Philosophy of Immunology
Philosophy of Immunology
Philosophy of Immunology
Philosophy of
Philosophy of Immunology
as Open Access on Cambridge Core at http://dx. doi
.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Immunology
About the Series Series Editors
This Cambridge Elements series provides Grant Ramsey
concise and structured introductions to KU Leuven, Belgium
Thomas Pradeu
all of the central topics in the philosophy Michael Ruse
of biology. Contributors to the series Florida State
are cutting-edge researchers who offer University
balanced, comprehensive coverage
of multiple perspectives, while also
developing new ideas and arguments
from a unique viewpoint.
PHILOSOPHY OF
IMMUNOLOGY
Thomas Pradeu
CNRS & University of Bordeaux
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
University Printing House, Cambridge CB2 8BS, United Kingdom
One Liberty Plaza, 20th Floor, New York, NY 10006, USA
477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, VIC 3207, Australia
314–321, 3rd Floor, Plot 3, Splendor Forum, Jasola District Centre,
New Delhi – 110025, India
79 Anson Road, #06–04/06, Singapore 079906
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781108727501
DOI: 10.1017/9781108616706
© Thomas Pradeu 2019
This work is in copyright. It is subject to statutory exceptions and to the provisions of
relevant licensing agreements; with the exception of the Creative Commons version
the link for which is provided below, no reproduction of any part of this work may take
place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press.
An online version of this work is published at doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706 under
a Creative Commons Open Access license CC-BY-NC-ND 4.0 which permits re-use,
distribution and reproduction in any medium for non-commercial purposes providing
appropriate credit to the original work is given. You may not distribute derivative
works without permission. To view a copy of this license, visit https://
creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0
All versions of this work may contain content reproduced under license from third
parties. Permission to reproduce this third-party content must be obtained from these
third-parties directly.
When citing this work, please include a reference to the DOI 10.1017/9781108616706
First published 2019
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library.
ISBN 978-1-108-72750-1 Paperback
ISSN 2515-1126 (online)
ISSN 2515-1118 (print)
Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of
URLs for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this publication
and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain,
accurate or appropriate.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Immunology
DOI: 10.1017/9781108616706
First published online: November 2019
Thomas Pradeu1,2
References 64
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Immunology 1
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
2 Elements in the Philosophy of Biology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Immunology 3
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
4 Elements in the Philosophy of Biology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Immunology 5
Tonsils
Thymus
Lymph node
Thoracic duct
Liver
Spleen
Kidneys Peyer’s patch
(in the small intestine)
Large intestine
Lymphatic
vessels
Bone marrow
Figure 2.1 Human immune system. The human immune system, which
comprises different organs (thymus, bone marrow, spleen, lymph nodes, and so
on), different cells (both circulating and resident) and molecules, and a network
of lymphatic vessels, exerts its influence everywhere in the organism. (Figure
drawn by Wiebke Bretting).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
6 Elements in the Philosophy of Biology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Immunology 7
Hosts and invaders continuously adapt one to the other. This constitutes
one of the main reasons why immune systems are so intricate, with so
many different components acting at various levels. Often, a pathogen
evolves a way to evade a given recognition system of its host species, but
then the host species evolves new recognition systems, which in turn
might be circumvented by the pathogen. Such host–pathogen competition
often takes the form of manipulation of the immune system by pathogens
(Finlay and McFadden 2006). For example, various bacteria display
molecular patterns that look like those of the host (molecular mimicry).
Furthermore, some bacteria can establish residence within immune cells,
which enables them to partly escape the immune response – as
Mycobacterium tuberculosis does in macrophages, for instance.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
8 Elements in the Philosophy of Biology
has long been used to make a distinction between two arms of immunity, namely
innate and adaptive immunity (Box 2.3).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
10 Elements in the Philosophy of Biology
When you cut yourself, in addition to the well-known action of platelets, which
initiate blood clot and vasculature closure, a horde of immune cells is required at
every stage of the repair process to insure proper wound healing (Gurtner et al.
2008; Wynn and Vannella 2016). The three key stages are inflammation, new tissue
formation, and remodeling. The main immune cells participating in tissue repair are
neutrophils and macrophages. The plasticity and adaptation to context of these cells
are crucial (Laurent et al. 2017). Immune cells are also important in processes of
regeneration, such as those found in plants, hydra, arthropods, and amphibians, and
by which entire complex structures such as limbs can regrow (Eming et al. 2014).
Another key daily activity of the immune system is the clearance of bodily debris,
coordinated by phagocytotic cells (Nagata 2018). In addition, the immune system is
essential for development, that is, the early construction of the organism. This
includes the indispensable role of immune-mediated apoptosis and phagocytosis
very early on in many developmental processes (Wynn et al. 2013; Okabe and
Medzhitov 2016), as well as the role of the complement in development (Ricklin
et al. 2010; Stephan et al. 2012) (e.g., phagocytosis mediates the indispensable
elimination of excessive tissues; the complement, a cascade of proteins in the blood,
remodels synaptic connections in the developing nervous system). Importantly,
even though the above description applies mainly to animals, the observation that
the immune system realizes various activities beyond defense holds across all living
organisms; for example, CRISPR-Cas systems in prokaryotes participate not only
in defense but also in repair.
Many of the same actors that ensure the defense of the organism against
pathogens, therefore, are equally central for processes previously considered as
nonimmune and which overlap to a significant degree (Figure 2.2). Perhaps one
could even consider that the very division of these processes into such cate-
gories as “defense,” “repair,” and “development” reflects more the way we, as
investigators, address questions about bodily systems (and divide such pro-
cesses into convenient categories) than real differences in nature. From this
point of view, there would be much to say in favor of a revised epistemology of
immunology, understood as a reflection on how the categories by which the
immune system has been conceived (in the context of the division into systems)
could be redefined and redrawn.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Immunology 11
Defence
Maintenance of Clearance
tissue homeostasis
Immune system
Development Repair
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
12 Elements in the Philosophy of Biology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Immunology 13
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
14 Elements in the Philosophy of Biology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Immunology 15
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
16 Elements in the Philosophy of Biology
(Billingham et al. 1953). For Burnet, therefore, the self is acquired, not innate:
the organism acquires at an early ontogenetic stage the capacity to recognize its
own constituents and to avoid their destruction (Burnet and Fenner 1949;
Burnet 1969). But Burnet argues that, in nature, contrary to what happens in
these experimental settings, the immunological self reflects the genetically
endogenous components of the organism because the repertoire of immune
receptors is constituted on the basis of these endogenous elements present in the
body (Burnet 1962). Burnet considers several obvious challenges to the self–
nonself framework, including autoimmune diseases and foeto-maternal toler-
ance as well as other forms of immunological tolerance (that is, the absence of
destruction of a foreign entity by the immune system). But he treats them as
exceptions to the general rule and considers that these exceptions must be
explained via specific mechanisms (pathological mechanisms in the case of
autoimmune diseases, and particular provisory mechanisms in the case of foeto-
maternal tolerance) (Burnet 1969). All these reflections constituted the founda-
tions of a fruitful theoretical and conceptual framework about the self and
nonself, which was developed by Burnet over more than three decades, and
which combined in an innovative way molecular, cellular, ecological,
and medical considerations (Burnet 1940, 1969, pp. 309–310). Burnet shared
the 1960 Nobel Prize in Physiology/Medicine with Medawar for what was
essentially a contribution of a conceptual and hypothetical nature, as acknowl-
edged by Burnet himself (Burnet 1960, p. 700).
From a theoretical viewpoint, what Burnet sees as his main contribution to
immunology is not primarily the self–nonself theory but rather the “clonal
selection theory.” The clonal selection theory goes against instructionist
approaches to antibody formation (especially that of Linus Pauling) by stating
that, when an antigen penetrates into the organism, immune cells bearing
receptors specific for this antigen undergo selection and are subsequently
responsible for the elimination of that antigen (Burnet 1959, p. 54). Burnet
therefore proposes the adoption of a Darwinian framework at the cell level
within the multicellular organism (Burnet 1959, p. 64) – an idea that had been
suggested before him but that Burnet framed in a much more precise way
(Schaffner 1992; Silverstein 2002).
Nonetheless, the clonal selection theory and the self–nonself theory are
intimately connected, so much so that Burnet generally argues for them in
parallel (e.g., (Burnet 1959, 1969)). The phenomena that the clonal selection
theory seeks to explain are immune recognition of the antigen, immune toler-
ance, and the acquisition of “self-knowledge” by the organism. To account for
these phenomena, Burnet proposes the existence of two selective processes: one
occurs in adult life, when an antigen enters into the body, as we just saw; but
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Immunology 17
another selective process occurs long before, in early life, and this other process
is the elimination of immune cells that recognize “self” components (Burnet
1959). This explains why, in 1969, Burnet writes that the clonal selection theory
provides “the simplest possible interpretation of how the body’s own constitu-
ents are shielded from immunological attack” (Burnet 1969, p. 12).
From the second half of the twentieth century to the present day, the self–
nonself framework has been adopted by a large majority of immunologists and
enriched by a host of experimental, conceptual, and theoretical contributions
(e.g., Bretscher and Cohn 1970; von Boehmer and Kisielow 1990; Janeway
1992; Langman and Cohn 2000). Today, the self–nonself remains the dominant,
if often implicit, framework in which immunologists conceive how the immune
system works (e.g., Stefanová et al. 2002; Goodnow et al. 2005; Jiang and Chess
2009; Fulton et al. 2015). This is particularly illustrated by the fact that when
a novel immune system is identified, as recently happened with the CRISPR-
Cas systems in archaea and bacteria, scientists spontaneously use the self–
nonself vocabulary to account for its functioning (Nuñez et al. 2015) (this
comes in addition to the idea of CRISPR-Cas as a system of defense, as
discussed in the previous section). Together with the persistent use of the
self–nonself vocabulary in several other domains (including, for instance,
studies on autoimmune diseases and transplantation), this confirms the long-
standing influence of this framework in immunology over the last six decades.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
18 Elements in the Philosophy of Biology
where they find nutrients and protection from competitors, among other things
(Donaldson et al. 2016). Microbes can also manipulate their host in many
different ways (Sansonetti and Di Santo 2007). Finally, it is crucial to understand
that the interaction between host and resident microbes is the product of
a complex equilibrium, in which the nature of the ecological relationship can
change through time depending on the circumstances and switch from mutualism
to commensalism to parasitism (microbes that switch from the status of symbionts
to pathogens have sometimes been called “pathobionts” (Chow et al. 2011)).
Recent work on immunological tolerance and the intimate dialogue between
host and microbes across the living world invalidates the claim that the immune
system eliminates foreign (nonself) entities. In the last two decades, symbiosis
in general and symbiotic interactions with microbes more specifically have been
recognized as ubiquitous and essential phenomena in nature. The specific
contribution of immunology to this literature is to ask how symbiotic entities
can be tolerated by the immune system and how they interact with this system in
several central physiological processes (see Box 3.1).
Delineation
Filtering over presence
Cohesion
Functional integration
Promotion of cooperation Near-complete
decomposability
Copperation and absence of
conflict
Figure 3.1 The three main activities by which the immune system
participates in the individuation of biological entities and how they map
onto the traditional conception of a biological individual. Filtering over
entry sheds light on the idea of the individual as a countable and relatively well-
delineated entity, while filtering over presence and promotion of cooperation
shed light on the idea of the individual as a cohesive entity.
determines which elements are tolerated, and therefore can remain part of that
living thing, and which elements are rejected, and therefore cannot remain part
of that living thing. But what exactly does the immune system detect in this
process of internal filtering? Although it has long been said that the immune
system controls the identity of the elements with which it interacts (that is, their
conformity with the self), my own view is that the immune system eliminates
elements that change too abruptly, while tolerating elements that change slowly
(Pradeu et al. 2013). Regardless of the criterion one adopts, though, it remains
that the immune system constitutes such a filter over internal elements in
addition to filtering the entry of external elements at bodily interfaces.
Lastly, the immune system plays an important role in the promotion of
cooperation between the components of the organism. It does so in two different
ways. First, the immune system can ensure long-distance communication
between remote components of the organism. In plants this is done through
the vasculature and thanks to metabolites (Shah and Zeier 2013). In metazoans
this is made possible by different processes, most prominently the unique
mobility of immune cells. For example, immune cells can inform distant organs
about the presence of a pathogen in the organism and also contribute to tissue
remodeling in remote sites (Eom and Parichy 2017). As we will see in Section 5,
other systems like the endocrine and the nervous systems are also capable of
long-distance communication in metazoans, but the immune system is unique in
its capacity to send cells to every compartment of the organism. Second, the
immune system can eliminate noncooperative elements (“cheaters”), for
instance, cancer cells (see next section) (Michod 1999; Frank 2007), via the
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Immunology 23
but this distinction is not to be confused with the opposition between the
“endogenous” (what comes from the inside) and the “exogenous” (what
comes from the outside). The resulting living thing does not coincide with the
traditional self and cannot be accounted for by Burnet’s self–nonself theory.
A related idea is that the process of dual filtering presented here is dynamic
and never-ending. There is, therefore, a constant re-delineation, through the
action of the immune system, of the constituents and boundaries of a living
thing. This sheds a crucial light on the diachronic identity of biological indivi-
duals (Wiggins 2016). An entity that is part of a living thing at a given moment
(for example, an immunologically tolerated virus) can cease to be part of that
living thing later in time (for example, if this virus is eventually eliminated by
the immune system). The resulting individuality is relative and changes con-
tinuously, but the criterion used to establish what is part and what is not part of
a living thing remains constant and offers a precise delineation.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Immunology 25
immunity: key immunological processes occur at the level of each cell (for
example, any cell of the organism infected by a virus will respond by triggering
a diversity of protective mechanisms, including the production of interferons
and other cytokines – a phenomenon often referred to as cell intrinsic immu-
nity – which can alter neighboring cells about the presence of the virus)
(Goubau et al. 2013) and at the level of each tissue. Most of the time, one can
distinguish degrees of immunological responses: in most multicellular organ-
isms, for instance, cell and tissue immunological responses are strongly con-
trolled and coordinated at the systemic level, so the systemic level seems to be
the level at which the highest degree of immunological integration is realized.
Interestingly, in some cases, the highest degree of immunological integration is
realized at the level of a colony rather than intuitively defined individuals. For
example, some data in a number of social insects such as termites and honey
bees suggest that key immunological processes occur at the colony level, which
has led to the concept of “social immunity” (Cremer et al. 2007; Jones et al.
2018) and has sometimes been used to support the superorganism hypothesis.
The conclusion of this discussion is that recent immunological research has
seen extensive revisions of its core concepts (particularly “self,” “tolerance,”
and “microbe”), which in turn have led to a significant reassessment of our
traditional understanding of biological individuality insofar as a living thing can
be seen as an immunologically unified chimera (Gill et al. 2006; Eberl 2010;
Bosch and McFall-Ngai 2011; Pradeu 2012). But do these changes have any
practical consequences? The short answer is that they have many practical
consequences, particularly from a therapeutic point of view. Let’s take two
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Immunology 27
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Immunology 29
“Why don’t we get more cancer?” asks Mina Bissell, a prominent specialist in
cancer (Bissell and Hines 2011). Certainly, most of us think that we do see
enough cancer around us. After all, approximately 90 million people had cancer
in 2015 (Vos et al. 2016) and cancer kills around 8.8 million people each year
(Wang et al. 2016). The 2014 World Cancer Report of the World Health
Organization estimated that there were about 14 million new cases of cancer
each year and that the financial costs of cancer were above US $1.16 trillion
per year. In this context, asking why we don’t get more cancer may seem
surprising if not shocking.
Yet Bissell’s question is entirely legitimate. We probably all have occult
tumors (Bissell and Hines 2011) – what Folkman and Kalluri called “cancer
without disease” (Folkman and Kalluri 2004). Autopsies of people dead due to
reasons unrelated to cancer reveal the high frequency of tumors, which can be
large but do not spread and do not seem to threaten the host. Prostate tumors can
be found in 30 to 70 percent of men over 60 years old, breast tumors in 7 to
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
30 Elements in the Philosophy of Biology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Immunology 31
of neoplastic cells” (Thomas 1982, p. 330). Thomas was convinced that humans
produce tumors all the time but keep them under control, thanks to the action of
the immune system. Burnet later expanded this idea and coined the term
immunological surveillance (sometimes called immunosurveillance) (Burnet
1970). According to immunological surveillance, the immune system is capable
of detecting and eliminating the “altered self” (Houghton 1994), that is, “new
antigens” (Burnet 1970, p. 7) (antigens that are different from those of the body,
also called “neoantigens” (Schumacher and Schreiber 2015)). In the 1970s, the
idea of immunological surveillance started to decline because several experi-
ments suggested that immunodeficient mice did not have a higher susceptibility
to spontaneous or chemically induced tumors (Stutman 1974). As a result it was
almost entirely abandoned for several years. A clear indication of this is the fact
that the highly influential review on the “hallmarks of cancer” by Hanahan and
Weinberg published in 2000 (Hanahan and Weinberg 2000) ignores the role of
the immune system in cancer (this was corrected in (Hanahan and Weinberg
2011)).
At the beginning of the 2000s, a series of experiments showed the impact of
the immune system on cancer development (Shankaran et al. 2001; Dunn et al.
2002). The supposedly immunodeficient mice used in experiments from the
1970s onward to invalidate the idea of immunosurveillance in fact had an
immune system (they had NK cells, γδ T cells, and even some αβ T cells)
(Dunn et al. 2002). During this period, the involvement of both innate and
adaptive immune components in cancer control was demonstrated (immuno-
chemical or functional ablations of NKT, γδ T cells, NK cells, αβ T cells, IFN-γ,
and interleukin 12 all lead to increased susceptibility to cancer).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Immunology 33
or suppress the immune response) and have a higher fitness in the immuno-
competent host (a process similar to the selection of more resistant pathogens).
Therefore, Robert Schreiber and colleagues proposed to use the term immu-
noediting instead of the traditional notion of immunosurveillance, reflecting the
fact that the immune system not only monitors tumors but also shapes them,
with both beneficial and detrimental consequences for the host (Dunn et al.
2002; Schreiber et al. 2011). Immunoediting is a more encompassing and more
accurate concept, especially because it emphasizes the diachronic character of
cancer development.
The concept of immunoediting is well-suited to describe the dual host-
protecting and tumor-sculpting actions of the immune system. According to
its proponents, immunoediting encompasses three different though largely
overlapping processes, referred to as the “3 e’s” (see Figure 4.1): “elimina-
tion” (which corresponds to the classic idea of immunological surveillance,
that is, the destruction of tumor cells by the immune system), “equili-
brium” (the immune system iteratively selects and/or promotes the genera-
tion of tumor cell variants with increasing capacities to survive immune
destruction), and “escape” (the immunologically sculpted tumor expands
beyond control in the host) (Dunn et al. 2002). In 2007, a landmark study
by Schreiber’s group confirmed the existence of the equilibrium phase
(Koebel et al. 2007).
The processes by which the immune system can have a tumor-promoting
effect go well beyond immunoediting and are actually quite diverse. In
particular, tumor-associated macrophages (TAMs) can sometimes be tumor-
suppressive, but in a majority of cases they favor tumor initiation, progres-
sion, and metastasis (Mantovani et al. 1992; Wynn et al. 2013). Indeed,
macrophages can sustain the chronic inflammation that often plays a role in
tumor initiation and promotion (Mantovani et al. 2008), skew adaptive
immune responses, and facilitate cell growth, angiogenesis (Murdoch
et al. 2008), matrix deposition, tissue remodeling (Mantovani et al. 2013;
Afik et al. 2016), and metastasis (Qian and Pollard 2010). The exact effects
of macrophages located in or around the tumor also depend on the tem-
poral sequence of events: tumor-preventing macrophages can switch to
a tumor-promoting role depending on the cues they receive from the
tumor microenvironment (Wynn et al. 2013). So-called myeloid-derived
suppressor cells (MDSCs) contribute to cancer and metastasis (Kumar et al.
2016), and tumor-associated neutrophils (Fridlender et al. 2009) as well as
regulatory T cells (Tanaka and Sakaguchi 2017) also, in many circum-
stances, can promote cancer.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
Figure 4.1 The three phases of immunoediting. According to the concept of immunoediting, three phases must be distinguished in the
interactions between the immune system and the tumor: (a) elimination, which corresponds to the destruction of tumor cells by the immune
system; (b) equilibrium, in which the immune system selects and/or promotes the generation of immunologically resistant tumor cell
variants; and (c) escape, which corresponds to the expansion of the immunologically shaped tumor that is now beyond the control of the
immune system. (Figure drawn by Wiebke Bretting, after (Dunn et al. 2002)).
Philosophy of Immunology 35
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
36 Elements in the Philosophy of Biology
environment includes the tissue context located at the vicinity of the tumor
(sometimes called the tumor microenvironment), but also elements located
quite remotely from the tumor in the organism (such as some immune-
associated organs and the microbiota, which recently has been proven to
influence cancer progression and therapies) (Zitvogel et al. 2018; Binnewies
et al. 2018; Laplane et al. 2018). Even authors who initially focused on
intrinsic molecular aspects of cancer development have later emphasized the
importance of the tumor microenvironment (Hanahan and Weinberg 2011).
Targeting the tumor microenvironment also offers enriched therapeutic stra-
tegies (e.g., (Joyce 2005)). There is a growing consensus that the immune
system plays a crucial role in the tumor microenvironment (Bissell and
Radisky 2001; Binnewies et al. 2018; Maman and Witz 2018). In fact,
given the centrality of immune components in the organization of, and
control over, the local tissue, it seems reasonable to say that every cancer
involves the immune system, which necessarily intervenes, at one point or
another, in the shaping of the local context that enables the tumor to emerge,
grow, and perhaps spread.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
38 Elements in the Philosophy of Biology
Immune System
Eliminates
abnormal cells
Immune System
Controls
Tissue Organization
Context
Mechanical
Pathogens Wounds
pressure
Immune System
Controls
Tissue Organization
resemble “wounds that do not heal” (Dvorak 1986, 2015; Schäfer and Werner
2008), which means that, in cancer, normal repair mechanisms are triggered but
generally without reaching the “resolution phase” (which, in the physiological
context, is indispensable to terminate the reparative process (Gurtner et al.
2008)). Furthermore, the tumor itself can be a major source of perturbation of
the local context: it can influence the immune system through a variety of
cytokines and can also increase inflammation and wounding, modify blood
vessels, reshape the extracellular matrix, or exert a mechanical pressure, among
many other possibilities. This is often described as the “hijacking” or “co-
option” by the tumor of physiological pathways and of the tissue microenvir-
onment (Kitano 2004a; Greaves 2007; Lean and Plutynski 2016). Despite its
importance, one must keep in mind that such co-option is only one of the many
ways in which the local context can become abnormal and favor the contribu-
tion of immune processes to cancer progression.
In all these contexts, immune-mediated decohesion results from the abnormal
realization of normal processes, and this can help explain why tumors largely
resemble organs (Egeblad et al. 2010) and are the products of classic develop-
mental (da Costa 2001; Radisky et al. 2001; Huang et al. 2009) and reparative
pathways (Bissell and Radisky 2001) realized in an abnormal context. There is no
doubt that the outcome is pathological (the promotion of a cancerous tumor,
including in some cases metastatic spread), but the immune system, in many of
these circumstances, does not strictly speaking “dysfunction”; it just does what it
always does (maintaining the local environment, repairing in case of wound, etc.).
If the view presented here is correct, then a much richer picture emerges
about how the immune system influences cancer and, ultimately, of potential
therapeutic opportunities as well. Indeed, the immune system influences cancer
through different processes (elimination, containment, maintenance, repair, and
so on), via many actors (not only lymphocytes, but also macrophages, neutro-
phils, and various cytokines), at several different levels (within the tumor, but
also around the tumor, in the whole tissue, and at a systemic level in the
organism), and at all temporal stages of cancer progression (initiation, neoplas-
tic progression, and metastasis). Additionally, the influence of the immune
system on the cancerous tumor can be negative (the immune system prevents
cancer progression) or positive (the immune system promotes cancer progres-
sion). All this suggests a whole series of new opportunities for investigating
immunotherapies, which could, at least in principle, target these different
processes, actors, levels, and temporal stages. Current immunotherapies (parti-
cularly immune checkpoint inhibitors and CAR-T cells (Joyce and Fearon 2015;
June and Sadelain 2018)) focus on lymphocytes in terms of actors and on
elimination and maintenance and rupture of chronicity in terms of processes,
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Immunology 43
but many other possibilities exist. Depending on where we are in the cycle of
cancer–immune system interactions and on the actors of the tumor microenvir-
onment involved, some therapeutic strategies will aim at normalization while
others will aim at denormalization. Examples of normalization include the
reduction of the level of inflammation in the tissue, the elimination of pathogens
and/or chronic wounds, the restoration of immune accessibility to the tumor,
and the facilitation of the resolving phase of tissue repair. In contrast, denorma-
lization would be a major aim when the immune system interacts with tumor
components as if they were normal constituents of the body, as, for example,
when the immune system is tolerogenic in the context of chronically present
tumor antigens or when the immune system continuously triggers repair path-
ways to respond to a local cancerous context that displays many features usually
associated with a wound.
In summary, this section has shown that focusing on the immune system is
essential for anyone studying cancer. Cancer is a disease of multicellularity
and, more specifically, of the cohesion of the multicellular organism.
Immunological surveillance constitutes one of the main and best described
mechanisms by which the multicellular organism exerts control over lower-
level entities. A major result of recent research is that the immune system can
both restrain and promote cancerous tumors, which may seem, at first sight,
paradoxical. Yet the situation becomes less paradoxical when one realizes that
immune-mediated decohesion is often due to an abnormal context rather than
a dysfunctional immune system. We have suggested here an extended view of
cancer–immune interactions, which opens up many opportunities for investi-
gating new mechanisms of tumor control and tumor promotion and, ulti-
mately, for developing novel therapeutic opportunities based on the action
of the immune system.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
44 Elements in the Philosophy of Biology
If you fall asleep reading this Element, this is probably simply because you are
tired or because its content is not entertaining enough. But if you are literally
falling asleep, then perhaps you have narcolepsy, a disorder estimated to affect
around one in 2,000 people. The symptoms of narcolepsy, which usually begin in
adolescence or early adulthood, include daytime sleepiness and, in some cases,
cataplexy – sudden muscle weakness during wakefulness that causes falls. Severe
forms of narcolepsy are associated with abnormally low numbers of neurons that
produce hypocretin, a protein that controls sleep–wake cycles. Recently, it was
suggested that narcolepsy might be the consequence of an autoimmune response
(following older work on association with some HLA alleles). Narcoleptic
patients have immune CD4+ memory T cells that target peptide fragments of
hypocretin, suggesting that autoimmunity could play a role in narcolepsy,
although the exact causal relationships remain to be determined (Liblau 2018).
A problem that affects many more people than narcolepsy is depression. All
readers of this Element certainly know somebody who has depression and/or
have experienced depression themselves. Depressive disorder, a multiform and
multifactorial condition, was estimated to affect 8.5 percent of people in Europe
(Ayuso-Mateos et al. 2001). For a long time, depression has been considered to
be a psychiatric disease, usually treated with serotonin-tweaking drugs like
Prozac. Yet a growing number of researchers look at depression from an
additional perspective based on immunology (Bullmore 2018; Dantzer 2018)
(more about this example below).
Such examples and many others suggest that the nervous system and the
immune system, far from being separated, can interact intimately in almost all
metazoans, including humans. The study of these interactions has given rise to
an interdisciplinary domain, neuroimmunology. My main objective in this
section is very modest: it is to offer a conceptual clarification of the different
issues raised by neuroimmunology, which often remain intertwined and insuffi-
ciently distinguished. To do so, after a short history of neuroimmunology,
I present important results concerning the interactions between the nervous
and the immune systems in health and disease. I then propose to distinguish five
different conceptual questions when dealing with neuroimmune interactions,
and finally I mention some important philosophical consequences neuroimmu-
nology can have, particularly about cognition. So, what will be said in this
section is no more than a preliminary conceptual and philosophical exploration
of the field of neuroimmunology. My hope is simply to convince some readers
to take up the challenge of immersing themselves in this fascinating domain.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Immunology 45
1
I thank Jan Pieter Konsman for many discussions about the history of neuroimmunology and
psychoneuroimmunology.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
46 Elements in the Philosophy of Biology
peripheral nervous system (PNS, the part of the nervous system that is outside the
brain and spinal cord).
Strikingly, the fields of neuroimmunology and psychoneuroimmunology,
since their inception, have given rise to controversies and have often been
accused of not following the most rigorous scientific standards. This accusation
has particularly targeted psychoneuroimmunology, as illustrated, for instance,
by the disagreement between (Maddox 1984) and (Ader and Cohen 1985), and
as discussed in detail by (Cohen 2006).
Here we will use neuroimmunology in an inclusive sense to refer to all the
approaches nowadays that study interactions between the nervous and the immune
system, at all levels, in health and disease, and with or without a focus on behavior.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Immunology 47
Figure 5.1 Microglia and their many activities. Microglia are a major element
of the brain’s immune system. These resident immune phagocytes constantly
monitor their microenvironment and participate in many processes in health and
disease, including engulfment of neural progenitor cells (NPCs), acute response
to CNS damage, engulfment of synaptic material, and homeostatic surveillance.
(Figure drawn by Wiebke Bretting).
the activities of immune cells include but are not limited to defense, comprising
also development, repair, clearance of debris, and so on (Michell-Robinson
et al. 2015).
The long-dominant view has been that, in healthy conditions, the brain is
devoid of lymphocytes, as these cells could cause major damage. Recently,
however, a “peri-cerebral” adaptive immune system has been described
(Figure 5.2): the meninges contain lymphatic vessels that remove waste from
the parenchyma, can relay information about possible infections in the brain,
but also harbor peripheral immune cells that communicate with the brain via
cytokines (Louveau et al. 2015b; Kipnis 2016). This discovery confirms that
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
48 Elements in the Philosophy of Biology
Figure 5.2 Immune communication between meninges and the brain. Apart
from microglia, immune cells are generally not present in the brain, as, in
nonpathological situations, they are thought to not cross the blood–brain barrier.
However, meninges contain lymphatic vessels and peripheral immune cells,
which communicate with the brain via cytokines. (Figure drawn by Wiebke
Bretting).
there is a rich immunological crosstalk between the brain and the rest of the
body, particularly via the meninges.
Collectively, these data confirm that there is a cellular and molecular immune
system of the brain. The actors and mechanisms just described come in addition
to various cell-intrinsic innate defense mechanisms used by neurons in case of
viral infections (Ordovas-Montanes et al. 2015).
Not only is there an immune system of the brain, but recent research confirms
that there are many interactions between the nervous and the immune system in
a healthy organism, with much richer communication pathways than initially
suspected (Figure 5.3). These interactions occur at various levels: molecules,
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Immunology 49
cells, organs, and at the systemic level. There is a dense sympathetic innervation
of all lymphoid organs (Dantzer 2018). The PNS regulates immunological
development (the sympathetic nervous system regulates haematopoiesis), prim-
ing (neurons influence the triggering of an immune response in lymph nodes),
and deployment (peripheral neurons associated with vessels can impact on
leukocyte recruitment into peripheral tissues) (Ordovas-Montanes et al.
2015). In response to pathogens or tissue perturbation, immune cells are
activated at the periphery and release cytokines and other inflammatory mole-
cules; these molecules have an impact on local sensory neurons and influence
signaling to the CNS (Chavan et al. 2017). Furthermore, pro-inflammatory
cytokines produced by immune cells at the periphery communicate with the
brain through afferent nerves, a process that leads to the production (by acti-
vated microglia) of other pro-inflammatory mediators in the brain itself. (Using
a perhaps slippery vocabulary, some authors say that the brain forms, via
neuromediators and immune mediators, an “image” of immune responses
occurring in peripheral tissues (Dantzer et al. 2008)).
Interactions between the nervous and the immune system can have important
functional consequences. For example, homeostatic circuits regulating tem-
perature maintenance, blood pressure, and intestinal mobility involve immune
cells. The vagus nerve is important for detecting and reporting on peripheral
immune responses and, in turn, efferent signals from the CNS are indispensable
for the regulation of inflammatory responses (Ordovas-Montanes et al. 2015).
Kevin Tracey in the 2000s proposed calling this neuroimmune network the
“inflammatory reflex” (reviewed in (Chavan et al. 2017)), a concept enriched
and discussed in subsequent research (Dantzer 2018).
Neuroimmune interactions can also involve additional actors. A major recent
example is research on the microbiome–gut–brain axis. Mouse and insect
models suggest that the microbiome influences brain development and behavior
(Sharon et al. 2016; Vuong et al. 2017; Schretter et al. 2018b), in part through
the mediation of the immune system (Fung et al. 2017). Whether this conclusion
may apply to humans remains an open question.
Crucially, neuroimmune interactions have recently been said to have an
impact on cognition. It has been proposed that cytokines play a critical role in
spatial memory (Sparkman et al. 2006) and that microglia are important for
learning and memory by promoting learning-related synapse formation through
brain-derived neurotrophic factor signaling (Parkhurst et al. 2013).
Furthermore, according to some authors, adaptive immunity influences cogni-
tion (Kipnis 2016). Mice deficient in T lymphocytes were found to exhibit
cognitive impairment in spatial learning/memory tasks and passive transfer of
mature T cells improves their cognitive function (Kipnis et al. 2004). A likely
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
50 Elements in the Philosophy of Biology
Figure 5.3 Communication between the nervous and the immune system.
According to the initial view (top) neuroimmune interactions were thought to
occur via neuroendocrine mediators released in the general circulation.
According to the current view, however (down), long-distance interactions
between the nervous and the immune system are mediated by neural pathways
much more than by circulating neuroendocrine mediators, and the
communication is bidirectional. (Figure drawn by Wiebke Bretting, after
Dantzer 2018).
this effect can be reversed by injecting wild-type T cells but not T cells that do
not express IL-4 (Derecki et al. 2010). Another, nonexclusive, possibility is that
this effect is mediated by myeloid cells. More recently, it has been claimed that
mice deficient in adaptive immunity exhibit social deficits and hyperconnectiv-
ity of fronto-cortical brain regions, that social deficits are reversible via repo-
pulation with lymphocytes, and that interferon-γ is a probable molecular link
between meningeal immunity and neural circuits involved in social behavior
(Filiano et al. 2016). Further work is needed to unravel the exact molecular and
cellular mechanisms by which neuroimmune interactions affect cognition, but
data accumulated in the last decade is highly promising and may open up new
important avenues for research.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
52 Elements in the Philosophy of Biology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Immunology 53
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
54 Elements in the Philosophy of Biology
The question of how exactly the nervous and the immune system interact is the
most basic and the most extensively discussed in neuroimmunology. Some of
the main results of this research have been presented in the previous two
sections. My aim here is not to give more details about this question but rather
to explain why it should not be confused with the four other questions that are
often raised in the scientific literature.
Figure 5.4 Neuroimmunology: A conceptual tree. This figure distinguishes five different questions raised by current scientific literature in
neuroimmunology, and which in general are insufficiently separated.
56 Elements in the Philosophy of Biology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
58 Elements in the Philosophy of Biology
and functional diversity rest on the fact that two systems realize entirely or
partially similar functions without being one and the same system because in
those cases distributivity is essential for maintaining robustness. For example, the
two systems will not be activated in the same circumstances or at the same time,
and/or the failure or insufficiencies of one system can be compensated by the
other. One promising research program for future neuroimmunology is to outline
and explain the circumstances in which the nervous and the immune system really
overlap in space and time, those in which they act at different moments or
different places, as well as those in which one system compensates for the other
or takes over from the other.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Immunology 59
across the animal kingdom. For example, recent work has shown that IL-17,
a pro-inflammatory cytokine, is a neuromodulator and contributes to behavior in
Caenorhabditis elegans (Chen et al. 2017). Thus, much more research is needed
about the history of the nervous and immune systems in all their diversity before
making a claim about their possible common origins.
Second, one cannot make direct inferences from similarity to common
evolutionary origins. There are obviously many different possible evolutionary
explanations for similarities, including homology (shared ancestry) and analogy
(convergent evolution). In future research deciding between these two options
at the system level will be important but it will also be difficult. The question has
also been raised at the cell level: did neural and immune cells evolve indepen-
dently but later co-opt functions from each other, or did they evolve from
a common ancestral cell able to recognize and interpret the environment,
communicate with other cells, and exhibit plasticity (Kioussis and Pachnis
2009)?
Additionally, evolutionary explanations will differ depending on whether we
want to explain interactions, similarities, or overlap between the nervous and
the immune system. This is more confirmation that one should be careful when
switching from one question to the other.
So, exciting research remains to be done for scientists and philosophers
interested in when and why nervous and immune (sub)systems emerged in
evolution and how they fit together. An interesting proposal has been made on
this topic by my colleague Jean-François Moreau (personal discussions). In his
view, the functioning and origins of the nervous and the immune system must be
put into the context of the emergence of multicellularity. Multicellularity pre-
supposes internal communication and in metazoans three types of long-distance
communication channels can be distinguished. The first resembles our electric
networks; it corresponds to the nervous system, and more specifically to
neurons, which can send information at a very high speed with a relatively
diverse content. The second resembles our water and/or sewage networks; it
corresponds to the blood and lymphatic vessels, where endocrine signals, in
particular, circulate. It delivers information at a relatively high speed with
a relatively diverse content. These first two systems (nervous and vascular)
are rigid: they can be modified (via neurogenesis and angiogenesis, for exam-
ple) but only at an extremely slow rate. The third system resembles our mail
carriers; it corresponds to immune cells, which are the uniquely mobile cells of
the organism and which can deliver information with extremely diverse content
everywhere in the organism, often over long distances though at a limited speed.
In addition to carrying information, immune cells can perform all sorts of
activities, including pathogen clearance, tissue remodeling, and tissue repair,
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
60 Elements in the Philosophy of Biology
among many others (Eom and Parichy 2017). Overall, this view suggests
interesting and important distinctions about the different selective pressures
that might have existed at the origins of nervous, endocrine, and immune
systems in metazoans. It is likely that some types of messages can be delivered
by one system only: for example, high-speed communication is best realized by
the nervous network, while other processes such as pathogen clearance and
tissue repair require the unique mobility of immune cells. All this constitutes an
invitation to explore not only the similarities between the nervous, immune, and
endocrine systems but also their complementarities, as well as the means that
evolved to coordinate these systems characterized by their different commu-
nication channels. Among other benefits, such research could constitute an
important contribution to current scientific and philosophical discussions
about how and why nervous systems originated in the animal world (Miller
2009; Keijzer et al. 2013; Godfrey-Smith 2016) by enriching the context of this
question with considerations about possible complementarities (and possible
trade-offs as well) between the nervous system and other bodily systems.
A question slightly different from the four others yet important in this discus-
sion is control. Many neuroimmunologists switch from the description of
intimate interactions between the nervous and the immune system to the idea
that one system controls the other (Chavan and Tracey 2017). When describing
what he sees as the emerging field of immunopsychiatry, Pariante (2015)
suggests that this domain, by giving prominence to the immune system, reverses
what “governs” and “is governed.”
It should be clear, however, that interactions between two systems and
control by one system over another are two entirely different things. It is not
because recent research has shown that the immune system could influence the
nervous system and its behavior that we should conclude that the immune
system controls the nervous system let alone behavior. More data would be
needed to demonstrate control though it is not entirely clear which data could be
considered conclusive in that case. Moreover, the choice between the “control-
ler” and the “controlled” seems to be more dependent on the disciplinary
background of the person making the claim than on anything else. Personally,
I don’t see the need to attribute control to one system or another.
In summary, we have singled out five questions in the neuroimmunological
literature and suggested that distinguishing them was useful not only as
a conceptual clarification of current research in that domain but also as an
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Immunology 61
invitation to further explore the questions that, as is typically the case with that
of evolutionary origins, have tended to remain in the background because their
specificities have not been sufficiently recognized.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
62 Elements in the Philosophy of Biology
either directly or indirectly (through its interactions with the CNS, PNS, endo-
crine system, and/or other systems). The immune system has an impact on
sickness behavior (Konsman et al. 2002) and major depressive disorder
(Dantzer 2018), and strategies are currently being developed to treat several
behavioral disorders by targeting the immune system. Another major example is
pain, a highly discussed topic in the philosophy of the neurosciences
(Hardcastle 1997) and in general philosophy as well. Activated immune cells
release pro-inflammatory cytokines, which sensitize sensory nerve endings,
leading to an amplification and prolongation of pain; but the pain response
also is downregulated via opioid-containing immune cells, as these cells release
opioid peptides, which interact with opioid receptors on sensory nerves (Stein
et al. 1990). All this corroborates the claim that pain is a highly complex process
with several feedback loops and involving several bodily systems (Hardcastle
1997). Last but not least, many researchers propose that the immune system, via
microglia, T cells, and cytokines, participates in cognition, particularly in
learning and spatial memory.
All these data contribute to question brain-centered and more generally
nervous system–centered views of behavior and cognition. Clearly, the nervous
system remains crucial in all the processes described above, but it would none-
theless be inadequate to consider only the nervous system when trying to
identify the biological basis of feelings, emotions, behaviors, and cognitive
states. Understanding these processes requires an integrative approach in which
the immune system could play an important role. Accordingly, neuroimmunol-
ogy lends more weight to the idea of embodied cognition, that is, the idea that
bodily elements distinct from the brain play a significant role in cognitive
processing (Shapiro 2010). It also offers additional arguments to those who
emphasize the importance of interoception (Craig 2002) insofar as it suggests
that the brain can form a representation of the immunological status of periph-
eral tissues.
One may wonder, though, whether the immune system is an essential com-
ponent of behavior and cognition. Here the answer will depend on what exactly
is meant by this question. If the question is whether the immune system could
influence behavior and cognition on its own, that is, independently of the
(central and peripheral) nervous system, then the answer is probably negative.
But if the question is whether the immune system is essential for proper
functioning of the nervous system in some behavioral and cognitive activities,
then the answer is affirmative, as exemplarily illustrated by microglia-mediated
synaptic remodeling. More specifically, I suggest that the immune system can
play three kinds of specific roles that are essential for the functioning of the
nervous system and particularly for the realization of some cognitive processes.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Immunology 63
First, the immune system is an informant for the nervous system. It provides
vital information about infections, damage, and other perturbations that occur in
any part of the organism. If, as proposed in Section 2, the capacity to respond to
pathogens and other sources of damage constitutes one of the strongest evolu-
tionary pressures on organisms, then conveying information to the nervous
system about the immunological status of the host is vital. Second, the immune
system is an executant for the nervous system: it realizes distinctive activities
indispensable for the functioning of the nervous system, such as elimination of
dead cells, repair, and so on. Third, and most crucially, the immune system is
a messenger for the nervous system: not only does the nervous system resort to
the molecular communication pathways of the immune system (cytokines) but
it makes use of the unique feature of immune cells, namely their mobility, which
allows them to reach any part of the organism and to deliver complex messages
there. I suspect that, in coming years, cognitive functions mediated by this
unique mobility of immune cells will be uncovered.
Current research in neuroimmunology raises other philosophically interest-
ing issues, which could not be examined here due to space restrictions. These
include how the nervous and the immune system interact in the construction of
biological individuality and rethinking central physiological concepts such as
homeostasis in light of the crosstalk between these two systems, among many
other questions. Again, the aim of this section was simply to convince the reader
that neuroimmunology is full of philosophical promise.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
References
Ader R (2000) On the development of psychoneuroimmunology. Eur
J Pharmacol 405:167–176
Ader R (1981) Psychoneuroimmunology. Academic Press, New York
Ader R, Cohen N (1985) High time for psychoimmunology. Nature
315:103–104. doi:10.1038/315103b0
Afik R, Zigmond E, Vugman M, et al. (2016) Tumor macrophages are pivotal
constructors of tumor collagenous matrix. Journal of Experimental Medicine
213:2315–2331. doi:10.1084/jem.20151193
Aktipis CA, Boddy AM, Jansen G, et al. (2015) Cancer across the tree of life:
cooperation and cheating in multicellularity. Phil Trans R Soc B
370:20140219. doi:10.1098/rstb.2014.0219
Anderson RM, May RM (1982) Coevolution of hosts and parasites.
Parasitology 85 (Pt 2):411–426
Anderson W, Mackay IR (2014) Fashioning the immunological self: the biolo-
gical individuality of F. Macfarlane Burnet. J Hist Biol 47:147–175.
doi:10.1007/s10739-013-9352-1
Anderton SM, Wraith DC (2002) Selection and fine-tuning of the autoimmune
T-cell repertoire. Nat Rev Immunol 2:487–498. doi:10.1038/nri842
Augustin R, Fraune S, Bosch TCG (2010) How Hydra senses and destroys
microbes. Semin Immunol 22:54–58. doi:10.1016/j.smim.2009.11.002
Ayuso-Mateos JL, Vázquez-Barquero JL, Dowrick C, et al. (2001) Depressive
disorders in Europe: prevalence figures from the ODIN study. The British
Journal of Psychiatry 179:308–316. doi:10.1192/bjp.179.4.308
Bach J-F (2002) The effect of infections on susceptibility to autoimmune and
allergic diseases. N Engl J Med 347:911–920. doi:10.1056/NEJMra020100
Bazin H (2011) Vaccination: a history from Lady Montagu to genetic engineer-
ing. John Libbey Eurotext, Montrouge
Belkaid Y, Harrison OJ (2017) Homeostatic immunity and the microbiota.
Immunity 46:562–576. doi:10.1016/j.immuni.2017.04.008
Bertolaso M (2016) Philosophy of Cancer: A Dynamic and Relational View.
Springer, Netherlands
Besedovsky H, Sorkin E (1977) Network of immune-neuroendocrine
interactions. Clin Exp Immunol 27:1–12
Besedovsky HO, Rey AD (2007) Physiology of psychoneuroimmunology:
a personal view. Brain Behav Immun 21:34–44. doi:10.1016/j
.bbi.2006.09.008
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
References 65
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
66 References
Cann SAH, Netten JP van, Netten C van (2003) Dr William Coley and tumour
regression: a place in history or in the future. Postgraduate Medical Journal
79:672–680
Carosella ED, Pradeu T (2006) Transplantation and identity: a dangerous split?
Lancet 368:183–184. doi:10.1016/S0140-6736(06)68938-1
Carson MJ, Doose JM, Melchior B, et al. (2006) CNS immune privilege: hiding in
plain sight. Immunol Rev 213:48–65. doi:10.1111/j.1600-065X.2006.00441.x
Casadevall A, Pirofski L (1999) Host-pathogen interactions: redefining the basic
concepts of virulence and pathogenicity. Infect Immun 67:3703–3713
Chavan SS, Pavlov VA, Tracey KJ (2017) Mechanisms and therapeutic relevance
of neuro-immune communication. Immunity 46:927–942. doi:10.1016/j
.immuni.2017.06.008
Chavan SS, Tracey KJ (2017) Essential neuroscience in immunology.
J Immunol 198:3389–3397. doi:10.4049/jimmunol.1601613
Chen C, Itakura E, Nelson GM, et al. (2017) IL-17 is a neuromodulator of
Caenorhabditis elegans sensory responses. Nature 542:43–48. doi:10.1038/
nature20818
Chen DS, Mellman I (2017) Elements of cancer immunity and the
cancer-immune set point. Nature 541:321–330. doi:10.1038/nature21349
Chen G, Zhuchenko O, Kuspa A (2007) Immune-like phagocyte activity in the
social amoeba. Science 317:678–681. doi:10.1126/science.1143991
Chen YE, Fischbach MA, Belkaid Y (2018) Skin microbiota-host interactions.
Nature 553:427–436. doi:10.1038/nature25177
Chiu L, Bazin T, Truchetet M-E, et al. (2017) Protective microbiota: from
localized to long-reaching co-immunity. Front Immunol 8:. doi:10.3389/
fimmu.2017.01678
Chow J, Tang H, Mazmanian SK (2011) Pathobionts of the gastrointestinal
microbiota and inflammatory disease. Current Opinion in Immunology
23:473–480. doi:10.1016/j.coi.2011.07.010
Chu H, Mazmanian SK (2013) Innate immune recognition of the microbiota
promotes host-microbial symbiosis. Nat Immunol 14:668–675. doi:10.1038/
ni.2635
Clarke E (2011) The problem of biological individuality. Biological Theory
5:312–325
Cohen IR (2000) Tending Adam’s Garden: Evolving the Cognitive Immune Self.
Academic Press, San Diego
Cohen N (2006) The uses and abuses of psychoneuroimmunology: A global
overview. Brain, Behavior, and Immunity 20:99–112. doi:10.1016/j
.bbi.2005.09.008
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
References 67
Dubernard JM, Owen ER, Lanzetta M, Hakim N (2001) What is happening with
hand transplants? The Lancet 357:1711–1712. doi:10.1016/S0140-6736(00)
04846-7
Dunn GP, Bruce AT, Ikeda H, et al. (2002) Cancer immunoediting: from
immunosurveillance to tumor escape. Nat Immunol 3:991–998. doi:10.1038/
ni1102-991
Dupré J (2010) The polygenomic organism. The Sociological Review 58:19–31.
doi:10.1111/j.1467-954X.2010.01909.x
Dupré J, O’Malley M (2009) Varieties of living things: Life at the intersection of
lineage and metabolism. Philosophy & Theory in Biology 1:. doi:http://dx
.doi.org/10.3998/ptb.6959004.0001.003
Dustin ML, Colman DR (2002) Neural and immunological synaptic relations.
Science 298:785–789. doi:10.1126/science.1076386
Dvorak HF (1986) Tumors: wounds that do not heal. Similarities between tumor
stroma generation and wound healing. N Engl J Med 315:1650–1659.
doi:10.1056/NEJM198612253152606
Dvorak HF (2015) Tumors: Wounds that do not heal – Redux. Cancer Immunol
Res 3:1–11. doi:10.1158/2326-6066.CIR-14-0209
Eberl G (2010) A new vision of immunity: homeostasis of the superorganism.
Mucosal Immunology 3:450–460. doi:10.1038/mi.2010.20
Eberl G (2016) Immunity by equilibrium. Nat Rev Immunol 16:524–532.
doi:10.1038/nri.2016.75
Egeblad M, Nakasone ES, Werb Z (2010) Tumors as organs: complex tissues that
interface with the entire organism. Dev Cell 18:884–901. doi:10.1016/j
.devcel.2010.05.012
Ehrlich P (1909) Ueber den jetzigen Stand der Karzinomforschung. Nederlands
Tijdschrift voor Geneeskunde 5:273–290
Eming SA, Martin P, Tomic-Canic M (2014) Wound repair and regeneration:
mechanisms, signaling, and translation. Sci Transl Med 6:265sr6.
doi:10.1126/scitranslmed.3009337
Eom DS, Parichy DM (2017) A macrophage relay for long-distance signaling
during postembryonic tissue remodeling. Science 355:1317–1320.
doi:10.1126/science.aal2745
European Directorate for the Quality of Medicines & HealthCare (2015)
Newsletter Transplant: International figures on donation and transplantation
https://www.edqm.eu/sites/default/files/newsletter_transplant_volume_21_
september_2016.pdf
Fernández-Sánchez ME, Barbier S, Whitehead J, et al. (2015) Mechanical
induction of the tumorigenic β-catenin pathway by tumour growth pressure.
Nature 523:92–95. doi:10.1038/nature14329
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
References 69
Godfrey-Smith P (2016) Other Minds: The Octopus, the Sea, and the Deep
Origins of Consciousness, First edition. Farrar, Straus and Giroux, New York
Goodnow CC, Sprent J, de St Groth BF, Vinuesa CG (2005) Cellular and
genetic mechanisms of self tolerance and autoimmunity. Nature
435:590–597. doi:10.1038/nature03724
Gordon S (2003) Alternative activation of macrophages. Nat Rev Immunol
3:23–35. doi:10.1038/nri978
Goubau D, Deddouche S, Reis e Sousa C (2013) Cytosolic sensing of viruses.
Immunity 38:855–869. doi:10.1016/j.immuni.2013.05.007
Greaves M (2007) Darwinian medicine: a case for cancer. Nat Rev Cancer
7:213–221. doi:10.1038/nrc2071
Greaves M, Maley CC (2012) Clonal evolution in cancer. Nature 481:306–313.
doi:10.1038/nature10762
Grossman Z, Paul WE (1992) Adaptive cellular interactions in the immune
system: the tunable activation threshold and the significance of subthreshold
responses. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences
89:10365–10369
Guay A, Pradeu T (2016) Individuals Across the Sciences. Oxford University
Press, New York
Gurtner GC, Werner S, Barrandon Y, Longaker MT (2008) Wound repair and
regeneration. Nature 453:314–321. doi:10.1038/nature07039
Haber MH (2016) The individuality thesis (3 ways). Biol Philos 31:913–930.
doi:10.1007/s10539-016-9548-9
Hanahan D, Weinberg RA (2011) Hallmarks of cancer: the next generation. Cell
144:646–674. doi:10.1016/j.cell.2011.02.013
Hanahan D, Weinberg RA (2000) The hallmarks of cancer. Cell 100:57–70.
doi:10.1016/S0092-8674(00)81683-9
Hansson GK, Hermansson A (2011) The immune system in atherosclerosis.
Nature Immunology 12:204–212. doi:10.1038/ni.2001
Hardcastle VG (1997) When a pain is not. Journal of Philosophy 94:381–409
Hartung HP, Toyka KV (1983) Activation of macrophages by substance P:
induction of oxidative burst and thromboxane release. Eur J Pharmacol
89:301–305
Haslam A, Prasad V (2019) Estimation of the percentage of US patients with
cancer who are eligible for and respond to checkpoint inhibitor immunother-
apy drugs. JAMA Netw Open 2:e192535–e192535. doi:10.1001/
jamanetworkopen.2019.2535
Heneka MT, Kummer MP, Latz E (2014) Innate immune activation in neuro-
degenerative disease. Nature Reviews Immunology 14:463–477.
doi:10.1038/nri3705
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
References 71
Heppner FL, Ransohoff RM, Becher B (2015) Immune attack: the role of
inflammation in Alzheimer disease. Nature Reviews Neuroscience
16:358–372. doi:10.1038/nrn3880
Hille F, Richter H, Wong SP, et al. (2018) The biology of CRISPR-Cas:
Backward and forward. Cell 172:1239–1259. doi:10.1016/j
.cell.2017.11.032
Hodi FS, O’Day SJ, McDermott DF, et al. (2010) Improved survival with
Ipilimumab in patients with metastatic melanoma. New England Journal of
Medicine 363:711–723. doi:10.1056/NEJMoa1003466
Hoeijmakers JHJ (2001) Genome maintenance mechanisms for preventing can-
cer. In: Nature. www.nature.com/articles/35077232. Accessed October 9, 2018
Hogquist KA, Jameson SC (2014) The self-obsession of T cells: how TCR
signaling thresholds affect fate “decisions” and effector function. Nature
Immunology 15:815–823. doi:10.1038/ni.2938
Hooper LV, Gordon JI (2001) Commensal host-bacterial relationships in the
gut. Science 292:1115–1118
Horvath P, Barrangou R (2010) CRISPR/Cas, the immune system of bacteria
and Archaea. Science 327:167–170. doi:10.1126/science.1179555
Houghton AN (1994) Cancer antigens: immune recognition of self and altered
self. The Journal of Experimental Medicine 180:1–4. doi:10.1084/
jem.180.1.1
Huang S, Ernberg I, Kauffman S (2009) Cancer attractors: A systems view of
tumors from a gene network dynamics and developmental perspective.
Seminars in Cell & Developmental Biology 20:869–876. doi:10.1016/j
.semcdb.2009.07.003
Hull D (1992) Individual. In: Keller EF, Lloyd EA (eds.) Keywords in
Evolutionary Biology. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, pp.
181–187
Hull D (1980) Individuality and selection. Annual Review of Ecology and
Systematics 11:311–332. doi:10.1146/annurev.es.11.110180.001523
Hull DL (1978) A matter of individuality. Philosophy of Science 45:335–360
Huneman P (2014) Individuality as a theoretical scheme. II. About the weak
individuality of organisms and ecosystems. Biol Theory 9:374–381.
doi:10.1007/s13752-014-0193-8
Jackson SA, McKenzie RE, Fagerlund RD, et al. (2017) CRISPR-Cas:
Adapting to change. Science 356:eaal5056. doi:10.1126/science.aal5056
Jain RK (2005) Normalization of tumor vasculature: an emerging concept in
antiangiogenic therapy. Science 307:58–62. doi:10.1126/science.1104819
Janeway CA (1989) Approaching the asymptote? Evolution and revolution in
immunology. Cold Spring Harb Symp Quant Biol:1–13
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
72 References
Janeway CA (2001) How the immune system protects the host from infection.
Microbes Infect 3:1167–1171
Janeway CA (1992) The immune system evolved to discriminate infectious
nonself from noninfectious self. Immunology Today 13:11–16. doi:10.1016/
0167-5699(92)90198-G
Jerne NK (1985) The generative grammar of the immune system. EMBO J
4:847–852
Jiang H, Chess L (2009) How the immune system achieves self-nonself dis-
crimination during adaptive immunity. Adv Immunol 102:95–133.
doi:10.1016/S0065-2776(09)01202-4
Jones B, Shipley E, Arnold KE (2018) Social immunity in honeybees – Density
dependence, diet, and body mass trade-offs. Ecol Evol 8:4852–4859.
doi:10.1002/ece3.4011
Jones JDG, Dangl JL (2006) The plant immune system. Nature 444:323–329.
doi:10.1038/nature05286
Joyce JA (2005) Therapeutic targeting of the tumor microenvironment. Cancer
Cell 7:513–520. doi:10.1016/j.ccr.2005.05.024
Joyce JA, Fearon DT (2015) T cell exclusion, immune privilege, and the tumor
microenvironment. Science 348:74–80. doi:10.1126/science.aaa6204
June CH, Sadelain M (2018) Chimeric antigen receptor therapy. N Engl J Med
379:64–73. doi:10.1056/NEJMra1706169
Kahan BD (2003) Individuality: the barrier to optimal immunosuppression.
Nature Reviews Immunology 3:831–838. doi:10.1038/nri1204
Keijzer F, Duijn M van, Lyon P (2013) What nervous systems do: early
evolution, input–output, and the skin brain thesis. Adaptive Behavior
21:67–85. doi:10.1177/1059712312465330
Kelly PN (2018) The cancer immunotherapy revolution. Science
359:1344–1345. doi:10.1126/science.359.6382.1344
Khandaker GM, Cousins L, Deakin J, et al. (2015) Inflammation and immunity
in schizophrenia: implications for pathophysiology and treatment. Lancet
Psychiatry 2:258–270. doi:10.1016/S2215-0366(14)00122-9
Kiecolt-Glaser JK, McGuire L, Robles TF, Glaser R (2002)
Psychoneuroimmunology and psychosomatic medicine: back to the future.
Psychosom Med 64:15–28
Kiers ET, West SA (2015) Evolving new organisms via symbiosis. Science
348:392–394. doi:10.1126/science.aaa9605
Kioussis D, Pachnis V (2009) Immune and nervous systems: more than
just a superficial similarity? Immunity 31:705–710. doi:10.1016/j
.immuni.2009.09.009
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
References 73
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
74 References
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
References 75
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
76 References
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
References 77
Nuñez JK, Harrington LB, Kranzusch PJ, et al. (2015) Foreign DNA capture
during CRISPR–Cas adaptive immunity. Nature 527:535–538. doi:10.1038/
nature15760
Okabe Y, Medzhitov R (2016) Tissue biology perspective on macrophages. Nat
Immunol 17:9–17. doi:10.1038/ni.3320
Okasha S (2006) Evolution and the Levels of Selection. Clarendon Press;
Oxford University Press, Oxford; NY
Ordovas-Montanes J, Rakoff-Nahoum S, Huang S, et al. (2015) The reg-
ulation of immunological processes by peripheral neurons in homeostasis
and disease. Trends Immunol 36:578–604. doi:10.1016/j.it.2015.08.007
Osimo EF, Cardinal RN, Jones PB, Khandaker GM (2018) Prevalence and
correlates of low-grade systemic inflammation in adult psychiatric inpatients:
An electronic health record-based study. Psychoneuroendocrinology
91:226–234. doi:10.1016/j.psyneuen.2018.02.031
Ottaviani E, Malagoli D, Franceschi C (2007) Common evolutionary origin of
the immune and neuroendocrine systems: from morphological and functional
evidence to in silico approaches. Trends in Immunology 28:497–502.
doi:10.1016/j.it.2007.08.007
Owen RD (1945) Immunogenetic consequences of vascular anastomoses between
bovine twins. Science 102:400–401. doi:10.1126/science.102.2651.400
Pamer EG (2014) Fecal microbiota transplantation: effectiveness, complexities,
and lingering concerns. Mucosal Immunology 7:210–214. doi:10.1038/
mi.2013.117
Pamer EG (2016) Resurrecting the intestinal microbiota to combat
antibiotic-resistant pathogens. Science 352:535–538. doi:10.1126/science
.aad9382
Pancer Z, Cooper MD (2006) The evolution of adaptive immunity. Annu Rev
Immunol 24:497–518. doi:10.1146/annurev.immunol.24.021605.090542
Pariante CM (2015) Psychoneuroimmunology or immunopsychiatry? Lancet
Psychiatry 2:197–199. doi:10.1016/S2215-0366(15)00042-5
Parkhurst CN, Yang G, Ninan I, et al. (2013) Microglia promote
learning-dependent synapse formation through brain-derived neurotrophic
factor. Cell 155:1596–1609. doi:10.1016/j.cell.2013.11.030
Pastor-Pareja JC, Wu M, Xu T (2008) An innate immune response of blood cells
to tumors and tissue damage in Drosophila. Disease Models & Mechanisms
dmm.000950. doi:10.1242/dmm.000950
Pauken KE, Wherry EJ (2015) Overcoming T cell exhaustion in infection and
cancer. Trends in Immunology 36:265–276. doi:10.1016/j.it.2015.02.008
Paul WE (2015) Immunity. Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
78 References
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
References 79
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
80 References
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Acknowledgments
I would like to thank my colleague and friend Jean-François Moreau, Professor
of Immunology at the University of Bordeaux, for his continuously inspiring
“big picture” of immunology. It has been a pleasure and honor to work at his
side since 2014. Maël Lemoine and Jean-François Moreau read the entire
manuscript and helped me to make it sharper. Lucie Laplane, Jan Pieter
Konsman, and Anya Plutynski each read one specific section and made very
useful comments. I owe special thanks to Wiebke Bretting, who drew several
figures of this Element. William Morgan made very useful suggestions. Many
thanks for discussions about immunology and philosophy to Lynn Chiu, Marc
Daëron, Louis Du Pasquier, John Dupré, Gérard Eberl, Melinda Fagan, Scott
Gilbert, Peter Godfrey-Smith, Deborah Gordon, Paul Griffiths, Matt Haber,
Philippe Huneman, Akiko Iwasaki, Jonathan Kipnis, Philippe Kourilsky, Bruno
Lemaitre, Tim Lewens, Richard Lewontin, Margaret McFall-Ngai, Alberto
Mantovani, Sarkis Mazmanian, Ruslan Medzhitov, Michel Morange, Alvaro
Moreno, Samir Okasha, Susan Oyama, Philippe Sansonetti, Ken Schaffner,
Elliott Sober, Kim Sterelny, Joan Strassmann, Marie-Elise Truchetet, Skip
Virgin, and Eric Vivier. My gratitude and admiration go to Jean Gayon
(1949–2018), my supervisor and friend, who is so greatly missed. This project
has received funding from the European Research Council (ERC) under the
European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation program – grant
agreement n° 637647 – IDEM. I thank all the past and present members of
that project. I also thank all the members of the Conceptual Biology and
Medicine group, as well as the ImmunoConcept lab as a whole, the CNRS,
and the University of Bordeaux. I am lucky to work in such a friendly and
inspiring interdisciplinary environment.
This Element is dedicated to Jean-François Moreau, who embodies
immunology.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Biology
Grant Ramsey
KU Leuven
Grant Ramsey is a BOFZAP research professor at the Institute of Philosophy, KU Leuven,
Belgium. His work centers on philosophical problems at the foundation of evolutionary
biology. He has been awarded the Popper Prize twice for his work in this area. He also
publishes in the philosophy of animal behavior, human nature and the moral emotions. He
runs the Ramsey Lab (theramseylab.org), a highly collaborative research group focused on
issues in the philosophy of the life sciences.
Michael Ruse
Florida State University
Michael Ruse is the Lucyle T. Werkmeister Professor of Philosophy and the Director of the
Program in the History and Philosophy of Science at Florida State University. He is Professor
Emeritus at the University of Guelph, in Ontario, Canada. He is a former Guggenheim fellow
and Gifford lecturer. He is the author or editor of over sixty books, most recently Darwinism
as Religion: What Literature Tells Us about Evolution; On Purpose; The Problem of War:
Darwinism, Christianity, and their Battle to Understand Human Conflict; and A Meaning to
Life.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706
Philosophy of Biology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 88.25.167.20, on 20 Jan 2020 at 15:10:21, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108616706