Ahloea 1 PDF
Ahloea 1 PDF
Ahloea 1 PDF
A Dissertation Presented
by
KRISTOFFER AHLSTROM
DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY
September 2010
Philosophy
© Copyright by Kristoffer Ahlstrom 2010
A Dissertation Presented
by
KRISTOFFER AHLSTROM
_______________________________________
Hilary Kornblith, Chair
_______________________________________
Jonathan Vogel, Member
_______________________________________
Christopher Meacham, Member
_______________________________________
Adrian Staub, Member
____________________________________
Phillip Bricker, Department Head
Philosophy
To Radha
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
Thanks to Richard Feldman, Mikkel Gerken, Alvin Goldman, Stephen Grimm, Klemens
Kappel, Christoph Kelp, Michael Lynch, Anne Meylan, Erik Olsson, Nikolaj Jang Lee
Linding Pedersen, Casey Perin, Duncan Pritchard, James Simmons, Robert Talisse, and J.
D. Trout for helpful feedback on different parts of the present material. Thanks also to
Christopher Meacham, Adrian Staub, and Jonathan Vogel for valuable comments and for
have asked for a better philosophical mentor. Last but in no way least, thanks to Radha—
for everything.
v
ABSTRACT
ON EPISTEMIC AGENCY
SEPTEMBER 2010
Every time we act in an effort to attain our epistemic goals, we express our epistemic
agency. The present study argues that a proper understanding of the actions and goals
recommendations about how the ways in which we actually express our agency can be
brought in line with how we should express our agency. More specifically, it is argued
that the actions relevant to such expressions should be identified with the variety of
actions characteristic of inquiry; that contrary to what has been maintained by recent
pluralists about epistemic value, the only goal relevant to inquiry is that of forming true
belief; and that our dual tendency for bias and overconfidence gives us reason to
agency in substantial ways. For example, we are often better off by gathering only a very
limited amount of information, having our selection of methods be greatly restricted, and
spending our time less on reflecting than on simply reading off the output of a simple
algorithm. In other words, when it comes to our freedom to express epistemic agency,
vi
TABLE OF CONTENTS
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS ...................................................................................................................... V
ABSTRACT .......................................................................................................................................... VI
CHAPTER
INTRODUCTION ................................................................................................................................... 1
2. I CAN’T MAKE YOU LOVE TRUTH (AND YOU CAN’T MAKE ME LOVE EVIDENCE)..... 35
7
4.2. On the Specialized Role of Epistemic Evaluation .......................................................... 123
8
INTRODUCTION
When considering the last fifty years of epistemology in the analytical tradition—filled
with far-fetched thought experiments involving evil demons, reliable clairvoyants, and
tradition, one of epistemology’s main missions is to provide hands-on advice, aiding the
epistemic inquirer in her pursuits. Understood thus, epistemology is not only normative,
in the sense that it concerns itself with specifically epistemic goods, but also
ameliorative, in that it attempts to say something constructive about how our odds of
(1999, p. 172). To the contrary, it was practiced by two of the most central historical
figures in Western epistemology, i.e., John Locke and Rene Descartes. The ameliorative
ambition of the latter is most obvious in his Rules for the Direction of the Mind and
Similarly, one of Locke’s main concerns was the reformation of people’s intellectual
lives from one based on tradition to one based on reason. Part of the motivation for such a
Conduct of the Understanding, simply that “there are a great many natural defects in the
understanding capable of amendment” (§2). In addition, bringing about the relevant kind
1
of amendment would, as Locke saw it, serve as a protection against the social conflicts
scale, social turmoil. The often banal ways in which our dual tendencies for bias and
unfortunately, often with far from banal consequences—is a sufficient reason for trying
to ameliorate our epistemic conduct and practices. On a more positive note, the very same
body of empirical research provides us with something that our epistemological ancestors
lacked, namely robust data on the systematic and often predictable ways in which we go
This is not to suggest that the epistemologist should be expected to do the job of
the empirical psychologist.2 Instead, it is to seek a middle ground between those who
would suggest that epistemology just is empirical psychology (as some uncharitable
readings of Quine would have him say) and those who wish to engage in amelioration
without at all engaging with the relevant empirical literature. As for the latter, consider
Robert Roberts and Jay Wood’s recent defense of what they call regulative
[…] to say that our virtue epistemology is regulative is not to deny that it’s
analytic. In fact, what we call analysis is our chief expedient of regulation. By the
1
See Wolterstorff (1996).
2
That is, unless the philosophers in question are trained to do so. In this context, consider
the interesting and in many ways commendable cross-scientific research associated with
so-called experimental philosophy.
2
conceptual work that is distinctive of philosophical discourse, we propose to
facilitate the improvement of intellectual character. If conceptual analysis is done
right, it clarifies the character of the intellectual life in a way that can actually
help people live that life. Conceptual clarification is an important part of
education, and the improvement of intellectual character is a kind of education.
Conceptual clarification is not the whole of education [but] it is at least
something, and it is what the philosopher is well suited to contribute (Roberts and
Wood 2007, pp. 27-28).
manner in which they restrict their contribution to that of conceptual analysis (as
evidenced by their book at large, not solely by the above passage) seems unnecessarily
is, clearly, something that comes in handy in all forms of inquiry. And it would probably
be a bad idea to assume that the skill-set of the typical philosopher naturally translates
into an aptitude for experimental work. But it is one thing to suggest that philosophers are
not well-suited for contributing empirical work of their own, and quite another to fail to
consult the vast amount of empirical work that is of high relevance to the multitude of
conducive to the relevant ends, given the surprising ways in which cognition sometimes
epistemic institutions. In fact, to be in the business of telling people how to think without
In contrast to the project of Roberts and Wood, the present study places itself
firmly within the ameliorative tradition of Locke and Descartes, as it has been developed
3
psychology of cognition in order to be effective.3 While much has been said about this
below is that one notion in particular has received little to no attention in connection with
the ameliorative project, i.e., the notion of epistemic agency. This omission is unfortunate
since the notion of epistemic agency has the potential of playing a central role in
agency is the kind of agency we express through actions performed in an effort to attain
our epistemic goals. This characterization begs for clarification on at least two points.
(Further clarifications will be postponed for now.) First, what are the actions by way of
which we express such agency? Second, what are our epistemic goals, or goal, if it turns
out that there is only one? Chapter 1 approaches the first question by considering three
candidate accounts of the relevant actions. The first account identifies epistemic agency
with doxastic agency, or decisions about what to believe. The second account identifies
epistemic agency with the kind of reflective agency or authority that some have
maintained that we have over our reflectively formed beliefs. The third account also
identifies epistemic agency with reflective agency, but motivates it with reference to the
All three accounts are rejected, the first one because it is committed to doxastic
voluntarism, the second one because it fails to delimit a sufficiently robust notion of
freedom to be relevant to amelioration, and the third one because it relies on too
optimistic a view of the epistemic merits of reflection. Contrary to other recent critiques
3
See, e.g., Bishop and Trout (2005), Kitcher (1992) and Goldman (1978).
4
See Kornblith (1994).
4
of the relevant accounts, however, it will not be concluded that the appeal to epistemic
agency, thereby, is “nothing more than a bit of mythology.”5 The notion of epistemic
understanding of the domain of epistemic agency serves to delimit exactly the kind of
In fact, understood thus, the question of what actions are relevant to the
expression of epistemic agency is almost trivial. After all, to perform actions for the
purpose of forming true belief in a manner that furthers our epistemic goals is to engage
in inquiry. In other words, epistemic agency is constituted by all the things we do when
conducting inquiry. We gather information, mull over our data, choose among different
methods of investigation, and so on, and in so far as we are doing all of this in an attempt
to attain our epistemic goals, we are expressing our epistemic agency. At the same time,
the very triviality of such an account of the actions relevant to epistemic agency suggests
that the interesting questions regarding epistemic agency lie elsewhere. One such
question is the ameliorative question, namely: How can the ways in which we actually
express our agency be brought in line with how we should express our agency, given our
epistemic goals? However, this question begs a further one, posed already in the above,
This gets back to the observation that epistemology is normative. To talk about
epistemic goals is to talk about epistemic value, in that the goals of inquiry determine
what activities, states, processes, practices, and so on, are epistemically valuable.
5
Kornblith (forthcoming, p. 118; all page references to this work refer to the manuscript).
5
Chapters 2 and 3 develop and defend a particular account of such value that has come
under fire in recent discussions in epistemic axiology, namely that true belief is the only
value. More specifically, the idea that believing truly is valuable thus is defended on two
fronts, both from those denying that true belief is a non-instrumental epistemic value, and
from those who deny that true belief is the only non-instrumental epistemic value.
Chapter 2 takes on the former challenge by considering the case for a kind of
evidentialism that takes believing upon sufficient evidence to be the only goal of inquiry
and, consequently, also the only thing of non-instrumental epistemic value. For reasons
that will be discussed below, the strategy will not be to reject such a take on value, but
merely to protect the idea that truth is of non-instrumental epistemic value from the
evidentialist’s contention that it is not. More specifically, it will be argued that the
prospects for providing someone who does not share one’s love for the relevant non-
instrumental epistemic goods with reasons for starting to do so seem dim. However, the
point applies equally to the evidentialist as to those of us who value true belief non-
instrumentally from an epistemic point of view. Moreover, given that failure to convince
someone to value something is by no means a sufficient reason for ceasing to value that
thing, this dialectical fact renders neither axiological position illegitimate. In light of this,
subsequent chapters assume the position taken by most epistemologists to the effect that
Chapter 3 takes up the second challenge, i.e., that of showing that true belief is
not just one non-instrumental epistemic value among many. Here, the strategy will be
less reconciliatory. Recently, epistemic value monism—i.e., the idea that believing truly
6
is unique in possessing non-instrumental epistemic value—has come under attack by
philosophers arguing that we cannot account fully for the domain of epistemic value in
monistic terms. However, it will be argued that the relevant critiques fail to establish any
such thing. For one thing, there is a presumption of monism due to considerations about
evidence to the effect that the relevant kind of monism makes us unable to fully account
for the domain of epistemic value. But a proper examination and subsequent rebuttal of
the most promising counterexamples to monism casts serious doubt upon the claim that
there is any such evidence. Consequently, epistemic value monism still stands, and true
belief is not only a but the only good of non-instrumental, epistemic value.
It does not follow from true belief being the only good of non-instrumental
epistemic value that all true beliefs are valuable thus. More specifically, chapter 4 argues
that the epistemic value of a practice is a function of the extent to which it yields true
beliefs that answer questions posed by relevant sets of inquirers. As such, the account
tells us something about what methods or practices inquirers should utilize, in so far as
they want answers to their questions. The remainder of the chapter is primarily concerned
with tracing the limits of this ‘should,’ and suggests that there are very real limits to the
extent to which we can make epistemological judgments about what questions inquirers
should pose (as opposed to about what practices to opt for, given a set of questions).
However, it is also argued that, rather than indicating a flaw in the account, this simply
suggests that it is able to account for the specialized nature of epistemic evaluation.
7
actions and goal relevant to epistemic agency can be used to make recommendations
about how the ways in which we actually express our agency may be brought in line with
how we should express our agency. More specifically, a case is made for the claim that
our dual tendency for bias and overconfidence gives us pro tanto reason for mandating
compliance with methods that have been shown to increase our reliability. Moreover, it is
argued that mandating compliance thus would be epistemically paternalistic, and that we
have reason—indeed, not just pro tanto but all-things-considered reason—to practice
To sum up, when properly understood, epistemic agency has nothing to do with
decisions about what to believe, and far less to do with reflection than some have
conducting inquiry. As such, epistemic agency is neither a myth, nor something the
expression of which should be considered epistemically valuable in its own right. After
all, given the plausibility of epistemic value monism and the prevalence of bias and
overconfidence, it turns out that we are often better off from the point of view of attaining
paternalistic practices. In other words, when it comes to our freedom to express agency,
8
CHAPTER 1
What is it to express epistemic agency? It is, clearly, to do something. But, surely, that is
not sufficient. Someone falling down a set of stairs is doing something, namely falling
down a set of stairs, but not, thereby, expressing any agency, let alone any epistemic
action. But the relevant kind of action cannot be directed toward just any goal. A stunt
man deliberately and skillfully falling down a set of stairs on a movie set is not only
doing something but also performing an action directed at the goal of making it seem as if
she is falling down the stairs by accident, while doing so deliberately and (if skillfully)
with no significant risk of harm. So, what is the particular goal—or goals, if there turns
needs to be directed? Subsequent chapters will make a case for a particular answer to this
question, namely true belief, and use it to provide the foundation for an account of
epistemic value. For the remainder of this chapter, however, this answer will simply be
at the goal of forming true belief, several questions remain. First, what does it mean to be
“directed” at the goal of forming true belief? Does it imply that the agent in question
consciously entertains that goal whenever performing whatever actions are associated
9
with expressions of epistemic agency? That seems too strong. Many paradigmatic
agency, such as the everyday inquiry of a scientific researcher, involve subjects that do
not consciously keep that goal in mind at all times. Surely, they could bring it to mind, if
properly prompted, and if we had to put any constraint on agency it would be that the
agent in question at least has the ability to entertain (and endorse) the relevant goal
epistemic agent. Such a constraint would rule out what seem less controversial instances
of non-agency, such as that of the infant crawling across the floor in proto-inquiry, or an
ant foraging. This is not to suggest that epistemic agency is a prerogative of adult
humans. Some adults might lack the conceptual sophistication required to think of
themselves as engaging in a project directed at forming true belief, and some non-human
Second, do the actions directed at the goal of forming true belief need to be
successful, i.e., actually terminate in the attainment of true belief, in order to qualify as
expressions of epistemic agency? In one sense, clearly not. A researcher has not failed to
express epistemic agency just because she gets something wrong. That said, our intuitions
get less clear when we consider the other limiting case, i.e., someone sincerely pursuing
truth but doing a terrible job at it. Consider, for example, an astrologist who sincerely
believes that her study of the movements and relative positions of celestial bodies
provides her with predictive data about human behavior. Could she (qua astrologist) still
account of how her ideas about what is truly predictive of what are so far off the mark,
10
we might want to put the following success constraint on epistemic agency: in order to
qualify as an epistemic agent, one’s methods of inquiry must be generally reliable with
respect to the relevant subject matters. Let us refer to a notion of agency invoking this
I hesitate to embrace such a strong notion because it places those in greatest need
of intellectual advice outside the scope of agency. Moreover, rejecting above success
constraint and, in effect, opting for what we may call a weak notion of agency, does not
serve to disqualify considerations about success from questions that may be posed in
qualify as an epistemic agent; she would just be a terrible epistemic agent. Given that
diagnosis, we could admit her into the domain of epistemic agency, and then determine
how she could start doing things differently, in order to make more successful predictions
about human behavior. After all, if you are interested in providing useful intellectual
advice, what you are interested in doing are two things. First, you want to determine what
people engaging in actions directed (successfully or not) at the goal of forming true belief
are actually doing. Second, to the extent that they are unsuccessful in their pursuits, you
want to say something constructive about what the agents in question should be doing
This provides the first motivation for an inquiry into the notion of epistemic
agency: Contrary to what its absence in previous epistemological treatments might lead
us to believe, the notion of epistemic agency has an important role to play in ameliorative
delimit exactly the kind of activities with which ameliorative recommendations are to be
11
concerned. One way to illustrate this point in more detail is by thinking of the domain of
C
B
A
D
A encompasses the ways in which we actually express our agency. These actions are
relevant because, as noted above, our actual epistemic practices provide the point of
departure for any ameliorative advice. C encompasses the ways in which we could
express our agency, and C–A the ways in which we could express our agency differently
from what we are presently doing. Furthermore, A∩B designates the ways in which we
are doing things right from the point of view of attaining true belief, and B–A the ways in
which we could be doing things differently and for the better. Finally, everything that
falls outside the scope of C pertains to the ways in which we could not express our
agency, designated above by D. As will become clear in the next section, D is relevant
for a purely negative reason in that it tells us something about the ways in which we
cannot do things differently, and what we, consequently, have to work around rather than
The second motivation for an inquiry into the notion of epistemic agency is what
most likely also provides the reason for the notion’s absence from the relevant
discussions, namely a series of accounts about what epistemic agency amounts to that are
12
of no help in so far as we are interested in amelioration. It is the burden of the remainder
of this chapter to consider some of the most prominent accounts of such agency,
demonstrate the ways in which they fall short as far as the ameliorative project is
concerned, and then show how the notion of epistemic agency can be re-established so as
to play an important role within that project, in line with what was just outlined.
Above, it was argued that to express epistemic agency is to engage in actions directed
(consciously or not) at the goal of forming true belief. What are the relevant actions? One
way to approach this question is by considering one of the most fundamental objects of
epistemic evaluation, i.e., belief. Beliefs can be justified, rational, and constitute
knowledge. In addition, our beliefs make up the “map of neighbouring space by which
we steer,” as pointed out by Frank P. Ramsey (1931). Given that some ways of steering
are more successful than others (epistemically or otherwise), one straightforward way to
understand the actions of epistemic agency is in terms of decisions about what beliefs to
form (or not to form). Let us refer to the relevant kind of agency—if there is, indeed, such
The main problem with the suggestion that epistemic agency is to be identified
with doxastic agency is that it amounts to assuming doxastic voluntarism. That is, it
amounts to assuming that belief-formation is under our voluntary control and that we, in
effect, are able to form beliefs at will. This view seems doubtful, to say the least.
“Believing, we feel, is not something one can in any sense decide to do or refrain from, it
13
seems rather a condition in which one finds oneself,” as John Heil writes (1984, p. 56).
Can you, at this moment, start to believe that the Roman Empire is still in control
of Western Europe, just by deciding to do so? If you find it incredible that you
should be sufficiently motivated to even try believing this, suppose that someone
offered you $500 million to believe it, and that you are much more interested in
the money than believing the truth. Could you do what it takes to get at the
reward? Remember that we are speaking of believing at will. No doubt, there are
things you could do that would increase the probability of your believing this
[but] can you switch propositional attitudes toward that proposition just by
deciding to do so? It seems clear to me that I have no such powers. Volitions,
decision, or choosings don’t hook up with propositional attitude inaugurations,
just as they don’t hook up with the secretion of gastric juices or with metabolism
(Alston 2005, p. 63).
At this point, the voluntarist may object that the aforementioned line of reasoning
presupposes a far too strong reading of “voluntary control.” More specifically, it might be
objected that it is being assumed that the relevant kind of voluntarism requires direct
control over our belief-forming processes, where having direct voluntary control implies
being able to bring about the object of control by a mere act of will, intention or volition.1
This is the kind of control we might have over mental imagery—i.e., our ability to bring
about mental pictures—but that we do not seem to have over our belief-forming
processes. However, the voluntarist may insist that there are other forms of control, most
decreasingly direct control. For example, certain things may be brought about not by a
direct act of will, but by way of a chain of events, making up a single, uninterrupted act.
This is the sense in which opening my door or adjusting the temperature in my office is
1
The distinction between direct and indirect voluntary control is borrowed from Alston
(2005), as are the further distinctions between different kinds of control discussed below.
14
within my voluntary control; while I may not be able to open the door or alter the
temperature merely by an act of will, the opening of the door and altering of the
possible for me to bring about the necessary chain of events that is me getting up,
walking across the room, and opening the door or turning the knob on the thermostat.
Even further out on the continuum of indirect voluntary control are the kinds of
acts that do not constitute single, uninterrupted acts, like walking over and opening a door
or turning a knob, but rather a series of inter-related actions spread out over an extended
period of time. This is the sense in which looking for more evidence, taking steps to
engage in more thorough consideration and weighing of evidence, and deliberating over
voluntary control. This is also the kind of control Roderick Chisholm seems to be getting
As pointed out by Alston, however, any attempt to frame doxastic voluntarism in terms of
15
namely the distinction between doing C to voluntarily bring about an E, and doing C to
In order that the phenomenon of looking for more evidence would show that we
have voluntary control over propositional attitudes, it would have to be the case
that the search for evidence was undertaken with the intention of taking up a
certain attitude toward a specific proposition. For only in that case would it have
any tendency to show that we have exercised voluntary control over what
propositional attitude we come to have (Alston 2005, p. 70).
In other words, the fact that we do have voluntary control over many actions that might
give rise to beliefs does not show that we have voluntary control over what beliefs we
form as a result of those actions. The same goes for various forms of indirect voluntary
directness—where we may take steps that either bring to bear on candidates for belief or
on our general belief-forming habits and tendencies. That we may have such influence
over our beliefs does not show that doxastic voluntarism is true, i.e., that we may
voluntarily choose what specific propositions to believe, anymore than our ability to open
our eyes and look out a window on a sunny day shows that we may choose whether or
The implications of this are far from trivial as for how we are to understand
epistemic agency, since the failure of doxastic voluntarism suggests that the domain of
belief-formation not only does not but cannot coincide with the domain of epistemic
agency. Indeed, above considerations suggest that the two domains are completely
distinct, since one pertains to something that we do (i.e., agency), and the other to
something that simply happens to us (i.e., belief-formation). More than that, if the two
16
relates to epistemic amelioration, will be reduced to a set of unhelpful intellectual
borrow Alston’s analogy, are no more helpful than dietary recommendations framed
At this point, it might be objected that the previous section invoked a too narrow notion
of our doxastic activities, as one involving mere responses to external stimuli. After all,
as human beings, we not only form first-order beliefs, such as perceptual belief; we also
second-order beliefs, or beliefs about our beliefs.2 More than this, unlike belief, reflection
is not simply a condition that we find ourselves in; it is something that we do. For one
thing, we may choose when and on what to reflect—a fact that will be considered in the
next section. For another, the phenomenology of reflection surely suggests that we have
some say when it comes to what beliefs we end up with as a result of reflecting.
important sense up to us. However, he explicitly rejects the idea that he is, thereby,
committing himself to any form of doxastic voluntarism: “The agency a person exercises
2
‘Reflection’ is sometimes used in a manner that does not (necessarily) involve any
second-order beliefs, as when we talk about reflecting on our data. That is not how the
notion of reflection will be used here.
3
Similar themes to those found in Moran can be found also in Korsgaard (1996), on
which parts of Moran’s investigation rest. However, given that Moran is more explicitly
concerned with belief-formation than Korsgaard is, I will focus on the former presently.
17
with respect to his belief and other attitudes,” he writes, “is obviously not like that of
overt basic actions like reaching for a glass” (p. 114). Still, we have a very real authority
over what beliefs we form, and this authority is what makes it possible for the agent to be
Beliefs and other attitudes […] are stances of the person to which the demand for
justification is internal. And the demand for justification internal to the attitudes
involves a sense of agency and authority that is fundamentally different from the
various forms of direction or control one may be able to exercise over some mind
or other (Moran 2001, p. 114).
It should be noted that Moran’s concern with a sense of agency and authority, albeit,
question is simply a matter of the agent assuming responsibility for her actions (e.g., on
p. 131)—a way of framing the issue that is compatible with such assumptions being
metaphysically mistaken. However, the great majority of passages makes clear that
formation not only seems to be but really is up to us. Indeed, Moran’s book is fraught
with locutions to the effect that we make up our minds (p. 92) by stepping back from
some content of consciousness (p. 141) in order to call into question what we are inclined
to believe (p. 143) and decide or commit ourselves to believing something (p. 145).
So, how are we to interpret these locutions, without either committing Moran to
18
The stance from which a person speaks with any special authority about his belief
or his action is not a stance of causal explanation but the stance of rational
agency. In belief as in intentional action, the stance of the rational agent is the
stance where reasons that justify are at issue, and hence the stance from which
one declares the authority of reason over one’s belief and action. Anscombe’s
question “why?” is asking not for what might best explain the movement that
constitutes the agent’s action, but instead is asking for the reasons he takes to
justify his action, what he is aiming at. It is as an expression of the authority of
reason here that he can and must answer the question of his belief or action by
reflection on the reasons in favor of this belief or action. To do otherwise would
be for him to take the course of his belief or his intentional action to be up to
something other than his sense of the best reasons, and if he thinks that, then
there’s no point in his deliberating about what to do. Indeed, there is no point in
calling it “deliberation” any more, if he takes it to be an open question whether
this activity will determine what he actually does or believes. To engage in
deliberation in the first place is to hand over the question of one’s belief or
intentional action to the authority of reason (Moran 2001, p. 127).
Understood thus, there might, at first glance, seem to be a tension between the rationality
and the agency of rational agency. After all, how do we square the idea of agency or
freedom with the restrictive demands of reason and rationality? To understand Moran’s
answer, it might help to consider Descartes’ answer to a question not too different from
this one. In his Meditations on First Philosophy, Descartes argues that God has bestowed
us with free will. At the same time, Descartes takes it that the purest form of freedom is
the one exercised when the clarity and distinctness of a truth is so apparent that it prompts
more or less automatic assent, and the will is completely overpowered, so to speak, by the
psychological force of the intellect.4 At first, this might seem incompatible with freedom,
[…] the will simply consists in our ability to do or not to do something (that is, to
affirm or deny, to pursue or avoid); or rather, it consists simply in the fact that
when the intellect puts something forward for affirmation or denial or for pursuit
4
See Descartes (1641/1984, p. 48; AT VII 69).
19
or avoidance, our inclinations are such that we do not feel we are determined by
any external force. In order to be free, there is no need for me to be inclined both
ways; on the contrary, the more I incline in one direction—either because I clearly
understand that reasons of truth and goodness point that way, or because of a
divinely produced disposition of my inmost thoughts—the freer is my choice
(Descartes 1641/1984, p. 40; AT VII 57-58).
In other words, to be free in the relevant sense is not to be able to opt out of the demands
of rationality, but rather to reason in ways that are sensitive to the demands in question.
In fact, according to Descartes, freedom takes its purest form when perfectly aligned with
those demands. Moran seems to be working with a relevantly similar notion of freedom,
as made clear in the following passage, where he discusses the relevant notions of
control, activity and responsibility, as they pertain to desires and belief (which, for
The person’s responsibility […] is to make his desire answerable to and adjustable
in the light of his sense of some good to pursue. It is not a responsibility that
reduces to the ability to exert influence over one’s desires, and that is why the
idiom of “control” is misleading in this context. When the desire is (already) the
expression of the person’s reasons, there is no need for exerting any control over
it. As in the case of ordinary theoretical reasoning, which issues in a belief, there
is no further thing the person does in order to acquire the relevant belief once his
reasoning has led him to it. At the beginning of his practical reasoning he was not
aiming to produce a particular desire in himself (as he might with respect to
another person), but rather holding open his desire to how the balance of reasons
falls out (Moran 2001, pp. 118-119).
In other words, the relevant kind of authority, i.e., rational authority (p. 124), is one on
which we are not so much choosing what to reflectively believe—as in: choosing what
our reflective faculties to lead us toward the proper conclusion, under the assumption that
they are sensitive to the demands that rationality places on us. That is why Moran’s
20
account of agency is compatible with doxastic involuntarism; the kind of freedom or
agency associated with rational authority does not require that we can decide what beliefs
That said, if this is Moran’s take on what it is for the beliefs formed on the basis
of reflection to be “up to us,” his account of the kind of authority at issue is not relevant
to epistemic agency, in so far as the latter notion relates to epistemic amelioration. To see
why, return to the first motivation for an inquiry into the domain of epistemic agency
discussed above. What we noted was that, in so far as we are interested in providing
intellectual advice, we are interested in finding out two things, namely what people
engaging in actions directed at the goal of forming true belief are actually doing, as well
as what they should be doing differently, in so far as they could be doing better with
respect to attaining that goal. Given that the objective of amelioration is to provide
intellectual advice, that someone should do something differently presupposes that the
target activity is one over which she has effective voluntary control—which was exactly
what disqualified doxastic agency as a plausible account of agency. Again, in want of any
in terms of decisions about what to believe, any more than dietary recommendations can
far as our beliefs are formed under the rational authority of reason. As we have also seen,
however, Moran makes it clear that the kind of authority manifested under such
circumstances neither requires nor typically involves any voluntary control (let alone any
21
acknowledgement has him steer clear of doxastic voluntarism, it also serves to insulate
the relevant reflective processes from ameliorative recommendations. After all, to have
authority over what you believe upon reflection is to hand over your belief-formation to
the authority of reason (as Moran puts it), and to do so is exactly to not be able to believe
Although this suggests that there is no agency of the kind relevant to amelioration
to be found in what Moran refers to as rational authority, it is important to note that this
does not serve to discredit his account, as far as his (non-ameliorative) project is
concerned. When encountering evidence that things are not going my way, I may have a
strong desire to believe contrary to what the evidence suggests. If I could believe (and not
believe) at will upon reflection, resisting the force of the evidence would be an easy feat.
That, however, does not change the fact that there is a sense in which I would not be
believing as I should, were I to resist the evidence thus. Differently put, as far as
be sensitive to what we want to believe, but rather to what we have reason to believe. So,
perhaps it is not such a bad thing that our belief-forming tendencies are to a certain extent
(albeit not completely, as instances of wishful thinking go to show) insulated from our
desires and the influence of the will—which, of course, is exactly in line with Moran’s
22
1.4. On the Epistemic Merits of Reflection
The previous section suggested that, in so far as there is a sense in which what beliefs we
end up with as a result of reflection is up to us, this does not serve to delimit a notion of
legitimate domain of agency associated with reflection, identified in passing above when
it was noted that we may choose voluntarily when and on what to reflect (although, as we
have seen, not what beliefs to form as a result of such choices). To this extent, reflection,
that is directed at the goal of forming true belief. The questions to be discussed in this
section, however, is whether it is the only thing that we can do thus, or even something
that it generally is a good thing to do, given the goal in question. Let us attend to the
[…] reflection aids agency, control of conduct by the whole person, not just by
peripheral modules. When reasons are in conflict, as they so often are, not only in
deliberation but in theorizing, and not only in the higher reaches of theoretical
science but in the most ordinary reasoning about matters of fact, we need a way
holistically to strike a balance, which would seem to import an assessment of the
respective weights of pros and cons, all of which evidently is played out through a
perspective on one’s attitudes and the bearing of those various reasons (Sosa
2004, p. 292).
Notice that Sosa’s claim that reflection aids agency depends, crucially, on certain
assumptions about the epistemic merits of reflection. After all, it would make little sense
to talk about reflection aiding agency, if it turned out that reflection generally did not
weigh pros and cons properly, nor strike an epistemically appropriate balance between
reasons. If that turned out to be the case, I highly doubt that Sosa would still be inclined
23
to consider reflection aiding agency, in the relevant sense.5 In short, in so far as reflection
This, moreover, is completely in line what Sosa (1991) says in relation to his
thereby, not only demonstrating a “direct response to the fact known but also [an]
understanding of its place in a wider whole that includes one’s belief and knowledge of it
and how these come about” (p. 240) will, at least in a preponderance of cases, make you
epistemically better off than not reflecting on your beliefs.6 Distinguishing reflective
from animal knowledge, i.e., the kind of knowledge resulting from a cognitive faculty
If Sosa is right, it would seem reasonable to have reflection play an important role in our
account of epistemic agency, since reflection would not only pertain to something we can
do but also to something the exercise of which serves the goals of such agency well. And
as we have seen, Sosa does, indeed, take reflection to be central to epistemic agency.
5
This is further evidenced by the fact that Sosa (in conversation) denies that that the kind
of empirical evidence to be discussed below, suggesting (it will be argued) that reflecting
does not generally make one better off from an epistemic point of view, gives us any
reason to re-evaluate the epistemic merits of reflection. Denying that such a re-evaluation
is called for would have been unnecessary, were the role of reflection in agency taken to
be independent of the epistemic merits of the former.
6
It is not completely clear on Sosa’s account whether the “understanding” in question
needs to be a result of conscious reflection, or whether a certain counterfactual sensitivity
to contrary evidence is sufficient. Some passages seem to suggest the latter (e.g., Sosa
1991, p. 240 and 2007, p. 111), others the former (e.g., 2007, p. 117). See Kornblith
(forthcoming) for a discussion.
24
However, if Sosa is not right in assuming that we in general are better off for reflecting as
opposed to not reflecting, then it would seem that, although epistemic agents may still
express their agency by reflecting, we lack good reason to endow reflection with a
particularly central role, at the expense of other cognitive tools or strategies with perhaps
cognitive faculties are field-specific.7 In other words, what is relevant for the epistemic
evaluation of a faculty is not simply reliability, but reliability with respect to a certain set
Just how fields are defined is determined by the lay of interesting, illuminating
generalizations about human cognition, which psychology and cognitive science
are supposed in time to uncover. […] Human intellectual virtues are abilities to
attain cognitive accomplishments in “natural” fields, which would stand out by
their place in useful, illuminating generalizations about human cognition (Sosa
1991, p. 236).
In other words, if we want to know how to individuate faculties for the purpose of
evaluating the reliability of those faculties, we need to look to cognitive science. So are
we, as a matter of empirical fact, in general better off from an epistemic point of view for
reflecting?
Relevant experimental evidence suggests that the answer is “no.” For one thing, it
is well known that we suffer from a variety of cognitive biases when reasoning under
uncertainty.8 This is not a problem for reflection per se, since many of the biases in
question pertain to non-reflective cognition. But keep in mind that the idea is supposed to
7
See Sosa (1991, p. 236).
8
See Gilovich et al. (2002).
25
be that, by reflecting on our first-order beliefs, formed non-reflectively, we will be made
better off from an epistemic point of view, due to the corrective influence of reflection.
Such an optimistic take on the power of reflection simply does not hold up in light of the
evidence, one important reason being that we systematically underestimate the extent to
which we (as opposed to everyone else) suffer from cognitive bias.9 More specifically,
when reflecting on our grounds for belief, we have a strong tendency to conclude that our
beliefs are well supported, even when they are not.10 For this reason, reflecting on our
grounds for belief does not invariably or even in general make us epistemically better off
In fact, we are sometimes worse off for reflecting, as opposed to not reflecting.
The last fifty years of predictive modeling suggest that we may often increase our
available evidence, and defecting from general rules in so far as the situation is perceived
models.11 In fact, the greatest challenge for those developing such models is no longer to
identify reliable models, but to convince people that they will be better off for using
them. In other words, it is not lack of reliability but defection from policies urging that
we use the models in question that is the main challenge. Moreover, as we will discuss at
length in chapter 5, one of the primary activities driving up the defection rates is subjects
9
See Pronin et al. (2002).
10
This finding should be considered against the background of a large body of
experimental research suggesting that we have a general tendency to overestimate our
abilities (cognitive or otherwise). See Taylor (1989) for an overview of relevant research.
11
See Dawes et al. (2002).
26
reflecting on their reliability and coming to believe—falsely and as a result of
overconfidence—that they will be better off by not relying on the models in question.12 In
other words, reflecting on our grounds for belief sometimes makes us epistemically
worse off than we would have been, had we opted for strategies that do not involve
reflection.
What is the implication for how we ought to think about the relation between
reflection and epistemic agency? It is not that reflection is a useless intellectual tool, or
that reflecting always leaves us worse off than not reflecting. Nor is it that decisions
about when or on what to reflect may not constitute expressions of epistemic agency.
Reflection has just turned out to have a mixed epistemic track-record—like most of our
related to epistemic agency than is any other goal-directed attempt to form true belief. In
This gets back to a question raised above: Is reflecting the only action relevant to
epistemic agency? It will be suggested below that the answer is “no,” and if we want to
understand what agents can actually do to increase their chances for forming true belief,
and, thereby, identify the ways in which questions about agency may be relevant to
12
See Sieck and Arkes (2005).
27
1.5. Is Epistemic Agency a Myth?
In a recent investigation into some of the same philosophers discussed above, Hilary
take on the connection between reflection and agency, Kornblith writes that “the appeal
to epistemic agency seems to be nothing more than a bit of mythology” (p. 118). About
introduced by Moran “do not provide us with convincing reasons to believe that there
really is such a thing as epistemic agency” (p. 126). As made clear above, there are
certainly things to be said about the particular ways in which Sosa and Moran are
The reason why this is so has been hinted at several times above, but let us revisit
the relevant issues in the context of Kornblith’s complaints. One of his complaints is that
moving from the unreflective to the reflective level of belief-formation does not introduce
any epistemic agency; in both cases, what beliefs I form is not up to me. Kornblith makes
serving on a jury, you may be doing several things, such as focusing your attention on
various pieces of evidence, as well as posing questions about their probity. Focusing your
attention thus, however, is no different as far as agency is concerned from you turning
your head or opening your eyes when forming various perceptual beliefs. Kornblith
writes:
28
Whether I turn my head is determined by my choice, but once my head is turned
in a certain direction, with my eyes open, and the lighting just so, my perceptual
mechanisms will simply operate in me in ways which have nothing at all to do
with the fact that I am an agent. The fact that I focus my attention, and question
the relevance and probity of the evidence, thus show no more agency when I
reflect than goes on in unreflective cases. Indeed, these activities not only show
no more epistemic agency than goes on in unreflective cases in human beings;
they show no more epistemic agency than goes on in lower animals when they
form perceptual beliefs. But this is just to say that these features of reflectively
formed belief do not exhibit epistemic agency at all (Kornblith forthcoming, p.
117).
doxastic agency, i.e., agency with respect to what beliefs to form. Only under this
presupposition does it follow from both the reflective and the unreflective case involving
an element of non-agency, in that what beliefs we form in response to the relevant stimuli
is not within our voluntary control, that neither case involves any agency whatsoever.
However, there is a perfectly good sense in which both the reflective and unreflective
scenario may involve a kind of epistemic agency. The best argument to this effect is that
only by acknowledging that this is so can we distinguish clearly between the kind of
ameliorative advice that is bound to be unhelpful, and the kind of advice that may be
effectively prescribed.
Consider the reflective case first. As we have seen, someone reflecting on her
beliefs does not, thereby, gain any control over what beliefs she form as a result of
reflecting. Consequently, any attempt at improving her reasoning by telling her what
beliefs to form or not to form on reflection are bound to be completely unhelpful. That
said, there are many other kinds of advice that she may be given, e.g., with respect to
what kind of evidence-gathering practices she should involve herself in over others,
29
under what conditions she is better off subjecting her beliefs to reflective scrutiny as
opposed to opting for strategies that involve no such scrutiny, and so on. Providing such
advice is worthwhile exactly because what she does on these scores is within her control.
Moreover, in so far as she chooses one option over the other in a manner that can be
properly characterized as directed at the goal of forming true belief, she is expressing her
ameliorative advice on the issue—that will actually make her better off with respect to
the formation of true belief, she is expressing her epistemic agency wisely.
the process of learning to read an x-ray plate. While no one has direct influence over
what perceptual beliefs they form as a result of observation, the medical student may,
clearly, benefit from being told exactly how and where to look at the plate. Advising her
thus is worthwhile exactly because what she chooses to do here is within her control.
Moreover, in so far as she looks in the right way and on the right locations, and,
eventually, arrives at an accurate diagnosis, she can be said to not only be expressing her
epistemic agency but to be expressing it wisely. And that is so irrespective of whether her
attention at any point in the process of following her teacher’s instructions moves from
previous sections have made clear, what is crucial as far as the expression of epistemic
agency is concerned is not that the agent in question reflects on her beliefs, but that she is
doing things (reflectively or not) in a manner that can be characterized as directed at the
30
Kornblith may, of course, grant this point, while maintaining that this kind of
epistemic agency is not the kind of agency that the philosophers traditionally writing on
the topic are interested in. On this point, consider what Kornblith has to say about the
passage from Moran quoted above (on p. 26), where he elaborates on the relation
between expressing rational agency, on the one hand, and what it means to (as he says)
hand over one’s belief to the authority of reason. According to Kornblith, there is a
tension between these two claims—a tension that was called attention to above in relation
to the relevant quote. According to Kornblith, the tension is such that we have reason to
give up the former claim (about agency), while accepting a qualified version of the latter
claim (about the authority of reason). However, as called attention to above, the tension
only arises if we take the relevant authority to require an ability to opt out of the demands
of rationality and, in effect, exert control (as opposed to mere authority) over what beliefs
no such thing is required. The only thing that is required is that we leave it up to our
reflective faculties to lead us toward the proper conclusion, under the assumption that
At this point, Kornblith may suggest that Moran is no longer talking about agency
in any robust sense of that term, and here me and Kornblith may be in agreement—at
least if the relevantly robust sense of agency is one that can figure constructively in
ameliorative contexts, in ways that I argued above that Moran’s account of authority
cannot. But as we have seen, this does not suggest that there is no such thing as epistemic
agency; at most, it goes to show that there are theories about agency that fail to account
31
for one important role that a concept of epistemic agency should play, i.e., exactly the
The same goes for Kornblith’s final complaint about epistemic agency, i.e., that
the idea of epistemic agency is wedded to an overly optimistic view about the epistemic
merits of reflection. Here, we are in agreement about what the relevant empirical research
shows. But as argued above, showing that reflection cannot carry the epistemic weight
that some philosophers (Sosa, supposedly, being one of them) has wanted to put on its
shoulders, neither shows that the decisions that go into when and on what to reflect may
not constitute expressions of epistemic agency, nor suggests that there is no such thing as
agency. If we acknowledge the weak notion of epistemic agency relied upon here, not
even evidence to the effect that reflecting does not generally improve our reliability
suggests that we may not express our agency by reflecting. At most, it suggests that we
are in need of amelioration with respect to an epistemic activity that we perhaps did not
think would require improvement, and that it will serve us well as epistemic agents to
consider alternative ways to express our agency, in the event that the mechanisms
1.6. Conclusion
Where does what we have seen above leave epistemic agency? Exactly where we left it.
Agency still pertains to actions performed in an effort to attain our epistemic goals and, in
particular, the goal of believing truly. It just turned out that (a) epistemic agency cannot
pertain to decisions about what to believe, since making such decisions is impossible; (b)
32
if there is a sense in which what beliefs we end up with as a result of reflection is up to
us, this does not serve to delimit a notion of agency that is relevant to amelioration; and
(c) reflection, due to its largely mixed epistemic track-record, should neither be
Keeping these points in mind, we see that there is a sense in which the question of
what actions constitute epistemic agency is almost trivial. After all, what is it to engage in
actions directed at the goal of forming true belief? It is to engage in inquiry. In other
words, the actions by way of which we express our epistemic agency are those we
our first-order beliefs. But we do so much more than that—and rightfully so, given what
we have found about the ways in which reflecting sometimes leads us astray due to a
different methods of investigation, and so on. And in so doing, we are expressing our
epistemic agency.
At the same time, the very triviality of this answer to the question of what actions
are relevant to epistemic agency suggests that the interesting questions regarding such
agency lie elsewhere. One question pertains to an assumption that was made at the
beginning of this chapter and relied on throughout, namely that believing truly is our only
value. This assumption will be elaborated on as well as defended in the next two
How exactly are we to bring the ways in which we actually express our epistemic agency
33
in line with the ways in which we should express our epistemic agency, given the goal of
34
CHAPTER 2
Why take true belief to be epistemically valuable irrespective of whether believing truly
is conducive to something else of epistemic value? In short, why take true belief to be of
non-instrumental epistemic value? One straightforward answer invokes the idea that true
belief is a goal of inquiry or cognition.1 More specifically, the relevant line of reasoning
Before turning to (1), consider the rationale for (2). It seems reasonable to believe that
goals of inquiry determine what states, processes, practices, and so on, are epistemically
valuable. Not in the sense of what is actually valued—people fail to value what is
rather in the sense of what is worthy of pursuit, given participation in practices that can
1
See, e.g., Lynch (2009a), Alston (2005, p. 30), Haack (1993, p. 199), and BonJour
(1985, pp. 83-84) for four representative statements, and David (2001) for further
references.
35
be plausibly characterized as aiming toward the goals in question. More specifically, if
true belief is a goal of inquiry, then true belief is of non-instrumental epistemic value
and everything that is conducive to true belief is (at least) of instrumental epistemic
Someone might deny (2) by maintaining that goals of inquiry are one thing and
epistemic value another, perhaps on account of the latter being a function of the
other words, someone may argue that epistemic value is to be measured by something
more akin to effort than to actual achievement, perhaps in a manner mirroring the
moral rightness.
epistemic value. For present purposes, however, we may disregard such conceptions, the
reason being that we are concerned with amelioration. Since the purpose of amelioration
is to say something constructive about how to improve our epistemic ways in the
contexts where we are failing to attain our epistemic goals, the kind of success we are
of any kind, is only of interest to the extent that investing great effort in achieving one’s
2
Feldman (1988) comes closest to defending such a position. As we shall see below
(§2.2 and n. 14), however, he no longer challenges (3) by denying (2), but by denying (1).
3
Interestingly enough, empirical evidence suggests that there is no strong correlation
between a great effort put into living up to the traditional canons of epistemic obligation
on the one hand, and the formation of true belief on the other. In fact, in some contexts,
the correlation is even negative. See Bishop (2000).
36
Returning to (1), and setting aside the questions of whether (a) true belief is the
only goal of inquiry, and (b) the goal is to be restricted to truths that are in some relevant
why accept the claim that true belief is a goal of inquiry? William Alston finds himself
I don’t know how to prove that the acquisition, retention, and use of true beliefs
about matters that are of interest and/or importance is the most basic and central
goal of cognition. I don’t know anything that is more obvious from which it could
be derived (Alston 2005, p. 30; emphasis in original).
Many epistemologists side with Alston here.4 For ease of reference, let us refer to any
shall see in §2.2, however, there are epistemologists who do not consider obvious what
Alston does. Richard Feldman, for one, blocks the inference to (3) by denying (1). The
accordance with one’s evidence, where true or reliably formed belief is neither necessary
nor sufficient for believing thus. What is particularly interesting about his position is that
Feldman, thereby, rejects (3), while steering clear of two problematic claims,
committed to no such claim. For one thing, he may reject (3) while consistently
maintaining that believing truly may be of instrumental epistemic value, to the extent
4
See references in n. 1.
5
The term is borrowed from Goldman (1999), who introduces the notion of veritism to
capture the particular brand of epistemology that is concerned with the varieties of
processes and practices involved in the production of true belief.
6
Stich (1990) comes closest to defending such a claim.
37
that believing truly is conducive to believing on the basis of sufficient evidence. For
another, he may also maintain that true belief is of instrumental pragmatic value, in
moral value, given how having an informed citizenry is conducive to the smooth
The second claim is that there are no constraints on what one’s epistemic goals
could be, nor, consequently, anything that stops one from taking virtually any good to be
Feldman neither makes nor needs to make any such claim, and the arguments that can be
leveraged against the claim in question, while establishing that there are some
substantive constraints on what one’s epistemic goals could be, neither single out true
belief as the only candidate, nor rule out believing upon the basis of sufficient evidence
Does it follow that we should give up on the idea that true belief, as opposed to,
below, the dialectical situation between the evidentialist and the veritist is symmetrical,
in that neither can impose their respective notion of value on the other—a conclusion
that will be drawn from the failure of several attempts on the part of both he evidentialist
and the veritist to break this symmetry, discussed in §§2.3-5 below. It is concluded in
§2.6 that, while there is no need to reject the evidentialist’s take on value in order to
protect the idea that truth is of non-instrumental value (although not necessarily for
7
See Kornblith (2002).
8
See Lynch (2004, pp. 174-176).
9
See Field (2001) for an endorsement of this claim, and Lynch (2009b) for a critique.
38
everyone) from the evidentialist’s contention that it is not, the prospects for convincing
someone who does not share one’s love for the relevant non-instrumental epistemic
cognitive attitudes,” which, in turn, “amounts to following one’s evidence” (p. 382).
Does this claim conflict with the idea that true belief is of non-instrumental epistemic
value? That depends on how we spell out what it is to follow one’s evidence, which in
is to have evidence, something is evidence for something else if and only if the former is
as reliable indicator of the latter.10 That, however, is not how Feldman understands what
experiences, these experiences do not reliably indicate anything about the subject’s
surrounding.
What is it, then, about evidence that justifies belief, if not a relation of truth-
10
See, e.g., Goldman (forthcoming).
11
See Feldman (1985).
39
[…] the general idea is that a person has a set of experiences, including perceptual
experiences, memorial experiences, and so on. What is justified for the person
includes propositions that are part of the best explanation of those experiences
available to the person. […] The best available explanation of one’s evidence is a
body of propositions about the world and one’s place in it that makes best sense
of the existence of one’s evidence. This notion of making sense of one’s evidence
can be equally well described as fitting the presence of the evidence into a
coherent view of one’s situation. So it may be helpful to think of our view as a
non-traditional version of coherentism. The coherence that justifies holds among
propositions that assert the existence of the non-doxastic states that constitute
one’s ultimate evidence and propositions that offer an optimal available
explanation of the existence of that evidence (Conee and Feldman, 2008, p. 98).
In other words, a person’s (ultimate) evidence consists in a set of experiences, and sets
that cohere with propositions asserting the presence of the experiences in question.
Coherence is a complex notion with a long history, and Feldman and Conee,
unfortunately, do not spell out the details of the particular notion that they have in mind.
However, there is an emerging consensus in the literature that coherence is not truth-
conducive, meaning that more coherence does not imply a higher likelihood of truth,
even ceteris paribus.12 More than that, such a disconnect between coherence and truth
would seem to be exactly what Feldman needs in order to accommodate the idea that
provide explanations of her experiences that cohere with the presence of those
experiences.
between following one’s evidence and believing truly. For one thing, Feldman takes it
12
See Olsson (2005).
40
that we can make a good case for most justified beliefs being true in the actual world.13
In other words, Feldman’s position is compatible with it being the case that, in a world
like ours, where experiences as a matter of contingent fact tend to provide pretty good
information about the external world, basing one’s beliefs upon one’s evidence is a good
means toward forming true belief. Crucially, however, Feldman denies that this is
diligence with respect to basing one’s belief upon one’s evidence will enable one to form
true beliefs about the external world, which is why neither true belief nor reliability is
Notice that a veritist may grant this. Nothing said so far implies that true belief is
the only goal of inquiry. However, Feldman is not only skeptical about the necessity of
truth or truth-conduciveness for epistemic success, but also about it being sufficient.
Registering his skepticism about the idea that mere true belief is an epistemic goal, and
[…] suppose a person acquires strong evidence against a proposition he has long
defended in public. Out of stubbornness, the person retains the old belief. And
suppose that, contrary to the new evidence, the old belief is in fact true. If the goal
is simply truth, he’s achieved the goal and is, in this case at least, an
epistemological success. But, as Locke said of a person who does not reason as he
ought, “however he sometimes lights on truth, is in the right but by chance; and I
know not whether the luckiness of the accident will excuse the irregularity of his
proceeding.” […] Setting aside questions of excuses, the idea here seems to be
that the person who reasons badly and stumbles onto a truth is not believing as he
ought, is not achieving epistemological success (Feldman 2002, p. 378).
13
See Feldman (2003, pp. 615-616).
41
Elaborating on a related scenario a couple of sentences further down, Feldman makes it
clear that he sides with Locke on this point. To simply achieve true belief is not to
Clearly, the idea that there is nothing epistemically meritorious about (mere) true
belief—that is, that believing truly is neither a goal nor one kind of epistemic success—
runs contrary to any account of epistemic value relying on argument (1)-(3) above.14
Granted, few veritists would deny that there is something epistemically lacking about the
person in the scenario Feldman imagines. For example, reliabilists about justification
would deny that she is justified. However, what is at issue here is whether there is
anything of epistemic value about her epistemic situation, and that is where the veritist
parts company with Feldman. Is Feldman in any relevant sense, thereby, mistaken about
epistemic value? The next section considers two arguments—both of which are,
14
Feldman (in correspondence) confirms that there has been a shift in his views on
epistemic value, from his (1988), where he accepts that true belief is a goal of inquiry and
simply denies that true belief has anything to do with value, to his (2002), where he (as
we have seen) denies that true belief has anything to do with value by denying that it is a
goal of inquiry.
42
2.3. Is Feldman Mistaken About Value?
Recently, Michael Lynch (2009a and b) has provided a series of arguments against what
he calls epistemic expressivism, or the view that there are no constraints on what one’s
epistemic goals could be, nor, consequently, on what one may take to be of non-
see, at least two of Lynch’s arguments (if successful) apply equally well to someone
who, like Feldman, simply denies that truth is of non-instrumental epistemic value.
First, consider what we may refer to as the no inquiry argument. The idea is that
someone who is forming belief in a manner that involves no commitment to the idea that
propositions are to be embraced if and only if they are true is not engaging in inquiry.15
someone—let us call him Steve—who is committed to the goal of “accepting” all and
only propositions that flatter his cultural origin. Is Steve, thereby, engaging in inquiry?
Lynch suggests that the answer has to be “no,” since the practice Steve is involved in
does not involve a commitment to the idea that propositions are to be embraced if and
only if they are true. Whatever practice Steve is involved in, it is not inquiry.
When applied to Steve, this line of reasoning is highly convincing. But does the
point in question generalize to any practice that does not involve a commitment to the
idea that propositions are to be embraced if and only if they are true, including a practice
15
The norm of embracing propositions if and only if they are true is, of course, not meant
to be action-guiding. Instead, the norm is supposed to tell us something about conditions
under which particular instances of inquiry have to be considered successful or
unsuccessful, namely to the extent that they terminate in true belief or false belief,
respectively.
43
that involves (nothing but) a commitment to the idea that propositions are to be
embraced if and only if they are based upon sufficient evidence, as spelled out by
Feldman? It is not so clear that it does. To see why, consider two ways in which the
relevant point about what constitutes inquiry could be pushed. On the one hand, it could
be maintained that the norm according to which we should believe something if and only
case, the dispute seems to boil down to one about meanings, and the veritist would have
prominent contributors—or granting that the evidentialist is using a different yet equally
On the other hand, Lynch makes it clear that this is not how he views matters:
[…] it isn’t at all obvious that the above arguments need to be understood as
being about the meanings of “inquiry” or “belief” or “language”. As we have
noted earlier, (TN) [i.e., the idea that it is prima facie correct to believe <p> if and
only if <p> is true] and what follows from it needn’t be thought of as conceptual
truths. One could take such points to be about inquiry and belief rather than
“inquiry” and “belief”. Cooking aims to produce food; comedy aims to produce
laughter. Likewise, one might think, inquiry aims to produce true beliefs. It is a
fact about such practices that they cannot be separated from their aims; their aims
are partly constitutive of them (Lynch 2009b, pp. 90-91).
In other words, rather than pertaining to conceptual necessities, the relevant truths about
inquiry may, as Lynch suggests, be truths of constitution. However, at this point, the
argument starts to look question begging, at least if leveraged against the evidentialist.
More specifically, the argument against counting above evidentialist practice as a form
of inquiry would, under this construal, require a premise to the effect that inquiry is the
44
pursuit of truth, which is exactly the claim that the evidentialist contests. Clearly, the
Lynch seems to admit this point when noting that he “cannot give a non-circular
veritist]; for in answering the question I am already committed to the value of the very
practice in question” (2009a, p. 239). Moreover, he grants that, far-fetched examples like
the one with Steve aside, it seems at least prima facie reasonable to say that someone
may engage in inquiry in a context where the latter is spelled out in terms of the goal of
this point, however, the second argument enters, an argument that we may refer to as the
No doubt, people can and do have such goals in pursuing inquiry. The question is
whether […] we can conceive of someone who has distinct epistemic goals that
don’t include the goal of having true belief. Of course, the typical way of
understanding inquiry does require that it have only one goal: truth […]. The
thought here is that the value of achieving, e.g. a coherent belief system lies in the
fact that doing so is instrumental to believing what is true and not believing the
false. […] If we didn’t think this, it seems unlikely that we would care about
whether our beliefs were coherent. But of course if this is how we see the matter,
having the goal of coherence or justification presupposes having the goal of true
belief (Lynch 2009b, p. 89).
The problem is, of course, that this is not how the evidentialist, at least of Feldman’s
stripe, sees the matter. As we saw above, he denies exactly that the value of justification,
16
The same points made here about the futility of discrediting the evidentialist’s account
of value with reference to a constitutive or conceptual connection between truth and
inquiry can be made, mutatis mutandis, against any analogous attempt in terms of there
being a constitutive or conceptual connection between truth and belief, on account of the
former being the norm of the latter, and inquiry being the practice of belief-formation.
See, e.g., Lynch (2009a).
45
i.e., of basing your beliefs upon sufficient evidence, is parasitic upon the value of
relationship would be to misconstrue it, at best, and to beg the question, at worst. As
such, we may conclude that neither of Lynch’s arguments establishes that Feldman is
any evidentialist elaboration on the notion of inquiry is equally unlikely to sway the
veritist, as above reflections on the veritistic notion are to sway the evidentialist—and
rightly so. As such, nothing said so far goes to show that the veritist should stop valuing
true belief non-instrumentally. The point is merely that neither the veritist nor the
evidentialist can impose their respective notion of value on the other, as long as the
relevant values are grounded in nothing but different conceptions of inquiry. The next
section considers an argument on part of the veritist that, if successful, would break the
symmetry, by grounding the value of true belief in the fact that certain true beliefs are
necessary parts of a flourishing life. If successful, the argument would provide reasons
for the evidentialist to start valuing (at least some) true beliefs non-instrumentally,
According to Lynch (2004), we care about having true beliefs, where “caring for
something entails that we treat it as [an] end” (p. 119). Differently put, we take true
belief to be of non-instrumental epistemic value. But what reasons do we—as in: all of
46
us, irrespective of our particular notions of inquiry—have for valuing truth thus? Lynch
provides two arguments meant to answer this question, both of which elaborate on the
intimate relationship between believing truly and being happy, in the sense of leading a
flourishing life.17 He refers to the first argument as the argument from self-knowledge.
Let us consider Lynch’s formulation of the argument, before turning to his definitions of
“If we grant,” Lynch continues, ”that whatever is part of happiness is worth caring about
for its own sake, from these premises we can deduce that the truth about what you care
about is itself worth caring about for its own sake” (p. 127). In other words, Lynch wants
(5) the truth about what you care about is worth caring about for its own sake,
(AP) If x is part of some y (e.g., happiness) that is worth caring about for its
own sake, then x is worth caring about for its own sake.
17
Actually, Lynch provides six arguments. However, three of these pertain to
instrumental values (see n. 8), and the fourth fails for the same reason as the first and
second (see n. 20), which leaves the two arguments to be discussed here.
47
Let us consider the premises in turn. To have self-respect, as Lynch understands it, is to
have a sense of your own value (p. 124), while authenticity is to identify with the desires
that effectively guide your actions (p. 125). To have a sense of self is to have true beliefs
about what you care about, as per premise (3). Since it is, arguably, impossible to either
have a sense of your own value, or to identify with the desires that effectively guide your
action, without having true beliefs about what you care about, self-respect and
Premise (2) maintains that self-respect and authenticity are parts of happiness.
Being a part of something is crucially different from being a means to it. A means
to an end is ipso facto different from the end itself. A necessary part of something,
on the other hand, helps make the whole of which it is a part the thing that it is.
Change or destroy the part and you change or destroy the whole (p. 128; emphasis
in original).
In other words, for some x to be a part of some y is for x to be a necessary part of y, such
that the absence of x implies the absence of y. Interpreting premise (2) accordingly, and
granting premise (3)—i.e., that having a sense of self means having true beliefs about
what you care about—it follows that having true beliefs about what you care about is a
(4*) Having true beliefs about what you care about is a necessary part of
48
It might seem strange to talk about something being a necessary part of something, other
something by necessity, i.e., irrespective of whether other things are equal. However,
what Lynch means to indicate by the qualification in terms of “other things being equal”
is that the value in question is pro tanto, in that it may be overruled by other
(5*) The truth about what you care about is worth caring about for its own sake,
in the sense that having the true beliefs in question is pro tanto good in
itself.
the effect that at least some true beliefs are (pro tanto) valuable in themselves,
irrespective of what happens to be one’s particular notion of inquiry. The problem with
the argument, however, is (AP). We may see more clearly what the problem is by
of something as follows:
about for its own sake—i.e., if x is such that its absences implies the
18
See Lynch (2004, pp. 46-51). This interpretation is confirmed by Lynch (in
correspondence).
49
absences of that of which it is a part—then x is worth caring about for its
own sake.
Clearly, (AP*) is not true. It does not follow from x being a necessary part of y, that if y
is worth caring about for its own sake then the same goes for x. By way of illustration,
assume that true belief is worth caring about for its own sake. If (AP*) were true, it
would follow that mere belief, being a necessary part of true belief, would be worth
caring about for its own sake. This clearly cannot be right, even if we qualify the good
involved as being a mere pro tanto good. Hence, (AP*) cannot be true. And if (AP*) is
not true, then we do not get the conclusion that Lynch wants to draw from (1)-(4),
namely (5*).19
suffers from an analogous problem. This argument attempts to establish the more general
conclusion that the very act of caring about truth as such is non-instrumentally valuable.
The reason, Lynch argues, is that caring about truth as such is essential to intellectual
19
Notice that we can run the same argument even if we interpret the relevant relation
between true belief and happiness in terms of supervenience. After all, it does not follow
from y being valuable in itself that, if x is part of the supervenience base of y, then x is
also valuable in itself. By way of illustration, assume (if only for the sake of the
argument) that being a person is valuable in itself. Assume, furthermore, that facts about
person-hood supervene on neurological facts, and that I am the person I am in virtue of
instantiating the particular neurological facts N1-N850. If you change any of those facts,
you change (if not destroy) the whole, i.e., me. (You might still have a person, of course,
but arguably not a person that is me.) Then, take any neurological fact in this series, say,
N46. Is instantiating N46 valuable in itself? It is not—despite it being part of the
supervenience base of something that (by hypothesis) is valuable in itself. In other words,
whatever value attaches to the supervenient does not trickle down to the individual parts
that make up the subvenient, in the manner that Lynch’s argument requires.
50
[…] one must be open to having true belief in general, and pursuing truth in
general, on those questions that come before you, whatever those may be. Caring
about truth for its own sake, that is, being willing to both pursue it and be open to
it, is therefore a necessary condition for intellectual integrity (p. 133).
something worth caring about for its own sake. We will return to this claim
momentarily, but let us first consider the argument that he sets out (and I quote):
This is a valid argument, but it is not sound. Consider the conditional in premise (1).
Why would it follow from intellectual integrity being a constitutive good, that caring
about truth as such is also a constitutive good? Lynch suggests that “[c]aring about the
therefore, to integrity proper” (p. 136). But, as already noted above in relation to (AP*),
it does not follow from x being a necessary condition for y, that, if y is worth caring
about for its own sake, then the same goes for x. Consequently, we cannot infer (3) from
Two things need to be noted about what should not be inferred from the failure of
Lynch’s arguments. First, while the arguments in question failed to establish that some
20
The same goes for Lynch’s (2004, p. 157) structurally identical argument about
sincerity.
51
true beliefs are non-instrumentally valuable (pro tanto or otherwise) irrespective of your
particular conception of inquiry, nothing said so far rules out the possibility that having
certain true beliefs (e.g., about what you care about), or perhaps even caring about truth
that at most establishes that some instances of true belief are instrumentally valuable, not
that they are non-instrumentally valuable. As such, it provides no reason for those who
do not already value (any) true belief non-instrumentally to start doing so.
Second, in accordance with what was noticed above, the failure of Lynch’s
arguments does not go to show that those who already value true belief non-
instrumentally should stop doing so. But in want of an account of the non-instrumental
value of true belief that appeals to something beyond conceptions of inquiry that are not
universally shared, the veritist must accept the fact that she can provide no reasons for
those who do not already share the relevant notion of inquiry to start valuing true belief
non-instrumentally. The next section considers the matter from the other side, by
investigating the possibility that the evidentialist can provide the kind of argument that
Lynch could not, i.e., an argument to the effect that we should value basing our beliefs
In his essay “The Ethics of Belief” (1866), W. K. Clifford famously argues that it is
52
which beliefs formed on the basis of insufficient evidence have dire consequences for
others, but suggests that believing thus would have been wrong even if the consequences
in question had not ensued. Moreover, Clifford takes it that the duty not to believe upon
insufficient evidence extends beyond those engaged in decisions involving high stakes.
Indeed, the duty is universal. As he famously sums up his position on the issue: “It is
wrong, always, and everywhere, and for everyone, to believe anything upon insufficient
For Clifford, this synchronic duty not to believe upon insufficient evidence
follows from a more fundamental, diachronic duty of inquiry, i.e., “the universal duty of
questioning all that we believe” (p. 343). In questioning our beliefs, we attempt to find
out whether or not they are based on sufficient evidence. If they are, we may continue
holding them, knowing that they have been “fairly earned by investigation” (ibid.). If
they are not, “we have to begin again at the beginning, and try to learn what the thing
[under investigation] is and how it is to be dealt with—if indeed anything can be learnt
about it” (ibid.). In other words, through persistent inquiry, we either uncover sufficient
evidence one way or the other and adjust our belief accordingly, or find that there is no
evidence either way and that suspension of belief, consequently, is the most appropriate
It is as a fruit of such “scrupulous care and self-control” (p. 347) that we, on
Clifford’s picture, should understand the value of believing upon sufficient evidence. To
believe thus is to have satisfied the duty of inquiry by making sure that, for every
53
turns out that nothing can be learnt about the object under investigation, believing upon
sufficient evidence may not be the only (albeit, possibly, the only happy) way of
satisfying the duty of inquiry.21 Still, if Clifford is right, even those who do not happen
to share Feldman’s conception of inquiry ought to value having their beliefs be based
upon sufficient evidence non-instrumentally. To see why, consider the fact that Clifford,
unlike the great majority of contemporary epistemologists, seems to take our epistemic
duties to be a mere subset of our ethical duties.22 With this in mind, consider the
following argument:
(1) We have a duty to only believe upon sufficient evidence, and the duty is an
ethical one.
propositions.
everyone.
21
However, given Clifford’s emphasis on our diachronic duty to question all that we
believe and, in effect, inquire as far as possible, it is unlikely that he would consider
complete suspension of belief as a acceptable way to satisfy the duty of inquiry, unless
such suspension constitutes the inescapable end point of pain-staking investigation.
22
See Haack (2001) for a convincing set of arguments to this effect.
54
Premise (1) captures the duty Clifford infers from the duty of inquiry, and identifies it as
may satisfy the duty in question by believing upon sufficient evidence. Premise (3)
amounts to an assumption that will be granted for the sake of the argument, i.e., that
Moreover, if all epistemic duties are ethical duties, the same applies to the former, as per
premise (4). Assuming that the relevant ethical duties apply universally, as per premise
(5), believing upon sufficient evidence is non-instrumentally valuable not only for those
who, like Feldman, share the evidentialist conception of epistemic success, but to
Albeit a valid argument, premise (1) is highly implausible. To see why, consider
that there, clearly, are cases in which one is not morally reproachable for believing upon
insufficient evidence, as famously pointed out by William James (1907) in his critique of
remote, is sufficient for moral culpability—a position that, as Susan Haack (2001) points
out, would imply that “not only drunk driving, but owning a car would be morally
culpable” (p. 27). Moreover, Clifford maintains that believing upon insufficient evidence
invariably strengthens the habit of credulity, in turn amounting to a risk for harm.24
tendencies that may lead to harm. But in maintaining that believing upon insufficient
23
See Clifford (1866, p. 342).
24
See Clifford (1866, pp. 344-346).
55
evidence invariably leads to credulity, Clifford seems to assume that such belief always
is the result of potentially harmful cognitive traits, and that is highly questionable.
Consequently, it would seem that Clifford has to grant James’ point that there are
including some held and debated within science and philosophy, are of no great moral
consequence. If Clifford were to acknowledge this, and at the same time hold on to (1),
he would have to maintain that the cases in question fall outside the scope not only of
moral evaluation but (consequently) also of epistemic evaluation, the latter being a
special case of the former. From this, it would follow that none of the beliefs in question
are held in ways that are epistemically impermissible. Such epistemic laissez-faire seems
undesirable, to say the least, and the way to block the conclusion is, of course, to deny
(1), and maintain that, in so far as we have a duty to only believe upon sufficient
between ethical and epistemic duties. For example, in spelling out his evidentialist take
on Clifford’s position, Feldman (1988, pp. 236-237) explicitly rejects the identification
of the domains of epistemic and moral obligations, and maintains that beliefs with
claiming that every person is required to try her best to bring it about that, for every
proposition considered, she accepts the proposition only if it is true, Roderick Chisholm
56
(1977, p. 14) specifies the requirement as a purely intellectual requirement.25 In other
words, the main modern defenders of Clifford’s project construes it not so much an
Clifford’s theory that would provide them with a way to convince the veritist of the non-
instrumental value of basing one’s belief upon sufficient evidence. As argument (1)-(6)
above makes clear, the reason Clifford’s account was promising on this score was
exactly because it took our duty to base our beliefs thus to be an ethical duty—a fact
that, given the wide scope and non-instrumental nature of our ethical duties, would
provide a lever for extending the normative force of the evidentialists’ emphasis on the
value of believing upon sufficient evidence beyond those who happen to share their
defenders of an ethics of belief, they may thereby be constructing far more plausible
accounts of the relevant evidentialist norms than Clifford did, albeit at the expense of
providing little by way of arguments for convincing the veritist of the non-instrumental
25
Chisholm does at times write as if epistemic duties are a mere subspecies of ethical
duties, e.g., in his (1991, p. 119). However, when spelled out, the claim turns out to be
that (a) ethical duties are duties that are not overridden by any other requirement, and (b)
non-overridden epistemic duties (like any non-overridden duties), hence, are ethical
duties (see pp. 127-128). Granting this somewhat questionable definition of an ethical
duty, it still only goes to show that some epistemic duties are ethical duties, not that all
are, nor consequently that the former are a mere subspecies of the latter.
26
Wolterstorff (2005) is a possible exception.
57
2.6. Conclusion
The failure of surveyed accounts to break the dialectical symmetry between the veritist
and the evidentialist does not prove that the symmetry cannot be broken. Still, the
absence of further, more successful accounts leaves us with no reason to think that the
requisite arguments are forthcoming. This is not to deny that we all have ample
instrumental reason to value true belief, given the ways in which believing truly may
further our pragmatic, moral or prudential endeavors. Furthermore, and as has been
stressed several times already, what has been argued here is neither to deny that many of
something else of epistemic value, nor to maintain that those of us who do should stop
doing so. As we have seen, there is a perfectly good answer to the question of why true
true belief being a goal of inquiry. It just happens to be an answer that cannot be invoked
in an argument to the effect that those who do not share the relevant notion of inquiry
This fact, taken together with the failure of surveyed accounts to ground the
relevant claims about value in something other than our notions of inquiry, suggests that
the prospects for convincing someone who does not share one’s love for the relevant
non-instrumental, epistemic goods to start doing so seem dim indeed. However, given
for ceasing to value that thing, there is no need to reject the evidentialist’s take on value
in order to protect the idea that truth is of non-instrumental value from the evidentialist’s
contention that it is not. Granted, I can’t make you love truth, if you don’t already do.
58
But by aforementioned symmetry you also can’t make me love evidence. For this reason,
subsequent chapters will assume the position taken by most epistemologists, to the effect
that true belief is, indeed, a non-instrumental, epistemic good—albeit, as we have seen,
59
CHAPTER 3
As noted in the previous chapter, most epistemologists take believing truly to be of non-
instrumental epistemic value in virtue of true belief being a goal of inquiry. It is far more
controversial, however, whether the following thesis holds—a thesis that we may refer to
epistemic value.1
The present chapter defends EVM against a series of objections coming out of recent
discussions about the value of knowledge. There is no doubt that these discussions have
epistemology. Still, it is the thesis of the present chapter that recent pluralistic critiques of
EVM fail to provide any convincing counterexamples, and that epistemic value monism
Before proceeding to EVM’s defense, let us clarify its component notions. First,
what is epistemic value? As noted in the previous chapter, it seems reasonable to believe
that (a) goals of inquiry determine what activities, states, processes, practices, and so on,
1
Recent proponents of EVM include Goldman (1999) and David (2005).
60
are epistemically valuable, (b) true belief is one such goal, (c) true belief, hence, is of
and non-instrumental value pertains to how value may be inherited across causal
relations. Another way in which value may be inherited is from parts to wholes. As we
shall see in §3.2, that some states inherit value from one of their components is important
to keep in mind when thinking about the comparative value of complex states. With this
in mind, let us say that something is of fundamental value if and only if its value does not
What is denied is simply that such a state—or, more generally, any state that involves
instrumental value. The notions of fundamental versus derived value may be applied also
to instrumental values. However, it will suffice to make the distinction in relation to non-
instrumental value for the purposes of the present investigation. Consequently, any
2
The relevant states do not literally have components. The components in question
correspond to the conditions included in a correct analysis of the state(s) in question. If a
state has no analysis—as Williamson (2000) has argued is the case for knowledge—it has
no components, but may still be of fundamental value.
3
The taxonomy developed here is not meant to cover all possible mechanisms for value
inheritance. For example, Goldman (Goldman and Olsson, 2009) argues that there are
instances in which the non-instrumental value of true belief may be inherited by token
processes in virtue of being instances of reliable types—a pattern of inheritance that can
be categorized neither as an instance of instrumental value nor as one of derived value.
61
It is controversial whether all bearers of non-instrumental value are intrinsically
addressed. The first issue is whether to understand intrinsic value as applying to objects
or to states of affairs. If the former, it is easy to come up with examples involving objects
tradition, such examples can be accounted for, and the claim that non-instrumental and
intrinsic values coincide be maintained.5 It is easy to see why one might want to opt for
an object-construal of intrinsic value when it comes to a bearer of value that has figured
prominently in the Kantian tradition, viz. the person. However, as far as epistemic value
is concerned, it is reasonable to think that the bearers of value are states of affairs—be it
states of affairs involving doxastic states, processes, practices, or what have you—rather
than objects. One strong indication of this is that it seems odd to say that a true belief (an
object) is valuable, unless this is just a different way of saying that someone believing
truly (a state of affairs) is valuable, and similarly for someone knowing, understanding,
being justified, and so on.6 Construed thus, the notion of non-instrumental value, as
That said, a lack of taxonomical exhaustiveness would only be a problem if the taxonomy
used somehow stacked the dialectical deck against the pluralist, which it does not. If
anything, by not incorporating the kind of value that Goldman introduces and argues can
be invoked in a solution to problems typically leveraged against monists, it might even be
that the present taxonomy stacks the deck against the monist—which, of course, makes
any defense of monism in terms of this taxonomy all the more significant.
4
See, e.g., Rabinowicz and Rønnow-Rasmussen (2000).
5
See Bradley (2006).
6
Similarly, in so far as references will be made below to “true belief” or “knowledge”
being epistemically valuable, this is not to suggest that abstract objects are proper bearers
62
Still, the discussions below will be framed in terms of non-instrumental rather
than intrinsic values. The reason for this taxonomical decision brings us to the second
issue, which is whether intrinsic value is to be identified with final value, i.e., the kind of
value that pertains to that which is valuable irrespective of any considerations about
conduciveness whatsoever. By way of illustration, consider the claim that true belief is
implies that true belief is of non-instrumental epistemic value. Maintaining that true
belief is valuable thus is perfectly compatible with also claiming that believing truly only
non-epistemic value (e.g., practical, prudential or moral), perhaps because they pertain to
questions posed by some relevant set of inquirers.7 In other words, true belief being of
non-instrumental epistemic value does not imply that true belief is valuable thus
Differently put, unlike bearers of final value, not all bearers of non-instrumental
with final value, then the intrinsically valuable is not to be identified with the non-
valuable on one qualification does not imply being non-instrumentally valuable without
qualification. As will be explored further in chapter 4, this is important to note not only
because it shows that some non-instrumental values are not final values, but also because
of such value, but simply short-hand for saying that (at least some) instances of people
believing truly or knowing things are epistemically valuable.
7
See, e.g., Goldman (1999, pp. 94-96).
63
it suggest that it does not follow from believing truly being of non-instrumental epistemic
value that all instances of true belief are of such value. Again, perhaps only those that
pertain to questions posed by some relevant set of inquirers are valuable thus. But more
For now, note that it not only does not follow from something being valuable on
one qualification that it is valuable without qualification; it also does not follow from
simpliciter. Even so, it does not follow that pleasure is of non-instrumental epistemic
value, for the simple reason that pleasure is not an epistemic value in the first place. We
To sum up, what follows from the above discussion is the following:
value.
Note that it does not follow from (1) that all true beliefs that are non-instrumentally
valuable are of equal non-instrumental value; some truths might very well be of greater
non-instrumental value than others. Furthermore, that some true beliefs are of
fundamental, non-instrumental epistemic value, clearly, does not imply that they are
64
unique in this respect—and this is a problem, in so far as we want to get from (1) to
If some instances of true belief are of fundamental, non-instrumental epistemic value, and
While (1) was motivated in the previous chapter with reference to how true belief
is at least one goal of inquiry, defending (2) from potential objections will take further
axiological legwork. To be exact, it will take the remainder of this chapter. It should be
noted right at the outset, however, that there is a presumption in favor of conjoining (1)
with (2), rather than conjoining (1) with a claim leaving room for a multitude of
bearers of fundamental value that is postulated. This principle is, in turn, an instance of
the more general thesis that we should prefer ontologies with fewer rather than more
8
Invoking this principle does not commit us to taking simplicity to be of fundamental,
non-instrumental epistemic value, as opposed to of instrumental epistemic value (e.g.,
pursuing simplicity in theorizing is conducive to forming true belief), or non-epistemic
65
of explaining all judgments regarding absolute as well as comparative epistemic value by
assuming one as opposed to several bearers of fundamental value. A pluralist might very
well accept that there is such a presumption. What she would argue, however, is that this
presumption is defeated by evidence to the effect that we cannot account fully for the
domain of epistemic value in monistic terms, which is exactly the kind of charge that we
will be concerned with below. Still, the presumption provides us with reason to prefer
conjoining (1) with (2) in the absence of any convincing evidence for such an inability,
and it is the burden of the remaining sections to show that there is no such evidence.
What constitutes relevant evidence here? (2) is equivalent to the universal claim
value of believing truly. Given the obvious difficulty of defending a universal claim, I
will restrict my attention to what, judging by recent work in epistemological axiology, are
values, i.e., knowing, being justified, and understanding, to be discussed in §§3.2-3, 3.4,
and 3.5, respectively. As we shall see, these candidates are typically taken to be backed
up by strong and widespread axiological intuitions. This suggests that, if any candidate
constitutes a challenge to (2), it will be found among these three. Consequently, if it can
be shown that none of them poses such a challenge, we may conclude that there is no
convincing evidence against (2), and that the presumption in favor of EVM still stands.
value (e.g., simplicity brings tractability, which is pragmatically valuable). However, see
Sober (2001) for a skeptical take on the possibility of understanding the value of
simplicity in terms of other values.
66
3.2. On the (Alleged) Surplus Value of Knowledge
What reason do we have for thinking that knowing is non-instrumentally valuable?9 One
reason is that knowledge is factive.10 Given that some instance of true belief are non-
instrumentally valuable, and knowledge implies truth, some instances of knowing may,
however, is that many philosophers have wanted to make a claim not merely about
knowing being valuable but about it being more valuable than believing truly. For
example, Ward Jones (1997) writes that “I want all of my beliefs to be true—otherwise I
would not believe them—but I would also rather they be known beliefs than mere true
beliefs” (p. 424). And Jones is by no means alone. Duncan Pritchard starts out an
involved in the relevant discussions, namely that “we clearly do value knowledge more
than mere true belief.” (p. 86). Moreover, many have argued that this idea can be found
[…] part of the challenge of explaining the value of knowledge is explaining how
it has more value than other things, one of these other things being true opinion—
as Meno claims after acquiescing to Socrates’ point that true belief is every bit as
useful as knowledge. “In that case, I wonder why knowledge should be so much
more prized than right opinion” (97c-d). Meno expresses here a common
presupposition about knowledge, one that is widely, if not universally shared.
Given this presupposition, an account of the value of knowledge must explain
more than how knowledge is valuable. It must also explain why the value of
9
Here and henceforth, any unqualified statement about value concerns epistemic value.
10
On one understanding of what knowledge is, knowledge just is true belief. We will not
be concerned with this weak notion of knowledge here, but see Goldman and Olsson
(2009) as well as Sartwell (1992) for two relevant discussions.
67
knowledge is superior to the value of true opinion (Kvanvig 2003, pp. 3-4;
emphasis added).
We will return to the issue of what exactly Plato seems to be saying about the value of
knowledge in the Meno in the next section. As far as contemporary discussions are
concerned, the particular interpretation of aforementioned claims about the surplus value
After all, there might be many respects in which knowing is superior to mere true belief,
including moral or practical. If it can be shown that knowing is valuable thus, that would
be interesting and important.11 But unless the surplus value in question is of a specifically
epistemic kind, it would not speak to EVM, which is a thesis exclusively about epistemic
value.
Could someone committed to EVM account for (K)? For one thing, (K) cannot be
accounted for in terms of the non-instrumental value that derives from the factivity of
that of true belief, would clearly not be an option for a defender of EVM. Another option
believing truly. However, this strategy raises a problem that is typically directed against a
particular account of what constitutes knowledge, namely reliabilism, but applies to any
11
See, e.g., Olsson (2007) on the practical surplus value of knowledge.
68
axiological account that defines the non-factive component of knowledge in terms of
Now clearly it is a good thing that our beliefs satisfy the reliabilist requirement,
for the fact that they do means that […] they will probably be true. But, if a given
belief of mine is true, I cannot see that it is any more worth having for satisfying
the reliabilist requirement. So long as the belief is true, the fact that the process
which produced it usually produces true belief does not seem to make that belief
any more worth having (Swinburne 1999, p. 58).
In other words, the problem is that the presence of truth seems to “swamp” the epistemic
value of truth-conducivity, to use Kvanvig’s (2003) term. This does not mean that a
defender of EVM cannot account for knowledge being epistemically valuable. It does,
Reliabilists have resisted this conclusion. For example, Alvin Goldman (Goldman
and Olsson 2009) argues that (K) can be accounted for in terms of a pattern of inheritance
by which token processes inherit value from states of true belief in virtue of being
instances of process types that reliably produce such states. Moreover, he argues, the
value of resultant true beliefs” (p. 31) and may, as such, be added to the value that the
relevant state of knowing has in virtue of its factivity. Presently, we will not be concerned
with whether this is a successful solution to the swamping problem. Instead, it will be
argued that any monistic attempt to account for (K) grants the defender of the swamping
argument too much, since we lack any strong, pre-theoretic reasons for accepting (K) in
the first place.12 If we lack such reasons, there is no longer any pressure to surrender
12
(K) has received some scrutiny in recent contributions to the debate, but not in a
manner amounting to a rejection. Baehr (2009) raises doubt about the extent to which the
69
EVM for the purpose of accounting for (K) with reference to some non-instrumental
value distinct from truth—or so it will be argued. Let us first spell out the case for the
Over the last couple of years, several analyses of knowledge have been motivated
on the ground that they imply and, thereby, can account for (K).13 Focusing on pre-
theoretic reasons amounts to excluding reasons flowing from such implications. In fact,
disqualifying theoretical reasons is in the interest of both parties of the debate, since the
dialectical deck can be stacked either way. In particular, allowing for theoretical reasons
to motivate or discredit (K) opens up for a very simple reply by the monist: Taken
together, reliabilism and aforementioned swamping considerations imply that (K) does
not hold; consequently, we have reason to believe that it does not. No one has pursued
this strategy and the reason is simple: Those involved in the debate assume that (K)
That said, making the case that we lack any pre-theoretic reasons for accepting
(K) is made complicated by the fact that it is hard to find any arguments for (as opposed
to statements of) (K) in the literature. One relevant discussion can be found in one of the
intuition typically reported in the form of (K) really is fully general, in the sense of
concerning all instances of knowledge, but seems to accept (K) as a rough generalization.
Greco (2009) questions the idea that there is widespread intuitive support for the further
idea that knowledge is more valuable than any subset of its constituents, while accepting
(K). As will be discussed below, Kvanvig (2003) denies that knowledge is more valuable
than any subset of its constituents, but accepts that (K) holds in virtue of the surplus value
of justified true belief over mere true belief. Pritchard (forthcoming) initially rejects (K),
but re-establishes it (at least in part) with reference to the value of understanding, arguing
that knowledge typically goes hand-in-hand with understanding.
13
See Pritchard (2007) for an overview.
70
earliest contributions to the contemporary debate regarding the value of knowledge, due
to Jones (1997). According to Jones, one possible motivation for (K) is that it constitutes
the best explanation of why so many philosophers have concerned themselves with
Surely it is the high value we place on knowledge which has motivated the
extraordinary volume of philosophical work which has gone into setting out the
conditions for knowledge as opposed to true belief (Jones 1997, pp. 423-424).
The problem with this line of reasoning can be brought out by considering the fact that
what any particular philosopher shows great interest in is a function of a whole host of
factors, such as (a) what her colleagues happen to be showing great interest in, which
influences the extent to which she will be successful in publishing her work or landing an
academic position that will enable her to remain in the field; (b) what her supervisors
happen to show great interest in, which influences the extent to which she will receive
sufficient professional attention to develop necessary academic skills; and (c) what her
philosophical predecessors happened to take great interest in, which influences the extent
to which she will consider becoming a philosopher in the first place. This is not to
suggest that philosophical inquiry is in no way sensitive to axiological facts, but merely
to point out that establishing facts about comparative interests is not sufficient for
establishing facts about comparative value, since what philosophers take great interest in
is partly a function of a great many sociological facts that cannot be assumed to track
relevant axiological facts about what degrees of value happen to apply to what states.
A second motivation for (K) may be gleaned from the fact that knowledge tends
71
Even more telling than philosophical infatuation is our unwillingness to endorse
or applaud those who succeed in guessing. What is more, those who repeatedly
guess tend to gain our disapproval, even though they may succeed at guessing. At
the very least, we lose trust in their reliability as informants. Even more than
valuing others’ knowledge, we value ourselves as knowers. For most (if not all) of
my factual beliefs, I take it to be important that they are knowledge and not lucky
guesses. I want all of my beliefs to be true—otherwise I would not believe
them—but I would also rather they be known beliefs than mere true beliefs (Jones
1997, p. 424).
To see the problem with this line of reasoning, we need to distinguish between two
targets of evaluation, i.e., doxastic states and belief-forming processes. With this
distinction in mind, consider, first, the fact that we do not applaud guessing. Construed as
a process, this could be explained with reference to the unreliability of guessing, and how
the process, hence, is of instrumental disvalue. But what about the doxastic states ensuing
true belief, which, furthermore, explains why we value lucky over unlucky guesses,
ceteris paribus. Notice, however, that it makes little sense to talk about a process of lucky
guessing, as opposed to one of guessing simpliciter. After all, what would such a process
involve? Surely, it would not involve consistently getting things right; in that case, it
some sub-personal sensitivity that (save for its reliability) might resemble guessing in not
being preceded by any deliberation. Indeed, as with any form of guessing, the process
would have to be one that is generally unreliable and, as such, one that we have little
reason to value.
Next, turn to the claim that we value ourselves as knowers. Construed as a claim
about how we value knowing things, this can be accounted for with reference to the
72
factivity of knowing. The same holds if we construe the claim as being about how we
value engaging in processes that involve us coming to know things. Consider, next, the
comparative claim that we value knowledge more than we value lucky guesses. On a
state reading, it is not clear that this claim is true. Imagine two scenarios. In one scenario,
you make a guess and form a true belief as a result. In the second scenario, you make a
reliable inference and, as a result, form a true belief that, moreover, amounts to
knowledge. Now, consider the comparative value not of your means of forming belief but
merely of the two resulting states. Is one really more valuable from an epistemic point of
view than the other? It is not clear that it is, given that they both involve true belief.14 In
so far as we intuit a difference here, it is likely that the intuition involved tracks what
does seem clear, namely that the processes involved in arriving at the respective states
are not equally valuable. The procedure utilized in the first scenario is of instrumental
disvalue in virtue of being unreliable, while that of the former is of instrumental value in
This brings us to the final claim of Jones’, i.e., that “I would also rather [my
beliefs] be known beliefs than mere true belief.” This is simply a restatement of (K), i.e.,
the very claim for which we are seeking a motivation. If it were the case that the
preceding claims could only be accounted for by assuming (K), then we could have
considered the statement a hypothesis, needed to account for the truth of the relevant
axiological claims. But what we have just seen is that it is perfectly possible to account
for those claims within a monistic framework in the manner just outlined. Consequently,
Jones’ assertion of (K) amounts not to an explanatory hypothesis necessary for explaining
14
Here, I’m siding with Kvanvig (2003, p. 148).
73
the observations preceding it, but simply to the statement of a preference. This is
certainly not to call into question the sincerity of Jones’ remark; it is simply to ask
This brings us to the third potential motivation for (K), gleaned from the
observation that Jones’ preference is fairly widespread, as noted already above. However,
it is questionable whether this provides any pre-theoretic reason for accepting (K) which,
as we saw above, is the kind of reason that needs to be provided. For one thing, we would
need evidence to the effect that the intuition in question is not merely a function of
previous theoretical commitments. This is not to defend some general form of skepticism
simply being taken at face value) exactly to the extent that they (a) pertain to subtle
philosophical matters and (b) are leveraged against reputable philosophical theories.
Since matters of comparative epistemic value are subtle, and EVM is a reputable theory
(which is something that has to be granted even by those who take it to be false), a
question arises: Is it the intuition that knowledge is more valuable than mere true belief
that provides the impetus for coming up with a theory that satisfies this intuition, or is it
the having of a theory on which knowledge is more valuable than mere true belief that
provides the impetus for the intuition? The absence of any arguments ruling out the latter
74
3.3. Meno and the Monist
There is one final place where the defender of (K) might seek pre-theoretic support for
the idea that knowing is more epistemically valuable than merely believing truly, even in
the absence of contemporary pre-theoretic support. That place is Plato’s Meno. In fact,
Socrates’ observations in the Meno about the surplus value of knowledge over mere true
belief has become such a common point of reference for defenders of (K) that the
problem of explaining why (K) holds often is referred to simply as the Meno problem.15
That said, this taxonomy is misleading on two points. First, as pointed out by
Dennis Whitcomb (forthcoming), it is misleading to talk about the Meno problem. In fact,
Whitcomb argues that, depending on exactly how the relevant surplus claim is spelled
out, there are at least 540 different problems that one can mean to be addressing. This, of
course, is compatible with it being the case that Plato and those that turn to him in
support of (K) still have the very same problem in mind. But this brings us to the second
point: As far as we are concerned with (K), it is even misleading to talk about the Meno
problem. More specifically, it will be argued that, to the extent that the there is a surplus
claim in the Meno, it is a claim that is differs from (K) with respect to both the scope of
the relevant claim and the kind of value that is at issue. Consequently, the defender of (K)
15
Here and henceforth, any reference to Socrates refers to the Socrates of Plato’s
dialogues, not to the historical Socrates.
16
It will be assumed presently that the term episteme is best translated as “knowledge.”
This translation has supporters in the literature (e.g., Fine 2004), but is not altogether
uncontroversial (see, e.g., Burnyeat 1980). Notice, however, that if episteme should not
be translated as “knowledge,” that is just yet another reason not to invoke the Meno in
support of (K).
75
Consider, first, the scope of the surplus claim that figures in the Meno. Towards
the end of the dialogue, Socrates suggests that knowledge is no more useful than mere
true belief (96c), and illustrates his point with reference to how someone knowing the
way to Larissa will be no worse of a guide to others with respect to getting them there
than someone who merely has a true belief about the way to Larissa (97a). This,
famously, makes Meno wonder “why knowledge is prized far more highly than right
opinion, and why they are different” (97c-d).17 In response, Socrates invokes the idea that
[…] true opinions, as long as they remain, are a fine thing and all they do is good,
but they are not willing to remain long, and they escape from a man’s mind, so
that they are not worth much until one ties them down by (giving) an account of
the reason why. And that, Meno, my friend, is recollection, as we previously
agreed. After they are tied down, in the first place they become knowledge, and
then they remain in place. That is why knowledge is prized higher than correct
opinion, and knowledge differs from correct opinion in being tied down (97e-
98a).
This, of course, is the very passage that has lead many contemporary epistemologists to
suggest that Plato subscribed to something along the lines of (K) in the Meno. However,
interpreting the passage thus is problematic. Notice that Plato identifies the reasoning18
relevant to knowing with recollection. Earlier in the dialogue, the process of recollection
reformulated by Socrates in terms of a dilemma. According to the first horn, the inquirer
“cannot search for what he knows—since he knows it, there is no need to search” (80e).
17
All translation of Plato are from Cooper (1997).
18
As indicated by the parenthetical remark in the translation “(giving) an account of the
reason why,” the relevant Greek phrase “aitias logismos” is generally thought to refer not
to the product but to the process of reasoning (logismos) to the cause or explanation
(aitia). See Fine (2004, p 58) for a discussion.
76
On the second horn, the inquirer also cannot search “for what he does not know, for he
Socrates’ solution to the paradox, involving the famous interrogation of the slave
boy about how to double the area of a square (82b-85c), is that “the man who does not
know has within himself true opinions about the things that he does not know” (85c) and
that, “if he were repeatedly asked these same questions in various ways, you know that in
the end his knowledge about these things would be as accurate as anyone’s” (85c-d). In
other words, the reason we can engage in philosophical inquiry is that we have tacit yet
true belief.19 All it takes is an elenchus. Through a persistent, dialectical inquiry in the
form of question and answer adversary argument, we may recollect what we used to
know when disembodied, but that has since been demoted from explicit knowledge to
That said, the claim that the theory of recollection is invoked by Plato to solve the
problem of inquiry is not altogether uncontroversial. For example, Dominic Scott (2006)
argues that the theory is instead invoked in a psychological strategy of carrot and stick,
attempting to both exploit Meno’s weakness for the exotic through allusions to ancients
myths in a context where he is getting tired of Socrates’ constant refutations, and arouse a
sense of shame in Meno by suggesting that he is weak for wanting to leave the
19
Some commentators (e.g., Taylor 2008 and Scott 2006) would prefer to talk about tacit
knowledge, and point to how Socrates (at 85d) talks about “the knowledge he [i.e., the
slave boy] now possesses”. Other commentators (e.g., Fine 2003) suggest that Socrates
here is referring to an envisaged future time, at which the slave boy has undergone a
successful elenchus, and point to how Socrates denies (at 85c) that the slave boy knows
anything at the end of the interrogation. Presently, I’m working with the latter
interpretation. Note, however, that the arguments to be made can be made just as easily
on the former interpretation as on the latter.
77
discussion.20 To the extent that the theory of recollection is introduced to solve any
asks, “if you really stumble upon it [i.e., the definiens], how will you know that this is the
thing you didn’t know before?” (80d). Scott refers to this question as posing a problem of
discovery.
There is no reason to doubt that Plato introduced the theory of recollection to play
a subtle rhetorical role in relation to Meno. It is less clear, however, whether it was not
also meant to solve the problem of inquiry. After all, what Scott refers to as the problem
of discovery seems a mere special case of the problem posed by Socrates’ second horn,
i.e., that the inquirer cannot search “for what he does not know, for he does not know
what to look for” (80e).21 On this point, notice that Meno does not resist Socrates’
reconstruction (81a). And why should he? Someone who does not know what he is
looking for has several problems as far as inquiry is concerned, one of which is that he
will not be able to tell if he has stumbled upon the target of investigation—unless his
inquiry is guided by tacit true belief, as postulated by the theory of recollection. That is
why inquiry is possible and the inquirer avoids the second horn. Moreover, given that the
beliefs guiding him do not constitute knowledge until tied down through the relevant
process of reasoning (i.e., through recollection), inquiry is still worthwhile and the
20
Hence, Socrates suggests that “we would be better, more manly and less lazy if we
believed that we ought to inquire into what we do not know, than if we believed that we
cannot discover what we do not know and so have no duty to inquire” (86b-c).
21
On this point, notice that Meno does not resist Socrates’ reconstruction (81a).
78
All of this is relevant presently for the following reason: If (a) the kind of
knowledge that Plato has in mind when having Meno suggest that knowledge is prized far
more highly than mere true opinion is the kind of knowledge that results from true belief
being tied through a process of reasoning; (b) to undergo the relevant process of
reasoning is, as Socrates suggests, to recollect; and (c) recollection is introduced for the
purpose of explaining why philosophical inquiry is possible, then the kind of knowledge
that Plato is concerned with in the Meno is not just any kind of knowledge; it is the
particular kind of knowledge had by those who have gained successful insight into the
This is not to suggest that Plato was committed to a theory of Forms already in the
Meno. It suffices to note that the one theme that is recurrent throughout the dialogues is
an inquiry into essences, or that by which the phenomena under investigation are what
they are.22 Given the epistemology of recollection introduced in the Meno, interpreting
that by which virtues “have one and the same form which makes them virtues” (72c) in
terms of proto-Forms is tempting but not necessary for present purposes. The only thing
maintained here is that, as far as the Meno is concerned, claims about the surplus value of
knowledge apply to the kind of knowledge relevant to recollection, and the kind of
22
Hence, when Socrates asks in the Meno “If I do not know what something is, how
could I know what qualities it possesses?” (71b), he not only seems to appeal to an
implicit distinction between essential and non-essential properties, but also follows up the
request for an account of the latter (at 72b) by asking for the nature of something, using
the same word (ousia) as he uses in the Euthyphro (at 11a-b) when asking for the essence
of piety. The same distinction between the essential and the non-essential appears in the
Laches (189e-190c), Protagoras (312c and 360e-361d), and Gorgias (463c).
79
whether or not such essences are to be spelled out in terms of Plato’s later ontology of
knowledge is also not to suggest that Plato necessarily took philosophical knowledge to
be the only kind of knowledge there is.23 If he did, then no qualification would be needed,
knowledge in general. Be that as it may; the only things necessary to make the present
point is that (a) contemporary epistemologists looking to the Meno in support of a claim
about the surplus value of knowledge do not restrict their claims to philosophical
knowledge, despite the fact that (b) the kind of knowledge at issue in the Meno’s
knowledge, whether or not Plato at any point took that to be the only kind of knowledge
there is.
One potential counterexample to (b) is the fact that the distinction between true
belief and knowledge is introduced in the Meno with reference to knowing the way and
guiding others to Larissa (97a). Taken literally, this example suggests that Plato’s
concerns in the Meno were not exclusively with philosophical knowledge. However,
consider that the topic of the dialogue, i.e., arete, which is typically translated as ‘virtue,’
not clear that we should understand the Larissa example as anything but a mere metaphor
for the kind of leading or guidance that Socrates ultimately seems to be concerned with,
23
There is some indication to the effect that Plato took knowledge to be restricted to
knowledge of forms in the Republic (see particularly the end of book V and books VI-
VII). See Taylor (2008, pp. 178-9) for a discussion.
24
See Scott (2006, p. 14) for a discussion.
80
i.e., the kind that Themistocles et al. are engaging in when leading their cities (99b).
After all, Larissa only figures twice in the dialogue; first, as a place inhabited by people
admired for their wisdom (70b), and, then, in aforementioned example, illustrating the
absence of a distinction between knowledge and mere true belief as far as usefulness is
concerned. At no point in the dialogue does Socrates concern himself with the kind of
knowledge that literal, geographical location and guidance would have to pertain to, i.e.,
empirical knowledge. Consequently, it is far from clear that Socrates would say that we
may literally know the way to Larissa, in the way that we (if genuinely virtuous) may
know how to lead a city, which is the kind of knowledge occupying the discussion at
large.25
As such, we may conclude that, to the extent that Plato subscribes to anything like
Understood thus, the problem as far as invoking the Meno in contemporary debates about
the value of knowledge is concerned, is that those invoking (K) in an argument against
EVM, as already noted, are concerned with knowledge in general. As such, there is a
clear difference in scope between the surplus claim found in the Meno and that defended
25
A similar point can be made about the passage at the very beginning of the dialogue
where Socrates talks about knowing who Meno is (71b), which, as Scott (2006, p. 21)
points out, “is best treated as a pedagogical device to give Meno an intuitive hold on the
idea of one question (‘what is x?’) having priority over another (‘what is x like?’).”
81
by recent epistemologists. Consequently, it is not clear that the passages typically quoted
In fact, further consideration of what Plato has Socrates say about the value of
knowledge suggests that the former’s take on the value of knowledge not only differs
from (K) with respect to scope, but also with respect to the kind of value involved.
According to Socrates, (philosophical) knowledge is more valuable than mere true belief
for being tied down through a process of reasoning about the relevant essences in virtue
of which the knowledge at issue, unlike the untied work of Daedalus, will “remain in
place” (98a). In other words, philosophical knowledge is more valuable than mere true
philosophical knowledge more fit for use in action, since Socrates explicitly denies that
there is any difference between knowledge and mere true belief on this score (98c).
A more plausible interpretation stays true to the central theme of the Meno, i.e.,
the relation between possessing philosophical knowledge and being able to teach virtue.
The connection between teachability and the stability of the former is not immediately
obvious from Socrates’ brief remarks in the Meno, but we may begin to see what is going
on if we follow Gail Fine (2004) in looking beyond the Meno toward the Republic.
According to Fine, the kind of stability at issue in the Meno should be understood in
terms of what is said in the Republic (540b-c) about how someone who knows (at least in
the limiting case of someone grasping the Good itself), unlike someone who merely
82
believes truly, is invulnerable to refutation.26 The same goes, of course, for someone who
just happens to be extremely dogmatic, which suggests that what is valuable about the
relevant kind of stability is not invulnerability per se, but rather the particular kind of
invulnerability that arises from judging things “in accordance with being” (543c).
Differently put, philosophical knowledge is not valuable because it is tied down, but
because of what it is tied down to, i.e., an account of the essence of things.
proposes in the Meno, having one’s beliefs be tied down thus is to have philosophical
able to teach virtue and, in effect, “make another into a statesman” (100a). In other
words, philosophical knowledge is (at the very least) valuable in that it enables one to
Throughout the Meno’s discussion about the value of virtue (87d-89a), the only value it is
explicitly said to have is that which it has on account of enabling one to use one’s assets
and philosophical true belief is instrumentally valuable, in that it enables one to use one’s
knowledge is more valuable than having true belief (philosophical or otherwise) because
someone endowed with the former not only will be able to use her assets correctly, but
26
See also Euthyphro, where Euthyphro complains that “whatever proposition we put
forward [for cross-examination] goes around and refuses to stay put where we establish
it” (11b), which prompts Socrates to make an allusion to Daedalus (11b-e).
83
also be capable of instilling the same capacities in others and, thereby, bring about
happiness on a much greater scale. More specifically, in so far as one has philosophical
knowledge, one will in general be able to bring about a much greater amount of
happiness, since the beneficial consequences of one’s endowment extends beyond the
(correct) use of one’s own assets, to include also the aggregate benefits of the actions of
highly (as Meno puts it) than mere philosophical true belief simply in virtue of how
bringing about more good is better than bringing about less good.
suggestion that philosophical knowledge tends to be prized far more highly than mere
philosophical true belief, as well as his explanation in terms of stability and recollection.
It does not go to show, however, that every instance of philosophical knowledge is more
valuable than every instance of mere philosophical true belief. After all, we can surely
amount of good on account of ruling a massive city correctly, while another statesman,
albeit endowed with knowledge, is unable to find neither subjects nor students on account
what Socrates sets out to show is merely that the former is prized far more highly than the
latter. To make that claim plausible, it is sufficient to show that philosophical knowledge
in general gives rise to more happiness than mere true belief, philosophical or otherwise.
Notice, however, that the above interpretation of Plato’s take on the value of
pertaining not to conduciveness to truth but to happiness. More specifically, if the value
84
of virtue is exhausted by the instrumental value it has because it is conducive to
happiness, does the presence of happiness swamp the value of virtue? It is not clear what
Plato would say here at the time of the Meno. It is interesting to note, however, that Plato
in the Republic sets out to defend the claim that justice is not only good as an instrument
but also as an end, in being both an instrument to happiness and an integral part of the
good life. However, no analogous claim is made about the value of virtue in the Meno,
which merely talks about the instrumental value of being virtuous. As such, I will leave it
open whether such a swamping problem would worry Plato at the time of the Meno.
This leaves us with one final question about Plato’s take on the value of
philosophical knowledge is valuable because it enables the knower to multiply virtue, and
virtue is valuable because it enables one to use one’s assets correctly and, in effect,
produce happiness, it seems fair to say that, whatever value attaches to knowledge on
value. In other words, in so far as Plato subscribed to anything like (K) at the time of the
Setting aside the issue that (K**), like (K*), only pertains to philosophical knowledge, as
opposed to knowledge in general, notice that (K**) is compatible with EVM, which is a
thesis exclusively about epistemic value. More generally, given that it does not follow
85
from something being valuable on one qualification (e.g., morally valuable, prudentially
valuable, or what have you) that it is valuable on every other qualification, (K**) is
compatible with EVM no matter how the relevant non-epistemic value is spelled out. In
fact, given that it does not follow from something being valuable without qualification
simply being more valuable simpliciter than mere true belief is compatible with EVM. In
conclusions, it is far from clear that contemporary critics of EVM have much to gain in
The previous sections suggested that there is scant pre-theoretic support for (K) in the
contemporary literature, and far less to gain for the defender of (K) in turning to the
Meno than what seems to be assumed in the literature. As such, there are no strong
reasons to account for (K), let alone to account for it in terms of knowledge being of
fundamental value. However, consider a point made recently by Jason Baehr (2009), who
valuable than true belief at the relevant intuitive level, we are thinking of it purely in the
abstract, without any (even implicit) reference to any of the features in virtue of which it
is apparently more valuable” (p. 51). This highlights a possibility ignored in the previous
sections, namely that the intuition behind (K) does not concern the surplus value of
knowledge directly, but rather the fundamental value of some component of knowledge,
86
that, when combined with the value of the factivity of knowledge, amounts to knowledge
What are the candidates for such a component? Clearly, truth is not one of them,
nor is mere belief. This leaves us with two partially overlapping candidates, namely
justification and warrant. Here, warrant is understood as whatever factor turns true belief
into knowledge (Plantinga 1993), and justification as warrant minus whatever condition
needs to be added to a JTB account in order for it not to have Gettier cases come out as
cases of knowledge. Presently, the focus will be on justification, the reason being that it is
unclear whether an account of warrant will tell us anything interesting about value. In a
passage commenting on Peter Klein’s (1981) attempt to avoid the Gettier problem by
In other words, any account that includes a Gettier clause (which any account of warrant
will) is bound to be ad hoc and gerrymandered, and any ad hoc and gerrymandered
87
analysis will fail to explain the surplus value of knowledge over justification. This
suggests that the most promising place to look for an account of the surplus value of
knowledge over true belief is not in the Gettier clause. Furthermore, since the Gettier
clause is what differentiates warrant from justification, focusing on the latter rather than
In fact, Kvanvig argues that there are at least two kinds of accounts of
justification that may escape the swamping problem and, thereby, account for (K),
namely certain (access) internalist and virtue epistemological theories. Further examples
can be found. As we saw in the previous chapter, Richard Feldman (2002) denies that
Feldman is right, (K) holds simply in virtue of the fact that (merely) believing truly is of
no non-instrumental epistemic value, while knowing is of such value in virtue of the non-
instrumental value of being justified. Since I have already discussed Feldman’s position
at length, I will not discuss it further here. Moreover, it is important to remember that
what we are after here are pre-theoretic reasons for at all seeking to account for (K). As
stressed above, simply providing a theory that implies that (K) holds, without providing
any reasons as for why theories should imply (K), would be in the interest of neither
With this in mind, return to the possibility called attention to above about the
intuition captured by (K) being an intuition not about knowledge per se, but rather about
27
This is not to suggest that an analysis being “ugly” yet correct implies that the
analysandum cannot be valuable. As pointed out by DePaul (2009), we cannot assume
that accuracy of analysis implies transparency with respect to value. The point relevant
here is simply that consulting analyses that are bound to be “ugly” does not constitute a
promising strategy, in so far as we are interested in questions about value, exactly
because we cannot assume such transparency.
88
the fundamental value of some component of knowledge, that, when combined with the
value of the factivity of knowledge, amounts to knowledge being more valuable than
mere true belief. Then assume, if only for the sake of the argument, that there is, in fact, a
widespread, pre-theoretic intuition to the following effect (for some sufficiently pre-
A widespread intuition to this effect would constitute prima facie evidence for the claim
that being justified is non-instrumentally valuable. Moreover, given that that justification
is non-factive, the non-instrumental value in question cannot be derived from that of true
belief, as in the case of knowledge and other factive states. Consequently, the most
plausible response to the evidence would be to consider the relevant value fundamental.
As such, the evidence in question would not only provide indirect support for (K) but also
constitute a direct challenge to (2), i.e., the idea that nothing is of non-instrumental
believing truly.
That said, the prima facie evidence in question might, like any prima facie
evidence, be defeated. In fact, it will be argued momentarily that the evidence in question
is defeated. More specifically, it will be argued that it cannot be ruled out that we would
intuitively take being justified to be non-instrumentally valuable even if it was not, given
what can reasonably be assumed about the central role that the inculcation and
89
inquiry. As such, the argument to be provided discredits the reliability of the particular
intuition in question, as far as the tracking of relevant axiological facts about the value of
justification is concerned, and suggests that even a widespread intuition to the effect that
(J) holds does not provide a reason for taking its content at face value.
valuable simply is for it to be valued (or preferred) in the relevant way, the confusion in
question is not possible. However, there are two problems with such a preferentialist
account of epistemic value. First, it does not do a good job of accounting for instrumental
value. Consider, for example, a particular research method. In so far as using that method
is conducive to something that is valuable for the inquirer, such as true belief, using the
method will be instrumentally valuable for the inquirer. However, it does not follow that
such usage, thereby, is instrumentally valued by the subject—after all, she may not even
be aware of the method, let alone of its virtues. Consequently, preferentialism is not a
non-instrumental value. The main problem is that such a thesis would either beg the
question against a defender of (J), or run the risk of rendering the domain of epistemic
value unrecognizable. To see why, consider that the thesis would be that all and only
90
beliefs formed on Wednesdays. Or rather, there is a possible constraint, to the effect that
that would simply beg the question against those who want to take the intuition to the
effect that (J) holds at face value and maintain that justification is valuable independently
identified with the significantly weaker thesis that non-instrumental value accrues only to
(but not to all) targets of non-instrumental preferences.28 Notice, however, that since such
instrumental value, it does not rule out the possibility that an inquirer values something
whether we should take an intuition to the effect that (J) holds at face value, we need to
say something about whether it is at all likely that the relevant kind of confusion—i.e., a
confusion to the effect that we mistakenly have come to consider justification non-
place and is driving the intuition in question. Above, it was suggested that epistemic
suppose that our intuitions about epistemic value will be sensitive to considerations about
the manners in which such goals are pursued in the practice of inquiry. With this in mind,
consider that we neither have voluntary influence over what we believe, nor an ability to
determine directly whether what we believe is true. Indeed, even such an optimist about
28
See, e.g., Rønnow-Rasmussen (2002).
91
introspection as Descartes took to developing rules for the direction of mind. Today, we
may have our doubts about the particular rules that he settled on, but the general insight
remains: we want truth, but in a “nonmagical world” like ours, to borrow a phrase from
Bernard Williams (1978), we have no choice but to resort to pursuing means for
This predicament has implications for what kind of norms of inquiry can be
fruitfully used and communicated in the process of epistemic education. The first
implication is a negative one: Norms formulated exclusively in terms of true belief, e.g.,
“Believe what is true,” will not only have an air of complete triviality about them—“Of
course we should believe what’s true,” the inquirer in training might say, and rightly so
from the point of view of teaching a budding inquirer how to conduct inquiry
successfully. The second implication is a positive one: The kind of norms that may be
fruitfully communicated in the process of epistemic education is exactly the kind that
pertains to means to truth, rather than to truth itself. This is mirrored by the way in which
inquiry (in its many manifestations) is typically taught. What is inculcated is not only a
love of truth, but also—and perhaps even more persistently—a love for a variety of
sometimes quite abstract principles about evidence, reflection, and coherence often found
In fact, it seems reasonable to believe that the majority not only of the inquirer’s
education but also of her subsequent inquiry will be concerned not with questions of truth
92
per se, but rather with the pursuit of means to truth. After all, the reason norms
formulated exclusively in terms of true belief are of so little use to inquiry is not merely
that they play a very limited role in the process of education, but also because they are
largely unhelpful for the practice of inquiry in general. More specifically, for any
question pondered by the inquirer, she either knows the answer, or she does not. If she
knows the answer, any injunction to the effect that she should believe what is true will be
unnecessary. If she does not know the answer, the same injunction will be useless. For
this reason, the love for the means to truth that is inculcated throughout an inquirer’s
education is likely to be further reinforced throughout her practice, and it cannot be ruled
out that she over time comes to value those states in themselves.
with what Goldman (Goldman and Olsson, 2009) recently has referred to as value
valuable later are “upgraded to the status of independent value, thereby accommodating
the legitimacy of adding their value to that of true-belief outcomes” (p. 35). As we saw
above, Goldman invokes this process in order to account for why we ascribe value in
accordance with (K). However, in the preceding sections, doubts were raised as to
whether we really have any pre-theoretic reasons to account for (K) in the first place. The
purpose of invoking an analogous process here is, therefore, not to account for (K), but
rather to undercut the claim that an intuition to the effect that (J) holds should be taken to
component of knowledge.
93
As such, the present argument is more directly related to John Stuart Mill’s (1861)
famously maintained about virtue that “[t]here was no original desire of it, or motive to it,
save for its conduciveness to pleasure, and especially to protection from pain” (p. 38).
However, due to that very conduciveness, we have come to not only associate the virtues
and vices with the moral and the immoral, respectively, but over time also forgotten the
yardstick against which the virtues originally earned their titles. Mill makes an analogy
with the love of money, noting that, even if the worth of money is solely that of the things
which it will buy, “money is in many cases desired in and for itself; the desire to possess
it is often stronger than the desire to use it, and goes on increasing when all the desires
which point to ends beyond it, to be compassed by it, are falling off” (p. 37). The
possibility pondered presently is that something similar might have happened with our
instrumentally valuable. Albeit valued in itself—and probably for good reason, given
how inquiry is taught and practiced—the means associated with justification remain of
mere instrumental value, in so far (and only in so far) as they enable the inquirer to form
true belief.
Naturally, none of this goes to establish beyond all possible doubt that such
axiological confusion has actually taken place. Still, the purpose of the present discussion
is merely to suggest that such confusion cannot be ruled out, given what we can
reasonably assume about the way in which inquiry is typically taught and practiced. This
ties in with what was suggested above about (K), namely that intuitions that pertain to
94
subtle philosophical matters and are leveraged against reputable philosophical theories
face value. It is in this context that the above line of reasoning should be understood. By
providing a plausible story suggesting that any intuition to the effect that (J) might not
track the relevant axiological facts, the argument puts a significant burden of proof on
those who want to take (J) at face value. In the absence of a rival account of the source of
the intuition in question that explains why it would track the relevant facts, we have no
reason to endow intuitions to the effect that (J) holds with any great evidential weight, or
As above, it bears stressing that this is not a case for general skepticism regarding
the evidentiary force of intuitions, but merely a suggestion to the effect that a particular
intuition cannot be taken at face value, given what we can reasonably assume about its
potential insensitivity to the relevant facts. Granted, a structurally similar argument could,
in principle, be given for other candidates for non-instrumental value as well. However,
two things should be noted. First, each such additional argument would have to be
considered on its own merit, with respect to how plausible a story it can provide about
how the intuitions in question fail to track the relevant axiological facts. In other words,
while the above argument may provide a structure for such arguments, it certainly does
not provide their conclusions. Second, interestingly, it is not clear that such an argument
could plausibly be given with respect the one value on which the present investigation
rests, i.e., the non-instrumental value of true belief. After all, such an argument would
have to conclude that true belief is not even a goal of inquiry—a claim that could be
interpreted in either of two ways. One the one hand, it could be understood as a claim to
95
the effect that there is a multitude of incompatible yet equally legitimate notions of
inquiry, only one of which is defined in terms of true belief. However, as we saw in the
previous chapter, this would, at most, imply that true belief is not non-instrumentally
valuable for everyone, not that true belief is not non-instrumentally valuable for anyone,
including those who engage in inquiry, as the latter is construed by the great majority of
epistemologists. On the other hand, it could be interpreted as a claim to the effect that
there is no such thing as inquiry at all. It is terribly hard to make sense of such a claim,
and an argument terminating in such a conclusion would, most plausibly, not be properly
To recapitulate, it has been argued that we lack convincing pre-theoretic reason to take
knowing to be of greater epistemic value than merely believing truly, or to consider being
justified non-instrumentally valuable. The present section considers the third and final
understanding will be discussed, the first one due to Kvanvig, and the second one due to
Kvanvig (2003) is concerned with what he refers to as objectual understanding, i.e., the
when we talk about someone understanding politics or the presidency (p. 191). According
96
to Kvanvig, such understanding is factive (p. 190), and requires the satisfaction of a
explanatory, logical, probabilistic, and other kinds of relations that coherentists have
not need to satisfy a Gettier condition and is not susceptible to the worries discussed at
This opens up the possibility that it can be shown for understanding what Kvanvig
argues cannot be shown for knowing, i.e., that it is more valuable than any proper subset
implying that p, and quite another to provide pre-theoretic reasons as for why we should
want our theory to imply that p in the first place. According to Kvanvig, “there is at least
as much intuitive support for the idea that understanding has value beyond that of its
subparts as there is for the idea that knowledge has such value” (p. 188). In light of what
has been argued above, this statement might be less comforting than Kvanvig probably
intended it—a problem that is exacerbated by the fact that Kvanvig provides no
additional pre-theoretic support for such value in the case of understanding, beyond that
understanding can be accounted for. Since the account provided is a highly intriguing
one, let us make an exception and waive the above requirement to provide pre-theoretic
97
support, if only for the sake of the argument. More specifically, let us grant Kvanvig the
then we have good reason to believe that we have found a candidate counterexample to
(2). After all, in analogy with what was said about (K) above, (U) could neither be
pain of falling prey to the swamping problem). Consequently, the most plausible
inference to draw from (U) would be that the surplus value of understanding over mere
true belief is due to a fundamental, non-instrumental value, distinct from that which
applies to true belief, which, clearly, would contradict (2). On the other hand, if the
account provided by Kvanvig does not make it plausible that (U) holds—and below it
will be argued that it does not—then (a) the same would have to be said for the stronger
claim about understanding being more epistemically valuable than any proper subset of
According to Kvanvig, the value relevant to accounting for (U) is that associated
with the satisfaction of the coherentist condition. In order to avoid the swamping
problem, Kvanvig takes the relevant kind of value to be non-instrumental (p. 200). In
explicating the relevant kind of value, Kvanvig makes a distinction between intentional
and effective means to goals, such as the goal of believing truly (pp. 63-64). Effective
means are instrumentally valuable in so far as they raise the likelihood of securing the
98
relevant ends. Intentional means are also valuable, according to Kvanvig, but not because
they raise the likelihood of securing the goals in question. Such means are involved in
trying to attain goals, and account for the value of such attempts even if they fail to raise
the likelihood of attaining the goals in question as a result of trying. It is in this kind of
value that we find the surplus value of understanding over mere true belief. More
Why is merely trying to attain true belief valuable, even if so doing goes no
lengths whatsoever toward actually attaining true belief? Kvanvig’s answer invokes a
story not too different from the one alluded to in §3.4, albeit with an introspectionist
twist:
Truth is not a property that is always reflectively accessible […] and so we must
adopt some means for identifying beliefs to hold in order to achieve the indirect
goal of believing a claim if and only if it is true. So we should try to have, or
value, beliefs with some other property, one that we can tell directly and
immediately whether a belief has (Kvanvig 2003, pp. 65-66).
Internalist justification is one such property—a “mark of truth” (p. 64), as Kvanvig calls
it—albeit one that is unable to account for the surplus value of knowledge over any
subset of its constituents due to aforementioned Gettier worries. Another such property is
the internal grasping of how various elements in a body of information are related.
Moreover, according to Kvanvig, the value associated with adopting such a grasp as an
intentional means toward believing truly is exactly what accounts for (U).
Or does it? Consider two possible interpretations of Kvanvig’s claim about the
value of adopting intentional means. First, let us assume that the idea is that simply trying
99
to attain true belief—no matter the instrumental merits of the means utilized—is
a subject that sincerely tries to attain true belief, yet opts for a reflectively accessible
means toward truth that, due to a particularly deviant conception on the subject’s part
about what will actually get her the truth, actually is highly detrimental to her attainment
of true belief. Claiming that the mere fact that she has adopted certain intentional goals
by virtue of sincerely trying to attain true belief makes her conduct epistemically valuable
seems highly implausible.29 This is not to deny that opting for reflectively accessible
surrogates for truth might often be a good thing for reasons not too different from those
discussed in the previous section, but merely to point out that opting for just any
reflectively acceptable surrogate does not yield any epistemic value as such.
Second, it might be argued that this interpretation ignores the nature of the
coherentist condition that Kvanvig takes to be central to understanding. That is, let us
assume that Kvanvig has in mind the significantly weaker claim that aiming for truth by
way of some particular intentional means—including but not necessarily limited to the
perhaps what explains the surplus value of understanding is not that something is
intentionally pursued as a mark of truth, but that what is intentionally pursued thus is
something with epistemically virtuous properties, where the virtue in question (on pain of
29
It might be objected that there is still something admirable or valuable about someone
sincerely pursuing truth, even if she does a horrible job at it. That may be so—after all,
we admire people and their conduct for all kinds of reason, most of which are not
importantly related to the formation of true belief. That said, to be relevant presently, the
kind of admiration or value at issue would need to be epistemic, and that is what seems
highly doubtful.
100
instrumental connections. This interpretation seems more faithful to what Kvanvig
eventually concludes about the value of understanding. At the very end of his book, he
that
[…] to have mastered such explanatory relationships is valuable not only because
it involves the finding of new truths but also because finding such relationships
organizes and systematizes our thinking on a subject matter in a way beyond the
mere addition of more true beliefs or even justified true beliefs. Such organization
is pragmatically useful because it allows us to reason from one bit of information
to other related information that is useful as a basis for action, where unorganized
thinking provides no such basis for inference. Moreover, such organized elements
of thought provide intrinsically satisfying closure to the process of inquiry,
yielding a sense or feeling of completeness to our grasp of a particular subject
matter. In sum, understanding is valuable because it is constituted by subjectively
justified true belief across an appropriately individuated body of information that
is systematized and organized in the process of achieving understanding, and
subjectively justified true belief that is systematized in this way is valuable
(Kvanvig 2003, p. 202).
In other words, there are three potential sources for the value of understanding. The first
one is that the relevant grasp may lead to new truths being found. However, considering
that the value in question would be instrumental, it could not account for (U), due to
systematicity to our thinking. That may be a good thing, but Kvanvig explicitly states that
the kind of value relevant to such systematicity is pragmatic, not epistemic. As such, it
cannot account for the surplus value relevant to (U). The third source is that
understanding brings a feeling of closure. Such a feeling may be pleasurable and, hence,
prudentially valuable. However, as such, it does not seem relevant to epistemic value,
nor, consequently, to (U). Hence, even waiving the requirement to provide pre-theoretic
support for (U), we still lack reason to believe that the value in question is not exhausted
101
by (a) the non-instrumental value derived from its factivity, and (b) the instrumental
3.5.2. Understanding-Why
There are, of course, other types of understanding besides objectual understanding. More
recently, Pritchard (forthcoming) has defended a view about understanding-why, i.e., the
Pritchard’s account is meant to account for what he refers to as the distinctive value of
degree and kind (p. 13). More specifically, while Pritchard takes understanding-why
(henceforth, simply “understanding”) to be factive (p. 113), he does not take the value of
understanding to be exhausted by the value that it has in virtue of its factivity. For
than anything that falls short of understanding, including true belief, and for that surplus
Presently, we will focus on the latter claim, since it is the more basic one of the
two. After all, the surplus value in question is supposed to be explained with reference to
the non-instrumental value of understanding. But before delving into Pritchard’s theory,
let us consider what pre-theoretic reasons we have for at all taking understanding to be
distinctively valuable is surely even stronger than the intuition that knowledge is
distinctively valuable” (p. 101). If what has been argued above is correct, it better be. But
102
since Pritchard does not elaborate on the claim, let us simply grant him an advantage
analogous to that granted to Kvanvig above, and waive the requirement on pre-theoretic
between two kinds of value that we familiarized ourselves with already in the above, i.e.,
final value and fundamental value. According to Pritchard, a fundamental epistemic good
is an “epistemic good whose epistemic value is at least sometimes not simply [an]
instrumental value relative to a further epistemic good” (p. 19). More specifically,
Pritchard takes the defining feature of fundamental epistemic value to be that it can “act
as the terminus for the instrumental regress of epistemic value” (p. 19). Consequently,
fundamental (non-instrumental) epistemic value above. After all, any good whose non-
instrumental epistemic value derives from the value of one of its components can not act
as the relevant kind of terminus, since any question about why that good is of non-
some instances of true belief are of fundamental epistemic value is compatible with
maintaining that (those) instances are only valuable thus in so far as they pertain to
103
questions posed by some relevant set of inquirers. In other words, maintaining that some
compatible with maintaining that those instances are valuable thus only in so far as they
simpliciter. So, again, fundamental non-instrumental epistemic value does not imply final
value.
epistemic value.” “After all,” he writes, “if an epistemic good has a value which is not an
instrumental value then, a fortiori, it has a value which is not an instrumental epistemic
value either” (p. 20). That seems right. But surely it does not go to show that final value
implies non-instrumental epistemic value. There are more ways of not being of
not be of any epistemic value at all. As we noted already in §3.1, there are plausible
candidates for finally valuable goods, such as the value that pertains to undergoing an
episode of pleasure, that, clearly, are not thereby of epistemic value, let alone of non-
This presents a problem for Pritchard, since he rests his entire case for the value
of understanding on this alleged implication. More specifically, he argues that the reason
skills, and thus creditable to the exercise of her abilities. Moreover, according to
Pritchard, such achievements are finally valuable. How so? Pritchard asks us to imagine
104
Imagine […] that you are about to undertake a course of action designed to attain
a certain outcome and that you are given the choice between merely being
successful in what you set out to do, and being successful in such a way that you
exhibit an achievement. Suppose further that it is stipulated in advance that there
are no practical costs or benefits to choosing either way. Even so, wouldn’t you
prefer to exhibit an achievement? And wouldn’t you be right to do so? If that’s
correct, then this is strong evidence for the final value of achievements (Pritchard
forthcoming, p. 44).
Combining Pritchard’s points about understanding and cognitive achievements, his case
This is a valid argument. But it is not sound, and for two reasons. First, as called attention
to above, all finally valuable goods are not of non-instrumental epistemic value, since
some finally valuable goods are of no epistemic value at all. This undermines (2).
cognitive achievement in the scenario imagined (as opposed to, perhaps, having no
preference either way), we have some reason to rule out exhibiting an achievement being
of instrumental practical value. However, this establishes neither that (a) exhibiting an
105
achievement is of non-instrumental practical value (since there are more ways of not
including to not be of any practical value at all), nor that (b) exhibiting an achievement is
not of some non-instrumental qualified value. As for the latter, it might, for example, be
that there is something intrinsically pleasing about exhibiting an achievement, and that
of this serves to establish the far stronger claim that cognitive achievements are of final
support the claim that such understanding is of non-instrumental epistemic value, even if
we waive the requirement to provide pre-theoretic support. For all we are being told, the
value of understanding is exhausted by the non-instrumental value that derives from its
achievement. However, contrary to what Pritchard argues, it is not clear that the latter
kind of value is final. Moreover, even if it is granted that cognitive achievements are
finally valuable, and that understanding is a form of cognitive achievement, this does not
conclude that Pritchard’s account of understanding poses no problem for (2), nor
106
3.6. Conclusion
Recently, epistemic value monism has come under attack by philosophers arguing that
we cannot account fully for the domain of epistemic value in monistic terms. But as we
have seen, the relevant arguments fail to establish any such thing. For one thing, there is a
a presumption would be defeated by positive evidence to the effect that the relevant kind
of monism makes us unable to fully account for the domain of epistemic value. However,
epistemic value, casts serious doubt upon the claim that there is any such evidence.
107
CHAPTER 4
The previous two chapters established two things. First, believing truly is of non-
instrumental epistemic value (albeit not necessarily for everyone), in virtue of true belief
being valuable thus. As noted earlier, this is not to say that all instances of true belief are
non-instrumentally valuable. As will be argued below, only the subset consisting of true
beliefs that are significant are valuable thus. Much of §4.1 will be devoted to spelling out
the relevant notion of significance, by explaining how believing some true propositions is
in some relevant epistemic sense more important to inquirers than believing other true
propositions, specifically in so far as the truths in question serve to answer questions that
should do, in so far as they want answers to their questions: they should employ the
particular practices that will enable them to answer those questions. §4.2 will be
concerned with tracing the limits of this ‘should.’ In particular, it will be suggested that it
follows from the account to be defended that there are very real limits to the extent to
which we can make epistemic judgments about what questions inquirers should pose (as
opposed to about what methods or practices to opt for, given a set of questions).
However, it is also argued that, rather than indicating a flaw in the theory, this simply
108
suggests that it is able to maintain a clear distinction between epistemic and other kinds
of betterness (e.g., moral, practical, etc.), and, thereby, account for the specialized nature
of epistemic evaluation.
recommendations can be implemented either on the individual or on the social level. For
reasons that will be discussed at length in the next chapter—in essence, that ameliorative
advice provided directly to the individual rather than implemented by way of a social
paternalistic mandate are likely to face problems of defection—the focus will presently
belief-forming process.1
about what it would mean for one practice to perform better from an epistemic point of
view than another. More specifically, any evaluation (and attempt at amelioration) needs
to be made against the background of (a) an account of what practices need to produce in
order to be positively evaluated, as well as (b) a framework for comparing practices with
1
See Goldman (1986, p. 93).
109
evaluation that involves an account of epistemic betterness, as applied to practices. The
present chapter develops such a framework in terms of the monistic account of epistemic
How are we to spell out the notion of epistemic betterness, given such an
of a practice, i.e., the ratio of true to false belief that the practice produces (or would
produce) under a given set of circumstances. However, a practice may generate a high
ratio but a very low number of true beliefs. For this reason, we may try to invoke a
combination of reliability and power, where the latter corresponds to the number of true
arises, to the effect that a practice may be extremely reliable and powerful without
answering any questions whatsoever, as in a case where it only generates high ratios and
numbers of true belief that are of no relevance whatsoever to the concerns of the agent.2
A more promising strategy is, therefore, to specify the relevant notion of power
relevant as far as power is concerned, is not that the agent arrives at a large number of
true beliefs per se, but that she arrives at a large number of true beliefs that answer
questions she wants answered.4 In light of this, consider the following triad of definitions,
2
Cf. Alston (2005) and Goldman (1986).
3
See Goldman (1986, p. 123).
4
This is a slight departure from Goldman’s formulation in terms of “the proportion of
questions [a cognitive system] wants to answer that it can answer (correctly)” (1986, p.
123; emphasis added). (See Goldman 1992a, p. 195 for a similar formulation in terms of
practices.) However, note that a formulation in terms of proportions of questions that the
subject wants answered would imply that a practice can be rendered less powerful (for
110
(B) A practice P1 is epistemically better than another practice P2 for a subject S
(O) a practice P1 outperforms another practice P2 for S iff P1 yields (i) a higher
ratio and number, (ii) an equal ratio but a higher number, or (iii) a higher
For ease of reference, I will henceforth refer to any combination of definitions by way of
their abbreviations, together with a ‘+.’ For example, I will refer to the combination of
above definitions as ‘(B)+(O)+(S1).’ (Definitions clearly assumed but not at issue will be
suppressed for the sake of brevity.) The above triad of definitions raises a number of
questions that will be addressed in the remainder of the section, where they will also be
refined and qualified in a number of ways. First off: What is a research agenda?
questions the pursuit of which the relevant inquirers consider most worthy of their limited
epistemic resources. A couple of comments are at place. First, the reasons for specifying
the set in terms of the questions deemed most worthy of pursuit will be discussed in due
course (see §4.2.1), and may be put to the side presently. Second, the questions featured
that subject) simply by increasing the number of questions asked, while a formulation in
terms of numbers would be sensitive to the factor that seems more relevant, i.e., the
numbers of questions answered.
111
on the agenda do not need to be explicitly formulated by the inquirer. A research agenda
may simply be the most plausible reconstruction of the questions that the inquirer deems
most pressing, as revealed by the choices that she makes in allocating her resources.
Third, while there is, clearly, legitimate room for a notion of an agenda as applicable to
an inquirer because an institution or other pertinent body considers the relevant set of
questions worthy of her limited resources, I will reserve the discussion of such an
For present purposes, we may assume that there are two broad classes of reasons
for pursuing some questions rather than others. On the one hand, there is the class of
reasons that we may ascribe to curiosity, or a desire for an answer to a question for the
mere purpose of attaining that answer. I will not delve into the nature or source of this
desire, but merely take it as a psychological fact that there is such a thing as a “sheer
intellectual curiosity” (Hempel 1965, p. 333) that, to paraphrase Larry Laudan (1977, p.
225), seems to be every bit as compelling to many of us as our need for clothing and
food. On the other hand, there is also the class of reasons that we may ascribe to a desire
to attain answers for some other sake than the mere attainment of those answers, be it for
pursues answers to questions because of curiosity or for some other reason, she will not
necessarily consider every true answer equally worthy of pursuit. To illustrate this point,
consider two social practices, P1 and P2. P1 generates x answers to questions on the
relevant inquirer’s agenda at a truth ratio of y within the relevant circumstances, while the
5
See Goldman (1999, p. 94) for a relevant discussion.
112
corresponding values for P2 are x + n and y, where x, y, and n > 0. Moreover, while P1
would have to say that P2 is epistemically better than P1 (for the inquirer in question).
Needless to say, that would not make for particularly good advice from the point of view
of amelioration.
I do not have a theory about what constitutes sufficiently informative answers, but
I am also not so sure that we need one. To make this point, I will, first, consider an
illustration of the relevant notion and, then, suggest that we have a sufficiently good
answers, respectively, for us to not require a theory. By way of illustration, consider the
following question:
We can imagine one answer that lists the actual cause(s) of x. Then we can imagine
another answer: “Something.” Both answers are true and on topic, but there is a sense in
which the latter is genuinely unhelpful. Returning to the two classes of reasons for
pursuing answers to questions introduced above, this might be so for either of two
reasons. Assuming that we are interested in finding an answer to (Q) for some other
reason than mere curiosity, e.g., if x constitutes a malfunction that we want to correct and
113
nothing whatsoever about how to go about doing this. Similarly, if we are interested in
(Q) as a result of curiosity, the mere fact that we are simply curious about an answer to
(Q) does not imply that we would accept just any true answer as a sufficiently
informative answer. For example, someone pondering what gave rise to some ancient
event may do so without having any practical (or moral, or prudential, or what have you)
stake in the answer—maybe she just finds thinking about these kinds of things
intellectually stimulating. Still, her curiosity might, nevertheless, only be satiated given
that the answer is sufficiently informative. Indeed, had she not been curious about the
question, she might have settled for a completely uninformative answer, like
“something.”
roughly that of the answer actually answering the question, in a sense that goes beyond
saying something that is both true and on topic. Interesting formal work has been done on
specifying the exact features that answers are typically required to have (beyond that of
being true and on topic) for a variety of question types.6 However, more relevant than the
details of the relevant literature—details that, for present purposes, would add formal
detail but not necessarily explanatory value—is the kind of data invoked in the literature,
6
See, e.g., Belnap and Steel (1976), as well as Jaworski (2009) for a recent application of
Belnap and Steel’s framework to certain kinds of how-questions.
114
(A) an answer a is a sufficiently informative answer to a question q iff (i) a is
true, and (ii) any normally functioning person that grasps the contents of
be true.
This might be more of a clarification than a definition. For one thing, a completely
satisfactory definition would need to spell out the relevant notions of normal functioning,
content and what it is to grasp content. That being said, I believe that (A), nevertheless, is
sufficient for present purposes, given our intuitive ability to provide reasonable verdicts
answers, respectively. Moreover, against the background of (A), we may reformulate (S1)
as follows:
(B)+(O)+(S2)+(A) yields the verdict that P1 is epistemically better than P2 in the above
(O) invokes the notions of ratios and numbers of belief. This seems to be presupposing
that beliefs can be individuated in systematic ways. However, any given belief can be
described at a number of degrees of generality. For example, should my belief “The sun
115
is shining right now” be distinguished from my belief that “The sun is shining on
September 14th, 2009”? Or from my belief that “The sun is shining in New Brunswick on
September 14th, 2009”? It is hard to say. More than that, in want of a principled account
problem about double counting and about not counting what should be counted. For this
reason, one may have one’s doubt about the usefulness of talking about ratios and
numbers of belief. These doubts may be intensified by the fact that we, on the present
account, need to individuate ratios and numbers of significant (true) beliefs, i.e., beliefs
we not only need to individuate beliefs, but also answers and agenda items.
In response to these worries, it should be noted that talk about ratios and numbers,
albeit convenient for the purposes of thinking clearly about the relevant issues, has as
Andrew Latus (2000) puts it a “misleading air of precision,” as far as the evaluation of
actual practices is concerned. More specifically, what I would like to suggest is that
account of belief, answer, and agenda item individuation. It only requires that we can
approximate the relevant magnitudes to an extent sufficient for making informative and
Let us start with the individuation of belief. As just noted, the kinds of claims we
have to be able to make on the present account are comparative claims. More than that,
the kind of comparative claims that concern us here are explicitly ordinal claims.
Consequently, when comparing two practices, the only thing required is that we are able
to make comparative claims about one practice yielding more significant true beliefs than
116
another, or one practice yielding a greater preponderance of significant true belief than
another. What I would like to suggest is that the kinds of problems coming out of dangers
of double-counting and not counting what should be counted are not on a scale that
undercuts the possibility of making such ordinal claims. And given that we do not need
anything beyond such claims to make sense of the comparisons involved in (O), the
present account does not fall prey to a problem of individuation, as far as the
suggested above that we have a fairly robust intuitive sense of what constitutes
associated with individuation would have to be severe enough to make impossible even
informed approximations in the form of comparative, ordinal claims about the relative
merits of two practices. In light of this, an answer similar to the one given above in
relation to belief individuation may be given also in the case of answer individuation.
More specifically, I submit that we can approximate the relevant magnitudes and
informative and roughly accurate comparative judgments, even in the absence of a fully
Consider, finally, the individuation of agenda items. Any given inquirer may want
less interconnected and of different degrees of generality. For example, consider a cancer
researcher. At the most general level, a cancer researcher may be interested in the causes,
treatment and/or prevention of cancer. With respect to each general area, the researcher
117
may, in turn, be interested in a series of more specific questions. For example, with
respect to the causes of cancer, the researcher may be interested in identifying common
types of mutated genes that tend to be causally implicated in turning normal cells into
cancer cells. Beyond that, the researcher may be particularly interested in a specific sub-
set of such genes, perhaps because understanding the nature of that sub-set has proven to
in turn, may have implications for the success of different forms of treatment and
strategies for prevention. So, how many items figure on her agenda?
It goes without saying that any numerical judgment made in this context is going
to be largely arbitrary. Still, it is likely that different disciplines have developed certain
rough standards for how to group different questions into hierarchies—hierarchies that
calls for papers. This is not to suggest that these hierarchies are, in any way, cutting the
space of taxonomical possibilities at its natural joints (if there even are any such natural
joints). Still, it is likely that we can expect a certain degree of homogeneity within
disciplines with respect to how inquirers will characterize their agendas. Moreover, if we
can expect there to be such hierarchies, and we see to it that we focus on the same level
of any given hierarchy in comparing how well two practices do with respect to answering
the questions contained on that level, then the possibility that every form of inquiry can
be described with reference to a great multitude of different questions does not seem to
118
4.1.3. Shared Agendas
So far, we have been concerned with what it is for one practice to be epistemically better
than another for an individual. As for what it is for one practice to be better than another
for a group of individuals, consider the following reformulations of (B), (O) and (S2):
(OG) a practice P1 outperforms another practice P2 for G iff P1 yields (i) a higher
ratio and number, (ii) an equal ratio but a higher number, or (iii) a higher
ratio but an equal number of beliefs that are significant to the subjects in G,
and
As these definitions make clear, what it is for one practice to be epistemically better than
another for a group is just a matter of aggregating the relevant ratios and numbers for the
group’s individuals, on the crucial assumption that the individuals in question share a
research agenda. In the interest of simplicity of exposition, I will stick to talking in terms
of epistemic betterness for an individual subject, and leave to the reader to draw the
However, note that none of this is to suggest that we cannot imagine comparative
epistemic measures across agendas. For example, a measure that can be extracted from
119
the present account fairly easily is the following: A practice P1 is more robust than
another practice P2 iff P1 outperforms P2 for a wider range of agendas than the range of
agendas within which P2 outperforms P1. Note, however, that one practice being more
robust than another does not imply that the former is epistemically better than the latter,
for the simple reason that epistemic betterness is defined with reference to a single
agenda. This mirrors the intuition that a practice might be epistemically better than
another given a very specific set of questions, without, thereby, being successfully
applicable to a whole host of other questions, as is surely the case with several practices
within the sciences that involve very specialized forms of methods, practices, and
instruments. We will return to this issue briefly in §5.3 below. Beyond that, I will not
have anything to say about comparative epistemic measures that may apply across
agendas.
4.1.4. On Incomparability
On (O), one practice outperforms another if and only if the former yields (i) a higher ratio
and number, (ii) an equal ratio but a higher number, or (iii) a higher ratio but an equal
number of true belief that are significant to S than the latter practice does. But what about
scenarios in which none of (i) through (iii) holds? By mapping out all the nine (i.e., 32)
possibilities, we see that there are easy as well as hard cases. More specifically, consider
the following table, representing the comparison of one practice, P1, with another
practice, P2, where ‘+’ represents P1 receiving a higher score than P2 on the relevant
factor, ‘–‘ represents P1 receiving a lower score than P2 on the relevant factor, and ‘=’
120
REL PWR
1. + + B
2. = + B
3. + = B
4. = = E
5. + – I
6. – + I
7. = – W
8. – = W
9. – – W
Rows 1 through 3 cover cases in which (i), (ii), or (iii) hold, and where P1, consequently,
is epistemically better than P2. Row 4 covers a case in which P1 and P2 are equally
epistemically good, and rows 7 through 9 cases in which P1 is epistemically worse than
(E) Two practices, P1 and P2, are equally epistemically good for a subject S iff
P1 and P2 yield equal ratios and numbers of beliefs that are significant to S.
iff P1 yields (i) an equal ratio but a lower number, (ii) a lower ratio but an
equal number, or (iii) a lower ratio and a lower number of beliefs that are
This leaves us with rows 5 and 6, involving cases where one of the two practices fares
better on one score, while the other fares better on the other score. What are we to say
121
(I) Two practices, P1 and P2, are epistemically incomparable for a subject S iff
This way of understanding incomparability is fairly standard in the literature.7 On (I), the
cases covered by rows 5 and 6 are instances of epistemic incomparability. That is, while
one practice is epistemically better with respect to power, and one with respect to
inferred that one is epistemically better than the other simpliciter. Consequently, in these
cases of incomparability, there are no epistemic reasons to prefer one of the practices to
the other.
However, it should be noted that this is perfectly compatible with there being a
whole host of non-epistemic reasons to prefer one practice over another, even in a
scenario where they are incomparable from an epistemic point of view. For example, we
can easily imagine cases in which avoiding error is more important than arriving at many
true answers, due to the fact that the moral or practical costs of a mistaken judgment
about the matters at hand far outweighs the benefits of being able to make a judgment. In
such cases, reliability might trump power, and P1, hence, be preferable on non-epistemic
grounds to P2 in the scenario represented by row 5, despite the two practices being
7
See, e.g., Chang (1997). This is not to say that the idea that this is the proper way to
understand incomparability is unchallenged. For example, Chang (2002) argues for the
existence of a fourth relation (beyond better, worse, and equally good), i.e., parity—a
relation that I will not consider presently.
122
important that an answer is generated than that the proportion of false answers to total
in cases of epistemic comparability. In the latter cases, however, such considerations are
not invoked in the absence of any epistemic reasons to opt for one practice over the other,
considerations. Still, qua non-epistemic considerations, they fall outside the scope of the
present investigation, beyond the extent to which they may serve to account for the
intuition that (a) epistemic incomparability is compatible with having reasons (as in: non-
epistemic reasons) to prefer one practice over another, and that (b) the epistemic reasons
considerations. We will find reason to return to the latter point in the next chapter (in
§5.4).
Let us take stock at what has been argued so far. The account of epistemic betterness
123
(O) a practice P1 outperforms another practice P2 for a subject S iff P1 yields (i)
a higher ratio and number, (ii) an equal ratio but a higher number, or (iii) a
higher ratio but an equal number of belief that are significant to S, and
true, and (ii) any normally functioning person that grasps the contents of
be true.
On this account, epistemic betterness is defined for practices, given a research agenda.
The account, thereby, tells us something about what inquirers should do, in so far as they
want to arrive at belief that answer their questions. In the remainder of this chapter, I will
address two concerns. First, while answering any questions on our agendas, clearly,
might be a good thing from an epistemic point of view, might it not be epistemically
better to answer some questions rather than others? In particular, might it not be
epistemically better to answer questions that we are more interested in than questions that
we are less interested in (ceteris paribus)? Second, what epistemic judgments can we
make with respect to what items should figure on agents’ agendas in the first place? Let
124
4.2.1. Degrees of Interest
significant to an inquirer that the belief (or, to be exact: its content) constitutes a
sufficiently informative answer to questions on her agenda. As we have seen, this makes
significance agent-relative in the sense that what true beliefs are significant is, in part, a
function of the questions posed by the inquirer. At the same time, significance is on the
present account an objective matter, at least in the following sense: A belief b1 is not
necessarily more significant for an agent than another belief b2 simply because she
considers the questions answered by b1 more interesting than the answered by b2.
discussed recently by Don Fallis (2006), in which there are two practices, P1 and P2,
available to an agent.8 P1 yields as its only output one believed proposition that answers
one question that the inquirer takes great interest in, viz. the question of how the world
could be made a good and happy place, while P2 yields as its only output two believed
propositions that answer two questions the inquirer takes some (but less) interest in, viz.
the questions when Hill Street Blues and Streets of San Francisco come on TV,
respectively. Assuming that the inquirers take sufficient interest in all three questions for
them to be featured on her research agenda, and that other things are equal—e.g., that the
believed propositions answer no more than one question each—it follows on the present
8
Fallis formulates his argument in terms of sets of doxastic states rather than in terms of
the processes or practices that generate these sets. In order to make his argument
applicable to the present account, however, I have reformulated it in terms of practices.
125
Is this a problem? To get a better grip on the issues relevant to answering this
question, let us consider Fallis’ suggestion as for an alternative account, on which the
epistemic value of forming a true belief is weighted by the degree of interest that the
agent has in the truth in question.9 Worries about how to properly quantify degrees of
interest aside, Fallis’ framework would, thereby, enable us to say that P1 is epistemically
better than P2, due exactly to the fact that the inquirer deems the question answered by
way of P1 more interesting than the questions answered by P2. Fallis introduces his
questions that interest the inquiring agent, in much the same way as epistemic evaluation
on the present account is restricted to questions that are featured on the relevant inquirer’s
research agenda.10 As such, the presence of interest, clearly, plays a role on Goldman’s
interest in an attempt to balance two desiderata. On the one hand, he acknowledges that
“a good epistemic practice should not be indifferent to the relative amounts of interest
that a given agent takes in different questions” (Goldman 1999, p. 95). On the other hand,
where the latter “might go so far as to use the degree of interest in a question to give an
overall weighting to an agent’s veritistic [i.e., truth-related] success” (p. 95). Goldman
sees two problems with letting interests play a pervasive role in evaluation:
9
See Fallis (2006, pp. 181-182).
10
See Goldman (1999, pp. 88 and 94-96).
126
First, one person’s questions of interest might be easier to answer than those of a
second. The fact that the first scores higher on the set of questions that interest her
does not demonstrate superior intellectual skill. Second, the intensity of interest a
person takes in a question may reflect factors that do not properly belong in an
epistemological analysis. The magnitude of interest may depend on the person’s
financial or mortal stake in the question. But that does not mean that his
succeeding or failing to answer those questions correctly should loom
disproportionately large in an epistemic analysis. This would lead down the path
toward abandoning the specialized, veritistic mission of epistemology in favor of
a more purely pragmatic enterprise (Goldman 1999, p. 95).
However, note that Goldman’s two objections to providing degrees of interests with a
pervasive role in epistemic evaluation apply even if reformulated in terms of the presence
(as opposed to degrees) of interest. As for easy answers, it is sufficient that a person only
true belief to be skewed in her favor, when compared to someone that is only interested
in hard questions. (This issue will be discussed in more detail below.) As for intensity of
interest, just like a person’s magnitude of interest may depend on the her financial or
mortal stake in the question, so, too, for her having any interest in the question.
Consequently, it does not seem that Goldman’s objections serve to favor giving degrees
of interest a modest rather than a pervasive role—which is, I take it, exactly Fallis’ point.
Where does this leave the present account? Unlike Goldman, I have no quarrel
with Fallis’ account per se. However, within the context of the present framework,
weighting the significance of answering agenda items by the degree of interest in the
unnecessary feature. The reason is that we do not imagine the typical research agenda as
one that contains both (what tends to be considered) paradigmatically pressing concerns,
such as those pertaining to the variety of projects that concern the scientific and political
127
community, and questions about when different TV shows come on TV. More to the
point, we are imagining that the span of degrees of interest that we have for the different
items on a particular agenda is far more narrow than in the kind of scenario Fallis
imagines, for the simple reason that what ends up on the research agenda are the
questions we deem most interesting out of all the questions that we may choose to pursue.
Consequently, it is not that degree of interest plays no role in the present account. It does,
but rather than playing a role by way of weighting, it plays a role in that agenda items
however, should not be taken to put any substantial restrictions on what inquirers may
deem most worthy of pursuits. So, let us turn to the question of what epistemic judgments
we can make with respect to what items should figure on agents’ agendas. For one thing,
we can often provide people with epistemic reasons to pursue at least some challenging
questions, if doing so would serve to sharpen their cognitive tools and, thereby, enable
them to answer whatever questions already figure on their agenda with a greater
efficiency. For another, we can often also make a case for engaging with specific
questions (be they challenging or not), since doing so may enable us to address already
existing agenda items in more productive ways. By the same token, failing to ask certain
new questions may have (comparatively) detrimental effects on the extent to which the
inquirer will be able to answers questions already on her current agenda. In such cases,
128
the inquirer has straightforwardly epistemic reasons for expanding or otherwise revising
parts her agenda, in so far as doing so will make her epistemically better off with respect
But what normative, epistemic judgments (if any) can we make beyond this? We
may use this question to put pressure on the point made above in relation to Fallis’
account, where it was suggested that agendas typically do not involve both questions
about what most people would consider paradigmatically pressing concerns and fairly
banal questions about TV shows. That this is so may be granted by Fallis, but the
question remains: What if such a span of topics actually happened to be considered most
illustration, consider a subject who can choose between utilizing two practices, P1 and P2.
P1 would enable her to answer a very small number of questions that figure on her agenda
about the causes, treatment, and prevention of cancer. P2, on the other hand, would
enable her to answer a great many questions, also figuring on her agenda, about a series
of utterly banal matters, primarily pertaining to the plots of a couple of soap operas that
she follows.11 Let us also assume that there is no overlap in the questions answered by the
two processes, and that the questions answered by P2 are so banal that no pursuit of
challenging questions would make any difference to her ability to answer them. If so, the
account defended here implies that P2 is epistemically better than P1 for the subject.
Does this amount to a reductio of the present account? I do not think that it does.
There are a number of ways in which the subject in question would be better off by
opting for P1. From a moral perspective, the questions answered by P1 have a potential to
11
Feldman (2001) invokes a similar scenario in a critique of Goldman (1999).
129
help people suffering from serious and often terminal diseases. From the perspective of
personal well-being, it might be that, if the subject is anything like most of us, engaging
with the questions addressed by P1 would provide her with a deeper sense of purpose and
intellectual stimulation than engaging with the questions addressed by P2 does. And so
specialized form of evaluation, namely the kind of evaluation that—if the observations
made above are on the right track—pertains to the generation of high ratios and numbers
of beliefs that answer whatever questions the relevant inquirers happen to be posing. As
such, it is to be expected that the present account will not capture aspects relevant to
other forms of evaluation, such as those just mentioned. Consequently, despite the fact
that opting for P2 makes the subject inferior in all aforementioned respects, she is not,
thereby, epistemically worse off, and suggesting that she is would simply amount to
evaluation of harmful pursuits. By way of illustration, consider a scenario exactly like the
one above, the only difference being that the questions answered by P2 pertain to how to
bring about the maximum amount of gratuitous pain and suffering in the maximal amount
of people. For reasons perfectly analogous to those just discussed, the present account
would imply that the subject is better off by opting for P2 rather than for P1. Is this a
this would not follow. Recently, Michael Bishop and J. D. Trout (2005) have suggested
that “the significance of a problem for S is a function of the weight of the objective
reasons S has for devoting resources to solving that problem” (p. 95). As for the specific
130
nature of such objective reasons, they make clear that their “general account of epistemic
(p. 99). Bishop and Trout do not say explicitly whose well-being is relevant to whose
objective reasons. However, most of their comments—such as that the “priorities of the
excellent reasoner (and more generally, of the wise person) are set so that they may serve
as a means to human flourishing” (p. 101)—suggest that the objective weight of S’s
betterness would imply that the subject would be epistemically better off by opting for P1
rather than for P2. However, there are two problems with forging such a strong
connection between significance and well-being. First, what is the normative force of this
connection? Is it that we ought to only engage in endeavors that are highly conducive to
general well-being? If this is the idea, the account seems to not only promote an
extremely skewed division of cognitive labor, but also render the majority of what makes
more lax construal of conduciveness would be problematic, since there are substantial
sets of questions and problems that lack any connection to the promotion of well-being.
For example, is it always possible to find, somewhere in the infinity of integers, a pro-
gression of any length of equally spaced prime numbers? Are there three, four or eleven
dimensions to our universe? It is not clear that either of these questions may be related to
131
matters of human-well being, or that this ought to imply that the corresponding beliefs
That being said, it might be possible to rework Bishop and Trout’s account in a
way so that the normative force does not flow from an injunction to maximize well-being,
but from a desire to ensure that inquiry is not detrimental to well-being. Still, a
fundamental point remains, which brings us to the second problem: While there is,
clearly, something to be said for the fact that the subject should not opt for P2, it is not
obvious that she should be considered epistemically worse off by doing so. As noted
beliefs the contents of which answer whatever questions happen to figure on the
betterness not captured by the present framework, i.e., non-epistemic aspects. However,
rather than indicating a flaw in the present account, the fact that it does not account for
such aspects simply suggests that it does not account for more than it should, qua an
12
Could the account be saved by appeal to the increase in well-being that may be
experienced by the researchers engaged in these ventures (ceteris paribus)? This would
imply that, if everyone engaging in foundational issues in mathematics, natural science,
and metaphysics (among other areas) ceased to experience any degree of well-being in
their pursuits, and no one else started doing so for them, the corresponding beliefs would
cease to be significant—and for that very reason. I suspect that this would give us a
notion of significance very different from what Bishop and Trout are looking for.
132
4.3. Conclusion
The previous two chapters argued that true belief is the only thing of non-instrumental
epistemic value. However, it does not follow from true belief being the only good of non-
instrumental epistemic value that all true beliefs are valuable thus. More specifically, the
present chapter argued that the epistemic value of a practice is a function of the extent to
which it yields beliefs that answer questions posed by relevant sets of inquirers. As such,
the account tells us something about what methods or practices inquirers should utilize, in
so far as they want answers to their questions. The remainder of the chapter was primarily
concerned with tracing the limits of this ‘should,’ and it was suggested that there are very
real limits to the extent to which we can make epistemic judgments about what questions
inquirers should pose, as opposed to about what practices to opt for, given a set of
questions. However, rather than indicating a flaw in the account, this simply suggests that
133
CHAPTER 5
When conducting inquiry we do a variety of things, such as gather information, mull over
our data, and choose among different methods of investigation—all for the purpose of
attaining our epistemic goal. In so doing, we are expressing our epistemic agency, as was
suggested in chapter 1. Chapters 2 and 3 provided an account of the relevant goal, i.e., the
goal of believing truly, and chapter 4 developed a theory about what it is for some
practices to be epistemically better than others with respect to that goal, in terms of how
good of a job they do in generating beliefs that answer questions posed by the relevant
inquirers. The purpose of the present chapter is to illustrate how we may use the
resulting notion of epistemic agency to say something constructive about how the ways in
which we actually express our agency may be brought in line with how we should
To this end, consider the fact that it, intuitively, might seem that, the greater our
freedom to express our epistemic agency, the better. At the very least, it seems prima
facie plausible that gathering more information, spending more time mulling over our
data, or choosing from a wider selection of methods cannot be a bad thing from the point
of view of forming true belief with respect to whatever matters happen to be under
investigation. However, the present chapter argues that, when it comes to our freedom to
134
express such agency, more is not always better. For example, it will be argued that we
often are better off by gathering only a very limited amount of information, having our
selection of methods be greatly restricted, and spending our time less on reflecting than
on simply reading off a market price or the output of a simple algorithm. In fact, we are
in many situations better off from the point of view of attaining true belief by having our
The case for this claim starts out with two psychological observations. First, as
noted already above, it is well known that we suffer from a variety of cognitive biases
accord with principles that (given certain normative assumptions) may be gleaned from
logic, probability theory, statistics, and related disciplines. Understood thus, certain
biases may very well be adaptive, and, as such, yield accurate judgments in many
situations, despite being arrived at by way of heuristics that fail to accord with
aforementioned principles.2 In light of this, a more useful way to understand what it is for
it due to a failure to form belief in accordance with principles gleaned from logic,
that faced our evolutionary ancestors and the cognitive challenges that face us today.
strategies, respectively—has to take into account another fact touched upon above,
1
See Gilovich et al. (2002).
2
See, e.g., Gigerenzer et al. (1999).
135
namely that each and every one of us tends to underestimate the extent to which we, as
opposed to everyone else, actually are prone to such biases.3 This is relevant since there
are (at least) two ways in which an attempt at de-biasing may fail. On the one hand, it
may fail to improve our reliability (within the relevant domain), even if the methods
prescribed are utilized properly. On the other hand, the methods prescribed may fail to be
utilized at all. Let us refer to the latter possibility as involving problems of defection.
predictive modeling in connection with the so-called “broken leg problem.”4 The
movie, but that should be disregarded upon finding out that the person in question has a
fractured femur. There is, certainly, something to be said for being sensitive to
information not taken into account by whatever models one happens to be relying on in
will be reliable in all domains. The problem is just that, in a wide range of domains where
financial decision making—people tend to see far more broken legs than there really are,
and, thereby, end up defecting from reliable models far more often than they should, from
Evidence suggests that that major culprit behind defection is that we are
3
See Pronin et al. (2002).
4
See Meehl (1954).
5
See Dawes et al. (2002).
136
Whitecotton (1996) found a correlation between confidence ratings and defection from
financial analysts, as did Arkes et al. (1986) in a similar study. The suspicion that this
Sieck and Arkes (2005). Several studies have suggested that overconfidence is a very
degree, however, are rigorous regiments of feedback.8 Building upon this fact, Sieck and
Arkes found that such feedback not only lowered people’s overconfidence in their
judgments in so far as they did not rely on the statistical models offered, but also led to
compared to a control group. This provides us with reason to believe that overconfidence
is one (albeit not necessarily the only) cause of many cases of defection.
This has implications for how we should go about the business of de-biasing.
expect that a great majority of us will be prone to defection. Moreover, since defection is
invoked in attempts at de-biasing, we can also expect that a great majority of us will be
Granted, it might be suggested that the empirical results in question suggests one way to
come to terms with problem of defection, namely by focusing our attention more directly
6
See Arkes et al. (1986).
7
See Lord et al. (1984).
8
See Arkes et al. (1987).
137
on strategies that temper people’s confidence in their own accuracy. However, the
schedule required to come to terms with it, renders the practical prospects of mitigating
For this reason, a different strategy will be pursued presently. More specifically,
since the above results suggest that a great majority of us will be prone to defection, no
matter the particular methods involved, the most promising approach to de-biasing will
be one that simply does not provide us with the option of not using the methods in
question. When the option of not using the relevant methods is removed thus, i.e., when
the inquirers, in effect, are left with no option but to utilize the methods in question, we
are mandating compliance with those methods. More specifically, I submit that the
aforementioned research on our dual tendency for bias and overconfidence makes
(C) For every judgment domain D, such that we (a) care about accuracy in
judgment within D, and (b) have methods available that (if used properly)
have been shown to make those making judgments within D better off from
practices, we have pro tanto reason for mandating compliance with the
A couple of comments are in order. First, the question of what it is for a method to make
someone better off from an epistemic point of view will be postponed until the next
138
section, although the discussions in the previous chapter should provide substantial hints
as for how this locution will be spelled out. Second, no necessary and sufficient
conditions will be given for what constitutes a judgment domain. Instead, subsequent
discussions will rely on paradigmatic examples, such as political polling and medical
diagnosis and prognosis. While working with paradigmatic examples rather than clear-cut
definitions, clearly, will leave room for some degree of ambiguity, that will present no
problem presently, as long as it can be agreed that the domains in question contain many
examples of judgment tasks that we typically want to get right, no matter the particular
ways in which the domains may be further specified. The presence of such tasks is
crucial—and, moreover, provides the motivation for including (a) in (C)—since it is not
clear that the mere availability of epistemically beneficial methods gives us any reason to
implement them, unless we care about accuracy within the domain(s) in question. But
when we do care thus, and relying on the methods in question have been shown to make
us better off from an epistemic point of view as compared to the methods involved in
prevailing practices—as per (b) in (C)—we have pro tanto reasons to mandate
compliance.
The remainder of the chapter is concerned with spelling out the implications of
(C). §5.2 argues that the relevant mandate is epistemically paternalistic, and briefly
§5.3 shows that the precedents in question do not imply that a commitment to the relevant
kind of paternalism is trivial, by discussing two domains that satisfy (C) but where the
controversial. §5.4 addresses the worry that, if we restrict ourselves to pro tanto
139
reasons—i.e., genuine but not necessarily decisive reasons, since the overall balance of
reasons may direct us to act differently—it might turn out that we have non-epistemic
reason not to impose paternalistic constraints on agency, even in cases where the
practices in question are epistemically beneficial. In response to this, it is argued that the
reasons involved in the cases considered actually amount to reasons all things considered.
The paper concludes in §5.5 that there, hence, are several cases in which we have not
only pro tanto but all things considered reasons for having our epistemic agency be
The idea that constraints on our agency can make us better off is not unique to the present
investigation. For example, Jon Elster (2000) mounts a persuasive case for agents often
certain future actions, either directly or by severely restricting the number and kinds of
options that will be available to them at a future time. However, the mandate in (C)
should not be understood in terms of such self-binding. If it were only for the fact that we
suffered from cognitive bias, self-binding might have provided a viable option for de-
biasing. However, given our tendency to also underestimate the extent to which we are at
all prone to bias, there is simply no reason to believe that we—as in: each and every one
of us—will see any reason to bind ourselves to the methods in question (and even if we
did, we would subsequently consider ourselves having ample reason to break that
140
short, due to our dual tendencies for bias and overconfidence, we cannot rely on
ourselves for doing what is best for us, from an epistemic point of view.9
For this reason, and as indicated above, a different and largely neglected approach
the few previous discussions of such practices is that of Goldman (1992b).10 Goldman
suggests that certain forms of information control practiced in society are motivated with
reference to how they protect us from our cognitive failings, but he neither discusses the
important role our tendencies for overconfidence play in motivating such protection, nor
dwells on the issue of defining the relevant kind of epistemic paternalism. Since we
discussed the former issue in §5.1, let us consider the latter. Judging by the vast literature
involves an interference with the liberty of another without her consent but for her own
paternalistic as follows:
(i) constrains inquirers’ freedom to conduct inquiry in whatever way they see
fit;
9
Elster (2000, ch. 2) does discuss other-binding, but only in terms of cases where the
binding in question is not for the benefit of those bound, as in the kind of de-biasing that
concerns us here, but simply for the protection of the binder(s).
10
However, see Sunstein and Thaler (2008) for a recent defense of what they refer to as
libertarian paternalism, invoked as a tool for ridding ourselves of a variety of behaviors
that are systematically detrimental to our well-being. See also Trout (2009 and 2005),
who will be discussed further below.
11
See Young (2008) and Dworkin (2002) for two overviews of relevant discussions.
141
(iii) is prescribed for the purpose of making those constrained better off from an
A couple of comments are at place. (i) is meant to capture the interference of paternalistic
practices. I will postpone further discussion of this aspect until we are considering real-
world cases below. (ii) is meant to capture the arrogance, if you will, of paternalistic
practices. Note, however, that this condition does not require acting against the consent
of those constrained. For example, the satisfaction of (ii) is compatible with the inquirer
in question appreciating the merits of the relevant methods and happily utilizing them.
What is crucial as far as (ii) is concerned is not that the inquirer is forced to do something
that she does not want to do, but simply that no effort has been made to seek her consent
on the issue.12
Condition (iii) is meant to capture what makes the relevant form of paternalism
epistemic.13 The kind of improvement relevant here can be defined in terms of the notion
think of what it is for someone to be made better off in the relevant sense in terms of how
compliance with methods that make her more reliable, without making her worse off in
some other epistemically relevant respect, e.g., with respect to question-answering power.
12
This is in line with Dworkin (2002).
13
It is compatible with a practice being epistemically paternalistic that it is motivated by
non-epistemic in addition to epistemic considerations.
142
previous chapter. To see why, consider two practices, P and P+, where the latter is a
will better than P with respect to reliability, and equally good or better with respect to
previous chapter.14
reliability ratios not in terms of true belief per se, but in terms of significant true belief,
to questions on the relevant agent’s research agenda. In light of this, we will need to
make two simplifying assumptions. First, since significance is a function of the relevant
agents’ research agenda(s), we will need to assume that those involved in the compared
practices are posing the same questions, at least as far as the relevant practices are
concerned. Second, we also need to assume that all agents involved function normally, in
that they would be able to identify sufficiently informative answers as such when they
grasp them. To make matters tractable, let us include these factors under a ceteris paribus
clause, and say that what it is for those constrained to be made better off from an
epistemic point of view is for the relevant paternalistic practice to yield a pareto
If we understand epistemic paternalism along the lines of (P), there does seem to
14
The reader may return to the table in §4.1.4 to confirm that this is so.
15
Why not drop the pareto qualification and simply talk about an improvement with
respect to reliability, ceteris paribus? Because that would not count as improvements
cases in which a practice makes the relevant agents better off with respect to reliability
and power. Such improvements would constitute pareto improvements but not ceteris
paribus improvements with respect reliability.
143
Goldman (1992b) discusses four such practices, pertaining to (a) the control of legal
curriculum selection in education, (c) the Federal Trade Commission’s actions against
false or deceptive advertisement, and (c) deliberate attempts within the news media to
simplify matters that are to be presented to the public. In the interest of adding to the
literature rather than simply repeating what has already been said, I will not dwell on
these practices. It suffices to note that they all serve to constrain peoples’ freedom to
conduct inquiry in whatever way they see fit by way of restrictions on information
access, without seeking their consent, for the purpose of making them better off
epistemically by protecting them from their own ignorance or bias in contexts where we
care about accuracy. As such, the practices in question are epistemically paternalistic, on
Any attempt to elaborate on the need for epistemic paternalism needs to answer to
a series of worries, three of which will be considered presently. Consider, first, the point
that the motivation for setting up epistemically paternalistic practices, as outlined above,
is a set of statistical facts about our cognitive tendencies. As such, there are likely to be
individual exceptions, in the sense that there will be some people who do not exhibit the
tendencies in question, even if the relevant statistics suggest that they will constitute a
minority. In light of this, the worry goes, is it really defensible to be paternalistic not only
with respect to the majority that is likely to benefit epistemically, but also with respect to
the few subjects who might either not be made better off, or that in some rare instances
144
perhaps even will be made worse off from an epistemic point of view for being imposed
upon thus?16
Two lines of response are available here. On the first one, we press the point that
the minorities are just that, i.e., minorities, and that the few that are not made better off or
that are made worse off, most likely, constitute statistical outliers. However, the problem
with this line of reasoning is that it seems to presuppose that, unless the minority is made
up of outliers, the relevant paternalistic practices would not be defensible. That seems to
be granting too much, which brings us to the second line of response: In mandating
compliance, the goal is not to make each and every one of those constrained better off; it
is simply to bring about a positive and hopefully significant epistemic net effect in the
relevant population of inquirers. Granted, the smaller the proportion of subjects that do
not exhibit the dual tendency of bias and overconfidence, the greater the net effect. But it
that those who do exhibit the relevant tendencies are in a majority and we, consequently,
can expect there to be such a net effect, irrespective of whether those who do not exhibit
different worry lurking in the background, pertaining less to the concern for maximizing
net epistemic effects among populations of inquirers, and more to a regard for the
integrity of the individual inquirers. This brings us to the second worry, according to
16
Thanks to Adrian Staub for raising this question.
145
Larry Laudan’s (2006) treatment of evidence control in law. Laudan is explicitly
concerned with the epistemic aspects of this practice. Moreover, he describes it as being
paternalistic, and clearly intends the term as a pejorative. However, when we turn to his
case against the practice in question, we see that Laudan’s complaint is that restricting
jurors’ access to certain kinds of evidence (such as character evidence) “is not a
promising recipe for finding out the truth” (p. 25). That is, even if Laudan is right in
claiming that we have reason to be skeptical about the epistemic merits of prevailing
systems of evidence control—and the “if” is important, since Laudan, unfortunately, pays
no attention to the body of empirical literature concerned with how jurors process
character evidence (e.g., Hunt and Budesheim 2004; Lupfer et al. 2000)—his complaint
is not that the practice should be given up because it is paternalistic but because it does
important task. But it is not one that will be undertaken here, and for the reason just
outlined: an argument demonstrating that a particular practice is not fulfilling its intended
implementing a different practice (paternalistic or not). For this reason, §5.4 will return to
a more promising way to spell out aforementioned worry, namely in terms of us having
where the practices in question are epistemically beneficial. Before considering that
possibility, however, the next section will consider a third worry. The worry in question
pulls in a completely different direction from the ones just considered, which suggested
17
See also Goldman (1999), who raises concerns that are very similar to Laudan’s.
146
that a commitment to epistemic paternalism is, in a sense, too controversial simply in
virtue of being paternalistic. The third and final worry is that the fact that we already
practices.
ingrained in the ways in which we set up epistemic practices for any attempt to argue that
is the burden of this section to argue that a commitment to epistemic paternalism is not
trivial in this sense. To make this point, it will be argued that a commitment to (C)
provides pro tanto reason for practicing epistemic paternalism on a wider scale than we
are currently doing. This point will be argued with reference to two domains clearly
satisfying (C), but where the relevant mandates are still to be imposed and the relevant
147
5.3.1. Prediction Models in Diagnosis and Prognosis
“institutional assistance,” as he calls them, for coming to terms with our sometimes quite
biased ways. The kinds of assistances he considers include taking advantage of our
rather than losses in order to encourage preventive medical testing, changing driving
behavior by way of chevrons, and allowing employees to direct a portion of their future
salary increases toward retirement savings and thereby using our tendencies for inertia
Interestingly, however, Trout goes out of his way to argue that, since the measures
“assist the person in effectuating their long-term goals or plans, there is no relevant
interference, and so [such] regulation is not paternalistic” (p. 409).18 There is certainly
something to be said for the practices not amounting to paternalism, but not because they
promote our long-terms goals. After all, many paradigmatic instances of paternalistic
motorcycle—are motivated exactly on the basis that they promote our long-term goals.
What makes the practices Trout considers non-paternalistic is rather that no one is, in any
For present purposes, however, the kinds of assistance not considered by Trout
are more relevant than the ones he does consider. In particular, Trout does not discuss a
kind of assistance that he has discussed at length elsewhere (with Michael Bishop in their
2005), and where an illustrative and straightforwardly paternalistic case can be made. The
18
The same approach is taken by Trout more recently in his (2009, p. 210).
148
practice in question is that of using prediction models as an alternative to relying on the
judgments resulting from the unaided reflections of clinicians in medical diagnosis and
prognosis. The last fifty years of empirical research on predictive modeling has not only
demonstrated the superiority of the former over the latter, but also provided ample
evidence of inquirers being very reluctant to comply.19 Again, this has received some
attention within recent epistemological literature, primarily due to Bishop and Trout’s
discussion. However, what has not been acknowledged is that the literature in question
also provides pro tanto reason for mandating the use of such models in medical diagnosis
The first thing to note here is that we typically care about accuracy in medical
diagnosis and prognosis, particularly given the potential human costs of inaccurate
judgment within these areas. As such, the relevant domains satisfy (C) (a). In light of
this, it should be considered good news that aforementioned models enable us to increase
reliance on unaided clinical judgments. Moreover, there is no reason to believe that such
a mandate would, in turn, decrease our question-answering power, i.e., that it would
confuse power with what the previous chapter referred to as robustness (see §4.1.3).
Granted, it is likely that unaided clinical judgment constitutes a more robust method than
does reliance on prediction models, since there are many questions for which prediction
19
See Dawes et al. (2002).
20
Despite resisting the term ‘paternalism’ in his (2005) and (2009), Trout (in
correspondence) suggests that there is an implicit case for paternalism in Bishop and
Trout (2005). If so, the following can be seen as an attempt to spell out the relevant case
explicitly.
149
models are yet to be developed and, hence, many questions for which the former would
outperform the latter. But power, like epistemic betterness, is a property defined for a
specific set of questions, i.e., an agenda. In other words, when comparing the power of
different methods, we need to hold fixed the questions at issue, such as the questions
available. Given such a set of questions, the claim is that the relevant prediction model
will not yield less true belief than do the corresponding unaided clinical judgment
models (whenever available) will lead to a pareto improvement in reliability for the
inquirers involved, ceteris paribus, and that the relevant domains, hence, satisfy (C) (b).
It might be objected that the answers provided by way of prediction models will
not be as informative as those yielded by unaided clinical reflection. Two things need to
be noted here. First, even if a case could be made to the effect that unaided clinical
judgments generally are more informative than the outputs of prediction models, it is
sufficient for the two methods to be on a par on this score that they are both sufficiently
informative to answer the relevant questions, whether or not one is more informative than
the other. Second, it is questionable that a case can be to the effect that unaided clinical
judgments generally are more informative than the outputs of prediction models. It
certainly cannot be ruled out that unaided clinical reflection often will yield judgments
containing more information than what can be gleaned from prediction models, which
typically yield a simple binary or numerical output. However, even if that is so, the fact
that the latter, nevertheless, tend to outperform the former suggests that whatever
150
is not of a kind that increases accuracy. And when it comes to diagnosis and prognosis, it
Keeping these points in mind, we see that the judgment domains of medical
diagnosis and prognosis, clearly, fall within the scope of (C), which suggests that we
have pro tanto reason for mandating compliance with the models in question. Moreover,
one thing, the practice would, as already noted, be motivated with reference to how
relying on said models makes inquirers epistemically better off relative to prevailing
practices (i.e., reliance on unaided clinical judgment). Consequently, the practice would
satisfy (P) (iii). Furthermore, a practice that mandated the use of predictive models (when
available) would put real restrictions on clinicians’ ability to pursue diagnoses and
prognoses in whatever manner they happen to see fit. Consequently, the practice would
satisfy (P) (i). As noted above, this is not to rule out the possibility that the relevant
inquirers may happily utilize the models, perhaps on account of appreciating their merits.
However, considering the well-documented prevalence of defection, and the fact that
inquirers have been shown to disapprove (even while lacking epistemic reason for doing
so), the practice of implementing the mandate can be motivated without any concern for
prediction models that have been shown to make us epistemically better off, as compared
epistemically paternalistic, in virtue of not only being motivated with reference to how it
151
would make clinician’s epistemically better off but also constraining their freedom to
conduct inquiry in whatever way they see fit, without seeking their consent in so doing.
Given that such a mandate is yet to be instituted, a commitment to (C), hence, provides
pro tanto reason to practice epistemic paternalism on a wider scale than we are currently
doing.
The second domain in which we have pro tanto reason to implement paternalistic
practices can be illustrated with reference to the fact that, in any reasonably complex
society or organization, it will often be the case that only a minority of the people
involved will be informed on any given issue. In those domains where we care about
accuracy, how are we to mine such informed minorities for information? One intuitively
understood as the process of a group of people exchanging reasons for and against a (set
of) conclusion(s) for the purpose of reaching a social verdict on the issue in question.
Does such a process do a good job of eliciting information from informed minorities?
in contexts of social deliberation. There are two possibilities. First, assume that the
members of the informed minority do not disclose their information. After all, there are
many circumstances under which people refrain from disclosing what they know (or what
they take themselves to know), either in light of the informational pressure coming out of
whatever happens to be the majority position (and the assumption on part of the minority
that they, not the majority, are probably mistaken), or the social pressure associated with
152
the risk of social sanctions against dissenters.21 In other words, in the event that there is a
diversity of opinions, and the informed members find themselves in a minority, there is a
real risk that the information they have in their possession will not even be submitted for
deliberation.
Second, assume that the members of the informed minority do disclose their
group? Given that the informed members make up a minority, the impact is likely not to
be particularly great, due to what is typically referred to as the common knowledge effect.
(Since the effect in question applies to information submitted for deliberation in general,
and not just to information believed in a manner that amounts to knowledge, a more
appropriate designation might have been “the common information effect”.) More
specifically, social psychologists Daniel Gigone and Reid Hastie sum up the relevant
research in terms of how “[t]he influence of a particular item of information [on the
judgment of a group] is directly and positively related to the number of group members
who have knowledge of that item before the group discussion and judgment” (Gigone
particular piece of information to the table. This would be great news, were there a robust
correlation between the information had by the majority and the truth. While such a
correlation might hold with respect to certain easy questions that have demonstrable
answers, it clearly does not hold with respect to a great many of the questions that we
21
See Sunstein (2006) for a discussion of the relevant evidence.
153
typically deliberate over, such as questions about politics, public policy, public health,
scientific research, and so on. Consequently, it does not seem that social deliberation
provides a particularly promising method for eliciting and aggregating dispersed pieces
questions that we care about answering. At best, it seems a prima facie promising method
for aggregating information that is already widely shared—which is not the kind of role
This gives us reason to look elsewhere for a more promising method for eliciting
information from informed minorities. One strategy that has received a lot of attention
designed and run for the primary purpose of (a) mining and aggregating information
scattered among traders, and subsequently (b) using this information in the form of
market values to make predictions about future events. As it turns out, the market prices
of such markets provide surprisingly accurate information about the events bet on.22
Moreover, there is evidence to the effect that accuracy of the market prices that
arise in prediction market are to a great extent due to small subsets of traders, typically
referred to as marginal traders.23 Beyond investing more money in the markets and
spending more time trading than the average trader, marginal traders also earn
significantly higher returns. While it might be thought that this is a mere artifact of
marginal traders simply investing more money than non-marginal ones, further
considerations suggest that the most plausible interpretation of these returns is that the
22
See Bragues (2009), Wolfers and Zitzewitz (2006), and Berg et al. (2003) on political
prediction markets, Pennock et al. (2001) on commercial forecasting, Chen and Plott
(2002) on sales forecasting, and Servan-Schreiber et al. (2004) on sports forecasting.
23
See Forsythe et al. (1999).
154
former simply are more informed and, consequently, place better bets than the latter.
After all, by virtue of their high trading frequency and higher than average investments,
marginal traders have a disproportionally high influence on the price signal. Given that
the price signals of prediction markets tend to amount to good predictions, this suggests
that the accuracy of the predictions of such markets are, to a great extent, due exactly to
the informed investments of marginal traders. In fact, there is further and more direct
evidence for this claim. Separating out the subset of marginal traders that are particularly
active in setting bid and ask prices, as compared to those traders (marginal or not) who
mostly accept others’ prices, Oliven and Rietz (2004) found that the average error rate for
the latter on the 1992 vote share market of the Iowa Electronic Markets—one of the
oldest and most prominent electronic prediction markets—was almost six times that of
The role played by such marginal traders in prediction markets has implications
for how to think about the respective merits of social deliberation and prediction markets.
More specifically, above discussion suggests that prediction markets do a good job of
mining information exactly under the conditions where social deliberation does not, i.e.,
in contexts of informed minorities. In fact, the evidence just reviewed gives us pro tanto
reason to institute a paternalistic mandate for using information gleaned from prediction
markets rather than that coming out of social deliberation, in cases where informed
minorities are present. To see why, consider, first, the fact that many of the issues that we
care to deliberate about socially, including issues pertaining to governmental policy and
organizational strategy, are ones where we care about accuracy. Consequently, the
domains in question satisfy (C) (a). Next, consider the relative epistemic merits of relying
155
on prediction markets as opposed to on social deliberation. More specifically, consider
(1) Forming beliefs on the basis of the judgments of deliberating groups; and
(2) forming beliefs on the basis of the price signals of prediction markets.
Given what we know about the workings of social deliberation and prediction markets,
respectively, we have good reason to believe that, if informed minorities are present,
someone forming belief in the manner described in 2 will form a higher ratio of true
belief than someone forming belief in the manner described in 1 (ceteris paribus).
Furthermore, in analogy with what was argued in relation to the power of prediction
models above (and keeping in mind the distinction between power and robustness), there
is no reason to believe that basing ones beliefs on the price signals of prediction markets,
Consider, also, the issue of whether the answers gleaned from prediction markets
are sufficiently informative. While the social verdicts of deliberating groups may,
certainly, provide more information than what can be gleaned from the price signals of a
prediction market, the fact that the someone relying on the latter as opposed to on the
significantly better job than do deliberating groups in harnessing the right information
and, in turn, making for accurate answers. As such, the relevant worry about
it is that socially deliberating groups might not satisfy a necessary condition on any
156
sufficiently informative answer, as defined in the previous chapter, i.e., that the judgment
In other words, there is good reason to believe that relying on prediction markets
(whenever available) will lead to a pareto improvement with respect to reliability for the
inquirers involved, ceteris paribus, and that the relevant domains, hence, satisfy (C) (b).
As such, the many domains typically associated with social deliberation fall within the
scope of (C), suggesting that we have pro tanto reason for mandating reliance on the
outputs of relevant prediction markets, whenever available. More than that, a practice
prediction markets. As such, it would satisfy (P) (iii). However, it should be stressed that
the practice of enforcing the mandate would not involve a ban on social deliberation.
Instead, it would involve a mandate on those making judgments within the relevant
domains to use information gleaned from prediction markets (when such markets are
available) rather than information produced by way of social deliberation. Since this
would put restrictions on the freedom of those making judgments to use whatever kind of
information they deem relevant, the practice would satisfy (P) (i). Moreover, since there
is far from a guarantee that those restricted thus would welcome the restriction, defection
is a real possibility, not the least given the risk that inquirers will exhibit overconfidence
in their assessments of whether they will be able to judge what kind of information is
most probative. As above, this is not to deny that some of those restricted may actually
welcome the restriction; it is simply to suggest that the practice can be motivated without
157
any concern for whether the inquirers themselves actually approve of its implementation.
deliberation satisfy (C), and we, consequently, have pro tanto reason to mandate reliance
relevant domains, whenever such markets are available. More than that, the practice of
mandating such reliance would be epistemically paternalistic, in virtue of not only being
motivated with reference to how it would make those making judgments within the
relevant domains better off, but also constrain their freedom to conduct inquiry in
whatever way they see fit, without seeking their prior consent. Given that such a mandate
is yet to be instituted on the scale considered presently, we thereby have yet another
example of how a commitment to (C) provides pro tanto reason to practice epistemic
The previous section argued that we have pro tanto reason for practicing epistemic
paternalism on a wider scale than we are currently doing, and illustrated this point with
reference to the use of prediction models in medical diagnosis and prognosis, and the
reliance on prediction markets as a tool for mining informed minorities for information.
The present section returns to a version of the worry discussed in §5.2, to the effect that
158
reasons not to impose paternalistic constraints on agency, even if such constraints turn
In order to address this worry, we need to say something about the conditions
under which pro tanto reasons amount to reasons all things considered. The following is
a sufficient condition:
there are no countervailing reasons, i.e., there are no reasons not to ϕ that
The final point to be argued in this chapter is that the reasons pertaining to the
paternalistic practices discussed in §5.3 amount to reasons all things considered, when the
relevant mandates are properly qualified. Let us consider the two cases in turn.
Opting for the output of a statistical model rather than relying on the judgment of
experienced clinicians might seem to amount to stripping the relevant patients of their
individuality. At least that is how it feels. But does that feeling give us an ethical reason
against mandating the use of prediction models? It is not clear that it does, considering
the ethical costs of relying on methods that consistently have been shown to be equally
reliable at best, and significantly less reliable at worst. In this respect, little has changed
159
No matter how much we would like to see this or that aspect of one or another of
the studies reviewed in this article changed, […] no matter how ethically
uncomfortable we may feel at ‘reducing people to mere numbers,’ the fact
remains that our clients are people who deserve to be treated in the best manner
possible. If that means—as it appears at present—that selection, diagnosis, and
prognosis should be based on nothing more than the addition of a few numbers
representing values on important attributes, so be it. To do otherwise is cheating
the people that we serve (Dawes 1979, p. 581).
In other words, it seems that ethical reasons might even speak for a strict reliance on
prediction models, given the potential ethical costs of relying on a method that has been
Another potential worry is that relying on prediction models will be more costly
and time-consuming than relying on unaided clinical judgments. However, the typical
prediction model tends to be developed exactly for the purpose of decreasing cost and
example, consider the model developed by Breiman et al. (1993) to classify potential
heart attack patients according to risk, in order to reduce the number of unnecessary
admittances of low risk patients to coronary care units. Beyond being more reliable than
both unaided clinicians and several complex statistical classification methods, the model
only requires the clinician to answer a maximum of three diagnostic, yes/no questions.
Stiell et al. (1992) as a tool for diagnosing ankle fractures for the purpose of reducing the
number of unnecessary x-rays. In using the rule, the clinician needs to answer a
Despite its simplicity, the rule has a very low rate of false negatives, yet allows for a
160
al. (2001) reports that, while 96% of emergency physicians in the United States are
familiar with the rule, 67% never use it, or only use it sometimes.
speaking for a strict reliance on prediction models, whenever available. This, of course, is
compatible with there being high costs associated with introducing (as opposed to using)
the models in question.24 This brings us to the third worry: There might be cases in which
introducing the model will exceed the benefits of using them. Needless to say, this
possibility cannot be ruled out a priori, even if the benefits of increased accuracy and
decreased cost and time used that result from opting for prediction models make it likely
that even a significant start-up cost can be offset over time. Still, it seems reasonable to
require that the mandate should not apply in cases where the costs of introducing the
models in question clearly exceed the benefits of using them. The relevant weighing of
costs and benefit will, most likely, have to be done on a case-by-case basis, in a manner
that is, hopefully, sufficiently sensitive to the variety of concerns that may be brought to
bear on the issues at hand to, at the very least, reveal cases in which even aggregate
prediction models as opposed to relying on unaided clinical judgments, unless the cost of
introducing the models in question clearly outweighs even the long-term benefits—
epistemic and otherwise—of doing so. Given this qualification, and in the absence of any
24
See Bishop and Trout (2005) for a good discussion.
161
further countervailing reasons, (S) implies that the pro tanto reason involved amounts to
Turning now to prediction markets, three concerns deserve mention. First, prediction
markets require a fairly demanding infrastructure, and there might be many situations
where constraints on cost and other available means (not the least with respect to
prediction market practically impossible. However, the mandate that concerns us here is
not one on setting up prediction markets, but rather on using the information coming out
of such markets, when available. The epistemic merits of using such information might
also give us pro tanto reason to set up more such markets. That, however, is a different
matter from the one that we have been concerned with here.
policies politically legitimate, particularly in so far as the policies in question involve the
use of force against those representing a minority opinion. In light of this, there might be
A couple of things need to be noted in response to this worry. The idea that
25
Thanks to Robert Talisse for raising this issue.
162
in which the justification of the terms and conditions of association proceeds through
public argument and reasoning among equal citizens,” to quote Joshua Cohen (1997, p.
72). The fact that the ideal is taken to apply to the justification of the terms and
conditions of association is important, since it suggests that the ideal is not meant to
apply to all instances of policy making, but only to those policies that settle fundamental
issues about what terms and conditions of democratic association would be just or fair.
On this interpretation, the deliberative ideal applies only to what John Rawls (1997) in
his account of public reason refers to as “constitutional essentials and matters of basic
justice” (p. 95), pertaining to issues such as “who has the right to vote, or what religions
are to be tolerated, or who is to be assured fair equality, or to hold property” (p. 94).
Needless to say, these are not the kinds of issues that we are imagining that the price
signals of prediction markets are to settle. Rather, prediction markets would enter at the
point where questions about constitutional essentials and matters of basic justice are
settled, and the relevant questions about governance are predictive questions about what
policies, as a matter of empirical fact, are likely to generate what goods, as defined by
That point aside, imagine that the ideal in fact does apply more generally, in that
it applies to any procedure invoked in arriving at policies that involve the use of force
against minorities. In this context, it is crucial to note that what we are dealing with here
is an ideal, that, as such, leaves open how we can best approximate this deliberative
and political behavior; it is not an immediate consequence of the deliberative ideal” (p.
163
85). Consequently, it cannot be ruled out that a proper realization of the deliberative ideal
might look very different from the ideal itself. To name but one respect in which this will
context in which “no force except that of the better argument is exercised” (p. 108). As
we have seen, actual social deliberation is very different from such ideal deliberation in
that several forces are exercised beyond that of the better argument, including the force
exerted by the sheer the number of proponents that a particular argument happens to
have, or the social or informational pressures that may suppress the arguments of
minorities from even being submitted for deliberation. As such, social deliberation is
under many circumstances simply not conducive to the inclusion of all participants’
intuitive ideal.26 In particular, and for reasons discussed above, the epistemic perspectives
of minorities are bound to lose out in contexts of social deliberation simply on account of
being minorities.
As we have seen, prediction markets do a much better job than social deliberation
in taking into account the reasons and perspectives provided by minorities, at least in so
far as they are informed on the relevant issues. Indeed, in contexts involving such
minorities, it seems that setting up a prediction market will actually provide a better
approximation of the deliberative ideal than social deliberation would do. This contention
might seem paradoxical, but should come as no surprise given (a) the idealized nature of
26
This is not to suggest that equality would be sufficient (as opposed to merely
necessary) for realizing the relevant ideal. If that were the case, a simple coin toss would
to the trick, as pointed out by Estlund (2008).
164
the intuition driving deliberative conceptions of democracy, and (b) the tendency for bias
and overconfidence that we are subject to as actual deliberators. Moreover, keeping this
in mind, it is not clear why the minority should feel any less compelled to accept
social deliberation, contrary to the worry raised above. In the event that the members of
the minority are uninformed, they will run the risk of being ignored irrespective of
(in the former case, by virtue of being uninformed; in the latter case, simply by virtue of
being members of a minority). More than that, if the minority happens to be informed, its
members might even have more reason to feel compelled thus in light of decisions taken
on the basis of markets rather than on deliberation, since they have a greater chance of
more decisions, as a result, will be based on the price signals of such markets, we can
expect attempts to influence those decisions through market price manipulations. How
prediction markets with the intention of boosting the perceived likelihood of their
candidate winning the relevant office. However, as pointed out by Rhode and Strumpf
(2009), there is little evidence that political prediction markets can be systematically
manipulated beyond short periods of time. By way of example, political betting markets
on Wall Street in the late 19th and early 20th century involved millions of dollars, and
165
speculations resulted in price change, but the prices returned to their pre-attack levels
within days.
themselves in the 2000 Iowa Electronic Markets’ presidential market led to large initial
price changes, but the prices reverted to their initial levels in a few hours. These are, of
course, exactly the results we should expect to get in a market where at least some of the
investors utilize accurate information for the purpose of profiting from the influx of
liquidity provided by the manipulators. That said, while available empirical evidence
indicates that manipulation may not be as urgent a problem as it might seem at first
glance, the possibility of such manipulation suggests that the mandate to rely on
strategic investments.
from prediction markets rather than information coming out of social deliberation, in
cases where we (a) have reason to believe that informed minorities are present, and (b)
lack any evidence for large-scale strategic investments in the relevant markets. Given this
qualification, and in the absence of any further countervailing reasons, (S) implies that
the pro tanto reason involved amounts to a reason all things considered.
166
5.5. Conclusion
When conducting inquiry, we gather information, mull over our data, choose among
different methods of investigation, and so on—all for the purpose of attaining true belief
relevant to the questions that we pose. In so doing, we are expressing our epistemic
agency. Above, it was argued that, when it comes to our freedom to express such agency,
more is not always better. These points were argued with reference to how our dual
tendency for bias and overconfidence gives us pro tanto reason for mandating
compliance with methods that have been shown to lead to pareto improvements in
epistemically paternalistic, and that we have not just pro tanto but all-things-considered
reason to practice such paternalism on a wider scale than we are currently doing. For
example, in many situations, we are better off by gathering only a very limited amount of
information, having our selection of methods be greatly restricted, and spending our time
less on reflecting than on simply reading off a market price or the output of a simple
prediction model. Consequently, when it comes to our freedom to express our epistemic
agency, more is not always better. In fact, less is often so much more.
167
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Arkes, H. R., Dawes, R. M., and Christensen, C., (1986), “Factors influencing the use of
a decision rule in a probabilistic task,” Organizational Behavior and Human
Decision Processes 37, pp. 93–110.
Arkes, H., Christensen, C., Lai, C., and Blumer, C., (1987), “Two Methods of Reducing
Overconfidence”, Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 39,
pp. 133–144.
Baehr, J., (2009), “Is There a Value Problem?” in A. Haddock, A. Millar, and D.
Pritchard (2009), pp. 42-59.
Belnap, N., and Steel, T., (1976), The Logic of Questions, New Haven: Yale University
Press.
Berg, J., Nelson, F., and Rietz, R., (2003), “Accuracy and Forecast Standard Error of
Prediction Markets,” manuscript, July 2003.
Bishop, M., (2000), “In Praise of Epistemic Irresponsibility: How Lazy and Ignorant Can
You Be?,” Synthese 122, pp. 179-208.
Bishop, M., and Trout, J. D., (2005), Epistemology and the Psychology of Human
Judgment, New York: Oxford University Press.
Bohman, J., and Rehg, W., (1997), Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and
Politics, Cambridge: The MIT Press.
Bradley, B., (2006), “Two Concepts of Intrinsic Value,” Ethical Theory and Moral
Practice 9, pp. 111-130.
Bragues, G., (2009), “Prediction Markets: The Practical and Normative Possibilities for
the Social Production of Knowledge,” Episteme 6 (2), pp. 91-106.
Breiman, L., Friedman, J. H., Olshen, R. A. and Stone, C. J., (1993), Classification and
Regression Trees, Boca Raton: Chapman & Hall.
168
Burnyeat, M. F., (1980), “Socrates and the Jury: Paradoxes in Plato’s Distinction
Between Knowledge and True Belief,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society
suppl. vol. 54, pp. 173-191.
Chang, R., (2002), “On the Possibility of Parity,” Ethics 112, pp. 659-688.
Chen, K., and Plott, C., (2002), “Information Aggregation Mechanisms: Concept, Design
and Implementation for a Sales Forecasting Problem,” CalTech Social Science
Working Paper No. 1131.
Chisholm, R. M., (1968), “Lewis’ Ethics of Belief,” in P. Schilpp, ed., The Philosophy of
C. I. Lewis, LaSalle: Open Court.
Chisholm, R. M., (1977), Theory of Knowledge, 2nd ed., Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.
Chisholm, R. M., (1991), “Firth and the Ethics of Belief,” Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research 51 (1), pp. 119-128.
Clifford, W. K., (1866), “The Ethics of Belief,” in L. Stephen and F. Pollock, ed.,
Lectures and Essays by the late William Kingdon Clifford, 2nd ed., London:
Macmillan and Co., pp. 339-363.
Cohen, J., (1997), “Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy,” in Bohman and Rehg
(1997), pp. 67-91.
Conee, E., and Feldman, R., (2008), “Evidence,” in Q. Smith, ed., Epistemology: New
Essays, New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 83-104.
David, M., (2001), “Truth as the Epistemic Goal”, in M. Steup, ed., Knowledge, Truth,
and Duty, New York: Oxford University Press.
David, M., (2005), “Truth as the Primary Epistemic Goal: A Working Hypothesis,” in M.
Steup and E. Sosa, (2005), pp. 296-312.
Dawes, R., (1979), “The Robust Beauty of Improper Linear Models in Decision
Making,” American Psychologist 34 (7), pp. 571-582.
Dawes, R., Faust, D., Meehl, P., (2002), “Clinical versus Actuarial Judgment,” in
Gilovich et al. (2002), pp. 716-729.
169
DePaul, M. R., (2009), “Ugly Analyses and Value,” in A. Haddock, A. Millar, and D.
Pritchard (2009), pp. 112-138.
Fallis, D., (2006), “Epistemic Value Theory and Social Epistemology,” Episteme 2 (3),
pp. 177-188.
Feldman, R., (1985), “Reliability and Justification,” the Monist 68, pp. 159-174.
Feldman, R., (1988), “Epistemic Obligations,” Philosophical Perspectives (2), pp. 235-
356.
Feldman, R., (2002), “Epistemological Duties,” in P. Moser, ed., The Oxford Handbook
of Epistemology, New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 361-384.
Field, H., (2001), Truth in the Absence of Fact, New York: Oxford University Press.
Fine, G., (2003), Plato on Knowledge and Forms: Selected Essays, New York: Oxford
University Press.
Fine, G., (2004), “Knowledge and True Belief in the Meno,” Oxford Studies in Ancient
Philosophy XXVII, pp. 41-81.
170
Fine, G., (2008), The Oxford Handbook of Plato, New York: Oxford University Press.
Forsythe, R., Rietz, T. A., and Ross, T. W., (1999), “Wishes, Expectations and Actions:
A Survey on Price Formation in Election Stock Markets,” Journal of Economic
Behavior and Organization 39, pp. 83-110.
Gigerenzer, G., Todd, P. M., and the ABC Research Group, eds., (1999), Simple
Heuristics that Make Us Smart, New York: Oxford University Press.
Gigone, D., and Hastie, R., (1993), “The Common Knowledge Effect: Information
Sharing and Group Judgment,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 65
(5), pp. 959-974.
Gilovich, T., Griffin, D., and Kahneman, D., (2002), Heuristics and Biases: The
Psychology of Intuitive Judgment, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Goldman, A., (1978), “Epistemics: The Regulative Theory of Cognition,” The Journal of
Philosophy 75 (10), pp. 509-523.
Goldman, A., (1992), Liaisons: Philosophy Meets the Cognitive and Social Sciences,
Cambridge: The MIT Press.
Goldman, A., (1992a), “Foundations of Social Epistemics,” in Goldman (1992), pp. 179-
208.
Goldman, A., (1999), Knowledge in a Social World, New York: Oxford University Press.
Goldman, A., and Olsson, E. J., (2009), “Reliabilism and the Value of Knowledge,” in A.
Haddock, A. Millar, and D. Pritchard (2009), pp. 19-41.
Graham, I. D., Stiell, I. G., Laupacis, A., McAuley, L., Howell, M., Clancy, M., Durieux,
P., Simon, N., Emparanza, J. I., Aginaga, J. R., O’Connor, A., and Wells, G.,
(2001), “Awareness and use of the Ottawa Ankle and Knee Rules in 5 countries:
Can Publication Alone be Enough to Change Practice?” Annals of Emergency
Medicine, 37(3), pp. 259–266.
171
Greco, J., (2009), “The Value Problem,” in A. Haddock, A. Millar, and D. Pritchard
(2009), pp. 313-321.
Haack, S., (2001), “’The Ethics of Belief’ Reconsidered,” in M. Steup, ed., Knowledge,
Truth, and Duty, New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 21-33.
Haddock, A., Millar, A., and Pritchard, D., eds., (2009), Epistemic Value, New York:
Oxford University Press.
Hunt, J. S., and Budesheim, T. L., (2004), “How Jurors Use and Misuse Character
Evidence,” Journal of Applied Psychology 89 (2), pp. 347-361.
James, W., (1907), “The Will to Believe,” in The Will to Believe and Other Essays in
Popular Philosophy, New York: Longmans Green and Co., pp. 1-31.
Jaworski, W., (2009), “The Logic of How-Questions,” Synthese 166, pp. 133-155.
Kitcher, P., (1992), “The Naturalists Return,” The Philosophical Review 101 (1), pp. 53-
114.
Kornblith, H., (1994), Naturalizing Epistemology, 2nd ed., Cambridge: The MIT Press.
Kornblith, H., (2002), Knowledge and Its Place in Nature, New York: Oxford University
Press.
172
Kvanvig, J., (2003), The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Latus, A., (2000), “Our Epistemic Goal,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 78 (1), pp.
28-39.
Laudan, L., (1977), Progress and Its Problems: Towards a Theory of Scientific Growth,
Berkeley: University of California Press.
Laudan, L., (2006), Truth, Error, and Criminal Law: An Essay in Legal Epistemology,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Locke, J., (1706/1996), “Of the Conduct of the Understanding,” in R. W. Grant and N.
Tarcov, eds., Some Thoughts Concerning Education and Of the Conduct of the
Understanding, Indianapolis: Hackett.
Lord, C. G., Preston, E., and Lepper, M. R., (1984), “Considering the Opposite: A
Corrective Strategy for Social Judgment,” Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology 47 (6), pp. 1231-1243.
Lupfer, M. B., Weeks, M, and Dupuis, S., (2000), “How pervasive is the negativity bias
in judgments based on character appraisal?” Personality and Social Psychology
Bulletin 26, pp. 1353–1366.
Lynch, M., (2004), True to Life: Why Truth Matters, Cambridge: The MIT Press.
Lynch, M., (2009a), “The Values of Truth and the Truth of Values,” in A. Haddock, A.
Millar, and D. Pritchard (2009), pp. 225-242.
Lynch, M., (2009b), “Truth, Value and Epistemic Expressivism,” Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research 79 (1), pp. 76-97.
Mill, J. S., (1861/2001), “Utilitarianism”; reprinted in G. Sher, ed., Utilitarianism and the
1868 Speech on Capital Punishment, 2nd ed., Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing
Company, 2001, pp. 1-64.
Moran, R., (2001), Authority and Estrangement, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
173
Oliven, K., and Rietz, T. A., (2004), “Suckers are Born but Markets are Made: Individual
Rationality, Arbitrage, and Market Efficiency on an Electronic Futures Market,”
Management Science 50 (3), pp. 336-351.
Olsson, E. J., (2005), “The Impossibility of Coherence,” Erkenntnis 63, pp. 387-412.
Olsson, E. J., (2007), “Reliabilism, Stability, and the Value of Knowledge,” American
Philosophical Quarterly 44 (4), pp. 343-355.
Pennock, D., Lawrence, S., Nielsen, F. Å., and Giles, C. L., (2001), “Extracting
Collective Probabilitistic Forecasts from Web Games,” Proceedings of the
Seventh ACM SIGKDD International Conference on Knowledge Discovery and
Data Mining, pp. 174-183.
Plantinga, A., (1993), Warrant and Proper Function, New York: Oxford University
Press.
Pronin, E., Lin, D. Y., and Ross, L., (2002), “The Bias Blind Spot: Perceptions of Bias in
Self versus Others,” Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 28, pp. 369-381.
Rawls, J., (1997), “The Idea of Public Reason,” in Bohman and Rehg (1997), pp. 93-141.
Rhode, P. W., and Strumpf, K. S., (2009), “Manipulating Political Stock Markets: A
Field Experiment and a Century of Observational Data,” manuscript, February
2009.
Roberts, R. C., and Wood, W. J., (2007), Intellectual Virtues: An Essay in Regulative
Epistemology, New York: Oxford University Press.
174
Sartwell, C., (1992), “Why Knowledge is Merely True Belief,” Journal of Philosophy 89,
pp. 167-180.
Servan-Schreiber, E., Wolfers, J., Pennock, D., and Galebach, B., (2004), “Prediction
Markets: Does Money Matter?” Electronic Markets 14, pp. 243–51.
Sieck, W., and Arkes, H., (2005), “The Recalcitrance of Overconfidence and its
Contribution to Decision Aid Neglect,” Journal of Behavioral Decision Making
18, pp. 29-53.
Sosa, E., (2004), “Replies,” in J. Greco, ed., Ernest Sosa and his Critics, Malden:
Blackwell, pp. 329-333.
Sosa, E., (2007), A Virtue Epistemology: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge, Volume I,
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Steup, M., and Sosa, E., (2005), eds., Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, Malden:
Blackwell Publishing.
Stiell, I. G., Greenberg, G. H., McKnight, R. D., Nair, R. C., McDowell, I, and
Worthington, J. R., (1992), “A Study to Develop Clinical Decision Rules for the
Use of Radiography in Acute Ankle Injuries,” Annals of Emergency Medicine
21(4), pp. 384-390.
Sunstein C., (2006), “Deliberating Groups versus Prediction Markets (or Hayek’s
Challenge to Habermas),” Episteme 3 (3), pp. 192-213.
Sunstein, C., and Thaler, R., (2008), Nudge: Improving Decisions about Health,
Happiness, Wealth, and Happiness, New Haven: Yale University Press.
Swinburne, R., (1999), Providence and the Problem of Evil, New York: Oxford
University Press.
175
Taylor, C. C. W., (2008), “Plato’s Epistemology,” in G. Fine (2008), pp. 165-190.
Taylor, S. E., (1989), Positive Illusions: Creative Self-Deception and the Healthy Mind,
Basic Books.
Trout, J. D., (2005), “Paternalism and Cognitive Bias,” Law and Philosophy 24, pp. 393-
434.
Trout, J. D., (2009), The Empathy Gap: Building Bridges to the Good Life and the Good
Society, New York: Viking.
Whitecotton, S. M., (1996), “The Effects of Experience and Confidence on Decision Aid
Reliance: A Causal Model,” Behavioral Research in Accounting 8, pp. 194–216.
Williams, B., (1978), Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry, Highlands: Humanities
Press.
Williamson, T., (2000), Knowledge and Its Limits, New York: Oxford University Press.
Wolfers, J., and Zitzewitz, E., (2006), “Prediction Markets in Theory and Practice,”
Research Paper No. 1927, Stanford Graduate School of Business Research Paper
Series.
Wolterstorff, N., (1996), John Locke and the Ethics of Belief, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Young, R., (2008), “John Stuart Mill, Ronald Dworkin and Paternalism,” in C. L. Ten,
ed., Mill’s ‘On Liberty’: A Critical Guide, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
176