Discretion in Administrative Law
Discretion in Administrative Law
Discretion in Administrative Law
Article 3
Volume 17, Number 1 (April 1979)
Citation Information
Grey, J. H.. "Discretion in Administrative Law." Osgoode Hall Law Journal 17.1 (1979) : 107-132.
http://digitalcommons.osgoode.yorku.ca/ohlj/vol17/iss1/3
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Osgoode Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Osgoode Hall
Law Journal by an authorized editor of Osgoode Digital Commons.
DISCRETION IN ADMINISTRATIVE LAW
By J. H. GREY*
I. INTRODUCTION
If administrative law is seen as the study of the use of power, one of its
most important interests is discretion, since the limits on discretion are at the
same time the limits on the power that anyone can have in our type of democ-
racy. The massive expansion of the powers of the state, and the growth of
immensely powerful committees, commissions and other bodies, against which
may be juxtaposed a new and fervent interest in civil liberties and human
rights, renders a re-examination of discretion and discretionary powers both
essential and inevitable. It is the purpose of this essay to clarify the concept
of discretion, to demonstrate how far the courts have been willing to tolerate
it, and to chart some of the new paths that appear to be opening before those
who advocate wide judicial review.
point the "duty" is ignored and the correlative "right" violated. As soon as
that point is reached, the courts can interfere; before that they will abstain
from doing so.
It is useful in dealing with the concept of discretion to consider the
notions of "weak" and "strong" discretion as explained by Dworkin:
I call both of these senses weak to distinguish them from a stronger sense. We use
'discretion' sometimes not merely to say that an official must use judgment in
applying the standards set him by authority, or that no one will review that
exercise of judgment, but to say that on some issue he is simply not bound by
standards set by the authority in question. 9
Dworkin used this distinction in order to show that "strong discretion"
does not exist in law and therefore legal positivism fails as a philosophy. This
is far removed from ordinary issues of discretion in administrative law. Never-
theless, the analysis suggested above is useful in explaining Dworkin's distinc-
tion. The "weaker" the discretion, the closer the point at which a "duty"
exists. Conversely, the "stronger" the discretion, the more distant and more
nebulous the duty.
"Strength" and "weakness" of a discretion are clearly part of a continuum
and not necessarily "either-or" alternatives. Dworkin appears to recognize
this when he says:
The strong sense of discretion is not tantamount to license, and does not exclude
criticism. Almost any situation in which a person acts (including those in which
there is no question of decision under special authority, and so no question of
discretion) makes relevant certain standards of rationality, fairness, and effective-
ness. We criticize each other's acts in terms of these standards, and there is no
reason not to do so when the acts are within the center rather than beyond the
perimeter of the doughnut of special authority.'9
Logically, the "strongest" discretion would mean untrammeled power to
act in any way that the party possessing the power desired. There would be no
duty at all, not even one of good faith. It goes without saying that the
"stronger" the discretion claimed by officials, the greater the controversy
about the possibility of this type of power in our law.
One more point should be noted in connection with the concept of dis-
cretion-it is not limited to public law. Private law is replete with examples
of discretion." Since Hohfeld dealt almost exclusively with private law,12 the
Hohfeldian analysis is, if anything, more apt in private law.'3 In any case,
there is very little difference between private and public law in this field and
one must agree with Dias when he says of powers: "Broadly, they may be
9 Dworkin, "Is Law a System of Rules?" in Summers, ed., Essays in Legal Philoso-
phy (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1976) 25 at 45. This
article also appeared as The Model of Rules (1967), 35 U. Chi. L. Rev. 33.
Iold. at 46 (Summers), 33 (U. Chi. L. Rev.). This weakens Dworkin's case against
the existence of "strong" discretion. He should perhaps have spoken of the "limits of
strong discretion" and concluded that the "strongest" type of discretion does not exist.
11 Discretionary trusts are perhaps the best example.
12 Tapper, supranote 6, at 247.
13 See, for instance, Harris, Trust, Power and Duty (1971), 87 L.Q. Rev. 31.
OSGOODE HALL LAW JOURNAL [VCOL. 17, NO. I
divided into 'public' and 'private', but for present purposes, nothing turns on
the distinction." 14
While we shall continue to treat discretion as a problem of public law,
we should keep in mind that much of what we conclude will be applicable to
private law fields. 15
Once we have defined and, to some extent, discussed the concept of dis-
cretion, it becomes necessary to consider it together with some of the other
fundamental notions of administrative law and to place review of discretionary
powers in the general context of judicial review.
III. DISCRETION AND JURISDICTION
Discretion and jurisdiction are both words of immense importance in
administrative law and since they are sometimes interchangeable, it is not
difficult to confuse them.
Discretion has been defined above. Jurisdiction is a more general concept
of power to do a particular thing, whether it involves discretion or not. One
could not improve on the formulation given by Dussault: "11 peut, en fait, se
dtfinir comme la capacit6 d'agir dans un domaine precis d'autorit6."' 10
It follows from this that in order to have discretion one must have juris-
diction, but that the converse is not necessarily true. If one exceeds the bounds
of one's discretion, one automatically exceeds one's jurisdiction, but the limits
of jurisdiction can be violated even by those who have no discretion. For
instance, an official who has, in the Hohfeldian sense, a duty only and no
power can act ultra vires by failing to carry out his duty.
Some have viewed discretion as an element tending to extend jurisdic-
tion.-7 However, the better view is that discretion is merely one type of juris-
diction. Courts will always review excesses of jurisdiction,' and thus an act
beyond the limits of discretion will usually be reviewed. A fact at times not
clearly understood is that, since powers and duties are often intertwined, an
official who does possess discretion may act ultra vires for reasons having
nothing to do with the discretion as such. The presence of discretion should
therefore not, in itself, suffice to prove unreviewability on other jurisdictional
grounds.' 9
35
Bhadauria v. MMI, supra note 30; Gana v. MMI, supra note 33; Martineau v.
Matsqui Inst. (No. 2), id.
36
See MMI v. Hardayal,supra note 22.
87 See Martineauv. Matsqui Inst. (No. 2), supra note 20; and Mullan, supra note 21.
88
De Smith, supra note 16, at 64, warns against any use of the adjective "quasi-
judicial." With respect to discretion, such a warning should be doubly potent and apply
to all such terms.
3
9 Bhadauriav. MMI, supra note 30; Gana v. MMI, supra note 33.
40
Boulis v. MMI, [1974] S.C.R. 875, 26 D.L.R. (3d) 216. It is interesting to remem-
ber that the very issuance of prerogative writs and injunctions is discretionary (e.g.,
R. v. Aston Univ. Senate, [1969] 2 Q.B. 538, [1969] 2 All E.R. 964).
41
See de Smith, supra note 16, at 59-60; and Dias, supra note 6, at 267-68. The
word "ministerial" appears with no explanation in Re Multi-Malls Inc. and Min. of
Transp. and Commun. (1976), 14 O.R. (2d) 49 (C.A.) at 60. It is also used with the
noun "function" in Services Juridiquesde St-Louis v. Commission des Services Jurdiques,
supra note 19, and here it seems to be used as a synonym for "duty."
OSGOODE HALL LAW JOURNAL [VOL. 17, NO. I
42
Boulis v. MMI, supra note 40, at 877 (S.C.R.), 217 (D.L.R.) per Abbott J.
43 Congreve v. Home Office, [1976] 1 Q.B. 629 at 649, [1976] 1 All E.R. 697 at 708.
44
Dias, supra note 6, at 267 distinguishes between powers which must be exercised
and those which need not, and calls the former "ministerial."
45
Boulis v. MMI, supra note 40; and Congreve v. Home Office, supra note 43.
46 See, for instance, Calgary Power Ltd. v. Copithorne, supra note 20.
47
See Bhadauriav. MMI, supra note 30.
19793 Discretion
The judgments discussed in the last few pages are freely embellished with refer-
ences to good and bad faith. These add very little to the true sense, and are hardly
ever used to mean more than that some action is found to have a lawful or un-
lawful purpose. It is extremely rare for public authorities to be found guilty of
intentional dishonesty: normally they are found to have erred, if at all, by
ignorance or misunderstanding. Yet the courts constantly accuse them of bad faith
merely because they have acted unreasonably or on improper grounds. Again and
again it is laid down that powers must be exercised reasonably and in good faith.
But in this context 'in good faith' means merely 'for legitimate reasons'. Contrary
to the natural sense of the words, they impute no moral obliquity. 48
Rand J. defined "good faith" in Roncarelli v. Duplessis:
"Good faith" in this context, applicable both to the respondent and the general
manager, means carrying out the statute according to its intent and for its purpose;
it means good faith in acting with a rational appreciation of that intent and pur-
pose and not with an improper intent and for an alien purpose; it does not mean
for the purposes of punishing a person for exercising an unchallengeable right; it
does not mean arbitrarily
49
and illegally attempting to divest a citizen of an incident
of his civil status.
There exist, of course, cases of the "moral" type of bad faith, 0 and, in
other cases, it is difficult to determine whether "moral" bad faith is involved.51
Nevertheless, it is clear that the notion of bad faith is being used to describe
various forms of behaviour, ranging from clear moral turpitude to errors not
intrinsically different from those influenced by irrelevant considerations or un-
reasonable acts.
It would probably serve clarity best if the expression "bad faith" were
limited to situations where moral turpitude was present 52 and if "irrelevant
motives" and "unreasonableness" were kept separate from it.53 At present, it
is difficult to be certain what type of error of discretion is invoked and discus-
sion can become very muddled. For instance, it is difficult to see the place of
"good faith" in relation to discretion in Wade's otherwise excellent analysis of
55
the subject.5 4 A narrower definition would bring everything into focus.
(b) The duty not to be influenced by irrelevantconsiderationsor motives
This duty appears to cover two types of problems. First, it forbids the
nonexercise of discretion for ulterior motives, such as personal gain, dislike,
ethnic feeling and so on. Second, and more significantly, it forbids the use
48
Wade, Administrative Law (4th ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977) at 372.
49
Roncarelli v. Duplessis, [1959] S.C.R. 121 at 143, 16 D.L.R. (2d) 689 at 707.
5
0A good example is Gershman v. Manitoba Vegetable Producers, Marketing Bd.
(1976), 65 D.L.R. (3d) 181, [1976] 2 W.W.R. 432 (Man. Q.B.); (1977), 69 D.L.R.
(3d) 114 (Man. C.A.).
51 E.g., Roncarelli v. Duplessis, supra note 49; Congreve v. Home Office, supra
note 43.
52 Gershman v. Manitoba Vegetable Producers'Marketing Bd., supra note 50.
53 It goes without saying that hermetic separation is impossible and that all three
will often be present. Indeed, Rand J.'s definition of good faith (Roncarelli v. Duplessis,
supra note 49) is a perfect illustration of this.
5
4 Wade, supra note 40, particularly at 372-75, but de Smith, supra note 16, at 304
makes a clear distinction between the concepts.
55 This is not to quarrel in any way with the result or reasoning of Roncarelli v.
Duplessis, supra note 49, but only to quibble about a definition.
OSGOODE HALL LAW JOURNAL [VOL. 17, NO. I
of discretion for purposes other than those intended by the instrument that
created the discretion. Although the two cases are frequently difficult to dis-
tinguish, 56 it is possible to point to examples that are more one than the other.
The celebrated case of Smith and Rhuland Ltd. v. The Queen is an ex-
ample of the first type of error, caused by consideration of an individual's
political views. 57 To an attempt to refuse certification of a union because its
secretary-treasurer was a Communist, Mr. Justice Rand answered as follows:
I am unable to agree, then, that the Board has been empowered to act upon the
view that official association with an individual holding political views considered
to be dangerous by the Board proscribes a labour organization. Regardless of the
strength and character of the influence of such a person, there must be some
evidence that, with the acquiescence of the members, it has been directed to ends
destructive of the legitimate purposes of the union, before that association can
justify the exclusion of employees from the rights and privileges of a statute de-
signed primarily for their benefit. 58
Examples of the second type of misuse of discretion abound, particularly
in recent years. Perhaps the classic statement can be found in Lord Reid's
judgment in Padfield v. Minister of Agriculture, Fisheriesand Food:
Parliament must have conferred the discretion with the intention that it should be
used to promote the policy and objects of the Act; the policy and objects of the
Act must be determined by construing the Act as a whole and construction is
always a matter of law for the court. In a matter of this kind it is not possible
to draw a hard and fast line, but if the Minister, by reason of his having miscon-
strued the Act or for any other reason, so uses his discretion as to thwart or run
counter to the policy and objects of the Act, then our law would be very defective
if persons aggrieved were not entitled to the protection of the court.5 9
This type of thinking was applied in a ringing manner in Congreve v.
Home Office, where Lord Denning emphasized that discretionary powers to
cancel a licence could not be used as a way of enforcing the purchase of a
new, higher-priced licence, and he made clear the importance of this principle
for human rights in a democratic society.60
An important recent Canadian application of this type of analysis can
be found in Re Multi-Malls Inc. and Minister of Transportation, where
Lacourci~re J.A. said:
I am of opinion that the Minister of Transportation and Communications allowed
himself to be influenced by extraneous, irrelevant and collateral considerations
which should not have influenced him in the exercise of his discretion to refuse
the entrance permit. It seems clear that the purpose of the Act in general is not
to ensure proper land use planning but generally to control traffic. 61
This is clearly one of the main battlegrounds in administrative law and
6
2 Associated Provincial Picture Houses, Ltd. v. Wednesbury Corp., [1948] 1 K.B.
223, [1947] 2 All E.R. 680. This case was at least partially discounted, however, in
Re Multi-Malls, id. See also Boulis v. MMI, supra note 40.
63
See Martineauv. Matsqui Inst. (No. 2), supra note 20; Kurek v. Solicitor General,
unreported, Federal Court (Tr. Div.) T-1324-75; Inuit Tapirasat of Canada v. Lgger
(1978),
64
87 D.L.R. (3d) 26 (F.C.T.D.); Bhadauriav. MMI, supra note 30.
Roncarelli v. Duplesis, supra note 49.
65 Re Multi-Malls, supra note 46; Re Doctors' Hosp. and Min. of Health (1976),
68 D.L.R. (3d) 220 (Ont. H.C.).
66 See de Smith, supra note 17, at 301-03; Re Bernstein and College of Physicians
and Surgeons (1977), 15 O.R. (2d) 447 (H.C.).
67 Re Township of Innisfil and City of Barrie (1978), 17 O.R. (2d) 277 at 287, 80
D.L.R. (3d) 85 at 95-96, 3 M.P.L.R. 47 at 62 (Div. Ct.).
OSGOODE HALL LAW JOURNAL [VOL. 17, NO. 1
1S As with many of our distinctions, however, the boundaries are often blurred
between evidentiary and other issues.
69 Boulis v. MMI, supra note 40.
70 De Smith, supra note 16, at 304.
7
1 Secretary of State for Educ. and Science v. Tameside Metropolitan Borough
Council. supra note 2, at 1064.
72
Dworkin, supra note 9.
73 Id. See also note 10, supra, and accompanying text.
74 Secretary of State for Educ. and Science v. Tameside Metropolitan Borough
Council, supra note 2, at 1047.
75 Special wartime laws, for instance, will rarely be reviewed; see note 129, infra,
and accompanying text.
76 Secretary of State for Educ. and Science v. Tameside Metropolitan Borough
Council,supra note 2.
1979] Discretion
77 It is likely that, with the growth of government, coupled with the increase in
regulation and the number of regulatory agencies, such conflict will become very common.
78
Secretary of State for Educ. and Science v. Tameside Metropolitan Borough
Council, supra note 2, at 1065 per Lord Diplock.
79 Id. at 1071 per Lord Salmon.
80 Id. at 1064; see also note 71, supra, and accompanying text.
87
Ramawad v. MMI, [1978] 2 S.C.R. 375. There are exceptions to this principle,
but they are outside the scope of this essay.
88
Re Township of Innisil and City of Barrie, supra note 67.
89 E.g., the illegality of Mr. Archambault's act in Roncarelli v. Duplessis, supra
note 49.
90 Manitoba Gov't Employees Ass'n v. Manitoba, supra note 86; R. v. Commissioner
of Police, [1968] 2 Q.B. 118, sub nom. R. v. Metro Police Comm'r, (1968] 1 All E.R.
763; Reference re Anti-Inflation Act, [1976] 2 S.C.R. 373 at 427-35, 68 D.L.R. (3d) 452
at 499-506. This does not mean, however, that there is never discretion not to apply the
law in a particular case. Such a discretion is essential if our laws are to be applied
humanely. See R. v. Catagas, [1978] 1 W.W.R. 282 at 287 (Man. C.A.).
91
Roncarelli v. Duplessis, supra note 49, at 140 (S.C.R.), 705 (D.L.R.).
9
2 Martineau v. Matsqui Inst. (No. 2), supra note 20, at 328.
1979] Discretion
In order to see whether any powers under our law are totally outside the
control of the courts,9 6 we shall look at several types of powers that have
been placed in such a category to see how far their immunity extends.
A. Administrative functions subject to political control only
While there have long been restrictions on the review of administrative
functions, discretionary or not,97 courts have rarely postulated complete un-
reviewability, save on the merits of a discretionary decision. 8 Nevertheless,
several recent dicta by the Federal Court might suggest such a doctrine.
Chronologically, the first was Kurek v. Solicitor General of Canada.99
This case dealt with the Crown prerogative of using section 21 of the
Immigration Appeal Board Act,'0 0 but its ramifications became far broader
when Addy J. said:
In any event, if the decision was a judicial or quasi judicial one it is reviewable
only by the Court of Appeal under section 28 and not by the Trial Division. If it
was a purely administrative decision, then, since it was rendered by the minister
in the exercise of the function with which he was charged by Parliament under
the Act, he is answerable first of all to Cabinet and finally to Parliament for any
such decision and not to the Courts.101 [Emphasis added]
In Inuit Tapirasatof Canada v. LUger, Marceau J. included a similar
statement:
93
Bhadauriav. MMI, supra note 30.
94
De Smith, supra note 16, at 253-62.
95
Wade, supra note 48, at 340.
96
We should keep in mind Lord Denning's view that the courts always retain a
power of last resort. For instance, in A.G. v. Chaudry, [1971] 1 W.L.R. 1614, [1971]
3 All E.R. 938, Lord Denning said at 1624 (W.L.R.), 947 (All E.R.): "The High Court
has jurisdiction to ensure obedience to the law whenever it is just and convenient so
to do."
97See Martineau v. Matsqui Inst. (No. 2), supra note 20; Mullan, supra note 21;
and Nakkuda Ali v. Jayaratne,supra note 21.
98
See Bhadauriav. MMI, supra note 30, and accompanying text.
99
Kurek v. Solicitor General,supra note 63.
100 R.S.C. 1970, c. 1-3.
01
1 Kurek v. Solicitor General, supra note 63.
OSGOODE HALL LAW JOURNAL [VOL. 17, NO. I
government policy decisions are harder to review than most other kinds. But,
as we shall see, such decisions are not, despite the relatively strong discretion
involved, completely immune from review, and the Federal Court probably
did not intend such a result.
In conclusion, it would almost certainly be wrong to classify all or even
some discretionary administrative functions as reviewable only before the
legislature, and not before the courts. Such a position would wipe out the duty
to be fair, and would be very unfortunate in the modem bureaucratic state,
where political redress is far more difficult to obtain than the judicial kind.
But the Federal Court cases can perhaps remain useful as examples of judicial
restraint on policy issues.
B. Crown prerogative
The jurisprudence yields many statements about the unreviewability of
the exercise of Crown prerogative. Re Multi-Malls Inc. and Minister of Trans-
portation is an excellent example:
The Courts have always been careful to distinguish between acts done pursuant
to the exercise of a statutory power-subject to Court review-and decisions made
109
under the Royal prerogative-which are not per se reviewable by the Courts.
Even this view would clearly allow the courts at least to restrict the
operation of prerogative to its proper limits."10 Now, however, in a rather
arcane case, Lord Denning has gone further:
The prerogative is a discretionary power exercisable by the executive government
for the public good, in certain spheres of governmental activity for which the law
has made no provision, such as the war prerogative (of requisitioning property for
the defence of the realm), or the treaty prerogative (of making treaties with
foreign powers). The law does not interfere with the proper exercise of the discre-
tion by the executive in those situations: but it can set limits by defining the
bounds of the activity: and it can intervene if the discretion is exercised1 im-
properly or mistakenly. That is a fundamental principle of our constitution." 1
Lord Denning's view was not necessarily the view of the other members
of the Court;" 2 nevertheless, it has great appeal and considerable authority
to recommend it. For instance, in Ex parte Lain, there was more than a hint
that any executive authority would be subject to review. 113
More important, a series of decisions of British cases has, without ex-
posing the executive to undue intervention and scrutiny, clearly placed the
prerogative within the ambit of the courts." 4
10
9 Re Multi-Malls, supra note 41, at 58; app'd in Re Doctors' Hosp. and Min. of
Health, supra note 65. See also Kurek v. Solicitor General, supra note 63.
110 I.e., the Crown could not both declare the scope of the prerogative and exercise it.
Il"Laker Airways Ltd. v. Department of Trade, [1977] Q.B. 643 at 705, [1977]
2 All E.R. 182 at 192.
112 But see id. at 728 (Q.B.), 210 (All E.R.) per Lawton Li.:
Far from curbing these powers, by section 19(2) (b) Parliament recognised that
the Crown had them. This is so; but the Secretary of State cannot use the Crown's
powers in this sphere in such a way as to take away the rights of citizens: see
Walker v. Baird, [1892] A.C. 491.
118 R. v. Criminal Injuries Compensation Bd. (Lain), [1967] 2 Q.B. 864, [1967] 2
All E.R. 770 (Div. Ct.).
114
Burmah Oil Co. v. Lord Advocate, [1965] A.C. 75, [1964] 2 All E.R. 348
(H.L.); Conway v. Rimmer, [1968] A.C. 910, [1968] 1 All E.R. 874 (H.L.); Nissan v.
A.G., [1970] A.C. 179, [1969] 1 All E.R. 629 (H.L.).
OSGOODE HALL LAW JOURNAL [VOL. 17, NO. 1
115 Allott, The Courts and the Executive: Four House of Lords Decisions, [1977]
Camb. LJ. 255 at 269.
116 ld. at 266.
11 7 See Bhadauriav. MMI, supra note 30, and accompanying text.
118 Friedmann, Law in a Changing Society (2d ed. New York: Columbia Univ.
Press, 1972) at 39; Professor Friedmann was here most concerned with the Crown's
liability in tort and contract.
1979] Discretion
ter of Housing and Local Government."9 In that case, the Minister had
refused to accept a planning inspector's report on Lord Luke's application for
a building permit. The Minister accepted the findings of fact, but came to
different conclusions. Lord Denning said:
I must say that I have considerable sympathy with Lord Luke. The inspector's
report was very much in his favour. But it must be remembered that the Minister
has the responsibility for planning policy. In order to preserve our countryside he
has adopted a policy of setting out an "envelope" for each village. Development
is permitted within the "envelope" and not outside it. If one person is allowed to
build outside, it will be difficult to refuse his neighbour. So the Minister must be
strict. This is planning policy and nothing else. 1The20
courts have no authority to
interfere with the way the Minister carries it out.
A recent case in which government policy was given priority was Re
Township of Innisfil and City of Barrie,in which the Ontario Municipal Board
was held to be entitled to consider itself bound by a minister's opinion.' 2 1
Indeed, it could be said that the famous case of Calgary Power Ltd. v. Copi-
thorne, so often used to thwart judicial review in Canada, was in essence
nothing more than an illustration of the executive's power to make policy
decisions without interference. 122 The series of Federal Court judgments dis-
cussed earlier in connection with review of administrative functions are also
relevant and helpful as another example of this principle12-
But are policy decisions truly unreviewable? It is submitted that they are
not. As part of the principle that they do not substitute themselves for offi-
cials, the courts try to avoid making blatantly political policy decisions and
decline to judge the merits of government policy. 2 4 As soon as policy deci-
sions are found to be illegal or unreasonable, however, the courts may inter-
fere, as they may with other forms of discretion.
Policy cannot justify the executive's dispensing with the laws.125 Nor can
it justify breaches of the law. 2 6 A pre-established policy may invalidate deci-
sions if the policy prevented the official from considering each case on the
merits, e.g., if a policy of "no parole for drug cases" were instituted. 2 7 Final-
ly, the case of Laker Airways Ltd. v. Department of Trade illustrates that
government policy, even on questions touching the sensitive area of interna-
tional relations, will not be permitted to 28
prevail over private rights in the
absence of clear statutory authorization.
The conclusion is that, although policy issues cannot be reviewed on the
merits, discretion which involves policy may be reviewed on much the same
"19 Pavenham v. Minister of Hous. and Local Gov't, [1967] 3 W.L.R. 801, [1967]
2 All E.R. 1066.
12 0 Id. at 807 (W.L.R.), 1070 (All E.R.).
12
1Re Township of Innisfil and City of Barrie, supra note 67.
122 Calgary Power Ltd. v. Copithorne, supra note 20.
12 8
See Kurek v. Solicitor General and Inuit Tapirasatof Canada v. Liger, supra
note 63, and accompanying text.
124
See Bhadauriav. MMI, supra note 30. See also Mullan, supra note 21.
125 E.g., R. v. Catagas, supra note 90.
126 Manitoba Gov't Employees Ass'n v. Manitoba, supra note 86.
12 T De Smith, supra note 16, at 274-77. But see Re Township of Innisfil and City of
Barrie,supranote 67.
128 Laker Airways Ltd. v. Department of Trade, supra note 111.
OSGOODE HALL LAW JOURNAL [VOL. 17, NO. 1
tions between the parties were purely contractual. 137 Such cases have theoret-
ically nothing to do with discretion or unreviewability as such, but rather with
the boundaries between private and public law.
Despite weighty jurisprudence to this effect, it is difficult to accept this
explanation in the case of prison disciplinary tribunals. Where a domestic
tribunal is connected with a private club or even a professional association,
the contractual avenue may provide an adequate recourse, and it is arguable
that the parties have bound themselves contractually to respect the tribunal's
decision. 138 Neither of these points makes sense in a prison situation. There-
fore, the Hull Prison case seems rather to be hinting at a special form of un-
reviewable discretion-that of prison discipline (and possibly certain other
similar fields).139 The true rationale is public order, and this becomes evident
when Lord Denning is quoted on this topic:
I am conscious of the fact that Lord Denning M.R. is so right, if I may say so,
in his judgment and the observation he made about this problem in Becker v.
Home Office [1972] 2 Q.B. 407, 418 where he said:
"If the courts were to entertain actions by disgruntled prisoners, the gov-
ernor's life would be made intolerable. The discipline of the prison would be
undermined. The Prison Rules are regulatory directions only. Even if they
are not observed, they do not give rise to a cause of action."' 40
These cases bear resemblance to the two recent Canadian cases involving
prison discipline, 141 and perhaps the whole subject should be viewed as sui
generis, without broad implications for administrative law.
Even so, it is difficult to believe that the discretion given to these unlike-
ly "domestic tribunals" is truly unreviewable and that the most blatant abuse
would be tolerated by the courts. What, for instance, if prison officials violated
all notions of humanity or decency in their penalties? What if prisoners' safety
were endangered? What if prisoners were given internal self-government so
that the stronger could terrorize the weaker through "domestic" trials? It is
obvious that a limit must exist and that courts would at some point determine
where it lies, giving prison officials more42 rope than other officials, but still
denying them infinite quantities of rope.1
The final conclusion on unreviewability must be that it is no part of our
law. Some discretions (e.g., wartime or prerogative ones) are stronger (in
Dworkin's sense) than others, but all are subject to review at some point.
137 Vidyodaya Univ. of Ceylon v. Silva, [1965] 1 W.L.R. 77, [1964] 3 All E.R.
865 (P.C.).
138 Pett v. Greyhound Racing Ass'n (No. 2), [1970] 1 Q.1. 46, [1969] 2 All E.R.
221.
130 R. v. Board of Visitors of Hull Prison, supra note 136.
140 Id. at 606.
141 Martineau v.Matsqui Inst. Inmate Disciplinary Bd. (No. 1), [1978] 1 S.C.R.
118. See also Martineau v. Matsqui Inst. (No. 2), supra note 20. Parole cases also tend
to be decided in this manner (e.g., Howarth v. National Parole Bd., supra note 29).
142 One might argue, however, that the courts could apply private law remedies-
damages and injunctions. Indeed, R. v. Board of Visitors of Hull Prison, supra note 136
only decides that certiorariis unavailable in these cases.
On the subject of prison correction and administrative law, see Price, Doing Justice
to Corrections?Prisoners,Paroleesand the Canadian Courts (1977), 3 Queen's L.J 214.
OSGOODE HALL LAW JOURNAL [VOL. 17, NO. 1
It should be added that if a discretion were created so strong that no
court could review it, even for clear excess of jurisdiction, the official entrusted
with this power would be usurping not only the functions of a court, 48
but
also of the legislature. He would be no less than a dictator, and the logic of
our division of power would be destroyed. Since this division has been judi-
cially recognized and invoked in many different situations, 44 it is likely
that the courts would find a way of striking down an instrument that pur-
ported to grant such vast powers or else of limiting the power by attaching to
it the fundamental duties which restrict the use of discretion.
143 Thus possibly violating section 96 of The British North America Act, 1867, 30
& 31 Viet., c. 3.
144 E.g., Gouriet v. Union of Post Office Workers, [1977] 3 W.L.R. 300, [1977] 3
All E.R. 70 (H.L.); and Hinds v. The Queen, [1977] A.C. 195 (P.C.).
145 See, for instance, Reference Re Regulations (Chemicals) under War Measures
Act, supra note 130, and Toronto v. Forest Hill, [1957] S.C.R. 569. However, in cases
of delegated legislation, unlike ordinary cases of discretion, it is difficult to speak of a
duty to be fair.
146 Rederaktiebolaget Amphitrite v. The King, [1921] 3 K.B. 500; Roman Corp. v.
Hudson's Bay Oil and Gas Co., [1973] S.C.R. 820, 36 D.L.R. (3d) 413.
147 R. v. Pickersgill (1970), 14 D.L.R. (3d) 717 (Man. Q.B.).
148 See, for instance, A.G. v. Chaudry, supra note 96.
149 Langan, Maxwell on the Interpretationof Statutes (12th ed. London: Sweet &
Maxwell, 1969) at 167 and 208-10.
150 Id. at 212-15.
1979] Discretion
jurisprudential examples illustrate that such decisions are far from simple or
mechanical. 58
The availability of the writ of mandamus is less problematic. Despite
occasional and, with respect, heretical dicta to the contrary,'r5 the distinction
between administrative and judicial functions has no place here, and the writ
can issue whenever a public duty is not performed. Since discretion is always
coupled with a duty, it follows that this is a very useful remedy in reviewing
abuse of discretion.
Although mandamus will issue to compel the performance of a duty, it
will usually not compel a particular result in the exercise of discretion. 1G 0
However, where an exercise of discretion is patently incorrect, the courts may
treat it as void and thus, indirectly, compel a different result by mandamus.161
Nevertheless, the theoretical explanation must remain the breach of a funda-
mental duty, which is enforced by mandamus.
It is possible that greater intervention in the merits of the exercise of
discretion could be justified in Qu6bec than elsewhere, because article 844
of the Code of Civil Procedure speaks not only of commanding the perform-
2-
ance of a duty but also of an "act which is not of a purely private nature."
However, if a broader base for review exists, it has so far remained unnoticed
by the courts, and no cases can be found concerning this difference.
The declaration is possibly the safest remedy; it is certainly the safest in
proceedings against the Crown. However, it too may be subject to technical
IX. CONCLUSIONS
It is difficult to reach specific and categorical conclusions in a survey
essay of this nature. However, the following tentative conclusions might be
accepted:
103 See, for example, Punton v. Minister of Pensions and Nat'l Ins., [1964] 1
W.L.R. 226, where a declaration is held not to lie where it would contradict a subsisting
ministerial order and thus produce two inconsistent "decisions." See also Poitras v. A.G.
Alta. (1969), 7 D.L.R. (3d) 161 (Alta. S.C.).
164 B. v. Commission of Inquiry re. Dep't of Manpower and Immigration, [1975]
F.C. 602, 60 D.L.R. (3d) 339 (F.C.T.D.).
110The holding in B.'s case, id., is currently being challenged before the Federal
Court of Appeal in Ospina v. Lefebvre after apparently having been upheld by Mr.
Justice D~cary, unreported, T-1263-78 (F.C.T.D.).
100
See, for instance, Podrusse v. Commissairesd'dcoles de St-Lgonard-de-Port-Maurice,
[1970] C.A. 324.
167 See Roncarelli v. Duplessis, supra note 49; and Gershman v. Manitoba Vegetable
Producers' Marketing Bd., supra note 50. The recourse in damages is essentially a private
law one, used in public law most often when an official is found outside the limits of his
discretion or is no longer acting in his public capacity.
108 Denning, Freedom Under the Law (London: Stevens, 1949) at 126.
109 Something that England, Ontario and New Zealand (to name a few) now
appear to have done.
170 Wade, supra note 48, at 556.
171 This was Lord Denning's view in Freedom Under the Law, supra note 168, at
OSGOODE HALL LAW JOURNAL [VOL. 17, NO. I
1. Discretion means essentially "power" and is, in public law, always coupled
with certain basic duties. Therefore, there is always a limit to judicial re-
straint in this field.
2. Discretions have different "strengths," and the threshold of judicial inter-
vention varies from statute to statute and from situation to situation, although
the principles remain fairly constant.
3. It is important to define discretion so as to separate it clearly from the
other fundamental concepts of administrative law. Once the concepts are
established, many of the complexities of the subject evaporate.
4. We live in an era of expansion of the concepts of "unreasonable" use of
discretion and use of discretion on irrelevant grounds, or in a manner con-
trary to the purposes of an instrument creating it. Except for Re Multi-Malls,172
the leading cases on the subject have been British cases, and the pioneering
judge has often been Lord Denning. There is no reason to think that, even
with Canada's recent conservatism in administrative law, 73 the basic prin-
ciples do not obtain here. There is no fundamental difference between Cana-
dian and British administrative law, and it would be to our detriment to
attempt to create one in this area. 74
5. No expansion of review of discretion can eliminate the principle that
courts do not interfere on the merits and substitute their opinions for those of
officials. To say otherwise would constitute a violation of our division of
powers, and would turn the courts into a superexecutive. This would probably
be administratively unmanageable, as well as constitutionally undesirable.
6. Crown prerogative, while justifiably difficult to review, is no longer to be
viewed as outside control at all times.
7. The expansion of review of discretion is justified by the corresponding
expansion of government, with increasing potential for abuse. The new weight
given privative clauses, although it has as yet had no serious consequences in
this area, can give rise to legitimate worry about the future, because it could
check the trend towards review without affecting the growth of bureaucratic
power.
8. The remedies must be simplified without delay, and the Federal Court
Act is a prime candidate for reform.
9. It is an essential part of our ideology that no official or type of case is
entirely immune from review. Some may be more protected than others, but
everyone works and lives under the law and therefore under the courts. This
should be kept in mind at all times.
72
1 Re Multi-Malls, supra note 41.
' 73 As contrasted with our vision twenty-five years ago. See Beaudoin, La Cour
supreme et la protection des droits fondamentaux (1975), 53 Can. B. Rev. 675.
174 Or, it is suggested, in any other.