can it be experienced through this repeated
note? Or is Fs a representation of the gaze? If so, why is the invisible and inac-
cessible gaze represented by that which is ubiquitous and compulsively rep-
etitious, by the sound that is closest and clearest to our ears?
The problem with Schwarz’s “representational” stance here and else-
where in the book is that it does not bear the weight of the post-Freudian psy-
choanalytic apparatus at all levels of argument. Thus, while psychoanalysis
in recent literary theory has served to disengage from interpretations of lit-
erary works as “expressions,” “representations,” or “reflections” of reality
(understanding them instead as forms of production that effect a way of per-
ceiving the world), Schwarz recapitulates the form of the former interpreta-
tions even if the “reality” his Schubert songs “represent” has been replaced
by the real, the drive, or the gaze. It is as if these psychoanalytic modalities
had already been established (thus functioning as the argument’s signified)
and the music was a representation (or signifier) of them. This pattern of
thought, a site of desire all of its own, pervades the book.
In the discussion of “Der Doppelgänger,” for example, Schwarz asserts
that “E minor is the music’s objet a, the signifier of the music’s irreducible
alterity” (1997, 70). In the discussion of Primus’s cover version of Peter
Gabriel’s song “Intruder,” a “listening gaze,” whereby “the music [is] listen-
ing to us,” is evoked “through the pounding bass guitar and percussion that
accompanies the text throughout, sounding just on our side of the listening
270 martin scherzinger
not always enough. Second, does the problem of immanence also haunt
accounts that go beyond (what Subotnik calls) the “internal configuration”
of the musical text (1991, 244)? I think the cases of Subotnik and Schwarz
suggest that it can do so. Moreover, when we speak of hearing tonal music
in terms of cognitive archetypes, for example, or when we speak about the
conventional dimensions of music-making as already established and fixed,
we risk immanentism. Subotnik, for example, renders “the common musi-
cal logic or well-established set[s] of convention” as “irrefutable” fact
instead of as negotiable determinant (1991, 245). What I am suggesting is
that we can build neat formalist circuits with hybridized language as well,
maybe even more believable ones.
The second orientation for listening, the “opening-possibility” sort, is one
that widens the horizon of musical meaning by marking various moments of
musical undecidability. This approach would give rise to new perspectives
and new ways of organizing musical sounds and their possible intersections
with social meanings. At the same time, it would resist meanings whose unity
is determined by the totalizing tendency (however grammatically frag-
mented and diverse its terminology may seem) that structures the multi-
plicity of the text.
With this distinction between analytic orientations in mind, my argument
is now going to take an unexpected turn. While I prefer the latter imagina-
tive and open-ended orientation, I want to argue that, even though both are
highly relevant to aspects of the political, neither of these ways of listening is
inherently more politically or socially beneficial than the other. In fact, I think that
assessing the political use to which ways of listening or methods of musico-
logical study can be put entails, first, an explicit formulation of the political
problem that is disturbing one (at least in the background of one’s work),
and, second, a program that puts the former in service of the latter. To quote
Derrida on the Politics of Friendship: “If the political is to exist, one must know
who everyone is, who is a friend and who is an enemy, and this knowing is
not in the mode of theoretical knowledge but in one of practical identification”
(1997, 116). Now, even while this choosing of friends and enemies turns out
to be a mad practice—a decision in the experience of the undecidable (rad-
ically unpredictable, radically contingent)—we are obliged to identify the
contexts that factually limit structural undecidability if we want to institute
political commitments.7
Now, I also think that both ways of listening I have just outlined (“imma-
nentist” and “imaginative”) can be, and often are, put in political service. Let
me demonstrate this with examples. First, let me mention two examples of
how a rigidly structural analysis of the immanentist and pedantically “limit-
ing” sort can yield ideas that can be put to politically progressive use.
Example 1: By taking seriously Schoenberg’s call for due attention to the
abstract musical “idea,” as well as Adorno’s praise for Schoenberg’s “nega-
274 martin scherzinger
tion of all facades” (in Subotnik, 1996, 150; 162), a music analysis of the
music of Webern (explicitly linked to Schoenberg throughout Subotnik’s
text) that counterintuitively ignores aspects of “color,” “medium,” and
“affect” (aspects of “stylistic listening”), and, in the domain of the brazenly
“structural” alone, may issue forth a radical critique of gender hierarchy.
The link between Webern’s musical material and the then prevalent dis-
course of “inversion” suggests that the former was elaborating, however
implicitly, an androgynous musical ideal. In Webern’s terms, the new
music’s preoccupation with formal symmetries was an effort to transcend
the gendered dualism of major and minor that culminated in an ungen-
dered atonal musical space.8 In short, reducing the music to its autotelic
inner structural symmetries can contribute to imagining the institution of
gender parity in the social world.
Example 2: By comparing the harmonic language, structurally speaking,
of Shona mbira dza vadzimu music of Zimbabwe with the nyanga panpipe
music of the Nyungwe of Mozambique or the kalimba and panpipe music
of the VhaVhenda of South Africa, a musical analysis may show cultural res-
onances between these “tribal” groupings that traverse the political border
of their respective modern nation-states. Thus, excavating various structural
affinities in music can assist in rewriting the past in terms of a shared,
instead of an irreducibly divided, history of southern Africa. In light of the
legacy of colonial investments in the invention of tribalism in southern
Africa, this music-analytic dogmatism can therefore challenge another,
more virulent, dogmatism.9 In short, the strategic mobilization of starkly
closed musical structures can contribute to the freeing up of post-colonial
social space.
Second, let me mention two examples of how a structural analysis—now
of the imaginative and “opening” sort—might equally yield ideas that can be
put to politically progressive use.
Example 1: By marking for consciousness that which is contingent and
particular (or inherently multiple and undecidable) in music of the canon,
close music analysis may disturb the unitary conception of the Western
canon figured as a cumulative-evolutionary narrative. For instance, if an
analysis of Beethoven’s Violin Concerto is startled by the radical peculiarity
of the Dss that interrupt the respectable tonal behavior (in D major) of the
first movement in measures 10 and 12, instead of with the way the move-
ment’s Urlinie realizes a latent world-historical trajectory, then Beethoven’s
organic connection to Perotin, Machaut, Josquin, Monteverdi, and Bach
cannot be taken with too much confidence.10 More generally, by resisting the
reductive, predictive, and generalizing tendency of immanentist music analy-
sis, imaginative close listening can encourage a social consciousness not
wholly absorbed by (what Georg Lukács calls) the “reification” of capitalist
the return of the aesthetic 275
rationality.11 In other words, the imagination can supplement the gap upon
which social conventions are founded, and thus contribute to the devolution
of power in the political world. This is why Murray Krieger insists that the aes-
thetic “can have its revenge upon ideology by revealing a power to compli-
cate that is also a power to undermine” (in Clark 2000, 1).
Example 2: By analyzing, for example, the perceptually beriddling
(indeed undecidable) harmonic and rhythmic patterning of Zimbabwean
mbira music, we may be, first, opening institutional space for African music’s
contribution to international musicological definitions and debates, and,
second, staking a claim on the canon (globally conceived) for music in the
marginalized world. First, the close analytic examination of African music’s
temporalities can revise our understanding of perceptions of meter and
rhythm in general. In this way, imaginative analysis may help to Africanize
those (Western) theories that go as universal. Second, the close analytic
examination of African harmony can demonstrate aesthetic complexities
that may encourage canonizing the music outside of the foreclosed cate-
gories of “world music.”12 This in turn can contribute to the structural uplift-
ing of African music in global modernity.13 Perhaps structural listening can
therefore help some of us hear value where we heard none before. (Or does
the supposition that structural listening, for example, is irreducibly not
“applicable to music that falls outside the canon” [Subotnik 1996, 158]
answer to another need—one that will not grant African music an unmarked
entry into global modernity?)14
I am trying to say that there are political reasons for not turning musical
formalism into a kind of Correct Consciousness taboo in the domain of cul-
tural politics on the left. If it is true, as Subotnik maintains, that structural
listening yields an “impression of objectivity,” “a unifying principle [that]
establish[es] the internal ‘necessity’ of a structure as tantamount to a guar-
antee of musical value” (1996, 158–9, italics mine) then why, in the wake of
this knowledge, do we choose to turn away from structural listening instead
of using its evident power to assign value to strategically reconstellate culture
in terms that we prefer? Nietzsche’s insight that we continue to hold on to
certain truths and values even after they are shown to be based on error or
on values that we do not agree with, makes me worry about giving up the
compelling territory of structural listening just because some musicologists
believe it is based on values they do not uphold. Rephrased in more recent
parlance, just because the emotional investments and the hopes that people
have are the result of what Laclau calls a “complex discursive-hegemonic
construction” (1996, 63), and not the expression of an a prioristic essence, is
no argument against their validity. If this scenario is right, then it will not do
for us to either celebrate structural listening as upholding some criterion of
truth or to recoil from its ideology in alarm. While it is true that formal
276 martin scherzinger
notes
1. On temporization, see Derrida 1986, 1–28.
2. On “transformation,” see Lewin 1987 and 1993.
3. On musical “sense,” see Dubiel 1992.
4. On the “unsayable,” see Budick and Iser 1989.
5. Boretz 1971, 149–55; Derrida 1997; Laclau 1996, 47–67.
6. It is important to point out that hearing this moment as a swerve away from
the opportunity to modulate depends on noticing mm. 15–18 as yielding to that pos-
sibility. This, to my mind, is what distinguishes the chromatic inflection in m. 20
from those in mm. 10 and 12. Only after hearing the move to the contrasting key
succeed in the previous phrase does the one in mm. 19–22 feel like an evasion. On
the other hand, the tenuousness of the B-flat major music (embedded in the key of
B-flat minor) makes it sound like the return of the octaves in m. 25 is all too due. I
would like to thank Joseph Dubiel for prompting me to refine my analysis of “Ihr
Bild.”
7. Like those supplemental criteria that unexpectedly encroach upon the con-
cept-metaphors of “friendship,” “toleration,” and “rhythm,” the political efficacy of a
chosen modality of listening to music is not logically entailed in that modality.
8. On the gendered history of major and minor and its undoing in the new music,
see Webern 1975, 28; 37; 43; For an extended analysis of these relations, see
Scherzinger 1997.
9. On the invention of tribalism in this part of the world, see Ranger 1985.
10. On the peculiarities of the Dss in Beethoven’s Violin Concerto and its con-
nection to the practice of music analysis, see Dubiel 1996, 26–50.
11. On “reification,” see Lukács 1971. On predictive and generalizing conceits in
music theory, see Maus 1993.
12. On the strategic canonization of African music, see Scherzinger 2001.
13. By focusing on harmony instead of rhythm, this kind of analytic work might
also demythologize the shorthand view that African music is predominantly “rhyth-
mic.” On the invention of African rhythm, see Agawu 1995.
14. Of course, Subotnik’s critique is concerned with legitimating non-canonic
the return of the aesthetic 277
music and not with marginalizing it further (as I suggest here). My point is that legit-
imation cannot be achieved through the critique of an institutionally accepted
method, but only—and then only perhaps—through a strategic use of the sanctioned
method. Therefore, the critique of a method (on grounds of its exclusionary “inap-
plicability” elsewhere) paradoxically produces a lack of interest in its progressive
potential.
after word
I can’t cry over the Ecstasy of St. Francis, or any other painting. I have joined the
ranks of the tearless. Like other art historians, I am fascinated by the pictures I study,
but I don’t let them upset my mental balance. It’s all right for a picture to be chal-
lenging, but I don’t think of pictures as dangerous: when I look at an image it doesn’t
occur to me that it might ruin my composure, or alter the way I think, or change my
mind about myself. There is no risk, no harm in looking. . . .
Each idea from a book is like a little tranquilizer, making the picture easier to see by
taking the rough edges off of experience. Once, it seemed there was nothing between
me and the Ecstasy of St. Francis but a foot or two of empty air. Now it’s like peer-
ing between the shelves in a library: somewhere back there, beyond the wall of books,
is the painting I am still trying to see. . . .
[T]he picture no longer . . . matters to my life, only to my work.
james elkins, Pictures and Tears
Not to be able to distinguish the noble from the deplorable is morally obtuse. In the
wake of Sept. 11 we may want, finally, to get beyond sentimental complacency about
art. Art is not blameless. Art can inflict harm. The Taliban know that. It’s about time
we learned.
richard taruskin, “Music’s Dangers and the Case for Control”
The biggest block to sensuous enjoyment may simply be the strange painfulness that
many of us feel when our minds are not occupied.
jon spayde, “Born Sensuous”
279
280 rose rosengard subotnik
The cultural prognostication biz is kaput. . . . [I]f it’s a fool’s errand to guess how a
war will change . . . the culture, that’s only half of the equation. The other, overlooked
half—though just as impossible to guess—is how the culture will eventually change
the war. In America, our take on our previous wars keeps changing. . . . The way any
war looks to its veterans may be unrecognizable to cultural consumers a generation
hence.
frank rich, “Close Reading”
Diagnosing the present is a lot like predicting the future, only riskier. Both
require the deciphering of clues laid down in the past. Both require the pas-
sage of time for an assessment of their accuracy. But tellers of the future
(including astrologers, weather forecasters, and economists) are frequently
absolved of their miscalculations; everyone understands that although such
people look toward the future, they cannot actually see it. Diagnosticians, by
contrast, look toward the past, asking not only where we are but also how we
got there. Working with their backs to those of us who come after, they dis-
tract us from realizing that they, too, could not see the future. We forget how
different the present looked in its own time, to its own viewers; and we fault
those viewers for failing to imagine a future perspective (our perspective)
from which their miscalculations would seem so evident (and so avoidable).
Limitations are harder to forgive in a diagnosis than in a prognosis.
My notion of structural listening first took shape in late 1985, in the draft-
ing of an essay I had been commissioned to write under the title of “The
Challenge of Contemporary Music.”1 My reaction to this title, which I sus-
pect surprised the editor who chose it, was to try to diagnose some of the rea-
sons that the twentieth-century music most admired by academic scholars
and composers during the 1970s and 1980s had so little resonance for most
of the people—by which I mean Americans—I knew. When I decided a year
later to expand my discussion of structural listening into an entire article,2
the object of my intended diagnosis grew with it. On one level, I continued
probing the social isolation of twentieth-century art music by tracing refer-
ences to structural values in writings by Schoenberg and Stravinsky,3 the pair
whose perceived polarity had shaped so much twentieth-century composi-
tion, especially in the academy. On another level, I wanted to understand
how values of structural listening could play a dominant role in traditions as
divergent as Adorno’s critical oeuvre, with its roots in Continentalist philos-
ophy and German musical thought, and analytic music theory, with its affini-
ties for what I had elsewhere called “Anglo-American empiricism.”4
Both of those traditions had had an enormous impact on my own musi-
cal career, the former on my scholarship, the latter on my education more
after word 281
generally. And the more I grappled with the notion of structural listening,
the more acutely I sensed troubles in the musical world I inhabited. Why, in
spite of my affection and admiration for my professors, had so much of my
graduate training struck me as irrelevant?5 Why did I so often resist reading
scholarly articles on music? Why had my discovery of a gripping musical
thinker, Adorno, endangered my survival as a musicologist?6 Slowest to
emerge, and hardest to confront, was this question: what in almost forty years
of serious musical study had overlaid my childhood love of classical music
with such burdensome feelings of anxiety and obligation?7
By itself, the notion of structural listening was not a sufficient answer to any
of these questions. But using dialectic to tease out something I called “style”
(which included sound and rhetoric8) from something I called structure
helped me to identify certain things I wanted to incorporate into the study of
music. On one side, I wanted thinking about music to intersect not just occa-
sionally but constantly with the most exciting issues available to the mind:
defining the good in life (moral philosophy and social theory) and in art (crit-
icism and aesthetic theory). On the other side, I wanted to find ways of engag-
ing with music that permitted me to say something valuable about a piece with-
out invariably needing first to achieve mastery over every element of its formal
detail. Most of all, I think, I was desperate for a norm of writing about music
that centered on good and exciting uses of the English language, uses that ban-
ished technical signs to the extent possible and referred those remaining not,
at least in the first instance, to scores or complex diagrams but to ideas in the
writing itself. For me, at least, it was important to encounter such writing on a
regular basis in order to sustain the intensity not only of my thinking about
music but also of my feelings for the music I was thinking about.
Today it seems obvious that what lay at the heart of my essay on structural
listening was a desire to diagnose the defects of a reigning scholarly para-
digm so as to help make way for its replacement. But although I used the
term “paradigm” in that essay (e.g. p. 173), and although Thomas Kuhn, who
coined the usage, had published his Structure of Scientific Revolutions twenty-
six years before my essay appeared, the term and its associated concept had
nothing like the currency in the 1980s that they have today. Nor is that the
only difference worth noting between the language and assumptions of the
time in which I wrote that essay and the time in which I write now. Many of
the differences that in retrospect seem most salient are essentially changes
in style, changes no doubt connected to some broader changes, which I have
analyzed elsewhere, in our conception of humanistic scholarship, from an
enterprise grounded on foundational principles to an enterprise guided by
an aesthetic sensibility.9 Other differences are due, more simply, to inter-
vening advances in research.
Thus on the one hand, the image I just used, of employing dialectic to
“tease” one concept out of another, is today a commonplace; several of the
282 rose rosengard subotnik
way, hasten the arrival of a day when we can no longer imagine such a notion
of listening. I have no interest in such a day. My original essay made clear the
value I attached to structural modes of listening even as I pleaded for the
enlargement of musical study through the development of other modes.14 I
have not changed my mind on this matter.
Nor would I want, through disavowing a discrete mode of listening, to
encourage, if only in a small way, the disintegration of scholarly confidence
into unfocused subtlety. Beyond structural listening itself, I have ideological
reasons for resisting a complete (post)modernization of outlook: as strongly
as I support the nurturing of an aesthetic sensibility in scholarship, I am not
comfortable with the prospect of losing all the strengths and priorities of the
older, foundationalist paradigms. To put it in personal terms, if once I felt
hopelessly (i.e., unemployably) ahead of American musicology in my pen-
chant for dialectical thinking, now I am content to bring up the rear by
defining oppositions in a way that allows for the integrity of each compo-
nent. When Martin Scherzinger proposes a dichotomy between “an embrace
of the tolerant coexistence of different readings” and “a structural undecid-
ability . . . [resulting from] a trace of contingency lodged within the logic of
any structure (at its origin),”15 he is making a distinction between what he
sees as my ideological position and a more current ideology to which he sub-
scribes. Whatever the political possibilities of these positions, the former
one, the one he attributes to me, is clearly compatible with traditional (pre-
postmodern) notions of liberalism. And although I would argue that my
essay in fact makes allowance for Scherzinger’s own position, that is, for a
structural rather than a merely historical or contingent gap in the processes
of communication,16 I would acknowledge that traditional liberalism
remains my position, even today.
The relationship between one’s time and one’s intellectual convictions is
always worth reconsidering. I cannot protect those elements of my structural
listening essay that seem outdated to a new generation from being read, at
least in part, as evidence of my failure to imagine myself out of the present
in 1986. Still, I hope that these elements will also be considered, at least in
part, at face value. For in addition to arising in ignorance of a future that is
now here, these elements also constitute an ideological position that I
worked out when I was fully adult. What has changed in fifteen years is the
genealogy I would ascribe to that position. Today, the ideological values
underlying my essay on structural listening seem traceable less to the dialec-
tical philosophy of Adorno, the primary subject of that essay, than to the lib-
eralism of Leonard Meyer, in whose honor the essay was written.
nity, in this afterword, to venture one or two predictions about the shape that
American musical scholarship will take in the coming decade. The oppor-
tunity is doubly enviable because Andrew Dell’Antonio, in bringing together
nine such diverse and original examples of new musical thinking, has pro-
vided an unusually rich basis for thinking about the future.
If it is fair to say that the present collection offers a window into the for-
mation of a new paradigm for musical scholarship, which I shall henceforth
call the “Next Paradigm,” one prediction seems safe: that new paradigm will
not concern itself, at least in the way I envisioned, with what I once called
“stylistic listening.” To the extent that the New Musicology, in its early stages,
wanted an alternative to Structural Listening, it probably shared my vision
of that alternative as a different sort of listening. Exponents of the Next Par-
adigm, as represented by the contributors to this volume, share the impa-
tience of the New Musicology with old models of Structural Listening;17 but
with few exceptions, and those are largely illusory, the alternative they pro-
pose is not simply some different sort of listening. In this connection it may
be useful to remark that the New Musicology has already become a target of
frequent criticism in this collection. But it is even more important to note
that representatives of music theory and analysis—formally oriented prac-
tices—may well be, in their various ways, the most outspoken critics of Struc-
tural Listening in this volume. Not one defends the concept.
This is not to deny a tone of defensiveness perceptible at times in essays
concerned with music theory. This tone puzzled me for a while, until I real-
ized that the negative elements in my critique of Structural Listening might
have struck a nerve among scholars dedicated to formal analysis. Such schol-
ars might even have seen my essay as part of a New Musicological onslaught
on the very survival of their field. My slowness to draw these conclusions
should not be taken as evidence of disingenuousness (or, I hope, stupidity)
on my part. Nothing could have been farther from my thoughts in the mid-
1980s than the idea that music theory might one day be an endangered
species of scholarship. Though my essay on Structural Listening dealt with
issues important to music theory, I gave little thought to theorists while I was
writing it; the scholars I wanted to reach were musicologists. For the most
part, I took musicology and music theory for essentially unconnected enter-
prises at that time, as they had been at Columbia University when I studied
there in the 1960s.18 Dell’Antonio’s inclusion of theorists in this collection as
well as the willingness of those theorists to participate in it are both signs that
the Next Paradigm will involve convergences between musicology and music
theory on many issues. The common aspects of the alternatives offered in
this volume to Structural Listening are a case in point.
When Fred Maus makes his elegant diagnosis of traditional music theory
as itself a kind of defense mechanism, he stresses not only the potentially
overwhelming power of music but also the lengths to which analysis typically
286 rose rosengard subotnik
goes to contain that power; in effect he presents the middle and late twenti-
eth-century paradigm of theory as an attempt at total control.19 In pointing
beyond that paradigm toward a new alternative based on “a tense, complex
relation of shared agency and responsibility,” that is, toward a “positive
model of shared creation,”20 Maus invokes two themes that underlie the reac-
tion to Structural Listening of just about every writer in this collection. The
first, which I have already identified in connection with criticism of my own
work, is the need for musical scholars to collapse philosophical distinctions
between seemingly opposed concepts. The other is the need for musical
scholars to renounce mastery as a goal, or, for that matter, even as a virtue.
Both can be related to sensibilities as well as anxieties that were barely evi-
dent at the time I wrote my Structural Listening essay.
Of the first theme, good evidence is provided by the orientation of so
many essays in this collection away from the scrutiny of objects, and toward
reflection on the processes of analysis and interpretation themselves. Maus
himself, for instance, is primarily concerned not with the ways in which the-
orists analyze music but with the imagery in which they couch their analyses.
Paul Attinello’s argument is designed to transform itself into an extended
meditation on the uses of self-reflexiveness in scholarship along with the
problems generated by such usage.21 Mitchell Morris is at pains to think out
the kinds of conditions under which we could interpret music ethically. Each
of these enterprises can be described as developing a self-reflexive scholarly
tendency that I believe first emerged clearly with the New Musicology: the
shifting of focus away from the signified to the signifier.22 At its best, this shift
can be associated with the refinement of a certain aesthetic sort of honesty,
whereby the scholar’s constant self-scrutiny raises his or her sensitivity to any
false move.
Indeed, even granting that the title of this collection encourages certain
priorities and concerns, most of the essays here suggest a growing preoccu-
pation among musicologists and music theorists alike with the act of listen-
ing itself; and concomitantly, an inclination not to disregard musical struc-
tures so much as to reconfigure all analysis of music within a larger analysis
of listening. This movement toward listening is most explicit in the sharply
contrasting, finely wrought efforts of Dubiel and Elisabeth Le Guin to distill
in its essence something like a bravely and exquisitely honest phenomenol-
ogy of listening. That project quintessentializes the resistance to binary dis-
tinctions that clarifies, in turn, why the Next Paradigm does not simply
replace Structural Listening with some other type of listening. Subtly disas-
sembling and reassembling, teasing out and conflating components within
the experience of listening, these two authors do in an especially direct way
what most of their fellow contributors do in a variety of ways. They make it
more difficult for us to place definitional barriers around the notion of
“structure,” and thereby to configure our own work as a hierarchy of clean
after word 287
whom every scholar dreams—the one who takes up where one has left off
and goes someplace unimagined and far better.25 On one level, he seems the
biggest exception of all to the movement I have been charting in the Next
Paradigm, away from my own binary thinking. Far from fleeing binary
oppositions, Dell’Antonio’s essay seems to revel in them: what makes his
study so ingenious is precisely his ability to analyze a new cultural practice,
watching MTV, by finding persuasive binary opposites to one after another
of the elements I once defined in Structural Listening.26
On another level, however, Dell’Antonio’s argument moves in the oppo-
site direction of Scherzinger’s and Levitz’s. Whereas they renounce binary
oppositions only to become caught up in them, Dell’Antonio’s seeming
embrace of those oppositions ends in his undercutting them. In shifting his
attention from the canon to MTV, Dell’Antonio does not stop at suggesting
that different musical objects invite different modes of listening. He further
proposes that modes of listening essentially create their objects (p. 222); in
making this proposal, he performs exactly the sort of anti-binary operation
that typifies this collection of essays: he turns the analysis of music into a
deconstruction of listening.
What Dell’Antonio conjures up here is the image of a quasi-Heisenberg
effect, whereby changes in the act of listening unavoidably alter our defini-
tions of what we listen to. This entire collection made me think in many con-
texts of such an image, as when Maus implies, in the final section of his essay,
that recognizing the dynamics in current analysis might alter the demands
we make on our musical culture (pp. 38–39); when Morris suggests that our
moral sense may precondition what we define as structurally satisfying (p.
51); or when Scherzinger quotes Zizek’s definition of an object as “a certain
curvature of the space itself which causes us to make a bend precisely when we
want to get directly to the object” (p. 270; italics Zizek’s).
Levitz, too, evokes this image in the sense that her method of analysis not
only expands the object she makes available but also alters the character of
that object. For in moving from the fixed notation of a score to the histori-
cally and structurally more fluid domain of choreography, Levitz forces
attention to the many aspects of music that cannot be fixed in a single, defin-
itive form or traced to a single, controlling author (see below, note 27). In
a sense this amounts to saying that she insists on infusing structural param-
eters with social ones, thereby rejecting a binary opposition between the two.
Of the decision to fold society into analysis, which tempts every contributor
to this collection except Dubiel, I regret I do not have the space here to say
more. More immediately relevant, in any case, is the extent to which Levitz’s
turn toward indeterminate aspects of music—whether these involve the
unrecorded movements of dancers or conflicting claims within an artistic
collaboration—dovetails with the second principal theme that I have noted
after word 289
contributors to this volume again and again make clear, the difficulties of
articulating the inarticulable are construed within the Next Paradigm as the
condition that underlies all writing about music. Scherzinger, for example,
concedes those difficulties directly in his reference to “the gap upon which
our language to describe . . . listening rests” as well as in his witty designation
of certain efforts to transcend that gap as “a kind of Freudian ‘talking cure’ ”
(pp. 263 and 267). Dubiel invokes those difficulties both in his rejection of
a one-to-one correlation between “a music-structural proposition” and the
“audible” and in his insistence on “some articulable relationship between
analysis and hearing” as the standard for analytical validity: the very strength
of his insistence suggests how easily one may fall short of this standard.41
What emerges from these numerous invocations of semiotic inadequacies,
difficulties, and gaps is the sense that the Next Paradigm is being shaped, in
part, by doubts, and even a pervasive anxiety, about the status and future of
writing. On one level the question being raised is this: in writing about music,
what can one say that is valuable and true? The ongoing shift I cited earlier,
from foundationalist principles to aesthetic sensibilities as a standard for
appraising scholarship, has decreased the possibility of answering this ques-
tion with authority; and the erosion of authority raises grounds for doubt, in
turn, about the general importance of one’s own work. When Dubiel advo-
cates, for instance, that “the main value of [one’s] analyses . . . be something
like responsiveness,”42 what warranty can he offer that the scholar’s responses
will have a claim on anyone else? Is his casual afterthought, that “a related
value is frankness,” intended to provide such a warranty? Is frankness suffi-
ciently rigorous to prevent the collapse of the individual into the solipsistic?
Le Guin and Attinello explicitly raise the specter of a merely private scholarly
writing: Le Guin as an inherent danger in attempts at wholly conscious lis-
tening, without reference to scores;43 Attinello in his ingenious suggestion
that practice in self-reflexive writing might help us in our writing to distin-
guish “the generalizable or the communicable from the private or the con-
tingent, from . . . more personal or accidental memories and wishes” (p. 171).
But beyond these specific and individualized worries lies a question about
writing with larger and more ominous implications: rather than “What is it
possible to write about music?” the question becomes, “Is it any longer pos-
sible to write about music at all?” Dell’Antonio goes a fair distance toward
arguing that as new conditions of musical life take hold, writing may be
superseded. Acknowledging the “apparent ‘inarticulateness’ ” of typical
responses to music videos, he goes on to observe that the “immediacy”
evoked by music videos “discourage[s] the distancing required for the
deployment of specific explanatory language,” adding that the descriptive
language involved in such responses loses its efficacy once the video is over.44
What is at stake in questions about the prospects of writing under the Next
292 rose rosengard subotnik
Paradigm is not just the legitimacy of any individual scholar’s work but the
future of musical scholarship itself. For young scholars in particular, that is
cause for anxiety indeed.
My nerve in predicting the directions that musical scholarship may take
does not extend to calculating odds on the survival of humanistic scholarship
as a profession. But I will venture this much: the best way to protect the sta-
tus of writing as scholarly paradigms change is for scholars to produce excel-
lent new writing. It is my strong conviction that each of the essays in this col-
lection meets that high standard. In concluding this afterword, I would like
to dwell briefly on two that arouse in me much optimism about the future of
musical scholarship, the first by Robert Fink, the second by Elisabeth Le
Guin. Each is a tour de force: although both explicitly renounce the kinds of
control that once informed standards of mastery, each displays a virtuosity
that recalls old-fashioned ideals of richness in art. For each draws into its
frame an ever-widening view of the past. One thereby closes, in a very satis-
fying manner, a circle in recent musicology. The other, which overwhelms
us with the unexpectedness of its form, makes us want to rush headlong into
the surprises of the future.
By no means the least appealing quality of Fink’s essay is its suggestion of
chivalry. Setting out to redress years of vilification directed at Susan
McClary,45 Fink mounts a rescue mission that has us sitting on the edge of
our seats. There is a delicious pleasure in watching Fink knock off McClary’s
attackers. When he steps forth at the end to top McClary’s accusation of rape
with his own of murder, the susceptible reader may be tempted to swoon.46
The larger significance of Fink’s success, however, comes from the utter
persuasiveness of his brilliantly planned defense. No essay in this collection
offers a more seamless or effective merger of hermeneutic interpretation
with structural analysis. One would be hard pressed to find a better demon-
stration anywhere of how to make rigorous metaphorical sense out of formal
relationships; so compelling is Fink’s interpretation of the Beethoven Ninth
that it just about succeeds in melting one’s [my] resistance to reading about
sharps and flats. By bringing in two centuries’ worth of critical responses to
the Ninth, and the theories underlying them, Fink gives his account of
McClary historical authority while shining a torch on the context of
McClary’s critique itself.
Especially fascinating is the aesthetic conundrum that Fink embeds at the
center of his enterprise, which he labels “Beethoven’s ‘aesthetics of fail-
ure.’ ”47 This conundrum itself has something of an illustrious history.
Mozart addressed one version of it in his famous dictum that even the most
violent of passions must be presented in a musically pleasing way.48 Schu-
mann addressed another in his suggestion that the “[reign of] disorderly
confusion” in the Finale of Berlioz’s Symphonie fantastique is “only fitting for
an infernal wedding”;49 and Tovey still another in his complaint about
after word 293
French composers who seem to look on Berlioz’s errors as the basis for a new
style of composition.50 Adorno hinted at yet another in his distinction
between the socially induced “fissures and fractures” in a composition and
“those [that] are attributable merely to the subjective inadequacy of the indi-
vidual composer.”51 Reduced to its essentials, the conundrum amounts to
this: how do we decide when disorder in music is legitimate?
By tying disruptions in Beethoven’s Ninth Symphony to a cave-in of the
formally controllable, Fink establishes the soundness of McClary’s critique,
on both musical and ideological grounds, and he confirms its importance.
Fink is right to argue that McClary’s confrontation of disturbance in a
revered masterpiece presents us not with a sacrilege but with an opportunity.
Her work enables us to gauge the full range of effects that can be exerted by
art, including danger and violence, conjured up so wonderfully by Fink’s
candid-camera shot of Furtwängler and Goebbels at the Beethoven Ninth.52
Fink’s announcement, at the outset of his essay, that he never took
McClary’s formulation as “an attack on Beethoven himself” (p. 110) quick-
ened my pulse, for it at once brought to my own mind Edward Lowinsky’s
long-ago warning that I would come to rue a limitation I had imputed to
Beethoven.53 So it was with something of thrill that I came upon a direct
quote, toward the end of Fink’s essay, of the very remark that had once raised
Lowinsky’s hackles (p. 145). In choosing to quote this particular sentence
from my work, Fink convinced me utterly of his sound historical instincts. He
had drawn exactly the line that I would have drawn from my work to Susan’s;
and he thereby closed a circle between where she and I are today, on oppo-
site coasts facing Fink’s paradigm, and where we were thirty years ago,
together in Chicago facing Lowinsky’s.
Le Guin’s achievement is of an order I have not encountered elsewhere.
Like Fink’s article, it never mentions my essay on structural listening; indeed
it does not mention me at all. And yet I can think of no work that I would be
happier to count in my legacy, no matter how distant or attenuated the con-
nection. The originality of Le Guin’s essay is so ferocious that it has an
extraordinary enlivening effect. Reading it, I had much the same sensation
that one might have in the first, scoreless hearing of an exciting new piece:
holding my breath with each surprise, unable at any moment to anticipate
where I was going, I had the sensation at every moment not of reading Le
Guin’s essay but of writing it. Even now, many months after I read it for the
first time, just thinking about her essay makes me feel more intelligent.
What is there to say about an essay that manages to condense three hun-
dred years of French art and thought into the bubble of a single musical
experiment? For one thing, that the essay itself seems very French: in its
choice of artists and thinkers; in its attachment to the Enlightenment; in the
elegant simplicity of its experiment; in its projection of a visuality so vivid
that one seems to read the essay to the accompaniment of an unfurling visual
294 rose rosengard subotnik
approached sufficiency to the chain of experiences set off by one bite into a
cookie (p. 248).
Another tool is (the fallacy of) the synoptic gaze or capture, a concept that
helps us to understand the fictions through which we transform multiple
experiences into the illusion of one fixed image.56 “[S]ynoptically ‘appreci-
ating’ or ‘capturing’ the motion of music through time [means] a process of
rendering it susceptible to description” (p. 242). Combining the synoptic illu-
sion with still other conceptual tools, such as Husserl’s bracketing, Le Guin
goes a long way toward suggesting how our actual notions of the “engaged lis-
tener” may not match our preconceptions thereof (preconceptions that
could include, I imagine, the Structural Listener).57 By her account,
“[W]rit[ing] of the agency of the [engaged] listener . . . [might mean] find-
ing out, tracing through, explaining what might have been brought to bear
on the listening experience at any given moment” (p. 248; italics hers).
This formulation has resonance in many directions. One paradoxical cor-
relate is a Germanic world of overdetermination, as represented by the
motivic web surrounding Wagner’s characters as well as by the sources of
Freudian dreams. But overdetermination is not limited to Germans; Proust’s
“nearly infinite regression of association” surely provides a classic instance
(p. 248). For our own purposes, however, what is most important about this
formulation is its apparent role in a new paradigm of how to analyze our lis-
tening experiences and, finally, of how to write about music. “[M]emory,
association, and reflection,” Le Guin observes, can all help us “tease[ ] forth”
the “musical work as heard” (p. 247). Tempered by various disciplining fac-
tors—Le Guin mentions two possibilities, the restrictiveness of the visual
score and the selectivity of Baudelaire’s “memory”58—the rigorous non-lin-
ear process she describes might well replace efforts to engage in structural
listening.59 It might even constitute the paradigm underlying her own essay.
No contributor to this volume is more attuned than Le Guin to the long
odds against writing anything true or valuable about music. In one guise or
another she is constantly mentioning the problem. “[N]o matter how lucid,
sensitive and perceptive the prose,” she says at one point, “transparency is
never achieved” (p. 246). Or again, Bergson’s conception of musical recep-
tion lies “outside of the realm of the explainable, even the articulable” (p.
243). Note her own discouragement toward the end of her essay: “Specificity
is much harder. . . . I am left, in the end, with an unfinished monument, a
descriptional torso. . . . I am bold to consider myself able to account for even
one [bar] in eight” (pp. 248–49).
And yet like Dell’Antonio in quite a different context (p. 220), Le Guin
adds one other element to the paradigm she constructs for writing about
music: performance. The “kind of description [that] unpacks the visualizing,
concretizing, freeze-frame synoptic process, and ‘musicifies’ reception
through description,” she writes, amounts to “a readerly reconstitution of the
296 rose rosengard subotnik
art object . . . [which is] really a kind of performance” (p. 247). If Le Guin’s
essay exemplifies the new paradigm she is developing for writing about
music, then writing about music is far from an insoluble problem. Le Guin’s
essay is not merely a performance; it is a bravura performance.
Although this essay makes no mention of Structural Listening, the under-
lying relationship does, in the end, seem clear: Le Guin has thought long and
hard about the structuring of listening. I am pleased to have given her an
occasion to present a piece of scholarship well beyond my own capabilities.
The same holds true for the other essays as well. Each contributor to this col-
lection has paid me the courtesy of using my essay on Structural Listening in
some way as a point of departure for work I could neither have done nor
imagined. Together they have given all of us in the older generation an
incomparable gift: a mountaintop from which we can imagine, at least, that
we see the future. And however much these young scholars may worry about
the prospects for writing about music, their own accomplishments, as rep-
resented in this volume, are the best reassurance they could provide. The
Next Paradigm of musical scholarship is in good hands.60
notes
Epigraphs: (1) Collins 2001, 16 (“Introduction to Poetry”); (2) Elkins 2001, x;
90–91; 92; (3) Taruskin 2001, 36; (4) Jon Spayde, “Born Sensuous: A User’s Guide to
Rediscovering Your Senses,” UTNE Reader (November–December 2001), quoted by
Leslie Brokaw, “Literary Life,” Boston Globe, 19 December 2001: C:3; (5) Frank Rich,
“Close Reading: On the Cultural Battlefields,” New York Times Magazine, 23 Decem-
ber 2001, 19.
1. By Philip Alperson (who also chose the title), for his 1987 collection of essays
by philosophers on music. Because of some unresolved editing problems in that ver-
sion of my essay, I direct readers to the corrected and revised version in Subotnik
1991, 265–93. The discussion of structural listening appears in the latter version on
pp. 277–83.
2. “Toward a Deconstruction of Structural Listening: A Critique of Schoenberg,
Adorno, and Stravinsky.” The first version of this article appeared in a Festschrift for
Leonard Meyer (Narmour and Solie 1988, 87–122). For a brief account of how this
essay originated, see Subotnik 1996, xxxii–xxxiii; see also below, note 18. The version
to which this afterword will refer, cited hereafter as “Subotnik 1996, ‘Structural Lis-
tening,’ ” is the revised version that appears in Subotnik 1996, 148–76.
3. The authorship of Stravinsky’s Poetics has never seemed in doubt to me. It is a
well-established tradition of ghostwriting that the work belongs to the public claimant,
not to the private writer. In terms of this tradition, Alexis Roland-Manuel has no more
claim to the Poetics than does Alex Haley to The Autobiography of Malcolm X.
4. On Anglo-American empiricism see “The Role of Ideology in the Study of West-
ern Music,” in Subotnik 1991, 3–14. The widespread influence of Schenker’s and
Schoenberg’s theories confounds, of course, any clean or thoroughgoing division
between Germanic and Anglo-American schools of musical thought, except perhaps
after word 297
24. The terms of this sentence are brought together from Levitz, p. 74. Her pres-
entation of Taruskin seems to me, in spite of itself, to confirm the value of the dialec-
tic that Taruskin in effect proposes between structure and social analysis. Taruskin
strikes me as right to insist that his “claim [about Stravinsky] is just one of many pos-
sible claims” (Mitchinson 2001, 39); in the same way, Levitz’s core evidence of the
Chosen One’s independence—the Chosen One’s use of “specific gestures” choreo-
graphed “note for note” (p. 85) to the music—could as well be read as evidence for
the character’s lack of independence, that is, for her status as puppet, or even slave,
in relation to Stravinsky’s music. Though perhaps my making these suggestions
merely confirms that Taruskin and I are both stuck in Scherzinger’s earlier stage of
deconstruction, the liberal stage, wherein we lean toward conceding the coexistence
of discrete interpretations; see above, note 15.
25. Andrew Dell’Antonio’s review of my second book, Deconstructive Variations
(Subotnik 1996), demands special appreciation in this regard (see Dell’Antonio
1998). If one wanted to make the case against a structural gap in the communication
between writer and reader, that review would provide a splendid piece of evidence.
Reading it, I had the sensation that Dell’Antonio had thought his way into my brain,
understanding my aims, concerns, and priorities from the inside out, exactly as I had
hoped they would be understood—and then synthesized and articulated them in ways
that I could not have done myself. The generosity of his willingness to understand me
on my own terms was unqualified and rare; I don’t know, obviously, if those qualities
played a role when Notes chose this piece in 2000 for its Eva Judd O’Meara Award
(annual award for best review published in Notes).
26. One additional binary that Dell’Antonio does not specify but nevertheless
strongly suggests is an opposition between Adorno, as associated with structural lis-
tening, and Walter Benjamin, whose notion of distraction (Benjamin 1969, 239–40)
bears such close affinities to the kinds of attention Dell’Antonio reports as directed
at MTV.
27. See especially Levitz, p. 98: “[The] historically contingent work [of Stravinsky,
Nijinsky, and Piltz] demonstrated the limitation of any project that tried to define Le
Sacre as an expression of an objective spirit, essentialist politics, or of pure reason
based on structural listening.” Also worth mentioning in this connection is the nega-
tive force of collaboration that Levitz invokes in her memorable image of Adorno and
Taruskin as figures who have “donned the bearskins and joined the elders, to sit in the
circle with Stravinsky and watch the Chosen One dance herself to death” (p. 79).
28. Attinello (p. 154). See also p. 170 for his use of a quote from the psychologist
Louis Sass to the effect that “some . . . statements . . . may . . . be attempts . . . to
express concerns that are just too all-encompassing or too abstract to be stated in
clear and specific terms, even by the most clear-minded of speakers”; and pp. 168–69
for his questioning of “rigor.”
29. See especially Dubiel, p. 193, where he rejects the notion that “nothing in a
great piece is allowed to be lost,” and his advocacy for the C-sharp minor Prelude in
Book I of Bach’s Well-Tempered Clavier as “in many ways a looser and more obscure
composition than it initially seemed it was going to be” (p. 193).
30. See Fink, e.g. p. 125, on situations where “beautifying criticism’s defensive
focus on formal innovation (‘new rules of the game’ [a term taken from Lyotard])
would provide little protection, since the collapse of the masterwork’s ‘organic’ form
300 rose rosengard subotnik
would be precisely the issue”; and p. 130 for his characterization of the start of the
recapitulation in the first movement of Beethoven’s Ninth as “a violent acting out cov-
ering up a more fundamental formal impotence.” See also p. 112, where he intro-
duces his notion of “Beethoven’s ‘aesthetics of failure’ ”; and below, notes 47 and 50.
31. On rejection of universals, see Morris, p. 67; for the quotations see Morris, p.
58.
32. See Scherzinger, p. 263: “[M]usic . . . multiplies a non-finite number of
semantic effects, which in turn break down a certain limit of the music/text, or at
least prohibit an exhaustive checklist of its signifieds.”
33. See Maus, pp. 37–38, on attempts to reverse control, and pp. 35–39, on a sado-
masochistic model of listening, beginning, perhaps, with the sentence “This is start-
ing to sound kinky.”
34. See Dubiel, pp. 186 and 187. See also p. 198: “I’ve been talking about some
musical percepts that don’t carry the connotations of intellectual mastery.”
35. See Dell’Antonio, e.g. p. 220, on “ ‘background’ music,” which “does not
occupy a listener/consumer’s full attention”; and p. 218, on the “Ideal Appraiser for
a video” as “unfocused.”
36. Dell’Antonio, p. 220. On the postmodernist turn in music from score to per-
formance as a paradigm see Subotnik 1993 and Subotnik 2003.
37. Le Guin, p. 250. The last phrase is immediately preceded by a reference to “a
real, Diderotic regret.”
38. Thereby, in a sense, reintroducing binary distinctions into an epistemologi-
cal pattern of infinite regress.
39. Beginning on p. 111, Fink structures his essay to a significant extent on
Lyotard’s distinction between the modern and the postmodern sublime. Attinello sets
up his use of the sublime in his discussion of Rilke; see pp. 155 and 156. Le Guin in
effect points to the notion of the sublime when noting that Enlightenment descrip-
tion was replaced by “the Romantically indescribable” (p. 245). An important musi-
cal analysis of the sublime appears in Adorno 1998, 196–99. See also above, note 22,
and below, note 55.
40. On violence see, e.g. Fink, pp. 142–46, moving from McClary through the
Reign of Terror and Furtwängler; and Attinello, p. 162, on the attempt of certain
modern music “to blow the world apart.”
41. Dubiel, pp. 187 and 175. On the latter point see also p. 187 on Dubiel’s “strict
interest in holding theoretical propositions to a standard of audible relevance
[although] the ways of meeting this standard are meant to be multiple, even beyond
anticipation.” See also above, note 11.
42. See Dubiel, p. 198, for this argument and the following reference to “frank-
ness.”
43. See Le Guin, pp. 248–49: “[E]xpression and meaning would arise from what
is essentially a sequence of minute surprises, the direction and referentiality of which
would lie very largely in the listener’s own private store of memory and association.”
See also below, note 58.
44. See Dell’Antonio, p. 217. Of importance to his line of reasoning is the argu-
ment he quotes (p. 217) from Simon Frith, that “ ‘the use of language in pop songs
has . . . more to do with articulating a feeling than with explaining it.’ ”
after word 301
45. The low point, which Fink does not mention, probably came when the
Reader’s Digest featured an item about McClary in its “That’s Outrageous” column,
contrasting the prestige of her MacArthur award against the scandal of her Beethoven
criticism. I saw this item but cannot say in what year or issue.
46. See Fink, p. 146: “Insofar as the celebration of an ideal society actually sounds
like a murder to us as listeners (‘bludgeoning the piece to death’ [see quote from
McClary, Fink, p. 142]), it flirts with the collapse of societal order, as it flirts with the
collapse of the musical form through which that order is embodied in sound” [ital-
ics his].
47. Fink, p. 112 and pp. 129–41. See also above, note 30.
48. From Mozart’s letter of 26 September 1781 to his father, explaining his
approach to Osmin’s music in The Abduction from the Seraglio: “[P]assions, whether vio-
lent or not, must never be expressed in such a way as to excite disgust, and . . . music,
even in the most terrible situations, must never offend the ear, but must please the
hearer, or in other words must never cease to be music” [italics Mozart’s]. See Ander-
son 1938, 1144. From Mozart’s formulation, I have derived the term “Osmin’s para-
dox,” which I often use in class as a shorthand label for the conundrum I am describ-
ing here, in all of its various guises.
49. Schumann 1835, 234. See also Schumann’s notion, in the same essay, that the
“undistinguished” melodic character of Berlioz’s idée fixe is suitable for representing
“a persistent, tormenting idea,” and that Berlioz “could not have succeeded better”
through any other sort of melody “in depicting something monotonous and mad-
dening” (242).
50. Tovey 1939, 44: “The canonizers (including the cleverest of all French acade-
micians, Saint-Saëns) seem almost to wish to institute Berlioz’s harmonic weaknesses
into doctrines for the future.” This formulation is not unrelated to Lyotard’s concept,
cited in Fink, pp. 124–25, that beautifying strategies of criticism solve disruptions in
order by calling them “‘new rules of the game.’ ” See above, note 30.
51. Adorno 1976, 63 (“Classes and Strata”). I discuss Adorno’s treatment of com-
positional flaws in Subotnik 1997, 139.
52. See Fink, p. 145. David Josephson has kindly called my attention to the video-
tape Great Conductors of the Third Reich (produced by Stefan Zucher [New York: Bel
Canto Society, c. 1997]). One clip shows Furtwängler conducting the closing sections
of Beethoven’s Ninth at a concert celebrating Hitler’s birthday, on April 20, 1942. As
the music ends and the applause begins, one sees Goebbels walk to the foot of the
stage and Furtwängler lean down to accept his handshake. Josephson, a first-class his-
torian and an expert on the exile of Jewish musicians from Nazi Germany, sees evi-
dent distaste in Furtwängler’s bearing at this moment. But whether or not one shares
Josephson’s reading, one cannot miss seeing in this film the ease with which the music
of the Ode to Joy serves the Nazi agenda on such an occasion. On page 7 of “Music in
the Third Reich,” the booklet that accompanies the Great Conductors video, Frederic
Spotts notes that “The [Ninth] Symphony was a musical fixture on such celebratory
occasions as Hitler’s birthday.” And indeed, the Furtwängler clip gives way immedi-
ately to another clip showing the close of the Beethoven Ninth, this one conducted
by Hans Knappertsbusch, at a Nazi-sponsored occasion that took place either in 1942
or in April, 1943.
302 rose rosengard subotnik
53. I recount the incident in Subotnik 1991, xv. The remarks Lowinsky ques-
tioned appear in the same source, 33–34.
54. The first of the Trois Poèmes de Stéphane Mallarmé (1913).
55. Le Guin, p. 245. The affinities of this notion to that of the sublime are obvi-
ous; see above, note 39 and also note 22.
56. See Le Guin, pp. 240–42.
57. See Le Guin, p. 248.
58. See Le Guin, pp. 249–50. Worth comparing, in this context, is the line of
thought that takes Adorno from a consideration of the “process of internalization, to
which music as a self-deliverance from the external world of objects owes its very ori-
gin,” and of the “active experience of music [as consisting] in . . . an imagination that
does justice to the matter” to a consideration of the possible benefits of “teaching . . .
listeners truly to ‘read’ music, to enable them to appropriate musical texts in silence,
in pure imagination” (Adorno 1976, 133–34). See also above, note 43.
59. The shift suggested here seems strongly related to a shift I discuss elsewhere,
from structural explanations of compositions to genealogical explanations of the
contexts, experiences, and other music absorbed into the process of composition.
See Subotnik 2003, 24–25.
60. I wish here to express my regret that the shape these remarks took eventually
excluded a number of topics I had initially hoped to address. Had I found a way to
include them, I would have made considerably more references to essays in this vol-
ume. Among those topics, and the scholars involved, were these: analysis of the con-
cept of self or subject (Maus, Morris, Attinello, Dell’Antonio); relation of musical
scholarship to political or social analysis (Morris, Levitz, Dell’Antonio, Scherzinger);
emphasis on the presence or absence of visual elements, including notions of the
gaze and scoreless listening (Maus, Levitz, Dubiel, Le Guin, Scherzinger); and
genealogical or dialogic modes of hearing and criticism (Morris, Levitz, Dell’Anto-
nio; see above, note 59). Above all I regret having to renounce an extended discus-
sion of ways in which the study of music is affected by the relationship of cognitive
and moral concerns. Many philosophical issues have interested me over the years; but
this difficult and unwieldy relationship has been a steady preoccupation, bordering
on an obsession, that lies at the heart of almost every bit of writing I have done. Had
I figured out how to focus here on the relationship of the cognitive and the moral to
the aesthetic, the star of my afterword would have been Mitchell Morris, whose essay
in this collection picks up that gauntlet and (to Americanize my sports metaphor)
runs with it. If Dell’Antonio has inherited my structural listening legacy, Morris, the
only one of the nine contributors who actually studied with me, has graciously pre-
sented himself in his essay as my philosophical heir.
bibliography
Acocella, Joan. 1987. “Photo Call with Nijinsky: The Circle and the Center.” Ballet
Review 14, no. 4:49–71.
———. 1991. “Nijinsky/Nijinska Revivals: The Rite Stuff.” Art in America 79:128.
Acocella, Joan, and Lynn Garafola. 1991. “Introduction.” In André Levinson on Dance:
Writings from Paris in the Twenties, edited by Joan Acocella and Lynn Garafola.
Hanover: Wesleyan University Press.
Acocella, Joan, Lynn Garafola, and Jonnie Green. 1992. “The Rite of Spring Considered
as a Nineteenth-Century Ballet.” Ballet Review 20:68–71.
Adair, Christy. 1992. Women and Dance: Sylphs and Sirens. New York: New York Uni-
versity Press.
Adorno, Theodor W. 1975. “Missverständnisse.” Melos 17, no. 3 (1950). In Gesam-
melte Schriften, edited by Rolf Tiedemann, vol. 12. Frankfurt am Main:
Suhrkamp.
———. 1976. Introduction to the Sociology of Music [1962]. Translated by E. B. Ashton.
New York: Seabury (Continuum).
———. 1978. Philosophie der neuen Musik. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
———. 1986. “What National Socialism has Done to the Arts.” In Gesammelte Schriften,
edited by Rolf Tiedemann, vol. 20/2. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
———. 1997. “Stravinsky: Ein dialektisches Bild”; Quasi una fantasia (1963). In
Gesammelte Schriften 16, edited by Rolf Tiedemann. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp,
1978. Translated by Rodney Livingstone. New York: Verso.
———. 1998. Aesthetic Theory. Translated and edited by Robert Hullot-Kentor. Min-
neapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Agawu, Kofi. 1993. “Does Music Theory Need Musicology?” Current Musicology
53:189–98.
———. 1995. “The Invention of ‘African Rhythm.’ ” Journal of the American Musico-
logical Society 48:380–95.
Allanbrook, Wye Jamison. 1983. Rhythmic Gesture in Mozart: Le Nozze di Figaro and Don
Giovanni. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
303
304 bibliography
Alperson, Philip, ed. 1987. What Is Music? An Introduction to the Philosophy of Music.
New York: Haven.
Anderson, Emily, ed. and trans. 1938. The Letters of Mozart and His Family, vol. 3. Lon-
don: Macmillan.
Asaf’yev, Boris. 1982. A Book about Stravinsky. Translated by Richard F. French, intro-
duction by Robert Craft. Michigan: UMI Press.
Attali, Jacques. 1985. Noise: The Political Economy of Music. Translated by Brian Mas-
sumi. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Attinello, Paul. 1995. “Performance and/or Shame: A Mosaic of Gay (and Other) Per-
ceptions.” repercussions 4, no. 2:97–130.
Barkin, Elaine. 1979a. “Arnold Schoenberg’s Opus 19/6.” In Theory Only 4, no.
8:18–26.
———. 1979b. “play it AS it lays.” Perspectives of New Music 17, no. 2:17–24.
Barthes, Roland. 1985. “The Grain of the Voice.” In The Responsibility of Forms: Critical
Essays on Music, Art, and Representation. New York: Hill and Wang.
Bataille, Jacques. 1986. Erotism: Death and Sensuality. Translated by Mary Dalwood. San
Francisco: City Lights Books.
Baudelaire, Charles. 1949. “Le peintre et la vie moderne” (ca. 1860). In Selected Crit-
ical Studies of Baudelaire, ed. D. Parmée. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Benjamin, Jessica. 1988. The Bonds of Love: Psychoanalysis, Feminism, and the Problem of
Domination. New York: Pantheon Books.
Benjamin, Walter. 1969. “The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction”
(1936). In Illuminations, ed. Hannah Arendt, trans. Harry Zohn, 217–51. New
York: Schocken Books.
———. 1979. One-Way Street and Other Writings. Translated by Edmund Jephcott and
Kingsley Shorter. London: Verso.
Benjamin, William E. 1981. “Schenker’s Theory and the Future of Music.” Journal of
Music Theory 25, no. 1:155–73.
———. 1999. “Schenker’s Theory and Virgil’s Construction of the World.” Theory and
Practice 24:107–16.
Berg, Shelley. 1988. Le Sacre du printemps: Seven Productions from Nijinsky to Martha
Graham. Theater and Dramatic Studies, no. 48. Ann Arbor: UMI Research Press.
Bergeron, Katherine. 1994. “The Echo, the Cry, the Death of Lovers.” 19th-Century
Music 18, no. 2, 136–51.
Berghaus, Günter. 1993. “Dance and the Futurist Woman: The Work of Valentine de
Saint-Point.” Dance Research 11, no. 2: 27–41.
Bergson, Henri. 1959. Matter and Memory [1908]. Translated by N. M. Paul and W. S.
Palmer. Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday & Co.
———. 1983. Creative Evolution [1911]. Translated by Arthur Mitchell. Lanham, M.D.:
University Press of America.
Bollas, Christopher. 1987. The Shadow of the Object: Psychoanalysis of the Unthought
Known. New York: Columbia University Press.
Boretz, Benjamin. 1971. “In Quest of the Rhythmic Genius.” Perspectives of New Music
9:149–55.
Boulez, Pierre. 1966. “Stravinsky demeure.” In Relevés d’apprenti, ed. Paule Thévenin.
Paris: Éditions du Seuil.
bibliography 305
———. 1997. Politics of Friendship. Translated by George Collins. London and New
York: Verso.
Diderot, Denis. 1875. Œuvres complètes de Diderot, revue sur les éditions originales. Edited
by J. Assézat. Paris: Garnier.
Docherty, Thomas. 1993. Postmodernism: A Reader. New York: Columbia University
Press.
Downes, Olin. 1935. Symphonic Masterpieces. New York: Dial Press.
Dubiel, Joseph. 1990. “ ‘When You are a Beethoven’: Kinds of Rules in Schenker’s
Counterpoint.” Journal of Music Theory 34, no. 2:291–302.
———. 1992. “Senses of Sensemaking.” Perspectives of New Music 30, no. 1:210–21.
———. 1996. “Hearing, Remembering, Cold Storage, Purism, Evidence, and Atti-
tude Adjustment.” Current Musicology 60–61:26–50.
———. 1997. “On Getting Deconstructed.” Music Theory Online 2.2 (March 1996);
reprinted in Journal of Musicology 15, no. 3:308–15.
———. 1999. “Composer, Theorist, Composer/Theorist.” In Cook and Everist 1999.
———. 2000. “Analysis, Description, and What Really Happens.” Music Theory
Online 6, no. 3. Followed by a Response by Allen Forte, Dubiel’s Reply to Allen
Forte, and another Response by Forte; also by a number of relevant messages on
mto-talk.
Dupuy, Dominique. 1995. “Entrer en notation: motus volant, scripta manent.” In La
memòria de la dansa: Colloqui Internacional d’Historiadors de la Dansa, Barcelona,
27–30 Octubre de 1994. Paris: A.E.H.D.
Eagleton, Terry. 1983. Literary Theory: An Introduction. Oxford: Blackwell.
Easton, Dossie, and Catherine A. Liszt. 1995. The Bottoming Book, or, How to Get Terri-
ble Things Done to You by Wonderful People. San Francisco: Greenery Press.
Eco, Umberto. 1990. I limiti dell’interpretazione. Milan: Bompiani.
———. 1997. Apocalittici e integrati: comunicazioni di massa e teorie della cultura di massa.
Milan: Bompiani. Original edition, Milan: Bompiani, 1964.
———. 1998. Lector in fabula: la cooperazione interpretativa nei testi letterari. Milan: Bom-
piani. Original edition, Milan: Bompiani, 1979.
Elkins, James. 2001. Pictures and Tears: A History of People Who Have Cried in Front of
Paintings. New York and London: Routledge.
Elterlein, Ernst v. (pseud. Ernst Gottschald). 1853. Beethoven’s Symphonien nach ihrem
idealen Behalt. 3d ed. Dresden: Brauer, 1870.
Epstein, David. 1979. Beyond Orpheus: Studies in Musical Structure. Cambridge, Mass.:
MIT Press.
———. 1990. “Brahms and the Mechanisms of Motion.” In Brahms Studies: Analytical
and Historical Perspectives, ed. George S. Bozarth. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Ernest, Gustave. 1920. Beethoven. Berlin: Bondi.
Feyerabend, Paul. 1978. Against Method. London: Verso. Original edition, London:
Humanities Press, 1975.
Fink, Robert. 1994. “Arrows of Desire: Long Range Linear Structure and the Trans-
formation of Musical Energy.” Ph.D. diss., University of California at Berkeley.
———. 1998. “Desire, Repression, and Brahms’s First Symphony.” In Music/Ideology:
Resisting the Aesthetic, ed. Adam Krims. Amsterdam: OPA.
———. 1999a. “Going Flat: Post Hierarchical Music Theory and the Musical Sur-
face.” In Cook and Everist 1999.
308 bibliography
———. 1999b. “ ‘Rigoroso ( = 126)’: Le Sacre du printemps and the Forging of a Mod-
ernist Performing Style.” Journal of the American Musicological Society 52:299–362.
Forte, Allen. 1977. “Schenker’s Conception of Musical Structure.” In Readings in
Schenker Analysis and Other Approaches, ed. Maury Yeston. New Haven: Yale Uni-
versity Press.
———. 1978. The Harmonic Organization of “The Rite of Spring.” New Haven: Yale Uni-
versity Press.
Franko, Mark. 1995. Dancing Modernism/Performing Politics. Bloomington, Ind.: Indi-
ana University Press.
Freud, Anna. 1966. The Ego and the Mechanisms of Defense. Translated by Cecil Baines
with later revisions. New York: International Universities Press, 1966.
Freud, Sigmund. 1961. Beyond the Pleasure Principle. Translated by James Strachey. New
York: W. W. Norton.
———. 1963. General Psychological Theory: Papers on Metapsychology. Edited by Philip
Rieff. New York: Collier Books.
Frith, Simon. 1996. Performing Rites: On the Value of Popular Music. Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press.
Garafola, Lynn. 1989. Diaghilev’s Ballets Russes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
———. 1999. “Reconfiguring the Sexes.” In The Ballets Russes and Its World, ed. Lynn
Garafola and Nancy and Norman Baer. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Gay, Peter. 1988. Freud: A Life for Our Time. New York: Doubleday.
Giertz, Gernot. 1975. Kultus ohne Götter: Emile Jaques-Dalcroze und Adophe Appia.
Münchener Universitätsschriften 4. Munich: Kitzinger.
Gilmore, Bob. 1995. “Changing the Metaphor: Ratio Models of Musical Pitch in the
Work of Harry Partch, Ben Johnston, and James Tenney.” Perspectives of New Music
33:458–503.
Goehr, Lydia. 1999. Review of Roger Scruton, The Aesthetics of Music. Journal of the
American Musicological Society 52:398–409.
Goldberg, Marianne. 1989. “Artifice and Authenticity: Gender Scenarios in Pina
Bausch’s Dance Theatre.” Women and Performance 4, no. 2.
Goodwin, Andrew. 1992. Dancing in the Distraction Factory. Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press.
Gracyk, Theodore. 1999. “Valuing and Evaluating Popular Music.” Journal of Aesthet-
ics and Art Criticism 57:205–20.
Gramsci, Antonio. 1975. Quaderni del carcere. 3 vols. Edited by Valentino Gerratana.
Turin: Einaudi.
Griepenkerl, Robert Wolfgang. 1838. Das Musikfest oder die Beethovener. Leipzig.
Quoted by Dieter Rexroth in Ludwig van Beethoven Sinfonie Nr. 9, ed. Rexroth.
Pocket score. Mainz: B. Schott’s Söhne, 1979.
Grossberg, Lawrence. 1993. “The Media Economy of Rock Culture: Cinema, Post-
modernity and Authenticity.” In Sound and Vision: The Music Video Reader, ed.
Simon Frith, Andrew Goodwin, and Laurence Grossberg. London: Routledge.
Grove, George. 1884. Beethoven’s Nine Symphonies. Boston, Mass.: Ellis.
———. 1896. Beethoven and His Nine Symphonies. 3d ed. London: Novello, 1898.
Guck, Marion A. 1993. “Taking Notice: A Response to Kendall Walton.” Journal of
Musicology 11, no. 1:45–51.
———. 1994. “Analytical Fictions.” Music Theory Spectrum 16, no. 2:217–30.
bibliography 309
———. 1997. “Music Loving, or, the Relationship with the Piece.” Journal of Musicol-
ogy 15, no. 3:343–52.
Gunter, Pete. 1983. “Introduction.” In Henri Bergson, Creative Evolution (1911).
Translated by Arthur Mitchell. Lanham, Md.: University Press of America.
Hanly, Margaret Ann Fitzpatrick, ed. 1995. Essential Papers on Masochism. New York:
New York University Press.
Hanslick, Eduard. 1982. “Vom Musikalisch-Schönen.” In Vom Musikalisch-Schönen,
Aufsätze, Musikkritiken, ed. Klaus Mehner. Leipzig: Reklam.
Hargrave, Susan Lee. 1985. “The Choreographic Innovations of Vaslav Nijinsky:
Towards a Dance-Theatre.” Thesis, Université du Québec à Montréal.
Hart, Lynda. 1998. Between the Body and the Flesh: Performing Sadomasochism. New York:
Columbia University Press.
Hill, Peter. 2000. Stravinsky: “The Rite of Spring” Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Hirata, Catherine Costello. 1996. “The Sounds of the Sounds Themselves: Analyzing
the Early Music of Morton Feldman.” Perspectives of New Music 34, no. 1:6–27.
———. 2002. “Analyzing the Music of Morton Feldman.” Ph.D. diss., Columbia Uni-
versity.
Hodeir, André. 1961. Since Debussy: A View of Contemporary Music. Translated by Noel
Burch. New York: Grove Press.
Hodson, Millicent. 1980. “A la recherche du Sacre de Nijinski.” Issue on Ballet: Danse,
l ’Avant scène 3.
———. 1986. “Ritual Design in the New Dance: Nijinsky’s Choreographic Method.”
Dance Research 4, no. 1.
———. 1987. “Sacre: Searching for Nijinsky’s Chosen One.” Ballet Review 15/3.
———. 1996. Nijinsky’s Crime against Grace: Reconstruction Score of the Original Choreog-
raphy for Le Sacre du Printemps. Stuyvesant, NY: Pendragon Press.
Hopkins, Antony. 1981. The Nine Symphonies of Beethoven. London: Scolar Press.
Horkheimer, Max. 1972. Critical Theory. Translated by Matthew J. O’Connell. New
York: Seabury.
Horkheimer, Max, and Theodor Adorno. 1991. The Dialectic of Enlightenment [1944].
Translated by John Cumming. New York: Continuum.
Hugo, Valentine. 1971. Nijinsky on Stage. London: Studio Vista.
Hull, Kenneth Ross. 1989. “Brahms the Allusive: Extra-Compositional Reference in
the Instrumental Music of Johannes Brahms.” Ph.D. diss., Princeton University.
Husserl, Edmund. 1960. Cartesian Meditations. Translated by Dorion Cairns. The
Hague: M. Nijhoff.
Jahn, Otto. 1882. Life of Mozart. Translated by Pauline P. Townsend. New York: E. F.
Kalmus.
Jameson, Fredric. 1979. “Reification and Utopia in Mass Culture.” Social Text 1.
———. 1981. The Political Unconscious: Narrative as a Socially Symbolic Act. Ithaca, N.Y.:
Cornell University Press.
———. 1983. “Postmodernism and Consumer Society.” In The Anti-Aesthetic: Essays on
Postmodern Culture, ed. Hal Foster. Port Townsend, Wash.: Bay Press.
Jameux, Dominique. 1990. “Le Sacre du printemps: modernité, archaïsme.” In Le Sacre
du printemps de Nijinsky, les carnets du Théâtre des Champs-Élysées. Paris:
Théâtre des Champs-Élysées.
310 bibliography
Jaques-Dalcroze, Emile, ed. 1912/1913. Der Rhythmus: Ein Jahrbuch I and II. Hellerau:
Hellerauer Verlag.
———. 1912. The Eurhythmics of Jaques-Dalcroze. London: Constable & Company.
———. 1965. Le rythme, la musique et l’éducation. Lausanne: Foetisch Frères.
Jeschke, Claudia, Ursel Berger, and Birgit Zeidler, eds. 1997. Spiegelungen: Die Ballet
Russes und die Künste. Berlin: Verlag Vorwerk 8.
Joseph, Charles M. 1999. “Diaghilev and Stravinsky.” In The Ballets Russes and Its World,
ed. Lynn Garafola and Nancy and Norman Baer. New Haven: Yale University
Press.
Kaplan, E. Ann. 1987. Rocking around the Clock: Music Television, Postmodernism, and
Consumer Culture. New York: Methuen.
Kerman, Joseph. 1980. “How We Got into Analysis, and How to Get Out.” Critical
Inquiry 7:311–31.
———. 1988. “Taking the Fifth.” In Das musikalische Kunstwerk: Festschrift Carl
Dahlhaus zum 60. Geburtstag, ed. Hermann Danuser, Helga de la Motte-Haber,
Silke Leopold, and Norbert Miller, 484–90. Regensburg: Laaber.
Kindermann, William. 1985. “Beethoven’s Symbol for the Deity in the Missa Solemnis
and the Ninth Symphony.” 19th Century Music 9, no. 2:102–18.
Kingsbury, Henry. 1988. Music, Talent, and Performance: A Conservatory Cultural System.
Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Kirstein, Lincoln. 1976. Nijinsky Dancing. New York: Knopf.
Knapp, Raymond. 1997. Brahms and the Challenge of the Symphony. Stuyvesant, N.Y.: Pen-
dragon Press
———. Forthcoming. “Utopian Agendas: Variation, Allusion, and Referential Mean-
ing in Brahms’ Symphonies.” In Brahms Studies, ed. David Brodbeck, vol. 3. Lin-
coln: University of Nebraska Press.
Komar, Arthur, ed. 1971. Dichterliebe: An Authoritative Score; Historical Background;
Essays in Analysis; Views and Comments. New York: W. W. Norton.
Koozin, Timothy. 1999. “On Metaphor, Technology, and Schenkerian Analysis.”
Music Theory Online 5, no. 3.
Kopelson, Kevin. 1997. The Queer Afterlife of Vaslav Nijinsky. Stanford: Stanford Uni-
versity Press.
Krasovskaya, Vera. 1971. Russian Ballet Theatre at the Beginning of the 20th Century. Vol.
1, The Choreographers. Leningrad: Isskustvo.
———. 1979. Nijinsky. Translated by John E. Bowlt. New York: Schirmer.
Kretzschmar, Hermann. 1886. Führer durch den Konzertsaal. 4th ed. Leipzig: Breitkopf
& Härtel, 1913.
Kuhn, Thomas. 1962. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chi-
cago Press.
Kundera, Milan. 1991. “Improvisation en hommage à Stravinski.” L’infini 36.
Lacan, Jacques. 1977. Écrits: A Selection. Translated by Alan Sheridan. New York: W. W.
Norton.
Laclau, Ernesto. 1996. “Deconstruction, Pragmatism, Hegemony.” In Deconstruction
and Pragmatism, ed. Chantalle Mouffe. London and New York: Routledge.
Lang, Paul Henry. 1971. Critic at the Opera. New York: W. W. Norton.
Launay, Isabelle. 1993. “A la recherche d’une danse moderne: Étude sur les écrits de
Rudolf Laban et de Mary Wigman.” Ph.D. diss., Université-Paris VIII (Saint-Denis).
bibliography 311
Nijinsky, Vaslav. 1995. The Diary of Vaslav Nijinsky. Unexpurgated edition, ed. Joan
Acocella, trans. Kyril Fitzlyon. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.
Noyes, John K. 1997. The Mastery of Submission: Inventions of Masochism. Ithaca, N.Y.:
Cornell University Press.
Nyman, Michael. 1999. Experimental Music: Cage and Beyond. London and New York:
Macmillan, 1974. Reprint, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Odom, Selma. 1997. “Nijinsky in Hellerau.” In Spiegelungen: Die Ballets Russes und die
Künste, ed. Claudia Jeschke, Ursel Berger, and Birgit Zeidler. Berlin: Verlag Vor-
werk 8.
Ostwald, Peter. 1991. Vaslav Nijinsky: A Leap into Madness. New York: Carol Publish-
ing Group.
Paddison, Max. 1993. Adorno’s Aesthetics of Music. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Pasler, Jann. 1981. “Debussy, Stravinsky and the Ballets Russes: The Emergence of a
New Musical Logic.” Ph.D. diss., University of Chicago.
Pirrotta, Nino. 1994. Don Giovanni’s Progress: A Rake Goes to the Opera. Translated by
Harris S. Saunders, Jr. New York: Marsilio.
Postel du Mas, Vivian. 1914. “Les caractères géométriques du danseur moderne.”
Montjoie 1–2.
Praz, Mario. 1970. The Romantic Agony. Translated by Angus Davidson. 2d ed. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Rambert, Marie. 1972. Quicksilber. London: Macmillan.
Ramsey, Burt. 1995. The Male Dancer: Bodies, Spectacle, Sexualities. London: Routledge.
Ranger, Terence. 1985. The Invention of Tribalism in Zimbabwe. Gweru, Harare,
Gokomere: Mambo Press.
Reich, Steve. 1987. “Notes.” In his Early Works: Come Out/Piano Phase/Clapping
Music/It’s Gonna Rain. New York: Elektra/Nonesuch 9 79169–2.
Rich, Adrienne. 1973. Diving into the Wreck. New York: W. W. Norton.
Richards, I. A. 1964. Practical Criticism, a Study of Literary Judgment. New York: Har-
court, Brace.
Ricoeur, Paul. 1986. Lectures on Ideology and Utopia. Edited by George H. Taylor. New
York: Columbia University Press.
Riemann, Hugo. 1880s? Concert Program w/Analysis. Unpub.
———. 1889. Grundriß der Kompositionslehre (Musikalische Formenlehre), Vol. I. Berlin:
Hesse.
Riezler, Walter. 1936. Beethoven. Berlin: Atlantis.
Rilke, Rainer Maria. 1984. Selected Poetry. Translated by Stephen Mitchell. New York:
Vintage/Random House.
Rink, John. 1999. “Opposition and Integration in the Piano Music.” In The Cambridge
Companion to Brahms, ed. Michael Musgrave. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Rivières, Jacques. 1947. Nouvelles études. Paris: Gallimard.
Rolland, Romain. 1941. Beethoven: Les Grandes Époques créatrices, Vol. 4 (La Cathédrale
Interrompue), 1 (La Neuvième Symphonie). Paris: Sahler, 1943.
Rosen, Charles. 1972. The Classical Style. New York: W. W. Norton.
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. Undated. Essai sur l’origine des langues (1754). Edited by
Pierre-Yves Bourdil. Paris: L’École.
314 bibliography
Rubin, Andrew, and Nigel Gibson, eds. 2002. Adorno: A Critical Reader. Oxford: Black-
well.
Said, Edward W. 1991. Musical Elaborations. New York: Columbia University Press.
Saint-Point, Valentine de. 1914. “La Metachorie.” Montjoie 1–2.
Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1992. Being and Nothingness: A Phenomenological Essay on Ontology.
Translated by Hazel E. Barnes. New York: Washington Square Press.
Sass, Louis. 1992. Madness and Modernism: Insanity in the Light of Modern Art, Literature
and Thought. New York: Basic Books.
Satin, Leslie. 1990. “Valentine de Saint-Point.” Dance Research Journal 22, no. 1:1–12.
Sauer, Wilhelm. 1958. Beethoven und das Wesen in der Musik. Berlin: Hesse.
Savran, David. 1998. Taking it like a Man: White Masculinity, Masochism, and Contempo-
rary American Culture. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Schenker, Heinrich. 1912. Beethovens Neunte Sinfonie. Leipzig. Vienna: Universal-Edi-
tion.
———. 1979. Free Composition. Edited and translated by Ernst Oster. New York:
Macmillan.
———. 1992. Beethoven’s Ninth Symphony. Edited and translated by John Rothgeb.
New Haven: Yale University Press.
Scher, Steven Paul, ed. 1992. Music and Text: Critical Inquiries. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Scherzinger, Martin. 1997. “Anton Webern and the Concept of Symmetrical Inver-
sion: A Reconsideration on the Terrain of Gender.” repercussions 6, no. 2:63–147.
———. 2001. “Negotiating the Music Theory/African Music Nexus: A Political Cri-
tique of Ethnomusicological Anti-Formalism and a Strategic Analysis of the Har-
monic Patterning of the Shona Mbira Song Nyamaropa.” Perspectives of New Music
39. no. 1:5–117.
Schoenberg, Arnold. 1978. Theory of Harmony. Translated by Roy E. Carter. Berkeley:
University of California Press.
———. 1984a. “New Music: My Music.” In Style and Idea: Selected Writings of Arnold
Schoenberg, ed. Leonard Stein. Berkeley: University of California Press.
———. 1984b. “On the Question of Modern Composition Teaching.” In Style and
Idea.
Schumann, Robert. 1835. “A Symphony by Berlioz.” In Cone 1971, 220–48.
Schwarz, David. 1997. Listening Subjects: Music, Psychoanalysis, Culture. Durham, N.C.
and London: Duke University Press.
Sedgwick, Eve Kosofsky. 1990. Epistemology of the Closet. Berkeley: University of Cali-
fornia Press.
———. 1993. Tendencies. Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press.
Small, Christopher. 1998. Musicking: The Meanings of Performing and Listening.
Hanover, N.H.: Wesleyan University Press/University Press of New England.
Smith, Richard Langham. 1973. “Debussy and the Art of the Cinema.” Music & Let-
ters 54:61–70.
Snarrenberg, Robert. 1994. “Competing Myths: The American Abandonment of
Schenker’s Organicism.” In Theory, Analysis, and Meaning in Music, ed. Anthony
Pople. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
———. 1997. Schenker’s Interpretive Practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Solie, Ruth. 1988. “Beethoven as Secular Humanist.” In Narmour and Solie 1988.
bibliography 315
Webern, Anton. 1975. The Path to the New Music. Translated by Willi Reich. London:
Universal.
Weingartner, Felix. 1907. On the Performance of Beethoven’s Symphonies. Translated by
Edward Crosland. London: Breitkopf & Härtel.
Werckmeister, Otto. 1981. Versuche über Paul Klee. Frankfurt am Main: Syndikat.
———. 1989. The Making of Paul Klee’s Career: 1914–1920. Chicago: University of Chi-
cago Press.
Whittall, Arnold. 1982. “Music Analysis as Human Science? Le Sacre du Printemps in
Theory and Practice.” Music Analysis 1, no. 1:33–54.
Williams, Christopher A. 1993. “Of Canons and Contexts: Toward a Historiography
of Twentieth-Century Music.” repercussions 2, no. 1:31–74.
Witkin, Robert W. 1998. Adorno on Music. London: Routledge.
Zizek, Slavoj. 1991a. For They Know not what They Do: Enjoyment as a Political Factor. Lon-
don and New York: Verso.
———. 1991b. Looking Awry: An Introduction to Jacques Lacan through Popular Culture.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
contributors
323
324 index
Authority: of critics, 67n3; social configura- sublime in, 111–12, 125, 139; postmod-
tion of, 54 ern sublime in, 129–41, 146; rape
Autonomy: of art works, 2, 12; of listeners, imagery in, 6, 110–12, 119–24, 142–43,
204; in modernism, 203, 204, 205, 226; 146–47, 292, 300n30; reception of, 124,
modernist standards in, 232n25 149n4; rhetorical violence of, 112;
Autonomy, musical, 9–10, 202, 204, 215; aes- Schenker on, 114–16, 123, 137–38,
thetics of, 254, 264; in Enlightenment 149n7; storm imagery of, 118–19, 121;
thought, 47; lyrics in, 50; North Ameri- subdominant collapse in, 135, 136, 137,
can theorists on, 74; in structural listen- 139; subject in, 121; the sublime in, 113,
ing, 49; of texts, 204 114, 125, 127, 144; tonality of, 115, 116,
Avant-garde music, 76 131–41; violence in, 40, 146; Wagner on,
117, 123
Bach, Johann Sebastian: C-sharp minor Prelude Beethoven, Ludwig van, works of: Fifth Sym-
(Well-Tempered Clavier 1), 192–98; relation- phony, 121, 133; Missa Solemnis, 131–34,
ship to Beethoven, 274; Schoenberg on, 140, 144–45; Violin Concerto, 200n12,
200n10 274
Bakhtin, Mikhail, 56 Benjamin, Jessica, 38–39, 42n24
Barkin, Elaine, 189 Benjamin, Walter, 154, 156; on distraction,
Barraqué, Jean, 155, 156, 162; Piano Sonata, 299n26; on history, 159; Theses on the Phi-
160, 161 losophy of History, 158–60
Barthes, Roland, 264 Benjamin, William E., 29, 41nn11–12
Bartók, Béla, 164 Bennett, William, 66
Barzun, Jacques, 297n5 Bergson, Henri, 244; on cinematographical
Bataille, Georges, 66, 69n20 innovations, 243; on kinesthesis, 243; on
Baudelaire, Charles, 66; on description, 250; language, 243; on musical reception, 295;
on memory, 249–50, 295 Nobel Prize of, 251n8; on time, 242–43
Bauman, Richard, 211 Berio, Luciano, 156
Bausch, Pina, 80, 98 Berlioz, Hector: idée fixe of, 301n49; Sym-
The beautiful: Burke on, 112; in modernism, phonie fantastique, 292–93
156–57 Biguet, André, 83
Beavis & Butt-head, collective appraisal in, Binarisms, musical, 4, 70, 71, 72, 287, 288
213–16 Blohmdahl, Karl Birger: Aniara, 163, 165,
Beethoven, Ludwig van: aesthetics of failure, 166; cantata, 164
112, 292, 300n31; as antihero, 118, 124, Blok, Alexander, 80
142–46; demonic aspects of, 112–19, 122, Bodily movement, communicative, 84,
123–24, 127; and early music, 274; femi- 101n25. See also Choreography; Dance
nist criticism of, 121, 122; heroic style of, Bollas, Christopher, 25–26
144; late style of, 144, 145; moral synthe- Boretz, Benjamin, 257, 272; deconstructive
sis of, 67n6; musical energy of, 153n28; readings of, 267; “Quest of the Rhythmic
sonata forms of, 151n23; tonal harmony Genius,” 265, 266; on rhythm, 266, 267
of, 135–36 Bork, Robert, 110
Beethoven, Ludwig van, Ninth Symphony: Boulez, Pierre: on control, 6; criticism of,
control in, 289; critical discourse on, 164; ideal reader of, 164; Le Marteau sans
114–16, 147–48; disturbances in, 293; maître, 163; Pli selon pli, 155, 156, 158; on
failure in, 117–18, 130, 133, 135–36, Stravinsky, Sacre du Printemps, 5, 72,
153n28; “German sixth” in, 126–28, 88–91, 94, 105n67; Structures Ia, 156
132–33, 135–36; and Goethe’s Faust, Brahms, Johannes, 8; compositional meth-
116–17, 118, 121, 122–23, 136; idealism ods of, 68n13; influences on, 59; Inter-
of, 121; as ideology, 144; key relations in, mezzo op. 118 no. 2, 59–61, 66; sense of
134, 151n23; “Lydian ascent” in, 130–39; hearing, 28; Subotnik on, 48
and Missa Solemnis, 131–34, 133; modern Brett, Philip, 31
index 325
Descartes, René, 294; first principles of, Faust: Goethe’s, 116–17, 118, 121, 122–23,
68n10 136; Mann’s, 145
Description: Diderot and, 247, 249, 251n13, Feldman, Morton, 199n7; notation of, 186;
294; as Enlightenment process, 244, 245, tempi of, 199n4; Triadic Memories,
294, 300n39; independence from object, 184–87
246–47; as performance, 295–96; recep- Formalism, musical, 12n2, 150n16, 151n17,
tion through, 244–45, 247; transparency 275; aesthetic analysis in, 253; and decon-
in, 247 struction, 258–72; Hanslick’s, 47, 71; her-
Diaghilev, Serge, 84–85, 86; and Nijinsky, 87, meticism of, 257; high-modernist, 111;
102n34, 104n64 mathematical elements in, 163; politics
Diderot, Denis: and description, 247, 249, of, 258; of structural listening, 257, 258;
251n13, 294; Salons, 246; on synopsis, Subotnik on, 47, 258
246; on vision, 245–46 Forte, Allen, 7; conception of psychoanalysis,
Docherty, Thomas, 10 22, 40n6; on control, 18–19, 30, 38; and
Domination: and identification, 30, 31, 41n9; listening, 26, 29, 37; on Stravinsky, Sacre
by musical personae, 24, 25, 26, 30, 32, du Printemps, 5, 72, 88, 91; temporal ref-
35–36, 40nn8–9. See also Control; Mastery erences of, 16, 17, 18; use of first person,
The Downward Spiral (Nine Inch Nails), 16, 17, 19; use of mirroring, 13–14,
64–65, 66 16–20, 30
Dukas, Paul: Piano Sonata, 235 Forte, Allen, works of: The Harmonic Orga-
Duncan, Isadora, 83, 97 nization of “The Rite of Spring,” 90; Introduc-
Dupuy, Dominque, 101n24 tion to Schenkerian Analysis, 41n10;
Duration, awareness of, 242–43 “Schenker’s Conception of Musical Struc-
ture,” 13–22, 23, 26, 28–30, 40nn4–6
Easton, Dossie, 36, 42n22 French Revolution: Terror in, 143; utopi-
Eco, Umberto, 201, 205–7; on critical read- anism of, 145
ing, 208, 211–12; on Gramsci, 224, 225 Freud, Anna, 37
Elkins, James, 279 Freud, Sigmund, 13; on active-passive rela-
Empiricism, Anglo-American, 280, 296n4 tionships, 37; on mourning, 63; on sado-
Enlightenment, 293; concept of art in, 47; masochism, 42n22
descriptive process in, 244, 245, 294, Fried, Michael, 246
300n39; reasoning in, 53, 143; and totali- Frith, Simon, 205, 210, 211; on fragmentary
tarianism, 143 appraisal, 220, 222, 290; on musical
Epstein, David, 68n16 assessment, 224; on music producers,
Erdgeist, 116, 122–23, 139 225; on popular music, 212, 217,
Ernest, Gustave, 118 300n44
Ethics: in decision-making, 51; of lateness, Furtwängler, Wilhelm, 152n27, 293, 300n40;
60; socially based, 58. See also Morality on Fernhören, 28; and Goebbels, 145, 293,
Ethics, musical, 11, 45, 286, 288; of com- 301n52
posers, 46; in listening, x, 46, 58, 289; in
structural listening, 2 Gabriel, Peter: Intruder, 269–70, 272
Eurythmics, 84–85, 103n53 Galas, Diamanda: Plague Mass, 270, 271,
Experience: assessment of, 247; auditory, 272
238; recreation of, 248 Garafola, Lynn, 82, 86
Experience, musical, 9; articulation of, Gaze: listening, 269; structuring activity of,
290–91; defensive response to, 39; eroti- 269; subjectivity in, 268, 272; synoptic,
cization of, 31–34; modernist ideals of, 295
222; particularity of, 253 Gender: in listening, 33; in musicology, 252;
studies, 166, 169
Fascism, 75; in interpretation of Stravinsky, Gesture, language of, 245
Sacre du Printemps, 78, 80, 98, 100n21 Goebbels, Joseph, 145, 293, 301n52
index 327
MacIntyre, Alasdair, 51–53, 67; After Virtue, 168; institutionalization of, 162; mysti-
53–57 cism in, 154; nineteenth-century, 11;
Mallarmé, Stéphane, 158; on music, 244; “La objectivity in, 10; poetry of, 156; post-
musique et les lettres,” 251n10; “Soupir,” modernism and, 11; postwar, 155;
235–37, 239 Romanticism as, 124; self-determination
Mann, Thomas: Dr. Faustus, 145 in, 203; selfhood in, 50, 54; subjectivity
Marnold, Jean, 84 in, 10; the sublime in, 156–57; unique-
Martinson, Harry, 165–66 ness in, 203; view of knowledge, 1; before
Marx, A. B., 130, 136, 150n10; Beethovens World War 1, 155
Leben und Schaffen, 116–18, 121, 122, Modes, musical: gendered dualism of, 274,
124 276n8
Massine, Leonide, 80, 100n23 Montjoie ( journal), 83, 96,102n38; Gross-
Mastery: attentiveness in, 289; collective ver- Hugo’s drawings for, 107n94
sus individual, 300n5; hearing and, 187; Morality: in classical languages, 52; in
intellectual, 5; and listening, 289; in human relationships, 67; in music, 2,
music theory, 5–6, 286, 292; rejection of, 45–47, 58. See also Ethics
289–90; and subservience, 7. See also Con- Mozart, Wolfgang Amadeus: on musical pas-
trol; Domination sion, 301n48; seductive qualities of, 33,
McClary, Susan, 210, 271, 276; and Adrienne 34, 42n21; signification in, 221
Rich, 142; antiformalism of, 120; on cul- Mozart, Wolfgang Amadeus, works of: Abduc-
tural practice, 254–55; Feminine Endings, tion from the Seraglio, 301n48; Don Gio-
109–12; feminist scholarship of, 149n3; vanni (“Là ci darem la mano”), 31–34,
on rape imagery in Beethoven’s Ninth 41nn19–20, 222; Marriage of Figaro,
Symphony, 6, 119–24, 130, 292, 293, 262–63
301n45; on role of music, 146; sexual pol- MTV, 7, 8, 288; authenticity of, 213, 224–25,
itics of, 110, 151n16; sublimating criti- 228, 229; average viewer of, 230n14; in
cism of, 124; van den Toorn on, 123, capitalist culture, 224; collective
124–25, 146 appraisal on, 213–18, 223, 231n15; collec-
Meaning: collective, 228; immediacy in, 221; tive viewers of, 201–2; critical process on,
negotiation of, 7; in speech, 62–63 223, 224–25, 227–28; in cultural forma-
Meaning, musical, 3, 204; in collective listen- tion, 226; cultural negotiation on, 224;
ing, 7; communication through dance, economic needs of, 225; incomplete
71; cultural, 73; historical, 99n12; imma- videos on, 208; iterative play on, 216;
nent, 78, 272; and listeners’ memory, musical repertory of, 216; as organic
300n43; in music videos, 214; negotiation intellectual, 229; as postmodern phe-
of, 8; in popular music, 204; in structural nomenon, 210, 230n8; programming on,
listening, 222; totalizing tendency in, 273; 203; public of, 202, 230n14; role in col-
undecidability in, 273, 274 lective meaning, 228; textual intention
Memory: and association, 249; Baudelaire in, 207; use of internet, 215, 216, 223. See
on, 249–50, 295; Husserl on, 247–48; and also Music videos
musical meaning, 300n43; selectivity of, Multimedia: appraisal of, 207–8, 229n2;
295 fragmented nature of, 222; in music
Meyer, Leonard, 284, 296n2 videos, 9
Michaelis, Friedrich: on the sublime, 112 Music, African, 274, 275; canonization of,
Middleground, 106n84; in Schenkerian 276n12; rhythm of, 276n13
analysis, 29, 41nn10,12 Music, modernist: avant-garde in, 169; col-
Mirroring, of text and music, 13–14,16–20, lapse in, 154, 155; destruction in, 154,
30 155; Geschichtsphilosophie of, 100n23; inef-
Modernism: autonomy in, 203, 204, 205, fable in, 154, 155; rigor in, 168–69; sensu-
226, 232n25; beauty in, 156–57; cultural ality of, 156, 163; transcendence in, 154,
bias in, 168; extreme emotion in, 161, 155; violence in, 156
330 index
Music, popular: authenticity in, 204; author- Music reading, 3; versus listening, 28; in
ial presence in, 203; collectivity of, musical analysis, 26–27, 29; as perfor-
212–13, 224; generic nature of, 204; mance, 27. See also Scores, musical
groups, 212; immediacy of, 217; meaning Music theory: agency in, 15–16, 19; control
in, 204; subject in, 204 in, 18–19, 21, 286, 292; as defense mecha-
Musical analysis: creative involvement with, nism, 285–86, 290; formalism in, 12n2,
29; culture of, 193; deconstruction in, 150n16, 151n17; Forte on, 13; generaliz-
257; Euclidean/Cartesian score-plane of, ing conceits in, 276n11; graphic repre-
259–60; frankness in, 198, 300n42; goal sentation in, 105n71; hearing in, 190;
of, 41n16; and hearing, 175, 291; listen- mastery in, 5–6, 286, 292; misunderstand-
ing in, 286; motivation for, 38; versus ing in, 16; versus musicology, 285; norma-
musical experience, 175–76; music read- tive subjectivity in, 15–16; North Ameri-
ing in, 26–27, 29; objectivity in, 8; physi- can, 14, 74; professionalization of, 14;
cality in, 8; poetics of, 259; processes of, psychoanalysis in, 21–22, 40n6, 271, 272;
286; progressive formalism in, 258; repre- reified, 15; scientific attitude in, 21–22;
sentational stance in, 272; responsiveness sketch studies in, 105n72; sublimating,
in, 198; technical material in, 199n5, 272; 123; traditional, 285. See also Musical
value of, 291. See also Music criticism; analysis; Music criticism; Musicology
Musicology; Music theory Music videos: aesthetic satisfaction in,
Music criticism: beautifying, 120, 299n39; 232n25; appraisal of, 201–3, 207–8, 210,
immanent, 74–75; moral, 45–47; Schu- 212–13, 226; as commercials, 209, 225;
mann’s, 11, 222, 231n22; sublimating, consumption of, 208; empty signifiers in,
120, 124, 141. See also Musical analysis; 210; explanatory language for, 291; ideal
Musicology appraisers of, 218, 221; immediacy of,
Musicology: Anglo-American paradigm of, 2, 211, 217, 291; iterative viewing of,
280, 297n4; anti-formalist, 257; binarisms 209–10, 216; mode of presentation, 221;
in, 4; British, 164–65; class in, 252; cogni- multiple valence of, 208; as performance,
tive concerns in, 302n60; deconstruction 217, 210–11, 220; as postmodern texts,
in, 256, 257; dialectic in, 281–82; dis- 210; semiotic agenda of, 208; signifying
agreements in, 44–45; epistemological process of, 217, 218; as stable commodity,
arguments in, 46; ethical assumptions in, 228; structural integrity of, 290; as texts,
45; explanation in, 190; feminist, 149n3; 209, 210–11; textual intention in, 207;
foundationalist paradigms of, 284; future visual parameters of, 208, 210, 217, 221.
of, 285, 291, 292; gender in, 252; Ger- See also MTV
manic paradigm of, 2, 297n4; late twenti-
eth-century, 252; moral concerns in, Nauert, Paul, 199n4
302n60; versus music theory, 285; “Next Nef, Karl, 118
Paradigm” in, 285, 286, 288, 291–92, 296; Nerval, Gérard de, 66
North American, 164; phrase-making in, Nietzsche, Friedrich, 255–56, 272, 275; Day-
164; pluralism in, 256; postmodern, 110, break, 258, 276; on reading, 258
284; poststructural, 267, 282; psycho- Nijinska, Bronislava: choreography of, 97;
analysis in, 170–71; race in, 252; set the- and Jaques-Dalcroze, 84–85; pregnancy
ory in, 259; sociopolitical issues in, of, 87, 95–96, 104nn62,66; on
253–54, 255, 256, 273, 302n60; standards self–expression, 98; on Stravinsky,
for, 291; subjectivity of, 154, 165, 170; “Danse sacrale,” 85, 86, 103n55, 104n60,
usefulness of, 167–68. See also Musical 105n74, 106n83
analysis; Music criticism; Music theory Nijinsky, Vaslav: androgyny of, 86; bisexuality
Musicology, “New,” 255–56; hermeneutics of, 81–82, 86–87, 104n61; bodily expres-
of, 146; Meyer and, 298n18; origins of, sion of, 84–88, 104n59; on bullfights,
254; and structural listening, 285; sub- 104n64; choreography of Sacre du Prin-
lime and, 129 temps, 7, 8, 10, 76, 78, 80–87, 91, 93–98,
index 331
101n27, 103nn51,55, 104n59; and Jaques- 30, 32, 35–36, 40nn8–9; gender of, 32–33;
Dalcroze, 71, 84–85; on dance, 104n66; identification with, 24, 25, 27, 30, 35; in
and Diaghilev, 87, 102n34, 104n64; men- listening, 7–8, 23; in Schenkerian analy-
tal illness of, 81–82, 102n34; musical abil- sis, 30, 41n15; in vocal music, 23
ities of, 101n32; and plastique animée, 83; Piltz, Maria, 87, 95–96, 98; critics on, 107n91
public opinion on, 101n30, 104n61; in Pirrotta, Nino, 33
Schéhérezade, 86; on scholars, 102n45; in Plastique animée, 71, 83, 97
Spectre de la rose, 86; and Stravinsky, 81, Pleasure, economy of, 208–9
83–84, 101nn31–32 Plotkin, Richard, 199n3
Nilsson, Bo, 156 Pluralism: liberal, 258; in musicology, 256;
Nine Inch Nails (group) 8, 64–65, 67 Subotnik on, 258
Norrington, Roger, 150n15 Poetry: Dadaist, 157; Modernist, 156–57; Sur-
realist, 157; Symbolist, 155
Objectivity, in modernist thought, 10 Postmodernism: aesthetics in, 7; angels in,
Obligation, 281, 297n7 158–62; consumer capitalism in, 228;
Observation, as mode of inquiry, 175 metanarratives in, 10; and modernism,
Oliveros, Pauline: Sonic Meditations, 42n23 11, 124; modes of hearing in, 1, 113; of
Olson, Charles, 62 MTV, 210, 230n8; in musicology, 110,
Organicism: of expression, 227; of groups, 284; subject position in, 202, 219–20; the
226–27; of intellectuals, 202, 224, 225, sublime in, 10, 111–13, 125, 129–41; view
228–29; in listening, 11; of masterworks, of knowledge, 4–5, 7, 10
299n30; in musical structure, 10–11; Poststructuralism, 257–58; music in, 264; in
Schenker’s, 120, 123 musicology, 267, 282
Ostwald, Peter, 81 Power relations: eroticized, 31; in music
Other: self and, 204; subject as, 268 reading, 27; negotiations of, 7–8; in sado-
masochism, 7, 36; social ideology of, 2; in
Pain: eroticization of, 35; the sublime in, structural listening, 67n3
6–7, 113. See also Sadomasochism Proust, Marcel, 294–95
Pasler, Jann, 105n76 Psychoanalysis: control and subordination
Perception: association in, 247; bracketing in, 22; Lacan’s theories of, 4–5; listening
of, 247; elusiveness of, 5; memory in, in, 267–68; in musicology, 170–71; in
247; of musical structure, 10, 196, 199n1, music theory, 21–22, 40n6, 271, 272;
261; occupational contexts of, 259; post-Freudian, 269
reflection in, 247; of Schubert’s Morgen-
gruß, 260, 261; socio-cultural forces in, Rambert, Marie, 85, 93, 96, 103n51; and Bal-
260, 262; temporalized, 241; of timbre, lets Rambert, 97; choreographic notes of,
241, 248 105n74; on Gross-Hugo, 107n94
Performance: authority-based concepts of, Ramsey, Burt, 104n61
39; description as, 295–96; as emergent Rationality: capitalist, 274–75; in structural
structure, 211; evaluation of, 54; of isola- listening, 48, 51; in traditions, 57
tion, 221; iterative exposure to, 209; Readers: communication with writers,
music as, 220; music reading as, 27; 299n25; ideal, 164, 201, 205–6, 207; and
music videos as, 210–11; normative interpretive coherence, 206; interpretive
behavior during, 38, 42n23; as paradigm, initiative of, 205; perceptual apparatus
300n36; structural listening in, 211; and of, 247
text, 210–12; work-based concepts of, 39; Reason: disengaged, 50, 51; Kant on, 122
writing as, 162–63 Reception, musical, 295; of Beethoven,
Performers: aural sensitivity of, 28; ethical Ninth Symphony, 124, 149n4; Debussy
positions of, 46; relationship with com- on, 234, 235; of Stravinsky, Sacre du Prin-
posers, 298n20 temps, 81, 101n28
Personae, musical: domination by, 24, 25, 26, Reich, Steve, 8; Come Out, 61–64
332 index
Reznor, Trent, 64; musical poetics of, 65–66; Beethoven, Ninth Symphony, 114,
music videos of, 65 115–16, 123, 137, 138, 149nn6–7,
Rhetoric, musical, 281, 297n8 151–52n25; conception of musical struc-
Rhythm: concept of, 267; non-rhythmic ture, 13; conception of musical time, 17;
dimensions of, 266; in Stravinsky, 88, fantasy recompositions of, 30; on Fern-
90–91, 265 hören, 28; graphic analyses of, 13, 29;
Rich, Adrienne, 130; “The Ninth Symphony influence of, 296n4; as listener, 28; Ker-
of Beethoven Understood at Last as a man on, 120–21; on middleground, 29,
Sexual Message,” 141, 142–43, 147 41nn10,12; motivic thought of, 18;
Rich, Frank, 280 organicism of, 120, 123; on Riemann,
Riemann, Hugo: on Beethoven, 118, 124; 124; as role model, 14; on Schumann,
Grundriß der Kompositionslehre, 115; and 16–22; Schwarz on, 268; Urlinie of, 272
Schenker, 124, 149n6 Schoenberg, Arnold, 193; Adorno on,
Rilke, Rainer Maria, 154, 300n39; angels in 273–74; on Bach, 200n10; Boulez on, 88;
poetry of, 155, 157, 170; Duino Elegies, influence of, 296n4; in musical canon,
155, 157; Sonnets to Orpheus, 155 90; on musical idea, 273; on musical
Rimbaud, Arthur, 69n20 meaning, 3; Six Little Piano Pieces, 187–92;
Rivières, Jacques, 84, 96 and structural listening, 2, 47, 70, 202;
Rock music: authenticity of, 225; avant- structural values of, 280; use of disso-
garde, 66; culture of, 212, 220, 224 nance, 73; and Webern, 274
Rodin, Auguste, 83 Schopenhauer, Arthur, 272
Roerich, Nicholas, 76, 79, 82, 95, 100n17; Schubert, Franz: Der Doppelgänger, 268–70;
The Call of the Sun, 85; and Russian homosexuality of, 46; Ihr Bild, 268–71;
totems, 103n57 Morgengruß, 259–62; Schwanengesang,
Roland-Manuel, Alexis, 296n3 268
Rolland, Romain, 118–19 Schumann, Robert: Aus meinen Thranen
Romanticism: the indescribable in, 245, 294, spriessen, 16–22; Dichterliebe, 16, 21, 50;
300n39; and Industrial music, 66; musical musical criticism of, 11, 222, 231n22;
sublime in, 112; as nascent modernism, Scenes from Childhood, 298n22; Schenker
124 on, 16–22; on Berlioz, Symphonie fantas-
Rosen, Charles, 42n21, 297n6 tique, 292–93
Rothstein, Edward, 148n1 Schwarz, David: Listening Subjects, 268, 271;
Rousseau, Jean Jacques: Essai sur l’origine des on Schenker, 268
langues, 245, 264 Science: modernist valuing of, 5; paradigm
shifts in, 231n23
Sacher-Masoch, Leopold von: Venus in Furs, Scores, musical: reading of, 3, 26–27, 28, 29,
43n26, 123 250n2; visual reference to, 249
Sade, Marquis de, 145 Scriabin, Aleksandr Nikolayevich, 100n17
Sadomasochism, 35–36; agency in, 39; femi- Sedgwick, Eve Kosofsky, 68n12
nist thought on, 42n24; Freud on, 42n22; Seduction, musical, 31–34; resistance to, 33
in listening, 300n33; power relations in, Self: analysis of concept, 302n60; dialogical
7, 36; roles in, 36, 38–39, 42n21; of the constitution of, 56; false, 25; isolation of,
sublime, 122 231n20; in modernism, 50, 54; narrative
Saint-Point, Valentine de, 83 constitution of, 53, 56; and Other, 204; in
Saint-Saëns, Camille, 301n50 Stravinsky, Sacre du Printemps, 78
Sartre, Jean Paul: Being and Nothingness, 268 Semantics, musical, 236, 300n32
Sass, Louis, 170, 299n28 Sensuality: of modernist music, 156, 163;
Sauer, Wilhelm, 119; patriarchal views of, sadomasochistic, 7
121 Serialism, 165, 166, 169
Schenker, Heinrich, 13–22; and the absolute, Set theory, 259, 272
48; Beethovens Neunte Sinfonie, 148; on Sexuality, and musical experience, 31–34
index 333
Signifiers: chains of, 248; destruction of, 219; subjectivity in, 7, 74–76, 100n21; Wig-
empty, 210; in Mozart’s symphonies, 221 man’s production of, 93, 98, 106n81
Smith, Richard Langham, 251n6 Structural listening, vii; absorption through,
Snarrenberg, Robert, 39n2, 40n6 7–8; Adorno and, 2, 47, 70, 75, 202; aes-
Sontag, Susan, 161 thetic dimension of, 2, 3, 230n4; alterna-
Sound: imagining of, 27; musical parameters tives to, 203; arrest in, 272; binary con-
of, 3; non-denotational, 244; physical ception of, 287; and collective listening,
manifestations of, 3; power of, 198 229; and compositional intent, 3; critical
Souriau, Etienne, 240, 248 distance in, 221; critiques of, 49; decon-
Spayde, Jon, 279 struction of, 202, 283; Dubiel on, 6; ethi-
Spivak, Gayatri, 255 cal dimension of, 2; formalism of, 257,
Spotts, Frederic, 301n52 258; historical context in, 50; intellectual
Stens, Olga, 105n74 response in, 8; limitations of, 49; mean-
Stockhausen, Karlheinz, 164 ing in, 222; modernism of, 4; musical
Stravinsky, Igor: compositional technique of, autonomy in, 49; and “new musicology”,
88; in musical canon, 90; on musical 285; and non-structural listening, 257,
meaning, 3; neoclassicism of, 81; and 297n12; as normative, 202; objectivity of,
Nijinsky, 81, 83–84, 101nn31–32; Poetics of 275; objects in, 298n17; obligation in,
Music, 70, 296n3; political aspects of, 45; 198; one-to-one communication in, 201,
and rationality, 48; sketchbooks of, 80, 202; in performances, 211; power rela-
90; and structural listening, 47, 70; struc- tions in, 67n3; processes in, 298n17;
tural values of, 280; Subotnik on, 48, 70 rationality in, 3, 48, 51; reconfiguration
Stravinsky, Igor, Sacre du Printemps: as of, 11; reification of, 173; relationships
absolute music, 8; Adorno on, 9, 72, in, 174; requirements of, 222; role for
73–80, 85–86, 88, 105n67; as art plastique, society in, 257; Schoenberg and, 2, 47,
80–84; authenticity of, 79; as avant- 70, 202; and stability of text, 211; Stravin-
garde, 76; as ballet, 88, 101n33; bodily sky and, 47, 70; and stylistic listening, 257,
sensation in, 77, 78, 80, 82; Boulez on, 5, 287; Subotnik on, 1–4, 47–49, 202, 222,
72, 88–91, 91, 94, 105n67; Chosen One 229n1; teaching of, 231n21; theoretical
in, 72, 74–80, 82, 85–98; collaborative models for, 175; as tradition, 57; training
process in, 82, 98, 289; collective will in, for, 2–3; virtue in, 57
76, 77, 78; community in, 82, 86, 91, 93, Structure, musical: analyzed and experi-
94; “Dance of the Adolescents,” 265–66; enced, 297n11; bounded concept of, 287;
“Danse Sacrale,” 72, 78, 88–94; extra- conceptualization of, 174; constructed-
musical elements in, 90; in Fantasia, ness of, 173; formation of, 196; hearing
105n68; fascist interpretation of, 78, 80, of, 173, 187, 192, 195–96, 197; and
98, 100n21; feminist production of, 98; hermeneutics, 287, 292; and musical
geometrical interpretations of, 107n89; value, 275; open-ended approaches to, 6;
gestural structure of, 71; harmony in, 90; organic unity in, 10–11, 248; perception
as historical event, 71–72; inspiration for, of, 196, 199n1, 261; rigor in, 2;
76, 100n18; morality of, 75; musical cells Schenker’s concept of, 13; and social
in, 88–90, 91, 93–94, 106n83; musical analysis, 299n24; versus style, 4
organization of, 10, 81; Nijinsky’s chore- Stylistic listening, 4, 202–3, 207, 222, 258;
ography of, 7, 8, 10, 76, 78, 80–87, 91, open-endedness of, 262; signification in,
93–98, 101n27, 103nn51,55, 104n59; 256; and structural listening, 257, 287;
powerlessness in, 9; premiere of, 83, 95, Subotnik on, 202–3, 207, 222, 256
96; reception of, 81, 101n28; rehearsals Subject: in Beethoven, Ninth Symphony,
of, 87, 103n55; rhythm in, 88, 90–91; self 121; as citizen, 226; communication of,
in, 78; sexual violence in, 82; sociopoliti- 298n22; listening, 267; oedipal, 219,
cal meaning in, 80; Stravinsky’s dream of, 231n19; as Other, 268; in popular music,
76, 100n 17; structural approaches to, 74; 204
334 index
Subjectivity: Adorno’s concept of, 73, 74; jectivity, 78; on dance, 79; Defining Russia
authorial, 205; in Beethoven, Ninth Sym- Musically, 101n27; on formalism, 151n17;
phony, 121; collective, 78; effect of on Fürtwangler, 152n27; on Roger Nor-
knowledge theory on, 5; gaze in, 268; rington, 150n15; on Scriabin, 100n17; on
instability in, 219; in listening, 11, 34, Stravinsky, Sacre du Printemps, 72, 73–80;
154, 160; masochistic, 3 6, 42n22; in on subjectivity, 75, 100n16
modernist thought, 10; of musicology, Taylor, Charles: Sources of the Self,
154, 165, 170; normative, 15–16; post- 50–51n19
modern, 202, 219–20; stable, 202, 218, Texts: blank spaces in, 205, 206; collective,
221; in Stravinsky, Sacre du Printemps, 7, 201–2; fixedness of, 222; ideal reader of,
74, 75–76; Taruskin on, 75, 78, 100n16; 201, 207; intentionality of, 201, 205;
of tonality, 73 interpretive process for, 205, 206; itera-
The sublime, 302n55; abjection before, 112; tive exposure to, 209; meaning in, 205;
in Beethoven, Ninth Symphony, 113, 114, mirroring of music, 13–14, 16–20, 30;
125, 127, 129–41, 144, 146; Burke on, multimedia, 9; music as, 1; and perfor-
112–13; Kantian, 298n22; modern, 8, mance, 210–12; stability of, 211, 221
111–12, 300n39; in modernism, 156–57; Texts, musical: aesthetic validation of, 10,
and new musicology, 129; nineteenth- 252; autonomy of, 204; formal character-
century, 69n21; pleasure and pain in, istics of, 252; immanence in, 283; inten-
6–7; postmodern, 10, 111–13, 125, tionality of, 201, 207; internal configura-
300n3; Romantic concept of, 112; sado- tion of, 283; listening and, 9–10;
masochism of, 122; sonic, 6; violence in, multiplicity of, 273; performative, 220;
290 structural development of, 202; subordi-
Submission: and control, 7; by listeners, nation to function, 254
34–38; masochistic, 36, 39 Thomas Aquinas: concept of virtue, 52, 53;
Subordination: and control, 18–19; in listen- moral synthesis of, 67n6
ing, 28; in psychoanalysis, 22 Timbre: in Debussy’s “Soupir,” 238–39, 240,
Subotnik, Rose Rosengard: on Adorno, 144, 248; perception of, 241, 248
145, 280, 281, 282; on artistic autonomy, Time: embodied experience of, 242; New-
12n2; on dancing body, 99n4; on decon- tonian idea of, 242
struction, 257, 258; on internal configu- Time, musical: organization of, 5; Schenker’s
ration, 273; on musical binarisms, 70, 71, conception of, 17
72; “new musicology” of, 255–56; on plu- Tomlinson, Gary: Listen, 231n16
ralism, 258; on relativism, 256; on Tonality: feminist critique of, 111; subjectiv-
Stravinsky, 48; on structural listening, ity of, 73
1–4, 47–49, 202, 222, 229n1; on struc- Total Request Live (MTV), 216
tural substance, 48; on stylistic listening, Tovey, Donald: on Beethoven, Ninth Sym-
202–3, 207, 222, 256; on vision, 71 phony, 119, 121; on Berlioz, 292–93; cos-
Subotnik, Rose Rosengard, works of: “The mic imagery of, 119, 150n13
Challenge of Contemporary Music,” 280; Treitler, Leo, 134, 151n21; “The Feminist
Deconstructive Variations, vii, 1, 255–59, Critical Perspective on Music,” 149n2; on
299n25; “Toward a Deconstruction of formalism, 150n16
Structural Listening,” 47–49, 202 Trilling, Lionel, 297n5
Synopsis, 247, 295; Diderot on, 246; frag- Twelve Angry Viewers (MTV): 214–16, 223,
mentary, 242; Guys’ use of, 249; as visual- 230nn13,14
ity, 245
Unconscious: extra-linguistic dimensions of,
Taruskin, Richard, 67n2, 99n12, 279; on 268; Jung on, 171
binary oppositions, 287; on the Chosen Unity, in musical structure, 10–11, 248
One in Stravinsky, Sacre du Printemps, Universality: of good, 58; rejection of,
75–80, 85–86, 106n79; on collective sub- 300n31
index 335
van den Toorn, Pieter C.: on Beethoven, Wackenroder, Wilhelm Heinrich, 263, 272
Ninth Symphony, 114, 127–29, 138; on Wagner, Richard, 295; on Beethoven, Ninth
McClary, 123, 124–25, 146; Music, Poli- Symphony, 117, 123; technique of, 180;
tics, and the Academy, 99n12, 146; on Tristan Prelude, 61, 176–84
Nijinsky, 101n32, 103n55; on Stravinsky, Walser, Robert, 210, 232n24
Sacre du Printemps, 5, 72, 81, 88, 90–92, Walton, Kendall, 41n13, 199n1
94 Webern, Anton: structural listening to, 274
Vieillermoz, Émile, 84 Wedekind, Frank, 122–23, 151n19
Violence: in modernist music, 156; musical Werckmeister, Otto, 158, 159
representation of, 63, 67; sonic, 154; in Wigman, Mary: choreography of, 93, 98,
Stravinsky, Sacre du Printemps, 82; in the 106n81
sublime, 290 Williams, William Carlos, 62
Virtue: Aristotelian, 52, 53, 55; Christian, 52; Woolf, Virginia, 171
in classical thought, 52; conflicts in, 55; Writing: insufficiency of, 294; as perfor-
Homeric, 52, 53; social configuration of, mance, 162–63
54–55
Virtue, musical, 7, 11, 58–59, 66; embodi- Yack Live (MTV), 213–16, 223, 230nn11–12
ment of, 8–9; institutions of, 55; in struc- Yudkin, Jeremy: Understanding Music, 231n16
tural listening, 57
Vision, Diderot on, 245–46 Žižek, Slavoj, 4–5, 7, 10, 11, 288
Text: 10/12 Baskerville
Display: Baskerville
Compositor: Binghamton Valley Composition
Music Setter: Mansfield Music-Graphics
Printer and Binder: Maple Vail Manufacturing Group