Taking Care - An Alternative To Therapy - David Smail
Taking Care - An Alternative To Therapy - David Smail
Taking Care - An Alternative To Therapy - David Smail
TAKING CARE
An Alternative to Therapy
David Smail
KARNAC
First published in 1987 by J.M. Dent & Sons Ltd
ISBN: 978-1-78220-286-8
Introduction 1
1 Dreaming and Wishing: The Individual and Society 7
2 The Pursuit of Happiness 24
3 Magic, Interest and Psychology 44
4 Faults and Reasons 66
5 Change: The Limits of Therapy 79
6 'Relationships' 93
7 Growing Up and Taking Care 122
8 Morality and Moralism 143
Index 163
To the memory of Don Bannister
New Preface
Of all my written works, Taking Care provides the clearest state-
ment of issues concerning psychotherapy and society which I have
been struggling with all my professional life. Less ambiguously than
previous books (Psychotherapy: A. personal approach; Illusion and
Reality), it sets out what I see as the limitations of conventional
approaches to psychotherapy. At the same time, it lays the ground
for subsequent works (The Origins of Unhappiness; How to Survive
without Psychotherapy) to elaborate, respectively, a detailed theor-
etical analysis of psychological distress and a kind of manual for
'ordinary people' to understand the significance of their own
suffering.
Principally because, in my view, it became a victim of publishing
take-overs in the eighties, Taking Care was not as widely read as
its predecessor, Illusion and Reality. I have always regretted this:
for me, it is the profounder and more mature of the two. I am
therefore particularly grateful to Carol O'Brien and Constable for
bringing it out in this edition.
It is, to put it mildly, a bracing read, bucking the trends of
fashion, I have to admit, almost foolhardily. For the most part,
works of popular psychology - and many academic approaches
too, come to that- seek to reassure their audience that all is not
as bad as it seems and that their ills can be overcome through the
exercise of some kind of technique or other discovered, or at least
propounded, by the author. Such, I think, is the secret of the success
of much of the best-selling literature in the psychology and psycho-
therapy field: it feeds on the hopes and fantasies of people struggling
against very difficult odds and only too ready to jump at relatively
painless solutions.
No such Panglossian philosophy underlies this work, I fear.
Reading it ten years on, even I was slightly taken aback in places
at the bleakness of the view of society it portrays. The message is
that, far from things being not as bad as they seem, they are in fact
worse, and the (largely commercial) apparatus of social control
through which the relatively more powerful maintain their advan-
tage over the relatively less powerful has become perfected to the
point where it is virtually insuperable. So far as repairing the
damage done by this society is concerned, psychotherapy is an
irrelevance: at best it is a temporary comfort, at worst a distraction.
There is no substitute for taking care, and in the long run how a
VII
New Preface
society takes care of its members is a political, not a therapeutic
matter.
Uncompromising though this message undoubtedly is, I do not
regret it, and indeed I have since retracted no part of it. And
although it is stated in these pages with some ferocity, in places, it
carries with it a level of reassurance for those in psychological pain
more profound than that provided by any form of 'treatment'. For
the whole point is that emotional suffering of the kind which comes
to be labelled 'neurotic' or 'clinical' is the result not of the indi-
vidual's inadequacies, shortcomings, personal or genetic weak-
nesses, but of the inescapable infliction on vulnerable bodies of
noxious social influences which have their origin, most often, far
beyond the orbit of our personal lives.
The issues of responsibility and blame, of what we can and
cannot will (spelt out in most detail, perhaps, in How to Survive
without Psychotherapy), constitute a theme which recurs through-
out my written work, and though I have been hammering away at
it in one form or another for twenty years, it is still, I think, the
one most people find hardest to grasp. The core of our problem is
stated about as clearly as I can manage in Chapter Four, where I
try to show that it is the apparent indubitability of our personal
experience - our intimate knowledge of our feelings - which makes
it so difficult for us to conceive of the source of our difficulties as
outside ourselves. We feel it inside, so we think that that is where
it must indeed originate, and we are, therefore, easily persuaded
that it is we who are responsible for what ails us.
We give up this notion, if at all, only with the greatest reluctance,
for we feel that to do so robs us of our freedom and our agency.
In my subsequent writing I have tried to elaborate the point that
we do have freedom and agency, but only to the extent that they
are accorded to us. The power(s) to choose and to act are not
God-given, personal attributes, simply matters of 'will-power', but
social acquisitions dependent on the availability of essentially
material resources in the world outside our skins. Though some
may find it paradoxical, I resolutely maintain that this is, for those
who are suffering, a counsel not of despair, but of comfort. Cer-
tainly, in my work as a clinical psychologist, I have met many
people who have found it comforting; better to be suffering than
to be sub-standard.
This book is, therefore, more a critique of the society which gives
rise to psychological distress than of the approaches to therapy
which have been spawned to assuage it; the focus has shifted from
individual experience (as in Illusion and Reality) to social structure.
Vlll
New Preface
It was not difficult to see ten years ago how pervasive make-
believe and wishfulness were becoming as ways of interpreting
experience and constructing means of social control - I claim no
prophetic powers- but even so the true prophets of 'postmodernity'
( Jean-Fran~ois Lyotard, Jean Baudrillard) may have seemed to be
over-stating their case. Where I wrote in Chapter One of our failure
to distinguish between emdodied reality and dream-like imagery,
the representation of war as an aesthetic, electronic experience was
still almost five years off. The nineties, however have seen the
extension of imagery and make-believe right into the core of the
body politic and the threats to our embodied hold on reality which
were identified in the earlier chapters of this book are now rep-
resented within the official institutions of our society more as a
virtue than a nightmare.
The further disintegration of any idea that politics could be the
proper concern of the citizenry is particularly to be deplored. In
what has become a kind of apolitical, almost 'virtual' government,
issues affecting the material reality of our lives, along with concepts
of economic fairness and social justice, have been set aside in favour
of, for example, variants on the theme of 'responsibility'. Rather
than either the regulation or the overt exercise of oppressive power,
there is an attempt to maintain control (whether of scapegoats,
such as the teachers, or of corrupt commercial institutions selling
pension plans) through shaming and admonishment. The mani-
pulation of image, the frank abandonment of actuality for appear-
ance (for example the celebration of fashion as an 'industry') have
become not just ideological tools of government but the very pro-
cess of government itself. Government has thus become the manage-
ment of appearance; what is done to people is considered
indistinguishable from what they think has been done to them
(hence the successful politician's obsession with 'focus groups' and
the consequent inevitability of demagoguery); magic is officially
rehabilitated at every cultural level - science and soothsaying are
seen as but alternative ways to 'the truth'. The collapse of the
distinction between public and private which so concerns me in
these pages is now virtually complete.
And yet, of course, reality will not be gainsaid. We are still
embodied creatures in a real world even though the concept of a
'real world' has been hopelessly undermined by market rhetoric.
What has happened, of course, is that the demands of global
Business have put out of sight and beyond the reach of our criticism
-beyond, most significantly, the power of national governments to
control - the actual levers of power which constistute the ultimate
IX
New Preface
influences on our lives. A 'Labour' Prime Minister can smugly extol
the virtues of a 'flexible labour market' because the 'reality' of his
world does not include being able to influence the policies of huge
multi-national companies - he can only dance to their tune. And
for the men and women thrown out of work in the interests of
'flexibility' there are no officially authorized words with which to
criticize their condition; if their distress is not simply dumb, it can
be given form only in the language of personal responsibility and
inadequacy. The unemployed are 'jobseekers' or 'welfare-
dependants' and rather than being able to earn the means of their
livelihood they are offered either moral exhortation or counselling.
We need more than ever before to rescue the reality of our world,
if only because of the pain which is inflicted on the lives of so many
'ordinary' people. Our virtual reality is bought at too high a price.
Even in relatively prosperous Britain the suffering of those at the
bottom of the heap - and they are no small minority - is a social
outrage. Though not exactly a secret (ask any inner-city teacher or
health worker) the extent of this suffering is resolutely obscured
by the official institutions of society, not least the therapy and
counselling industry. The very first thing we have to do, therefore,
is to establish with fearless clarity what the nature of our predica-
ment is, and that may indeed prove a somewhat harrowing process.
Our real problem, however, is in knowing where to go from there.
It is easy enough to construct formulae for how our personal
lives should be lived - the philosophy of life sketched in Chapter
Seven, for example, still seems to me a fair enough ideal - but
turning insight into action is not simply a matter of the exercise of
personal will, for as individuals we are not in control of what we
do. In this book I make the case for taking care rather than provid-
ing therapy, but how that is to be achieved requires a political
analysis and understanding beyond the scope of these pages. One
thing, however, is certain: it will require the exercise of social
power.
David Smail
Nottingham, 1997
X
Introduction
Our accustomed ways of looking at the world suggest that we all
live in an unalterable, shared reality which exists quite indepen-
dently of any feelings we might have about how it ought to be.
Equally, our accustomed view of knowledge- especially scientific
knowledge - is that it gives a dispassionate, disinterested descrip-
tion of the way things are, again independently of how we might
like them to be.
These accustomed ways of looking at the world and viewing
knowledge have long been known - at least by many of those
whose business it is to think about such things - to be false.
In fact, the 'reality' we believe in is an illusion. In fact, our
'dispassionate' knowledge is highly partial and selective: it has aims
and purposes inextricable from the interests of power. We use
knowledge to subordinate nature, and that includes ourselves.
These issues may seem a long way from the concerns of a
psychologist whose job it is to try to understand and if possible
alleviate the emotional distress of individual people. However,
having worked for a number of years in the field of psychological
'treatment', I have become convinced, in the first place, that these
issues are central to an understanding of human despair, and in the
second that they should no longer remain the particular property of
'those whose business it is to think about such things'. These issues
are everybody's concern, and though it may be in the professional
interest to limit serious consideration of them to the experts, to do
so would not be, and is not, for the public good.
The central argument of this book is a very simple one, but,
obscured by my professional blinkers, it has taken me nearly three
decades to see it: psychological distress occurs for reasons which
make it incurable by therapy, but which are certainly not beyond
the powers of human beings to influence. We suffer pain because
we do damage to each other, and we shall continue to suffer pain
as long as we continue to do the damage. The way to alleviate and
mitigate distress is for us to take care of the world and the other
people in it, not to treat them.
Although (to me, but I am sure also to many others) this 'insight'
has now become blindingly obvious, it is extraordinarily difficult
to marshall the arguments and evidence which support it, since
they so often run counter to our customary ways of seeing and
thinking about things. It is, however, my belief that one cannot
expect people to give up the hope (not to mention the resources)
1
Introduction
they invest in 'treatment' until they have gained access to and had
a chance to consider for themselves what the arguments and
evidence are. And one cannot expect the sum of human distress to
diminish until we give up our investment in treatment, and address
instead the daunting task of taking care.
In my previous book, Illusion and Reality: The Meaning of
Anxiety, • my basic concerns were not different from those
informing the present work, but my focus was particularly upon
individuals and their experience of anxiety within the compass of
their own lives. My aim was to try to offer encouragement to
people {that is, all of us) who have been bludgeoned out of their
understanding of the world by a remorseless 'objectivity', to risk
trusting themselves to become the 'subjects' that, in fearful secret,
they somehow know themselves to be. This time my focus is wider;
having, as it were, stated the dilemma in terms of the way it
presents itself in our immediate experience, I want now to broaden
the view to show how that experience is formed and influenced by
the social and cultural structures which we inhabit, and to suggest
what the implications of that may be for the way we should
conduct ourselves towards one another.
An attempt to understand the influence of social and cultural
structures takes one beyond present times and places, and chal-
lenges familiar and unthinkingly accepted views of what 'society'
is about. In the following pages I shall suggest a number of things
which may well seem at first - or even second - sight hard to
swallow: for example, that the world we seem to know, and which
seems so unalterably hard, and real and resistant to our will, is in
several important ways the illusory creation of our wishes, the
fabrication of our dreams. Indeed, there is a sense in which
dreaming, even when awake, is inescapable. We are, as it were,
doomed to 'grasp' reality only through our interpretation of it, and
hence we cannot really grasp it at all. But we can, as I shall also
argue, have respect for it: we may dream recklessly, or we may go
carefully because we know we are dreaming.
Again, I shall argue that what we take to be dispassionate
knowledge is in fact suffused with interest; that is, our knowledge
is inseparable from the uses to which we wish to put it- we exploit
our knowledge in order to explott the world's resources (including
people), and because so much of that exploitation is fundamentally
dishonourable, we hide its nature from ourselves (we 'repress' it).
My particular concern here will of course be with psychological
knowledge, and again I shall have the difficult - and to many
people perhaps unpalatable - task of suggesting that the main
*Dent, 1984.
2
Introduction
use to which psychological knowledge has been put has been the
exploitation of some people by others for purposes which, though
they do not appear in those others' conscious awareness, neverthe-
less suit them rather well.
Furthermore, if one is to understand the workings of interest,
particularly in relation to psychology and 'treatment', one must
investigate the sources of the plausibility in which it manages to
clothe itself. In part, I believe, these are to be traced to an age-old
and ever-present attraction to magic (which also shapes much of
our dreaming). Magic, indeed, is not at all a relic of the past, but
is found at the very kernel of our enthusiasm for science.
These factors (our wishful dreaming, magic, and interest)
combine with what we take to be the point of our lives - the
'pursuit of happiness' - to enslave us within a society in which
exploitation and indifference are the norm. In this society also, the
intellectual and conceptual means whereby we might get a purchase
on our predicament are largely obscured from us. Nowhere is this
more so than in the case of psychological distress and its treatment,
in which our ideas about why we suffer as we do, and whom we
are to 'blame', as well as how we may change or be 'cured', are
shaped by our social and cultural concerns much more to justify
and permit further exploitation than to allow us an insight into
the true reasons for our ills.
Far from being repairable machines, human beings are embodied
organisms on whom damage will at best always leave a scar. We
simply cannot get away with using and abusing each other as we
do, and it is small wonder that the ways of life into which we have
uncritically fallen, and which we take for granted as the natural
response to an inescapable reality, reverberate so disastrously in
our conduct towards and experience of each other - that is, in
our 'relationships', where, again without noticing, we have carried
exploitation to the very heart of our social undertakings, placing
it between man and woman, and parent and child.
The sense of 'therapy' which the subtitle of this book calls
into question is that in which therapy is 'officially' offered (and
undoubtedly widely accepted in the public mind) as a technical
procedure for the cure or adjustment of emotional or psychological
'disorder' in individual people. There are 'unofficial' aspects of
psychotherapy - recognized at least implicitly by many of its prac-
titioners - which I would not want to question, and indeed in
pursuance of which this book could be said to be written. These
aspects, however, are, in contrast with the grandiose claims and
aspirations of most 'schools' of psychotherapy, extremely limited
(sadly necessary palliatives in a disordered society) and not justifi-
ably professionally 'patentable'. Elaboration of them should in no
3
Introduction
way distract us from the much more essential task of trying to
understand and prevent the processes whereby we come to inflict
upon each other so much incurable damage.
As a matter of fact, though their stated profession and unstated
interest may be to offer cure, most therapists of good will also play
an inadvertently subversive role within the society which damages
us so profoundly. As I tried to show in Psychotherapy: A Personal
Approach, • what most often psychotherapists actually (as opposed
to professedly) do, is to negotiate a view of what the patient's
predicament is about which both patient and therapist can agree
(which is to establish, as closely as one ever can, what is the truth
of the matter), and then to encourage the patient to do what he
or she can to confront those elements of the predicament which
admit of some possibility of alteration. This almost inevitably
means that patients begin to criticize aspects of a social 'reality'
which before they had always taken for granted, and, with courage
or grace, to learn actively to dissent from and oppose the
constraints it had placed upon them: to overcome the tyranny of
objectivity. I would now lay more emphasis than I did in that book
on the value of comfort: for many people, psychotherapy provides
the only source of comfort they are likely to find in what has been,
for them at least, a predominantly cruel world.
The actual possible achievements of therapy may thus be
summarized very briefly as establishing what is the case ('demys-
tification'), and providing comfort and encouragement. Inasmuch
as this book is addressed primarily to people trying to make sense
of their own and others' distress, it is my hope that lessons I have
learned from the experience of psychotherapy (as I have come to
understand it) may to some extent transfer to these pages.
The process of demystification, the examination and clearing of
the confusions which surround the person's deceived or self-
deceiving view of what lies behind the 'symptoms', often forms the
longest part of the therapeutic enterprise. There are, it is true,
therapists who feel that, as long as they are sure of how they can
make patients confront the difficulties which beset them, there is
really no point in spending much time in demystification: what
matters, they say, is getting on with tackling the problems, not
investigating the reasons why they arose in the first place. I do not
myself agree with this view, though I have no doubt that it may
sometimes 'work'. It seems to me essential for people to enter into,
to have the full opportunity to alter and argue with the processes
whereby someone else arrives at a formulation of 'the problem';
the alternative constitutes reliance upon an authoritarian or
•Dent, 1978.
4
Introduction
any such society (could anyone, who sees the lack of restraint in
our history and the destructive intent of our technology?), but it
might, with the very greatest effort, just be possible.
There is probably not very much of comfort in all this. However,
my experience both personally and professionally is that the
greatest comfort derives from having one's view, however
despairing it may be, confirmed by someone else who is not afraid
to share it. As long, then, as this book helps some people in their
quest to identify the roots of their unease, I hope it may even be
comforting. It would certainly comfort me to think that here or
there it might find an echo.
There is one central and essential point I wish to emphasize
above all others in this introduction, and to beg the reader to bear
in mind throughout what follows: it is neither my wish nor my
intention to engender in him or her any sense of guilt or blame. It
is extremely difficult, perhaps impossible, seriously to criticize our
society and our conduct toward each other without challenging
very fundamental and widely shared assumptions, without showing
anger and having at times almost deliberately to shock. Even the
most constructive criticism, if it is to avoid superficiality, necessi-
tates seeing some very familiar things in some very unfamiliar ways.
There are thus some elements of trying to 'negotiate' a view which
just cannot be at all times measured and reasonable and cool. But
it is part of the very heart of my argument that no body - singular
or collective - is to blame for the predicament in which we find
ourselves. We are all, certainly, responsible, in the sense that
nobody but we ourselves wreak on each other the havoc we do,
but the concept of blame is one which mystifies and obscures the
processes whereby this comes about. (Blame is an effective means
of manipulating people and groups, not a valid concept for under-
standing them.) As anyone who has an intimate concern with
human misery knows, blame and guilt, invoked as explanations,
are simply ways of evading the difficulties involved in tackling it.
The same, it seems to me, is likely to be true of misery on a societal
scale.
6
1
Dreaming and Wishing:
The Individual and Society
'All life is a dream, and dreams are just dreams.'
What seemed to me as a schoolboy no more than a poetic
affectation useful for quoting in exams, comes to mind thirty years
later as a statement of the simple truth.
Perhaps all that signifies is that literature is wasted on some
schoolboys; perhaps anyway Calderon • meant something entirely
different by his words from what I now understand by them.
However that may be, it seems to me that we may be sunk more
deeply into our dreams than at any previous time in our recorded
history, and in any case more deeply than we can afford to be, for
our dreams are full of a destructive rage and hatred, a frustrated
craving for omnipotence, a desperation for satisfaction beyond the
bounds of mere greed, through which we may dream ourselves to
our own annihilation.
We can see the world only in the ways that human beings,
with their own particular ways of sensing and experiencing (and
interpreting sensation and experience) can see it. Whatever reality
there may be beyond the 'reality' which filters to us through our
individual, historical and cultural ways of seeing, we shall never
be able to say what it 'is'. We have, of course, a naive belief in a
scientifically establishable, objective reality, but subscribing to that
belief is in truth doing no more than taking, in a very grandiose
way, what is merely our best guess so far about the nature of
things as the nature of things. We have yet fully to accept that we
can never get beyond guesswork.
So we are dreamers within a reality we cannot ever completely
know, but which is nevertheless vulnerable to our conduct. Our
lives are dreamt within a world, indeed a universe, which permits
our dreaming and exists independently of it. Though we cannot
know our world, we can certainly dream its destruction (and
thereby put an end also to our dreaming).
That 'primitive man' lives in a dream is easy enough for most
of us to grasp as we read of his nervous transactions with a world
of ghostly ancestry and dangerous magic. What we find less easy
to see is that our own world is to just about the same extent
constructed out of superstitious fantasies, centring, in our case,
7
Dreaming and Wishing: The Individual and Society
8
Dreaming and Wishing: The Individual and Society
9
Dreaming and Wishing: The Individual and Society
10
Dreaming and Wishing: The Individual and Society
12
Dreaming and Wishing: The Individual and Society
13
Dreaming and Wishing: The Individual and Society
14
Dreaming and Wishing: The Individual and Society
15
Dreaming and Wishing: The Individual and Society
17
Dreaming and Wishing: The Individual and Society
18
Dreaming and Wishing: The Individual and Society
19
Dreaming and Wishing: The Individual and Society
20
Dreaming and Wishing: The Individual and Society
21
Dreaming and Wishing: The Individual and Society
they seem to be trying to do, in which case the aims may become
quite surprisingly obvious. In the same way, if one wants fully to
comprehend the impetus behind our collective, social conduct, one
need often do no more than ignore the rhetoric and look instead
at our actions. Such ingenuous observation only goes to confirm
the ubiquity of interest. We have carried the commercial values
developed over the last five centuries, at first with shame and later
with enthusiasm, to a point where all our dealings with each other,
at the institutional as much as if not more than at the personal
level, are based on the advantages which are likely to accrue in
terms of power and money. Socially, politically, recreationally,
intellectually, educationally and academically, in every sphere and
department of life, it is towards money and its power that our
conduct is orientated.
There is still a touch of shame about this. Though our fasci-
nation with the struggle for money-power is only too evident to
the most casual observer, we still often tend to hide it behind a
moralistic screen of judgments of good and bad, and in this are
not unlike our Puritan ancestor described by Tawney:
Convinced that character is all and circumstances nothing,
he sees in the poverty of those who fall by the way, not a
misfortune to be pitied and relieved, but a moral failing to
be condemned, and in riches, not an object of suspicion -
though like other gifts they may be abused- but the blessing
which rewards the triumph of energy and will. Tempered by
self-examination, self-discipline, self-control, he is the prac-
tical ascetic, whose victories are won not in the cloister, but
on the battlefield, in the counting-house, and in the market.
In recent years, our love of money and confidence in the values
of the market place, the primacy of cost-benefit analysis to moral
questions of right and wrong, have become more overt, as has our
readiness to expend each other, sacrifice our young and discard
our old in our personal interest. But even still there is a tendency
to disavow our intentions, or at least to draw a veil of repression
over our most basic inclinations.
The crude, 'value-free', 'objective' and mechanistic preoccu-
pations of 'modern science' have of course done much both to
obscure the nature of our enterprise and to lend it an authority
which might otherwise be less easy to establish. This is certainly
the case with psychology, which serves with studied innocence to
divert our gaze from our least creditable undertakings. An examin-
ation of the indexes of the nine textbooks of psychology to be
found in our local university book shop reveals that only three
mention 'power' and none mention 'money'. How seriously should
22
Dreaming and Wishing: The Individual and Society
one take a 'science' which claims to deal with 'motivation' and the
'prediction and control of human behaviour' and yet which fails
to mention the one most powerful motivator in every Western
person's life? (The answer should probably be very seriously, since
psychology is clearly about something quite other than a disin-
terested examination of 'what makes us tick', and it is presumably
important to know what that something other may be.)
It is my belief, then, that to trace the sources of what we feel
as our individual distress, we shall need to turn to a critical examin-
ation of what our collective enterprises are. The intertwining of
our interest with our dreams is leading us into a progressive care-
lessness of each other's welfare, to an extent indeed which will, at
the very best, damage us for generations to come.
23
2
The Pursuit of Happiness
It seems a matter of self-evidence to most people (indeed I wonder
if, in our hearts, any of us can escape such a view) that the point
of life is to be happy. If, in an attempt to tap a relatively selfless
opinion, you ask people what they would most want for the lives
of their actual or hypothetical children, they will usually say 'happi-
ness'. They may also specify other conditions, like health, material
success or a modest degree of fame, upon which happiness may be
taken to depend. Not everybody chooses happiness, but most
people do, and in the highly informal 'experiments' I have made
in asking people this question there seem to be no unusual patterns
to the responses they give in terms of age, sex, class, etc.
And yet, in some ways, to hold happiness as the ideal of life
seems to me to involve a number of difficulties and paradoxes, not
the least of which is the extreme infrequency with which, despite
all our best efforts, it seems to be achieved. We appear to be
surprisingly undaunted by disappointment. Infrequency of achieve-
ment does not in itself, of course, render the ideal of happiness
invalid in any way, but it does among other things add an element
almost of cruelty to the pursuit of our elusive goal.
Further reflection leads one to wonder whether the attainment
of happiness may be so infrequent because in fact it is not even
possible. How, for example, does one know that one has reached
the point in one's life where happiness has been achieved? What
does one do with it when one has got it? Can one specify the
conditions in which it may be retained? Can one see what other
people need to do to gain it, perhaps being able to draw up a kind
of blueprint for the achievement of general happiness?
Even if one cannot easily arrive at a formula for the capture of
happiness in the present, it may be misleadingly simple to imagine
what a human life in which ultimate happiness has been reached
might look like, and those of us who have found the early and
middle years of life less rewarding in terms of happiness than
perhaps we had hoped as children, can still probably fantasize how
we may yet grasp it in our declining years. The 'happiness' which
throughout our lives stayed just beyond our reach becomes, in the
nick of time, the 'fulfilment' of old age. Our faded gaze rests with
contentment on the persons of those who love us and who accept
from us with gratitude the fruits of a mellowed wisdom as they
enact in our autumnal world the little dramas we ourselves have
known so well. I have read about such old people, but I have never
24
The Pursuit of Happiness
25
The Pursuit of Happiness
26
The Pursuit of Happiness
*In this connection see I. D. Suttie, The Origins of Love and Hate,
Penguin Books, 1960.
27
The Pursuit of Happiness
28
The Pursuit of Happiness
29
The Pursuit of Happiness
And:
Commerce and liberty, so Voltaire maintained in his Philo-
sophical Letters, are intimately associated. The close link
between literature and finance was, he thought, one of the
glories of the eighteenth century. No Rotarian could be more
enthusiastic about the benefits of commerce than was Joseph
Priestley. By bringing the merchant into contact with other
places and people, he tells us, commerce 'tends greatly to
expand the mind and to cure us of many hurtful prejudices';
it encourages benevolence and a love of peace; it develops
such virtues as punctuality and 'the principals of strict justice
and honour' ... 'Men of wealth and influence', so he sums
up, 'who act upon the principles of virtue and religion, and
conscientiously make their power subservient to the good of
their country, are the men who are the greatest honour to
human nature, and the greatest blessing to human societies.'
A connection between big business and philanthropy would
be unlikely to be one impressing itself upon modern intellectual
observers of society, although of course it is one which big business
seeks, through procedures of 'image building', to create. Once
again, those processes which at the time looked to constitute a
liberating move and were advocated with enthusiastic optimism by
those caught up in it, came very rapidly to be exploited in the sole
interests of those- now the 'bourgeoisie'- with power.
It is instructive in this respect to reflect upon the career of the
most 'official' sanction we have to pursue happiness. It was of
course Thomas Jefferson who first articulated 'the pursuit of happi-
ness' as one of the rights of men in the American Declaration of
Independence. According to Hannah Arendt,* however, Jefferson
himself may at that time not have been entirely clear about what
he meant by the phrase, and his idea of happiness and ours may
well have diverged considerably in the intervening two hundred
years. She argues that by 'happiness' he may have meant, at least
partly, what he meant elsewhere when he wrote of 'public happi-
ness', that is the freedom of people to take part in their political
self-determination. However, as she points out, the phrase
was almost immediately deprived of its double sense and
understood as the right of citizens to pursue their personal
interests and thus to act according to the rules of private
self-interest. And these rules, whether they spring from dark
30
The Pursuit of Happiness
the past four centuries and on the other by our enthusiasm for
greedy exploitation. Our technological bent has led us to isolate
the happiness we have rightly observed as occasionally
accompanying our activity, to posit it as the point of life, and then
to try to manufacture it as a commodity. Our greed has led us,
freed from the repressive moral strictures of a 'parental' religious
authority, to throw ourselves upon the world's bounty with all the
lack of restraint of a group of adolescents at their first party. And,
of course, our genius for exploitation has quickly revealed that
our unrestrained adolescent greed offers a market for ever more
'exciting' and 'satisfying' commodities which may be tended and
stoked and stimulated more or less endlessly. Rather than being,
as it were, encouraged by our social and cultural in<;titutions to
grow out of our infantile craving for the delights of the womb and
the breast towards a mature and sober undertaking of a contri-
bution to the life of our society and the continuation of our species,
it has become our aim to benefit in every way possible from a
concerted pandering to our longing for blissful satiation. We all
believe in happiness, and most of us have a stake in its production
and consumption. We thus become caught up in a frenzied pursuit
of happiness which, being illusory, renders us ever more dazed and
out of touch with our embodied reality, and ever more vulnerable
to and injured by the abuses of our exploitation of each other.
People suffer bitterly, go crazy and even kill themselves because
(among other reasons) they are unhappy. It is easy to see why: to
be unhappy means in our society to have lost the point of living.
(In making this point I do not wish to justify unhappiness nor to
advocate the policy of the stiff upper lip. All too often unhappiness
is seen as something some people have to get used to so that other
people can escape it. This constitutes a version of moralism about
which I shall say more in the final chapter.) The inevitable non-
achievement of the greedy individualistic satiation which we take
to signify happiness, means that we suffer from a kind of collective,
chronic frustration.
In the very midst of a kind of lunatic celebration of symbolic
satisfactions, a mirage of pleasures excited and achieved, people are
in fact almost beside themselves with need. A sense of despairing
neediness seems to me to be endemic at all levels of our society -
experienced just as much by the 'helpers' as by those they seek to
help - and to lie curled at the centre of most 'relationships'. For
our frantic search for happiness meets only emptiness, and if we
could we would all scream like abandoned infants as our mouths
fail to encounter the promised breast. We are, however, not infants,
but rather adolescents who don't know our own strength, and the
33
The Pursuit of Happiness
*It is significant in this respect that even so humane and critically gifted
a believer in the greatest happiness for the greatest number as William
Godwin (see his Enquiry Concerning Political Justice, 1793) should have
fallen for a Utopian fantasy of man as non-reproductive and immortal.
There are no doubt millions today who would see nothing the matter with
that as an ideal for the future.
34
The Pursuit of Happiness
35
The Pursuit of Happiness
37
The Pursuit of Happiness
38
The Pursuit of Happiness
battery animals, lifted from the course of time to be located in an
endless present.
'A function may be defined as an activity which embodies and
expresses the idea of social purpose.'• If life is not simply some-
thing for-oneself, to be enjoyed and indulged and spun out as
long as possible (its dream-ideal thus being some form of solitary
immortality), then its most profound value (and satisfaction) may
come from the individual's being able, along with others, to make
a contribution to- perform a function within- something infinitely
larger than him- or herself. As part of an ever-evolving social
process the individual is shaped by a largely unknown past and
projected towards a totally unknowable future. Thus the individual
becomes a tiny particle through which the course of social evol-
ution moves; the meaning of our lives cannot be understood outside
the context of the social and cultural processes in which they are
embedded. It is probably misleading to speak of our bodies as
having been designed for anything, but certainly if there is anything
for which the design of our bodies is suitable, it is for contributing
to a process far too great for us to be able to understand and a
future far too distant and impenetrable for us to be able to divine.
To see our bodies as being designed merely for the experience of
pleasure or 'happiness' is surely to trivialize human existence to
the point of utter despair .
. . . to say that the end of social institutions is happiness, is
to say that they have no common end at all. For happiness
is individual and to make happiness the object of society
is to resolve society itself into the ambitions of numberless
individuals, each directed towards the attainment of some
personal purpose.
Such societies may be called Acquisitive Societies, because
their whole tendency and interest and preoccupation is to
promote the acquisition of wealth. The appeal of this concep-
tion must be powerful, for it has laid the whole modern world
under its spell. •
Human functions are, sadly, extremely vulnerable to exploi-
tation by interest. Almost anything that people can do in the way
of productive or creative work can be mechanized, objectified,
appropriated and then sold back to them as passive consumers.
The social activity of making music, for example, becomes the
solitary reception of mass-produced sounds through headphones.
Production becomes consumption, activity becomes spectacle. Even
39
The Pursuit of Happiness
42
The Pursuit of Happiness
order to get to grips with this paradox, one must attempt to gain
a view of the way in which social forces operate through rather
than within individuals, how personal conduct can only be compre-
hensible in the light of collective aims.
43
3
Magic, Interest and
Psychology
Throughout our culture there are, I believe, widely shared and
deeply held misconceptions about human psychological makeup,
particularly concerning 'motivation' (or why we do things) and
'change' (or how in the course of our individual lives we may
become happier, more 'adjusted' people). These misconceptions
make it very difficult indeed for us to get a helpfully explanatory
purchase on the reasons for psychological distress and the chances
of avoiding it. So solidly are they embedded in our culture,
however, we can scarcely even see them. In order fully to expose
their foundations, I believe that one must approach them through
what might at first seem like a detour: one must examine the nature
of 'official' psychology itself.
For while there may be no very direct relation between, on the
one hand, what people-in-the-street consider the causes of their
actions and the possibilities for their self-improvement, and, on the
other hand, the speculations of the professionals, there is little
doubt that both will reflect a general cultural impetus, and this
latter, for me at any rate, is easier to detect in the relatively well
formulated 'official' views than in the often unspoken or more
tentative assumptions of the 'ordinary person'. Though it would
certainly be a mistake to suppose that 'the experts' determine what
the 'lay' person thinks, it is altogether more likely that those forms
of psychological preconception to which our culture inclines us
will find their most exact expression in 'expert' opinions and
procedures. More important than this, clues as to the reasons why
we think about ourselves as we do are, I think, most clearly
revealed by a clarification of the reasons for our having 'a
psychology' at all.
In trying, then, to understand (in the two chapters following
this) how we have come to adopt ideas about 'motivation' which
in fact enslave us, and ideas about 'change' which delude us, I
think it may be illuminating (even if only by indirect lighting) first
to gain some insight into how official psychology and psycho-
therapy came about, and what purposes they serve.
Whether as individuals or groups, people seem particularly
prone to construct for themselves a myth of origin - i.e. a story
about their beginning. Psychologists are no exception. We are the
44
Magic, Interest and Psychology
children, so the story goes, not of Adam and Eve, nor even of their
simian substitutes, but of science.
Though psychologists and other professionals and academics of
the 'psycho-' variety quarrel bitterly amongst themselves about the
legitimacy of their claim to scientific respectability, virtually all of
them trace their origin to a period during the second half of the
last century when scientific method came to be applied to matters
of psychological concern. Most of us, in this way, live with the
happy myth that, intellectually speaking, we arrived but recently
on the scene, bringing with us a clear and virginally pure scientific
gaze with which to peer through the murk of metaphysics and
superstition which had until so recently obscured our under-
standing of the workings of the human mind. It took the world a
long time to get round to the one true belief - science - but as its
children we are unsullied by the ignorance and incomprehension
of the past, and (especially those of us in Britain and America) we
now have the infallible canons of 'objective scientific method'
which, as long as we remain true to them, will guide us through
a future in which freedom from the errors of former times is
guaranteed.
However, the very failure of psychology in its 'applied' and
therapeutic forms to cope with the emotional distress and
confusion which are so prevalent in our society exposes the falli-
bility of our 'scientific' dogma and indicates the falsity of our myth
of origin. And in fact, of course, psychology did not undergo a
virgin birth in the last century, but, like any other human
endeavour, evolved out of, and still serves, concerns and interests
that have been identifiable within our culture for as long as its
intellectual history has been recorded. Indeed, not only are
psychology's claims to an objectively valid understanding of and a
therapeutically effective concern with the ills which beset us false,
but it is more than possible that psychology, far from minimizing,
actually compounds our difficulties.
If I am not to be really seriously misunderstood, however, I
must at the outset make one thing very clear, and that is that I do
not regard psychologists, or psychotherapists, or practitioners of
psychological medicine, as charlatans, nor do I wish in any way
to impugn their motives. A charlatan is one who knowingly
pretends to knowledge and ability he or she in fact does not
have. As far as psychology is complicit in the social evils and self-
deceptions of our time, it is so without (except perhaps for a very
small minority) the knowing connivance of its practitioners. Almost
without exception, the psychologists, psychotherapists and
psychiatrists I have met are, professionally speaking, honest,
concerned and conscientious people who work in what they see as
45
Magic, Interest and Psychology
the best interests of their clients and patients, and who do much,
at the very least, to offer comfort and support to people who have
no one else to turn to.
It is, however, an irony instructive of the very points I want to
make in this chapter, that (with some very important exceptions)
it is the 'psycho-' disciplines themselves which have led us
(misguidedly) to seek the reasons for human conduct in the indi-
vidual (and often conscious) motivations of those who enact it. It
thus becomes extremely difficult to call into question the effects of
somebody's actions without apparently implying an insult to the
person; it is hard for me to suggest that what you do has an
effect contrary to what you say your intention is, without seeming
thereby also to suggest that you are a liar. But if we are to be able
to engage with good will and mutual respect in a search for the
truth of the matter, it is essential that we be able to distinguish the
meaning of an action in its widest social context from the verbal
account of his or her intentions the individual actor gives. The fact
is that often, perhaps most often - and arguably even always - we
do things for reasons of which we are not only unaware, but could
not be aware (more will be said about this later), but of which we
are understandably tempted - and easily able - to give a plausible
account.
So-called neurotic symptoms are frequently the experience or
expression of a distress for which individuals cannot accurately
account through an examination of their own conscious purposes.
This of course does not mean that their conduct and experience
itself (as opposed to their conscious articulation of it) is irrelevant
to an explanation of their distress - indeed it is likely to be crucial.
In exactly the same way, psychologists must acknowledge that
what they say they are doing may have very little relevance to what
they actually are doing, and that a more satisfactory explanation
must be sought elsewhere. With individuals, one has to formulate
explanations (as well as evaluations) of their conduct (a) from a
consideration of their history, and (b) by inferring their intentions
from the actual fruits of their activity. The case is no different with
collective human undertakings such as psychology.
The definition of psychology which was taught to me was 'the
scientific study of human behaviour', and the chief aim of its most
representative school - behaviourism - 'the prediction and control
of behaviour'. I am not sure how far academic psychologists have
in recent years modified the expression of this aim, but in so far
as they have softened somewhat its rather stark outline, I suspect
that this would stem less from any embarrassment over its almost
touchingly ingenuous revelation of a dubious interest than from
an uncomfortable awareness that psychologists have, over the last
46
Magic, Interest and Psychology
*K. Thomas, Religion and the Decline of Magic, Penguin Books, 1973.
47
Magic, Interest and Psychology
ance of the confessional and the emergence of a note of puritanical
disapproval on the part of the clergy of the kinds of problems for
which people might seek help. Indeed magic, Thomas argues, 'may
have provided as effective a therapy for the diseases of the mind
as anything available today'.
People have always sought to influence by magical ritual what
they could not control in any other way. 'Witchcraft was thus
generally believed to be a method of bettering one's condition when
all else had failed. Like most forms of magic, it was a substitute
for impotence, a remedy for anxiety and despair.' There is of course
an element of pure wishfulness about this, but, again as Thomas
notes, there are facilitative aspects of much magical ritual which,
though they form no part of its central rationale, have the effect of
encouraging people to make up their minds concerning a particular
course of action, or of comforting the person who distractedly
seeks a solution to his or her dilemma. Divination, for example,
could help men to take decisions when other agencies failed
them. Its basic function was to shift the responsibility away
from the actor, to provide him with a justification for taking
a leap in the dark, and to screw him up into making a decision
whose outcome was unpredictable by normal means.
The diviner's predictions, therefore, did not deflect his
clients from their original intentions; on the contrary, it was
the process of consultation which forced them to know their
own minds. Divination could set the imagination free.
In this respect, magical procedures acted precisely in the way
that, as I suggested earlier, psychotherapy acts today. Psycho-
therapy also makes claims to technical processes of cure which are
in fact invalid, but in the course of doing so dispenses comfort and
encouragement which are far from ineffective.
Apart from the directly therapeutic significance of magical
modes of thought, one may note that, for example, both in its
methods (which were to a surprising extent 'objective' and stat-
istical) and in its concerns (which included the study of 'individual
differences' and human typology, vocational and educational guid-
ance, etc.), seventeenth-century astrology bore resemblances to
'modern' psychology so strong that one can scarcely believe one is
reading about a different discipline. Actually, of course, one is not:
As Auguste Comte was to recognize, the astrologers were
pioneering a genuine system of historical explanation. In their
confident assumption that the principles underlying the devel-
opment of human society were capable of human expla-
nation, we can detect the germ of modern sociology.
48
Magic, Interest and Psychology
50
Magic, Interest and Psychology
52
Magic, Interest and Psychology
time eat away the bonds of iron and steel, but they are
powerless against the habitual union of ideas, they can only
tighten it still more; and on the soft fibres of the brain is
founded the unshakable base of the soundest of Empires ...
Already one begins to see why, having considered the associ-
ationist psychology which grew out of Locke's philosophical
analysis, Passmore should judge that:
It is not surprising that, under Pavlov's influence, such a
psychology won official approval in the Soviet Union and
wide acceptance in the United States, both of them countries
which are deeply involved in the technological 'management'
of human beings ...
Independent testimony to the success of this enterprise is lent
by the words of two modern American writers, who in the course
of a disturbing analysis of the uses to which 'therapeutic'
psychology has been put in the United States to control the behav-
iour of children who are in one way or another troublesome to
authority, note that 'behaviour modification can make the effects
of such authority more painless than, for example, the use of a
club or the threat of punishment, but in its ideal form it will erase
all awareness of its existence and thereby make it absolute.'t
Nobody has done more than Michel Foucault to show how the
development over the last few centuries of the human sciences has
become saturated throughout with the interests of power. In his
magnificent book Discipline and Punish, for example, he argues
that 'all the sciences, analyses or practices employing the root
"psycho" ' have arisen in the course of a process in which the
punishment of illegal acts by otherwise anonymous malefactors,
has turned into the maintenance of discipline in people by means
of an ever more finely differentiated analysis of their individual
characteristics. Where once the state discouraged threats against it
through an ostentatiously terrifying recourse to spectacular tortures
and execution, it now does it through a scientific technology of
power - i.e. discipline. Through the use of scientific observation,
the objectifying 'gaze' which seeks to see without itself being seen
(a necessity well known to every student of psychology in search
of 'uncontaminated' observations), social scientists become prac-
titioners of a discipline which dissects, orders and normalizes indi-
53
Magic, Interest and Psychology
54
Magic, Interest and Psychology
55
Magic, Interest and Psychology
behaviour'. Such screening is now common, even for four-
year-aids.
While procedures such as these are justified by a rhetoric of welfare,
their actual effect is that
this generation is learning at a very young age that there is
nothing unusual about being watched, questioned, tested,
labelled and 'treated', or about the fact that the results of all
that watching and questioning are being stored and processed
in machines over which the individual has no control. It is
hardly worth saying again that the existence of such a record
can have a chilling effect or that privacy is 'the right to be
left alone'. But for those who have become habituated to
such records and treatment from the age of five, that chilling
effect may never occur because they have never been left
alone, and they will therefore never suspect that there might
have been another way.
And so:
An entire generation is slowly being conditioned to distrust
its own instincts, to regard its deviation from the narrowing
standards of approved norms as sickness and to rely on the
institutions of the state and on technology to define and
engineer its 'health'.
If one is to understand the processes whereby 'scientific
psychology' comes to cooperate with the state in the realization of
the latter's interests, one must, I think, guard against the temptation
- at times very strong - to attribute to those involved, i.e. the
economically powerful, the politicians and the 'scientific'
professionals, implication in some kind of malevolent conspiracy.
Although it would no doubt be equally mistaken to rule out the
possibility that there can be quite deliberate and conscious
components to the exploitation of the weak by the strong, the
process of exploitation as a whole is probably facilitated most of
all by our having been overtaken in recent times by a general
lowering of moral and political awareness. 'Politics and religion',
together perhaps with too indecently direct reference to money (as
in the question of how much a person earns), have become subjects
which many people feel it indelicate to inquire into too closely or
too publicly. This constitutes a form of repression the effect of
which (as is, after all, commonly the case with repression) is to
allow the interests which might otherwise be challenged by, in
this case, moral and political awareness to operate all the more
unrestrainedly. Professional collaborators with such interests have
56
Magic, Interest and Psychology
57
Magic, Interest and Psychology
Because:
... all the planning which under the old system was done
by the workman, as a result of his personal experience, must
of necessity under the new system be done by the management
in accordance with the laws of science. •
The prestige of 'science' becomes associated with whatever social
processes are necessary for the achievement of the economic inter-
ests of power, and to this purpose the 'social sciences' lend them-
selves admirably. As Schrag and Divoky put it:
The normative assumptions and natural order invoked by the
new modes of control are, in one sense, disciplinary replace-
ments for Social Darwinism. Each in its own time was (or is)
'scientific'. But while Social Darwinism was almost entirely
an economic 'law' concerned with the individual's fitness for
the labour market (and particularly the factory), its contem-
porary substitute is concerned with every aspect of the indi-
vidual's life and, most particularly, with his potential as a
client. The system no longer requires his muscle, but it needs
his obedience. It no longer must train him to be a reliable
worker, but it must condition him to be managed.
What Christopher Lasch calls the 'tutelary complex' - i.e. the
amalgam of educational, social and therapeutic agencies concerned
with our 'adjustment' - has in fact become the instrument of
managerial discipline. In a passage strongly reminiscent of
Foucault, he suggests that the tutelary complex:
... both reflects and contributes to the shift from authori-
tative sanctions to psychological manipulation and surveil-
lance - the redefinition of political authority in therapeutic
terms - and to the rise of a professional and managerial class
that governs society not by upholding authoritative moral
standards but by defining normal behaviour and by invoking
allegedly non-punitive, psychiatric sanctions against
deviance.t
Interest is at once the most powerful and the least honourable
motivation of human conduct. Unchecked, its operation is likely
to be extremely destructive, since its long-term effect is to wear
away the ligaments which bind a society in communal purpose. If,
into the bargain, its operation is repressed - i.e. unnoticed and
58
Magic, Interest and Psychology
""Since these words were written the British government has adopted an
altogether more workmanlike approach to the manipulation of managerial
interest. The Guardian, 3 September 1986, reports that: 'Health authority
managers could be denied an annual pay rise if they fail to achieve their
individual targets under the Department of Health's new merit pay
system ... But those "consistently exceeding short-term objectives and
making excellent progress towards long-term goals" will be awarded an
extra 4 per cent on salary in the first year ... Health service unions have
attacked the plan as an incentive scheme for accelerating hospital closures
and service cuts .. .' The article goes on to describe how each tier of
management will be 'assessed' by those next highest in authority. This
provides as good an example as any of how interest can be manipulated
via a pyramidal hierarchy ('management') in order to achieve higher-order
political goals.
62
Magic, Interest and Psychology
64
Magic, Interest and Psychology
65
4
Faults and Reasons
Who is to blame? Whose fault is it? That is the question which
seems these days to leap to the mind of anyone who tries to
understand the causes of unhappiness. It is, for example, conspicu-
ously the question which obsesses all those - particularly journal-
ists, 'media people' and politicians - who have some part to play
in the public analysis of misfortune or unrest. Most inquiries into
politically significant disturbances or catastrophes seem to come to
rest once the blame for them has been established, and indeed the
haste to identify a blameworthy person or group is often positively
indecent. 'Activists', 'extremists', 'criminal elements'- these are the
familiar targets of blame whose identification somehow satisfies, or
perhaps rather pre-empts, our need to understand the causes of
disturbance in our society. The search for a person or people to
blame is equally remorseless in the case of less obviously politically
loaded misfortunes. A child is battered to death: do we blame the
parents, or do we blame the social workers, health visitors, doctors
who had contact with the family? An aeroplane crashes: do we
blame the pilot, the manufacturers, the maintenance engineers, the
air traffic controllers? We do not, it seems, rest happy until we
have located the cause of the disaster inside a person or group of
people.
The case is no different with our individual conduct and experi-
ence. Whose fault is my unhappiness? Is it mine, is it yours, my
spouse's, mother's, employer's?
And yet we have not always been so obsessed with blame.
Explanations for why people do things, or react in the way that
they do to what has been done, seem to conform (within limits)
to fashion. Not long ago, for example, the fashion was to refer
for explanations of human distress to concepts of illness, i.e. to
impersonal, 'dysfunctional' mechanisms within people. Just
recently, the fashion has become more to look for some kind of
{largely unelaborated) moral failing. In psychotherapy, it used to
be an advance for patients to accept a measure of responsibility
for their actions, since this allowed them to get a subjective grip
on their circumstances rather than seeing their 'inadequacy' as the
result of some kind of mechanical deficiency. Now, however, it
seems a positive disadvantage for patients to see themselves as
responsible for their actions, since they appear not to be able to
make a conceptual differentiation between responsibility and
66
Faults and Reasons
67
Faults and Reasons
68
Faults and Reasons
69
Faults and Reasons
70
Faults and Reasons
71
Faults and Reasons
73
Faults and Reasons
74
Faults and Reasons
75
Faults and Reasons
76
Faults and Reasons
directly and solely from the processes of therapy itself. I feel guilty
that I cannot make magic.
But, like everyone else, my patients feel and act the way they
do because they are bodies in a world, and only in so far as
'therapy' can affect that relation can it be of any help. On the
whole, it is of much less help than almost any of us can bear to
think. That is not necessarily quite such a bad thing as it sounds,
for if therapy were as effective as we would like it to be - if the
relation of the body with the world were so easily manipulated -
human life would quickly be rendered almost entirely trivial. To
gain a deeper understanding of these issues we need, I think, to
examine the processes of 'change'.
78
5
Change: The Limits of
Therapy
Psychotherapists have always had the greatest difficulty in demon-
strating that their activities actually lead to anything remotely
resembling a 'cure' of the 'conditions' presented by the patients
who consult them. The focus of this book is not psychotherapy,
and it is not my intention to try to deal exhaustively with the
question of the usefulness or otherwise of the therapeutic enterprise
as a whole; rather, I want to use the experience of therapy and
therapists to examine the processes whereby people change. For
nowhere do people try harder to change than in psychotherapy,
and few people can have put more effort into trying to get other
people to change than have psychotherapists.
There can, surely, be very few people who do not at some time
in their lives want to change either the way they feel (because they
feel distressed or unhappy) or the way they act (because alternative
courses of action would be practically or morally preferable). But
the possibility of change is not just important as a way of making
life more pleasant, it seems also that flexible modification of charac-
teristic forms of conduct will be necessary if people are to bring
to bear an influence on the world. If we are to understand, and
perhaps even give some deliberate direction to the way the social
world evolves, we shall need to gain some kind of articulate idea
of the ways in which people may change and how these may be
facilitated. I do not believe that the kind of people who consult
psychotherapists are particularly unusual, nor that the kinds of
'problems' they have are any different from anyone else's. Differ-
ences between the kinds of emotional pain and distress people feel,
and whether or not they experience them through 'symptoms', are
matters of degree rather than of kind. For these reasons, what one
learns from the observation of people trying to change through
psychotherapy almost certainly has, I believe, more general
relevance. I suspect also that it is in the various ideas about change
which psychotherapists have developed that the most 'sophisti-
cated' psychological concepts concerning the processes of change
in our culture are to be found. As will become apparent, this, I
think, is not saying very much about the levels of sophistication
psychologists have achieved in this respect.
There is a truly huge literature bearing upon research into the
outcome of psychotherapy. For obvious reasons, it is very much
79
Change: The Limits of Therapy
80
Change: The Limits of Therapy
82
Change: The Limits of Therapy
*Valuable accounts of this kind have more recently been given by Peter
Lomas, The Case for a Personal Psychotherapy, Oxford University Press,
1981, and R. F. Hobson, Forms of Feeling. The Heart of Psychotherapy,
Tavistock Publictions, 1985. See also my Psychotherapy: A Personal
Approach.
84
Change: The Limits of Therapy
85
Change: The Limits of Therapy
86
Change: The Limits of Therapy
87
Change: The Limits of Therapy
- in fact the latter would be by far the easier task. The fact is that
people are organisms and their experience is acquired organically,
and so deeply and inextricably bound up is it with the very struc-
tures of the body that erasure of the experience would entail
destruction of the organism. We cannot, like magnetic tape, be
wiped clean of our history, which is, on the contrary, acquired as
are the growth rings of a tree. Our history, the knowledge we have
built up of the world, is our physical, organic structure. Body and
mind are not just inseparable, they are one and the same.
It is certainly an expectation of our therapeutic culture that
somehow our painful experience can be eradicated, or at least that
the misery we feel in the present can somehow be wiped away to
leave us with a 'clean slate' on which to start to chalk up a new
and more promising future. Only an entirely unreflective ideology
of mechanism allows us to think in this way and to shut our eyes
to the obvious fact that our present feelings and perceptions have
a history which is, as it were, deeply and ineradicably inscribed
upon our bodies. In clinging on to a therapeutic illusion, we exempt
those aspects of our conduct and experience we would like magi-
cally to change from rules of common sense which we would think
it close to madness not to apply in other, related areas. Our ability
to construct a social world at all depends on our being able
correctly to anticipate a high degree of regularity and predictability
in the character and conduct of other people. It is in many ways
important that leopards should not be able to change their spots,
and it is certainly our experience that they do not. Nor do any of us
expect to be able to change as the result of any kind of 'therapeutic'
intervention the way we speak, or move, or argue, think, interpret,
react, and we pursue our aims, enact our abilities and competences,
speak languages and ride bicycles without expecting ever to be
'cured' of doing so. It is not, of course, that there is no possibility
of our being able to learn new and different ways of doing things,
but in learning of this kind we anticipate the difficulty involved in
a way which is less characteristic of our therapeutic aspirations,
and we also know that what we learn does not expunge (again, in
the manner of magnetic tape) what was there before.
Over and over again the rooted, organic nature of our experi-
ence has been misinterpreted as indicative of some form of malfunc-
tion or maladjustment. If people do not operate in a mechanically
adaptable way in relation to some particular set of circumstances
defined (usually by a professional group) as ideal, they are seen as
somehow resistant or faulty, for example as demonstrating 'trans-
ference neurosis', 'inappropriate conditioning', etc. However, a
person is not formed by what goes on physically or psychologically
inside his or her own skin, but from a highly permeable relation
88
Change: The Limits of Therapy
with a context - the world in which we are situated flows into us
and we into it in a way which makes us inseparable from it, and
which is indelibly recorded in our history. This is the basis of the
importance to human beings of familiarity; we make sense of and
struggle with and grow from our roots in whatever world we
happen to be, and to have been, located. You will not want to
exchange your Belfast back street for a desert island paradise not
because you are crazy or stupid, but because your experience is
inseparable from the one and irrelevant to the other. We can only
deal with what we know. If you suspect that all men are bullying
tyrants as your father was, this is not so much a mistake you are
making as a particular, and quite valid, form of knowledge you
are not merely unwilling, but, as it were, organically unable to
abandon. Our bodies make sure that we do not forget the lessons
of our past. I do not want to say that people are incapable of
developing or modifying experience as they go through life, but
that such development or modification must fit in with and grow
out of what has gone before- it must be organic. People grow from
one position to the next, they cannot be switched. Our experience is
hard won, built into our living tissue, and it should be respected
rather than measured disparagingly against a set of professional
norms of 'adjustment' or 'mental health'.
Unhappily for those who place their hopes in therapy, the
lessons of our exposure to pain, deprivation, injustice and misfor-
tune, are registered as indelibly on our bodies as are those of
love, security and nurturance, and indeed as are those practical
acquisitions (like learning a mother tongue or being able to swim)
which we tend to take for granted. There is no difference in terms
of the quality of the knowledge itself between what an insecure
and anxious person knows about the world in terms of its brutality
and unpredictability, and what a secure and confident person
knows about its potentialities for affection and achievement. There
is no reason at all why one should consider the one person's
experience and expectations 'pathological' and the other's
'adjusted', except of course that a confusion of social with quasi
medical values makes it much easier to ignore the harm we do
each other and to establish a uniform view that any casualties
which may occur in what purports to be a fundamentally benign
society are solely the result of individual 'dysfunction', inappro-
priate 'projection', and so on.
It is, of course, against the interests of a hierarchy of power
which depends on exploitation for people to recognize that the
distress or despair they feel stems from their bodily relatedness to
a noxious world, since any such recognition, should it occur on a
wide enough scale, would quickly lead to demands for social
89
Change: The Limits of Therapy
90
Change: The Limits of Therapy
91
Change: The Limits of Therapy
92
6
'Relationships'
By far the greater part of the misery which is experienced by people
in the modern world is unquestionably inflicted through human
agency. It is the things we do to each other which are the immediate
causes of our distress. Superficially, therefore, it might seem as
though one need look no further than our 'relationships' one with
another to identify, and in principle also to rectify, the origins of
our unhappiness.
At no time in previous history, certainly, have 'relationships' so
directly been a focus of concern and discussion as in our own time.
Entire industries have grown up around our ability, or lack of
ability, to attract or be pleasing to others and to enjoy what they
have to offer us. Not the least important section of this market is
that exploited by the therapy industry: 'interpersonal relationships'
are acknowledged as the core concern of a hundred different
'schools' of therapy and counselling, and not surprisingly so, for
anxious rumination about one's personal adequacy in relation to
others, dread of rejection by them and frustration at lack of satis-
faction in 'relationships' seem to lie at the very centre of much of
our acute personal unhappiness. For most of us our 'relationships'
- or at least our fantasies of how they might or ought to be - seem
to constitute the very meaning of our existence: life would appear
to have no point at all were it not for the promise it holds of
satisfying personal relationships.
However, far from exposing or providing an understanding of
the nature of our predicament, this pervasive, almost obsessive
concern with 'relationships' seems to me actually itself to form a
large part of what ails us. Indeed, our desperation to enjoy 'good
relationships' lies behind a great deal of the damage we do each
other, and constitutes much more a reflection than a critique of
social values stemming from the commercialized pursuit of
happiness.
The commercial process turns abstractions like 'happiness' into
saleable commodities. In exactly this way, abstract relations
between people have been turned into 'relationships' which are
treated as the end-product of a process in which people themselves
form the raw material. Thus people have become secondary to the
relationships of which, interchangeably and expendably, they form
a part: what matters is the 'quality of the relationship', not the
characteristics or conduct, or even ultimately the welfare, of the
people who form its terms.
93
'Relationships'
MAKE AN IMPRESSION!
This course deals with all aspects of self-presentation,
whether in the workplace or in social or family life. The idea
of 'self-marketing' is a major theme and situations in which
the skills have an important role include:
Y starting and maintaining relationships
Y interview training
Y self-presentation in groups
Y developing closer relationships
Y building better interactions at work
Y handling rejection effectively
Y establishing arenas for 'self-marketing'
Y making and clarifying agreements with others.
This, then, is the 'arena' where people ('selves') have become
caught up in a commercialized and competitive jockeying for
position, in which the adequacy of 'self-presentation' will determine
how satisfactory 'relationships' are, and in which the terrors of
rejection may be 'handled effectively' through development of the
appropriate 'skills'.
As the virtually inexhaustible supply of raw material for saleable
satisfactions in the form of 'relationships', people become almost
less than commodities, and this no doubt accounts for the intense
and obsessive anxiety which they experience over their relations
with others. Usually from bitter experience, most people know
how easily dispensed with they are as those 'significant others' with
whom they come into contact during their lives seek through them
the satisfaction of their needs. At the centre of our anxiety, then,
is to be found the terror that we shall simply disappear if we are
not wanted, needed, or 'loved' by someone. Our very sense of
identity and existence depends upon the gaze of someone else
falling upon us - and it is noticeably with identity and existence
that twentieth-century people, as well as much of their literature,
art, psychology and philosophy, have been particularly preoccu-
pied. We are objects, and as such have to be noticed in order to
94
'Relationships'
achieve full 'objectivity'. Objects exist only for others; only subjects
can exist independently of the regard of 'the Other'. And, of course,
we use others in precisely the way we fear they may use us - we
treat them not as ends in themselves, but as means to more or less
satisfactory 'relationships'. As far as you do not satisfy some aspect
of my needs, you do not exist for me. In other words, if one is
nobody's object one is, quite literally, nothing. The value of people
thus becomes entirely utilitarian - if they are no use to anyone,
they are simply expendable. It is no longer human lives which are
important, but the quality of the relationships and satisfactions to
which they contribute.
Our acceptance of the expendability of people who fail to
contribute to our personal happiness is perfectly obvious if one
examines the content of our fantasy. In the media of popular
entertainment, for example 'successful' television drama, characters
are kept in existence only so long as they contribute to the sexual
or material satisfaction of the protagonists. In the glossier American
television series, moreover, these vehicles of gratification are
completely interchangeable, conforming to a standard mould of
youth and 'beauty' which, even though it makes them hard to tell
apart, becomes the heartbreakingly unattainable ideal of those
more normally fashioned viewers who dread being exposed as
substandard. And one should not be led by the tastelessness of
such fantasies as these into believing that they bear no relation to
the values we really hold dear - indeed, their very popularity
betrays the coarse directness of their celebration of what we have
come to be interested in.
Up until very recently there seemed to be little conscious aware-
ness among people I saw as patients (whom, again, I single out
only because I know them best, not because I see them as different
from the rest of us) that the injuries they occasioned and incurred
in the course of their pursuit of happiness were anything other
than the necessary result of failures in 'relationship'. People longed
for relationships they fancied they had never had, or pined for lost
relationships they feared they would never have again. They fretted
and seethed over frustrating relationships they could no longer
abide, they struggled with the panicky loss of identity consequent
on scarcely having any relationships at all, or they tried desperately
to piece themselves together after emerging from years of being the
victim of punitive or destructive relationships. In nearly all cases
these seemed to be 'relationship problems' arising more or less
directly out of human nature itself, and the 'answer' to them
seemed to lie in 'finding a good (or better) relationship'. All that
was needed, so it seemed, was love.
Now there are, I think, signs of a change taking place: no longer
95
'Relationships'
96
'Relationships'
Friendship
With one or two notable exceptions - for example the American
psychiatrist H. S. Sullivan- friendship is a form of relationship little
discussed in the 'clinical literature' of psychology and psychiatry,
though loneliness and isolation play a very prominent role in the
kinds of emotional distress which drive people to seek help from
the 'experts'. The ideal 'therapeutic' solution to such loneliness is
often seen as the formation of a long-term sexual bond, and when
most people talk of their need to establish 'a relationship' what
they usually mean is an exclusive liaison with someone of the
opposite sex. In this way, and with consequences I shall come to
consider shortly, heterosexual pair-relationships carry a very heavy
therapeutic load in our society: warmth, safety, fulfilment and
97
'Relationships'
98
'Relationships'
99
'Relationships'
100
'Relationships'
The reasons for the violence we do each other are all too clear,
but do not reside in the individual agent. This insight - common,
I think, to many of those who work in the 'helping professions'
even if they do not always make it explicit - is one which renders
particularly repugnant the righteous indignation of those who
pontificate about the state of public morality, and utterly disgusting
the 'media's' baying for the punishment of people whose wretched-
ness leads to tragedy.
Given a safe enough environment, then, it seems to me that
most people are glad of an opportunity to love their fellows. The
travesty of friendship which one sees in our rituals of fake intimacy,
the timid confidences which are barely heard by partners absorbed
in the formulation of what they intend to confide in their turn,
indicate an altruism stunted and frustrated by a society which
dislocates people from a world of constructive action and turns
them against each other in bitter competition. If we do not truly
'open up' to each other, 'be sensitive', 'show our feelings' in the
way that the therapy industry encourages us to do, it is because
we have good reasons not to - we live in a social world which
really is dangerous. To try to solve the 'problem' by, again, manip-
ulating the surface phenomena of individual behaviour (i.e. simu-
lating behavioural effects rather than tackling socio-economic
causes), is to foster just the kind of faking and artificiality with
which we are so familiar from the world of 'marketing' and to
ignore the abuses of power which underlie our rational fear and
suspicion of each other.
On the evidence to date, it would stretch credulity beyond all
reasonable limits to suggest that human beings, or human society,
were truly perfectible in any absolute sense, and I do not want to
lay claim to a vision of a utopian world in which sweetness and
light will reign supreme and undisturbed. One need not lapse into
'biologisms' concerning human 'nature' or 'instincts' to observe
the hair-trigger nervousness and violence with which people and
societies react to threat,* and the quite appalling terror and
oppression which they will resort to in establishing and protecting
their interests. But however inevitable much of this may be there
is still enormous room for improvement, and such improvement
can only sensibly be looked for in the social, moral and political
101
'Relationships'
Sex
It has become almost impossible to think clearly or constructively
about sex, since sexual satisfaction is the pivot around which our
commercial culture turns, the sacred central axiom of a dogma of
gratification which will not allow itself to be questioned or criti-
cized. To suggest, for instance, that sex should be for anything
other than itself, or to speculate that there could be any grounds
for control of or abstinence from sexual indulgence (even, for
example, in order to avoid a risk of fatal disease) is to invite
immediate dismissal from the community of rational beings, even
to occasion worried concern for the state of one's mental health.
The isolation of sex from procreation and the refinement and
promulgation of sexual pleasures of every form and variety, the
'liberation' of women by the pill and the widespread acceptance
and endorsement of forms of sexuality once considered 'perverse',
all these are seen as the triumphs of an age which has freed us
from sexual prudery, repression and hypocrisy, and given us
permission to pursue our pleasures, to explore and exploit each
other's orifices without a shred of shame.
Let me hasten to reassure the reader at this point that I am not
about to advocate a 'return' to no-doubt mythical standards of a
past sexual propriety, to suggest that we abandon contraception,
impose unnecessary abstinence upon ourselves or make homosexu-
102
'Relationships'
103
'Relationships'
105
'Relationships'
people experience and the injuries they inflict on each other in their
sexual encounters. There is an enormous contrast between the
images of sexual satisfaction in which our culture trades and the
actual experience of the people who are subjected to them, but
attempts to explicate sexual experience (rather than to tend it or
stoke it 'therapeutically') are quite often met with refusal or even
anger. But, I suspect, if one is to gain any understanding of the
painful strife which so often these days infuses both hetero- and
homosexual relations, one will have to be prepared to trace them
back into the power relations which society imposes on its
members. In this way, the sexual experience and proclivities of
individuals cannot be fully understood without investigating their
personal history, particularly in terms of the permutations of
relations between mothers and fathers and sons and daughters,
since it is through these relations that the wider social influences
make themselves felt. Inevitably, we are the agents of our society's
exploitation, and the most potent source of learning in the ways
of relationship (for good or for ill) is the family. The purpose of
trying to trace, for example, the significance of (among other
things) individuals' sexual conduct back into their personal
histories is not, as will be evident from the previous chapter, to
seek to change it, but rather to develop the beginnings of an
understanding of how we come to shape our children in ways of
relationship which they cannot escape.
Marriage
For the psychologist (or anyone else) interested in the kinds of
'relationship' which seem so to preoccupy us, marriage provides
the magnifying glass through which they may be most closely
studied, for it is in the (relatively) long-term contract of marriage
that our mythical expectations as well as our actual experience of
'relationship' are most clearly exposed.
More than any other form of relationship, marriage carries our
hopes for a warm, fulfilling, safe, confiding, mentally and physically
satisfying bond with another person. Yet in practice marriage
causes more bitterness, resentment, disappointment and inarticu-
late pain than all our other 'relationships' put together. For count-
less people, what is confidently embarked upon as an exclusive
mutual alliance against an indifferent or hostile world, a search for
a haven of warmth in a cold and competitive society, turns out to
be a journey into a totally unexpected, private and unanalysable
hell - one seeming, furthermore, to constitute an entirely personal
and exceptional misery which, if it is not ended in a burst of hatred
106
'Relationships'
107
'Relationships'
108
'Relationships'
109
'Relationships'
tion in each other wears away and the exigencies of the world
outside 'the relationship' begin to reassert themselves, each partner
reads in the conduct of the other a personal betrayal, or in their
own disappointment a shameful failure of commitment. The
husband (to take the still typical case) finds his wife's lack of
understanding for the call on his attention of his work commit-
ments, and her demand for continual demonstration of his interest
in and affection towards her, irksome and unfair - can't she see
how much he thinks of her? Can't she tell that the work he does
is for her (and perhaps for their young children)? Can't she see
that he needs to relax when he gets home, not to talk about a day
he wants to forget, nor to hear the trivial details of hers? These
feelings his wife interprets as a treacherous decrease of the loving
involvement he had shown. He no longer seems to care, and all
she experiences is the enervating isolation of a life incarcerated
with small children, few friends and a family she rarely sees. Her
husband is uncommunicative, elsewhere, absorbed in a world of
power and money (even if only at the very bottom of its hierarchy)
which seems to mean more to him than she. They no longer talk
to each other as they did. He gets more out of talking to the people
who share his working world, she makes a confidante of one or
two young mothers she knows. She feels his sexual interest in her
as invasive and insincere, mere lust. He is hurt and bewildered by
her lessened sexual interest in him. Each feels that 'the marriage'
threatens to be a failure; it is not what it was, and has not turned
out either as they expected or as it should. Perhaps they were, after
all, not right for each other.
And so to the phase of re-illusion, in which the partners cast
around to rediscover what they feel they have lost. For the wife,
busy with tending to the needs of children, this may mean little
more than daydreaming, fantasizing the appearance of a kind and
attentive, gentle man who will love her for herself alone. As long
as she is dependent on her husband for her keep, she can afford to
show him little of these feelings, but if she becomes more financially
independent as the children get older, she may begin to allow her
contempt and resentment to show rather more boldly; perhaps also
she will turn the children into partners in an alliance against the
unfeeling and insensitive male, the father/husband whose still too-
powerful figure begins to throw a shadow almost of dread over
the household. Re-illusion is perhaps particularly the province of
the male. The husband, sexually rejected, hurt and perhaps
excluded (though perhaps none of these, but rather just pining
for the lost adulation of a woman) finds himself embroiled in a
'relationship' with another woman - the disillusioned wife of a
friend, possibly, or a younger unattached woman at work. The
110
'Relationships'
114
'Relationships'
*L. Stone, op. cit. See also Phillipe Aries, Centuries of Childhood,
Jonathan Cape, 1962.
115
'Relationships'
117
'Relationships'
118
'Relationships'
119
'Relationships'
121
7
Growing Up and Taking
Care
Understanding, as I have tried to show, does not equal cure. For
the individual starting out on psychotherapy it often seems as if
all that is needed for the relief of his or her nameless distress would
be a clear sight of what the reasons for it are. But even though the
gaining of such a clear sight may be a lengthy, painful and testing
procedure, its difficulties are as nothing compared with those which
arise once the mist disperses and the person can see quite clearly
the nature of his or her predicament. For the predicament is where
one is, and though one may be able to envisage in perfect detail
where one would like to be, the greatest difficulties are encountered
in knowing how to get there. There are, of course, some advantages
in knowing where you are, and for many patients this is an
improvement on the confusion and discomfort of their original
condition, and indeed one which often they have to settle for, if
only because their history or their situation precludes their being
able to act on their world in such a way as significantly to change
it. But even for those who do have some prospect of being able to
influence their situation through their own conduct, the way is
never less than daunting and always demands great effort and
courage.
Precisely the same kind of constellation of difficulties, though
on a vastly greater scale, faces the analysis, such as it is, presented
in this book. Whatever clarity may have been gained through
having broken free of the conceptual restraints placed on our
understanding of human distress by the disciplinary structures,
greedy individualism and meshed interests of a hierarchy of power,
we are still no nearer to knowing how to change our lives or to
escape the influences we may now see as damaging us. However,
perhaps it is a little easier to catch a glimpse of how, if only we
could change them, our lives ought to look: the ends may be fairly
clear even if the means are as obscure as ever. In this chapter, then,
I shall undertake the relatively uncomplicated task of suggesting
what indications for less destructive and deluded ways of living
seem to me to follow from the foregoing analysis. In the next, and
final, chapter I shall discuss, without hoping to resolve, some of
the difficulties and dilemmas involved in trying actually to bring
into existence forms of social conduct which are, I think, easily
enough identified as desirable.
122
Growing Up and Taking Care
Growing Up
The blissful security of infancy - the inevitable if for some pitifully
short foundation of our experience - is, as has been noted, not to
be recaptured. In circumstances rather saner than those pertaining
in the 'civilized' world towards the end of the twentieth century,
it is likely to be the natural course of a person's life that it should,
once delivered from the womb, turn progressively outwards
towards the world. The process of growing up corresponds to the
cultivation of a 'public' life in which the person is enabled, as well
perhaps as obliged, to make a contribution to the social world
before coming to the end of his or her brief sojourn in it. This is
not to say that 'private' life - the internal world of feelings and
'relationships' - is unimportant or to be despised, but rather that
it is of little interest to anyone other than th,~ individual in question
and those with whom he or she comes into intimate contact.
It is in the public sphere that one may have a more or less
formal function through which one contributes to the world, and
it is in the private sphere that one may tend to the concerns of the
self. The 'pursuit of happiness' is properly a private matter, the
instrumental use of one's body in a social context properly a public
matter. We are, in ways and for reasons which may become a
little clearer in the course of this discussion, chronically confused
between the public and private spheres.
The possibility of public life confers a kind of dignity, a social
as opposed to a purely personal value, even at the lowliest level.
The doorman, for example, in his commissionaire's uniform, may
for many be little more than a slightly comical symbol of petty
authority, but the 'publicness' of his role at least permits him to
wear an expression of pride which will almost certainly be absent
123
Growing Up and Taking Care
124
Growing Up and Taking Care
125
Growing Up and Taking Care
126
Growing Up and Taking Care
127
Growing Up and Taking Care
128
Growing Up and Taking Care
129
Growing Up and Taking Care
precisely that, and not to try to push them into conformity with
some standardized conception of 'mental health'. Rather than
being, as they unwittingly too often are, representatives of a form
of social discipline, psychotherapists could better become the reti-
cent and unheroic assistants of people whose private struggles are
nobody's business but their own and that of those in whom they
choose to confide. In this way psychotherapists should occupy a
status position more similar to that of those old-fashioned phys-
icians who in order to test their patients' urine had to taste it than
to that of magicians or social engineers; there is, in other words,
not a great deal of glamour or mystery in examining the difficulties
and distress we encounter in our private lives.)
While an individual's happiness or despair may indeed reside in
his or her private life, the point of living has more relevance to the
public sphere. Indeed, the very possibility of being able to
contribute to the society in which one lives may well redeem or
give meaning to a life lived otherwise in misery. Even were our
exclusive interest in people's private lives compassionate rather
than commercial, we should still, by draining off the possibility for
public conduct, render them meaningless. Suffering is not to be
desired for itself, but better suffering with the possibility of redemp-
tion than a purely private bliss.
It is almost impossible to envisage what sort of society it would
be which permitted or encouraged all its members to turn their
lives towards some public function. Our own society, certainly, is
diametrically opposed to this: it siphons off the possibility of 'other-
directed' (altruistic) conduct in order to commodify its products
and sell them back to people as consumers. But if there is any
'point' to living, it must surely lie in what we can do; our embodied
organisms are surely for something other than their own satisfac-
tion. Only if we live in the perpetual 'now' of the advertiser's
euphoric world could we really believe that a life which is not
permitted to develop and apply its talents for the benefit of all is
not, no matter how great its private satisfaction, a life wasted. It
is the instrumentality of the body which renders it indispensable
to the evolution of a social world, not its capacity for enjoyment,
nor even, I would suggest, its inclination towards spiritual
'fulfilment'.
It is indeed the very uni-dimensionality of our materialistic phil-
osophy which leads us to think it essential that we should know
what the 'point' of living is in any case. We tend to assume, for
example, that unless we can identify a 'point', life becomes pointless
or absurd. But there is no compelling reason to believe that, for
there to be a point, we should know what it is. It is, after all, likely
to take many more thousands of centuries before we have got as
130
Growing Up and Taking Care
131
Growing Up and Taking Care
Taking Care
It is not easy to think of the privileges and obligations of growing
up in any terms other than those relating to an economics of
consumption, the values of which are essentially passive and mech-
anically automatic. Thus progressive maturity becomes a question
of the widening availability of certain commodities or pleasures
(initiation into smoking, drinking, sex and 'adult' entertainment,
availability of credit facilities, mortgages, etc.) and responsibility in
observing certain legal and fiscal rules (e.g. in relation to taxation,
military obligations, etc.). Since our ethics are those of the market-
place and our view of knowledge and learning mechanistic and
'objective', we tend not to regard the transmission of our culture
as a central task of all those 'embodied organisms' who go to make
up our society, but rather as something which can safely be, and
probably should be, left to professional experts of one kind or
another. The rest of us can then get on with the serious business
of making enough money to enjoy ourselves.
If, however, one takes seriously the argument put forward earlier
in this book that indeed we are embodied organisms, that we are
formed in the context of a history and a current set of circum-
stances whose effects are likely to be ineradicable, and that the
132
Growing Up and Taking Care
133
Growing Up and Taking Care
134
Growing Up and Taking Care
135
Growing Up and Taking Care
136
Growing Up and Taking Care
138
Growing Up and Taking Care
139
Growing Up and Taking Care
141
Growing Up and Taking Care
142
8
Morality and Moralism
It is hard to conceive of a society in which all its members actually
treat each other well. Presumably there has never been one. There
have been, and are, societies in which a (usually religious) ethical
code prescribes how people ought to treat each other even though
they fail lamentably to live up to it. It is becoming increasingly
apparent that contemporary Western society has no such ethical
code. The empty shell of a system of Christian ethics, having for
many centuries been laid siege to by the interests of power, has at
last been taken over by the values of the market: Christianity
becomes simply another way of getting things, achieving 'fulfil-
ment' or a kind of exclusive 'salvation'. Most of us, therefore, live
in a society in which there is no formal moral authority, no ethically
based, publicly institutionalized code of conduct to which people
subscribe in common. This is not to say, of course, that people do
not still behave decently towards one another, but the grounds of
this decency are hidden away tacitly and informally (and vulner-
ably) in their private lives. The maxims of public life centre around
competition, cost-effectiveness and the 'creation of wealth'. Ours,
in short, is no longer an ethical community.
There are many perfectly understandable reasons for this state
of affairs, but I suspect that the most important are those of which
'ordinary people' are least aware. For many people moral attitudes
and prescriptions have too often been associated either with no
longer credible religious magic or with hypocritical abuse of auth-
ority for them to be able to submit to rules which so often turn
out to be in somebody else's interest. The gradual fusion since
mediaeval times of religious ethics with powerful commercial inter-
ests has more recently accelerated to culminate in the supplantation
of the former by the latter, has rendered moral understanding
increasingly obscure, and has bred an entirely justifiable distrust
of what has come to be seen as moralism. However, by far the
most important reason for the disappearance of what one might
call a 'public ethical code' is that its continuation would place
unacceptable restraints on commercial exploitation. However
brutal the mediaeval feudal lords may have been, and however
corrupt the Church, at least, officially, they were not supposed to
be. We have now reached a stage when the precepts of exploitation
and self-interest are being slid into the place of moral values which
can scarcely any longer be remembered.
The very idea of 'morality' - again understandably - is likely
143
Morality and Moralism
of prudence and thrift, when they might better consider the purely
logical dependence of wealth upon poverty and the social issues
raised thereby.
Moralism is typically exemplified in the imputations of blame
through which, as was argued in Chapter 4, the inequalities and
injustices of our society are 'explained' as the moral failings of
individuals. It is characteristic of moralism to attempt to cast
morality in an explanatory form, either as causes of distress or
failure or as motives which may be appealed to in exhortations to
bear with adversity. But, of course, moral precepts are not things
or forces which can be appealed to as operating somehow mechan-
ically inside people, but rather are formulated as guides to public
conduct. People, clearly, may conduct themselves morally or
immorally, but they do not do things because of morality or
immorality.
Moralism 'privatizes' morality. 'Moral responsibility', writes the
archpriest of monetarism, • 'is an individual matter, not a social
matter.' This, of course, leaves one conveniently placed to chide
individuals who have succumbed to misfortune for their lack of
moral fibre while allowing public conduct to be determined by the
dictates of 'the market'. The 'invisible hand' of the market relieves
one of the disagreeable necessity for deciding whether one's public
activity is right or wrong, since its guidance is regarded as somehow
infallible. Moral values thus become prescriptions identifiable by
powerful people whose public conduct is seen itself as somehow
above moral judgment, and applied to private individuals usually
in the form of explanations concerning the personal failings that
have led to their lack of success. The apparatus of interest, by
transforming morality into moralism, turns it to its own advantage:
the undoubted force of moral precept is deflected from its valid
function of guiding public conduct and reshaped as a mystifying
'explanation' (as individual fault) of evils which are in fact the
consequence of an immoral abuse of power.
One of the most striking and interesting things about the concept
of morality itself is precisely its force. However disguised its oper-
ation or mystified its application, morality will simply not go away.
Despite a widespread dissatisfaction people seem to feel with
having to base their conduct on anything so vague and uncertain
as moral judgment, and despite also the success of technological
approaches which are based on a science supposedly 'value free',
we can still, it seems, not dispense with words like 'right' and
'good' and 'ought'. It is no doubt easy to confuse technical with
moral prescription: there are many areas in which accurate know!-
145
Morality and Moralism
146
Morality and Moralism
149
Morality and Moralism
former way of life and is ready to adopt the new. The whole
world feels it, and is convinced of it. But inertia and fear of
the unknown retards the application in practice of what has
for a long time been realized in theory. In such cases it
sometimes needs only one word to make the force called
public opinion change the whole order of things at once, and
do it without struggle or violence.
'The freeing of men from servitude, from ignorance, can
not be obtained by revolution, syndicates, peace congresses,
etc., but simply by the conscience of each one of us forbidding
us to participate in violence and asking us in amazement:
Why are you doing that?
'It is enough for us to emerge from the hypnosis that hides
our true mission from us, for us to ask with dread and
indignation how any one can insist upon our committing
such horrible crimes. And this awakening can take place at
any instant.'
This is what I wrote fifteen years ago, and I repeat today
with conviction that this awakening is about to take place.
Certainly I shall not be there to take part in it, I, an old
man, more than eighty years of age; but I know with the
same certainty as I see spring follow winter and night day,
that this hour has already come in the life of Christian
humanity.•
In 1921 R. H. Tawney's The Acquisitive Society was published.
In its final paragraph Tawney states its principal conclusions and
predicts the disappearance from society of purely economic
preoccupations with a confidence beginning to sound rather
familiar:
The burden of our civilization is not merely, as many suppose,
that the product of industry is ill-distributed, or its conduct
tyrannical, or its operation interrupted by embittered
disagreements. It is that industry itself has come to hold a
position of exclusive predominance among human interests,
which no single interest, and least of all the provision of the
material means of existence, is fit to occupy. Like a hypochon-
driac who is so absorbed in the processes of his own digestion
that he goes to his grave before he has begun to live, indus-
trialized communities neglect the very objects for which it is
worth while to acquire riches in their feverish preoccupation
with the means by which riches can be acquired.
*L. Tolstoy, The Law of Love and the Law of Violence, Anthony
Blond, 1970.
154
Morality and Moralism
155
Morality and Moralism
156
Morality and Moralism
158
Morality and Moralism
159
Morality and Moralism
160
Morality and Moralism
161
Index
Adler, A., 113 Davidson, N., 73n
'Angry Young Men', 155, 157 death instinct, 28
Arendt, H., 30-1, 35 Debord, G., 10n
Aries, P., 115n delinquency, 54
astrology, 48-9 demystification, 4-5
determinism, 75
Bacon, F., 50 Dickens, C., 20, 139
'Beat Generation', 155, 157 difficulty, 88, 91, 122, 128
beauty, 141 discipline, 53-5, 67, 128-30, 142,
behaviourism, 46, 51 148-9
Bion, W., 12, 13n disease, 73-4
blame, 6, 66-72, 76, 90, 115, 145 disillusion, 109-10
bliss, memory of, 26-7, 33, 73, divination, 48
123-4 Divoky, D., 53n, 55, 58
Boorstin, D., 10n dreams, 2, 7-11, 16, 75, 81, 120,
Braude!, F., 158-60 128, 140-1
bulimia, 42
Buss, R., 65n embodiedness, 11, 13, 74-5, 120,
133, 138-42
Calderon, P., 7 encounter groups, 99, 102
caring, 72 encouragement, 4-5, 48, 51, 126,
categorical imperative, 148 142
change, 44, 79-81, 84-7, 90-1 Enlightenment, the, 29
children, 106, 113-20, 127, equality, 77, 142
135-6 examinations, 54-5
Christianity, 138, 143 'excellence', 136
Church, the, 17, 29, 149 exploitation, 69, 77, 89, 106, 115,
comfort, 4, 6, 46, 48, 51, 91, 142 120, 143, 147, 152, 160
commitment, 96, 107, 112 Eysenck, H. j., 57
commodity, 19, 33, 93-4, 96-7,
103-4 factory farming, 37, 87
Comte, A., 18, 48 faith, 132
consumption, 39, 97, 117, 126, familiarity, 34, 36, 89, 142
132 family, 106, 113-19
counter-culture, 157 Farber, L. H., 75n
cruelty, 120 fathers, 106, 114-15
culture, 19, 132-5, 138 fault, 19, 67-8, 77, 109
cure, 15, 48, 73, 79-82, 85-6, 90, feelings, 72-4, 127, 129
122 fixation, 126-8
Foucault, M., 53-5, 58, 65, 67,
Danziger, K., 64, 65n 103, 113
daughters, 106, 114-15 freedom, 7 6, 91
163
Index
Freud, S., 9, 15, 26, 28, 84, 85n, Laing, R. D., 134
103, 113-14 Langer, S., 9n
Friedman, M., 145n language, 69, 137, 139
friendship, 97-102 Lasch, C., tOn, 38n, 58, 157
Fromm, E., lOln learning, 81-4, 136-9
function, 39-40, 96, 123, 133 Locke, J., 52-3
future, 39-40, 131, 133-4, 141-2, Lomas, P., 84n
152-3 love, 5, 27, 81, 85-6, 96, 100-1,
142, 152
gender, 105
God, 150, 159 magic, 3, 11, 13, 15, 47-51, 78,
Godwin, W., 34, 153, 156 81-2, 132, 141-2, 144
Goldsmith, 0., 108 managerialism, 40, 57-8, 61
Goodman, P., 14, 28n, 155 Marcuse, H., 118n
gratification, 95-8, 102-4, 112, marketing, 37, 59, 101, 136
129, 142 marriage, 106-13, 126, 129
growing up, 123-32 men,98-9, 104-5,107
guilt, 6, 51, 55, 70-2, 75 monetarism, 145
money,22,28,40, 56,103,119
happiness, 24-35, 39-40, 42, 68, moral inversion, 146, 149, 160
72-3, 83, 90, 93, 95, 103, 108, moralism, 68, 103, 115, 143-47,
120, 125, 141-2, 148-9 160
history, cultural, 20-1, 29, 135 morality, 143-52, 160-1
history, personal, 46, 69, 74, mothers, 106, 114
88-91, 103, 106 motivation, 44, 60
Hobson, R. F., 84n Mozart, W. A., 25
hope, 159 Mumford, L., 156
mystification, 15, 47, 73, 90, 108,
Illich, 1., 73, 105, 134, 139 147, 149
image, 10, 17, 38, 61, 99
individualism, 34, 41, 77, 87, 109, need, 33, 95-6, 99, 120
120, 125, 141 negotiation, 4
individuals (vs. society), 19, 67, New Right, 68, 75-6
70, 104 'normality', 90-1, 139
insight, 81-2, 84, 91, 152
interest, 2, 16-22, 28, 39, 47, 51, Oedipus complex, 114
56, 58-65, 68-9, 72, 81, 83, old age, 24-5, 111, 126
96, 105, 108, 115, 125, 131, oppression, 70, 101
145, 148-51, 161 optimism, 139, 142, 153, 157, 160
interpretation, 15, 86, 91 organism, 88-9, 91-2, 133-4
intimacy, 98-9, 102, 129 'otherness', 105, 139-40
'Invisible Hand', 60, 145-6
pain, 11, 41, 73, 112, 128, 141
Jefferson, T., 30 parenthood, 72, 126
justice, 77, 142 parents, 113-20
Passmore, J., 29, 30n, 52-3
Kant, 1., 148-50 past, 40
knowledge, 133, 136-8 point of life, 26, 33-4, 93, 99,
Kumar, S., 134n 124-5, 130-1
164
Index
Polanyi, M., 146 'skills', 82-3, 94, 99, 132, 137
politics, 56-7, 147, 161 slavery, 35, 131, 159
posterity, 40-2 Smith, A., 60, 146
power, 22, 30, 47, 53-4, 57-70, social evolution, 39
77, 89, 102, 105-6, 113-20, sons, 106, 114-15
147, 151-2, 161 stoicism, 128
private life, 123-31, 15 2, 160-1 Stone, L., 108-9, 115n
psychiatry, 20 Sullivan, H. S., 97
psychoanalysis, 68-9, 82 Suttie, I. D., 27n, 85n
psychology, 11, 19-20, 22, symptoms, 41, 46, 57, 79, 82
44-53,56-9,64-5,81,83
psychotherapy, 3, 11, 48, 79-82, taking care, 93, 132-42, 152
84-5, 91 Tawney, R. H., 20-2, 39n, 154,
public life, 123-31, 133-4, 139, 157
143-9, 152, 159-61 Taylor, F. W., 58n
television, 10, 38, 87, 90, 95
reality, 7-11, 36, 75, 141 terror, 113
reasons, 69, 71, 75 therapeutic assumption, 73-4, 77,
re-illusion, 109-10 80, 86
'relationships', 33, 93-7, 99-100, therapy, 3, 77-8, 90, 93, 139, 142,
104-13, 118, 120, 123, 137, 161
140-1 Thomas, K., 47-51
religion, 56, 68, 143-4, 147 Tolstoy, L., 17, 109n, 141, 153,
renunciation, 128, 142 154n, 156
repression, 16-17, 22, 34-5, 41, Townsend, P., 73n
56, 58-9, 77, 103, 105, tradition,41-2, 135, 137
113-15 treatment, 70, 152
research, 80-1 truth, 75, 142, 150
resignation, 109, 111
Rogers, C. R., 84 'understanding', 90-1, 98, 112,
Rousseau, J.-J., 108 119, 140
Utilitarian philosophy, 29, 52,
Salmon, P., 127n
148, 151, 153
satisfaction, 40-1, 93-4, 96,
103-4, 112, 120, 124
Schafer, R., 69, 86 violence, 99-100, 113-15, 120,
Schrag, P., 53n, 55, 58 125
science, 9, 17, 29, 45, 50-1
secret ballot, 147 Wertham, F., 101n
self, 98-100, 141 will, 75, 77
Servan, J., 52 women, 104-5, 107, 111
sex, 38, 102-6, 113-14 Wood, G., 68
shame, 67
Shotter, J., 57n young people, 14, 134
165