Unit 1 Types of Categorical Propositions: A, E, I, O and Square of Opposition
Unit 1 Types of Categorical Propositions: A, E, I, O and Square of Opposition
Unit 1 Types of Categorical Propositions: A, E, I, O and Square of Opposition
1.0 OBJECTIVES
First objective of this unit is to introduce you to the elements of categorical proposition.
This is intended to be achieved through the introduction of the nature of terms and
their distinction from words. The second objective is to establish an important
distinction between sentence and proposition. The last, but not the least, objective
is to familiarize you with certain forms of logical relations called immediate inference
which should in turn enable you to establish and discover certain other important
logical relations.
1.1 INTRODUCTION
As a form of critical thinking, logic has its origin in several ancient civilizations, like
Indian, Chinese, Greek, etc. In the Western tradition, logic was systematized by
Aristotle and hence he is credited with its origin. Logic, ‘the tool for distinguishing
between the true and the false’ (Averroes), examines the general forms which
arguments may take, and distinguishes between valid and invalid arguments. An
argument consists of two sets of statements called premise or premises, on the one
hand, and the conclusion on the other. The premises are designed to support the
conclusion. The presence of this complex relation (also called inference) makes a
group of statements an argument and with which logic is concerned. Thus mere
collection of propositions does not constitute an argument when this relation is absent.
In this unit we shall confine ourselves to an analysis of terms and propositions which
are basic to our study of logic and postpone a detailed study of inference to the next
unit.
a,b,c,
S = {a,b,c,d,e,f}
S d,e,f P = {a,b,c,d,e,f,g,h,i}
∴ S ⊂ P or P ⊃ S
g,h,i P
2) SEP
S = {a,b,c,d,e,f}
S a,b,c, g,h, P P = {g,h,i,j,k}
d,e,f I,j,k
∴SΔP
3) SIP
S = {a,b,c,d,e,f}
S a b g P P = {b,c,d,g,h,i}
e c h
∩P = {b,c,d}
∴ S∩
f d i
4) SOP
m P
S* a S* = {a,b,c}
n
b s
g P = {m,n,g,h}
c h
Now we are in a position to examine the fourth group. It requires a little explication
to understand the status of O with regard to distribution. In this instance S* is
incomplete, i.e., undistributed and P is completely excluded by S*. It shows that P
is distributed. Let us see how this happens.
1) Let S = {a,b,c,d,e,f}
12
4) Let S - S* = S** (S** ≥ Φ) or S = S* + S** Types of Categorical
Propositions: A,E,I,O and
‘ Φ’ reads phi which stands for null set. Square of Opposition
5) S** ⊆ P
6) S* || S**Φ || means that elements of subsets S* and S** are different.
∴ S* || P
∴ Elements of S* and P are different.
John Venn followed a very different method. We shall begin with this proposition.
9 All rabbits are herbivorous - RAH.
Since rabbits are animals, the universe of discourse is, obviously, 'animals'. Venn
represents the universe of discourse with a rectangle. If rabbits are the elements of
the set R, then all other animals than rabbits constitute the complement of the set R.
Complement of R is represented by R and the same explanation holds good for all
classes. Now a new term is introduced, viz., 'product class'. Any product class is
an intersection of two or more than two sets (as far as logic is concerned, the number
is restricted to three). {RH} is the product class of R and H. Such product classes
may or may not be null sets. But {R R }, {H H } (for example, the set of animals
which are rabbits and other than rabbits at the same time) are invariably null sets.
When there are two terms, we get four product classes, which are as follows.
13
Classical Logic The statement (proposition is also called statement), 'All rabbits are herbivorous',
does not really mean that there are rabbits and all those rabbits are herbivorous. On
the other hand, the statement really means that if there are rabbits, then, they are
herbivorous. Clearly, it means that in the set of non-herbivorous not a single rabbit
can be found. Therefore is a null set. Similarly, the statement 'No rabbits are
herbivorous' - (REH) indicates that in the set of herbivorous not a single rabbit can
be found. Therefore {RH} is a null set. In Figures 1 and 2, those parts of the circle
or circles which represent null sets are shaded. RAH and REH only demonstrate
that there are null sets, but they are silent on non-null sets. Therefore an important
conclusion is imminent; universal propositions do not carry existential import.
It is widely held that all scientific laws are universal. An important fall-out of this
assumption is that if universal propositions do not carry existential import, then it
also means that scientific laws do not carry existential import in which case they
apply only to non-existing entities. Therefore all physical objects only approximate
to these laws. A scientific law, when stated in absolute terms, has to be construed as
a limiting point.
The case of particular proposition is different. The statement 'Some rabbits are
herbivorous - RIH' is true only when 'there exists at least one rabbit which is
herbivorous, not otherwise. Therefore the product class {RH} is a non-null set.
On the same lines, it can be easily shown that ROH shows that {RH} is also a non-
null set. Therefore particular propositions carry existential import.
Let us proceed on a different line. Verbal description makes room for symbolic
representation because this method proves to be a boon at a later stage.
The following two schemes and one diagram offer visual aid to retain more easily in
mind what we have just said about the 'opposition' of propositions:
For the sake of simplicity the truth - relation which holds good between various
relations is provided in a nutshell.
Inferences in Subalternation
From truth of universal → truth of particular
From truth of particular /→ truth of universal
15
Classical Logic From falsity of particular → falsity of universal
From falsity of universal /→ falsity of particular
→ : Can infer
→ : Cannot infer
/→
II) Mnemonic Device for remembering the Square of Opposition (Lander
University, Greenwood).
A) If you picture God at the top of the square of opposition and the Devil at the
bottom of the square and remember the phrase 'both cannot be ...' for contraries
and subcontraries, the following mnemonic device might be helpful.
B) The big 'X' across the center of the Square represents contradictories with
opposite truth - values. This should be very easy to remember.
C) Since God (or truth) is at the top of the diagram, both contraries 'cannot be
true.'
D) Since the Devil (or falsity) is at the bottom of the diagram, both subcontraries
'cannot be false'.
E) With subalternation, God can send truth down, but we cannot know what it
means for God to send falsity down (hence this would be indeterminate).
But, the Devil can send falsity up (since this is what Devils are good at), and we
cannot know what it means for the Devil to send truth up. So this relation is
indeterminate.
III) 'Bouncing Around the Square of Opposition.'
Suppose we know that O (Some S is not P) is false. In how many ways can we
determine the truth - value of I ('Some S is P')?
There are four ways of determining the truth-value. These four ways consist in
travelling between different points (here the propositions are points). The four routes
are as follows.
(Notice that we could set an itinerary of our journey along the selected four routes.
The 'reason,' given below, is, so to speak, our 'inference ticket' for travel Cf. Lander
University, Greenwood).
Originating Point Through Terminating Point
1) SOP Direct SIP
2) SOP SEP SIP
3) SOP SAP to SEP SIP
4) SOP SEP and SAP SIP
A 3 E
4 2
I 1 O
Route 1: O to I
16
Statement of Reason Truth -Value Types of Categorical
Propositions: A,E,I,O and
1) Some S is not P. Given false Square of Opposition
2) Some S is P. subcontrariety true
Route 2: O to I through E
Statement Reason Truth - Value
1) Some S is not P. given false
2) No S is P. subalternation false
3) Some S is P. contradictory true
Route 3: O to I through A and E
Statement Reason Truth - Value
1) Some S is not P. given false
2) All S is P. contradictory true
3) No S is P. contrariety false
4) Some S is P. contradictory true
One would think that if our logic were consistent, all possible routes from the false O
to I would result in a false truth - value for the I. But consider the following case--
Route 4.
Route 4: O to I through E and A
Statement Reason Truth -Value
1) Some S is not P. given false
2) No S is P. subalternation false
3) All S is P. contrariety indeterminate
4) Some S is P. subalternation indeterminate
Variance of truth-value in the fourth instance of I proposition indicates a hidden part
of the nature of immediate inferences. There is no technique to determine the truth-
value of the conclusion when the premise is indeterminate. The logical relations involve
deduction but not reflection. Change in quantity or quality affects logical force. The
logical force, consequently, differs from one proposition to another. Further, the
truth - value of the conclusion depends upon the logical force of the given proposition.
These factors explain variance in truth - value in the above mentioned instance.
Traditional logic ignored asymmetry involved in universal - particular relation which
was pointed out by Susan Stebbing. On this ground, she replaced square by a
figure:
17
Classical Logic Gaps at four corners point to asymmetry in this interpretation. The truth of A (or E)
implies the truth of I (or O), but the reverse order does not hold good. On the other
hand, the falsity of I (or O) implies the falsity of A (or E), but the reverse order does
not hold good. This is what precisely asymmetry is. These gaps, distinct lines for
superaltern and subaltern relations and unequal lines make this figure of opposition.
At this stage, it is important to become familiar with two other types of relation
called conversion and obversion. They are also known as equivalent relation because
the truth-value of both the premise and the conclusion remains the same, i.e. if the
premise is true, the conclusion is true and if the premise is false, the conclusion is
also false. When there is a change in the structure of sentences, on some occasions
meaning remains unchanged. It only means that the very same information is provided
in different ways. Recognition of this simple fact helps us in testing accurately the
validity of arguments and also in avoiding confusions. There are two primary forms
of equivalent relation; conversion and obversion. The conclusion in conversion is
called converse and in obversion obverse. The processes of conversion and obversion
are quite simple. These operations deserve a close scrutiny.
Conversion: This is governed by three laws.
1st Law: S and P must be transposed.
After transposition P becomes subject and S becomes predicate. This is the 1st
stage.
2nd Law: Quality of propositions should remain constant. If the premise is affirmative,
the conclusion must be affirmative. If the premise is negative, the conclusion must
be negative.
3rd Law: A term, which is undistributed in the premise, should remain undistributed in
the conclusion. It can be stated in another way also. A term can be distributed in the
conclusion only if it is distributed in the premise. However, a term, which is distributed
in the premise, may or may not be distributed in the conclusion. The following examples
illustrate these rules.
10) All philosophers are kings PAK
Converse: ∴ Some kings are philosophers. KIP
11) No vegetables are harmful. VEH
Converse: ∴ No harmful things are vegetables. HEV
12) Some women are talkative. WIT
Converse: ∴ Some talkative people are women. TIW
There are three aspects to be noted. Conversion of A is conversion by limitation
because the quantity is reduced from universal to particular after conversion. Secondly,
conversion of E and I is simple because in these cases S and P are just transposed
and no other change takes place. Thirdly, while A, E and I have conversion, O does
not have conversion. What happens when A undergoes simple conversion and O is
converted? In these cases conversion leads to a fallacy called fallacy of illicit
conversion. Fallacy in formal logic arises when a rule is violated. In both these cases
conversion violates a rule or rules.
Consider these statements.
13) All Europeans are white.
∴ All white people are Europeans.
18
14) Some gods are not powerful. Types of Categorical
Propositions: A,E,I,O and
∴ Some powerful beings are not gods. Square of Opposition
Conversion in these two cases is invalid because the terms, 'white' and 'gods' are
distributed in the respective conclusions while they are undistributed in the respective
premises. This type of conversion violates the third law. The terms 'white' and
'gods' remain undistributed in the premises since the former is the predicate of an
affirmative premise while the latter is the subject of a particular premise. If we
obtain affirmative converse from a negative premise in order to undistibute predicate
term, then we violate the second law of conversion. It only means that when A
undergoes simple conversion and when O is converted, in the case of A the third law
is violated and in the case of O second or third law of conversion, as the case may
be is violated. Therefore A becomes I after conversion and 'O' has no conversion.
Obversion: This is one technique of preserving the meaning of a statement after
effecting change of quality. The procedure is very simple; change the quality of the
premise and simultaneously replace the predicate by its complementary. We apply
this law to the premises (A, E, I, and O) to obtain the conclusions. The conclusion is
called obversion.
15) All players are experts. PAE
∴ No players are non-experts. PEE
16) No musicians are novelists. MEN
∴ All musicians are non-novelists. MAN
17) Some scholars are women. SIW
∴ Some scholars are not non-women. SOW
18) Some strangers are not helpful. SO H
∴ Some stranger are non-helpful. SIH
Check Your Progress II
Note: Use the space provided for your answers.
1) Give symbolic representation of propositions? What do the symbols stand for?
....................................................................................................................
....................................................................................................................
....................................................................................................................
....................................................................................................................
....................................................................................................................
2) Determine all possible product classes of the following terms and their
complements.
....................................................................................................................
....................................................................................................................
....................................................................................................................
....................................................................................................................
....................................................................................................................
19
Classical Logic a) players and experts b) philosophers and kings c) fruits and vegetables d)
actors and directors
20
Types of Categorical
UNIT 2 CATEGORICAL SYLLOGISM Propositions: A,E,I,O and
Square of Opposition
Contents:
2.0 Objectives
2.1 Introduction
2.2 Reason and Inference: Meaning and Objections
2.3 Kinds of Inference
2.4 Deductive Reasoning and Syllogism
2.5 Kinds of Syllogism
2.6 Let Us Sum Up
2.7 Key Words
2.8 Further Readings and References
2.0 OBJECTIVES
This unit introduces you to the essence of Aristotelian logic. Since syllogism is the
most important form of inference, you ought to have a background of the nature
of inference and various issues associated with it. One objective of this unit is to
give a brief explanation of the nature of deductive inference and contrast it with
inductive inference. Another objective is to analyze different kinds of syllogism to
enable you to understand variety in syllogism.
2.1 INTRODUCTION
Categorical syllogism is the essence of traditional logic. This form of inference is
called mediate inference because the conclusion is drawn from two premises. Further,
this is called categorical because all propositions involved are categorical. Since
syllogistic inference is nearly identical with deductive inference, an exhaustive analysis
of inference is required as a prelude to a proper understanding of syllogism.
32
Categorical Syllogism
2.8 FURTHER READINGS AND REFERENCES
Azzopardi, Salvino. Logic. Pune: Jnana Deepa Vidyapeeth, 1981.
Baronett, Stan. Logic. New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 2008.
Copi, Irving M., and Carl Cohen. Essentials of Logic. 2nd ed. Upper Saddle River,
N.J.: Pearson Prentice Hall, 2007.
Priest, Graham. Logic. New York: Sterling Publishing. 2010.
Yoder, Gil ‘Categorical Syllogisms’ http://www.oabs.org/classes/logic/
categorical%20syllogisms.pdf accessed August 2, 2010.
33
Classical Logic
UNIT 3 FIGURE, MOOD AND THE
POSSIBLE TYPES OF
SYLLOGISMS
Contents
3.0 Objectives
3.1 Introduction
3.2 Moods of Categorical Syllogism
3.3 Figures of Syllogism
3.4 Incomplete Syllogism and Compound Syllogism
3.5 Dilemma
3.6 Avoiding Dilemma
3.7 Let Us Sum Up
3.8 Key Words
3.9 Further Readings and References
3.0 OBJECTIVES
This unit proposes to introduce a very interesting aspect of syllogism, viz. figures
and moods. Through a study of figures and moods you will be in a position to gain
an insight into the intricacies of categorical syllogism. This is the main objective of
this unit. Second objective is to introduce you to the abridged and extended versions
of syllogism.
Another equally important objective is to bring out the features of dilemma which is
a sort of pseudo- syllogism so that you will be in a position to contrast a genuine
argument like syllogism with a pseudo-argument. Thereby another objective is also
served. Your acumen to evaluate the logical significance is further sharpened. This is
the most invaluable gift of logic.
3.1 INTRODUCTION
Arguments are of complex nature. It is not possible to bring all arguments, even
arguments of one class, under a common head. A detailed analysis of syllogism
reveals the hidden complexities of the same. Such a study consists in the discussion
of the structure of syllogism which leads to figures and moods. A clear understanding
of the structure of syllogism exposes the wealth of syllogistic argument. As usual, the
premises have to be taken as true, whether or not they are factually true.
I
M P
Major Premise: All artists are poets. AAP
S M
Minor Premise: All musicians are artists. MAA
Conclusion: ∴ All musicians are poets. MAP
S P
II
P M
Major Premise: All saints are pious. SAP
S M
Minor Premise: No criminals are pious. CEP
Conclusion: No criminals are saints. CES
S P
III
M P
Major Premise: All great works are worthy of study. GAW
M S
Minor Premise: All great works are epics. GAE
Conclusion: ∴ Some epics are worthy of study. EIW
S P
37
Classical Logic IV
P M
Major Premise: No soldiers are traitors. SET
M S
Minor Premise: All traitors are sinners. TAS
Conclusion: ∴ Some sinners are not soldiers. SOS
S P
We will consider figures in conjunction with moods. Then only knowledge of the
‘figure of syllogism’ permits us to compute the total number of possible moods.
Mood is determined by quality and quantity of propositions, which constitute
syllogism. Since there are four figures, in all two hundred and fifty six ways of arranging
categorical propositions is possible. These are exactly what we mean by moods.
However, out of two hundred and fifty-six, two hundred and forty-five moods can
be shown to be invalid by applying the rules and corollaries. So we have only
eleven valid moods. Even this is not sufficient to have a clear picture. There is no
figure in which all eleven moods are valid. Within the framework of traditional logic,
in any given figure only six moods are valid. They are as follows:
I AAA, AAI, EAE, EAO, EIO and AII
II AEE, AEO, EAE, EAO, EIO and AOO
III AAI, AII, IAI, EAO, EIO and OAO
IV AAI, IAI, AEE, AEO, EAO, and EIO
In all these cases, first letter stands for the major premise, second for the minor and
third for the conclusion. Moods are represented above in three ways. Moods in
italics and bold form are called strengthened moods, and moods in mere italics are
called weakened moods. All other moods are represented in normal form. It is
important to know the difference between the first two types. When the laws of
syllogism permit two universal premises to yield logically only particular conclusion,
then such moods are called strengthened moods. On the other hand, if we deduce
particular conclusion from two universal premises, even when the laws of syllogism
permit two universal premises to yield logically a universal conclusion, then such
moods are called weakened moods.
In this scheme, we notice that EIO is valid in all the figures. Interestingly, IEO is
invalid in all the figures. The only difference between EIO and IEO is that the minor
and the major premises are only transposed which clearly shows that the position of
premises, which is a part of the structure, determines the validity of argument. Though
EIO is valid in more than one figure it is one mood in one figure and some other in
another figure. Likewise, AEE is valid in the second and the fourth figures. But it is
one mood in the second figure and a different mood in the fourth figure.
Since Aristotle argued that the first figure is the perfect figure, he felt the need to
transmute all valid arguments in II and III figures to I figure so that if the transmuted
mood is valid in I figure, then the corresponding mood in any figure other than the
first is also valid. Transmutation from fourth figure to the first figure must have been
evolved by the inventor of the former. Reduction is the tool to test the validity of
arguments. In the thirteenth century, one logician by name Pope John XXI, devised
a technique to remember the method of reducing arguments from other figures to the
first figure. This technique is known as mnemonic verses. Accordingly, each mood,
excluding weakened moods, was given a special name:
38
I) Fig: AAA BARBARA III. Fig: AAI DARAPTI Figure, Mood and the
Possible Types of
EAE CELARENT IAI DISAMIS Syllogisms
AII DARII AII DATISI
EIO FERIO EAO FELAPTON
OAO BOCARDO
EIO FERISON
II) Fig: EAE CESARE IV. Fig: AAI BRAMANTIP
AEE CAMESTRES AEE CAMENES
EIO FESTINO IAI DIMARIS
AOO BAROCO EAO FESAPO
EIO FRESISON
The method is like this. If the names begin with C, then the syllogism has to be
reduced to the first figure which begins with a C. For example, CESARE (a syllogism
of the second figure) has to be reduced to CELARENT. Other consonants of the
name have also their significance; ‘s’ (like in CESARE) signifies that the preceding
‘E’ needs to undergo simple conversion; ‘p’ signifies that the preceding proposition
has to be converted by ‘limitation’; ‘t’ signifies that the order of the premises has to
be changed; ‘st’ indicates that two operations, viz., simple conversion and
transposition of the proposition represented by the preceding vowel are required to
be carried out. BAROCO and BOCARDO are reduced in a different manner. O
propositions in both the moods have to be obverted first and then follow the relevant
path to effect reduction.
However, the situation in modern logic is very different. The logicians proved that
from universal propositions alone particular proposition cannot be derived and vice
versa. Accordingly, both strengthened and weakened moods become invalid. Thus
in the new scheme the number of valid moods reduces to fifteen.
40
Consider this example. Figure, Mood and the
Possible Types of
1. Premises Hidden conclusions (a and b) Syllogisms
1. All A are B. a. All A are C.
2. All B are C.
3 All C are D. 3. All C are D.
——————
b. All A are D.
4. All D are E All D are E
All A are E.
It is easy to understand this structure. From (1) and (2) we have derived (a). This is
hidden because at no point of time is this expressed. When this is conjoined with
(3), (a) becomes a premise. So is the case with b. This shows that every hidden
conclusion is, in fact, the premise of next argument. In this argument ‘a’ and ‘b’ are
hidden conclusions which become premises at subsequent stages. In Aristotelian
sorites, the subject of the first premise is also the subject of the conclusion and the
predicate of the last premise is also the predicate of the conclusion. In the set of
hidden conclusions also the same pattern can be noticed. This pattern shows that in
Aristotelian sorites the first premise is the minor and the last premise is the major.
Let us consider the rules of Aristotelian sorites.
1) Only major premise (last premise) can be negative.
2) Only minor premise (first premise) can be particular.
In Goclenian sorites the order is reversed. Consider this example.
2)
Premises Hidden conclusion (a and b)
1 All A are B. a All C are B.
2 All C are A.
3 All D are C. 3 All D are C.
b All D are B.
4 All E are D. 4 All E are D.
All E are B.
In this kind the predicate of the conclusion is the predicate of the first premise.
Therefore the first premise is major. The subject of the conclusion is the subject of
the last premise. Therefore the last premise is the minor. The rules of this kind are as
follows.
1) Only the first premise (major) can be negative.
2) Only the last premise (minor) can be particular.
One point should become clear at this stage. One kind of sorites is the reversal of
the other. If we disregard the positions of premises, then the difference between
these two kinds becomes insignificant.
3.5 DILEMMA
The dilemma consists of three propositions of which two constitute premises and
third one is the conclusion. One of the premises is a conjunction of two hypothetical
41
Classical Logic propositions and the other one is disjunctive. The conclusion is either disjunctive or
simple. Since the dilemma consists of two hypothetical propositions conjoined by
the word ‘and’, it is possible that two different propositions are found in place of
antecedents and two different propositions are found in place of consequents. But
it is not necessary that it should be so. It is likely that both propositions have a
common consequent. If such consequent becomes the conclusion, then, the
conclusion is a simple proposition.
Let us consider its so-called value before we proceed further with our analysis. The
dilemma, in the strict sense of the word validity, is neither valid nor invalid. This is so
because in this particular pattern there is no way of fixing the truth-value of the
propositions. The dilemma does not contribute to the growth of knowledge. Nor
does it help in testing what is in need of testing. Its significance is only restricted to
rhetoric. The dilemma is an example of misuse or abuse of logic. Such a situation
arises when a person, who is ignorant of logic, is confronted by an unscrupulous
logician. It is most unlikely that the dilemma was ever seriously considered by any
professional committed to logic. It, then, means that the dilemma has only negative
significance, i.e., to know how not to argue.
The Structure of Dilemma:
Let us begin with the structure of dilemma. Its uniqueness is quite interesting.
a) The first premise (p1) consists of two hypothetical propositions conjoined
together.
b) The second premise (p2) is a disjunctive proposition. Its alternatives either
affirm or deny the consequents of the hypothetical major premise.
Dilem ma
43
Classical Logic i) Complex Constructive Dilemma (CCD):
p
p1: If (any government wages war to acquire wealth), then (it becomes a
q r
rogue government) and if (it wages war to expand its territory), then (it
s
becomes colonial).
p r
p2: (Any government wages war either to acquire wealth) or (to expand its
territory)
q s
q: It (becomes a rogue government) or (colonial).
ii) Simple Constructive Dilemma (SCD):
p q
p1: If (taxes are reduced to garner votes), then (the government loses
revenue).
r
and if (taxes are reduced in order to simplify taxation), then (the
q
government loses revenue).
p r
p2: (Taxes are reduced either to garner votes) or (to simplify taxation)
q
q : ∴ (The government loses its revenue).
iii) Complex Destructive Dilemma (CDD):
p q
p1: If (the nation wages war), then (there will be no problem of
r
unemployment) and if (the nation does not revise her industrial policy),
s
then (it will lead to revolution).
not- q not - s
p2: The (problem of unemployment remains unsolved) or (there will not be
any revolution).
not - p not - r
q : (The nation does not wage war) or (the nation will revise her
industrial policy).
iv) Simple Destructive Dilemma (SDD):
p q
p1: If (you are in the habit of getting up early), then (you are a
p r
theist) and if (you are in the habit of getting up early), then (you are a labourer).
not - q not - r
p2: (you are not a theist) or (you are not a labourer).
not - p
q : ∴ (you are not in the habit of getting up early).
44
The first way of avoiding the dilemma, i.e., escaping between the horns of dilemma Figure, Mood and the
can be illustrated using 1 (CCD). It is possible to argue that, when the government Possible Types of
Syllogisms
wages war, the motive is neither to acquire wealth nor to expand its territory in
which case, the government is neither rouge nor colonial. The motive may be to
spread its official religion or personal vendetta or it may be to protect its interests. If
the last one is the motive, then, it becomes difficult to find fault with such government.
Any one of the proposed alternatives or all alternatives to disjuncts may be false.
There is no way of deciding what the situation is. The reader can select remaining
examples to illustrate this method. Likewise, consider fourth argument to illustrate
the second method. I may concede that a person gets up early only because he
wants to maintain health. So the purpose is not to worship God. Nor is he a
labourer. Again, this is also an assumption.
Rebutting of dilemma requires a different type of example. Consider this one:
i) p ¬q
p1: If (teacher is a disciplinarian), then (he is unpopular among students)
and
¬p ¬r
if (he is not a disciplinarian), then (his bosses do not like him).
p ¬p
p2: (Teacher is a disciplinarian) or (he is not a disciplinarian).
¬q ¬r
q: ∴ (Teacher is unpopular among students) or (his bosses do not
like him).
A witty teacher may respond in this way.
ii) ¬p q
p1 : If (teacher is not a disciplinarian), then (he is popular among students)
p r
and if (he is a disciplinarian) then (his bosses will like him.)
¬p p
p2 : (Teacher is not a disciplinarian) or (he is a disciplinarian)
q r
q : ∴ (Teacher is popular among students) or (his bosses will like him)
Only a student of logic discovers that these conclusions of i and ii are not
contradictories (you will learn about it in the forthcoming units) in the strict sense of
the term. Hence, there is really no rebuttal.
Further, the dilemma, which an individual faces in day-to-day life, is very different.
For example, moral dilemma has nothing to do with the kinds of dilemma which
we have discussed so far.
45
Classical Logic
Check Your Progress II
Note: Use the space provided for your answer.
1) What are the characteristics of dilemma?
...........................................................................................................
...........................................................................................................
...........................................................................................................
2) What are the methods of avoiding dilemma?
...........................................................................................................
...........................................................................................................
...........................................................................................................
...........................................................................................................
...........................................................................................................
Contents
4.0 Objectives
4.1 Introduction
4.2 The Rules of Categorical Syllogism
4.3 Special Applications of General Rules
4.4 Reduction of Arguments to I Figure
4.5 Antilogism or Inconsistent Triad
4.6 Venn Diagram Technique
4.7 Boolean Analysis
4.8 Let Us Sum Up
4.9 Key Words
4.10 Further Readings and References
4.0 OBJECTIVES
This unit brings out the most important part of your study of categorical syllogism.
You will be introduced to the rules which determine the validity of arguments. While
this is the most important objective, the icing on the cake is the variety of the methods
of determining the validity of arguments. Both traditional and modern methods of
testing the validity receive due recognition in this unit. Therefore contribution of both
John Venn and George Boole find place in this unit. This particular study enables
you to grasp the relation between logic and set theory which is brought to the fore in
this unit.
4.1 INTRODUCTION
In the second and third units we learnt two important aspects of categorical syllogism,
viz., figures and moods. However, we did not develop the technique of distinguishing
valid from invalid arguments. Consequently, we could not know under what conditions
a mood becomes valid and what is still worse, we could not understand why a
certain arrangement or configuration of propositions in one figure is legitimate (only
a legitimate combination of propositions yields valid mood) and in some other figure
illegitimate yielding only invalid moods, and conversely, why a certain configuration
of propositions is illegitimate in some figures and legitimate in some other figure or
figures. In other words, the question what makes an argument valid was not raised
at all. The point is that the validity of an argument depends on whether or not the
conclusion is a conclusion in the strict sense of the word, i.e. whether or not it
logically follows from the premises. This brings us to the vital aspect of our study.
Just as application or non-application of rules makes a game legitimate or illegitimate,
mere application or non-application of rules makes an argument valid or invalid.
Application of rules demands knowledge of rules. Therefore we must focus on the
question what rules are there which determine the validity of syllogism.
47
Classical Logic
4.2 THE RULES OF CATEGORICAL SYLLOGISM
Classical Logic lists eight rules of valid categorical syllogism; four of them concern
the terms, and four of them concern the propositions. These rules are not provable.
They have to be either accepted or rejected. If they are rejected, syllogism is not
possible. Therefore what is given is only an explication of the rules. Classical logic
classified these rules under rules of structure, rules of distribution of terms, rules
of quality, and rules of quantity.
I) Rules of structure
1) Syllogism must Contain Three, and Only Three, Propositions
Syllogism is defined as a kind of mediate inference consisting of two premises
which together determine the truth of the conclusion. This definition shows
that if the number of propositions is more than two, then it ceases to be
syllogism. Therefore by definition syllogism must consist of two premises
and one conclusion. Therefore together they make up for three propositions.
2) Syllogism must Consist of Three Terms Only
A proposition consists of two terms. However, three propositions consist
of only three terms because each term occurs twice. Suppose that there are
four terms. Then there is no middle term, a term common to two premises.
In such a case the violation of rule results in a fallacy called fallacy of four
terms. Such a fallacy is never committed knowingly because knowing fully
well the fixed number of terms, we do not choose four terms. But we do it
unknowingly. It happens when an ambiguous word is used in two different
senses on two different occasions. Then there are really four terms, not
three terms. If an ambiguous word takes the place of middle term, then the
fallacy committed is known as fallacy of ambiguous middle. Similarly, if an
ambiguous term takes the place of the major or the minor term, then the
fallacy of ambiguous major or ambiguous minor, as the case may be, is
committed. The following argument illustrates the fallacy of ambiguous middle.
Fallacy of Ambiguous Middle
All charged particles are electrons.
Atmosphere in the college is charged.
∴Atmosphere in the college is an electron.
The word in italics is ambiguous. The other two fallacies are hardly committed.
Therefore there is no need to consider examples for them. The moral is that all
sentences in arguments must be unambiguous. This is possible only when all terms
are unambiguous in the given argument. We must also consider the inversion of
ambiguous middle. Suppose that synonymous words are used in place of middle
term. Then apparently there are four terms. But, in reality, there are three terms. For
example starry world and stellar world are not two terms. Such usages also are
uncommon. Hence they deserve to be neglected.
II) Rules of Distribution of Terms
1) Middle term must be distributed at least once in the premises. If this rule is
violated, then the argument commits the fallacy of undistributed middle. One
example will illustrate this rule.
48
2 All circles are geometrical figures. Validity, Invalidity and List
of Valid Syllogisms
All squares are geometrical figures.
∴ All circles are squares.
2) In the conclusion, no term may be taken in a more ‘extensive’ sense than in
the premises. It also means that a term which is distributed in the conclusion
must remain distributed in the respective premise. This rule can be stated
this way also. A term which is undistributed in the premise must remain
undistributed in the conclusion. However, it is not necessary that a term,
which is distributed in the premise, must be distributed in the conclusion.
Suppose that the major term violates this rule. Then the argument commits
the fallacy of illicit major. When the minor term violates this rule, fallacy
illicit minor is committed. The following arguments illustrate these fallacies.
3) All philosophers are thinkers.
No ordinary men are philosophers.
∴ No ordinary men are thinkers.
4) All aquatic creatures are fish.
All aquatic creatures swim.
∴ All those which swim are fish.
First argument illustrates the fallacy of undistributed middle; second illustrates the
fallacy of illicit major and the third illustrates the fallacy of illicit minor.
III) Rules of Quality
1) From two negative premises, no conclusion can be drawn. It only means
that at least one premise must be affirmative.
2) If both premises are affirmative, the conclusion cannot be negative.
Negatively, it only means that a negative conclusion is possible only when
one premise is negative.
IV) Rules of Quantity
If both premises are particular, no conclusion can be drawn or the conclusion must
always follow the weaker part. Here weaker part is particular. This rule shows that
at least one premise must be universal.
If one premise is particular, then the conclusion must be particular only. It means that
universal conclusion is possible only when both premises are universal. In practice,
last three sets of rules play an important role in determining the validity of categorical
syllogism.
Check Your Progress I
Note: Use the space provided for your answers.
Examine the following arguments.
1) All kings are thinkers.
Some ordinary men are not kings.
∴ No ordinary men are thinkers.
...........................................................................................................
...........................................................................................................
49
Classical Logic ...........................................................................................................
...........................................................................................................
...........................................................................................................
51
Classical Logic III) Figure:
a) The ‘minor’ must be affirmative.
b) The conclusion must be Particular.
M–P
M–S
S–P
a) Minor must be affirmative because negative minor gives only negative conclusion
in which case P is distributed in the conclusion. P can be distributed in major
only if it is negative. Negative minor results in negative major which is not
allowed. Therefore minor must be affirmative.
b) The conclusion must be particular. Otherwise S becomes distributed in the
conclusion while it remains undistributed in affirmative minor.
The valid moods are listed below.
III) Fig: AAI DARAPTI
IAI DISAMIS
AII DATISI
OAO BOCARDO
EIO FERISON
EAO FELOPTON
IV) Figure:
a) If the ‘major’ is affirmative, the ‘minor’ must be universal.
b) If the minor is affirmative, the conclusion must be particular.
c) If the conclusion is negative, the major must be negative.
P–M
M–S
S–P
The valid moods are listed below.
AAI DARAPTI
AEE CAMENES
EAO FESAPO
IAI DIMARIS
EIO FRESISON
It would be good logical exercise for the student to take up these special rules and
try to deduce them from the general ones. This is the reason why we have left the
special rules of figure 4 unexplained.
‘S’ and ‘T’ after ‘E’ show that ‘E’ (minor premise) should undergo simple conversion
and both premises be transposed. ‘S’ after second ‘E’ shows that this ‘E’ (conclusion)
also should undergo simple conversion. [The student is advised to construct arguments
for this and subsequent reductions.]
II Figure
II Figure I Figure
FESTINO FERIO
PEM → Conversion → MEP
SIM SIM
SOP SOP
FESTINO becomes FERIO when the major premise undergoes simple conversion.
The kind of reduction of the above mentioned moods is known as direct reduction.
BAROCO becomes FERIO through the process of indirect reduction. Indirect
reduction includes, in addition to conversion, obversion also.
II Figure
II Figure I Figure
BAROCO FERIO
P A M → obversion P E M → Conversion → MEP
S O M → obversion S I M SIM
SOP SOP
53
Classical Logic III Figure
III Figure I Figure
DARAPTI DARII
MAP MAP
MAS → Conversion → SIM
SIP SIP
DATISI DARII
MAP MAP
MIS → Conversion → SIM
SIP SIP
FELAPTON FERIO
MEP MEP
MAS → Conversion → SIM
SOP SOP
‘P’ which follows ‘A’ in DARAPTI and FELAPTON shows that conversion by
limitation applies to ‘A’.
FERISON FERIO
MEP MEP
MIS → Conversion → SIM
SOP SOP
54
IV Figure Validity, Invalidity and List
of Valid Syllogisms
IV Figure I Figure
BRAMANTIP Weakened mood
PA M MAS
MAS PAM
SIP P A S → Conversion →S I P
CAMENES CELARENT
PA M MES
MES PAM
SEP SEP
DIMARIS DARII
PIM MAS
MAS PIM
SIP SIP
FESAPO FERIO
P E M → Conversion→ MEP
M A S → Conversion→ SIM
SOP SOP
As usual ‘S’ stands for simple conversion of ‘E’ (major Premise) and ‘P’ stands for
conversion by limitation of ‘A’ (minor premise). This process is similar to the one
applied for first and third moods of III figure.
FRESISON FERIO
P E M → Conversion→ MEP
M I S → Conversion→ SIM
SOP SOP
From reduction technique one point becomes clear. Originally, there were twenty-
four valid moods. Later weakened and strengthened moods were eliminated on the
ground that particular proposition (existential quantifier) cannot be deduced from
universal propositions (universal quantifier) only, and the number was reduced to
fifteen. Now after reduction to first figure the number came down to four. Strawson
argues that reduction technique is superior to axiomatic technique to which he referred
in the beginning of his work ‘Introduction to Logical Theory’. He regards the moods
as inference-patterns. He argues that the path of reduction should be an inverted
pyramid. Strawson also maintains that in addition to equivalence relation, we require
opposition relation also to effect reduction. What we gain in the process is economy
in the number of moods.
In this case, antilogism satisfies all the requirements. ‘I’ is common to equations; in
one equation it is positive and in another negative. There is only one inequation.
Remaining terms appear in inequation. In all cases, this is the method to be followed.
If any one of these characteristics is absent in antilogism, then the corresponding
mood is invalid.
Now antilogism can be easily constructed for the remaining fourteen moods.
I Fig.
1) CELARENT
Contradiction
MEP MP= Ø
SAM SM = Ø
SEP → SIP SP ≠ Ø
2) DARII
MAP M P =Ø
SIM SM≠Ø
SIP → SEP SP=Ø
3) FERIO
MEP MP=Ø
SIM SM≠Ø
SOP → SAP S P =Ø
II Fig.
4) CESARE
PEM PM=Ø
SAM S M =Ø
56 SEP → SIP SP≠Ø
5) CAMESTRES Validity, Invalidity and List
of Valid Syllogisms
PAM P M =Ø
SEM SM=Ø
6) FESTINO
PEM PM = Ø
SIM SM ≠ Ø
SOP → SAP S P =Ø
7) BAROCO
PAM P M =Ø
SOM S M ≠Ø
SOP → SAP S P =Ø
III Fig.
8) DISAMIS
MIP MP≠ Ø
MAS M S =Ø
SIP → SEP SP=Ø
9) DATISI
MAP M P =Ø
MIS MS≠Ø
SIP → SEP SP=Ø
10) BOCARDO
MOP MP ≠ Ø
MAS M S =Ø
SOP → SAP S P =Ø
11) FERISON
MEP MP=Ø
MIS MS≠Ø
SOP → SAP S P =Ø
57
Classical Logic IV Fig.
12) CAMENES
PAM P M =Ø
MES MS=Ø
SEP → SIP SP≠Ø
13) DIMARIS
PIM PM≠Ø
MAS M S =Ø
SIP → SEP SP=Ø
14) FRESISON
PEM PM=Ø
MIS MS≠Ø
SOP → SAP S P =Ø
II Fig.
Weakened mood:
PAM P M =Ø
SEM SM=Ø
SOP → SAP S M =Ø
While listing product classes, sufficient care should be taken to ensure that no product
class is repeated. It is always advisable to make a list of product classes with diagrams
and mark classes accurately to avoid confusion.
Now let us use diagram to represent the propositions. The procedure is as follows.
null sets are shaded and non-null sets are starred. We should also note that product
of null set and non-null set is a null set. It is like saying that 4 x 0 = 0. But the union,
i.e., addition of a non-null set and null set is a non-null set. Remember 4 + 0 = 4.
Since M P is a null set, not only SM P , but also S M P is a null set. It does not
mean that there are two null sets. There is only one null set. S M is also a null set.
Therefore not only the product of S M & P, but also S M and P is a null set.
Now we shall shade relevant subsets, which are null.
Fig. 2.
2 BAROCO
3 DATISI
q: Some S are P. S P≠ Ø
60
Validity, Invalidity and List
4 DISAMIS of Valid Syllogisms
q: Some S are P. S P≠ Ø
5 FERISON
p1: No M are P. MP=Ø
p2: Some M are S. MS≠Ø
________________ ______________
q: Some S are not P. S P ≠Ø
61
Classical Logic
7 CAMENES
q: No S are P. SP=Ø
S P
p1
p2
62
Validity, Invalidity and List
of Valid Syllogisms
8 DIMARIS
S P
*
p1
p2
9 FRESISON
S P
p2
*
p1
Let us examine a few weakened and strengthened moods using Venn’s diagram.
63
Classical Logic
10 BRAMANTIP
S P
p1
?
p2
AAI
p1: M A P. MP = Ø
p2: S A M. SM= Ø
______________________________ ______________
q: S I P. SP≠Ø
S ? P
p2
p1
.
×S= 1b
2) Law of addition: The addition of complementary sets is universal set.
S S 1 2
MPMP 1 Rule 1b
M P S S MP Rule 2
MP S M P S M P Rule 4
Now we shall pass on to the second stage.
S M P SM P
a) Rule 1
S MP S MP
M P SM P S MP
The last line corresponds to the expansion of major premise. While expanding these
lines, we must obtain the addition or union of the product of all relevant sets and
their complements as well. On these lines, we shall expand remaining lines.
P SM PSM
b) Rule 1b
P SM PSM
PSM S MP
Rule 3b
PSM SM P
S M S MP S M P
65
Classical Logic The last line corresponds to the expansion of minor premise.
⎫
S P × M = SP M = Φ
c) ⎬ Rule 1b
SP × M = SPM = Φ ⎭
SP M = SM P = Φ ⎫
⎬ Rule 3b
S P M = SM P = Φ ⎭
S P = SM P + S M P = Φ
a + b = SM P + S M P + SMP + SM P = Φ
Since the union of four product classes is null set any set in this group is null set.
Consider the union of relevant sets.
SM P + SM P = Φ
Since this is equivalent to what we have obtained from the conclusion, the argument
is valid. This shows that the expansion of conclusion must be equal to or less than
the union of premises if the argument is valid. Hence this conclusion is not repeated
further while dealing with some arguments which are valid. Since we follow this
method throughout, we should bear in our mind all these details.
2) CELARENT
p1 : No M are P. MP = Φ
p2 : All S are M. SM = Φ
q : ∴ No S are P. SP = Φ
Expansion of major premise:
a : SMP + S MP = Φ
Expansion of minor premise:
b : SM P + S M P = Φ
Expansion of conclusion:
c : SMP + SM P = Φ
SP M = SMP
a+b ⇒ SMP + S MP + SM P + S M P = Φ
c = SMP + SMP = Φ
a+b=c
3) DARII
p1 : All M are P. MP= Φ
p2 : Some S are M. SM ≠ Φ
q : ∴Some S are P. SP≠Φ
Expansion of major premise:
66
Expansion of minor premise: Validity, Invalidity and List
of Valid Syllogisms
b: SM P S M P
Expansion of conclusion:
c: SMP SM P
SPM SMP
a b SMP S MP S MP S M P
c SMP SM P
a b c
Since SMP is a non-null set, its union with null set yields a non-null set.
4) FERIO
p1 : No M are P. MP=
p2 : Some S are M. SM
q: Some S are not P. SP
Expansion of major premise:
a: SMP S MP
Expansion of minor premise:
b: SMP SMP
Expansion of conclusion:
c: SMP SM P
SM P
SM P SM P
c SM P S M P
a+b=c
5) CESARE
p1: No P are M. PM
p2 : All S are M. SM
q: No S are P.. SP
6) CAMESTRES
p1 : All P are M. PM
p2 : No S are M. SM
q: No S are P. SP
Expansion of major premise:
a: SMP S MP
Expansion of minor premise:
b: SMP SMP
Expansion of conclusion:
c: SMP S M P
a b S M P S M P SMP SMP
SMP SM P
c SMP S M P
a+b = c
7) FESTINO
p1 : No P are M. PM
p2 : Some S are M. SM
q: Some S are not P. SP
a b SMP S MP SMP SM P
SM P
SMP
c SM P SM P
a b c
68
8) BAROCO Validity, Invalidity and List
of Valid Syllogisms
p1 : All P are M. PM
p2 : Some S are not M. SM
q: Some S are not P. SP
Expansion of major premise:
a: SMP S MP
Expansion of minor premise:
b: SM P S M P
Expansion of conclusion:
c: SM P S MP
a b S M P S M P S MP S M P
SM P
SM P
SM P SM P
a b c
9) DISAMIS
p1: Some M are P. MP
p2 : All M are S. MS
q: Some S are P. SP
SMP
SMP SMP
a b c
10) DATISI
p1: All M are P.. MP
p2 : Some M are S. MS
q: Some S are P. SP
69
Classical Logic Expansion of major premise:
a + b ⇒ SM P + S MP + SMP + SMP ≠ Φ
= Φ + SMP ≠ Φ
∴SMP ≠ Φ
∴ SMP + SM P ≠ Φ
a+b = c
11) BOCARDO
p1 : Some M are not P. M P ≠ Φ
p2 : All M are S. M S = Φ
∴ SMP ≠ Φ
∴ SMP + SM P ≠ Φ
a+ b= c
12) FERISON
p1 : No M are P.
p2 : Some M are S. MS ≠ Φ
a+b = c
13) CAMENES
p1 : All P are M. PM
p2 : No M are S. MS
q: No S are P.. SP
Expansion of major premise:
a: SMP S MP
Expansion of minor premise:
b: SMP SM P
Expansion of conclusion:
c: SMP S M P
a b S MP S MP SMP SMP
S M P SMP
a+b =c
14) DIMARIS
p1 : Some P are M. PM
p2 : All M are S. MS
q: Some S are P.. SP
a b SMP SMP S MP S MP
SMP
SMP
c SMP S M P
a+b = c
15) FRESISON
p1 : No P are M. PM
p2 : Some M are S. MS
q: Some S are not P.. SP 71
Classical Logic Expansion of major premise:
a: SMP S MP
Expansion of minor premise:
b: SMP SM P
Expansion of conclusion:
c: SM P S M P
a b SMP S MP SMP SM P
SMP
SM P
SMP SM P
a+b = c
Let us examine an invalid mood which is regarded as valid in traditional framework.
16) AAI
p1 : All M are P. MP
p2 : All S are M. SM
q: Some S are P. SP Ø
a+b c
74