Thirteenth Oration of Dio Chrysostom
Thirteenth Oration of Dio Chrysostom
Thirteenth Oration of Dio Chrysostom
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
The Society for the Promotion of Hellenic Studies is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,
preserve and extend access to The Journal of Hellenic Studies
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Journal of Hellenic Studies 125 (2005) 112-38
Abstract: This paper takes the Thirteenth Oration as a test case of many of the questions raised by the career and
works of Dio Chrysostom. The speech's generic creativity and philosophical expertise are demonstrated. Historical
problems are clarified. Analysis shows how Dio weaves seemingly diverse themes into a complex unity. New
answers are given to two crucial interpretative problems. Exploration of Dio's self-representation and of his handling
of internal and external audiences and of temporal and spatial relationships leads to the conclusion that he has a serious
philosophical purpose: the advocacy of Antisthenic/Cynic paideia in place of the current paideia both of Romans and
Athenians. Paradoxically, this clever, ironic and sophisticated speech deconstructs its own apparent values in the
interests of simple, practical moralizing.
FROM his own day on, Dio of Prusa has always been a controversial figure: variously character-
ized as sophist, philosopher (whether Cynic, Stoic, Platonist or general Socratic), sophistic
philosopher, philosophical and political turn-coat, earnest moralist, relentless self-advertiser,
friend and critic of Rome, counsellor of emperors, middling local politician, literary and philo-
sophical bantam, of the same stature, among philosophers, as Plutarch or Epictetus, or, among
literary figures, as Lucian and the novelists. All these questions converge in Or. 13: in von
Arnim's judgement, 'one of the most beautiful of Dio's pieces',l but also one of his most
demanding.
STRUCTURE
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
THE THIRTEENTH ORATION OF DIO CHRYSOSTOM 113
maintained) "when you were better than nobody in the past, you learned easily a
things that you wished: I speak of horsemanship, bowmanship and hoplite w
original ending must be lost,2 but analysis will show that the speech is substantial
One problem with the progression of the argument must be deferred.3
That the place of delivery was Athens, focus of a third of the speech (14-28), cannot immediate
be proved (the ancient title In Athens Concerning Exile may only be an inference), yet will seem
persuasive. The speech was made after Dio was exiled (1). Most scholars date the speech after
the end of the exile (AD 96), partly because the great majority of Dio's extant works are post
exilic and partly because of Dio's description in section 1:
when it came to me to be exiled on account of a stated [keyojouvrii] friendship with a man who was
not base [&v6pb; oi -novipob],4 but who was very close to those who were then fortunate and ruling
[,c6v ... z6te e 8aitg6vov -re izai &pX6vrov] but who was put to death because of those things because
of which he seemed blessed to many and indeed to practically everyone - because of his relationshi
and kinship with those people, this accusation [airir;] having been brought against me, that indeed
[8ii] I was the man's friend and counsellor, for this is the custom of tyrants, just as it is among the
Scythians to bury cupbearers and cooks and concubines with their kings, so to those who are being pu
to death by them to add others for no reason [aizdr].
These scholars take 'those who were then fortunate and ruling' as an allusion to a now defun
Flavian dynasty,5 and they believe in the Flavian contacts that Dio himself claimed.6
But in an influential attack upon that belief,7 Sidebottom takes 'ruling' as referring merely t
'leading Romans', as sometimes elsewhere in Dio.8 This seems impossible. The phrase shou
refer to a general category: close kinship to 'the then dynasty' makes sense (such kinship did
undo some); close kinship to 'the then leading Romans' does not. The man's very high rank is
further supported by his 'seeming blessed to many and indeed to practically everyone', by h
being compared to 'kings' and by the clear allusions to Herodotus 1.5.3-4, 6.1, and 30.2-33 (th
mutability of ea68tatovif, Croesus the 'tyrant', the deceptiveness of worldly E6attgovia and
'calling no man happy until he is dead'). As in Herodotus, 'the then fortunate' were 'fortunat
only in their self-estimation and that of the world, and the reality comes in 24, where Dio's trans-
parent allegory9 makes Domitian a 8aL~ov and his subjects KaK0o8aigoveg, and in 31, where
Dio tells the Romans they need a good education 'if they are going to be fortunate (E68caitoveq
in actuality and in truth, and not, as now, in the opinion of the many'. In 33, the full phras
ebaig ove~ KQx ~ipxovrte is applied to the Romans in general, of the 'self-rule' necessary for
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
114 JOHN MOLES
GENERIC AFFILIATIONS
Following the ancient title, scholars have taken Or. 13 as a Hep't pi4q, and appreciation
Dio's handling of exilic topoi has grown steadily. Whereas Haisler and Doblehofer detect only
one topos,12 Verrengia sees that Dio covers some topoi by implication,13 and Claassen that, in t
opening, consolatory section, Dio refashions the usual writer/addressee relationship into an
internal dialectic, with Dio himself both questioner and questioned.14 Whitmarsh no
numerous reversals of topoi: creation of conversational immediacy through the omission of
formal prologue (1), failure to attribute the exile to philosophical Rtaxpproia (1), apparently
'accidental' becoming a philosopher (3; 11-12), and the simplicity of the means by which Dio
'discovers' philosophical truths (2; 3; 7).15
More could be said. Exilic cosmopolitanism is reflected in Dio's claim that competent philo
sophical teachers can be Greeks, Romans, Scythians or Indians (32). Exilic rejection of Athen
civic ideologyl6 is additionally pointed when Athenians are both internal and external audienc
Whereas exile characteristically entails physical separation and philosophical alienation from
'the city', Dio the dramatic character ends up in Rome (29ff.) and Dio the speaker speaks in
Athens. While Dio preserves the traditional cosmopolitan sentiment (32), he 'homes in'
Rome as the central place of the earth (36). These last examples illustrate the challenging-ne
of Dio's response to the exile genre: the logic of the speech progressively moves away from
and finally 'rejects' it, the focus becoming ever more civic.
For numerous other genres also signify. Philosophical autobiographyl7 and protreptic (16, 2
are obvious. There are also affinities with a Floktze8ial and with a Flp' 7ratxitS;. Debate
dialectic between old and new types of nxat86Ei is a theme of non-philosophical works such
Aristophanes' Clouds (to which Dio alludes).19 The speech also has features from epic20 a
tragedy,21 with Dio 'hero' of both.22 Herodotean and Thucydidean allusions23 import a histor
graphical quality, as of a narrative formally 'true', imbued with high seriousness and moral
10 P. 125; this contrast is also structural in17theJouan (1993b).
Kingships: Jones (1978) 118-22; Moles (1983a) passim;
18 Similarly, the Borystheniticus: Schofield (1991)
(1990) passim. 57-92; Moles (1995b), esp. 191; and the Euboicus: Moles
11 Von Amim (1898) 331, 334; Jones (1978) (1995b)
53-4,
178-9.
135; Sheppard (1984) 162, 173; further support19for 19, a
23 - Nub. 965, 967, 985-6 (p. 130).
post-exilic dating in sustained parallels with 20 4the
- Od. 1.48-59; 81; 10 - Od. 11.119-34; 10-11: p.
123 and122,
Kingships (nn.10, 101), especially Or. 1 (nn.117, n.121.
129, 135, 143, 183, 186, 189, 217, 220), crucial parallels
21 Cf. the shrewd allusion of Dio's biographer
with Or. 79 (p. 129), and points of contact with (VS 488) to 'the man's going off stage [par-
Philostratus
odos]
Olympicus (nn.192, 219) and Or. 72 (n.167); to the Getic tribes'; 1 - Hdt. 1.32.1; 2-4 - Diog.
contra
n.133. Laert. 6.38 (Diogenes' tragic verses); 2, 20 (emphasis on
12 Hdisler (1935) 37, 55; Doblehofer (1987) 42. io~ruXia); 5 - Soph. El. 233-6 (note t6nov for the MSS
13 Verrengia (2000) 87-8, 135.
v6otov); 14 ('like a god from a machine'); 20-1 (disquisi-
14 Claassen (1999) 25, 166. tion on tragedy).
15 Whitmarsh (2001) 160-2. 22 P. 124.
16 Whitmarsh (2001) 142-5, 151 (Musonius); 172, 23 1 Hdt. 1.32; 1 (Scythian royal burials) Hdt.
175-8 (Favorinus); Socrates'/Dio's rejection of the epi- 4.71.4; 6-8 - Hdt. 1.55; 1 - Thuc. 5.26; 6 - Thuc. 1.70.3;
taphios tradition (23-6) is particularly relevant; on that 15 - Thuc. 1.22.
tradition within exile literature: Whitmarsh (2001) 175-7.
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
THE THIRTEENTH ORATION OF DIO CHRYSOSTOM 115
purpose, and having particular concern with 'the city', its authority deriving from
PHILOSOPHICAL MATERIAL
The Socratic logos (14-28) raises huge controversy. The closeness of 14-17 to t
Cleitophon32 makes many scholars think that Dio is following it directly,33 but others th
Antisthenes is the common source.34
This dispute is one of the key elements in the general debate concerning the presence o
absence of Antisthenes in Dio, a debate which connects with two others: the extent of Cyn
influence on Dio and the importance within the general Socratic tradition of Antisthenes him
Brancacci has recently reaffirmed Dio's extensive use of Antisthenes, notably in the Third a
Fourth Kingships and in Or. 13, whereas Trapp sees Plato as the dominant source. This
agreement concerns also the kind of Socrates projected in the sources and inherited by Dio, w
Brancacci insisting on a distinctively Antisthenic/Cynic/Dionian Socrates qua dogmatic tea
of positive moral truths and Trapp denying that distinctiveness.35 The dispute affects the in
pretation of Or. 13 and cannot be evaded.
The verbal resemblances are as shown below.
Or. 13 Cleitophon
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
116 JOHN MOLES
Items 2-5 are very close, and so is item 1.37 Any nEnat8eF6igvog must take Dio's 'as some-
one has said' (item 2) for a 'pointer' to the very popular Cleitophon.38 Item 6 is also close. While
the positive 'good teacher' theme of 407c-d does not appear in the Socratic logos, it does appear
when Dio is speaking in propria persona (31ff.): seemingly, Dio himself has transferred it
there,39 to fit the speech's general movement from negative to positive.40 Thus Dio is here fol-
lowing the Cleitophon directly.
The rest of the Socratic logos (17-28) enlarges on the inadequacy of conventional education.
Dio is writing freely.41 The refutation (23-7) of the claim that Athens' military victories showed
her superior education controverts the epitaphios. The anachronistic allusion in 26 to Cnidus,
taken by Cobet as illustrating the historical ignorance of later rhetoricians and sophists and by
von Arnim and Giannantoni as showing Dio's uncritical reliance on a text written after 394 BC,42
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
THE THIRTEENTH ORATION OF DIO CHRYSOSTOM 117
But if you wish truly to learn that wisdom is something lofty, I invoke neither Plato nor Aristotle as
witnesses, but the wise Antisthenes, who taught this road. For he says that Prometheus spoke to
Heracles as follows: 'Your labour is very cheap, in that your care is for human things, but you have
deserted the care of those things which are of greater moment; for you will not be a perfect man until
you have learnt the things that are loftier than human beings, but if you learn those things, then you
will learn also human things; if, however, you learn only human things, you will wander like a brute
animal.' For the man who studies human things and confines the wisdom and intelligence of his mind
in such cheap and narrow things, that man, as Antisthenes said, is not a wise man but like to an ani-
mal, to whom a dung-pit is pleasing. In truth, all celestial things are lofty and it behoves us to have a
lofty way of thinking about them.
This must come from Antisthenes' Heracles. The scene reworks the Prodican Choice of
Heracles, with an admixture of the Aeschylean interpretation of the relationship between
Prometheus (- intelligence) and Zeus (~ power).47 The choice is between 'human' and 'celes-
tial' 'learning' and is not absolute: 'learning' only the former will leave Heracles in a bestial
state; 'learning' the latter is far the more important, but will immediately secure the former;
Heracles will then be a 'perfect man'.
A passage in Dio's Fourth Kingship (Diogenes the Cynic is the dramatic speaker) contains
the following elements (29-33):
(i) the 'double paideia', one part of which is divine, the other human, the former
superior and 'easy', the latter inferior, but both necessary for complete education;
(ii) the claim that knowledge of the divine paideia easily confers knowledge of the human;
(iii) Heracles as representative of divine education;
(iv) the sophists, including Prometheus, as representative of human education;
(v) road imagery (good and bad roads);
(vi) comparison between human education/sophists and animals.
Many have taken this passage as Antisthenic.48 Trapp, however, holds that 4.29-33 is merely
one of a series of items drawn from Alcibiades I, ex hypothesi the Platonic 'master-text' of the
43 Menex. 244d-46a (including Cnidus) and Symp.46 Antisthenes F27 Caizzi; V A 96 Giannantoni
182b and 193a (which Dio noted: Moles (2000a) 201Moles (2001) and (2003b).
n.37). 47 Kitto (1961) 61.
44 Diimmler (1882) 8-11; Giannantoni (1990) 4.350; 48 Diimmler (1882) 14; Weber (1887) 241; von Fritz
Brancacci (2000) 249-50. (1926) 78; Hiistad (1948) 56-9; Moles (1983a) 270;
45 H6istad (1948) 171-3 argues a plausible general Brancacci (2000) 254-5; Giannantoni (1990) 4.312-13;
case for Antisthenes' 'double paideia' in Or. 13; cf also Whitmarsh (2001) 191 n.43.
n.69.
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
118 JOHN MOLES
49 Trapp (2000) 226-7, cf 232-4; the authenticity of 57 Griffin (1993) 251-8; (1996) 197-204.
Alcibiades I (advocated by Denyer (2001) 14-26) is here 58 Diog. Laert. 6.73, 103-4.
immaterial, authenticity being anciently accepted. 59 Space, however, precludes discussion of this possi-
bility here: Moles (2003b).
50 H6istad (1948) 213-20; Moles (1983a), esp. 268-9
n.65. 60 Whitmarsh's claim that Dio is engaging with
51 E.g. Diog. Laert. 6.44, 70; Antisthenes and
Musonius' Iepi ptyifg;: p. 121; another possibility:
Cynicism: p. 119; 'easiness' in Or. 13: p. 123. n.140.
52 Similarly 24, where the Persians have no education 61 Dudley (1937) 150-1; Moles (1978) 99-100; Jouan
(1993a) 393.
but some military 'training', a significantly parallel pas-
sage, as it emerges (nn.115, 156). 62 Cf., e.g., Kindstrand (1976) 161-3; p. 135.
53 P. 122; in Antisthenes, e.g. Diog. Laert. 6.2, 6.14-15. 63 Dio's Cynicizing representation of his wanderings:
54 H6istad (1948) 50-7, 86-94; note that Or. 4 is 1.9,
a 50-1; 4.1, 6-11 (Diogenes - Dio); 6.1ff. (Diogenes -
year earlier than Or. 13 (nn. 11, 101). Dio); 7.9, 81; 8.1 (Diogenes - Dio); 12.16-20; 19.1;
55 P. 123. 33.15; 36.1; 45.1; further Montiglio (2000) 98ff.
56 Virg. Aen. 6.847-53; Petrochilos (1974) 58-62; 64 See, e.g., Martin (1996).
Whitmarsh (2001) 9-17.
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
THE THIRTEENTH ORATION OF DIO CHRYSOSTOM 119
Dio's deployment of the Cleitophon is also apposite. Whereas that work's Socrates is
ironized by his inability to explain what virtue is,71 Dio largely discards the irony and uses the
Cleitophon image of Socrates as a representative of moral virtue at its most robust and uncom-
promising. This procedure, also adopted by Dio's fellow Stoic, Epictetus, in his On Cynicism
(3.22.26), is philosophically justified, because the Socrates parodied in the Cleitophon was very
like the Socrates championed by the Cynics and by Antisthenes. Use of the Cleitophon also
underwrites the move from individual ethics to social and political ones.
Use of Antisthenes is also compatible with the Cynic 'feel' of the speech, since, whoever
founded Cynicism, Antisthenes undoubtedly influenced it,72 as Dio knew.73 On the whole, Or.
13 inclines towards the 'soft', here Antisthenic, type of Cynicism, which (here) involves the
acceptance of human beings' social and political obligations, however redefined, and an intense
concern with the well-being of 'the city', rather than towards the 'hard' Diogenic version.
More generally, Dio's rich play with the metaphorical and moral implications of place and
travel74 can be regarded as Platonic75 and/or Herodotean,76 although such play is also found within
Cynicism, albeit in less developed form.77
Discussion of Or. 13's philosophical content must tackle the question of irony. A certain
degree of ironization is intrinsic alike to the model of the Cynicized Socrates and to the self-
representation of the Cynic himself;78 hence these elements are 'always already' present both in
Dio's representation of Socrates and in his self-representation. Nevertheless, Dio has somewhat
increased that irony by introducing the sorts of equivocation highlighted by Whitmarsh,79 includ-
ing the characterization of Socratic doctrine and of himself, Dio, as 'old'/'old-fashioned'
(archaios):
(14) ... while I was upbraiding all the others and first and most of all myself in these and similar ways,
sometimes through lack of resources I would go to a certain old logos, spoken by a certain Socrates ...
65 See, e.g., Brown (1949) 38-51; Moles (1995a) 146-9. Diogenes); Diog. Laert. 6.2; H6istad (1948) 10-11;
66 Moles (1993); (1996); pace Montiglio (2000) 99- D6ring (1995); Goulet-Caz6 (1996) 414-15 (favouring
100.
Antisthenes); influence: von Fritz (1927); DSring (1995).
67 P. 122. 73 Or. 8.1, with Brancacci (2000) 256-7.
68 N.51 and p. 123. 74 P. 122.
69 Though extant Dio does not use the word 75 See, e.g., Pender (1999).
aruripcexta, he often comes close, as at 34-5: Xavrt6vov 76 See, e.g., Redfield (1985).
... SeIoeo0e (virtually the standard definition). Dio's 77 Diog. Laert. 6.73 with Moles (1995a) 139-40;
formulations hereabouts resemble Diog. Laert. 6.11 Diog. Laert. 6.37, 68.
(Antisthenes); I suspect implicit punning on 78 Cynic theatricality and exaggeration (both devel-
OC/l&pKlEta/self-cApijl, as perhaps in Plato (e.g. Rep. opments of Socratic characteristics) and their clear pro-
369b; Polit. 271d) and (surely) in lost Cynic material. treptic/paideutic justification: Diog. Laert. 6.35;
Dio's thinking about this idea: Brenk (2000). Kindstrand (1976) 208-9; Moles (1983a) 274-6; (1983b)
70 Brancacci (2000) 249. 108-9; p. 000 below; contra Branham (1996); cf also the
71 Slings (1999) 209-12. spoudaiogeloion: n.204.
72 Dudley (1937) 1-15, 54-5; Giannantoni (1990) 79 Whitmarsh (2001) 160-7.
4.223-33; (1993); Moles (2000b) 417 (all favouring
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
120 JOHN MOLES
HISTORICAL PROBLEMS
There are three: (a) who was the Roman whose fall caused Dio's exile? (b) Where was Dio exi
from? (c) How reliable is Dio's account of his becoming a philosopher? All three historical pr
lems have important interpretative implications.
(a) Possibilities are: Q. lunius Arulenus Rusticus; M. Arrecinus Clemens; L. Salvius O
Cocceianus; T. Flavius Sabinus; non liquet.87
The crucial passage has already been quoted.88 There are two criteria: (i) the man must b
closely related to the Flavians;89 (ii) Dio's exile was long.90 Rusticus, killed in, or shortly bef
93,91 is excluded by (i) and (ii). Clemens, executed in 93, is excluded by (ii). Otho Cocceianu
is excluded by (i). Sabinus, cousin of Domitian and cos. 82, the year of his death,92 satisfies
criteria, as do also Dio's Flavian contacts.93 The man's identity and the date of Dio's exile a
worth (re-)establishing for the historical reconstruction of Dio's early career.
But a problem remains. Was Dio in fact Sabinus' <pi(oc/amicus and Y6fpouoc/consiliarius
Is Dio admitting this or merely recording the charge and then, while implying Sabinus' innoc
either leaving the truth of the alleged relationship between himself and Sabinus open or impl
its non-existence? Verrengia takes yoj7gPvrlg as 'cosiddetta' and comments: 'da tale amicizi
Dione intende prendere le distanze'.94 On this reading, 6il is presumably also distancing.95
the usual reading, however, these words merely gloss the charges as stated.96
Since Dio characterizes Sabinus as 'not base' and compares himself to Scythian kings' cup
bearers, cooks or concubines, he is not denying that he 'knew' Sabinus. He represents Sabin
(qua 'not base') as innocent; Sabinus' innocence necessarily makes Dio also innocent, but
innocence seems to exceed this: Scythian cup-bearers, cooks and concubines are not ki
friends and counsellors, and the aitia made against Dio was without aitia (even on its
terms, 'without cause'). Thus ke~yogvvrlg and 86i do have a distancing quality. Dio is represen
himself as legally cleaner than clean, though the full implications of this dextrous passage o
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
THE THIRTEENTH ORATION OF DIO CHRYSOSTOM 121
become clear later.97 As to the facts, Dio admits that he knew Sabinus; his im
he was his friend or counsellor, doubly motivated as it is, does not establish a h
I conclude that Dio was close to Sabinus. Dio had the highest court contacts a
mighty.
(b) Where was Dio exiled from? Prusa, certainly (Or. 19.1-2); on the usual forms of exile,
also Bithynia, qua province, and Rome and Italy, qua communis patria of Roman citizens.98 But
Desideri has repeatedly maintained that Dio's exile took the lighter form of civitate pellere, since
sections 29ff. have Dio philosophizing in Rome.99 These sections are usually read as referring
to Dio's philosophizing after his recall and return to Rome in 99/100,100 when he philosophized
before Trajan among others.10l Resolution of this problem must be deferred.102
(c) How reliable is Dio's account of his becoming a philosopher?
Simple acceptance103 is immediately threatened by the elaborate Socratic, Diogenic,
Antisthenic, Zenonian and Cynic associations which Dio invokes.104 There is every reason to
accept Fronto's testimony that Dio learnt philosophy from Musonius Rufus, i.e. before the
exile.os05 Hence another reading of the speech: as a self-serving rewriting of Dio's autobiography.
By post-dating his philosophizing, Dio buries his early pupillage under Musonius, his unsavoury
oscillations between philosophy and sophistry and his collaboration with Vespasian's campaign
against philosophers in 71.106 From these perspectives, Or. 13 conveys a most misleading
impression.
What, then, of Whitmarsh's claim that Dio is here engaged in a Freudian/Bloomian struggle
for 'authority' with his teacher, Musonius?107 Since another of Dio's works alludes obliquely to
Musonius,os08 some other works show Musonian influence,109 and Musonius' Hepi tpuy4; was in
Greek, Dio 'the man' can hardly have been unconscious of his master's voice. But it is another
question whether Musonius is 'in the text'. There are no significant parallels nor any 'contra-
dictions' so sharp as to imply polemic. Any active presence of Musonius would sabotage the
narrative's basic credibility.110
Thus on the general issue of when and how he became a philosopher Dio should still be
convicted of disingenuousness. This, however, does not provide a sufficient explanation of the
speech or even of the function within it of Dio's autobiography.111
The important question of the historicity of the consultation of Delphi involves so many other
questions that I defer it.112
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
122 JOHN MOLES
MAIN THEMES
I here summarize main themes and note interconnections, without prejudging ultimate interpre-
tative questions:
(a) Place. Like all exiles, Dio faces the question: where can the 'displaced' exile 'place' him-
self (5)? The speech ends with Rome as the central 'place' of the world's riches (36). Place can
also be metaphorical: Apollo's oracular reply in 9 is itonto; - seemingly, 'out of place'. Physical
place is less important than moral place. Even at the end, Rome will not be truly 'strong' (34)
with the standard pun,113 unless she 'renames' herself under Dio's philosophical programme by
reducing her luxury, consumption and very population, thereby becoming a smaller place (34-5)
Places, too, are not what they seem: Rome under Domitian resembles Scythia at its most
barbarous (1), or Athens rent by war or stasis (1, 6);114 similarly, Socrates' description of Persia
under Xerxes (24) eerily evokes Rome under Domitian.115
(b) Travel. Dio, like many exiles, must 'wander'. He consults Delphi because Apollo is a
Ktavb pooo; (9): he can 'reach' the right advice or help humans to 'reach' the right goal
(iKav6S iKVEO~(uXl).116 By contrast, ordinary politicians are not 'competent to give advice' (22).
T6 icmav6v becomes one of the speech's philosophical desiderata (9, 16, 19, 22, 27, 32). Travel
can be both literal and moral/metaphorical or simply metaphorical (13, 16, 19). The speech itself
becomes a philosophical journey. When Dio starts his philosophical preaching (14), he 'goes to'
an old, Socratic logos, and it is the 'old' logos of the Cynicized Socrates which enables the moral
progress of Dio himself and of his individual listeners as he wanders and which is finally
capable of saving Rome (29ff.).117
The horizontal movement of travel is matched by vertical movement downwards through
time (16, etc.). The acme of the travel imagery is reached in 35, where Dio expatiates on the
rewards the Romans will gain 'when you have reached the peak of virtue', a phrase which com-
bines horizontal movement and vertical movement, and vertical movement in two senses
upwards to a peak of virtue and upwards in time.
The imagery of (a) and (b) is, indeed, almost all-pervasive, and, once established, energizes
ordinarily inert words. For example, in 13 'the present evils, great ignorance and disturbance'
and in 32 'the unchastenedness and havingness' are, as it were, 'places' to get away from
ouragivWo, a leitmotiv of the speech (1, 6 [bis], 12, 26), is similarly energized: moral problem
involve not only human beings as agents, who have to progress in the right way, but also as
passive before challenges which come from the outside. Ultimately, therefore, exile, wander-
ings and travel, while literal enough, are also metaphors for moral states or aspirations. By
contrast, place, while sometimes also metaphorical, retains important literal force in the case of
Rome, though she too has to 're-place' herself morally.
In this Dionian speech, as in others,118 the relationships between literal, metaphorical and
textual places and travels present puzzles. Apollo's oracle to Dio, seemingly 'out of place', is (9)
'not easy to put together' (oulgcxiv). Apollo, qua inav6bq oA3pouo;, tells Dio to keep on wan-
dering until he comes to the last place on earth, just as - Dio reflects - Teiresias, qua g6toi.oog,
told by
even Odysseus to wander
hearsay'. There untiland
are insistent hesuitably
'met together with'
oracular verbal (apt6L,,)
plays. people
Apollo poses 'who knew
a prophetic not the sea
puzzle both for Dio, qua dramatic character, and for Dio's audience/readers to 'put together'.
113 Erskine (1995); Whitmarsh (2001) 21, 149; cf 116 Cf. 30.1, 45 with Moles (2000a) 197-8.
n. 110 above. 117 The same enabling role of logos in the First
114 N.23. Kingship (Moles (1990) 311, 322, 325-6) and the
115 Domitianic are: (a) the Persian king (cf. Orr. 4 and Charidemus (Moles (2000a) 197-8); cf the related 'wan-
6; von Amim (1898) 261-2; Desideri (1978) 202, 244 n.5, dering physically'/'wandering in words' (4.37; 7.1, 127;
288); (b) the tiara (cf 1.79; 3.41; 4.25, 61); (c) the evil 12.16; Moles (1995b) 179; Whitmarsh (2001) 160).
daimon (cf 45.1); (d) the alleged military incompetence. 118 P. 126.
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
THE THIRTEENTH ORATION OF DIO CHRYSOSTOM 123
oYtg[ouko; is transformed into a more explicit 8616 Kcahok (32, cf 17). This th
dimension to Dio's veiled and equivocal allusion to Sabinus (1). Dio's implicit d
association extended to friendship and counsel adumbrates an ideal counsellor
ship. Dio has now left behind the glittering, meretricious world of high-level
(d) The search for the right education. This theme first becomes explicit in t
section, which it proceeds to dominate (16ff.; 23; 24-6). Similarly, Dio in Rom
for good education and good teachers (31-3), and ends by expounding the An
paideia (37). But the theme is latent from the very beginning of the speech, as
literature and then to the Delphic oracle for guidance on the correct response
(e) In this speech, apart from the puzzling oracle, what seems hard is actually
and easy being used both of worldly states and of the intellectual and moral c
to cope with them. Exile and all other similar disasters seem hard: they are ac
with (2-8). And the speech ends (37) with the Antisthenic 'double paideia',
which are 'easy'.
(f) A related idea is that true philosophical virtues are the opposite of world
teristically those held by the ignorant majority (2, 7, 31). Exile, etc. are not e
way, goods: rt6vo;g ya06v (Diog. Laert. 6.2). The shape of the speech again
moral lesson. Sabinus seems very close to the 'fortunate rulers', but they we
tunate, and by the end the only 'good fortune' and 'rule' that matter are ph
fortune' and self-rule (31, 33).
(g) Divine authority is stressed throughout: the 8at&t6vtov (3), the various o
Delphi (2, 6-10, 36). This does not mean that 'religion' is more important tha
as in the Socratic-Antisthenic-Cynic philosophical tradition generally, the tw
implicated. The 8atxi6vtov co-exists with human ea68t~ovia. Xerxes/Dom
an 'evil spirit' and himself 'unfortunate' and the agent of 'misfortune' in othe
(h) As a dramatic figure within the text, Dio himself helps to knit together
parate elements and to embody major themes. His unclarified relationship w
brates the oa3oupolog and 8tS6wKcog; themes. His 'experiencing' of exile,
of Delphi and his and Socrates' sermons on the 'use' of wealth are all interlin
Xpeotlat (3, 9, 16, 23):120 the right 'use' of apparent misfortune, of oracles and
is always the same thing: the right individual and collective response to exte
Dio's initial apparent misfortune anticipates all the other problems. His povert
ures Socrates' attacks upon Athenian materialism and his own attacks upon Ro
His 'wandering' is itself morally ambiguous: it can be a symbol of folly, a ro
itself already a form of 'truth' (,rl pexa -~ %1jfEta).121 Dio dangles these alternatives in 10-11:
exhorting myself in this way [according to the example of Odysseus] neither to fear nor to be ashamed
of the thing, and putting on humble dress and in all other respects chastening myself, I began to wan-
der [Xil&jrlv] everywhere. And the people who chanced to meet me, when they saw me, some of them
called me a wanderer [&Xlttrv], but certain others actually a philosopher.122
119 Pace Brenk (2000) 269-70. 14.122-7; Hdt. 1.29.1-30.2; 4.76.2; P1. Apol. 22a;
120 Similar play in Or. 10 (2ff.): both perhaps inspired Redfield (1985) 98-9.
by Hdt. 7.140-1 (p. 000 and n.147). 122 Closely similar are 1.9 (Dio's self-introduction in
121 The ambiguity: Moles (1990) 309, 322; Montiglio the First Kingship), with Moles (1990) 309, and 72.2, 11.
(2000); Whitmarsh (2001) 162, 198-200; Hornm. Od.
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
124 JOHN MOLES
(1) Dio writes (29): 'so to the others I used to say practically the same things [as Socrates
things old-fashioned and stale, and when/since they would not let me be in peace when I
to Rome itself, I did not dare to speak any word of my own ...' Here 'the others' me
'everybody other than the Romans' and 'when I got to Rome' refers to a later time.127
clear implication that sections 29ff. mark the culmination of Dio's exile wanderings har
fits the hypothesis that Dio was never exiled from Rome.
(2) In sections 30-1 Dio writes: 'Archelaus, king of the Macedonians ... summo
[Socrates] with the inducement of gifts and fees, that he might hear him speaking these words.
In the same way I too tried to speak to the Romans, when they summoned me and asked
to speak.' This analogy between Archelaus' 'summoning' of Socrates and the Romans' 'sum
moning' of himself can hardly apply to Domitianic Rome.
(3) Dio elsewhere, in contexts where duplicity is unlikely and would have been risky
damaging his credibility, or inviting ridicule, were his claims falsifiable), states, or impli
that, once exiled, he was absent from Rome for the rest of Domitian's reign and that his return
was secured by Domitian's death and Nerva's accession.128s
However, if sections 29ff. refer to Dio's post-exile philosophizing in Rome, three questi
arise: (i) how can Dio's exile narrative legitimately include allusion to his post-exilic ph
sophical activity in Rome? While it is easy to see that Dio might want to represent his ph
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
THE THIRTEENTH ORATION OF DIO CHRYSOSTOM 125
sophizing in Trajanic Rome as part of his whole philosophical project ever sinc
a philosopher, indeed as the culmination of his philosophical career,129 how can
the logic of this speech? (ii) How can Dio convey an allusion to his recall by N
to Rome under Trajan without explicitly alluding to them? (iii) How can he l
post-exile phases of his career so as to imply both difference and continuity?
Question (i) is fundamental, and questions (ii) and (iii) concern Dio's t
sections 29ff. represent Dio's philosophizing in Rome as the culmination of h
ings, then, since Socrates is a figure for Dio, it is easy to read Archelaus ('rule
who 'summoned' Socrates, as an analogue of either Nerva, who recalled Dio to
Trajan, for whom Dio performed the ag30ou0o; role that Archelaus had solicit
or indeed of both Nerva and Trajan, such 'allegory', whether simple or double,
Dionian, in the Kingships and elsewhere.131 The wording is suspiciously '
'knew many things and had associated with many of the wise' (like Nerv
[Socrates] with presents and fees, in order that he might hear him saying th
logoi', formally Socrates', can also be Dio's, 'now' or on similar occasions.1
ring-structure and contrast: between Rome at the beginning under the tyrann
Rome at the end under the 'good' 'ruler' of his people, Nerva and/or Trajan,
to bring Dio's philosophical teaching to the Romans at large. So 'the Romans
effectively implies: 'Nerva/Trajan gave me this huge philosophical commissio
Dio's return becomes a metaphor not only for Trajan's celebrated 'repatriatio
and intellectualsl34 but also for the return from exile of the entire Roman wor
Trajan, and Dio's exile a metaphor for the exile of the spirit imposed on all h
'evil 8aiCiov' Domitian, who frustrated his subjects' eii8otGovia (1, 24).135
As for (i), part of the answer lies in Dio's response to Apollo's oracle to go to
earth. In a way, he did: he penetrated deeply into Dacia, Scythia and the Blac
sumably his audience knew and as he himself described in other works.136 Suc
his moral authority: as the wanderer par excellence who has travelled to the en
has done, and seen, it all. As the ultimate Cynic 'scout' (KardOKonog),137 he
fied to apply his experience to the task of reforming Rome, the central t6ono;
But it is not only a question of Dio's response to the oracle: it is also a questi
meaning.
(b) Apollo's oracle to Dio, seemingly 'out of place', was 'not easy to put together' (oug-
a3cAXiv). Apollo told Dio to go to the last place on earth, as Teiresias told Odysseus to wander
until he 'met together with [ougp'di]] people who knew not the sea even by hearsay'.
129 Cf the First Kingship: 1.56-8 (the Arcadian Nerva)? (v) nothing in the passage suggests violent
prophetess). change; (vi) Dio is surely alluding to himself (p. 133) but
130 45.2-3 with Moles (1984) 67-8. hardly also to Trajan (or any other potential emperor):
131 Moles (1990), e.g. 328; (2000a) 206-7. this is a philosophical teacher. 'Establishment on the
132 For the nicely blurred focalization, cf 'this father' Acropolis' entails 'philosopher-ruler', but this is not
in the Charidemus (30.45): Moles (2000a) 205-6. 'Trajan as philosopher-king' but philosopher as philoso-
133 A referee objects that 32-3 (on the ideal teacher to
pher-&pov (= Dio as Trajan's court-philosopher),
be established on 'the Acropolis') alludes both to Dio and Trajan's &pxil having already been covered by 30
Trajan and that 'it hasn't happened yet', hence an earlier 'Apxxo;.
Nerva/Trajan allusion in 30-1 is excluded and the speech 134 Plin. Pan. 47.1-2.
is exilic. But: (i) other considerations make the speech 135 The First Kingship enacts the same philosophi-
post-exilic (p. 114; n. 11); (ii) 32-3 is future in relation to cal/political narrative of 'mass exile': 1.55, with Moles
31, where Dio is already in Rome, not (or not necessari- (1990) 321, 370 n.82.
ly) in relation to the delivery context; (iii) in Domitianic 136 12.10-20; 36.1; Philostr. VS 487-9.
Rome Dio could hardly be publicly arguing, however 137 Diog. Laert. 6.17-18; 6.43; Norden (1893) 373-
allusively, for Domitian's removal; (iv) how could Dio 85; Moles (1983b) 112; Schofield (2004) 453-5.
then know that Trajan would replace Domitian (and
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
126 JOHN MOLES
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
THE THIRTEENTH ORATION OF DIO CHRYSOSTOM 127
recalled, it might ... seem that this oracle was made up after the event.'l46 Moreov
of the earth' is an exilic topos; Delphi told the Athenians in 481/80 to flee to th
earthl47 (hence Dio's Athenian audience might be tickled by such an invention);
plays a crucial role in Or. 13's spatial and moral architecture.
Yet such invention might, even for Dio, be an invention too far. The 'coincide
being 'at the end of the earth' when recalled is only excessive if the oracle's respo
me to keep doing the very thing on which I was148 engaged with all enthusiasm,
and useful activity, "until," he said, "you come to the end of the earth"') was to
'when will my exile end?'l49 Dio omits the question, but it is better understood as
I do in my exile?' He then found the response 'out of place' and 'not easy to
because it was not easy to see how wandering was a fine and useful activity, nor
end of the earth', nor to understand how attaining it was a solution to his problem
tively, Delphi provides the ultimate divine and philosophical grounding for the s
would be weakening, if that grounding were entirely groundless, especially, perha
very public association with Delphi of Plutarch and the rivalry between the
Greeks.o50 Rather, when the sentence of exile was passed, Dio immediately began
and his inventiveness comes into play, not with the consultation itself nor with
response (oracles, too, use t6r'ot),152 but with the many philosophical associ
thereby invokes and with the paradoxical twist that he gives to 'the end of the
Apollo's instruction as the basis for a rewriting of his whole career, a rewriting w
practical advantage of suppressing his pre-exile philosophizing and related aspect
reputable past, but which, more importantly, gives divine sanction to his post-exil
Nerva and Trajan and to his project of the conversion of Rome.
As to why Dio consulted Delphi, he may have been influenced by the motives th
(8), commonplace though they are,153 and, as a Stoic (mostly), he should have accep
but he must already have been conscious of the philosophical associations of his a
already have been stage-managing the drama of Dio Socraticus et Cynicus.
INTERPRETATION
There is much to consider: the speech's wit, irony and literary sophistication; its moral serious
ness; its philosophical content; its view ofpaideia; Dio's own dramatic role; the representation
of fifth-century Athenians, of contemporary Greeks other than the Athenians (11-15), and of t
Romans; the apparently dominant focus on Rome at the end; the teaching that Dio gives the
Romans; the relationship between internal audiences (especially the Romans) and extern
audience (Athenians).
I start with the last.
146 Jones (1978) 47 (quotation), 51, 176 n.57. 149 As Fontenrose (1978) 15 n.4.
147 Hdt. 7.140 (which perhaps influenced Dio 150inLamprias Catalogue 204, 227; Desideri (1978) 4-5.
another respect: n.120), and e.g. Ov. Tr. 1.2.85, 151
2.195,
Had Dio settled elsewhere, he would have lost his
3.3.3; Sen. Ep. 28.4. Bithynian properties: von Arnim (1898) 235-6.
148 'I am engaged' (Cohoon) could only be justified
152 Fontenrose (1978) 166ff.; Hammerstaedt (1993)
405. I am
were Dio saying: 'to do the very thing on which
[now] engaged' (post-96 Dio could still represent himself
153 Verrengia (2000) 87-8, 136.
as wandering: 12.16ff.); but 'the very thing' implies
154 Contrast his more Cynic voice in 1.56 and 10.17ff.
'more of the same', an implication reinforced by the
Odyssean analogy; tpd6crtEtv means 'to keep doing' (thus
also Cohoon); the present etipt is 'vivid'.
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
128 JOHN MOLES
155 Contrast 3.34, 50; 41.9 (see n.213) and 79.5. 161 Thus, e.g., Fuchs (1938) 18 n.65; Jones (1978)
129 and 195 n.26, comparing Lucian's Nigrinus, also set
156 37 - 32 - 24 (the Persians); also (?) - Virg. Aen.
6.847ff. (n.59). in Athens and seemingly critical of Roman morals; con-
157 Swain (1996) 213. tra Desideri (1978) 253-4 n.10; sophisticated analysis in
158 Pp. 120 and 121. Whitmarsh (2001) 265-79 (though I do not agree that
159 E.g. 3.12-25; Or. 57. Nigrinus offers no moral locus).
160 Moles (1995b) 183-4; Swain (1996) 200-3; 162 34 'but as for now [Rome's] greatness arouses
Klaucke and Bdibler (2000) 158-9; pace Billaut (1999) suspicion and is not at all secure': thus rightly Swain
218-19; Greeks slaves of Rome: 31.125; 34.39, 51; (1996) 212, pace Cohoon and Verrengia; cf Dio's bril-
Moles (1995b) 178 n.5; Veyne (1999); pace Salmeriliant reworking (36) of ll. 23.161-77.
(2000) 86; Roman militarism: also 30.35 with Moles 163 Cf. the Olympicus, in which 'it is Greek poets,
(2000a) 209. artists, and philosophers ... who have most perfectly rep-
resented the divine, and ... contemporary Greece is suf-
fering from Roman misrule' (Moles (1995b) 184).
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
THE THIRTEENTH ORATION OF DIO CHRYSOSTOM 129
they are, paradoxically, both uneducated and easily educable, and the latter no
the intrinsic 'easiness' of the Antisthenic/Cynic education, but because the R
expertise has already demonstrated their capacity for learning and because th
between Roman virtus and Cynic virtue. The practicability of that virtue is fur
the transition from Domitianic to Nervan and Trajanic Rome.164
Moreover, the content of Dio's teaching of the Romans is important. Desp
ticism,165 his claim (29ff.) to have publicly exhorted the Romans to virtue i
Or. 79,166 which attacks the city's materialism and argues that she will follow
into oblivion, if she does not reform (cf. Or. 13); by Or. 72,167 which wryly
larity of philosophers' preachiness (9); and by the Euboicus (Or. 7), which tac
of suitable work for the urban poor, which was delivered, among other plac
which, like Or. 13, has a certain Cynic underpinning.l68 Further, Or. 13 allu
sophical relationships with Nerva and Trajan, and it has repeated conceptual
First Kingship.169 Thus Orations 1-4 (the Kingships), 7, 13, and 79 (and, in l
contribute to a post-exilic project for the moral reform of Rome, with the Kin
the new emperor, the others on the Romans en masse.
This suggests another context for Or. 13. Although most of Dio's works are
delivery and many are occasional, some of the occasional pieces were recycled
texts;170 Dio emphasizes the paideutic value of reading; and some of his
reading works.171 Hence, besides the primary audiences of speeches deliv
Athens, Dio may also have envisaged a 'reading audience',172 which could con
13 alongside Orations 1-4, 7 and 79 and construct intertextual relationships.
readings 'work'. One might hold that Or. 13's subtleties make private reading
tion context anyway. The moral teaching of 29ff. could have been directly ava
as well as to Athenians and other Greeks.
But, if on any view Dio's moral teaching of the Romans is substantial, he is also saying pro-
foundly uncomfortable things to his primary audience. Any cosy feelings of Greek superiority
(cultural or other) are undermined on a number of levels. Athenian military successes of the fifth
and early fourth centuries BC are summarily dismissed by Socrates (25-6)173 - and the emphasis
matters, because of the parallel dismissal by Dio of Roman power (32, 34). Greeks who yearned
for the glory days174 are granted no indulgence. Even more challengingly dismissed are the main
constituents of traditional Athenian (and general Greek) paideia: music, athletics, the highest
literary achievements. This dismissal cannot be sanitized as 'inert' repetition of 'historical'
philosophical positions: in the Second Sophistic era, when Greece was, from one perspective,
under Roman rule (as this speech stresses), these were things that the Greek elite vigorously
celebrated.
Dio in fact uses various devices to suggest the collapsing of time between Socrates and
himself. One is to imply parallels between then and now (the triviality and impermanence of
164 Cf Tac. Agr. 3.1, etc. 171 Or. 18 is a reading-list for a politician and Or. 2 a
165 Swain (1996) 213; Whitmarsh (2001) 164, 215. reading-list for Trajan: Moles (1990) 346; Or. 3.3
166 Schmid (1903) 857; Moles (1983c) 130-1; contra approves Trajan's reading of 'the ancients' (including
Sheppard (1982) (exilic delivery in Tarsus) and DesideriDio's own Kingships); and Or. 52 starts from Dio's read-
(1978) 232-4 (exilic). ing of tragedy.
167 Von Arnim (1898) 276 (add 72.13-16 - 12.6-8); 172 Intriguingly, Whitmarsh (2001) 162: 'the sophisti-
Crosby (1951) 174-5; Russell (1992) 166; Desideri's
cated reader'. Note also 15, where Dio's playful
exilic dating ((1978) 235; 259 n.68) is untenable.
Thucydidean stress on the difficulty of recalling
168 Moles (1995b) 177-9 (naturally not the only philo-Socrates' X6yot gains piquancy from his own reliance on
sophical underpinning). a written text.
169 N.i1. 173 Similar in tone to Charidemus 30.35, with Moles
170 Cf 3.12; 4.73; Or. 5; Or. 7 (with Moles (1995b) (2000a) 209.
177); 11.6; Or. 57. 174 Bowie (1970); (1974); Plut. Praec. pol. 814a-c.
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
130 JOHN MOLES
Kingships,'77 the highly 6TaotSceuitvog Dio shows admirable flexibility in varying the dose
of conventional paideia to suit particular moral needs. And as in the Charidemus and Borys-
theniticus,178 Dio disconcertingly plays internal and external audiences off against each other.
This paradoxical convergence of need is pointed by structural patterning: just as Socrates
ended his appeal to the Athenians by engaging with their national myth (the epitaphios), so Dio
ends his appeal to the Romans by engaging with theirs (Romans do power, not culture); and the
175 Clearly Dio's own intervention: Desideri (1978) 177 Moles (1995b) 185.
221. 178 Russell (1992) 23; Moles (1995b) 184-92;
Nesselrath, Bibler, Forschner and de Jong (2003) appear
176 Of course, attacks on Roman luxury must also
impact on wealthy Athenians. uninterested in these interpretative aspects of the
Borystheniticus.
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
THE THIRTEENTH ORATION OF DIO CHRYSOSTOM 131
Philosophical simplicity
The speech issues an even more uncomfortable challenge to that most characte
sophisticated intellectuals (Greek and Roman, ancient and modern): that the
philosophy, the better it is. But, for all its philosophical allusions, Or. 13's m
essentially simple, as Dio insists,181 and it culminates in the exposition, direct
implicitly to the Athenians, of a modified version of Antisthenes' 'double ed
explicitly 'easy'. That the physical end of the speech which articulates that d
end of the speech (in the sense of its ultimate meaning) is conveyed by num
cumulative sense that Dio's 'wanderings' point towards 'the truth'; the status
Apollo-inspired final destination of those wanderings; the status of the text it
the sense of Dio as Nerva and Trajan's 'ambassador' to the Romans and as the
3pouog of the speech; and the sense that the Antisthenic 'double education' is
speech's quest for true education.
interested
179 Here the Charidemus is different: in the 'construction' of virtue; he take
Moles (2000a)
209. 'Romanness' and 'Greekness' (and 'Indianness' and
'Scythianness')
180 Hence another parallel with the subtly destabiliz-as givens. Nor is his double typology -
Greeks
ing Borystheniticus: Russell (1992) 23; Moles and Romans different, Greeks and Romans th
(1995b)
190-2. Whitmarsh's claims ((2001) 20, same
31) that "'Greek"
(as fellow members of the Roman empire) - prob
and "Roman" ... [are] constructed self-positions,
lematic. Ofideal-
course, one can decide which to emphasiz
ized reifications rather than self-evident
in a subjectivities'
given context, but that is not 'construction'.
181 P. constituted
and that 'identity is not expressed through but 123.
by social discourse' seem to me overwrought: Dio is
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
132 JOHN MOLES
Irony
How, then, does Dio's elaborate irony play within this ultimately simple moral scenario? Irony's
many effects undoubtedly include complicit pleasure between sophisticated audiences/readers
and sophisticated speakers/writers. 'For a sophisticated reader, the thirteenth oration's con-
spicuous focus upon [Dio's] ... random discovery of philosophy must be offset against his
knowing evocation of a deeply established narrative paradigm.'l82 But there is also philosophi-
cal irony, both Socratic and Cynic.
A main function of such irony is to challenge audiences' ability to discern underlying
seriousness. Dio's 'random discovery of philosophy' is notfinally random: apparent chance is
divine chance.183 The 'modesty' of his disclaimer of the title of philosopher is short-lived: such
terminology was avoided by Socrates himself (28). A more involved example is Dio's charac-
terization both of Socrates' logos and of himself as 'old' (14/29).184 There is much irony: the
allusion to 'a certain Socrates' (14),s85 the characterization of Socratic doctrine as 'old' and
'stale' (29), the very notion (especially in this highly sophisticated speech) of Dio himself as old-
fashioned and unlearned. Still, it is 'not hard' to see that the 'old' (dcXpXtiog) logos of 'old'
Socrates and 'old' Dio (who in 101 was even literally 'old' and looked it)186 unites such appar-
ently varied themes as the superiority of old wisdom to new; the inversion of beginning and end;
the associations between ancient wisdom, beginnings, endings and ruling (apjlj), and ruling as
self-rule, ruling others, and having good or bad rulers;187 the association between all these things
and 'good' and 'bad' fortune and 'good' and 'bad' 'chance';188 and the idea that Dio himself is
the mediator between past and present and between Greek and Roman and the instantiation of
the 'old', 'beginning', 'ruling' logos which potentially solves all moral problems. Dio constructs
a similar overriding architectural and thematic role for himself in other speeches, notably in the
First and Fourth Kingships, Euboicus, Olympicus, Borystheniticus and Charidemus.189
The move from formally depreciatory to positively assertive is underscored by several factors.
The characterization 'old and stale' (29) is elegantly 'pre-cut' by 15:
I requested them ... not to pay any the less attention just because I was saying the things which hap-
pened to have been said many years before, 'For,' I asserted, 'perhaps you will be helped most in this
way. For it is not at all likely that the words of old have evaporated like drugs and lost their power.'
The apparent equivocations about Socrates' logos are supplanted by the statements (30) that he
was admired by all the Greeks for his wisdom and esteemed wisest by Apollo. The always
implausible picture of Dio as an unoriginal and reluctant(!) performer (29) is undermined by the
allusions to his relations with Nerva and Trajan (analogous to Socrates' with Archelaus) and to
the Delphic oracle (another ring-structure), which reinforce the parallels between Socrates and
Dio and the validation of 'ancient wisdom'. Existing admirers of Dio (who certainly got the
invitations) will already know that appeal to such wisdom is one of his commonest moves.190
So much for irony as challenge to audiences' discernment of underlying seriousness.
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
THE THIRTEENTH ORATION OF DIO CHRYSOSTOM 133
Paideia
If Dio's supple and flexible irony does not threaten the simplicity of his moral teaching but on
the contrary emphasizes it, what of the speech's literary sophistication?
Of course, that literary sophistication, too, is to some extent pleasurable in its own right. Not
only, however, do the literary allusions become progressively more sparing,197 but there is a gath-
ering sense of literature's inadequacy as a moral guide. Exiled from his glittering Roman world,
Dio turns to epic and tragedy, Classical Greece's highest literary forms, but they counsel only
despair (4-6). Later, Dio notes that 'no one has propounded a tragedy about anyone simply
because he is poor' (20), pointedly underlining tragedy's incapacity as a vehicle for the Cynic
philosophical solution propounded by the speech itself. Better the 'tragic performance' of
Socrates (14) - or the tragic metabasis of Dio, returned from exile to Rome but as a chastened
Cynic. Dio's is the 'true', Cynic, tragedy - the one that works, both for himself and as a
paradigm for others.198 Not conventional paideia, then, but the paideia of Cynicism, which
rejects conventional paideia and replaces it with a simple moral programme. If, at the begin-
ning, the apparent simplicity of the speech is (on one level) deconstructed by its literary sophis-
tication and complexity, by the end (metaphorically, literally and literarily), that complexity itself
is unwinding.
It is course an acute paradox that a speech that rejects conventional paideia should itself con-
tain such paideia and in such large quantities. But such paradox is not 'play' for its own sake.
Cynic rhetoric is again relevant. Paradox itself challenges audiences to think about essentials.199
Cynics' use of sophisticated philosophical devices (for example, Diogenes' Politeia and syllo-
gisms)200 preempts intellectual contempt for the simplicity of Cynic moral teaching. His learned
and deft mobilization of different philosophical sources should prevent patronizing disparage-
191 Cf., e.g., Demetr. Eloc. 261; Diog. Laert. 6.38 194 Cf., e.g., Diog. Laert. 6.35, 38.
(Diogenes' self-description); Epict. 3.22.90; Dio 72.13. 195 P1. Ap. 36d.
192 12.12, 27-8, 47-8 (also 70.8), with Moles (1995b) 196 On this clever passage cf also n.133.
182 and n.21; I adhere to 97 as the Olympicus' date (also 197 Illustrative material in nn. 19-24.
Sheppard (1984) 159); 101 (Jones (1978) 53, 176 n.69) 198 Thus the implicit 'tragedy of Diogenes', arche-
might also allow Olympicus' priority; only 105 (far tootypal poor philosopher (2-5; n.21), is proleptic of the
late, I believe) would exclude it. 'correct tragic solution'.
193 The Palamedes being one of Gorgias' most cele- 199 Discussion in Moles (1993) 259-62; (1996) 105-7.
brated works, 21 also conveys anti-sophistic polemic. 200 Moles (1995a) 129-43 and (2000b) 423-32.
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
134 JOHN MOLES
Cynic (n;oatoy'Xotov.204
More fundamentally, however, the
paideia. Dio's Athenian audience need
systematically demonstrated to it,
sive retreat, and the blithe conclud
cation has no moral significance w
Ever since Philostratus and Synesius,205 critical discussion both of Dio's varied corpus and of
ambiguous career has revolved around the debate whether he should be classified as a philo
sopher or as a sophist, with such concomitant polarities as 'serious/playful', 'weighty/trivial'
'sincere/insincere'. The post-exile Dio wrote some sophistic works and sometimes performe
a sophist and had pupils who became sophists.206 He also wrote unequivocally philosoph
works. And some of his works actively resist such pigeonholing.207 'Sophistic' is part of 'p
formance culture', but 'philosophy' can be too. Cynics were necessarily public performers,
though some also wrote. Dio himself was one of the biggest public performers of his age.
it is also a philosophical technique (going back to Socrates and Plato) to 'out-sophist sophist
as a preliminary, or adjunct, to the proper business of philosophizing, or as a reducti
absurdum.209 Of course, the polarities 'philosopher/sophist', 'serious/playful', etc. are
sharp, particularly as applied to this period of Greek literature. Nevertheless, it may still
worth establishing the dominant propensity of a particular work, because that propensity m
itself be part of the meaning of the work (and of other similar works, though not necessaril
the oeuvre). Where, then, within these competing but overlapping landscapes, should we lo
Or. 13, performed in Athens (though arguably also a reading text)? Does it belong within '
highly charged, highly agonistic space of sophistic performance' and demonstrate that 'litera
can be sophisticated, ludic, self-ironizing, and/or irresponsible' and that 'literary texts do
provide a clear window into the souls of their authors'?210
Dio's 'sincerity' does not ultimately matter, although in one respect he is being insincere,2
and wedges between texts and authors can be excessively great (it would, for example
highly counter-intuitive to deny that Dio had a colossal ego, apparent throughout Or. 13).
it is the text that counts, and between the polarity of 'ludic' and 'sincere' lies the crucial tert
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
THE THIRTEENTH ORATION OF DIO CHRYSOSTOM 135
quid of 'serious'. This speech makes an argument, and, while that argument is ulti
ple, it is also serious, because practically everything in the speech contributes to i
'ludic' qualities positively reinforce its moral teaching, which is both overtly philos
we discount Dio's tissue-thin equivocations) and implicitly anti-sophistic.212 N
'contradictions' with other Dionian speeches explicable only in terms of 'the highl
highly agonistic space of sophistic performance'.213 Rather, the speech takes its pla
concerned with the Romans' moral status, though it simultaneously targets the Ath
it is actually its performance context (whether that in Athens or that which we as reader
reconstruct) that provides the last proof of its radically philosophical claims.
Dio says that, as part of his 'self-chastening' in response to the Delphic oracle, h
'humble dress' (10 orohiv ... tonetvilv). In context, this dress is Cynic and Dio's
it symbolises proleptically his conversion to Cynicism.214 Such Cynic dress is as 'u
may be (short of 'Gymnosophy' or 'Cynogamy'). When the Cynicized Socrates appe
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
136 JOHN MOLES
JOHN MOLE
University of Ne
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Amim, H. von (ed.) (1893) Dionis Prusaensis quem vocant Chrysostomum quae exstant omnia 1 (Ber
-(1898) Leben und Werke des Dion von Prusa (Berlin)
Billaut, A. (1999) 'Dion Chrysostome avait-il une theorie de la sculpture?', BAGB 1999, 211-29
Blomqvist, K. (1989) Myth and Moral Message in Dio Chrysostom. A Study in Dio 's Moral Thought
a Particular Focus on his Attitudes towards Women (Lund)
- (1995) 'Chryseis and Clea, Eumetis and the Interlocutress. Plutarch of Chaeronea and Dio Chrysos
on women's education', Svensk Exegetisk Arsbok 60, 173-90
Bowie, E.L. (1970), 'The Greeks and their past in the Second Sophistic', P&P 46, 3-41; revised v
(1974) in M.I. Finley (ed.), Studies in Ancient Society (London)
Boys-Stones, G.R. (2001) Post-Hellenistic Philosophy. A Study of its Development from the Stoics
Origen (Oxford)
Brancacci, A. (1992) 'Struttura compositiva e fonti della terza orazione Sulla Regalita di Dio
Crisostomo: Dione e 1' Archelao di Antistene', ANRW 2.36.5, 3308-34
- (2000) 'Dio, Socrates, and Cynicism', in Swain (2000) 240-60
Branham, R.B. (1996) 'Diogenes' rhetoric and the Invention of Cynicism', in Branham and Goulet-C
(eds) (1996) 81-104
- and Goulet-Caz6, M.-O. (eds) (1996) The Cynics. The Cynic Movement in Antiquity and its L
(Berkeley)
Brenk, F.E. (2000) 'Dio on the simple and self-sufficient life', in Swain (2000) 261-78
Brown, T.S. (1949) Onesicritus (Berkeley)
Brunt, P. (1973) 'Aspects of the social thought of Dio Chrysostom', PCPS 19, 9-34
Caizzi, F.D. (ed.) (1966) Antisthenisfragmenta (Milan)
Claassen, J.M. (1999) Displaced Persons. The Literature of Exile from Cicero to Boethius (London)
Cobet, C.G. (1878) Collectanea critica quibus continentur observationes criticae in scriptores Graecos
(Leiden)
Cohoon, J.W. and Lamar Crosby, H. (trans., eds) (1932-1951) Dio Chrysostom (5 vols, Cambridge, MA
and London)
Denniston, J.D. (1954) The Greek Particles (2nd edn, Oxford)
Denyer, N. (ed.) (2001) Plato. Alcibiades (Cambridge)
Desideri, P. (1978) Dione di Prusa. Un intellettuale greco nell' impero romano (Messina and Florence)
- (1991) 'Tipologia e variet" di funzione comunicativa degli scritti dionei', ANRW 2.33.5, 3903-59
Doblehofer, E. (1987) Exil und Emigration. Zum Erlebnis der Heimatferne in der r6mischen Literatur
(Darmstadt)
Ddring, K. (1995) 'Diogenes und Antisthenes', in G. Giannantoni et al. (eds), La tradizione Socratica
(Naples) 125-50
Douglas, A.E. (1966) Cicero. Brutus (Oxford)
Dudley, D.R. (1937) A History of Cynicism from Diogenes to the Sixth Century A.D. (London)
Diimmler, F. (1882) Antisthenica (Bonn)
- (1889) Akademica (Giessen)
Emperius, A. (1847) Opuscula Philologica et Historica (Gdttingen)
Erskine, A. (1995) 'Rome in the Greek world: the significance of a name', in A. Powell (ed.), The Greek
World (London) 368-79
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
THE THIRTEENTH ORATION OF DIO CHRYSOSTOM 137
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
138 JOHN MOLES
This content downloaded from 134.198.4.41 on Mon, 12 Aug 2019 00:33:07 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms