Law and Literature
Law and Literature
5-8-2013
Recommended Citation
Seaton, James (1999) "Law and Literature: Works, Criticism, and Theory," Yale Journal of Law & the Humanities: Vol. 11: Iss. 2, Article
8.
Available at: http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol11/iss2/8
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Yale Law School Legal Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Yale
Journal of Law & the Humanities by an authorized administrator of Yale Law School Legal Scholarship Repository. For more information, please
contact julian.aiken@yale.edu.
Seaton: Law and Literature: Works, Criticism, and Theory
James Seaton*
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol11/iss2/8 2
Seaton: Law and Literature: Works, Criticism, and Theory
1999] Seaton
demands "a complete and cataclysmic change in all our ideas of literary history and literary
meaning." ELAINE SHOWALTER, Introduction: The Feminist Critical Revolution, in THE NEW
FEMINIST CRITICISM 3, 10 (1985). According to Showalter:
Feminist critics do not accept the view that the canon reflects the objective value
judgments of history and posterity, but see it instead as a culture-bound political
construct. In practice, "posterity" has meant a group of men with the access to publishing
and reviewing that enabled them to enforce their views of "literature" and to define a
group of ageless "classics."
Id. at 11. Feminist criticism, she declares, "shares the same enemies" as other "avant-garde"
movements: "namely, those who urge a return to the 'basics' and the 'classics."' Id. at 16.
9. WEISBERG, supra note 2, at 122.
10. Id. at 119.
11. Id. at xii.
12. LIONEL TRILLING, On the Teaching of Modern Literature, in BEYOND CULTURE:
ESSAYS ON LITERATURE AND LEARNING 3, 26-27 (1978).
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol11/iss2/8 4
Seaton: Law and Literature: Works, Criticism, and Theory
tragic literature owes its power to the high esteem in which it holds
the common routine, and the sentiment of being which arises from it,
the elemental given of biology."'"
Modern literature, in contrast, is marked by its "failure to conceive
the actuality of the life of common routine," a life lived within the
boundaries of laws and social convention, in favor of "the fantasy of
death."22 Meanwhile, Jane Austen's Mansfield Park commends to its
readers "the idea of society as a limiting condition of the individual
spirit," the very idea, according to Trilling, against which modern
literature mobilizes its fiercest energies.' And yet in discussing
Emma, Trilling also discovers in Austen a conception of the
possibilities of this limited self that holds out a "rare hope" more
generous than anything offered in contemporary literature.24
A brief consideration of works from only a slightly earlier time
than the modern period suggests that the characteristic productions
of modernism do not speak with the authority of literature in
general. It is, furthermore, by no means obvious that the great works
of the modern period allow alienation the last word, as Trilling
uneasily supposes and as Weisberg enthusiastically assumes. One
example must suffice. In a passage in which Mann considerately
italicizes the key sentence, The Magic Mountain's protagonist Hans
Castorp explicitly affirms a moral far more in accord with traditional
Christian morality than suits Weisberg's thesis:
I will keep faith with death in my heart, but I will clearly
remember that if faithfulness to death and to what is past rules
our thoughts and deeds, that leads only to wickedness, dark lust,
and hatred of mankind. For the sake of goodness and love, man
shall grant death no dominion over his thoughts.5
Lionel Trilling came to feel that even the great masterpieces of art
and literature could sometimes be wrong, while Richard Weisberg
seems certain that they always speak the truth. One cannot help but
feel, however, that there is more intelligent respect for the great
works in Trilling's troubled disagreements than in Weisberg's
certainty that the masterpieces share his program.
Martha Nussbaum seems convinced that "the literary imagination"
of any period fosters solidarity rather than the alienation Weisberg
emphasizes. She identifies "the literary imagination" with "the
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol11/iss2/8 6
Seaton: Law and Literature: Works, Criticism, and Theory
1999] Seaton
33. JAMES BALDWIN, Many Thousands Gone, in NOTES OF A NATIVE SON, supra note 31,
at 18,35.
34. NUSSBAUM, supra note 4, at 99.
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol11/iss2/8 8
Seaton: Law and Literature: Works, Criticism, and Theory
Vision notes limitations that not only reduce the novel's literary
standing but also vitiate its force as a witness on behalf of a "case for
equal sexual liberty."35 Her discussion is echoed by Richard Posner's
observation that "Forster was a novelist of great distinction, but
Maurice is his weakest novel."36 Rosecrance begins her discussion of
Maurice by noting that "[tihe two Forster novels with which Maurice
invites comparison, A Room with a View and The Longest Journey,
both expose the poverty of the homosexual novel."37 Rosecrance
points out that the novel's literary flaws affect its value as a socio-
political statement:
But not only does Maurice suffer from its limitation as a thesis
novel: at the heart of the thesis is a contradiction that prevents
even its narrow purpose from being realized. For despite his
assertion of fulfillment, Forster cannot overcome his
ambivalence about the homosexual condition, and throughout
the novel an inner schism undermines the brave ideology of his
postscript.'
Perhaps Forster intended his novel to demonstrate what Nussbaum
calls "the flourishing of Maurice and the stunted life of Clive," but
Rosecrance convincingly demonstrates that the dramatic effect of
the novel is by no means so straightforward. Her careful analysis
demonstrates that, contrary to Nussbaum's assertion and contrary,
apparently, to Forster's own intentions, "the novel's real center of
interest is not Maurice but Clive, whose inner harmony and moral
superiority Forster unambiguously endorses .... Clive receives the
greater authorial approval."39
On this reading Maurice reveals a tortured dividedness over
homosexuality, a complexity that belies Nussbaum's simple contrast
between "flourishing" and "stunting":
His [Forster's] equivocation pervades the portrait of Maurice,
and his confusions beset the novel's two love affairs. The result
is a novel whose interest lies not in its artistic claim, which is
slight, but rather in its expression of an inner conflict whose
psychological and social implications reflect their historical
context and reveal heretofore hidden aspects of the man.'
Unlike Native Son and Maurice, Hard Times is a major work by
one of the great novelists of the English language. Not
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol11/iss2/8 10
Seaton: Law and Literature: Works, Criticism, and Theory
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol11/iss2/8 12
Seaton: Law and Literature: Works, Criticism, and Theory
1999] Seaton
forties and fifties the focus "on the work of art as an object in itself" 71
was challenged by Marxists, Freudians, myth critics, and many
others.'
Since the 1960s the prestige of the New Criticism has declined.
Ren6 Wellek, himself an admirer of the school, though not an
uncritical one, was forced to conclude in 1978 that "[t]oday the New
Criticism is considered not only superseded, obsolete and dead, but
somehow mistaken and wrong."'73 Although Dworkin acknowledges
in a general way that "critics themselves are thoroughly divided
about what literary interpretation is,"'7 his failure to discuss specific
schools, and especially the New Criticism, allows him to propose "to
use literary interpretation as a model"75 as though there were only
one "model" available: the one Dworkin offers as "the aesthetic
hypothesis,"'76 thereby gaining what seems an unearned rhetorical
advantage. In referring to the approach he is commending as the
"aesthetic hypothesis," he leaves the implication that he is not
turning merely to one critical school among others but rather
adopting an approach shared, in some variation or other, by literary
critics generally.
Dworkin's "aesthetic hypothesis" assumes that the methodology of
literary criticism both commits its practitioners to readings that cast a
text in as favorable a light as possible and then commands them to
disregard the intentions of its author in working out those readings.
Both assumptions are wrong. First, the notion that good criticism
always attempts to bring out the strengths of a work is not supported
by the actual practice of literary critics. Second, even New Critics
like Cleanth Brooks, whose work provides the strongest support for
Dworkin's theory, maintain a commitment to authorial intention
denied by the "aesthetic hypothesis."
All literary works are not masterpieces, just as all legislation is not
necessarily well-advised. The New Critical technique of close reading
can be used with devastating effect to bring out the shortcomings of
a poem or novel just as surely as it can reveal the hidden riches of a
masterpiece. Dwight Macdonald's close reading of James Could
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol11/iss2/8 14
Seaton: Law and Literature: Works, Criticism, and Theory
1999l Seaton
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol11/iss2/8 16
Seaton: Law and Literature: Works, Criticism, and Theory
1999] Seaton
89. GEORGE SANTAYANA, CHARACTER AND OPINION IN THE UNITED STATES 16 (John
W. Yolton ed., Transaction 1991) (1920).
90. DWORKIN, supranote 64, at 154.
91. Id. at 163.
92. Id. at 155.
496 Yale Journal of Law & the Humanities [Vol. 11: 479
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol11/iss2/8 18
Seaton: Law and Literature: Works, Criticism, and Theory
1999] Seaton
205 (1984).
99. Id. at 215.
100. Id. at 210.
101. E.D. Hirsch, Jr., The Validity of Allegory, in CONVEGNO INTERNATIONALE SUL
TEMA: ERMENEUTICA E CRITICA 215,221 (1996).
102. Id. at 227.
103. Id. at 228.
the spirit has in fact been more than empty rhetorical gesture." °"
Interpretations are always debatable, but there is a clear difference
between those that at least aim at fidelity to the original and those
that practice what Hirsch calls "the hermeneutics of violence."'" °
104. Id.
105. Id. at 233.
106. STANLEY FISH, Working on the Chain Gang: Interpretationsin Law and Literature, in
DOING WHAT COMES NATURALLY, supra note 85, at 87, 98.
107. FISH, supra note 86, at 103, 108.
108. STANLEY FISH, Anti-Foundationalism, Theory, Hope, and the Teaching of
Composition, in DOING WHAT COMES NATURALLY, supra note 85, at 342,355.
109. Stanley Fish, Mission Impossible: Settling the Just Bounds Between Church and State,
97 COLUM. L. REV. 2255, 2332 (1997).
110. STANLEY FISH, Consequences, in DOING WHAT COMES NATURALLY, supra note 85,
at 315, 325.
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol11/iss2/8 20
Seaton: Law and Literature: Works, Criticism, and Theory
1999] Seaton
practices." ' What Fish calls "theory talk" may indeed have all sorts
of rhetorical effects, but none of these, in his view, could possibly
have anything to do with the logic of an argument, what Jirgen
Habermas calls the "unforced force of a better insight.""'2
Most works discussing the connections between law and literature
propose ways in which legal thinking might be improved by the study
of either works of literature or theories about literature and its
interpretation. Weisberg, Nussbaum and Dworkin all make such
proposals. Fish, however, makes none. Instead he advocates looking
at both law and literature from a perspective that sees both as
exemplifications of "the truth that all operations... are
'
rhetorical."" In turn "rhetoric" is simply "another word for force,""' 4
and "force" itself "is simply a (pejorative) name for the thrust or
assertion of some point of view," or, to put it another way, "force
' 5
is
just another name for what follows naturally from conviction.""
At times, Fish seems happy to affirm this thesis in a way that
emphasizes his radical break with common sense. Common sense
holds that there is a big difference between making a decision
because one chooses to do so and obeying an order made by
someone holding a gun to one's head. According to Fish's
philosophy, however, there is "finally no difference at all"116
' between
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol11/iss2/8 22
Seaton: Law and Literature: Works, Criticism, and Theory
1999] Seaton
there is a realm beyond "mere practice" is, in Fish's view, the key
error that Dworkin's "law as integrity" shares with "external
skepticism."'" Dworkin, on the other hand, claims that it is "people
like Fish"'27 who most strikingly exemplify external skepticism. For
both Fish and Dworkin, the only skepticism worth taking seriously is
a limited skepticism, a skepticism about means rather than ends.
Thus the doubts of an "external skeptic" about the value of sports in
general would be irrelevant to the concerns of baseball players and
managers, while the skepticism of an analyst of the game who
doubted the value of home run hitters as opposed to batters who
could get on base frequently might be relevant."H In any case, Fish
agrees with Dworkin when the latter asserts "[t]his kind of
skepticism can make no difference to our own efforts to understand
and improve interpretation, art and law."'' Thus, their answers to
Dworkin's rhetorical question "What do we lose in giving it up?'M0
would seem to be the same: nothing very important.
An advocate of "external skepticism" might reply that something
very important would indeed be lost: the possibility of escaping at
least occasionally from our usual goal-oriented perspective to view
the world sub specie aeternitas, under the aspect of eternity. The
stance of the mystic or contemplative philosopher might well be
characterized as "external skepticism" without thereby impugning
the enterprise. Metaphysicians and theologians have argued that the
attainment of such a perspective is the height of wisdom, bringing
with it serenity and fulfillment. This defense would not be open to
Fish himself, since he views the world not as a source of
contemplation but rather "as a field of possibilities to be seized."'' It
is possible that some readers, delighted to find relief of any sort from
the anxieties of contemporary life, may feel only gratitude for the
verbal legerdemain by which Fish makes the case that "finally" and
"[i]n the end" the difference between making up one's own mind and
being threatened by a gunman is unimportant. Most of those
interested in the connections between literature and law, however,
are likely to turn to Fish's work not for therapy but for assistance in
clarifying, refining, and explicating the distinctions that enable them
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol11/iss2/8 24
Seaton: Law and Literature: Works, Criticism, and Theory
1999] Seaton
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol11/iss2/8 26
Seaton: Law and Literature: Works, Criticism, and Theory
1999] Seaton
VI. CONCLUSION
I began this essay by questioning the characterizations of literature
by some legal theorists. In doing so, I may have seemed to imply that
law professors and other legal scholars should stick to their own
discipline and leave literature to the accredited experts in the field.
Literature, however, is too important to be turned over to literature
professors. Literature's importance to judges, lawyers, and law
professors follows from its importance to human beings in general.
Likewise, the argument that literature has no special relevance for
legal studies depends on the larger claim that literature provides
little or no insight into human life in general. When Posner wants to
deny the pertinence of literature to legal studies, he first argues that
literature is irrelevant to moral questions of any sort. Posner argues
persuasively that literature does not provide vindication of the
favored doctrines that Weisberg and Nussbaum profess to discover.
There are, however, more substantial arguments for the relevance of
literature to life, and thus to law, than those offered by Weisberg and
Nussbaum.
Posner believes that the arguments about literature's relevance
may be subsumed into two traditions: the "aesthetic tradition,"
which he favors; and an "edifying tradition," which he opposes."5
However, it is not necessary to insist on edification as the end of
151. Aristotle, On the Art of Poetry (Poetics), in CLASSICAL LITERARY CRITICISM 29, 43-
44 (T.S. Dorsch trans., Penguin Books 1965).
152. Id. at 44.
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol11/iss2/8 28
Seaton: Law and Literature: Works, Criticism, and Theory
1999] Seaton
http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/yjlh/vol11/iss2/8 30