Taking Bak Philosophy
Taking Bak Philosophy
Taking Bak Philosophy
PHILOSOPHY
A Multicultural Manifesto
B R YA N W. VA N N O R D E N
Foreword by Jay L. Garfield
TAKING BACK
PHILOSOPHY
TAKING BACK
PHILOSOPHY
A M U LTICU LTU R AL MAN I F E STO
1
I am a citizen of the world.
—Diogenes
—Wang Yangming
CONTENTS
Foreword xi
Jay L. Garfield
Preface xxiii
2 Traditions in Dialogue 38
Metaphysics 40
Political Philosophy 52
Ethics 62
Weakness of Will 72
Other Voices 82
3 Trump’s Philosophers 85
Building Racial Walls in American Politics 86
x Y Contents
Notes 161
Index 203
FOREWORD
JAY L. GARFIELD
T
his book has its origins in what Bryan Van Norden and
I had thought was an innocuous opinion piece in The
Stone column of the New York Times, one we thought
likely to be completely ignored, but which instead, to our aston-
ishment, ignited a firestorm of controversy across the philosophy
blogosphere. That column had its origin in a rather wonderful
conference on minorities in philosophy, hosted by the Univer-
sity of Pennsylvania philosophy department, and organized by
its graduate students. The graduate students and the many oth-
ers who attended that conference were delightful.
Bryan and I were struck, however, by the fact that, despite
including the keynote address in the regular department collo-
quium series, and even though the conference was held at
the philosophy department, the Penn faculty almost entirely
boycotted the proceedings. Most members of that department
were simply not interested in hearing about non-Western
philosophy, even if their own graduate students organized a
conference on the topic in their own department.
We found that surprising. And out of that surprise came our
short editorial, which is reproduced in chapter 1 of the present
volume. From our previous experiences, we expected that most
xii Y Jay L. Garfield
of our colleagues would roll their eyes and ignore it as one more
lunatic fringe call for change in a field notoriously resistant to
change. We hoped that a few would take us seriously and either
bite the bullet and agree that their departments should be re-
named or think about expanding their curriculum and hiring
(and indeed a very few have taken the latter course).
We thought that a few more would offer the same tired argu-
ments against change: It is too hard to cover the “core,” so how
can we possibly devote scarce resources to the non-Western
fringe? There just aren’t any good graduate programs training
people in these areas, so how can we hire? We don’t read the
languages, so how can we seriously address these texts and tradi-
tions? We lack the expertise to determine what is good and what
is bad in non-Western philosophy, so how can we hire or assess
our colleagues’ work? What would we cut to make room for this?
We know how to respond to those rejoinders, and we find
ourselves doing so all the time. Indeed, the present volume ad-
dresses these arguments carefully and in detail. But while
there were a few of those in the eight hundred replies we re-
ceived the first day on the Times website (a record for The Stone)
and in the thousands of others that quickly populated other
philosophy sites, we were not prepared for the level of vitriol,
personal attacks, and frank racism that characterized most of
the replies, including many from within our own profession.
Nor were we prepared for some of the spectacularly ill-informed
essays that appeared subsequent to our editorial in response to
it. On the one hand, we regretted having provided an occasion
for some of this rhetoric; on the other hand, we are glad that it
is out in the open, as it demonstrates clearly what is at stake as
we consider the future of our profession. This book is a careful,
if polemical, consideration of that future in response to this
wave of hostility.
Foreword Z xiii
concluding not only that Plato was not a philosopher, but also
that there are no philosophers in the West.3 In subsequent cor-
respondence, Tampio acknowledged that he hasn’t actually
read Kongzi or Candrakürti, let alone any of the thinkers who
are in dialogue with them. (In this respect, he is less qualified
to have an opinion than even Macaulay was regarding Indian
philosophy.) Nonetheless, he is comfortable dismissing their
work. Here is one reason to extend the canon: perhaps if philo-
sophical education were sufficiently broad, philosophers would
neither think nor write like this.
Finally, Tampio suggests that exalting non-Western intel-
lectual activity (no matter what its form) as “the possession of
wisdom” (rather than philosophy, the love of wisdom) is more
respectful than the colonialist impulse to assimilate it to what
we do. We should not, that is, take our own practices to be hon-
orific standards against which to hold others. Fair enough. But
what do we mean by apparently innocuous phrases like “wis-
dom traditions”? There are two things to say about this: First,
this is not a way of honoring, but of condescendingly disparag-
ing a tradition. We have departments of philosophy because we
value philosophy as an activity. Those departments are reso-
lutely Eurocentric because we take European philosophy as the
default, or paradigm, case of philosophy, conceived, as Tampio
himself puts it, as reflective rational investigation of an argu-
ment about the fundamental nature of reality, or, as Sellars so
perfectly put it, the attempt “to understand how things in the
broadest possible sense of the term hang together in the broad-
est possible sense of the term.”4 We don’t have departments of
“wisdom traditions,” because we don’t value what we take them
to be—nonrational exercises in mythopoetic thinking, or some-
thing like that. To praise Kongzi and Candrakürti by putting
xviii Y Jay L. Garfield
J
ay Garfield and I did not anticipate the storm of contro-
versy that would result when we published “If Philoso-
phy Won’t Diversify, Let’s Call It What It Really Is” in
The Stone column of the New York Times blog (May 11, 2016). Per-
haps we should have: after all, we were calling upon ethnocentric
philosophy departments to rename themselves “departments of
Anglo-European philosophy” to reflect their intentional disre-
gard of everything outside the mainstream philosophical canon.
However, it immediately became obvious that our challenge to
the chauvinism of US philosophy departments had struck a
nerve. This book is an effort to develop in detail the case for a
multicultural approach to philosophy.
Like the original editorial, this book is polemical and inten-
tionally provocative in the hope that it will incite discussion
and raise awareness. This work is also intended to be interesting
and accessible to general readers. Since the point is to get non-
specialists excited about the issues so they will want to read
more and gain a deeper understanding, my argumentation is
less guarded and less detailed than I would produce in a work
intended solely for my fellow scholars. In addition, my editor
specifically asked for a work that is “cheeky,” so I tried to deliver
x xiv Y Preface
that tone, and have not shied away from being openly partisan
in my presentation, and sometimes sardonic in a manner I
would eschew in the classroom or in a scholarly publication.
To assist those who want to learn more about philosophy
outside the Anglo-European canon, I maintain a bibliography,
“Readings on the Less Commonly Taught Philosophies,” at
http://bryanvannorden.com. I am grateful to James Maffie and
Sean Robin for suggestions of some titles to include related to
Native American thought, and to Travis W. Holloway for ad-
vice about readings in Continental thought.
I owe thanks to Jay Garfield for many things: for providing
an inspiring example of how to engage in multicultural philos-
ophy, for the initial suggestion about renaming ethnocentric
philosophy departments, and for writing the generous foreword
to this book. (Unfortunately, his numerous other commitments
made it impossible for him to be a coauthor.) I am indebted to
Wendy Lochner, my editor at Columbia University Press, for
suggesting a book developing in more detail themes from the
editorial Jay and I wrote. Wendy has also provided much help-
ful feedback on earlier drafts of this book, as did Erin Cline,
Benjamin Huff, Jeffrey Seidman, Victor Mair, David E. Mung-
ello, Matthew Walker, and two anonymous referees. My copy-
editor, Robert Demke, did a thorough job of correcting a num-
ber of careless mistakes in my original manuscript. I am also
thankful to Lewis Gordon, Charles Goodman, and Kyle Whyte
for advice about doctoral programs in Africana, Indian, and In-
digenous philosophy, respectively. William Levitan helped me
to avoid a mistaken attribution to the learned abbess Héloïse. I
offer prospective thanks to Professor Wu Wanwei of the Wuhan
University of Science and Technology, who is already at work
on the Chinese translation of this book. Of course, I owe an es-
pecially great debt to Barbara, Charles, and Melissa Van Norden,
Preface Z x xv
We’re going to let our children know that the only philosophers
that lived were not Plato and Aristotle, but W. E. B. Du Bois
and Alain Locke came through the universe.
—Martin Luther King, Jr.
P
hilosophy has been a favorite whipping boy in the
culture wars since 399 bce, when an Athenian jury
sentenced Socrates to death. However, philosophers
nowadays are seldom accused of “corrupting the youth.” In-
stead, a surprisingly wide range of pundits—from celebrity sci-
entist Neil deGrasse Tyson (majoring in philosophy “can really
mess you up”) to Senator Marco Rubio (“Welders make more
money than philosophers. We need more welders and less phi-
losophers”)—assert that philosophy is pointless or impractical.1
Tyson’s comment is ironic, since he is a PhD, a doctor of phi-
losophy, reflecting the historical fact that natural science developed
out of the field he denigrates. Moreover, truly great scientists
2 Y A Manifesto for Multicultur al Philosophy
The venerable canon of the liberal arts is largely built upon the
hegemony of western, European, and British writing, art, culture
and perspectives. Many faculties, including ours at Trinity in
Washington, have done great work over the years transforming
courses and curricula to include many more voices and contribu-
tions from a remarkably broad range of cultures and traditions.
These changes have strengthened and enriched the entire liberal
arts curriculum, making it more open and accessible to a signifi-
cantly more diverse generation of students. Let’s face facts: there’s
a Muslim Mayor in London, signifying the fact that even those
who revere All Things British need to catch up with the now-
settled reality of great diversity in contemporary life. The canon
of learning should reflect that, including Philosophy.29
“really cool ideas” about the topic anyway, and that the whole
class would benefit greatly from hearing them. My grade would
be “D-. See me!”
If you are offended when someone says you are wrong, you
have no business claiming to be any kind of intellectual. But
there is a great difference between a sincerely reasoned argu-
ment and an unargued dismissal. As English clergyman William
Paley (1743–1805) lamented, “Who can refute a sneer?” After all,
“such attacks do their execution without inquiry.” Much more
of philosophy than we like to admit is simply argumentum per
supercilia, “argument by raised eyebrows.” The great economist
John Maynard Keynes gave a wonderful description of how this
technique was practiced by one of the founders of analytic phi-
losophy, G. E. Moore (1873–1958):
ESSENTIALIST ETHNOCENTRISM
of ethics and politics adapted to the present life and the use of
mortals.”58
In 1721, the influential philosopher Christian Wolff echoed
Leibniz in the title of his public lecture Oratio de Sinarum Phi-
losophia Practica (Discourse on the Practical Philosophy of the
Chinese). Wolff argued that Confucius showed that it was pos-
sible to have a system of morality without basing it on either
divine revelation or natural religion. Because it proposed that
ethics can be completely separated from belief in God, the lec-
ture caused a scandal among conservative Christians, who had
Wolff relieved of his duties and exiled from Prussia. However,
his lecture made him a hero of the German Enlightenment, and
he immediately obtained a prestigious position elsewhere. In
1730, he delivered a second public lecture, De Rege Philosophante
et Philosopho Regnante (On the Philosopher King and the Rul-
ing Philosopher), which praised the Chinese for consulting “phi-
losophers” like Confucius and his later follower Mengzi (fourth
century bce) about important matters of state.59
Chinese philosophy was also taken very seriously in France.
One of the leading reformers at the court of Louis XV was
François Quesnay (1694–1774). He praised Chinese governmental
institutions and philosophy so lavishly in his work Despotisme
de la China (1767) that he became known as “the Confucius of
Europe.”60 Quesnay was one of the originators of the concept
of laissez-faire economics, and he saw a model for this in the
sage-king Shun, who was known for governing by wúwéi (non-
interference in natural processes).61 The connection between the
ideology of laissez-faire economics and wúwéi continues to the
present day. In his State of the Union Address in 1988, Ronald
Reagan quoted a line describing wúwéi from the Daodejing,
which he interpreted as a warning against government regula-
A Manifesto for Multicultur al Philosophy Z 21
Kant ranks the Chinese with East Indians, and claims that
they are “static . . . for their history books show that they do not
know more now than they have long known.”67 So Kant, who
is one of the most influential philosophers in the Western tradi-
tion, asserted that Chinese, Indians, Africans, and the Indige-
nous peoples of the Americas are congenitally incapable of
philosophy. And contemporary philosophers take it for granted
that there is no Chinese, Indian, African, or Native American
philosophy. If this is a coincidence, it is a stunning one.
Because of Kant’s racism, it is difficult to believe that his
judgments on Confucianism in his lectures on Physical Geogra-
phy are based on a rational assessment of the evidence: “Phi-
losophy is not to be found in the whole Orient. . . . Their
teacher Confucius teaches in his writings nothing outside a
moral doctrine designed for the princes . . . and offers exam-
ples of former Chinese princes. . . . But a concept of virtue and
A Manifesto for Multicultur al Philosophy Z 23
The same could be said about the Daodejing and the Changes:
without a great deal of effort and assistance in understanding
their background and influence, it would be easy to walk away
from these works thinking that Chinese philosophy is nothing
but shallow platitudes or simply word salad. Ironically, begin-
ning the study of Chinese philosophy with the Analects, Daode-
A Manifesto for Multicultur al Philosophy Z 29
So far, I have replied to those who would deny the title of “phi-
losophy” to non-Western thinkers on the grounds that they
don’t engage in anything recognizable as competent philosophy
(an assertion that can be falsified by simply reading the thinkers
in question), and I’ve challenged the essentialist ethnocentrism
30 Y A Manifesto for Multicultur al Philosophy
I
n the previous chapter I called for greater inclusivity and
openness to philosophy outside the mainstream Anglo-
European canon. I dropped the names of a few texts,
thinkers, and issues that could contribute substantially to a
broader dialogue. However, it is fair to ask for more detailed
examples. Consequently, in this chapter I provide a few specific
illustrations of how different intellectual traditions can be
brought into dialogue. Some readers will be disappointed to
discover that my comparisons are only between a handful of
Asian and European philosophers. However, I can only re-
sponsibly discuss the areas in which I claim competence. To
advocate that we teach the less commonly taught philosophies
(LCTP) is not to suggest the unrealistic goal that we should all
be equally adept at lecturing on all of them. Moreover, I do not
Tr aditions in Dialogue Z 39
METAPHYSICS
asks his readers, “does the same wax remain? One must confess
that it does: no one denies it; no one thinks otherwise. What
was there then in the wax that was so distinctly comprehended?
Certainly none of the things that I reached by means of the
senses. For whatever came under taste or smell or sight or touch
or hearing by now has changed, yet the wax remains.”8
The material thing that remains the same through the vari-
ous changes is the substance. But what is this substance? You
cannot identify the substance with any properties, like being
hot or cold, hard or malleable. The substance is the thing that
has these qualities, and remains the same as the properties
change. This led Aristotle to suggest at one point that there
must be what he called “prime matter,” a quality-less substra-
tum that is the bearer of properties.9 Something seems incoher-
ent, though, about the notion of a thing that has an identity but
no properties.
Descartes compares our knowledge of substances to seeing
people out his window, crossing the street in the dead of winter,
completely bundled up in clothes: “But what do I see over and
above the hats and clothing? Could not robots be concealed un-
der these things? But I judge them to be men.”10 Similarly, “when
I distinguish the wax from its external forms, as if having taken
off its clothes, as it were, I look at the naked wax.”11 (How
quaint Western philosophy is, with all its little similes and met-
aphors!) The problem, of course, is that we have seen people
without their coats and hats on, and we know what they look
like. In contrast, we have not seen wax without its “external
forms.” As Descartes admits, we know the wax in itself “neither
by sight, nor touch, nor imagination.”12
Descartes discusses space-occupying substances as a step
toward understanding what a thinking substance is. However,
his account of souls inherits all the problems that afflicted his
42 Y Tr aditions in Dialogue
POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY
that “if you try to guide the common people with coercive reg-
ulations and keep them in line with punishments, the common
people will become evasive and will have no sense of shame. If,
however, you guide them with Virtue, and keep them in line by
means of ritual, the people will have a sense of shame and will
rectify themselves.”45 The Confucian critique of authoritarian po-
sitions like that of Hobbes is that, no matter how severe the pun-
ishments and how intrusive the government surveillance, people
will endlessly devise ways to evade the laws so long as their only
motivations for compliance are self-interested. In contrast, if
humans can cultivate compassion and integrity (“Virtue”) and
respect for social conventions that they regard as sacred (“ritual”),
the laws and punishments will be almost unnecessary.46
Mengzi, a philosopher of the fourth century bce, defends
Confucius’s political thesis, arguing that a state can be prosper-
ous in the long run only insofar as its citizens are motivated by
benevolence (compassion for the suffering of others) and righ-
teousness (disdain to do what is shameful, like lying and cheat-
ing). In contrast, being motivated by profit—even if it is the
profit of a group to which one belongs—is self-undermining.
Mengzi warns a ruler:
The reason why I say that humans all have hearts that are not
unfeeling toward others is this. Suppose someone suddenly
saw a child about to fall into a well: everyone in such a situation
would have a feeling of alarm and compassion—not because
one sought to get in good with the child’s parents, not because one
wanted fame among their neighbors and friends, and not be-
cause one would dislike the sound of the child’s cries. From this
we can see that if one is without the heart of compassion, one is
not a human.48
crowd of people: they only have one Pattern, but there is the
third son of the Zhang family and the fourth son of the Li fam-
ily; the fourth son of the Li family cannot become the third son
of the Zhang family, and the third son of the Zhang family
cannot become the fourth son of the Li family.”60 Consequently,
romantic intimacy, filial piety, and other attachments are justi-
fied because there genuinely are individual husbands who love
their individual wives, individual children who respect their in-
dividual parents, and so on.
I worry that the Neo-Confucians have fallen back into a
paradoxical notion similar to a Cartesian substance or Aristote-
lian prime matter: the quality-less individual that stands in
relationships but is not defined by them. However, there is
something very appealing about the Confucian effort to do jus-
tice both to the fact that we are dependent upon others and to
the fact that we are individuals with our own needs, goals, life
histories, and attachments.
During his reelection campaign in 2012, President Barack
Obama gave a speech in which he (unknowingly) expressed this
Confucian perspective:
If you were successful, somebody along the line gave you some
help. There was a great teacher somewhere in your life. Some-
body helped to create this unbelievable American system that
we have that allowed you to thrive. Somebody invested in roads
and bridges. If you’ve got a business—you didn’t build that.
Somebody else made that happen. . . . The point is, is that when
we succeed, we succeed because of our individual initiative, but
also because we do things together.61
and their right to profit from the fruit of their labor.62 However,
for those who have learned the lessons of Neo-Confucianism,
Obama’s statement is simple common sense.
I am not a businessman, but I too am proud of my accom-
plishments. I am proud of having taught generations of stu-
dents, and of publishing a number of books and articles. I
believe that my successes in teaching and publication would
not have occurred without my hard work and ability. However,
I suffer from no delusions that I am some sort of intellectual
Robinson Crusoe.63 I know that I did not single-handedly
come up with every idea and methodology I have ever de-
pended upon as a stepping-stone to developing my own orig-
inal thoughts. I am indebted to my parents for giving me
opportunities they did not have. My career is dependent on
every teacher I have had from first grade through graduate
school. And, of course, my roles as teacher and author are com-
pletely dependent upon my students and my readers. So you
should look with pride upon your individual accomplishments,
but you should also not lose sight of the fact that you did not do
that alone.
Confucians are certainly not the only political theorists in
China. Mozi argued two millennia before Hobbes that conflict
in the state of nature necessitates the establishment of govern-
ment. Moreover, Mozi’s version of this argument is more plau-
sible than that of Hobbes, because Mozi does not assume that
humans are self-interested. He argues that the conflict in the
state of nature arises from the fact that humans have different
conceptions of right and wrong.64 Legalists like Shen Dao
and Hanfeizi argued that humans are largely (although per-
haps not exclusively) self-interested, and so governments can
only succeed through explicit and clear laws that are enforced
with lavish rewards for compliance and severe punishments for
62 Y Tr aditions in Dialogue
ETHICS
Transformation of our
potentiality into actuality
through ethical cultivation
Uncultivated human
Immorality
nature at birth
FIGURE 2.1
Uncultivated human
Immorality
nature at birth
FIGURE 2.2
WEAKNESS OF WILL
person with Sincerity will hate evil like she would hate a bad
odor, and love goodness like she would love a lovely sight. What
is distinctive about hating a bad odor is that cognition and mo-
tivation are combined. To recognize an odor as disgusting is to
be repelled by it. If I smell the milk and recognize that it has
gone bad, I do not have to try to muster the motivation to avoid
putting it in my coffee. My hatred of evil should manifest the
same unity of cognition and motivation. If I recognize that
something is evil, I should be repulsed by it, viscerally and au-
tomatically. I should not have to force myself to avoid doing
evil, any more than I have to force myself to avoid drinking
spoiled milk.
“Loving a lovely sight” illustrates the same point, but it re-
quires explanation to see why. The term I am translating as
“sight” here is sè. In classical Chinese (the language in which
the Great Learning is written), sè can mean color or appear-
ance,95 and some translations render it this way.96 However, it
more commonly means lust, or the physical beauty that inspires
lust. Thus, Confucius once complained, “I have yet to meet
someone who loves Virtue as much as he loves physical beauty
(sè).”97 Consequently, “loving a lovely sight” does not refer to
our fondness for a particular shade of blue, or even our admira-
tion for a beautiful sunset. It refers to being erotically attracted
to physical beauty.98
So when the Great Learning tells us that we should hate evil
“like hating a hateful odor” and we should love goodness “like
loving a lovely sight,” it means that we are to hate evil the
same way we are repulsed by a disgusting odor, and we are to
love goodness the same way we are erotically drawn to physical
beauty. The substantive content of these similes is the claim
that our hatred of evil and our love of goodness should be si-
multaneously cognitive and affective. When we recognize that
74 Y Tr aditions in Dialogue
One who fully grasps that she “forms one body” with others
can no more be indifferent to the suffering of her neighbor than
she can be indifferent to an injury to her own limb. However,
one can choose whether to attend to this knowledge or not. If
one decides not to attend to his ethical knowledge, he is deceiving
himself about who he really is. Hence, he is doubly engaging in
self-deception: he is deceiving himself about what his self is.
When we lie to ourselves in this way, we are “conflicted,” as the
Great Learning says, because there is a tension between one
part of ourselves, our moral nature, and another part, our selfish
desires.100
Neo-Confucians in general would agree with the preceding
account, both as an interpretation of the Great Learning and as
a description of human moral psychology. However, there is a
crucial disagreement on one detail. This ambiguity is suggested
by a distinction drawn by Cheng Yi (1033–1107):
The fear of the farmer who had been mauled by a tiger is an-
other example of the sort of visceral combination of cognition
and motivation that the Great Learning illustrates with the
76 Y Tr aditions in Dialogue
For Wang, the simile from the Great Learning does not describe
the goal of cultivation, in which ethical knowledge and motiva-
tion are fully unified after years of effort; instead, it describes
what genuine ethical knowledge is like from the very start. In
the vocabulary of Western ethics, Wang is a motivational inter-
nalist, who holds that to know the good is intrinsically to be
motivated to pursue it.107
Wang’s second argument for the unity of knowing and act-
ing is that merely verbal assent is insufficient to demonstrate
knowledge: “One cannot say that he knows filial piety or broth-
erly respect simply because he knows how to say something
filial or brotherly. Knowing pain offers another good example.
One must have experienced pain oneself in order to know pain.
Similarly, one must have experienced cold oneself in order to
know cold, and one must have experienced hunger oneself in
order to know hunger.”108 To understand the important episte-
mological and linguistic point Wang is making here, consider a
variation on a classic example from Western philosophy. Imag-
ine a hypothetical individual, “Mary,” who is forced to perceive
the world through a black and white television monitor. She
becomes a brilliant neuroscientist specializing in vision, and
eventually knows everything there is to know about the physics
and neurology of color experiences. However, suppose she is
finally released from her bondage to the black and white televi-
sion monitor and can go and see the world as it is. Now she will
learn something new. She will finally know what phenomenal
colors are like. Previously, Mary knew more about color expe-
riences than anyone else, but she did not know what phenome-
nal colors are.109 Similarly, Wang says, you might know a lot
about pain, hunger, feeling cold, and goodness, but you do not
know pain, hunger, feeling cold, or goodness itself unless you
Tr aditions in Dialogue Z 79
Wang has in mind the followers of Zhu Xi, but his point has
contemporary relevance. Eric Schwitzgebel has done empirical
research on the relationship between studying or teaching eth-
ics and actual ethical behavior. He acknowledges that the data
is limited, but so far he has been unable to find any positive
correlation between the theoretical study of ethics and being
ethical.114 Wang would argue that this proves his point: the ab-
stract and theoretical study of ethics will not make you a better
person. However, Wang would insist that what is wrong with
Western ethics is not that it tries to make humans better peo-
ple, but that it does not try in the right ways. If we have any
interest in our courses in ethics and political philosophy mak-
ing a difference, it is worth looking at what else thinkers like
Tr aditions in Dialogue Z 81
OTHER VOICES
I hope readers of this chapter have found some things that they
agree with or at least find intriguing conceptual possibilities.
However, this chapter discusses subtle and complex issues in
only a few pages, so I would be surprised if you found nothing
you want to challenge. (In fact, if you have no questions or ob-
jections, I’m disappointed in you. As Zhu Xi said, “Those who
don’t have opinions simply have not read carefully enough to
have any doubts!”)117 But there is one thing I believe I have es-
tablished beyond any possible doubt. (And that is not a phrase I
use very often.) Buddhist, Confucian, and Neo-Confucian
texts can obviously be brought into productive dialogue with
major Anglo-European philosophical works. It’s fine to tell me
that you don’t agree with them, but philosophy is not about
teaching only figures whom you agree with. (I regularly teach
Descartes, Hobbes, Hume, Russell, and Sartre, each of whom I
think is deeply and fundamentally wrong.) So after reading this
chapter, don’t try telling me that Buddhist, Confucian, and
Neo-Confucian thinkers are not really philosophers.
Given limitations of space and of my own abilities, I have only
talked about a few philosophers from outside the Anglo-European
mainstream. However, any acquaintance with Indian philosophy
reveals that, in terms of both methodology and subject matter, it
is philosophical even according to the most narrow standards that
Anglo-European philosophy might supply. Just open a book!
(One place to start is my bibliography of readings on the less com-
monly taught philosophies at http://bryanvannorden.com.) Afri-
can-American, feminist, Islamic, Jewish, Latin American, and
LGBTQ philosophies are influenced by the mainstream Anglo-
European traditions, so it should come as no surprise that they
can easily be integrated into the curriculum of US colleges and
Tr aditions in Dialogue Z 83
D
onald Trump repeatedly promised to build a wall be-
tween the United States and Mexico, and Ronald
Reagan promised to protect “states’ rights.” President
Xi Jinping has praised classical philosophers like Confucius for
forging the “unique mental outlook of the Chinese.”1 Conser-
vative intellectuals have warned of the dangers of higher edu-
cation betraying “our Western heritage.” And contemporary
philosophers, including ones who identify as politically pro-
gressive, click their tongues about how everything outside the
86 Y Trump’s Philosophers
scaffold went up around it. When the scaffold came down, the
statue was gone.10 Official sources were initially silent about the
removal of the statue. Eventually, they explained that the plan
all along had been to temporarily display the statue in Tianan-
men Square, and then later move it to a courtyard in the nearby
museum of antiquities, where the statue now sits. However, if
this were the plan, why hadn’t the authorities announced this in
advance, or at least explained it immediately when questioned
about the statue’s disappearance?
Tiananmen Square is a sensitive location for many reasons.
It is in front of the Forbidden City, the home of China’s emper-
ors in the Qing dynasty. It is the location of the mausoleum of
Mao Zedong (1893–1976), the founder of the People’s Republic
of China.11 And it is the site of what is discreetly referred to in
China as “the incident of June 4, 1989,” in which student pro-
testors agitating for government reform were killed by the
army. Consequently, the political significance of anything that
happens there is magnified. The peek-a-boo of the Confucius
statue reflects an ideological struggle for the soul of China be-
tween China’s left and right. For China’s left, Confucius is a
symbol of feudalism, superstition, and exploitation of the peo-
ple by the privileged. For China’s right, Confucius is an example
of the greatness of Chinese civilization, a guide to personal mo-
rality of contemporary relevance, and a symbol of what uni-
fies all Chinese as a people. In order to understand the contours
and significance of this debate, we need to take a quick look at
recent Chinese history.
After leading the Chinese Communists to victory in the
civil war against the Nationalists (1949), Mao Zedong insti-
tuted the radical agricultural and industrial “reforms” of the Great
Leap Forward (1958–61). The results were disastrous. Tens of
90 Y Trump’s Philosophers
that it is one of the causes of the second problem. (2) When in-
dividuals have no ethical vocabulary in which to articulate deep
values, they are easily prone to certain kinds of wrongdoing.
Everyone can see the force of satisfying immediate and superfi-
cial desires, such as desires for food, sex, wealth, prestige, and
power. There is nothing intrinsically wrong with any of these
motivations. However, if pursued without regard for other val-
ues, they can easily lead to corruption and cruelty.17 (3) A third
problem is that, in the absence of an ethical vocabulary, it is far
too easy for those who wield power to do so in an arbitrary or
self-serving manner. I take this to be part of the point that Mi-
lan Kundera is making when he writes that “The struggle of
man against power is the struggle of memory against forget-
ting.”18 Insofar as we, as a community, remember our shared
ethical vocabulary, we can deploy that vocabulary to resist arbi-
trary exercises of governmental (or other) authority. For all
three of these reasons, post-Mao China needs new ethical vo-
cabularies in which people can believe.19
The complexity of the intellectual situation in China was
brought home to me at a conference I attended in Wuhan,
China, in 2014.20 Of the Chinese philosophers in attendance, I
would say that about 40 percent were Marxist philosophers,
approximately 40 percent were specialists in some kind of
Anglo-European philosophy (including Western political phi-
losophy), and about 20 percent were specialists in traditional
Chinese philosophy (who seemed interested only in narrow
philological issues). Throughout the conference, the three groups
largely spoke past one another. I don’t assume that these exact
percentages are representative of the state of the field in China
as a whole; however, the discipline of philosophy in China is
largely segregated along these lines, and dialogue across the
divides seems minimal.
Trump’s Philosophers Z 93
truth that the icon can never fully reveal to us.35 Nationalistic
demagogues around the world are guilty of idolatry, of wor-
shiping some limited product of human history as if were the
truth that it guides us toward. There is a problem with encour-
aging idolatry, though. The classics are classics for a reason, and
if you tell young people to revere the classics, they just might
take you seriously. In other words, they might start reading the
classics with care and understanding, so that they search for the
great truths that the classics point toward. All great philoso-
phies and religious traditions have sometimes been co-opted as
ideologies to support the status quo, or to encourage nationalis-
tic intolerance. But thinkers in every generation have been in-
spired by these same traditions to think for themselves, chal-
lenge injustice, and fight for the well-being of the common
people, not just the elites. This is what gives us people like
Martin Luther King, Jr., Mahatma Gandhi, Akbar the Great
(1542–1605), and Kang Youwei (1858–1927).
As we shall see in the next section, there are those who gen-
uinely treat the classics as icons rather than as idols, but none-
theless want to build walls between civilizations. However, I
will argue that their views are ultimately incoherent. Once you
are serious about seeking the truth, you cannot have any plau-
sible reason for silencing other voices in that quest.
Men must love and be loyal to their families and their peoples in
order to preserve them. Only if they think their own things are
*Bryan waves.
104 Y Trump’s Philosophers
good can they rest content with them. A father must prefer his
child to other children, a citizen his country to others. That is
why there are myths—to justify these attachments. And a man
needs a place and opinions by which to orient himself. . . . The
problem of getting along with outsiders is secondary to, and
sometimes in conflict with, having an inside, a people, a culture,
a way of life.47
In short, in order to continue to exist and to flourish, it is
necessary for the members of a culture to believe that “their way
of life is the best way, and all others are inferior,” even if myths
are needed to sustain this ethnocentrism.48
JERICHO
So the people shouted when the priests blew with the trum-
pets: and it came to pass, when the people heard the sound of
the trumpet, and the people shouted with a great shout, that
Trump’s Philosophers Z 109
the wall fell down flat, so that the people went up into the city,
every man straight before him, and they took the city. (Joshua
6:20, KJV)
W
hen Marco Rubio quipped, during one of
the 2016 GOP presidential debates, “Welders
make more money than philosophers. We need
more welders and less philosophers,” he was doing more than
making a grammatical error.1 He was also guilty of several fac-
tual errors. First, as any economist will tell you, the fact that
profession X is paid more than profession Y does not mean that
the economy needs more people to do X. The supply and de-
mand for X and Y may have achieved equilibrium at different
salary levels from each other. (Does Rubio think that in an ideal
economy neurosurgeons would be paid the same as chimney
sweeps?) More importantly, philosophy majors on average earn
more than welders. The median starting salary for those who
studied “welding technology” was $37,000 per year, while those
Welders and Philosophers Z 111
PHILOSOPHY AND
OCCUPATIONAL TR AINING
Philosophy majors earn more than those with any other hu-
manities degree,3 and my own students have gone on to success
in a variety of different professions, including medicine, sec-
ondary teaching, social work, and law enforcement. For those
considering a law degree, it is worth knowing that undergradu-
ate philosophy majors on average score higher than any other
major on the Law School Admission Test.4 (As I am writing
this, I currently have three former students attending top law
schools: one at Columbia Law School, another at NYU Law
School, and a third at the University of Michigan Law School.
Their parents must be thinking: “Oh, if only they had majored
in welding!”) Philosophy majors also have the highest average
score on the GRE Verbal and GRE Analytical Writing, and
are among the highest-scoring majors for the GMAT, the busi-
ness-school admissions test.5 Perhaps most impressively, phi-
losophy majors have the highest average probability of getting
admitted to medical school, better on average than any other
major, including biology and chemistry!6 We shouldn’t be sur-
prised that Darrell Kirch, MD, the CEO of the organization
that administers the Medical College Admission Test, was an
undergraduate philosophy major himself.7
What else do people who majored in philosophy do? A phi-
losophy major can be president of Morgan Stanley (Robert
Greenhill), founder and manager of a hedge fund (Don Brown-
stein), an investor (George Soros and Carl Icahn), CEO of
Overstock.com (my former Stanford classmate Patrick Byrne),
CEO of Time Warner (Gerald Levin), cofounder of PayPal
(Peter Thiel), a Supreme Court justice (Stephen Breyer and Da-
vid Souter), cofounder of Wikipedia (Larry Sanger), mayor of
Welders and Philosophers Z 113
PHILOSOPHY AND
DEMOCR ATIC CITIZENSHIP
the beginning was the Word, and the Word was with God, and
the Word was God,” where “Word” is logos [John 1:1, KJV].) The
Stoics argued that the best way of life is to live in accordance
with the natural law dictated by the reason that exists within
each of us. (Compare this with Romans 2:14–15: “For when the
Gentiles, which have not the law, do by nature the things con-
tained in the law, these, having not the law, are a law unto
themselves: Which shew the work of the law written in their
hearts” [KJV].)
If the philosophers are not responsible for the fall of Rome,
what is? Edward Gibbon (1737–94) argued in his classic The De-
cline and Fall of the Roman Empire that “the introduction, or at
least the abuse of Christianity” was a contributing factor to the
decline of the empire, because it preached “the happiness of a
future life” over political activity in this life.16 Indeed, Gibbon
claimed that the preference for the afterlife was so extreme
among Christians during the period of persecution that they
actively sought martyrdom, going unsummoned to the tribunal
to gratuitously confess their faith and demand to be executed.17
Gibbon editorialized that, after Christianity was legalized by
Emperor Constantine (r. 306–37), “the active virtues of society
were discouraged . . . the last remains of military spirit were
buried in the cloister” and the “sacred indolence of the monks
was devoutly embraced by a servile and effeminate age.” When
the Church did encourage activity, it was often counterproduc-
tive: “the church, and even the state, were distracted by religious
factions, whose conflicts were sometimes bloody and always
implacable.”18 Of course, Gibbon is not the last word on later
Roman history.19 But almost all serious historians would agree
with one point he makes: “instead of inquiring why the Roman
empire was destroyed, we should rather be surprised that it had
subsisted so long.”20 Rome fell for many complicated social, po-
Welders and Philosophers Z 119
Teddy Roosevelt (Phi Beta Kappa and Magna Cum Laude grad-
uate of Harvard), Hoover (who spoke Chinese and translated
the Renaissance work of metallurgy De Re Metallica out of
Latin), 29 Eisenhower (graduate of West Point, war hero, and
president of Columbia University), Nixon (who earned a degree
from a liberal arts college and then went on to law school), and
George H. W. Bush (Phi Beta Kappa at Yale). However, the GOP
has now become the party of B-movie actor Ronald Reagan
(who confessed that he could not remember whether he had vio-
lated his administration’s own policy by trading arms to Iran in
exchange for hostages),30 C-student George W. Bush (“They
misunderestimated me”),31 and D-list celebrity Donald Trump
(“I’m very highly educated. I know words, I have the best words.
I have the best, but there is no better word than stupid.”).32
What happened?
In his book Too Dumb to Fail, Lewis does an excellent job of
diagnosing some of the causes of the rising anti-intellectualism
of the GOP, including the need to please evangelical voters in
southern red states, who often believe, mistakenly, that Chris-
tianity is inconsistent with education and reflectiveness. In ev-
ery presidential election since 1980 (the year Reagan was first
elected), the Republican presidential candidate has won in the
Bible Belt states of Alabama, Mississippi, Oklahoma, South
Carolina, and Texas. But pleasing this constituency sometimes
leads to embarrassing results. None of the GOP candidates in
2016 would admit to believing in evolution. When Gov. Scott
Walker was in the running for the Republican presidential
nomination and visited the United Kingdom, he was ridiculed
by a BBC interviewer for evading a question about whether he
believed in evolutionary theory: “Any British politician, right-
or left-wing, would laugh and say, ‘Yes, of course evolution is
true.’ ”33 Ted Cruz also evaded questions about his views on the
122 Y Welders and Philosophers
topic. However, even though “the son will not bear the punish-
ment for the father’s iniquity” (Ezekiel 18:20, KJV), it is diffi-
cult not to quote Cruz’s father on this topic: “Communism and
evolution go hand and hand. Evolution is one of the strongest
tools of Marxism because if they can convince you that you
came from a monkey, it’s much easier to convince you that God
does not exist.”34 Finally, Rubio, when asked how old he thought
the Earth is, sounded like a student trying to bluff when he had
not done the reading:
I’m not a scientist, man. . . . At the end of the day, I think there
are multiple theories out there on how the universe was created
and I think this is a country where people should have the
opportunity to teach them all. I think parents should be able
to teach their kids what their faith says, what science says.
Whether the Earth was created in 7 days, or 7 actual eras, I’m
not sure we’ll ever be able to answer that. It’s one of the great
mysteries. 35
And when his disciples were come to the other side, they had
forgotten to take bread. Then Jesus said unto them, Take heed
and beware of the leaven of the Pharisees and of the Saddu-
cees. And they reasoned among themselves, saying, It is because
we have taken no bread. Which when Jesus perceived, he said
unto them, O ye of little faith, why reason ye among yourselves,
because ye have brought no bread? . . . How is it that ye do not
understand that I spake it not to you concerning bread, that ye
should beware of the leaven of the Pharisees and of the Saddu-
cees? Then understood they how that he bade them not beware of
the leaven of bread, but of the doctrine of the Pharisees and of
the Sadducees. (Matthew 16:5–12, KJV)
These are all liberal arts majors. Why would anyone think that
other liberal arts majors are more practical or employable or
economically valuable than philosophy? Do we imagine a busi-
nesswoman at the office confiding to a coworker: “That was close.
My son was going to be major in philosophy. Can you imagine?!
Thank God he switched his major to public policy. He’s going
to be raking in the big bucks now!” The only person on the stage
that night with a conventionally “practical” major was Donald
Trump, who studied economics (and subsequently led multiple
companies to bankruptcy and lost almost a billion dollars dur-
ing an economic boom).
When Rubio stood on a stage with a group of people who,
between them, have seven bachelor’s degrees (six of them in the
liberal arts), two JDs, an MBA, and two MDs, yet denigrated
liberal arts education, it sent a clear message to the electorate:
“We are highly educated; you should not be. We will get the educa-
tion and training that will allow us to effectively pursue our
goals; you don’t need information or practice in thinking objec-
tively or critically about the world. We will study something that
opens our minds and helps us to choose our own futures; you
should study something that makes you useful to the economic sys-
tem that we run.” A century ago, John Dewey warned of the dan-
gerous political implications of publicly funding only a narrow
vocational education: “This movement would continue the tradi-
tional liberal or cultural education for the few economically able
to enjoy it, and would give to the masses a narrow technical trade
education for specialized callings, carried on under the control of
others.” 45 This would make the educational system nothing but
“an instrument in accomplishing the feudal dogma of social pre-
destination” and for “transferring the older division of . . . directed
and directive class into a society nominally democratic.”46
128 Y Welders and Philosophers
better that such should be sought for and educated at the common
expence of all, than that the happiness of all should be confided
to the weak or wicked.51
PHILOSOPHY’S VALUE TO
CIVILIZATION
For our discussion is not about some ordinary matter, but the
way one should live.
—Socrates
T
o paraphrase Frost, I have a lover’s quarrel with aca-
demic philosophy. Although the narrow-mindedness
of many contemporary philosophers infuriates me, I
love philosophy itself: I love teaching it, and I love discussing it
with students and colleagues. I also recognize that academic
philosophy has a very distinctive role to play in higher educa-
tion, especially today. I’ve mentioned in earlier chapters that
philosophy teaches reading, writing, and reasoning, but in a
way that is distinctive from other disciplines. Let me explain
more clearly what I mean.
The Way of Confucius and Socr ates Z 139
SO WHAT IS PHILOSOPHY?
They’re like us. Do you suppose, first of all, that these prison-
ers see anything of themselves and one another besides the
shadows that the fire casts on the wall in front of them?
How could they, if they have to keep their heads motionless
throughout life. . . .
Then the prisoners would in every way believe that the truth
is nothing other than the shadows of those artifacts.
They must surely believe that.
Consider, then, what being released from their bonds and
cured of their ignorance would naturally be like. When one of
them was freed and suddenly compelled to stand up, turn his
head, walk, and look up toward the light, he’d be pained and
dazzled and unable to see the things whose shadows he’d seen
before. . . . And if someone dragged him away from there by
force, up the rough, steep path, and didn’t let him go until he
had dragged him into the sunlight, wouldn’t he be pained, and
irritated at being treated that way? And when he came into the
light, with the sun filling his eyes, wouldn’t he be unable to see a
single one of the things now said to be true?9
you do nothing, but will only kill one person if you pull a lever
redirecting the train?20 Should we explain the fact that some
sentences must be true (like “1 + 1 = 2”) while others only hap-
pen to be true (like “Obama won in 2012”) by postulating that
there are an infinite number of alternative possible universes,
each of them just as real as the one we inhabit, and that some
sentences are true in all of them, while other sentences are only
true in some of them?21 What evidence do we have that emeralds
are green rather than grue, where “grue” refers to anything we
observed up until today that is green, or to anything we did not
observe before today and is blue.22 The examples I have drawn
so far are from analytic philosophy, the style that is dominant
in the English-speaking world. However, Continental philosophy
is not immune to degrading into intellectual onanism. I think
that Martha Nussbaum’s comment about Jacques Derrida could
be applied to many other recent Continental thinkers:
Once one has worked through and been suitably (I think) im-
pressed by Derrida’s perceptive and witty analysis of Nietzsche’s
style, one feels, at the end of all the urbanity, an empty longing
amounting to a hunger, a longing for the sense of difficulty and
risk and practical urgency that are inseparable from Zarathus-
tra’s dance. . . . Nietzsche’s work is profoundly critical of existing
ethical theory, clearly; but it is, inter alia, a response to the origi-
nal Socratic question, “How should one live?” Derrida does not
touch on that question. . . . After reading Derrida, and not Der-
rida alone, I feel a certain hunger for blood; for, that is, writing
about literature that talks of human lives and choices as if they
matter to us at all.23
FOREWORD
1. Thomas Babington Macaulay, “Minutes on Education in India,” in Se-
lected Writings, ed. John Clive and Thomas Pinney (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1972), 241.
2. Nicholas Tampio, “Not All Things Wise and Good Are Philosophy,”
Aeon, September 13, 2016, https://aeon.co/ideas/not-all-things-wise
-and-good-are-philosophy.
3. Suzy Q. Groden, trans., The Symposium of Plato (Amherst: University of
Massachusetts Press, 1970), 61 (Stephanus 189e–190b).
4. Wilfred Sellars, “Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man” (1962),
quoted in “Wilfrid Sellars,” by Willem deVries, Stanford Encyclopedia
of Philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/
win2016/entries/sellars/.
1. A MANIFESTO FOR
MULTICULTURAL PHILOSOPHY
The epigraphs to chapter 1 are from Immanuel Kant, Physical Geogra-
phy, translated in Julia Ching, “Chinese Ethics and Kant,” Philosophy
East and West 28, no. 2 (April 1978): 169; and Martin Luther King, Jr.,
“Address Delivered at Poor People’s Campaign Rally” (March 19, 1968;
Clarksdale, Mississippi), cited in James Cone, Risks of Faith (Boston:
Beacon, 1999), 152n20 (original transcript of speech archived at the King
Center, Atlanta, GA, document 680323-02).
162 Y 1. A Manifesto for Multicultur al Philosophy
27. Jay Garfield and Bryan Van Norden, “If Philosophy Won’t Diversify, Let’s
Call It What It Really Is,” The Stone, blog, New York Times, May 11, 2016,
www.nytimes.com/2016/05/11/opinion/if-philosophy-wont-diversify-lets
-call-it-what-it-really-is.html.
28. “What’s Your Take on the Recent NYTimes Article Advocating Di-
versification in Philosophy Departments in the West?” www.reddit
.com /r /askphilosophy /comments /4j0un6 /whats_your_take_on_the_
recent_nytimes_article/. An especially insightful online response to
critics of our piece is Amy Olberding, “When Someone Suggests Ex-
panding the Canon,” http://dailynous.com/2016/05/13/when-someone
-suggests-expanding-the-canon/. Other interesting online discussions
(pro and con) include Brian Leiter, “Anglophone Departments Aren’t
‘Departments of European and American Philosophy,’” Leiter Reports:
A Philosophy Blog, May 11, 2016, http://leiterreports.typepad.com/blog
/2016 /05 /anglophone -departments -arent -departments -of -european
-and-american-philosophy.html; John Drabinski, “Diversity, ‘Neutral-
ity,’ Philosophy,” http://jdrabinski.com/2016/05/11/diversity-neutrality
-philosophy/; Meena Krishnamurthy, “Decolonizing Analytic Political
Philosophy,” Philosopher, blog, June 3, 2016, https://politicalphilosopher
.net/2016/06/03/meenakrishnamurthy/; and Justin Smith, “Garfield and
Van Norden on Non-European Philosophy,” www.jehsmith.com/1/2016
/05/garfield-and-van-norden-on-non-european-philosophy-.html.
29. Patricia McGuire, comment on Jay Garfield and Bryan Van Norden,
“If Philosophy Won’t Diversify, Let’s Call It What It Really Is,” New
York Times, www.nytimes.com/2016/05/11/opinion/if-philosophy-wont
-diversify-lets-call-it-what-it-really-is.html#permid=18491745.
30. Shawn (no last name supplied), comment on Jay Garfield and Bryan
Van Norden, “If Philosophy Won’t Diversify,” New York Times, www
.nytimes .com /2016 /05 /11 /opinion /if -philosophy -wont -diversify -lets
-call-it-what-it-really-is.html#permid=18491934.
31. George Joseph, The Crest of the Peacock: Non-European Roots of Math-
ematics, 3rd ed. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2010).
32. Josh Hill, comment on Jay Garfield and Bryan Van Norden, “If Phi-
losophy Won’t Diversify,” New York Times, www.nytimes.com/2016/05
/11/opinion/if-philosophy-wont-diversify-lets-call-it-what-it-really-is
.html#permid=18495750.
1. A Manifesto for Multicultur al Philosophy Z 167
51. D. Kyle Peon, “Yes—Let’s Call Philosophy What It Really Is,” Week-
ly Standard, May 19, 2016, www.weeklystandard.com/yes-lets-call
-philosophy-what-it-really-is/article/2002458.
52. Nicholas Tampio, “Not All Things Wise and Good Are Philoso-
phy,” Aeon, https://aeon.co/ideas/not-all-things-wise-and-good-are
-philosophy. See Jay Garfield’s foreword to this book for a detailed dis-
section of Tampio’s essay.
53. Christopher Cullen, Astronomy and Mathematics in Ancient China: The
Zhou Bi Suan Jing (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
54. Encyclopedia Britannica, 11th ed., s.v. “Siger De Brabant” (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1911).
55. Peter K. J. Park, Africa, Asia, and the History of Philosophy: Racism in the
Formation of the Philosophical Canon, 1780–1830 (Albany: State Univer-
sity of New York Press, 2013), 76.
56. Even if it turns out that, as a matter of historical fact, Greek philosophy
developed in complete isolation from Indian and African philosophy,
this would not demonstrate that the latter was not philosophy. The
important point to learn from Park is that it is not an a priori truth that
“all philosophy begins in Greece.”
57. David E. Mungello, The Great Encounter of China and the West, 1500–
1800, 3rd ed. (New York: Rowman and Littlefield, 2009), 100–4.
58. Leibniz, Introduction to Novissima Sinica (1697), cited in Franklin Per-
kins, Leibniz and China: A Commerce of Light (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2007), 146.
59. For discussions, see Robert Louden, “ ‘What Does Heaven Say?’ Chris-
tian Wolff and Western Interpretations of Confucian Ethics,” in Con-
fucius and the “Analects”: New Essays, ed. Bryan W. Van Norden (New
York: Oxford University Press, 2002), 73–93; and Donald F. Lach, “The
Sinophilism of Christian Wolff (1679–1754),” Journal of the History of
Ideas 14, no. 4 (October 1953): 561–74.
60. Mungello, The Great Encounter of China and the West, 128.
61. Derk Bodde, “Chinese Ideas in the West,” unpublished essay prepared
for the Committee on Asiatic Studies in American Education (March
9, 1948), http://afe.easia.columbia.edu/chinawh/web/s10/ideas.pdf.
(I am indebted to Mark Csikszentmihalyi for bringing Quesnay’s
interest in China to my attention.) On king Shun, see Analects 15.5.
1. A Manifesto for Multicultur al Philosophy Z 169
62. Ronald Reagan quoted Daodejing 60 in his State of the Union Address
on January 25, 1988, archived at The American Presidency Project, www
.presidency.ucsb.edu/ws/index.php?pid=36035.
63. Park, Africa, Asia, and the History of Philosophy, 69–95.
64. Edward Said, Orientalism (New York: Vintage, 1994), 73–92.
65. Kant AA xxv.2 1187–1188, cited in Mark Larrimore, “Sublime Waste:
Kant on the Destiny of the ‘Races,’” Canadian Journal of Philosophy,
supplemental volume 25 (1999): 111–12. I learned of Kant’s discussion of
race in his lectures on anthropology from an excellent talk by Peter
K. J. Park, “Kant’s Colonial Knowledge and His Greek Turn,” American
Philosophical Association, Baltimore, MD, January 6, 2017.
66. Immanuel Kant, Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and the Sub-
lime, ed. Patrick Frierson and Paul Guyer (New York: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 2011), 61. If you really want to be horrified, see the passage
from Hume that Kant approvingly quotes, ibid., 58n82.
67. Kant AA xxv.2 843, cited in Larrimore, “Sublime Waste,” 111.
68. Immanuel Kant, Physical Geography, translated in Ching, “Chinese
Ethics and Kant,” 169. All of us interested in Kant’s views on China
are deeply indebted to Helmuth von Glasenapp, ed., Kant und die Reli-
gionen des Ostens, Beihefte zum Jahrbuch der Albertus-Universität Königs-
berg/Pr. 5 (Kitzingen-Main: Holzner, 1954).
69. Immanuel Kant, Physical Geography, cited in Gregory M. Reihman,
“Categorically Denied: Kant’s Criticism of Chinese Philosophy,” Jour-
nal of Chinese Philosophy 11, no. 1 (March 2006): 63n22.
70. David E. Mungello, Drowning Girls in China: Female Infanticide Since
1650 (New York: Rowman and Littlefield, 2008), 3. Infanticide by drown-
ing (never hanging) was the preferred method in China, and it resulted
in a quick death, as opposed to the European preference for infanticide
by abandonment, which resulted in a slow, lingering death.
71. Ibid.
72. Mungello, The Great Encounter of China and the West, 134–39. For a
more detailed discussion see Mungello, Drowning Girls in China, 14–62.
Christian missionaries and Chinese Christian converts also took part in
charitable efforts to save children (99–115).
73. G. W. F. Hegel, Lectures on the History of Philosophy: Greek Philosophy
to Plato, trans. E. S. Haldane (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press,
170 Y 1. A Manifesto for Multicultur al Philosophy
1995), 121. In their brilliant The Nay Science: A History of German Indology
(New York: Oxford University Press, 2014), Vishwa Adluri and Joydeep
Bagchee note that Hegel was also seminal in expelling Indian philo-
sophical texts from the philosophical canon and relegating them solely
to philology and social history.
74. G. W. F. Hegel, Lectures on the Philosophy of History, trans. Ruben Al-
varado (Aalten, Netherlands: WordBridge, 2011), 124.
75. Theodor Mommsen, The History of Rome, trans. William Dickson, vol. 4
(New York: Scribner’s, 1887), 726.
76. Alston Hurd Chase, Time Remembered (San Antonio: Parker, 1994), 2.1,
www.pa59ers.com/library/Chase/time2–1n2.html.
77. Herbert Fingarette, Confucius—the Secular as Sacred (New York: Harp-
er, 1972), vii.
78. Martin Heidegger, What Is Philosophy? trans. William Kluback and Jean
T. Wilde (New York: Twayne, 1958), 29–31, cited in Park, Africa, Asia,
and the History of Philosophy, 4. Heidegger’s views on Asian philosophy
varied over the course of his career. At one point, he began to collabo-
rate on a translation of the Daodejing, which he said had anticipated
his own philosophical views. However, his final view of philosophy was
ethnocentric. See Taylor Carman and Bryan W. Van Norden, “Being-
in-the-Way: A Review of Heidegger and Asian Thought,” Sino-Platonic
Papers 70 (February 1996): 24–34.
79. Du Xiaozhen and Zhang Ning, Delida zai Zhongguo jiangyanlu [Lec-
tures by Derrida in China] (Beijing: Zhongyang Bianyi, 2002), 139, cited
in Carine Defoort and Ge Zhaoguang, “Editors’ Introduction,” Contem-
porary Chinese Thought 37, no. 1 (Fall 2005): 3 and 9n14.
80. Gayatri Spivak, “Translator’s Preface,” in Of Grammatology, by Jacques
Derrida, rev. ed. (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1998),
lxxxii. For a detailed critique of Derrida’s Orientalism, see Jin Suh
Jirn, “A Sort of European Hallucination: On Derrida’s ‘Chinese Preju-
dice,’” Situations 8, no. 2 (2015): 67–83.
81. Eugene Park, “Why I Left Academia: Philosophy’s Homogeneity
Needs Rethinking,” November 3, 2014, www.huffingtonpost.com/hippo
-reads/why-i-left-academia_b_5735320.html.
82. Said, Orientalism, 40.
83. Ibid., 38.
1. A Manifesto for Multicultur al Philosophy Z 17 1
2. TRADITIONS IN DIALOGUE
The epigraphs to chapter 2 are from Terence, The Self-Tormentor, act 1,
scene 1, and Confucius, Analects, 12.5.
49. Mengzi 7B16, in Ivanhoe and Van Norden, Readings in Classical Chinese
Philosophy, 155. More literally, the Chinese states “humaneness [rén ṩ]
is human [rén Ṣ].”
50. Martin L. Hoffman, Empathy and Moral Development (New York:
Cambridge University Press, 2001).
51. Charles Darwin, The Descent of Man (Amherst, NY: Prometheus, 1998),
pt. 1, chaps. 4–5, 100–38.
52. A classic essay on this topic is Robert L. Trivers, “The Evolution of
Reciprocal Altruism,” Quarterly Review of Biology 46 (1971): 35–57. Triv-
ers’s paper is often misinterpreted as arguing that seemingly altruistic
actions are actually self-interested; however, his actual view is that “the
emotion of sympathy has been selected to motivate altruistic behavior; . . .
crudely put, the greater the potential benefit to the recipient, the greater
the sympathy and the more likely the altruistic gesture, even to strange
or disliked individuals” (49, emphasis mine).
53. Mengzi 3B9, in Ivanhoe and Van Norden, Readings in Classical Chinese
Philosophy, 134–35.
54. Mengzi 1A7, in Ivanhoe and Van Norden, Readings in Classical Chinese
Philosophy, 122.
55. Analects 12.18, in Ivanhoe and Van Norden, Readings in Classical Chinese
Philosophy, 37.
56. Tiwald and Van Norden, Readings in Later Chinese Philosophy, 201.
“Substance” here is literally “body.” It is not being used in quite the
same sense as “substance” in the Western tradition, but the differences
are not important for grasping the basics of the argument.
57. Tiwald and Van Norden, Readings in Later Chinese Philosophy, 88.
“Dharma” here refers to an instance of one of the Five Aggregates.
58. For the Confucian critique, see Han Yu, “A Memorandum on a Bone
of the Buddha,” and Lu Xiangshan, “Letter to Wang Shunbo”; for a
Buddhist response, see Huiyuan, On Why Buddhist Monks Do Not Bow
Down Before Kings, all in Tiwald and Van Norden, Readings in Later
Chinese Philosophy.
59. Tiwald and Van Norden, Readings in Later Chinese Philosophy, 152.
60. Ibid., 174.
61. President Barack Obama, “Remarks by the President at a Campaign
Event in Roanoke, VA,” White House Office of the Press Secretary,
2. Tr aditions in Dialogue Z 177
79. Xunzi, “An Exhortation to Learning,” cited in Ivanhoe and Van Nor-
den, Readings in Classical Chinese Philosophy, 256. I think Confucius
himself viewed moral cultivation as re-formation, but this would be
heatedly disputed by many interpreters.
80. Xunzi, “Human Nature Is Bad,” cited in Ivanhoe and Van Norden,
Readings in Classical Chinese Philosophy, 298.
81. Xunzi, “An Exhortation to Learning,” cited in Ivanhoe and Van Nor-
den, Readings in Classical Chinese Philosophy, 260.
82. See Eric Schwitzgebel, “Human Nature and Moral Development in
Mencius, Xunzi, Hobbes, and Rousseau,” History of Philosophy Quarterly
24 (2007): 147–68. I borrow the terminology of “the what” and “the why”
of ethics from Myles Burnyeat, “Aristotle on Learning to Be Good,”
in Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. A. O. Rorty (Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1980), 69–92.
83. See Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Émile: Or On Education, trans. Allan Bloom
(New York: Basic, 1979); and Martha C. Nussbaum, Not for Profit: Why
Democracy Needs the Humanities (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
2012), 27–46 (passim).
84. Mengzi 1A7, in Ivanhoe and Van Norden, Readings in Classical Chinese
Philosophy, 119.
85. Mengzi 1A7, in Ivanhoe and Van Norden, Readings in Classical Chinese
Philosophy, 120.
86. David Wong, “Reasons and Analogical Reasoning in Mengzi,” in Es-
says on the Moral Philosophy of Mengzi, ed. Xiusheng Liu and Philip
J. Ivanhoe (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2002), 187–220.
87. This is suggested by the seminal essay on this passage, David S. Nivison,
“Motivation and Moral Action in Mencius,” in The Ways of Confucian-
ism, ed. Bryan W. Van Norden (La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1996), 91–119.
88. Mozi 45, “Lesser Selections,” translation mine but see Nivison, “Mo-
tivation and Moral Action in Mencius,” 97–98, for the comparison of
Mengzi’s use of the term and the Mohist one.
89. Edward Slingerland argues plausibly that “In order to engage in or
guide an abstract process such as education or self-cultivation, we must
inevitably make reference to some sort of metaphorical schema, and the
schema we invoke will have entailments that will serve as important
determinants of our practical behavior.” Slingerland, Effortless Action:
180 Y 2. Tr aditions in Dialogue
Xi, Lunyu jizhu, commentary on Analects 9.18, cited in Tiwald and Van
Norden, Readings in Later Chinese Philosophy, 191n44.
98. One might argue that this example is intrinsically sexist. It certainly
assumes what critic Laura Mulvey referred to as “the male gaze,” in
her classic essay “Visual Pleasure and Narrative Cinema,” Screen 16,
no. 3 (1975): 6–18. The authors of the Great Learning and over two mil-
lennia of Confucian commentators typically envisioned the “lovely
sight” in question as a beautiful woman, a woman who was excluded
from higher education and public office, and whose sexuality was a po-
tentially dangerous distraction from Virtue. However, the situation is
more complex than it appears at first. Generations of Confucians were
quite aware that many an emperor was led to disaster by the influence
of a handsome male lover. Furthermore, both male and female readers
today can sympathize with the example of being drawn to someone
erotically, even though they will conceptualize it according to their
own tastes.
99. Wang Yangming, “Questions on the Great Learning,” cited in Tiwald
and Van Norden, Readings in Later Chinese Philosophy, 241–42 (glosses
in original translation).
100. There is a classic debate in ethics over unity vs. conflict as ideals of
psychological health. When Jesus demands that a demon name itself,
it replies, “My name is Legion: for we are many” (Mark 5:9, KJV). This
suggests that the evil are divided within themselves. On the other hand,
Walt Whitman celebrates psychic conflict when he asks, “Do I contra-
dict myself ? / Very well then I contradict myself, / (I am large, I contain
multitudes.)” “Song of Myself.”
101. Cheng Yi, Er Chengji (Beijing: Zhonghua shuju, 2004), 1:16, cited in
Tiwald and Van Norden, Readings in Later Chinese Philosophy, 159.
102. Great Learning, classic, in Tiwald and Van Norden, Readings in Later
Chinese Philosophy, 189 (emphasis mine).
103. Zhu Xi, Zhuzi yulei (Beijing: Zhonghua shuju, 1986), 1:148, cited in
Tiwald and Van Norden, Readings in Later Chinese Philosophy, 181.
104. David S. Nivison was the first to note the significance of weakness of
will as an issue in Chinese philosophy. See especially “The Philosophy
of Wang Yangming,” in The Ways of Confucianism, by David S. Nivison,
ed. Bryan W. Van Norden (Chicago: Open Court, 1996), 249–60.
182 Y 2. Tr aditions in Dialogue
105. Wang Yangming, A Record for Practice (Chuan xi lu), §5, cited in Tiwald
and Van Norden, Readings in Later Chinese Philosophy, 267.
106. Wang Yangming, A Record for Practice, §5, cited in Tiwald and Van
Norden, Readings in Later Chinese Philosophy, 267.
107. One of the classic Western essays on internalism is Donald David-
son, “How Is Weakness of the Will Possible?” in Essays on Actions and
Events, 2nd ed. (New York: Clarendon, 2001), 21–42. Intriguingly, Da-
vidson thanks David S. Nivison, a leading scholar of Chinese philoso-
phy, in the acknowledgments to this anthology (xx).
108. Wang Yangming, A Record for Practice, §5, cited in Tiwald and Van Norden,
Readings in Later Chinese Philosophy, 267 (italics in original translation).
109. Frank Jackson, “Epiphenomenal Qualia,” Philosophical Quarterly 32, no.
127 (1982): 127–36.
110. Wang Yangming, A Record for Practice, §5, cited in Tiwald and Van
Norden, Readings in Later Chinese Philosophy, 268.
111. Wang Yangming, A Record for Practice, §5, cited in Tiwald and Van
Norden, Readings in Later Chinese Philosophy, 268 (glosses in original
translation).
112. Nivison, “The Philosophy of Wang Yangming,” 218.
113. Wang Yangming, A Record for Practice, §5, cited in Tiwald and Van
Norden, Readings in Later Chinese Philosophy, 268.
114. Eric Schwitzgebel, “The Moral Behavior of Ethicists and the Role of
the Philosopher,” in Experimental Ethics, ed. H. Rusch, M. Uhl, and
C. Luetge (New York: Palgrave, 2014); Schwitzgebel, “Do Ethicists
Steal More Books?” Philosophical Psychology 22 (2009): 711–25; Schwit-
zgebel, “Are Ethicists Any More Likely to Pay Their Registration Fees
at Professional Meetings?” Economics and Philosophy 29 (2013): 371–80;
Eric Schwitzgebel and Joshua Rust, “The Moral Behavior of Ethics
Professors: Relationships Among Self-Reported Behavior, Expressed
Normative Attitude, and Directly Observed Behavior,” Philosophical
Psychology 27 (2014): 293–327; Schwitzgebel and Rust, “Do Ethicists and
Political Philosophers Vote More Often Than Other Professors?” Re-
view of Philosophy and Psychology 1 (2010): 189–99; Schwitzgebel and
Rust, “The Self-Reported Moral Behavior of Ethics Professors,” Philo-
sophical Psychology 27 (2014): 293–327; Schwitzgebel and Rust, “Ethicists’
and Non-Ethicists’ Responsiveness to Student Emails: Relationships
Among Expressed Normative Attitude, Self-Described Behavior, and
3. Trump’s Philosophers Z 183
3. TRUMP’S PHILOSOPHERS
The epigraphs to chapter 3 are from Donald J. Trump, Announcement
of Presidential Candidacy, June 16, 2015, New York, NY; Mao Zedong,
“Mount Liupan,” translation mine but see Willis Barnstone, ed., The
Poems of Mao Zedong (Los Angeles: University of California Press,
1972), 68–69 for the Chinese text and an alternative translation; Richard
Nixon, “Exchange with Reporters at the Great Wall of China,” Febru-
ary 24, 1972. (In context, Nixon’s comment is not as silly as it sounds.)
2. Days after the election, Trump acknowledged that it could be “part wall,
part fence” (interview with Lesley Stahl, “The 45th President,” 60 Minutes,
aired November 13, 2016). A few weeks after that, he admitted that parts
of the border do not need a wall “because you have, you know, you have
mountains, you have other things” (interview with Sean Hannity, Fox
News, December 1, 2016, http://insider.foxnews.com/2016/12/01/donald
-trump-hannity-his-election-victory-message-protesters). This version
of Trump’s plan would involve no change from current policy, since the
border already has a combination of walls, fences, and natural barriers.
3. Trump, Announcement of Presidential Candidacy.
4. Ana Gonzalez-Barrera, “Migration Flows Between the US and Mexico
Have Slowed—and Turned Toward Mexico,” Pew Research Center, No-
vember 19, 2015, www.pewhispanic.org/2015/11/19/chapter-1-migration
-flows-between-the-u-s-and-mexico-have-slowed-and-turned-toward
-mexico/#number-of-unauthorized-mexican-immigrants-declines.
5. Richard Pérez-Peña, “Contrary to Trump’s Claims, Immigrants Are
Less Likely to Commit Crimes,” New York Times, January 26, 2017, www
.nytimes.com/2017/01/26/us/trump-illegal-immigrants-crime.html.
6. The prevalence of the us vs. them mindset is illustrated by a comment
from Representative Robert Pittenger (R, NC). When asked what mo-
tivated those who protested a police shooting in Charlotte, he asserted:
“The grievance in their minds is—the animus, the anger—they hate
white people because white people are successful and they’re not.” “NC
Congressman: ‘Protestors Hate White People Because They’re Suc-
cessful,’” New York Post, September 22, 2016, http://nypost.com/2016
/09/22/nc-congressman-protesters-hate-white-people-because-theyre
-successful/. (Videos and photographs show what is clearly a multira-
cial group of protestors.)
7. Since the election, some conservatives have crowed that Trump’s vic-
tory shows how out of touch the intellectual elite is with mainstream
America. See Charles C. Camosy, “Trump Won Because College-Edu-
cated Americans Are out of Touch,” Washington Post, November 9, 2016,
www.washingtonpost.com/posteverything/wp/2016/11/09/trump-won
-because-college-educated-americans-are-out-of-touch/. However, the
reality is that 53 percent of those who voted opposed Donald Trump,
Clinton won the plurality of the popular vote, and she won “big league”
3. Trump’s Philosophers Z 185
among both Americans under thirty and people of color (who consti-
tute the fastest-growing share of the US population). The future does
not look bright for those who supported Trump.
8. Bob Herbert, “Righting Reagan’s Wrongs?” New York Times, November
13, 2007, www.nytimes.com/2007/11/13/opinion/13herbert.html.
9. Alexander P. Lamis, ed., Southern Politics in the 1990s (Baton Rouge:
Louisiana State University Press, 1999), 8. The Atwater interview was
not noticed by the mainstream media until it was cited in an edito-
rial by Bob Herbert, “Impossible, Ridiculous, Repugnant,” New York
Times, October 6, 2005, www.nytimes.com/2005/10/06/opinion/impos-
sible-ridiculous-repugnant.html. The audio recording of the interview
is archived at Rick Perlstein, “Exclusive: Lee Atwater’s Infamous 1981
Interview on the Southern Strategy,” Nation, November 13, 2012, www
.thenation.com/article/exclusive-lee-atwaters-infamous-1981-interview
-southern-strategy/.
10. Andrew Jacobs, “Confucius Statue Vanishes Near Tiananmen Square,”
New York Times, April 22, 2011, www.nytimes.com/2011/04/23/world/
asia/23confucius.html.
11. I have visited Mao’s mausoleum on several occasions. On each visit, I
have been told that the body is not available for viewing because it is be-
ing “cleaned.” I am beginning to think that he just doesn’t want to see me.
12. Chris Buckley, “Mocking Mao Backfires for Chinese TV Host,” Sino-
sphere, blog, New York Times, April 9, 2015, http://sinosphere.blogs
.nytimes .com /2015 /04 /09 /joking -about -mao -lands -tv -host -in -hot
-water/.
13. Nonetheless, the amount of support for Mao, at least as a symbol, is
often surprising to first-time visitors to China. A nontrivial number of
young people, who have no firsthand knowledge of the Cultural Revo-
lution, actually seem nostalgic about it. See Kiki Zhao, “Graduates’ Red
Guard Photos Cast Doubts on What They Learned,” Sinosphere, blog,
New York Times, June 26, 2014, http://sinosphere.blogs.nytimes.com
/2014 /06 /26 /graduates -red -guard -photos -cast -doubt -on -what -they
-learned/. I have even met intellectuals who were “rusticated” during
the Cultural Revolution (sent to do hard labor in the countryside) who
feel that China under Mao had a positive moral spirit that is lacking in
China today.
186 Y 3. Trump’s Philosophers
14. Paul Gewirtz, “Xi, Mao, and China’s Search for a Usable Past,” China
File, January 14, 2014, www.chinafile.com/reporting-opinion/viewpoint
/xi-mao-and-chinas-search-usable-past.
15. See, for example, Charles Taylor, The Ethics of Authenticity (Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1992).
16. Fu Danni, “Life Is Meaningless, Say China’s Top Students,” Sixth Tone,
November 23, 2016, www.sixthtone.com/news/life-meaningless-say
-china’s-top-students.
17. This is very similar to the view developed in Mengzi 6A15, cited in
Philip J. Ivanhoe and Bryan W. Van Norden, eds., Readings in Classical
Chinese Philosophy, 2nd ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2005), 151.
18. Milan Kundera, The Book of Laughter and Forgetting, trans. Aaron Asher
(New York: Harper Perennial, 1996), 4.
19. I originally developed the ideas in the preceding paragraph in
“Zhuangzi’s Ironic Detachment and Political Commitment,” Dao 15,
no. 1 (March 2016): 1–17.
20. I was the only philosopher at the conference who was not Chinese.
When I showed my son the official group photograph of the confer-
ence, he quipped, “Where’s Waldo?”
21. Chris Buckley and Didi Tatlow, “Cultural Revolution Steeled a Schoolboy,
Now China’s Leader,” New York Times, September 25, 2015, www.nytimes
.com/2015/09/25/world/asia/xi-jinping-china-cultural-revolution.html.
After the Cultural Revolution, Xi studied chemical engineering and later
earned an LLD from Tsinghua University (the MIT of China).
22. ㆹ奱⼿ㆹẔ㖞恋ᶨẋ曺⸜ㆸ攧Ⰽ⌮⯙㗗乊⌓ℝ㖞ẋ嶇䛨㽨≐炻恋㗗ᶨ
䥵ね互炻恋㗗ᶨ䥵㯃⚜烊⇘Ḯ㔯⊾朑␥䎮゛䟜䀕炻㚨⎶⎀⼿䓂军㗗ᶨ䥵
嘂㖈䘬ˤ(⣖奮˪᷄㕡㖞䨢˫䚩⥼Ḏ存䲣↿ᶻ孧:Ḉ㏆⸛) November 16,
2003, http://news.sina.com.cn/c/2003–11–16/11182145564.shtml. My
thanks to Professor Wu Wanwei for locating the Chinese original of
this quotation. English translation from Jonathan Watts, “Choice
of ‘Princeling’ as the Country’s Next President Came as a Shock to
Many,” Guardian, October 26, 2007, www.theguardian.com/world/2007
/oct/26/china.uknews4.
23. Max Fisher, “Trump, Taiwan and China: The Controversy, Explained,”
New York Times, December 3, 2016, www.nytimes.com/2016/12/03/
world/asia/trump-taiwan-and-china-the-controversy-explained.html.
3. Trump’s Philosophers Z 187
24. See Chris Buckley, “Xi Touts Communist Party as Defender of Confu-
cius’s Virtues,” Sinosphere, blog, New York Times, February 13, 2014, http:
//sinosphere.blogs.nytimes.com/2014/02/13/xi-touts-communist-party
-as-defender-of-confuciuss-virtues/.
25. Xi Jinping, How to Read Confucius and Other Chinese Classical Think-
ers, ed. Fenzhi Zhang ( Jericho, NY: CN Times Books, 2015), 55. (This
book consists of brief excerpts from Xi’s speeches where he mentions
classical Chinese texts, along with the editor’s comments.) Xi is quot-
ing Analects 2:1; translation from Ivanhoe and Van Norden, Readings in
Classical Chinese Philosophy, 5. On the Confucian emphasis on rule by
moral suasion rather than brute force, see chapter 2.
26. Xi, How to Read Confucius, 101–2. Xi was quoting the Great Learning,
commentary 3, which states that the sage-king Tang had the follow-
ing phrase inscribed on his bathtub: “Genuinely renew yourself daily.
Day by day renew yourself, and continue to do so each day.” As Zhu Xi
(1130–1200) explains, the sage meant that “people cleanse their minds to
remove evil just like they bathe their bodies to remove dirt.” See Zhu
Xi, Daxue jizhu (translation mine).
27. Xi, How to Read Confucius, 264–65. Xi is quoting Analects 2.4; translation
from Ivanhoe and Van Norden, Readings in Classical Chinese Philosophy,
5. He does exactly the same thing with the phrase “at fifty, I understood
Heaven’s mandate” (also from Analects 2.4) in commemorating the fif-
tieth anniversary of the establishment of diplomatic relations between
China and France (Xi, How to Read Confucius, 168–69).
28. Xi, How to Read Confucius, 185–86. Xi is quoting Analects 13.20; transla-
tion from Ivanhoe and Van Norden, Readings in Classical Chinese Phi-
losophy, 40.
29. Mengzi 4B11, cited in Ivanhoe and Van Norden, Readings in Classical
Chinese Philosophy, 139.
30. Kant, “On a Supposed Right to Lie Because of Philanthropic Con-
cern,” in Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. James W. El-
lington, 3rd ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993).
31. Ḉ㏆⸛, “曺⸜天冒奱嶝埴䣦Ểᷣᷱ㟠⽫ẟῤ奪.” Translation mine. These
quotations are largely drawn from the Analects of Confucius, and
the Mengzi, but some are from other classics, including the Classic of
Changes and Record of Rites.
188 Y 3. Trump’s Philosophers
Presidential Candidate (New York: Simon and Schuster, 2015), 241. Bush
the Younger and Trump are not isolated incidents. See Daniel Golden, The
Price of Admission (New York: Broadway, 2007) for an exposé of how
the wealthy routinely buy admission into elite colleges for their children.
54. Award-winning author Jennine Capó Crucet, the first person in her
family to attend college, explains how absolutely incomprehensible and
terrifying everything about college was to her and her family, including
things so obvious to most students that they are never explained. “Tak-
ing My Parents to College,” New York Times, August 22, 2015, http://nyti
.ms/1Lr81YG.
55. Hendrik Hertzberg, “Buckley, Vidal, and the ‘Queer’ Question,” New
Yorker, July 31, 2015, www.newyorker.com/news/daily-comment/buckley
-vidal-and-the-queer-question.
56. White House Press Briefing by Deputy Press Secretary Larry Speakes,
October 15, 1982. See the brief documentary film with the audio of the
exchange by Scott Calonic, “When AIDS Was Funny,” December 1,
2015, http://video.vanityfair.com/watch/the-reagan-administration-s
-chilling-response-to-the-aids-crisis.
57. The statement was in a direct mailing sent out over the signature of
Gregory T. Angelo, president of the Log Cabin Republicans (a pro-
LGBT conservative group), cited in Steve Rothaus, “Log Cabin Re-
publicans: Party Passes ‘Most Anti-LBGT Platform’ in GOP History,”
Miami Herald, July 12, 2016, www.miamiherald.com/news/local/com-
munity/gay-south-florida/article89235362.html.
58. Will Drabold, “Here’s What Mike Pence Said on LGBT Issues Over
the Years,” Time, July 15, 2016, http://time.com/4406337/mike-pence
-gay-rights-lgbt-religious-freedom/.
59. See Saul Bellow, Ravelstein (New York: Penguin, 2001). Bellow, who
wrote the foreword to The Closing of the American Mind, explicitly stated
in interviews that Bloom is the model for the title character of this ro-
man à clef.
60. D. T. Max, “With Friends Like Saul Bellow,” New York Times, April 16,
2000, www.nytimes.com/2000/04/16/magazine/with-friends-like-saul
-bellow.html. This review is an informative and insightful discussion
of the general issue of the relationship between Bloom and Bellow’s
Ravelstein.
4. Welders and Philosophers Z 191
/a-harvard-medical-school-professor-makes-the-case-for-the-liberal
-arts-and-philosophy/.
9. In chapter 5, I shall discuss the distinctive contribution that philosophy
makes to the humanities and social sciences.
10. Examples include Yuanpei College of Peking University, College of
Arts and Sciences of the University of Tokyo, Ashoka University, Delhi,
College of Liberal Studies of Seoul National University, S. H. Ho Col-
lege of the Chinese University of Hong Kong, and Yale-NUS College
in Singapore. See Sergei Klebnikov, “The Rise of Liberal Arts Colleges
in Asia,” Forbes, June 3, 2015, www.forbes.com/sites/sergeiklebnikov
/2015/06/03/the-rise-of-liberal-arts-colleges-in-asia/. A representative
view is expressed by Po Chung, cofounder of the multinational corpo-
ration DHL, who explained that the liberal arts education he received
at Whittier College in the United States paid off in his career in ways
that he never expected. Consequently, he is now an ardent supporter of
the growing liberal arts programs in Hong Kong (“How General Edu-
cation Can Sharpen Hong Kong’s Edge,” South China Morning Post,
October 23, 2012).
11. “Transcript: Marco Rubio: ‘I Ask the American People, Do Not Give
in to Fear,’” Los Angeles Times, March 15, 2016, www.latimes.com/politics
/la-pol-prez-marco-rubio-speech-transcript-20160315-story.html.
12. Donovan Slack, “Whoops! Carly Fiorina Falls off Stage,” USA Today,
May 2, 2016, www.usatoday.com/story/news/politics/onpolitics/2016/05
/02/whoops-carly-fiorina-falls-ted-cruz/83831470/.
13. Phil Mattingly, “Ben Carson’s Longshot Presidential Bid Sudden-
ly Looks a Lot More Realistic,” Bloomberg Politics, October 15, 2014,
www.bloomberg .com /politics /articles /2014–10–15 /carsons -longshot
-presidential-bid-suddenly-looks-a-lot-more-realistic.
14. For discussions, see R. Bett, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Ancient
Skepticism (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2010); John Cooper,
“Arcesilaus: Socratic and Sceptic,” in Knowledge, Nature, and the Good:
Essays on Ancient Philosophy (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
2004); and Katja Vogt, “Ancient Skepticism,” Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, Fall 2015 ed., ed. Edward N. Zalta, http://plato.stanford.edu
/archives/fall2015/entries/skepticism-ancient/.
15. For discussions of the various Western philosophical schools in this era,
4. Welders and Philosophers Z 193
28. On Lincoln’s fondness for Euclid, see David Herbert Donald, Lincoln
(New York: Simon and Schuster, 1996), 142–43; and Henry Ketcham,
The Life of Abraham Lincoln (New York: A. L. Burt, 1901), 64–65. For the
influence of Pericles on Lincoln, see Garry Wills, Lincoln at Gettysburg
(New York: Simon and Schuster, 1992).
29. See Patricia Zengerle, “Huntsman Wouldn’t Be the Only U.S. Presi-
dent to Speak Chinese,” Reuters, January 9, 2012, http://blogs.reuters
.com/talesfromthetrail/2012/01/09/huntsman-wouldnt-be-the-only-u
-s-president-to-speak-chinese/, and Georgius Agricola, De Re Metal-
ica, trans. Herbert Hoover and Lou Henry Hoover (New York: Dover,
1950).
30. President Ronald Reagan, Televised Speech from the Oval Office,
March 4, 1987. Reagan also believed that the Chernobyl nuclear accident
fulfilled a prophecy in the Bible. Lou Cannon, President Reagan: The
Role of a Lifetime, rev. ed. (New York: Public Affairs, 2000), 679. Haines
Johnson probably gives the best overall assessment of Reagan: “He was
much more than he seemed to his detractors, who continually dispar-
aged him, and much less than his partisan followers believed him to
be.” Johnson, Sleepwalking Through History: America in the Reagan Years,
rev. ed. (New York: Anchor, 1992), 41.
31. George W. Bush, Campaign Speech at Bentonville, Arkansas, Novem-
ber 6, 2000.
32. Donald J. Trump, Campaign Rally in Hilton Head Island, SC, Novem-
ber 25, 2016, video archived at http://dailycaller.com/2015/12/30/trump
-i-know-words-i-have-the-best-words-obama-is-stupid-video/. As if to
prove my point that the Democratic and Republican parties have traded
identities, Trump has hung a portrait of Andrew Jackson in the Oval Of-
fice, and laid a wreath on Jackson’s grave. Jamelle Bouie, “Donald Trump
Sees Himself in Andrew Jackson,” Slate, March 15, 2017, http://www.slate
.com/articles/news_and_politics/politics/2017/03/donald_trump_sees_
himself_in_andrew_jackson_they_deserve_one_another.html.
33. Francis Perraudin, “Scott Walker Dodges Question About Evolu-
tion Beliefs During Trade Visit to UK,” Guardian, February 11, 2015,
www.theguardian .com /politics /2015 /feb /11 /scott -walker -special
-relationship-trade-cheese-republican-chris-christie.
34. Brian Tashman, “Rafael Cruz: Evolution Is a Communist Lie,” Right
4. Welders and Philosophers Z 195
56. Drake, Discoveries and Opinions of Galileo, 252–256. Galileo couches his
point in hypothetical terms, but this is presumably because he was wary
of making unqualified assertions that would get him in trouble with the
Inquisition.
57. “Rapport fait a l’Académie Royale des Sciences, par MM. Fougerous,
Cadet & Lavoisier, d’une observation, communiquée par M. l’abbé
Bachela, sur une Pierre qu’on pretend être tombée du ciel pendant un or-
age,” Observations sur la Physique ( June 1772): 63–76, cited in Matt Salus-
bury, “Meteor Man,” Fortean Times 265 (August 2010), http://mattsalusbury
.blogspot.com/2010/08/meteor-man-from-fortean-times-265.html.
58. Arthur Fine, The Shaky Game: Einstein, Realism, and the Quantum
Theory, 2nd ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996).
59. Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, trans. Walter Kaufman (New York:
Vintage, 1989), §18, 24.
60. Thomas Kuhn, The Copernican Revolution (Cambridge: Harvard Uni-
versity Press, 1957), 117. For more on medieval Scholastic criticisms and
refinements of Aristotle’s view, see ibid., 115–23.
61. Jaroslav Pelikan, The Vindication of Tradition (New Haven: Yale Univer-
sity Press, 1984), 16.
62. Bertrand Russell, The Problems of Philosophy (Indianapolis: Hackett,
1990), 155.
63. Matt Warman, “Stephen Hawking Tells Google ‘Philosophy Is
Dead,’ ” Telegraph, May 17, 2011, www.telegraph.co.uk/technology/google
/8520033/Stephen-Hawking-tells-Google-philosophy-is-dead.html. I
have a philosophical colleague who was at a public lecture that Hawk-
ing gave on the problem of free will and determinism. He said he was
honored to have been invited, but wanted to slink out in embarrassment
after hearing the talk. He explained: “If Hawking’s talk were turned in
as an essay in a freshman philosophy course, it would have earned a B+
at best.” Sounds like Stephen should keep his day job.
64. This distinction comes from Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific
Revolutions, 3rd ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996).
65. Albert Einstein, Letter to Thornton, December 7, 1944, Einstein Ar-
chive, 61–574.
66. Erwin Schrödinger, Nature and the Greeks (New York: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 1996), 95.
198 Y 4. Welders and Philosophers
67. It goes without saying that I just used the rhetorical device of apophasis.
68. John Cleese, “Ideas Transform,” public service announcements by
John Cleese in honor of the hundredth anniversary of the American
Philosophical Association, 2000, www.publicphilosophy.org/media/100
YearsofPhilosophyInAmerica/18-IdeasTransform.mp3.
17. Bernard Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Cambridge: Har-
vard University Press, 1985), 1.
18. Hillary Putnam, Reason, Truth, and History (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press: 1981), 1–21.
19. Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (New York: Oxford University Press,
1986), 199–201.
20. Philippa Foot, “The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of the Dou-
ble Effect,” in Virtues and Vices (New York: Clarendon, 1993), 19–32.
21. David Lewis, On the Plurality of Worlds (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1986).
22. Nelson Goodman, Fact, Fiction, and Forecast, 4th ed. (Cambridge: Har-
vard University Press, 1983), chap. 3, “The New Riddle of Induction.”
23. Martha Nussbaum, Love’s Knowledge: Essays on Philosophy and Litera-
ture (New York: Oxford University Press, 1990), 171.
24. Bryan W. Van Norden, “Unweaving the ‘One Thread’ of Analects 4.15,”
in Confucius and the “Analects”: New Essays (New York: Oxford Univer-
sity Press, 2002), 216–36.
25. Bertrand Russell, The Problems of Philosophy (Indianapolis: Hackett,
1990), 161.
26. Bertrand Russell, The Autobiography of Bertrand Russell (London:
Unwin, 1975), 149. Russell also discussed how important the poetry of
Shelley (35) and Blake (55) had been to him.
27. That such a horrible experience of a friend’s suffering could have a posi-
tive effect on one’s character illustrates Iris Murdoch’s insight that “the
kind of suffering which brings wisdom cannot be named and cannot
without blasphemy be prayed for.” Murdoch, The Nice and the Good
(New York: Penguin, 1978), 56.
28. Plato, Seventh Letter, in Paul Friedländer, Plato: An Introduction (Princ-
eton: Princeton University Press, 1973), 5. Some question whether the Sev-
enth Letter is authentic; see, for example, Myles Burnyeat and Michael
Frede, The Pseudo-Platonic Seventh Letter, ed. Dominic Scott (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2015). However, I am inclined to agree with my
old teacher, Charles Kahn, that the arguments against its authenticity
are unpersuasive. See Kahn, review of Buryneat and Frede, The Pseudo-
Platonic Seventh Letter, Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, November 9,
2015, http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/62135-the-pseudo-platonic-seventh-letter/.
5. The Way of Confucius and Socr ates Z 201
29. Iain King, “Thinkers at War: John Rawls,” Military History Monthly,
June 13, 2014, www.military-history.org/articles/thinkers-at-war-john
-rawls.htm.
30. John Rawls, “Fifty Years After Hiroshima,” Dissent (Summer 1995),
www.dissentmagazine.org/article/50-years-after-hiroshima-2.
31. Ved Mehta, The Fly and the Fly-Bottle: Encounters with British Intellectu-
als (New York: Columbia University Press, 1983), 50.
32. James Stockdale, “The World of Epictetus,” in Vice and Virtue in Every-
day Life, 3rd ed., ed. Christina Sommers and Fred Sommers (New York:
Harcourt, Brace, Jovanovich, 1993), 658–74.
33. See chapter 4.
34. See chapter 3.
35. Stockdale, “World of Epictetus,” 670–71.
36. King, A Testament of Hope: The Essential Writings and Speeches of Martin
Luther King, Jr., ed. James M. Washington (New York: HarperCollins,
1986), 372.
37. Ibid., 291.
38. Ibid., 46–48.
39. Plato, Apology, 38a (translation mine).
INDEX
Dole, Bob (Robert), 126 filial piety, xvi, 6, 58, 60, 77–78,
Drabinski, John, 166n28 149
Du Bois, W. E. B., 1 Fingarette, Herbert, 24, 175n46
Duhem, Pierre, 13, 134 Fiorina, Carly, 2, 116, 126
Durkheim, Emile, 91 Five Aggregates, 44–49, 176n57;
Dussel, Enrique, 33–34 defined, 43
Flanagan, Owen, 164n20
egoism, 52, 55, 61, 68, 174–75n36 Foot, Philippa, 178n72; runaway
Einstein, Albert, 132, 133; on value train example of, 151–52, 153
of philosophy, 2, 134, 137 Ford, Harrison. See Regarding
Eisenhower, Dwight D., 121 Henry
Epictetus, 31, 126, 156 fortune cookies, xiii, 12, 147
Epicurus, 117 Foucault, Michel, 13, 136
ethics, 5–6, 19–20, 26, 32, 39, 80–81, Freud, Sigmund, 136
83, 115, 135, 137, 144, 149, 153, 154, Frost, Robert, 138
179n82, 181n100; meta-, 14, 26, Fung, Yu-lan, 180n96
58, 70–72, 78, 180n93; utilitarian,
135–36, 155–56. See also virtue; Gadamer, Hans-Georg, 149–50
weakness of will Galileo Galilei, 130–31, 132, 134,
ethnocentrism: examples of, xiii, 197n56
xiv, 11–16 (passim), 21–27, 34, Gandhi, Mahatma, 33, 98
103–4, 188n38. See also racism Garfield, Jay, xi–xxi, xxiii–xxv
Euclid, 17, 120 (passim), 8–10, 16, 35, 36, 44,
evolutionary theory, 120, 121–22; on 165n22, 174n29
origin of altruistic motivations, Geertz, Clifford, 113
56–57, 176n52. Gervais, Ricky, 113
existentialism, 64, 135. See also Gewirtz, Paul, 91
Beauvoir, Simone de; Camus, Gibbon, Edward, 118
Albert; Sartre, Jean-Paul Gleick, James, 174n32
God. See theism
Fanon, Frantz, 10 Goodman, Charles, xxiv, 163n6
Fazang, 14, 49–50, 58–59, 174n29 Goodman, Nelson, 83; “grue”
feminist philosophy, 3, 14, 25, 27, 33, paradox of, 152
41, 82, 117, 119–20, 149, 154, Gore, Al (Albert), 119
193n26. See also sexism Graham, Angus C., 165n23, 177n64,
Feyerabend, Paul, 13 198n2
208 Y Index
Mengzi, 5, 6, 20, 29, 31, 81, 83, 105, language competence objection,
171n88, 187n31; on human nature 33–34; nonexistence objection,
and political philosophy, 14, xiii, xviii–xix, 5–7, 14, 29,
54–57, 176n49; on ethical 143–44, 149; quality objection,
cultivation, 66, 67–69; on xiv, 5–7, 12–16, 108, 147–48. See
normative ethics, 95, 148 also intellectual imperialism
meta-ethics. See ethics, meta- objection; less commonly taught
metaphysics, 17, 25, 31, 32, 40–52, philosophies (LCTP); noble
58–60, 80, 83, 144, 151, 172n7; savages; pipeline problem
defined, 39. See also mind-body Mulvey, Laura, 181n98
problem; personal identity Mungello, David E., xxiv, 23
problem; prime matter; soul; Murad, Shaykh Abdal Hakim
substance (Timothy Winter), 195n39
Milinda (king), 44, 46–48 Murdoch, Iris, 178n72, 200n27
mind-body problem, 14, 46–47, 124, Murray, Bill, 101–2
173n18
Minorities and Philosophy, xi, xxv, Nāgasena, 44, 46–49
8, 34 Native American. See Indigenous
Mohism, 7, 14, 29, 69, 141; Americans; Indigenous
contrasted with Hobbes, 61, philosophy
177n64 naturalism. See ethics, meta-
Molière (Jean-Baptiste Poquelin), Neo-Confucianism, 14, 29, 39–40;
63, 177n67 on personal identity, 58–61;
Mommsen, Theodor, 24 on ethical cultivation, 69–72.
Moore, G. E., 15 See also Wang Yangming;
Mou Zongsan, 14 Zhu Xi
Mozi. See Mohism New Confucianism, 4, 29. See also
multicultural philosophy, xxiii, Mou Zongsan
xxiv, 10–11, 35–37 (passim), 84; Newton, Isaac, 133, 134
objections to: xii; Anglo- New York University, 112, 163n8
European philosophy matters Nietzsche, Friedrich, 25, 29, 104,
too objection, 102–3, 159; area 125, 132, 136, 152
studies objection, 5, 9, 27; Nivison, David S., 80, 179nn87–88,
comprehensiveness objection, 181n104, 182n107
32–33, 38, 143; essentialist Nixon, Richard M., 85, 121, 183
objection, xiv–xv, 16–19, 25, 108; (epigraph sources)
212 Y Index
noble savages, xv–xvi, 25, 86. See Paul (saint), 117, 118, 122, 123
also intellectual imperialism Paul, Rand, 195–96n44
objection Peking University, 91, 94–95,
nonaction. See wúwéi 192n10
(non-interference) Pelikan, Jaroslav, 97–98, 132
Norton-Smith, Thomas M., 83 Pence, Mike (Michael), 107
Nussbaum, Martha, 178n72, 193n15; Peone, D. Kyle, 16
on Aristotelianism 100–1; on Pericles, 120
comparative philosophy, 6; on Perkins, Franklin, 162n5, 168n58
Derrida, 152; on education, 129, Perry, John, 173n13
179n83 personal identity problem, 10,
41–51, 57–60, 173n13. See also self;
Obama, Barack Hussein, II, 48, soul; substance
152; election of 2008, 126; Phillips, Stephen, 163n6
quoted, 60–61 Phillips, Stone, 113
objections to multicultural philosophy: of language, 3, 6–7, 155;
philosophy. See multicultural political, 4, 5, 14, 19–20, 32, 33,
philosophy, objections to 39, 52–62, 64, 80, 83, 92, 101, 104,
Olberding, Amy, 162n5, 166n28 135, 144, 155–56, 166n28, 172n1,
Orientalism, xiv, 21, 170n80; 174–75n36, 175n40; problem of
defined, 27–28 defining, 13, 16–19, 25, 29–31,
Oxford University, 119 108, 142–49, 151; renaming
Ozbey, Sonya, 162n4 departments of, xii, xxiii, 9–10,
11, 35; subfields in, 32, 135. See
Paley, William, 15 also analytic philosophy;
Palin, Sarah, 119–120, 193n24, Anglo-European philosophy;
193n26 Continental philosophy; ethics;
Parfit, Derek, teleporter thought less commonly taught
experiment of, 151, 153 philosophies (LCTP);
Park, Eugene, 26–27, 150 metaphysics; multicultural
Park, Peter K. J., 19, 21, 168n56, philosophy; weakness of will
169n65 Pigliucci, Masimo, 13–14, 27
Parmenides, 3, 16, 29, 39, 163n9 pipeline problem, 33–34
Pascal, Blaise, 104, 136 Pittenger, Robert, 184n6
Patil, Parimil, 163n6 Plato, xxvi, 1, 14, 30, 86, 116, 124,
Pattern, 59–60, 69 148, 159, 200n28; on Heraclitus,
Index Z 213