Reflections On Mathematics Education Research Questions in Elementary Number Theory
Reflections On Mathematics Education Research Questions in Elementary Number Theory
Reflections On Mathematics Education Research Questions in Elementary Number Theory
Annie Selden
Tennessee Technological University
John Selden
Mathematics Education Resources Company
This monograph intentionally raises more questions than it answers. Indeed the editors'
aims included convincing readers that many interesting questions in the teaching and
learning of number theory await their attention, and that there are engaging number
Developing Mathematical Reasoning in Grades K-12 (Stiff, 1999), one finds almost
nothing on students' engagement with number theory topics. By number theory we mean,
as do the monograph editors, results concerning the structure of the integers that are not
primes. Whatever the reasons for this research lacuna, this monograph, devoted entirely
to various number theory investigations and reports, should help fill this void and
heighten the community's awareness of the potential for fruitful investigations. These
might concern individual students' cognitions on a variety of topics from divisibility and
number theory from a broad range of perspectives and investigate university students
contributions, however, are several common threads upon which we will comment: the
potential of number theory for the teaching and learning of problem solving, reasoning
and proof; questions regarding the language and images of divisibility; philosophical
stances taken; theoretical frameworks used; and implications for teaching. In the spirit of
the monograph and drawing on it, we will focus primarily on questions and new
directions for investigation, some ranging well beyond number theory itself.
Elementary number theory seems an ideal place to learn about problem solving,
reasoning, generalization, abstraction, and proof because students from middle school
through university feel comfortable dealing with whole numbers. They are much more
familiar with the positive integers than with rational, real, or complex numbers.
Principles and Standards (2000) calls for such problem solving and argumentation in
both the Reasoning and Proof and the Number and Operations Standards for Grades 6-8.
Middle school students could, for example, explain why the sum of the digits of any
multiple of 3 is itself divisible by 3 (NCTM, 2000, p. 217). Also the Number and
Operations Standard for Grades 9-12 explicitly states that all students should "use
2
number-theory arguments to justify relationships involving the whole numbers." One
could ask: What can you say about the number that results when you subtract 1 from the
square of an odd integer? Students could easily verify that the number is divisible by 4
and conjecture that it is divisible by 8. Proving this would involve representing the
Teppo's vignette (this volume) shows how students can begin reasoning about the
number of divisors of small positive integers. Then, with scaffolding by the teacher
along with a suitable didactic object (a divisor table), students can conjecture rules and
explain why they hold. This can lead to subsequently considering the general question of
how to determine the number of divisors of any positive integer, given its prime
mathematicians that number theory questions and conjectures can be easy to state but
phenomenally hard to prove (e.g., about partitions or the distribution of primes). While
the ordered partition problem (Rowland, this volume) is a potentially rich classroom task,
finding regularity in numbers of (unordered) partitions is subtle and difficult and involves
means, along with advice for teachers on potential student "pitfalls," would be a useful
pedagogical aid.
3
Why might elementary number theory be a good place for university students to
number theory proofs than say, abstract algebra proofs, and this can be an advantage for
students with a weak conception of proof. Currently in the U.S., university mathematics
majors, including preservice secondary teachers, can often avoid dealing with proofs until
a "bridge" course on proofs, often followed by an abstract algebra course. Such students'
entire previous experience may lead them to believe that mathematics deals mainly with
numbers and functions. Suddenly, in an abstract algebra course they need to treat
mathematics majors, we observed some difficulties with abstraction. The students were
presented with various sets, together with operations. They were asked to determine
whether these were semigroups and contained an identity, a zero, or other idempotents.
The sets were subsets of the reals, 2 2 real matrices, or real functions. The students
"knew" that juxtaposition stood for the (appropriate) operation, yet several students
student said, "When I see this [juxtaposition], I think it's multiplication." For these
students, juxtaposition should have been, but was not, functioning as a visual metaphor,
i.e., suggesting the operation worked a little, but not exactly, like ordinary multiplication.
4
It has been observed that in trying to cope with abstract algebra questions, university
students often attempt to reduce the level of abstraction by "folding back" to what they
know about numbers, thereby changing an unfamiliar problem into a more familiar one
(Hazzan, 1999). This kind of difficulty with abstraction often occurs while students are
also struggling to construct a conception of proof that is consistent with the standard
By contrast, in elementary number theory, students deal with objects (integers) and
operations (ordinary multiplication and addition) that are familiar to them. Hence, they
simultaneously having to extend their conceptions of the operations and objects they are
triple of primes if and only if all three of p, p 2, p 4 are primes. The only triple of
primes is 3, 5, 7. Our "bridge" course students have found this statement challenging, but
possible to prove. One student said, "The triple of primes problem kept me up until two
in the morning. I was in bed staring at the ceiling when inspiration struck around four in
Rowland (this volume) makes a convincing case for the use of generic proofs in
number theory but also notes (Footnote 12) that sometimes generic presentations seem
ruled out. One question to ask from a pedagogical point of view is whether a specific
generic proof is likely to be illuminating, even if one can easily find a suitable particular
case. For an example at the school level, consider the proof that subtracting 1 from the
5
square of an odd integer yields a number divisible by 8. It is hard to see that a generic
to follow Rowland's first four principles (this volume). The particular case, 11, is neither
trivial nor too complicated. After one has written 11= 2 5 1 , one can track 5 through the
stages of the argument. Invariant aspects of the proof transfer to values of n other than 5,
and the reasoning is constructive. By contrast, a generic proof of the digit-sum rule for
elegant proof that the Euler -function is multiplicative. On the other hand, we rewrote
Bolker's (1970) textbook proof of the same result using m 3 and n 8 and concluded it
would not be illuminating. Thus, not every proof seems suitable, ex post facto, for
treatment via generic example, even following Rowland's principles, and we join him in
ability to see the features of the general argument in the particular case, i.e., on a student's
generalization for mathematical induction problems, in which students look for a pattern
relating a statement about one integer to the (same) statement about the next (or previous)
integer. Just one of Harel's student groups seems to have, on their own, come upon
6
process pattern reasoning for the sequence 2 , 2 2 , K ; a way of
2 2 2 ,
thinking subsequently encouraged by the instructor. Not all students seem to make such
generalizations naturally. Are there ways to help students become better at it? Harel
suggests the importance of repeated reasoning, the R in his DNR system. A carefully
studies could help provide details which might help teachers engender such reasoning in
their students.
In summary, why is number theory ideal for introducing students to reasoning and
proof? (1) Students get to deal with familiar objects, thereby reducing the level of new
abstraction and the concomitant disequilbration. (2) When suitably selected, such proofs
are accessible, i.e., students need only reason from first principles together with a certain
amount of ingenuity. (3) Often number theory proofs have generic versions, allowing
students to see, or even to prove on their own, a general result after having seen a suitable
particular case.
Within mathematics, the concept of divisibility in the integers seems somewhat unusual
in having such a wide assortment of terms to describe different aspects of essentially the
Billstein, Libeskind, and Lott, 1984, p. 167 ) and for discrete mathematics (e.g., Epp,
1990, p. 164), it is simply stated that these five phrases are alternative ways of expressing
7
the fact that there is a unique integer C such that A=BC. But why are there so many
different terms? What aspects of the concept does each highlight? To what extent, does
the mere existence of so many essentially equivalent terms cause students confusion?
How do students cope with this variety of terms? What is the effect of students' own
alternative terms, e.g., B divides A evenly? We speculate on some of these issues, but
The words divisible, divides, and divisor emphasize those integer division situations
in which the remainder, R, in the division algorithm, A=BC+R, 0 R<B, is zero. In the
case of divisible, A's role is highlighted, whereas in the case of divides and divisor, B's
role is stressed. The terms factor and multiple emphasize two slightly different
multiplication situations. In the case of factor, it is the factorization, and to some extent
the prime factorization, of A that is being regarded, with B's role in that factorization
the integers may be being stressed, with emphasis on the fact that A=B+B+ L +B, where
there are C of the B's. Mathematically, the division algorithm, prime factorization, and
the Archimedean property stress somewhat different features of the positive integers, but
textbooks often only offer students a formal definition, i.e., the simple requirement that
there exist a unique C such that A=BC, together with illustrations and exercises. Yet in
selecting one term over another, it may sometimes appear that division is being stressed,
while at other times, multiplication. Also, sometimes A's role is emphasized, other times
B's. This, in itself, might cause students some confusion. This is not to say that
beginning university students should be introduced to all these nuances, but only that
there's probably more here than just five ways of saying exactly the same thing and that
8
the terminology used may influence what comes to mind at various times during
cognition.
"What is the remainder if you divide 6 147+1 by 6?", students seem to be trying to make
sense of the question in their own everyday language by asking the interviewers whether
"divides evenly" or "what's left over" is wanted (Campbell; Brown, Thomas, & Tolias;
Zazkis; this volume) . This suggests that some students may be bringing to mind various
suggested by Campbell (this volume), but might also be of other kinds. For example,
might the terms quotient and remainder bring to mind visual images such as
2 quotient
4 11 xxxx xxxx xxx 11 2 4 3
or or ?
8 2 groups of 4 3 left over
groups of 4 3 left over
3 remainder
In the first of these, it is possible to interpret the quotient as what sits on top and the
remainder as what's left at the bottom. One discrete textbook author uses these three
question to see what sorts of mental images of the division algorithm, or of prime
factorization, that university students bring with them and to what the degree they are
9
When one asks students such questions as "Is M=33 52 7 divisible by 15?" or "Is 34
55 73 1318 a multiple of M?", not only is one asking them to discriminate between
multiplication and division and between integer and rational division, but one is also
divisible by 5?" seemed relatively easy for many students like Alice because they could
see the 5 "in there" (Brown, et al., this volume), the question of divisibility by 15 often
found them resorting to their calculators to find M and divide by 15 to see whether "it"
elicited the same tendency to calculate M? We think not. This resort to an action
(Pirie & Kieren, 1994; Towers, Martin, and Pirie, 2000), i.e., to a portion of one's
mathematical knowledge with which one is comfortable and secure -- a way to deal with
the complexity of the situation. In addition, for preservice elementary teachers, it may be
that their view of doing mathematics consists largely of performing computations to get
such tasks. Furthermore, to determine whether a specific number not given in prime
factored form, such as 344578, is divisible by and other number, say 457, it seems quite
natural to resort to long division or a calculator. While the formal definition of "B
divides A" is especially good for proving results, such as M|N and N|P together imply M|
P, it gives no means of deciding whether for specific integers there actually is a C such
that A=BC.
10
We have noticed a slightly different image of divisibility used by some of our
A
theory. They often want to convert "B divides A" into " is an integer." This leads to
B
contemplating properties of pairs of numbers, e.g., what can be said about a noninteger
times an integer? Such reflections do not seem as straightforward as working with the
equation A=BC, where A, B, C are integers. To see this, consider the following theorem:
If M divides N and M does not divide P, then N does not divide P. The essence of one
student's "proof" went as follows: "Since M divides N, there exists an integer K so that
N P
N=MK and so is an integer. Since M does not divide P, is not an integer. Then
M M
P P
is not an integer. So N does not divide P." To complete the proof, the student
N MK
P
would have needed to argue that a noninteger such as divided by an integer such as K
M
A
is a noninteger. This image of divisibility results in the consideration of an object, ,
B
but one not as easily handled as the object A=BC, for which most students know
image of divisibility.
11
concept images, some which included an idea of "taking something out" (Campbell, this
volume). There seem to be several possible interpretations of this idea. One could "take
3 5 out" of M to produce 15 as Riva and Lanny did and then have difficulty interpreting
the role of 15 (Campbell, this volume). In the case of M, one "takes out" a factor of 15.
However, there are other possible interpretations of "taking out." Considering the case of
11 divided by 4, one might also think of "taking 4 out" of 11 twice, using a repeated
subtraction view of division, and having 3 "left over." Or, one might also "take 2 fours
out" of 11 and have "3 left over." Depending which image of "take out" comes to mind,
one might have a factor, a divisor, or a quotient, making it difficult to answer the question
correctly. In what ways do phrases like "take out" and "what's left over" influence
students' ways of looking at questions such as "Is M=33 52 7 divisible by 15?" While
students should learn to use mathematical terms precisely, they also need to unpack them
and call on relevant mental images and generic examples. If a term like "left over" calls
up an appropriate quotitive view of division, this would seem especially useful later for
preservice teachers.
Many other issues regarding divisibility have been raised by various chapter authors,
e.g., the necessity to distinguish the indivisible units of integer division from the
successfully between the modular ( 2 10 1 ), fractional (10 1 2 ), and decimal (10.5)
representations of "21 divided by 2" (Campbell, this volume). All of these are ripe for
further investigation.
PHILOSOPHICAL POSITIONS
12
In the introduction, under Epistemological Orientation, Campbell and Zazkis remark on
the relevant philosophical views of the contributors to this monograph and, more
philosophical views of the authors. Nevertheless such views do play an important role in
research because they influence the kinds of questions that will be, or even can be, asked
as well as the kinds of studies regarded as providing acceptable warrants for answers to
these questions.
Campbell and Zazkis correctly point out that the research community in
mathematics education takes a constructivist view of learning. This entails two main
ideas. First, individuals construct their own knowledge from their experiences and what
they already know. Here "construct" is not synonymous with "invent" -- few people
would claim students invent all of mathematics themselves. "Construct" also refers to the
thinking about one's actions (including mental actions or thoughts) and their effects. We
note that reflection requires focusing one's attention and suspect one's focus (James,
1910) plays a large role in learning. Perhaps the importance of focus in learning can be
most easily seen in situations involving its absence. Many people have had the
experience of looking up a phone number, dialing it, and moments later not being able to
remember it. No doubt their focus was on something other than the number, even though
they were sufficiently conscious of it to dial it correctly. Like dialing a phone number,
13
small mathematical tasks can be accomplished without much focus and it seems very
unlikely that such situations could lead to the construction of lasting conceptual
knowledge.
The role of focus in learning has not been well investigated in mathematics
education, although it could be. For example, one might study it by examining the effects
of tasks that incorporate distractions (i.e., that reduce focus) or by asking a number of
students to report on what they are thinking about at various times. It would be
interesting to know what students were focusing on during various kinds of lectures,
group problem-solving sessions, etc. It might also be interesting to know the effects of
The idea that knowledge is individually constructed leads to studies of how this
occurs, that is, to studies of the mind. It provided legitimacy for research that had been
largely blocked as late as the mid twentieth century by behaviorism, the then dominant
view in psychology. The idea was that science should be very reliable and predictive,
rather like physics, and thus should depend only on directly observable phenomena. This
lead to concentrating on stimuli and responses, and eventually to the idea and study of
conditioning. Such work was very reliable, but of limited use in explaining mathematical
understanding, problem solving, learning, etc. More importantly, the logical positivist
Zazkis (this volume) is that "there is no way of knowing about any metaphysical or
14
mathematical realities independently of our own experience" or, more briefly, one cannot
objectively know about things in the external world. Constructivism that includes this
idea is called radical constructivism and only some of the mathematics education
community ascribe to it. It is often difficult to see the effect of radical constructivism in
individual research papers. Viewed as a whole however, much of the literature has little
to say about the relationship between an externally presented mathematical task and a
boundary between "outside" and "inside" could be just a matter of chance, or it might
derive from a feeling that a person cannot really "know" about the "outside" task or that
all that really matters is the perception of the task -- basically radical constructivist points
of view. Seen in this way, radical constructivism may guide research to questions that do
not consider the boundary between "outside" and "inside" and be limiting in a way
similar to the way behaviorism was limiting some twenty or thirty years ago (although to
a lesser degree). For example, there is essentially no work on the role of mimicking in
distinguishing humans from other primates who favor emulation (Tomasello, 1997).
procedural knowledge (this volume) illustrates this, in that nothing could be said about
The central idea of radical constructivism, i.e., that one cannot objectively know
about the external world, follows from the fact that one has a single set of senses and, as a
result, has nothing independent against which to test perceptions. Indeed the perceptions
15
themselves depend on one's own conceptions and knowledge, and thus inherently lack
objectivity. While these points seem irrefutable, there is more to say. The important
thing about human intelligence is not that people cannot objectively know about the
external world (in an absolute sense), but rather that they can know about it (in an
knowing about the external world, they do gradually develop mental mechanisms that can
be used for reducing uncertainty about it. They are able to take several perspectives and
can call on previous experience. Observations may be revisited and the results of their
integration into a person's knowledge base can be questioned and adjusted (through
yield a reliable, integrated, inner picture of (part of) the external world requires a way of
such a way, but it is not deductive reasoning itself because (two-valued) logic does not fit
Radical constructivism does not take account of this perspective and implicitly
sees knowledge in an all or nothing way, i.e., as expressed by statements that have only
two truth values and that are combined using ordinary deductive reasoning and two-
valued logic. This view of knowledge and reasoning is very widely accepted, especially
in the West. However, in practice, people often appear to successfully use something like
logic and deductive reasoning with statements that are not quite certain, i.e., statements
neglect. We think approximate truth and reasoning can be precisely modeled. Doing so
16
might suggest a more moderate view of radical constructivism and thereby enlarge the
The uncertainty of statements can be viewed in two ways. One, that we will call
probabilistic uncertainty, views statements as two-valued, even though the value may not
be known. In the other, that we call synthetic uncertainty, the uncertainty is due to a
synthetic definition or concept (as opposed to the precise, analytic kind of definition
into a statement. For example, if one says a country M is "fairly democratic," one does
not mean that out of ten copies of M, eight would be democratic and two would be
"democratic." Indeed, in normal usage there might not be an exact meaning that is
Often probabilistic uncertainty does not combine well with deductive reasoning
because valid arguments can yield conclusions with probabilities much smaller than the
probabilities of the premises. For example, in modus ponens, if the premises both have
probability at least x, 0 x 1 , then one can only be sure the conclusion has probability
at least 2x -1, e.g., premises with probability at least 0.8 only yield a conclusion with
probability at least 0.6. Thus, at this degree of probability, chains of several deductions
yield conclusions with probabilities too small to be informative. However, often a person
makes an observation of great (but not absolute) certainty. For example, a reader of this
monograph may be quite certain that he or she is actually reading it, as opposed to
17
dreaming, say with probability 0.99. This level of certainty works very well with modus
ponens because premises with probability at least 0.99 yield a conclusion with probability
at least 0.98. This is also true for modes tollens and a number of other valid arguments.
The effect of this is that modest chains of deductions yield "almost certain" conclusions
For synthetic uncertainty the situation is better. One might analyze this kind of
uncertainty by assigning statements a numerical valve between 0 (false) and 1 (true), just
as in the case of probabilistic uncertainty. But here it seems appropriate to take the value
of the statement "p and q" to be the minimum of the individual values of p and q, the
value of the statement "p or q" to be the maximum of the individual values, and the value
of "not p" to be the one minus the value of p. These values together with the operations
"and," "or," and "not" form a lattice with all of the properties of a Boolean algebra except
the existence of complements, i.e., "p or not p" might not have value 1, and "p and not p"
might not have value 0. Using these values and operations, modus ponens and modes
tollens and many other arguments valid in ordinary logic are valid in the sense that if the
premises are approximately true (to some degree), then so is the conclusion (to the same
degree). Indeed, any argument valid in the ordinary sense is also valid in this
are reliable, i.e., do not lose truth value just as is the case with ordinary deductive
reasoning.
uncertainty suggests that a person can (tacitly) use it as part of the process of integrating
18
new information into his or her knowledge base and can very reliably know about the
external world, although perhaps not quite in the (two-valued, objective) sense referred to
investigations of the border between the external world and the inner mental world. In
particular, the relationship between a mathematical problem written on paper and the
corresponding inner speech version, that is normally produced when reading, can be
investigated. To what degree is this correspondence "accurate"? For example, one of our
college algebra students ignored the word "positive" in a test problem even after it was
pointed out to him. To what degree, and why, do such discrepancies occur? What
knowledge does a problem call to mind and by what mechanism? What part of solving a
When solving a linear equation a person may report nothing conscious between
writing one line and writing the next. This suggests a significant part of the process is not
conscious. In addition, if immediately after a line of the solution is written, that line is
covered from the solver's view, then the solving process may become very difficult. This
suggests the actual written work is an integral part of the cognitive process of solving
investigate the relationships between the nonconscious part, the conscious (mental) part,
the external physical part, and the way relevant information is brought to mind. Could
there be ways of writing when attempting the solution of a problem that enhance a
student's cognition?
These ideas extend far beyond the teaching and learning of elementary number
theory. However, number theory would be an ideal setting in which to investigate them.
19
THEORETICAL FRAMEWORKS
Several monograph authors refer to interesting theoretical frameworks, i.e., collections of
specialized, interrelated concepts that help express their point of view. One of these,
APOS theory, is used by Ferrari (this volume) and is central in the analysis of Brown, et
al. (this volume). Campbell and Zazkis have previously relied on APOS theory and here
it becomes part of their view of number theory as a conceptual field, in the sense of
Vergnaud. While we agree this can be a fruitful point of view, we also think APOS
theory might be more widely applied, and to that end, we will sketch an extended view of
it.
APOS is an acronym for action, process, object, and schema, which together form
Here, in discussing an idea such as number or function, we will reserve the term concept
mental knowledge -- knowledge that can become conscious, but cannot be precisely
communicated or directly observed, only inferred. Because APOS has been described by
Brown, et al. (this volume), we will only recall it through an example. A student, on first
only work with specific examples and could not think about or discuss functions in
general, he or she would have an action conception. Repeating this kind of action a
20
number of times and reflecting on it can lead to the ability to think about functions
without having a specific function in mind, i. e., can lead to interiorizing the experience
into a process conception of function. With such a conception the student could think in
a general way about carrying out the required operations without having a specific
formula such as f ( x ) 3 x 2 or might think of input and output, but still might not see
this process as a whole or single unit that could be acted upon. On (probably
function into an object conception, i.e., be able to think of it as a single unit that could be
acted upon.
functions can be regarded metaphorically as objects rather like physical objects -- Brown,
sense "divisible" is a property (of two numbers), rather than an object. In the context of
APOS theory, there seem to be two main ideas associated with "object." One of these,
perhaps intended by those referring to "cognitive object," is the idea that an object
without parts. The other is that an object conception is like a physical object -- something
that not only can be seen as an undivided whole, but can also be acted upon, can be an
element of a collection, etc. Separating these two ideas, wholeness and objectness,
development of conceptions.
We propose that concepts, and the associated conceptions, can be separated into
21
and activities (factoring, solving, dividing, integrating). Relations (less than, divides) can
be regarded as properties of two or more objects. In this categorization, objects can have
properties and be the subject of activities; properties can be associated with objects and
activities; and activities can transform objects to yield other objects. Thus "object" as
used in APOS theory might better be called entity (in this proposed categorization) with
its key feature being a unitary or gestalt nature that allows it to take on the role of object,
property, or activity. One might, for example, have an action, process, or entity
framework allows distinctions between kinds of entities, however it has no effect on the
APOS view of schema and does not alter the central ideas behind APOS theory itself.
or entity) may or may not have. This might be called efficacy and it permits fluent speech
and cognition. That is, an efficacious conception can be used in cognition (and speech)
experiences that went into its formation. This may appear to resemble the unitary nature
of entity conceptions, but is meant only to refer to the way a conception is used in speech
can be seen in the first transcript of Brown, et al. (this volume). There Adam appears to
be fluent with his conception of divisor because he begins calculating at once without
having to think about the meaning, despite only having an action or process, not an entity,
conception.
the lack of it are common. For example, most mathematicians have an efficacious, entity
22
conception of the concept "group;" they can understand or speak complex sentences
about groups without bringing the definition to mind. In contrast consider a somewhat
topological semigroup with identity. We suspect that many mathematicians would have
to consciously review the meaning of "clan" to fully comprehend, "In any clan there is a
minimal subclan connecting the identity to the minimal ideal." That is, they would not
have an efficacious conception of "clan" even though they would see it as an object.
logically as an entity, and to suspend or ignore the confusion associated with not having
either an efficacious or an entity conception, while they work procedurally at the action
conception. Many university students appear unable to apply this "bootstrap" process and
may even be unaware that such a thing is possible. They may also avoid use of
conceptions which are not efficacious. We suspect that beginning number theory students
who are not fluent with one of their conceptions -- divides, multiple, or factor -- may
avoid using it and the symbolic representation it calls for, perhaps substituting more
familiar terminology of their own, e.g., divides evenly. It would be good to know the
Zazkis (this volume) remarks in her conclusion that many preservice elementary
teachers are reluctant to adopt formal mathematical terminology, e.g., persistently using
terms like "goes into" instead of "divides." In explanation, following Sfard, she suggests
that mathematical objects emerge in an interaction between metaphor and rigor. The
23
We suspect that, as children, many of the students Zazkis is referring to
division with remainder zero. For many, this conception would be efficacious and have
the sign (name, symbol) "divides evenly" (or some synonym), with "divides" treated as a
contraction of "divides evenly." While for young children such a conception might be
metaphorical because numbers might be seen as attached to specific sets, for adults
numbers have become objects in their own right and this conception seems neither
especially metaphorical nor unrigorous. Later, when the standard mathematical concept
of divides is introduced, the students may construct another relation conception, but one
based on an object, i.e., the defining equation A=BC, and be encouraged to use what to
them is approximately the same sign, "divides." It is hard to see how two different
conceptions with (essentially) the same sign could both be efficacious. Furthermore, it
seems unlikely that the first conception ("divides evenly"), or any conception, could be
eradicated -- short of waiting a very long time. To take an everyday example, can people
stop having a conception of car, or for that matter of unicorn? In this situation, students
might best be helped to construct a schema containing both conceptions so that when one
comes to mind, the other is also readily available. Fortunately, the two conceptions are
complementary. The one based on an activity can yield numerical results such as 15|
1080, while the object conception can be used to support reasoning and proofs.
theoretical framework inspired by the three stages Piaget (1978) employed to describe
doing so with understanding. Brown, et al., substitute a procedural mathematical task for
24
the physical task. They follow Piaget in taking indicators of understanding to include the
ability to explain why parts of the procedure work and the ability to predict the results of
carrying out parts of the procedure before actually doing so. This rather broad
procedural mathematical task for a physical task may turn out not to be a very radical
i.e., to depend on the partly physical acts of writing and reading in a way inextricably
integrated with the mental activity. For example, in solving an equation one of our
calculus students wrote "+ 4" so that the horizontal bar of the "+" was half complete
causing the inscription to resemble "- 14" after which the student erroneously used "- 14."
Such errors depend specifically on interpreting the most recent inscription and could not
happen if the written work was merely a (partial) transcription of otherwise wholly
mental activity. Writing and seeing what she had written seems to have been an essential
Using the three stage framework to examine the way procedural knowledge
interesting picture of their preservice teachers' knowledge. But it also suggests a much
broader application. The teaching and learning of procedural knowledge has been
neglected in recent years by the mathematics education research community (Star, 2000).
Yet procedural knowledge is often most of what is assessed at the lower division
undergraduate level and some mathematicians believe it supports, and its mastery must
25
evidence this last belief is inaccurate, that the mastery of procedures need not precede the
provide situations, patterns, and experiences upon which reflection can lead to the
learn to execute the rules of the game of checkers (procedurally) after which one has an
opportunity to reflect and discern its strategies (Simon, Tzur, Heinz, & Kinzel, 2000). In
themselves -- the basis of the three stage framework. Perhaps one might think of a
Because of the nature of their data -- single interviews with preservice teachers --
Brown, et al., mainly describe the current state of their subjects' knowledge, not lasting
one can see students actively constructing understanding, e. g., Alice progresses from
Stage I to Stage II and Karyl moves through Stage II to Stage III. This suggests single
situations that facilitate students' progress from Stage I to Stage III, i.e., that facilitate the
number theory would be a good topic for such a study because it can be taught early,
minimizing the effects of prior knowledge and habits of mind so as to isolate situations
26
that facilitate conceptual learning. Any results, however, might be of interest far beyond
them, teachers could try to probe students' understanding or help them with
volume) seem sufficiently novel that students first resort to their calculators, and when
The two problems: (1) Can you find a rule for determining the number of different
divisors of any number, given its prime factorization? (Teppo, this volume). (2) Given
an N K grid, how many squares are crossed by the diagonal? (Edwards & Zazkis, this
volume), are requests for a generalization, with the accompanying need to consider
examples and make and test conjectures. Both problems can be used with preservice
27
relationships between consecutive terms and explain their reasoning (in the form of
from the chapters, although some of these can also be found elsewhere. Teppo's
classroom vignette can serve as a prototype for guiding students to think for themselves,
using appropriate teacher scaffolding and a suitable didactic object (divisor table), while
The interviews of Brown, et al. (this volume) were not meant as teaching sessions,
but seemed to help students develop insights. Perhaps with some modest adjustments
they could serve as a model for teaching the understanding of procedures on an individual
or small group level. Providing individual assistance is a small, but important, role of
with lists of problems and questions, might prove helpful to teachers. Indeed, it might be
useful to circulate such interview material, together with annotations on student reactions,
The value of appropriate generic proofs for exposition in number theory was argued
convincingly, along with some general principles for selecting a particular case. There is
also the admonition that writing up a more formal proof can be a nontrivial task for
The idea that the type and sequence of problems is of "paramount pedagogical
importance" is not new, nor is the idea that such sequencing of tasks should follow
students' conceptual development (Harel, this volume). What is new is the somewhat
counterintuitive notion that teaching, at least for mathematical induction, should begin
28
with suitably chosen "harder" problems, rather than the more usual progression from
influenced students' success in the mathematical induction teaching experiment were the
generalization), the opportunity to clarify and rewrite one's solutions, and the request that
students summarize the most important ideas of the mathematical induction unit in their
Elementary number theory tasks are a rich and accessible area with which to enhance
elementary number theory, but others suggest using number theory tasks to investigate
REFERENCES
Bills, L. (1996). The use of examples in the teaching and learning of mathematics. In L.
Puig and A. Gutierrez (Eds.), Proceedings of the 20th Conference of the
International Group for the Psychology of Mathematics Education (Vol. 2, pp. 81-
88), University of Valencia, Spain.
Billstein, R., Libeskind, S., and Lott, J. (1984). A problem solving approach to
mathematics for elementary school teachers, 2nd edition. Menlo Park, California:
Benjamin Cummings Publishing Company.
29
and learning, New York: Macmillan Publishing Company.
Hazzan, O. (1999). Reducing abstraction level when learning abstract algebra concepts.
Educational Studies in Mathematics, 40(1), 71-90.
Heid, M. K. (1988). Resequencing skills and concepts in applied calculus using the
computer as a tool. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 19, 3-25.
Peterson, I. (2000). The power of partitions: Writing a whole number as the sum of
smaller numbers springs a mathematical surprise. Science News, 157(25), 396-397.
Simon, M. A., Tzur, R., Heinz, K. & Kinzel, M. (2000). Articulating theoretical
constructs for mathematical reasoning. In M. L. Fernández (Ed.), Proceedings of the
22nd Annual Meeting of the North American Chapter of the International Group for
the Psychology of Mathematics Education (Vol. 1, pp. 213-218), Columbus, OH:
ERIC Clearinghouse for Science, Mathematics, and Environmental Education.
Tomasello, M. (1997). Human see, human do. Natural History, 106(8), 45-47.
Towers, J., Martin, L., & Pirie, S. (2000). Growing mathematical understanding:
Layered observations. In M. L. Fernández (Ed.), Proceedings of the 22nd Annual
Meeting of the North American Chapter of the International Group for the
Psychology of Mathematics Education (Vol. 1, pp. 225-230), Columbus, OH: ERIC
Clearinghouse for Science, Mathematics, and Environmental Education.
30
31