Cicero de Natura Deorum, Libri Tres (1880) Vol 1
Cicero de Natura Deorum, Libri Tres (1880) Vol 1
Cicero de Natura Deorum, Libri Tres (1880) Vol 1
of Cormtto
DE NATUKA DEORUM
LIBRI TRES
13Y
TOGETHER WITH
BY J. H. SWAINSON, M.A. ^
VOL. I.
amim&ge :
HI
FEATRI DILECTO
JOHANNI E. B. MAYOR,
LATEJARUM LITTERARUM APUD CAXTABRIGIENSES PROFESSOR!,
DEDICATUR.
"*HN MEN OYN rrpo THC TOY Kypi oy nApoyciAC eic AIKAIOCY NHN
"E/\/\HciN ANAfKAiA ({)i/\oc<>4)i A, NYNH Ae xpHCiMH npoc GeoceBeiAN
I,
npOnAlAei A TIC ofCA TOIC THN TTICTIN Al ATTOAei zeoOC KAp-
CLEM. AL. Strom. I. c. 5 28.
Nam, itt vcre loquamur, superstitio fsn per gcntes ofipressit omnium fere
animos atqy.e hominum imbccillitotem occupavit. Quod et in Us libris dictum
propaganda etiam est, qvae est juncta cum cognitione naturae, sic supersti-
by the latter,
April, I860.
TABLE OF CONTENTS.
PAGE
INTRODUCTION :
.....
.
(1)
*
The modern works which have been found most useful in drawing up this
sketch are the following, arranged in what I consider to be their order of im
portance. Full references will be found in the two which stand at the head of
the list.
M. C. b
X INTRODUCTION.
world. But while the former with the Ionic sensitiveness to all
outward influences dwelt more upon the material element itself and
the life which manifested itself in its ever-changing developments,
the latter (who, if not themselves Dorian, were yet surrounded by
Dorian settlers, with their Doric ideal of
discipline, order, stability,
have said that the magnet had a soul. It is this portion of his
doctrine which is travestied by the Epicurean critic in Bk. I 25.
The second of the Ionic philosophers was Anaximander, also an
inhabitant of Miletus (B.C. G10 He followed
Thales in seeking
5-iO).
for an original substance to which he gave the name of dpxrf, but he
The elementary contraries, hot, cold, moist, dry, are separated from
this firstmatter by virtue of the eternal movement belonging to it ;
thus are produced the four elements ; the earth was in the form of a
62
xii INTRODUCTION.
things are in flux like the waters of a river. One tiling alone is per
manent, the universal law which reveals itself in this movement.
illusion of the senses which makes us fancy that there are such things
Fii e exhibits most clearly the incessant
as permanent substances.
movement and activity of the world: confined in the body it con
stitutes the human soul, in the universe at large it is God (the
substance and the process being thus identified).
Heraclitus is the first philosopher of whom we read that he
referred to the doctrines of other philosophers. He
said to have
is
spoken some
highly of of the seven Wise Men, but condemned
severely Pythagoras and Xenophanes as well as the poets Hesiod,
Homer and Archilochus. Though I agree with Ueberweg in classing
him with the older Ionics, yet his philosophy was no doubt largely
developed with a reference to the rival schools of Italy.
In the N. D. allusion is twice made to the obscurity of
Heraclitus (i 74, in 35), but he does not appear in the catalogue of
as opposed to the Ionic systems, was that it found its apx7?* its
point of view, as being the first square number, equal into equal,
it was conceived to be Justice). Yet once more, One was the central
fire,the hearth of the universe, the throne of Zeus, round which
revolved not only the heavenly bodies, but the earth itself. The
Decad is the ordered universe surrounded by its fiery envelope.
The Pythagorean doctrine of the soul and of God is variously re
ported. Zeller thinks that Cicero s representation belongs to the later
teachers, and not to Pythagoras himself, as it is not supported by
Plato and Aristotle. If we may trust the oldest accounts, there does
not seem to have been any close connexion between the religious and
philosophical opinions of Pythagoras. We
are told that he believed in
One God eternal, unchangeable, ruling and upholding all things, that
the soul was a harmony, that the body was its prison, in which it
was punished for past sin and disciplined for a divine life after
death, that those who failed to profit by this discipline would pass
into lower forms of life, or suffer severer penalties in Hades (N. D. i
27, 74, in 27, 88).
The second of the Italic schools was the Eleatic, founded by
Xenophanes of Colophon in Asia Minor (b. 569 B.C.), who migrated
to Elea in Italy about 540 B.C. While the Pythagoreans strove to
explain nature mathematically and symbolically, the Eleatics in their
later developments did the same by their metaphysical abstractions.
asserted, with distinct reference to him, that all that exists has
existed and w ill exist the same for ever, that it is change and
r
The clearly marked opposition between the Ionic and the Eleatic
views of nature, as shown in Heracljtus and Parmenides, had a
powerful influence on the subsequent course of philosophy. Em
pedocles. Anaxagoras, and the Atomists agreed in accepting the
Eleatic principle of the imnmtability of substance, while denying its
absolute Oneness; and they explained the Ionic becoming as the
result of the mixture of a number of unchangeable substances.
Empedocles of Agrigentiim (b. 500 B.C.) held that there were four
eternal, self-subsistent roots of things, which were
elements or
having begun well, he failed to make full use of the right principle
with which he started, and turned his attention to mechanical causes,
only having recourse to Nous as a deus ex mac/tina when the others
failed. (N. D. I 2G.)
Diogenes of Apollonia in Crete was a younger contemporary of
Anaxagoras, against whom he took up a reactionary position and
defended the older Ionic doctrine, assuming Air to be the one
principle out of which all things were produced, and assigning to it
all the attributes of Nous. Both he and Anaxagoras taught at
Athens, but were compelled to leave it on a charge of impiety.
(N.
D. i 29.)
Of far greater importance is Democritus, born at the Ionic colony
of Abdera in Thrace, B.C. 4GO, the chief expositor of the Atomic
theory, which was originated by his elder contemporary and friend,
Leucippus the Eleatic (N. D.i
66). Briefly stated, their doctrine is
that of Anaxagoras, minus Nous and the qualitative diversity in the
seeds or atoms. They adopted the Eleatic view so far as relates
to the eternal sameness of Being, applying this to the indivisible,
impinged one upon another, and gave rise to all sorts of oblique and
contrary movements, out of which was generated an all-absorbing
rotatory motion or vortex. Under these various movements cor
responding atoms found their fitting places and became entangled
aud hooked together so as to form bodies. Thus the earthy and
watery particles were drawn to the centre where they remained at
rest, while the airy and fiery rebounded from them and rose to the
which iu the case of the former revealed to him the inner truth of
nature ;
those who were worthy to receive the revelation listened
political power*.
Protagoras of Abdera (B.C. 490 415) and Gorgias of Leontini in
Sicily (B.C.
480
375) are the earliest of the so-called Sophists.
Protagoras taught in Sicily and at Athens, from which latter place
he was banished on a charge of impiety in consequence of his treatise
on Theology referred to by Cicero, N. D. I 29 & 63. His treatise
on Truth began with the famous sentence, Man is the measure of
all things; meaning that truth is relative, not absolute, that what
each manholds to be true, that is true to him ; and similarly in
anything did exist, still it could not be known; 3rd that even if
it could be known, the knowledge of it could not be communicated
*
The general features of the Sophistic period are photographed in the
Clouds of Aristophanes, and in Thucydides chapters on the Plague of Athens
and the Corcyrean revolution, and his speeches generally.
XX INTRODUCTION.
one of his disciples was told by the Oracle at Delphi that Socrates
was the wisest of men. Socrates could not conceive how this should
be, as he was conscious only of ignorance ; but he determined to
question some of those who had the highest repute for wisdom;
accordingly he went to statesmen and poets and orators, and last
of all to craftsmen, but everywhere met with the same response :
none really knew what were the true ends of life, but each one
fancied that he knew, and most were angry when Socrates attempted
to disturb their illusion of knowledge. Thus he arrived at the
conclusion that what the oracle meant was that the first step to
knowledge was the consciousness of ignorance, and he believed, in
consequence of other divine warnings, that it was his special mission
to bring men to this consciousness.
The next step on the way to knowledge was to get clear general
notions,by comparing a number of specific cases in which the same
general term was employed; or, according to the phraseology of
ancient philosophy, to see the One (the kind or genus, the general
principle, the law, the idea,) in the Many (the siibordiuate species or
individuals, the particulars, the phenomena, the facts) and conversely
to rise from the Many to the One. The process of doing this he
called Dialectic, i. e. discourse, since it was by question and answer
that he believed the proposed definition could be best tested, and
the universal idea which was latent in each individual could be
brought to light.Truth and right were the same for all it was :
that man was the object of His special providence and might look
for guidance from Him in oracles and otherwise. The soul was
immortal, and had in it a divine element. Socrates believed that
he was himself favoured beyond others in the warning sign (TO
&ai[i.6viov)
which checked him whenever he was about to take an
ill-judged step.
The personal enmity provoked by the use of the Socratic elenchus,
and the more general dislike to the Socratic method as unsettling the
grounds of belief and undermining authority, a dislike which showed
itself in the Clouds of Aristophanes as early as 423 B.C., combined
to the fact that Socrates freely pointed out the faults of the Athenian
vice. Virtue is wisdom, and the wise man is always perfectly happy
because he is self-sufficient and has no wants, no ties and no weak
nesses. The mass of men are fools and slaves, and the wise man
is their appointed guide and physician. Acting on these principles
the Cynics were the mendicant Friars of their time, abstaining from
marriage and repudiating all civil claims while they professed them
selves to be citizens of a world-wide community. On the subject of
religion Antisthenes stated explicitly, what was doubtless implied in
the teaching of Socrates, that there was only one God, who is invisible
and whose worship consists in a virtuous life.
Aristippus of Cyrene (N. D. in 77), the founder of the Cyrenaic
school, resembled Antisthenes in dwelling exclusively upon the prac
tical side of his master s teaching. He interpreted the somewhat
ambiguous language of Socrates about happiness in a purely cudae-/,
monistic sense and declared that the only rule of life was to enjoy
the present moment. Wisdom was essential to this, as it freed the
mind from was the boast of Ai-istippus
prejudice and passion. It
no less than of Antisthenes non me rebus subjungere
mihi res,
conor Among the more prominent members of this school were
.
more of pain than pleasure, the aim of the wise man should be not
INTRODUCTION.
Athens 4-8 B.C. and became a disciple of Socrates in 408 B.C. After
the death of his master he left Athens and lived at Megara with
Euclides. From thence he visited Gyrene, Egypt, Magua Graecia
and Sicily. years of travelling he took up his
After nearly ten
residence again at Athens and began to lecture in the gymnasium
of the Academia. He died in his eightieth year.
Building on the foundation of Socrates, he insists no less than his
master on the importance of negative Dialectic, as a means of testing
commonly received opinions ; indeed most of his Dialogues come to
no positive result, but merely serve to show the difficulties of the
subject discussed and the unsatisfactory nature of the solutions
hitherto proposed. As he makes Socrates the spokesman in almost
all the Dialogues, not always easy to determine precisely where
it is
the line is to be drawn between the purely Socratic and the Platonic
doctrine, but the general relation of the one to the other may be
stated as follows.
In his theory of knowledge Plato unites the Socratic definition
with the Heraclitean Becoming and the Eleatic Being. Agreeing
with Heraclitus that all the objects of the senses are fleeting and
unreal in themselves, he held that they are nevertheless participant
of Being in so far as they represent to iis the general terms after
which they are named. Thus we can make no general assertion with
it is merely a
regard to this or that concrete triangular thing :
upon crystallizes into the geometrical forms of the four elements, and
assumes the shape of a perfect sphere rotating on its axis. The
Kosmos thus created is divine, imperishable and infinitely beautiful.
*
The reader remember the magnificent ode in which Wordsworth has
will
embodied Plato sublime conception. The fact which underlies it was well
s
illustrated by the late Prof. Sedgwick, commenting on Locke s saying that the "
mind previous to experience is a sheet of white paper" (the old rasa tabula),
"Naked he comes from his mother s womb, endowed with limbs and senses
indeed, well fitted to the material world, yet powerless from want of use and :
as for knowledge, his soul is one unvaried blank; yet has this blank been
already touched by a celestial hand, and when plunged in the colours which
surround it, it takes not its tinge from accident, but design, and comes forth
covered with a glorious pattern." Discourse p. 53. The Common-sense Philo
sophy of the Scotch and the a priori judgments of Kant are other forms of the
same doctrine.
M. C. C
XXVI INTRODUCTION.
Pythagoreans.
Wehave now to speak of his ethical doctrines, which were
based upon the psychological views mentioned above. The soul is
on a small scale what the State or city is on a large scale it is a :
prose and worked out in detail. The vague mysticism, the high
poetic imagination, of the master was altogether alien to the
scholar, but the main lines of the two systems are the same.
Plato s Dialectic method was
developed by Aristotle into the
strict technical science of Logic Plato s Ideas were shorn of their
:
the object and end of all effort, of all desire. The universe itself
is eternal, a perfect sphere, the circumference of which is composed
into organic, from plant into animal, from life which is nutritive
and sensitive only into life which is locomotive and finally rational
in man. The human soul is a microcosm uniting in itself all the
faculties of the lower orders of animated existence, and possessing
besides, the divine and immortal faculty of reason. As each thing
attains its end by fulfilling the work for which it is designed by
c2
XXViii INTRODUCTION .
schools, the Older, the Middle and the New Academy*. To the
first belong the names of Speusippus (i 32), Xenocrates
(i 34) and
Polemo, who successively presided over the school between 347 and
270 B.C., as well as those of Heraclides of Pontus (i 34),
Grantor
and Crates. They appear to have modified the Platonic doctrines
mainly by the admixture of Pythagorean elements. Grantor s writings
were used by Cicero for his Consolatio and Tusculan Disputations.
The chief expounders Middle Academy were its founder
of the
Arcesilaus 315 241 B.C.
(i 11, 70),
Carneades of Gyrene 214 129
B.C. (i 4, ii 65, in
44), one of the Athenian ambassadors to Rome in
155 B.C., and Clitomachus of Carthage, his successor in the presi
dency. They neglected the positive doctrine of Plato, and employed
themselves mainly in a negative polemic against the dogmatism of
the Stoics, professing to follow the example of Socrates, though
* Cicero
only recognized the Old and the New Academy, the latter cor
responding to what is above called the Middle Academy, but including Fhilo.
Antiochus himself claimed to be a true representative of the Old Academy.
Later writers made five Academic schools, the 2nd founded by Arcesilas, the 3rd
by Carneades, the 4th by Philo, the 5th by Antiochus.
GREEK PHILOSOPHY. XXIX
Carthage,
O Persaens,
7
who like his master was a native of Citium
(N. D. I
38), Aratus of Soli in Cilicia, the author of two astronomical
bringing the actions into harmony with the general order of the
world, it is essential to know what this order is, and thus we arrive
at the famous triple division of philosophy into physics, including
cosmology and theology, which explains the nature and laws of the
universe ; loyic, which ensures ns against deception and supplies
the method for attaining to true knowledge ; ethics, which draws the
conclusion for practical life. The chief point of interest in the Logic
of the Stoics is their theory as to the criterion. They considered
the soul to resemble a sheet of blank paper on which impressions
one part passive, one part active, but all is alike material. The
active portion is soul, a fiery ether pervading the whole, but having
its principal seat in the heaven which encompasses it on every side ;
body, it will only retain its individual existence till the next con
flagration, and that only in the case of the wise. The stars being
made of pure fire are divine.
In we see the influence of Heraclitus, who was much
all this
17011 5^ fj.
c3 Zei>,
Kal ffv y 77 llcTrpu!/j.{i>r),
1
the true end, viz. acting not for self, but for the whole. Man s reason
being a part of the reason of the universe reveals to him the divine
law. As the emotions are liable to confuse or to disobey reason, it
is the part of the wise, i. e. of the virtuous, man to uproot them
and good ; all the actions of the latter foolish and bad. There may
be a progress towards wisdom, but, until the actual moment of con
version, even those who are advancing (ot TrpoKoVroi/Te?) must still be
classed among the Thus we have the strange union of a highly
fools.
teaching in his own Garden, which became not less famous than the
Stoic Porch .
Among his most distinguished disciples were Metro-
dorus (N. D. 86, 113) and others mentioned N. D. i 93. Cicero men
I
59, 93) and Philodemus of Gadara and his account of the Epicurean
:
Epicureanism had great success among the Romans; but, with the
exception of the poet Lucretius, none of the Latin expounders of
the system seem to have been of any importance. Cicero speaks
with great contempt of Amafinius and Rabirius (cf. Tusc. n 7, and
Zeller on the Epicureans, ch. 15).
The end of the Epicurean philosophy was even more exclusively
practical than that of the Stoics. Logic (called by Epicurus Canonic ,
as giving the canon or test of truth) and physics, were merely sub
ordinate to ethics, the art of attaining happiness. Knowledge in
itself is of no value or interest. IT. fact it has a tendency to corrupt
and distort our natural judgment and feeling: and thus Epicurus
prided himself on being mainly self-taught (N. D. I 72). Truth is
based on the senses our sensations are always to be trusted
: error :
in all other cases. Epicurus himself does not seem to have carried
his logical investigations further than this.
The only reason for studying physics was to free the soul from
superstitious fears, and with this
view to prove that the constitution
of the universe might be explained from mechanical causes. The
two main principles asserted by Epicurus were that nothing could
be produced out of nothing, and that what exists cannot become
non-existent. From these principles he deduced the truth of the
atomic system, differing however from Democritus in one important
point, viz. in his explanation of the manner in which the atoms
were brought together. Democritus had asserted that the heavier
atoms overtook the lighter in their downward course, and thus
initiated the collision which in a general vortical
finally resulted
movement. Epicurus retaining the same crude view of up and down
held that each atom moved with equal speed and that they could
And he pleased himself with the thought that he might find in the
Gods a pattern of the true philosophic life. Perfect happiness, im
mortality and human shape were of the essence of this TrpoAiji/us.
Hence he inferred that they must be composed of the finest atoms
and enjoy eternal repose in the vacant spaces between the worlds,
undisturbed by those labours of sustaining and superintending the
universe which were ascribed to them by other schools, as well as
by the popular religion (N. D. I 43 56). Such Gods were worthy
of the worship and the imitation of the philosophers. On the nature
of the soul and the manner in which it receives its impressions by
the Gods and of death, because he has learnt to moderate his passions
and desires, because he knows how to estimate and compare pleasures
and pains so as amount of the former with the
to secure the largest
least of the latter. The distinction between right and wrong rests
merely on utility and has nothing mysterious about it. One chief
means of attaining pleasure is the society of friends. To enjoy this
we should cultivate the feelings of kindness and benevolence.
mind, never satisfied either with himself or with the party or the
persons with whom he is most closely allied. And this indecision of
2. ANALYSIS OF BOOK I.
good of man, while the Academy holds that man has no right to dog
matize, and confines itself to the criticism of other schools. 1 5.
XXXVlli INTRODUCTION.
i.
Epicurean criticism of the theological tenets of twenty seven
philosophers from Thales to Diogenes of Babylon, x 25 xv 41.
ii. Epicurean criticism of the popular belief, as seen in the
writings of the poets or in Oriental religions, xvi 42, 43.
bodily senses. That they are immortal is farther shown by the law
of equilibrium, which provides that what is deficient in one place is
arguing from our limited experience, and it shows also that a body
which is suitable for man is unsuitable for such a being as God is
supposed to be. xxvn 76 xxxvu 102.
3. DRAMATIS PERSONAE.
beyond the fact that he was born at Lanuvium (N.D. i 82), was a
friend of the orator Crassus (see note on I 58) and held the office of
Tribune in the year 90 B.C. He is called rudis dicendi (Or. in 78),
and is described as holding the first place among the Romans of his
sect(N.D. i 15). In the De Finibus L. Manlius Torquatus is the
Epicurean disputant.
Of Q. Lucilius Balbus, the spokesman of the Stoics, we know-
even less. He was an interlocutor in the lost dialogue entitled
Hortensius and is praised as not inferior to the most distinguished
Stoics of Greece. In the De Finibus the Stoics are represented
by Cato, in the De Divinations by Q. Cicero.
In this dialogue as in the De Eepublica and De Oratore Cicero
himself merely appears as a Koxfrov Trpdo-wTrov see my. note on I 34
:
s. v. Ileraclides.
The dialogue is dedicated to M. Junius Brutus, the conspirator,
M. C. d
xlii INTRODUCTION.
(De intei -pretatione Timaci, Gott. 1842,) has given reasons for believ
1
Compare on this subject Hir/.el UntersucJiunycn zu Cicero s Philosopliisclien
flchriften pp. 4 45,Schwcncko in the Jtihrb. f. clans, pliilol. 187 J pp. 49 Gil, (
and Dicls Doxoyraphi Gracci p. 121 foil., a work which has appeared since my
own remarks were written; also Spengel 1 hilodcmus vepl evffefJeias, Munich 18G3;
Sauppe Philodemi De l Giittin^cn 18(51; Nauck Ueber Philodcmtm irifil
ict<tt<>,
MSS, London 31); and also from the fact that most of the
1811, p.
MSS found there contained treatises by writers belonging to the
Epicurean school, of which Piso was an adherent, and that many of
them bore the name of Philodemus, who is known (from Cicero s
speech in Pisoneni) to have been the intimate friend and instructor
of Piso. The difficulty of unrolling the charred papyri was very
great, and it was not till the year 1793 that the 1st Vol. of
Herculanensia (containing the treatise of Philodemus Trepi /xovcrtK^s)
appeared at Naples. At the instigation of the English Ambassador,
Sir W. Hamilton, the Prince of Wales undertook to supply the
necessary funds for carrying on the work more actively, and also
sent his librarian, the Rev. John Hayter, to assist in opening and
maintains that two of the busts found there represent Piso and his colleague
Gabiuius ; and certainly they agree remarkably well with Cicero s description of
Babylon, who died not later than 150 B.C. The strongest argument
however in favour of Phaedrus is, that in a letter to Atticus (xni 43),
written about the time of the composition of the N. Cicero asks Z>.,
to have his treatises rrcpl Qtiav et Trepl IlaXXaSos 2 sent to him; just
as in xni 8 he asks for Panaetius Trcpl Trpovcu as, which we know to
have been used by him in JV. D. n 118, De Divin. i
6, 12, n 88;
1
See n. on 39 under Clmjsippm.
-
The older readingis irtpiaauv et EX\a 5os, which was supposed to
<J>cu5pou
refer to two books of Dicaearchus, C. having asked for other writings of his in
earlier letters. It was suggested that the former treatise might be a criticism
<t>va-ew<s
of Phaedrus ;
but in 1862 it appeared in the 2nd. vol. of the
new series of Herculauensia published at Naples, as a portion of a
much larger whole (12 columns out of 147) bearing the name 4>tXo-
IlEpt euo-e/3eias of which the three capital letters alone are now
8-^fji.ov
Cicero ?
that not less than 36 treatises by him have been discovered at Hercu-
laneum 4 He was much influenced by Zeno, whose disciple he was,
.
/cat
Aoyous TWV TOVS eKKet/xe vous Trpoe^epero /cat rotairrais
ai/Ti8ofaoVTa>v
aVavT^ o-eo-i vrpog avrovg e^p^ro, also p. 26, and cf. the reference to Z. s
lectures in the irepi euo-e/3eias p. 118 Gomp. [at] Zi/Vwvt yei/o /Aeyai
1
It had been however already claimed for Pkilodenms in 1818, by Blomfield
on jEsch. Ag. 1. 362, and in the Italian Bullet. Archeolog. for 1835 p. 46.
2
See Sauppe p. 4, Nauck p. 589.
3
Gomperz has stated all that is known on this point in a letter printed by
Diels, Doxographi p. 529.
4
Comparetti (I. c. p. 5) has more recently fixed the number at 26.
xlvi INTRODUCTION.
blances, and I think it will be seen that they cannot be simply set
origin of the world and the nature of God (^ 1824); (2) a critical
review of earlier philosophers from Thales to Diogenes of Babylon,
followed by a brief notice of the popular mythology in Greece
and elsewhere (.$$ 23 13); (3) an exposition of the Epicurean theo
logy. Similarly the Philodemian treatise, as we have it, is made up
of three parts (1) a criticism of the popular mythology (pp. 5 61);
S
(2) a criticism of older philosophers (pp. 05 9); (3) an exposition
<
lows :
(1) Tholes, (2) Anaximander, (3) Anaximenes, (4) Anaxagoras,
(5) Alcmaeon, (6) Pythagoras, (7) Xenophanes, (8) Parmenides, (9) Em-
pedocles, (10) Protagoras, (11) Democritus, (12) Diogenes of Apollo-
nia, (13) Plato, (14) Xenophon, (15) Antisthenes, (16) Speusippus,
(17) Aristotle, (18) Xenocrates, (19) Heraclides, (20) Theophrastus,
(21) Strata, (22) Zeno, (23) Ariston, (24) Cleanthes, (25) Persaeus,
(20) Chrysippus, (27) Diogenes of Eabylon. The first name which
we meet with in the Philodemian fragment is Pythagoras p. 66, but
there are clear allusions to Anaximenes
(1) in p. 65, to Anaxagoras
1
The names which appears only in one list are printed in italics. Diels has
facilitated the comparison of Cicero and Philodemus by printing them in parallel
columns (Doxog. pp. 531 550).
2
The order is sometimes hardly what we should expect, e.g. the Xeno-
phontic Socrates comes after Plato and before Antisthenes.
3
This is especially remarkable in a writer like Philodemus, who, as we know
from the anonymous treatise published by Comparetti, Turin 1875, had touched
on these later Stoics in other writings.
xK lii INTRODUCTION .
the Stoics in a later pnge, ami tliat Cicero wrote in too great a hurry
either to foresee this, or to correct what he had already written.
Perhaps this is going too far. It is plain that Cicero felt the neces
sity for compressing very much the historical review, and a simple
means of doing this was to omit repetitions. He was also about to
speak of Prodicus in Cotta s reply (iV. ]). I 118), and he alludes to
Heraclitus as the forerunner of the Stoics in in 35, stating that, as
he chose to be unintelligible, it was useless to discuss his opinions.
So far there appears to be no improbability in Cicero s having
borrowed dii-ectly from Philodemus, but it becomes more difficult to
suppose this, when we compare the two writings more minutely.
Thus, while both criticize Anaximenes, Ph. has nothing in common
with C., but merely speaks of air as without sensation; while there
isa fair agreement as to the doctrines of Anaxagoras, there is no
criticism in Ph.;
on Pythagoras and Democritus Ph. is too frag
mentary to allow of comparison; on Parmenides there is hardly any
agreement; on Diogenes they agree to a certain extent, but Ph. is
much fuller; on Xenophon Ph. quotes correctly, as far as the frag
ment is legible, but
gives no criticism, while C. is wrong throughout;
on Antisthenes they agree, but Ph. has no criticism; on Aristotle
thei e is nothing legible in Ph. beyond the actual reference; on Theo-
who could fear these senseless elements? None would regard Gods
incapable of motion or of sense; or pay any heed to the moral teach
ing of those who are in doubt whether there are Gods or what is
their nature, or plainly deny them: men might even be encou
who
raged to sinby those who speak of endless strife among the Gods.
Thus the philosophers are reducing men to the state of brutes, for
they remove the check of religion and also of public opinion, which
are the best helps for restraining injustice. It is plain that there
is more of serious
thought and of a real interest in religion and
morality here, than there is in the flippant sarcasms put into the
mouth of Velleius.
We go on to the other sections of Philodemus. The first, dealing
with the popular mythology, is made by C. a mere appendix to the
section we have just been considering; and while it occupies some
60 pp. in Ph. it is condensed into a dozen lines by C. It will be seen
from my nn. on 42, 43 that most of the points touched by C. are
fully treated by Ph., but there is no allusion to the Magiaus in the
extant fragments of the latter. In the 3rd section, as far as we can
judge from broken phrases (see n. on 49 docet earn esse vim), Ph.
seems to have treated of the divine nature in a manner not unlike C. :
he speaks of the Gods as free from anger and favour and absolutely
perfect and blessed, and he is equally strong against superstitious
fears; but he makes religion a much more practical thing (see the
passages quoted on 44 quod beatum esset). Thus piety is productive
of innocence and harmlessness (p. 95); by innocence man may imitate
the blessedness of the Gods (p. 148); Epicurus honoured his parents,
loved his brothers, observed all religiousduties (p. 118), and charged
his disciples to do the same in obedience to the laws (p. 126), but
not for that reason only, but also because prayer is natural when we
think of beings surpassing in power and excellence (p. 128); while
1 JNTROnrCTlOX.
attention to the fact that certain points e. g. the lcrovof.ua and the
exposition which had been already dealt with by Cotta. His allu
sions to the remainder of the speech of Velleius are very scanty
that of Velleius ($ 59). It would further seem tliat Cicero has pre
served Zeno sayings, which were softened down by the gentler
s sharj)
Philodemus, who may also have added a good deal of his own in the
later section
1
. But then why does the historical review stop at the
middle of the 2nd century B. o. ? It seems as if we must go back
a step further and trace Zeno s criticisms to Apollodorus o K-TJTTOTV-
pavvos, the predecessor of Zeno in the chair of Epicurus, who flou
rished towards the end of the 2nd century B.C. and is said to have
written more than 400 books (Zeller Stoics tr. p. 389).
With regard to the sources of the other two sections I do not think
we are yet able to arrive at any positive conclusion. It is possible
thatZeno wrote a treatise vrept Oewv in four books, the 1st disproving
what might be considered the orthodox theology of Plato and the
Stoics, the 2nd giving a history of the traditional beliefs, the 3rd a
quoted by name in bk. in 29, 41, but never in bk. I, where, on the
contrary, we find Posidonius referred to as the authority from whom
a part of the argument is borrowed (123); and Schwencke has
pointed out the strong vein of Stoicism which runs through the
speech. Compare for instance the jest at the expense of the Academy
in 80, the definitions of sanclUas and jrictas in ^ 115, the view of
wisdom as a bond of union not only between man and man, but
between man and Cod 121, the idea of virtue as an active principle
1
Ilirzel assigns the historical section to Philodemus, as the author, and the.
curlier and later sections to Zeno. Schwencke would give all to Zeno (pp. 50,57).
Diels (p. 120) is inclined to make Philodemus copy from Phaedrus, which does
not seem to me probable.
SOURCES OF BOOK I. liii
Epicurean treatise used by him for the earlier sections; that pre
cise references therefore to the preceding argument are probably
additions by C. ; and from this he draws the conclusion that the last
part of Cotta s speech, from 115 to the end, has undergone least
manipulation and most faithfully represents the original authority;
and it is precisely here that we find the largest amount of Stoic
matter. Again, noticing the remarkable break after 105, where
Cicero after proposing to consider the question of the abode and
manner of life of the gods in 103, suddenly recurs to their nature,
leaving the previous question altogether unanswered, he suggests
that we have here a fragment of the original, which C. began to
translate, but found to be unsuited to his purpose of meeting the
G4, and may suppose both to have been similarly stated by Posidonius,
though he expressed his own assent to the latter ; that C. s motive
for maintaining the other view in 85 was probably the wish to give
his own
experience on the subject; lastly that the anti-Stoic remarks
are no more than were required in order to give the proper colour
The text which I have given agrees in the main with that of
the latest editor, C. F. W.1878, but I have
Miiller, Teubner,
endeavoured throughout to weigh the evidence, internal and ex
ternal, for each reading to the best of my ability ; and I have in
some instances retained the reading of the MSS, where it had been
altered by Miiller in common with all the recent editors. Thus
I have thought it unnecessary to insert a second eadem before require
in 21, and I have three times ejected a non which they had
inserted, before potesl in 21, before nildl in 93, before pudeat
in 111. Elsewhere I have ventured on transposition of sentences
as in 5, 30 and 97; and on emendations of words, as in !$ 2G,
49, 71. In the critical notes my object has been to put the reader
in possession of the requisite data for forming an independent judg
ment on the text. As
a foundation I have given the more im
1
For a description of the MSS see the uoto prefixed to the text.
TEXT AND ORTHOGRAPHY. Iv
evidence in the case of us readings, that scarcely one in ten of the inferences
which I had drawn ex silentio on the part of the Oxford collator of 1783 was
verified on examination of the MSS themselves.
hi INTRODUCTION.
M. c. e
Iviii INTRODUCTION.
by Sck., Ba. and Mu., but all alike change the reading. MS
modo deus moveri for modo mundus moveri. (Sch. gives a
different conjecture.)
39. universitatemque for universam atque.
45. vitae actionem mentisque agitationem for vitam ct actionem
mentis atque agitationem.
49. ad nos for ad deos. Ba. gives a different conjecture.
G4. om. aut before Neptuni.
70. fieret for fieri.
nimis collide for nisi collide.
Any one who will take the trouble to compare the text of the
N. D., as it now stands, with the text of the earlier editions from the
Ed. Pr. of 1471 to the Variorum Ed. of 1818 will be astonished at
the improvement which has been effected, owing in great part to
by the readings cited under the last head, but it may be proved even
more conclusively by reference to other passages, which did not
admit of the same brevity and simplicity of statement, such as 24
quodque in deo, 25 si di possunt, G5 nihil est enim, in which it is
confessed that the present text is wrong, though editors are not
agreed on the right mode of restoring the true text. Whilst I am
upon this subject, it may be well to give a few illustrations from
the present book, of the commoner
soui ces of corruption in MSS,
so as to assistmy younger readers in judging of the admissibility of
any proposed emendation. The illustrations are taken from the
various readings in Orelli s edition as well as from my own. I make
no attempt at an exhaustive analysis, but simply group together
examples of similar confusion.
Addition or omission of final m
see critical notes on *speciem
:
l
*
99, fiyuram 97, *quae 89, exorientem 79, imbecillilate 122,
tu 112 and 106, offensionem 85, facilem * simile and conti-
53,
nente ardore 28, *natura 23, partum ortumque 41.
1
An asterisk is prefixed wherever the reading is doubtful.
Ix INTRODUCTION.
12, 31, 50, 55, 61, 6G, 103, 113, 116, 122, 123.
15, pulcfterrima est 48, aestimanda est 55, aliquando est 68,
ausa est 93, dicenda est 95, natura est 96, variae sunt 1, *vero
sint 25, caelo sunt 34, quidem sunt 41, innumerabilia sint 50,
anirnis sunt 103, sunt quae 109.
(3) of Second and Third Person; see on inquit 100 and * 109,
attigeris 104.
Interpolation,
theory and practice of the most eminent both amongst our own
and foreign scholars. I think however it is not mere obstinacy
which prompts me to follow my own course in this matter, even
Ixii INTRODUCTION.
against the advice of friends for whoso judgement I have the highest
respect, and who have studied the subject far more deeply than I
can pretend to have done.
It appears to me that this apparently unimportant question is
not obscurely connected with the larger question whether the Classics
are still to form the staple of higher education amongst us. If their
claim to do so is to be allowed, they must show good reasons
for it, and they must at the same time leave room for other more
immediately pressing studies. I believe that this claim will be
allowed in so far as the study of the Classics supplies the necessary
instrument for entering into the life and thought of the ancient
world, and one of the best instruments for learning the laws which
regulate the expression of thought.But the Universities will have
to see to more thoroughly than it has yet
it that this is done far
been done and for this purpose it will be necessary to drop some
;
1
Sec on tins subject the very- sensible remarks of Ritschl, Opitsc. n pp. 722
foil, and 728. I cau but echo his final words, spoken with reference to tho
TEXT AND OKTHOGRAPHY. Ixiii
(2) I have always written ^<, after v; Miiller generally does so,
e.g. -cult in 13, 33, 34, GO; wdtis in 89, 103, 107; Vulcunus
81 ;
but volt in 41 ;
vohis 93 ; Volcanus $ 83 and 84.
Miiller usually has is, but we find ittilcs, salutares, 38, inmortales
45, leves 59, similes 90, 91, venerantes 85, nodes 54 though
partis comes just before. Baiter consistently gives -is in all cases.
1.
12; so conligatus
inlustris 9, but colligo 4, compa.ro 1 G
Assimilation of d:
f. adjluo 49, but ajjluo 114 and ajjluentla 51, adfcctus 3G,
but afflcio 19; so adfero, adjlrmo &.c.
r. udrideo 17 and 97, but arripio 77.
I. allicio 11G.
s. adsentior 12, adsequor 23, adsidue 114.
/. attinet 84.
a,, ad n no 113.
c. accurate 15.
. / ddgredior ->~.
Mtiller varies, giving exsistnnt 97, vjcistat 49, cjstitit 12 aud 21,
cjctitit 55 and 91, extimjui 29.
TEXT AND ORTHOGRAPHY. Ixv
Madvig s rule (Gram. 33 obs. 3), Where both forms are in use, it
is better to adhere to the Latin in accordance with the principles
,
(7) I have always written di in the Nona, and dis in the Abl. ;
keeps) not merely on the ground that it has most authority in its
favour, but because it is the more rational, as showing better the
1
See bis own remarks on the uutrustwortliiness of MSS in their spelling of
double letters, 1. c. p. 138.
Ixvi INTRODUCTION.
by the consonant which follows, secunda enim litera in his verbis per
duo i, non per unum scribenda est ; nam verbum ipsum non est icio
sed l
iacio et praeteritum non icit facit, sed iecit . Id ubi compo-
situm est, a litera in i mutatur, sicuti fit in verbis insilio ,
et
1
withj in all except the rare cases in which the consonantal i ceases
to exercise any influence on the quantity of the preceding syllable, as
in reice Verg. Ed. in 96, ddicit Mart, x 82 1. In such exceptional
cases the spelling would be changed as in other cases of syncope
or diaeresis.
It is a curious fact that, of the six MSS used by Davies for his
edition of the Natura Deorum, viz. the Codex Regius, Bp. Moore s
copy of the Stephanus edition containing two marginal collations
(styled by Davies Codices Elienses), the MS lent to him by Dr Richard
Mead (Med.} and those belonging to the Cambridge University
Library (Cant.) and to the Library of Lincoln College, Oxford (Line.),
all but the two last have disappeared. In order to save trouble to
others who may be interested in the text of Cicero, and also in the
hope that possibly some one among my readers may be able to sup
plement my account with further information, I print here all that
I have been able to ascertain about the history of the lost MSS.
In the Preface to the 1st edition of the N.D. 1718, Davies de
scribes the Codd. El. as follows : usurti editionis /Stephanicae cum
duobus optlmis MSS collatae dedit summits mei, dum in vivis erat,
patronus, Joannes Morus, nuper Eliensis Episcopus. Ten years
later, in the Preface to his edition of the De Legibus, he speaks more
1
Fortassis legendum itaque prima i vim : ita vidctur enatum ex more
librarionim exarantium I* pro prima Otho s note in . loc.
Ixviii INTRODUCTION.
employs the Sing. Codex, as lie also does in the list of MSS used
by
him 1725 (collationem MS factam in ex-
for the Acadernica I, A. D.
three together in his notes as Elienses tres, e.g. on nisi, haereret I 27.
From this it would appear that the collations of the two codices were
in the same handwriting, and that Davies, after he had brought out
his 1st ed., discovered in Bp. Moore s Library a complete text of the
Tusculans copied out by the writer of the collations. No mention is
the De
Legibus as belonging to the Royal Library at St James ;
mutilus est, nee ultra mediam partem libri secundi progreditur. Est
annorum, ut videtur, cccc. It was also used for the Academica Bk. II
and for the De Divinatione and De Fato, but apparently not for the
Tusculans, where Reg. stands for a Paris Codex. Bentley who suc
ceeded Justell as "Library Keeper to His Majesty James
at St in
"
As
regards the value of these MSS, Madvig in his Preface to the
De Flnibus makes a broad distinction between Cod. El. 1 and C od.
El. 2, considering the latter to belong either to the better or to the
mixed class of MSS, while he has no hesitation in classing the former
with the inferior MSS. He finds fault with Davies for so frequently
EXPLANATION OF SYMBOLS 1
.
B. Codex Leidcnsis (Vossianus) no. 86, written in the xnth century (13
in
3
Moser) .
P. Codex Palatinus no. 1519, a defective but very ancient us, containing
i 2775, ii 1C GS, 111-156, 162168, in G 95.
V. Codex Yindobonensis no. 189, written in the xth century. Defective,
wants the whole of Bk i, and Bk n 116, and 86 92 5 .
1
The account of the first six .v?s is taken from the 2nd ed. of Orelli as revised by TCaiter ISfil.
says of this N. Jahrb. x 144 A is an arbitrary text, inferior to both li and V. The
2 Miiller
writer omits what lie could not make sense of.
3
15 is taken directly from the archetype of the existing MSS, according to Halm, but the writer
mistakes the abbreviations &c. Alullcr l.r. 1 rnm the description in Orelli it would seem as if
S SI of Jik i were wantini;, but 15 is often cited in the critical notes on these S, and it is evident
t>4
from liaku s ed. of the De. Leiilbux p. 105, that these pa^es are simply misplaced in the Codex.
4 C is carelessly written, but without deliberate alteration of the older M.s . AI tiller /. c.
B V is the nearest approach to the archetype. Its marginal readings of the h rst hand arc correc
tions from the archetype AUiller /. . <;.
EXPLANATIONS OF SYMBOLS. Ixxi
Mus. denotes the consensus of the Museum MSS, so far as the contrary is not
stated.
[ ]
The present editor, thinking it more satisfactory that the evidence for
each reading should be given in a positive form, has made use of square brackets
to signify that the MSS denoted by the inclosed letters are presumed, ex silentio
on the part of previous editors, to show a given reading.
+ denotes that the same reading occurs in other MSS besides those cited.
Or. The revised Orelli, 1861.
edd. denotes the consensus of the four editions. It is always stated when the
reading in one of these differs from that of the text.
Ed. denotes that the present editor is responsible for a reading.
M. TULLII CICERONIS
DE NATUKA DEORUM. .
LIBER PRIMUS.
I. CUM multae res in philosophia nequaquam satis adhuc 1
ut Asc. B 2 UILO (erased by corrector), om. AB J CEBK-f Ba. id magno Or. Ba.
fter Ernesti. esse debeat sententias ( 2) om. AC BEMR. debeat BC 2 E
nd MSS generally, debeant L Sch., debc,nt M
(of Moser) Ba. 7 causam
principium Asc. C (recentl manu margini adscriptum) El.UTHILNV, causa
2
i est
5
principium Sch. Mu., causam esse inscientiam Wytt. Heind. Creuz. id est
-inscientiam om. C. esse inscientiam El., esse scientiamMSS generally, esse sen-
mtiam HN. 9 turpius Asc. Palat. 3 Herv. El. Oxf.^C 2, fortius MSS generally,
icdius Manutius, Klotz.
M. C. 1
2 DE NATURA DEORUM.
juvare nee volunt nee omnino curant nee quid agamus animad-
vertunt nee est quod ab iis ad bominurn vitam pennanare
possit, quid est quod ullos dis immortalibus cultus, honores,
preccs adhibeamus ? In specie autem fictae simulationis, sicut
reliquae virtutes, item pietas inesse non potest, cum qua simul 2
admirabilis
quaedam continuatio seriesque rerum, ut alia ex alia
10 nexa et omnes inter se aptae colligataeque videantur. V. Qui
autem requirunt, quid quaque de re ipsi sentiamus, curiosius id
faciunt, quam necesse est; non enim tam auctores in disputando 25
quam rationis momenta quaerenda sunt. Quin etiam obest
plerumque iis, qui cliscere volunt, auctoritas eorum, qui se
docere profitentur; desinunt enim suum judicium adhibere, id
habent ratum, quod ab eo, quern probant, judicatum videut.
Nee vero probare soleo id, quod de Pythagoreis accepimus, quos 30
ferunt, si quid affirmarent in disputando, cum ex iis quaere-
retur, quare ita esset, respondere solitos :
Ipse dixit .
Ipse
autemerat Pythagoras. Tantum opinio praejudicata poterat,
11 ut etiam sine ratione valeret auctoritas. Qui autem admirantur
nos hanc potissimum disciplinam secutos, iis quattuor Acade- 35
22 alia ex alia nexa [X], alia ex aliis ncxa B 1
,
aliae ex aliis nexac MNC.
25 auctores ACE [Mus], auctoritates B Heiud., auctoritatis El. Davics. 35 iis
12 [philosophos] Ba. after Bake. 21 [Ex quo regeretur] Or. Ba. after
Heind. existit ACEBCM + , existit et BUTHIL, exstititKB Or. Ba. Sch. Mu.
after Heind. 23 iis Or. Ba. Sch. Mu., his MSS. 29 ut est in Synephebis
Mu., ut in Synephebis est Sch., ut ille in Synephebis Or. Ba. after Ursinus, ut
in synefebis A, ut...inefebis B, ut insine febis C, ut Terentius in ephebis E, ut
Plautus in synephebis OU, ut Statius in Synephebis Mars. Lambinus. 80 om
nium omnium Manutius, omnium uss.
G DE NATURA DEORUM.
capitalia,
ab amico amante argcntum accipere meretrix non vult ;
3 non vult MSS, ncvoU Or. Ba. Sch. after F. A. Wolf. 13 est B (superscr. sit)
C, sitACEUMus. 16 Epicurci C Mu., Epicurii Or. Ba. (but Eplcurci else
3 haec Asc. U+ ,
hoc X. 19 intermundiis AB CBK+
1
,
internuntiis B 2E, in-
ternuntius Asc. descendisset B Asc. CNMR, descendis sed AHTT., descendens sed
CEBE, descendisset sed U+ . 22 irpovoiav edd., pronoeam MSS. 26 oculis
Asc. V
Or. Ba., oculis animi MSS Sch., oculis [animi] Mu. 31 e quibus X,
ex quibus Asc. Sch. Mu. 32 afficiendum Sch. conj., ejji^icndum MSS.
8 DE NATURA DEORUM.
20 (iuam inventa videantur; sed ilia palmaria, quod, qui non mode
natum mundum iritroduxerit, sed ctiam
factum, is manu paeue
eum dixerit fore sempiternum. Hunc censes primis, ut dicitur,
labris gustasse pliysiologiam, id est naturae rationem, qui quic-
quam, quod ortum sit, putet aeternum esse posse? Quae est 5
enim coagmentatio non dissolubilis? aut quid est, cujus princi-
pium aliquod sit, nihil sit extremum ?
Upovota vero si vestra
est, Lucili, eadem, require, quae paulo ante, ministros, machinas,
omnem totius operis designationem atque apparatum; sin alia
1 ilia palmaria Dav. palmare Dav. cd. 2, ilia palmaris MSS Sch.
cd. 1, illud
3 dixerit MSS, dixit Mu. (Adn. 7 irpbvota Manutius, pronoea MSS Sch. Mu.
Cr.).
vero si vestra est Lucili cadcm rcquiro ABC Mus., si vero vestra est lucili eadcm
require E, vero si vestra e.st Lucili eadem, eadcm requiro Hcind., vero vestra si
eadem est, Lucili, eadem requiro Sch. after Lambinus, vero vestra si, Lucili,
eadem est, eadem rcquiro Madv., vero vestra, Lucili, si est eadem, eadcm rcquiro
Or. Ba. Mu. 9 designationem G Et + dissignationcm ABBK Mu. 18 intellegi
potest XBHKLO, intellegi non potest Asc. UCIMNV + Sch. Or. Ba. Mu. (who also
suggests qui potest). quod ne esset transposed by Wyttenbach before scd
fuit 1. 16 (perhaps better before spatio), see (Jomm.
21 Trpfooia see above.
LIB. I CAP. VIII X 19 25. 9
cli
possunt essc sine scnsu, mcntem
cur aquae adjunxit? Menti
auteni cur aquam adjunxit, ipsa mens constare potest vacans
si
aer sine ulla forma deus esse possit, cum praesertim deum non
modo aliqua, sed pulcherrima specie deceat esse, aut non omne,
([iiod ortum sit, mortalitas consequatur. XL Inde Anaxagoras, 10
qui accrpit ab Anaximenc disciplinam, primus omnium rerum
discriptionem et modum mentis infinitae vi ac ratione desigriari
et confici voluit; in quo non vidit neque motum sensui junctum
et continentem in ullum esse posse, neque sensum
infinite
omnino in eo quod non ipsa natura pulsa sentiret. Deinde 15
si mentem istam quasi animal aliquod voluit esse, erit aliquid
1 sensu, mcntem Ed., seiisu et mente AJ3 2 CE Mus., scnsu ct mcntem B 1 visu ct,
mcnte Asc. +. cur aquae BE, euro, quac A, curaque CBK. ailjun.rit oin.
CBK. Menti ad * 1
-it om. MSS., for the readings of the odd. sec Comm.
12 discriptionem Al liscreputioncm CB, drscriptionem E + . modum MSS,
iiumdum H, mttn.^. A c., motum Or. Ba. Sell, after Eigalt. dcsiijnari CE
Mus., di^ifjnari AB Mu. 13 sensui Asc.VUE (corr. fr. sensus) B, sftwu AC
Mus. li continentem Asc.CHMRVU, incontinentem XBKO + in CUBV, .
omnium CEUBC, omnium TILO. 25 carpcrentur XBK, caperentur E1. HLN. 1>2>
partem esse miseram quod fieri non potest. Cur autem quic- 28
;
5 [praeterea quod esset] Ed. see Comm. 6 reprA tur ECLMN, repre-
hcnderct (corr. reprehenditur) B, reprehenderetur ACBK ?,_ c ndetur Asc.UH
[ut Gracci dicunt aaw^arov] Or. Ba. 9 asomaton X. 13 iis Asc., his X.
17 diximus M
of Moscr, dicimus Mus. X
23 a magistro non dissentiens
Dicl s Doxog. p. 539, a magistro uno Platone dissentiens XBHK Oxf. co + a may. ,
Plat. dins. UV Oxf. u, a mag. suo Plat. diss. Red., a magistro suo Platone non
dissentiens Or. Ba. Sch. Mu. after Ileind.
LIB. T CAP. xii xiv 2936. 13
25 mantem certe volumus esse. Atque hie idem alio loco aethera
deum dicit, si intellegi potest nihil sentiens deus, qui numquam
nobis occurrit neque in precibus neque in optatis neque in
votis ;
aliis autem libris rationem quandam per omnem naturam
2 modo deus moveri Mu. after Schiitz, modo mundus moveri MSS generally, modo
mundus moveri potest, El. GU + modo moveri Or. Ba. after Heind., modo mundum
,
ABCPK + ,
et turn modo mundum El.j 2- EBCV + et turn mundum M of Moser, Or.
,
Ba., et deum modo mundum Dav., modo mundum deum Walker, dum modo mun-
dum Heind. 20 minuendi XBK + ,
viinucndi immittendi El., min. immittendi-
que Asc. V+ ,
min. immutandique Herv. Dav. Heind. 23 prohibentem E
Sch. 28 omnem G Eed. Asc.V, omnium MSS generally, see 27.
14 DE NATURA DEORUM.
astris, turn nihil ratione censet esse divinius. Ita fit, ut deus 20
ille, quern mente noscimus atque in animi notione tamquam in
Theocioniam [id est orig. deor.] Mu. 4 usitatas X + imitas GUH Man. ,
15
aer per maria manaret, eum esse Neptunum, terramque earn
esse quae Ceres diceretur, similique ratione persequitur voca-
bula reliquorum deorum. Idemque etiam legis perpetuae et
aeternae vim, quae quasi dux vitae et magistra officiorum sit,
Jovem dicit esse, eandemque fatalem necessitatem appellat,
jo sempiternam rerum futurarum veritatem quorum nihil tale ;
8 universitatemque edd. after Heind., universam atque MSS. vim El. Sch.
Mu., umbram MSS see Comm., -\-umbram Or., normam Ba. after Madv. 19 ean
demque see Comm. 24 dixerat UTLO Ern. Heind. Sch. Ba. Mu. dixerit MSS
,
generally Or. 25 sint MSS, sunt CI Or. Ba. Sell, after Ern. 27 partum
ortumque [BE + ], partu ortuque ACPBK+. 28 disjungit Asc. V, dejungit
MSS generally Or. Ba. Sch., dijungit Mu. after Heind. and Ern.
1G DE NATURA DEORUM.
blepsin CK, problebsin EP, pro plebs in B (but problcbaim 1. 28), prolepsim Asc.
24 esse om. Or. (by mistake?). fere BE, fieri ACl BK. 25 fateamur 13
M. C. 2
18 DE NATURA DEORVM.
3 viderit CEK, vidcrat APB Asc., videat BU. ut manu docet C Man., w
manu doceat MSS, ut ducat nos manu fam docet esse vim G, ut manu nos ducat docct
cam esse vim Heind. 5 cernantur Sch. nequc cadem ad numerum sit Ed., nee
ad numerum MSS, see Comm. G ore/^/ma [P], steremnia ABCE,stcremia Asc. + ,
ffrepta U. 7 cum MSS, cumque Or. Ba. Sch. after Walker, cum enim Dav.
8 series Mu. after Briegcr and Hirzel, species MSS. Or. Ba. Sch. 9 ad nos
Lamb., ad decs ACB -EP Mus., ad cos GUB ^, a dto Man. Or. Ba., a dels Dav.,
1
a diis ad nos Heind. cum X (corr. fr. turn B) UHM + turn BK-(- Walker. ,
ses. Mihi enim non tarn facile in mentera venire solct, quare
verum sit aliquid, quam quare falsum; idque cum sacpe, turn,
cum te audirem, paulo ante contigit. Roges me, qualem natu
ram deorum esse ducam, nihil fortasse respondeam. Quae- 10
ras, putemne talem esse, qualis modo a to sit exposita, niliil
dicam milii videri Scd ante quam aggrediar ad ea,
minus.
58 quae a te disputata sunt, do tc ipso dicam quid sentiam. Saepe
enim de familiari illo tuo videor audisse, cum tc togatis omnibus
sine dubio anteferret et paucos tecum Epicureos e Graecia com- 1
5
BEU Asc. + Sch. (in brackets), familiari illo tuo C Bed. + HeinJ. Mu., familiar e
illo tuo ACEl BK Or. Ba. Sch., illo familiari tuo B,/am. tuo illo Asc., de illofam.
tuo U. 15 ct Asc. PBH-t-, om. ABCE (cf. 103). 17 bcnivolentiam X
Mus. Mu. 19 difficili ABCEBK, difficillima El.GM + Sch. 21 KopvQalov
quales sint
corpore, animo, vita; haec enim
desidero. scire
5 exterminatus est GUC (possibly the position of est in other MSS is owing to
n dittographia of ext.). 11 ut Carbo CB. Neptuni Jos. Scaligcr, aut
Neptuni MSS, [aut] Nept. Sch. 17 doce [PJCHL Ecd. Asc., doces ABCEBK,
doceas UO. 22 nihil est enim see Cornm. 24 oracula [A]U, oracla
BCEPBK + . veri tamen similiora [A], veri simile tamcn similiora B^KN, vcri
simili tamen similiora B-PHMOV
Asc., veri simile tamcn si mcliora CB, veri-
similiora tamcn U + . 26 quaedam levia MSS generally, quaedam quaedam
1. 0, quaedam alia L, conj. J. S. Reid; see Comm. rotunda alia MSS
generally, alia rotunda THV Asc. + .27 partim autem angulata X, part,
ang, C, alia autem partim any. Asc., partim quaedam ang. UHILO. et pyra
midata hamata quaedam Ed., hamata quaedam E E1. 2 Or. Ba. Sch. Mu., firamata
quasi adunca, ex his effectum esse caelum atque terrain nulla co-
gente natura, sed concursu quodam fortuito, hanc tu opinionem,
C. Vellei, usque ad hanc aetatem perduxisti, priusque te quis de
omni vitae statu quam de ista auctoritate dejecerit; ante enim
5 judicasti Epicureum te esse oportere, quam ista cognovisti. Ita
necesse fuit aut haec flagitia concipere animo aut susceptae
view of the evidence it appears to me probable that the reading of the archetype
was piramata amata. 12 punctis [B] Asc. U, cunctis ACEPBKLO. 13 in
[AEPK], oni. BC Mus. 18 quod enim El. Eeg. UO + quod autem Asc. Than.
,
Herv. Mars. H+ ,quid autem Red., quia enim XBKL4-, quia enim quod C, quic-
quid Lamb. 19 aliquando est Lamb., aliquando sit MS see Madv. Fin. p. 448.
>
24 BE NATURA DEOHUM.
70 lulum. Hoc dicere turpius est quam illud, quod vult, non posse
defendere. Idem facit contra dialecticos; a quibus cum tradi- 10
turn omnibus disjunctionibus, in quibus aut etiam aut
sit in
aut etiam aut non negavit esse necessarium; quo quid dici 15
potuit obtusius? Urgebat Arcesilas Zenonem, cum ipse falsa
omnia diceret, quae sensibus viderentur, Zeno autem non nulla
visa esse falsa, non omnia; timuit Epicurus, ne, si unum visum
esset falsum, nullum esset verum: omnes sensus veri nuntios
dixit esse. Nihil horum nimis callide; graviorem enim plagam 20
71 accipiebat, ut leviorem repelleret. Idem facit in natura deorum;
8 derecto Mu. (Adn. Cr.), dirccto MSS generally Or. Ba. Sch. deorsus
ABEP, deorsum CU Mas. 11 disjunctionibus EU
Asc. CIV, dfjunctionibus
or devinctionibus MSS generally, dijunctionibus edd. cf. 41. 12 alterum
utrum XBK, alterutrum CLU + Sch. esse i-crum TUL+, esset verum XBKM.
14 altcrutrum fieret edd., alt. fieri MSS. 20 nimis callide Allen, n callide K,
nisi callide CEBC, nisi valde ABPVUT + ,
nisi calide Dav., nisi calde Kl., nisi
valide Kreuzer. 26 quod i~os Asc. CRMN, qnttm ros XBK + 28 si MSS
.
diceretur Ed. see Comm., fingeretur MSS and edd. 2 J corpus aut quasi
quidem, Vellei, sed non vis fateri. Ista enim a vobis quasi 72
dictata redduntur, quae Epicurus oscitans halucinatus est, cum
sus modo
intellego. Ncque tu me celas, ut Pythagoras solebat
alienos, nee consulto dicis occulte tamquam Heraclitus, sed
30 (quod inter nos liceat) ne tu quidem intellegis. XXVII. Illud 75
4 Ba. Mu.
et MSS, ei Klotz, Or. equidem Lamb., quidem MSS. 5 cre
derem A2B
ETOL, credem A. E\ credemus CBK, credam HMCR + credatur U.
2 1
,
6 olet BLO, floret ACEP and MSS generally, ei olet Kl. nihil ex OUH, nihil ne
ex XBK + .
Lyceo Sch., Lycio UR Or. Ba. Mu. (but all read Lyceo Div. i 22),
leucio XTBKH+. 17 quid est X, quid enim El. UV, quid est enim 0.
20 inane edd., inancs MSS. 23 quid intellegis MSS generally, quid sit
intellegis El. V Asc. Bed. Heincl. 29 consulto [CE], consulta ABPU Mus.
30 liceat edd., liqueat MSS (so A has Quotta for Cotta in 1.
26).
26 DE NATURA DEORUM.
6 res Asc. V, rcm MSS Or. Ba. 11 Kit mentibus om. B. informatum
X+ ,
in forma deorum Asc. VU. 12 anticipatumque NHC + , anticipatum
MSS generally, om. Or. Ba. de deo X Mus., deum Asc. El. UG + . 13 quod
deum et deum differt, nulla est apud deos cognitio, nulla per-
81 ceptio. Quid, si etiam, Vellei, falsum illud omnino est, nullam
aliam nobis de deo cogitantibus speciem nisi hominis occurrere? 10
tamenne ista tarn absurda defendes? Nobis fortasse sic occurrit,
corruption in Ley. n
apparuisse (or aperuisse) MSS, om. Mars. Dav. Hciiid.
9),
Jnnonem MSS generally, om. 13 reliquosque AB+, reliquos CEBK.
>CB.
auditum R[CE], audilu ABU Asc. MKRO. crocodilum see n 129. 21 Aegyptio
Asc., Aegypto MSS generally. ceimes Apim ilium [ABEJCM, censes apud nullum
CB. 2G Arnini (^. Red. + Wcscubcrg (quoted hy Orelli on Tusc. i 113) Sch.
Ba., Aryia MSS generally Or. Mu. 27 alia wlii* eild. after Ursiuus, om. MSS.
LIB. i CAP. xxvin xxx 7985. 29
putas esse aut tui deum ? Profecto non putas. Quid ergo ?
20 solem dicam aut lunam aut caelum deum ? Ergo etiam beatum?
Quibus fruentem voluptatibus ? Et sapientem? Qui potest
esse in ejus modi trunco sapientia ? Haec vestra sunt. Si 85
igitur nee humano visu, quod docui, nee tali aliquo, quod tibi
ita persuasum est, quid dubitas negare deos esse ? Non audes.
25 Sapienter id quidem, etsi hoc loco non populum metuis, sed
ipsos Novi
deos. ego Epicureos omnia sigilla venerantes ;
quamquam video non nullis videri Epicurum, ne in offensionem
6 laudamus Athenis I of Moser, I. A. esse I (corr. et) f, Athenis laudamus
Vj,
laudamus esse Atlienis MSS generally, cum quidem essem Athenis laudabamus G,
laudamus visentes Athenis Klotz from the parallel passage in Val. Max. see
Comm. 9 age et MSS generally, age ut GH Bed. + Heind. facimus MSS
generally, faciamus GO Keg. Eed. Heind. 10 nominantur? edd. after Madv.
quot [A CE]KBTUC, quod A B.
2 :
12 idem in Africa om. Mu. (by mistake?).
17 nescires T[CE]BK + nescis A 2 B, nesciris A 1 nescieris CHM + nescitis U.
, , ,
23 humano visu edd., Immano usu NOV Asc. Herv., humana specie C, humano
XTBK + . tali MSS generally, alio G La. of Moser Dav. Heind. 24 ita
MSS generally, om. Beg. GTK+ Sen. 26 venerantes edd. after Manut.,
numcrantcs MSB Heind., inhiantes El. 1>2
Dav. 27 offensionem [EJHCUT
Asc., o/ensione ABCBK.
30 DE NATURA DEORUM.
paulo ante te. Ille vero deos esse putat, nee quemquam vidi,
qui magis ea, quae timenda esse negaret, timeret, mortem dico
et deos. Quibus mediocres homines non ita valde moventur,
his ille clamat omnium mortalium mentes esse perterritas. Tot
milia latrocinantur morte proposita, alii omnia quae possunt, 15 ;
fana compliant. Credo, aut illos mortis tirnor terret aut hos
religionis.
87 Sed quoniam non audes (jam enim cum ipso Epicuro loquar)
negare esse deos, quid est, quod te impediat aut solera aut
mundum aut mentem aliquam sempiternam in dcorum numero 20
ponere ?
Numquam vidi , inquit, animam rationis consiliique
Ut, si
Seriphi natus esses nee umquam egressus ex insula, in
qua lepusculos vulpeculasque saepe vidisses, non crederes leones
et pantheras esse, cum tibi, quales essent, diceretur si vero de
;
9 ea qua MSS generally, eaque CT (corr. to ea qua) Reg. Dav. Ba. 15 scmi-
naw B, semina MSS generally Sch. 20 possim MSS generally, possem KR
Dav. Heind. Sch. 22 liberet MSS generally, subiret conj. Moser and Cobet
V. L. p. 401. 25 decreverint ABCBK, decrcverunt EUTC Sch. Or. Ba.
30 discriptione ABC, description E + Sch. 31 itaque potest see Comm.
LIB. i CAP. xxxn xxxiv 89 95. 33
8 est B^, sit AB 2EBK + . 17 nihil MSS generally, non nihil N Ked. edd.
after Pearce. 19 Silum CBK, Sillum UHMR + ,
sillim A, Syllum Asc. + Sch.,
Chrisippam BH K crisippam CECO, chry-
2 2
sive BE. 21 Crysippam AUG, ,
sippum BffK
1
, cesippum V Asc., Chesippum Dav. Heind.
M. C. 3
34 DE NATURA DEORUM.
non sit bipcs ? aut ista, sivc bcatitas sivc beatitude dicenda cst
sumet alius nisi in terrestri, nisi in eo, qui natus sit, nisi in eo,
qui adoleverit, nisi in eo, qui didicerit, nisi in eo, qui ex animo
constet et corpore caduco et infirmo, postremo nisi in Jhomine
modo illi
ergo ? et quorum imagines ?
Orpheum poetam docet
Aristotelcs numquam fuisso, ct hoc Orphicum carmen Pytha-
2 ncc ca forma edd. after Lamb., ncc ex forma MSS, nedum ea forma conj. J. S.
Ecid. quo modo illi ergo XBKR, quo modo ergo illae
ergo illi UCV, quae
G Hcind., quo modo illae ergo J. S. Ileid. 5 Cercopis Victorius, Cerconis AECK
Omnis tamen ista rerum effigies ex individuis quo modo cor- 110
poribus oritur ?
quae etiamsi essent (quae nulla sunt), pellere se
ipsa et agitari inter se concursu fortasse possent, formare, figu-
rare, colorare, animare non possent. Nullo igitur modo immor-
5 talem deum efficitis. XL. Videamus mine de beato. Sine
virtute certe nullo modo ;
virtus autem actuosa, et deus vester
nibil agens ; expers virtutis igitur ;
ita ne beatus quidem.
Quae Suppeditatio inquis, bonorum nullo malorum
ergo vita? , in
interventu Quorum tandem bonorum? Voluptatum, credo;
.
generally. 2 quae nulla sunt TJTO[B], om. ACHCRBK + Scb. Or. Ba., que
nulla sunt trans, after corporiltus E. 3 ipsa Asc. CR, ipse ABEBK, ipsae C.
agitare conj. Mu. 12 Vellei MRVU + velle XBK. ,
13 pudeat MSS, non
pudeat edd. after Lamb. quarundam Kl. Scb. Mu. after Lacbmann on Lucr.
iv 116, earundem (for carundem = quarundam, see Mu. Adn. Cr. on tbe intercbange
of e and c) CUCMRV Herv. ASC. + , earum BOL Or. Ba., eadem ABK, eodem E,
ejusdem T. 19 ut MSS, ac Ernesti Or. Ba. Scb., et Walker Mu., aut Herv.
nectar ambrosiam MSS, bracketed Or. Ba. Mu., nectar ambrosiamque Asc. Heind.
Scb. epulas MSS generally, epulis UILNO Asc. Heind., in epulas J. S. Eeid
conj. 20 Juventatem [ABJBK, juventutem CE. 26 nam etiam Philo G,
nam enim Philo (orfilo) XBK + , nam Philo LRVT.
40 DE NATURA DEORUM.
qui quam ob rem colendi sint, non intellego, nullo nee accepto
ab nee sperato bono.
iis
XLII. Quid est autem, quod deos veneremur propter ad- 117
mirationem ejus naturae, in qua egregium nihil videmus ? Nam
I0 superstitione, quod gloriari soletis, facile est liberari, cum sustu-
leris omnem vim deorum ;
nisi forte Diagoram aut Theodorum,
(cf. Lachm. Lucr. iv 1130), Ceus Dav. Sch., chiuis ABC, chiius B, chius ET + .
30 Eleusinem ACE + Eleusina B, Eleusinam HLNVT.
, 31 orarum [BC 2 E]CT,
horarum AC S*, orai conj. Bentley on Hor. Od. i 35. 29.
42 DE NATURA DEORUM.
tis, quae sint in eodem universe, deos esse dicit, turn animantcs 10
imagines, quae vel prodesse nobis soleant vel nocere, turn ingen-
tes quasdam imagines tantasque, ut universum mundum com-
tibus etiam ignotis esse amicos. Nihil est enim virtute amabi-
11 soleant EN of Mosor, solent ABC Mus. Kl. 17 din MSS, in dis Or. Ba.
19 dical MSS, dicit Walker Heind. 25 ab aliis alii om. Cobet F. L. p. 4(Jl.
23 adeptus erit MSS generally, adeptus fuerit El. lleg. Dav. 29 in iinbecilli-
egentes sunt (cf. 11 21 sunt carentia) MRC El. li2 Eeg. Asc. U 13 liber est
Epicuri MSS generally, Epicuri liber exstat OUT + . 20 liomunculi MR Oxf. e
Herv. + homunculis XBH + Heind. Allen.
,
24 gratificantem, omnino nihil
CB Asc. Sch. Mu., gratificantem omnino, nihil Or. Ba., gratificantem, nihil
omnino C Red. Heind.
PREFACE TO THE COLLATIONS.
styled
"
H. Harleian MS
2465, late Parchment for the
15th cent.
first 21 folios, the rest paper written in a different and later hand
li-
Though the
transcriber is careless and the MS. is full of his corrections, yet
this is the best of the Ilarleian MSS, often closely agreeing with
B. and Cod. C. of Orelli.
(Written in Flanders or Germany.) The
united testimony of B and K is almost always decisive as to
orthography.
L. Ilarleian MS 4GG2, latter part of the 15th cent, pai chment.
The present chapters are marked in the margin by a later hand.
Followed by the De Diuinatione (which is full of lacunae) and the
Paradoxa. It abounds with transpositions and mainly agrees with I.
[Notwithstanding its eccentricities, it contains some valuable read-
ings. Ed.] (Italy.)
[The scribe is more intelligent than the writer of I, but very un-
conscientious. Ed.] (South Germany or North Italy. I am
indebted to Mr E. M. Thompson for this information, and for the
correction of the dates in the Catalogue.)
PREFACE TO THE COLLATIONS. 47
C. MS 790 Dd.
xiii. 2, in. the Cambridge University Library,
it on I 20,
"
Vatican called La. by Moser, or from some MS from which La. was
derived, hence the reading Antenulus for a nonnullis in 53, c. m
V. The Venice edition of 1471 printed by Yindellinus de Spyra.
There is a copy of this in the Grylls Collection in the Library of
BOOK I.
gravi
tate] grauitati C. constantia] constanciae C. aut] ut C. falsum] om. N.
explorate perccptum] cxploratum prcceptum I. velut] ualde IN, uelud C. 2
omnes] omnes scse C, hos 0. venimus] NC, uehimur BHIKRV, uehimur ucl
uenimus L. deos] om. C. Protagoras] Pitagoras H, Pithagoras IV,
N.
Pittagoras L, Pictayoras N. et
Tlieodorus] ct Teod. L, Etrodoni*; Cyre-
naicus] ct Ctjrcnaici C. putaverunt moh stum sit] om. N. et] HLC,
M. C. 4
50 COLLATIONS OF EXCLISII MSS.
cnntinet] c. est ILRV (cat om. Vj). niliil ay ant] om. M. nihil] niehil
BNC passim. omni] an ab oinni HILO, et omni C, ab omiti V. curatione]
creatione L. et administratione] et ainm. BCR, om. I. re rum] r. naturae C.
I, pm<(
K. ?c/-
^)<
.s ff <>.<(] temjiestas B. omnia quae] omnibus N. digital] gignit 0.
LO, ^oe/if M.
&e;ie om. INO, in CM. disseruit] disserit H, diseruit K, it<]
om. BL, etiam IN. necopinatum a nobis] ne opinatum a nobis I, nee a nobis
opinatum V, text Vr sitsceptwri] suspectvm LN. cocpirmis] cepimus M.
philosophari] philosopliiam N. in eo] meae I. studio] studii HKLHV.
turn] tune 10, tamcn C. philosophabamur] praeliabamur 0. oraiiones]
oratores I. re/ertae] refercte IM. sente?itiis] sententiam N. Dio-
dotus] Diodorus ISO, diodoctus L. Philo] phile L, ^iZt o N, ,/iZio C. ^4rc-
f. exp. C. possmus] possumus HINO. CMOT otj o] ofto cum IL, cwm
oracione MC. is esset] is esse B, met is H. rei publicae] rei B.
wm us] minus V, text Vj. atque cura...nostris] marg. only of H. pnmwm]
praemiis N. caza pldlosopliiam"] cum I, earn N.
ei m. N. waf/ni]
interesset R. om. V, rest. Vr
ae? /aitrfem] ad om. IL. tarn]
e] g;</rt
N. dixit] aura?
<pa
V adds. ta?ttu?n] tarnen cum I. .
praeiudicata] praeiudicare K-.
poterant N. tta??i] om. HILO. gui autem] guod aut L. 11
42
52 COLLATIONS OF KNOLISH MSS.
RV. */-]
om. R.
rideretur] uid. tnr KN. sententiam] scntentia B. flJn t/t H.s] B, an:
COLLATIONS OF ENGLISH MSS. 53
verenunciis O1 ,
iwre modus N. descendisset CNMR, descendens. Sed BK,
descendens si 0, descendis. Sed HILV, descendis Vj. futiles commenticiasque]
inutiles futules c. K, commentitias R, commentitias futilesque V.
c. I, aerft-
autumant eum K2 .
rotundum] et r. HV, rotundumque R. cylindri]
cil. BV, c7tiZ. HIMNCV, chili dri L. significetur] Z. appulsu] apulsu
HN, apulsu I. obriguerit] obriguit B, obruerit N. at^we] at R, atgai V. 25
Ttaec gutdem] eryo quidcm H, quaeque N, 7iaec om. C. vt ro V, ?tero S/H<]
est B, we?-o sw?it HIMNOCR, om. K. super iorum] om. K. Thales] Tales
LMNC. eni j/i] om. ILO. rebus] om. 0. eani mentem] m. eum
HI. cwncta] cucta B. faigeret} yigncret V. St <Z/]
S/c de B,
Sic di K, (Serf rf/ L. sensu] visa V, text Vj. et/r rt</ae] curaque BK.
aiZt unxt t] om. BK. s/ctt EX. constare] stare
s<]
L. pute.st]
rerHi] om. ILO. omncm] omnium BILCV r cajyt reHfwr] cajj. HLNRVj.
contingent] contingit M. ?;iist raHi] miserrimam H. guod ] fy?/0(f y!<?n
23 si fieri
^
32 XLU. etiam] om. LMNOV, rest. Vj. Antisttienes] tajitis thenis B, Antis-
tencs H, Antisthenis K, Anthistenes C. Speusippus] pseusipus N, Pseusippus C.
33 subsequent] sequens LO. a?j( m(sj animo HN. Aristotelesque] Aristoti-
lesque BK, Aristotilcs LN, Aristoteles quoque MCR, Aristoteles V. turbat]
tractnt HINVj, turbantia L, tra(Z/t 0, 710/1 PZafo;u ] wno Platone BHKCR,
Platone uno ILM, SHO Platone N, Platone V. d/cit esse] J/c/t 0. ceZen <rt<e]
infixa caelo] infixa quasi c. HN, fixa c. LO, infra caelos M, infra infixa caelo C.
sunt] aint BKLM. octavamque] octauumqite HIMNRV. qui quo...nonpotest]
om. LO. possint] possunt HMN. Heraclides] Er. BMC, Eraclitus N,
Heraclites R. modo] turn modo BHNOCV, tamen modo KMR, inde modo
L. turn] dum IL, tarn N. etiam] om. LO. ire libra] in om.
RV, text Vx .
esse] sit ILV^ om. 0. affectam] qffectum H, effecta Vx .
theogoniam id est originem deorum] Z (but t d est originem is only in marg.
of L). usitafas] insitas HVj, usititas V. appelletur] HKMCRV, appcl-
latur BLO. sententia est] sentias B, sentencias K. Cleanthes] Cleantes 37
IIKCR, Cloantcs I. mundiim dcum] M, d. TO. BHK. undique...atque]
om. C. undique] undecunque Vj. cinyentem] cingente B, agentem L.
gut aef/ier] g Hi a eMer B. nominetur] nominatur L. de/iraH*-] deliber-
ans K. us] /as BV. voluptatcm] uoluntatem HILMOV. divinius]
diuiiiitus K, diuinus LO, diuinum V. anii(] animo K. ioi(07ze] rationem
H, ratione LNO, nacione C.
XV. at Pe? sae;<s] atque persedius N, at Perses 0. dicit] HMNCRV, 38
om. BIEL, t u^ 0. a gi(/iis] e quibus K. <7?<o 5?nVZ] quicquid K.
morte] Zefo K. Chrysippus] cUrisippus B. vaferrimus] ueterimm HN, 39
aufferimus 0, ?/cra referimus L, ueterrimus MC , C2
1 "
uaferimus al."
, ueferri-
mits R. fos 7k ] eos HLMCR, ?iec eos N.
j
cogitatione] cognitione 0.
7i<?c
formationem] //
. HV r iicc intelliyi quicquam] om. B. nee disputari]
om. LO. potent] possit LOV. CM/MX] quoins HM, qua nis L, quamuis C.
al. ct hide"
Vj. cognitioncs] coijitationcs
MRV. 07/1711 M7/i] 0//1 /i is H. dcos] deum 0. /crc] ./icri BKLO, om. N.
fateamur] fatcmnr BHKMOCV. etiam] iani H. TT/JJXT/^IJ problcbsim B,
]
ot / 1
t] cxibcre B, cxibile L, exhiberi NC. <aZ/]
et n// K. imbecilla]
om. L, imbecilia N, imbecillia V (sec Madv. de Finn. p. 730). qiiaereremus]
quaerimus KOV. co7ert 7//.7/s] calamus LO. ft r/] e( om. 0. liberaremiir}
liberemur H. eraf] tswt HN. TiiiZZos] nullus KLMNC. hnpeiuh-re]
impediri M, om. N, impendet C. ?icfi/.s] mofws N. (niqnirit] BK 1
,
HN, om. 0. idderit] KM, vidcrat BO, imZrrtf HCRVr .s/f] si B. tractct]
EIIKNCRVj, tractat 0. ?/I/IH docct] C ,
manu doccat BKMNOR, manu doccat
itos H, doceat nos manu V. soliditatc~\ solitudine B. nee ad] nee om.
KV, rest. Vr 7/t] et N. propter firmitatem] illc pr. inf. H, ;.
i"Z/e
53 7IC6- HV, text V r fabrica tamque earn] fabricamquc cam HN, fabricatam
cam L, fabricatam camqtie V, text V P facilcm] facile HO. net) a tin]
om. 0. hinc] hie 0. vobis] nobis HV. exstitit] existit NO. ilia 55
fatalis] f. ilia C. elfjLapfj.^vrjv]
marmanem B, (lacuna) manen H,
hi
BIKLO, res mihi C. ceteroqui] ceteroque BK, ceterorum qui H, cetera quoqne
0, caetera quae IL, coetera qua M, cetera qui N, ceterum quia C, cetera quam
R, caeteraque V, text V r metZiocr/] etiam med. HR, TZC mediocri N. con- 61
f/one] contentione HILOV, text Vj. ei] 0, et ??i all others. consessn]
R, consensu BHIKLMNCV. ?j;se] i7Ze RV, om. 0. is hoc } ex hiis hoc
HN, is om. C, Us hoc V. opinione] ad opinionem Vr
XXIII. argumentum esse] esse om. HN. Zere] lene B. Di a^orns] 62
Diagora B. fi^eos gzti] acteos qui H, aeaos 0, gia atheos C, atheos qui 63
others. posteaque] postea quod 0. pe? te] aparte B, a parte K.
Tiam] rza/71 et HTtlNCR. ^Mt vte] aderites H, adherites N, Aderides V,
text Vj. quidam qui H, quideni qui
t/u/Je/n] et MNCRVj, quidem et V.
<./]
.s/< Z. 7(?Ht] ?(ft HNV, text Vj.
* /] sit C. ?;i((/((Zo] timodo
cst] B, om. H, filiinentittus cst I, alum-inatus et LO, allucinatus est MV, abluci-
ruitus cst N, alitcinatiis cst C (see Corssen i.
100). qitidem] quidam C.
tectum] architect!! B. <>? ; olct e.r Academia] LO, CM/HI floret e.r Ac. BXV,
f/n m ex achad. floret HN, floret c.r Ac. MCR. ex I,;/ceo] nc ex leucio BKMC,
ex leucio HV, eat leucio N, lie ex Lycio R, ex liceo V,. ?ic f pucrilibus]
nc om. 0. v/noH] om. K. patent] putanl MCRV. I amphiliim]
modo] non 0. me] om. 0. ceZas] credos HV (text Vj), caelas M, seoVjs
quasi] et quam Z. sui sit lena] sui sit lenis ILO, solicita sui sit foetus V,
solicita sui sit lena V v terra] terrae K. maxime] om. 0. ni]
nisi HMCR. egwae] aequae M. con rectatione] contraction K.
vaccae] uacae B.
XXVIII. at] out K. me hcrcule] me ercule B, hercule K, me hercle 73
V. fuerit] fait V, om. 0. vexit] uescit B, duxit I, euexit L. hoc
loco] loquor N, hie loco C. figuraque] fiyurae V. invehens] om. N.
corporj] corpore BIK. rzoZi s] ueZ/m N, nolim 0. rersor] uersorum B.
nemo] ncmini K. hominis] homini HIKNOV. /orwn ca] HO, om. BKMCR. yg
fto tame/i] tamen ita V. iucuwda] iocunda BHKMNCV. Tiaerus] neuos
BK, Fenus N, ne uos C, neuus VO. articulo pueri] pericle puero H 2 .
macula naevus] macularia eius B, macula Venus N. Q. Cafu/ws] Quintus
Catulus BHNC, Quintus Catullus V. Roscium] roseum K 1
,
text K2 . ex-
perversissimix] 2>rattisximis
H 2
,
peruersissimus N. salsuni] falsutn Z.
ct C. itna cut omnium fad ex] cat om. H, omn. fac. cst una C, cxt
} ni/a omn. f. RV. dijj ert] rcfcrt N. quid] quod HMCR. nob is]
uobis B. nitllam aliam...speciem...occurrere] nulla alia... species... occurrit 0.
CR. fai lcm] H KMN, fccelon B, /</t-i I, H C, Ht V, /c/cw others /<-//t /<-7/t
H -L -
t
.sc//r.f] BK, </(/<;
c ncsderis HV, (yo(Z itcsdcris MNCR. cffitticntcm] ejfllci-
;/"]
erno BHMNV, text Vr s njilla]
cijrias do.ras V l
and others. 2
1
"
] P>
<"i V.
XXXI. /(;.<(///
((] inxdta B, iuxlitia I, insdciitia K. plane 1 cfore insdtia C.
COLLATIONS OF ENGLISH MSS. 61
fecerat] fecerit Z except fecerun B. (Heat aliquid esse beatitm] die. al. 86
beat, esse H, dicat aliquid iste beat. and others, d.i. a. b. C, al. dieat iste b. V.
sit] sit id esse immortals C, sit id esse mortale BKLO. ammadvtrtWlf] enim
aduertunt B. te] om. BHKNV, rest. Vj. esse putat] p. esse C. his]
Us R. ille] ergo B. proposita] postp. HV, text Vj. religionis] 87
CHO, religiones BK, religio MR. Epicuro] Epicureo B. Zoguar]
loquor N. aZfgwam] om. V. numero] natura Z, except which has
naturam. inquit] inquid B, om. ILO. in ulla alia] in nulla alia B.
ulla alia H, in nulla C, nulla alia V. humana] in h. KG. numquidnam]
unquam R. hanc lustrationem] C, wane illustr. BKLMOV, text Vv autem
illustr. HNR. ineensa] incensam V, text Vr jprop/ws] propinquius L.
tantus] est iste tantus H, est iste talis V, text V r seminane] semina Z. 91
decidisse] cccidisse V. cnc?o] de caelis ILON, <fe om. C. essemus
similes] s. fss. V. passim] BHILMCV, pnssem KR.
XXXIII. liberet] KW.G B,V,juberet BL, uidetur N. esse] om. H. tisgue]
aisque K. a] ad I. 27<aZe J/j/esj o] Thalem Milcsium IVj, TJialete
Milesio C. deorum natura] n. d. V. omnesne tibi] omnes CH, text Q2
marg. H. deZi rare] deliberare H 1
,
text H2 , declinare 0. posse] om.
HVO. decreuerint] BK, decreverunt others. ?ze] nee HV, text Vr
qwrte^ue] gwae H, que 0, quantaque V. opportunitas] oport. BCV. ? -
deis Ku .
Hermarchus] Synmcus H, Haecmacus marg. H, Hermarcus KR, 93
Tu c marcus N, Hemarcus C, Simachus V. Lcontium] Leonticum 0, ?eno-
G2 COLLATIONS OF ENGLISH MSS.
ilia 0, quidem ilia CRV. Attico] attice I. sed tamen tantum] BHKL
MR, sed tamen iinde I, sed tamen cur tantum N, sed tantnm C, sed cur tan-
turn V. hortus] art us KCOV, text V,. queri] qnaeri M, quaerere NV,
text V,. Pltaedro] fedro B, fedrone C. Aristoteleni] Aristotilem BKC,
Aristoclem Vr Pliaedoni] fedroni C, phedroni V, text V 1 . Timocratem
quid] Timocrateii quia BC, Timocratemque H. conciderit] contendcrct HN,
concideret 0. 7ii)til] non nihil N.
aneum BK, siipervacuum 0. ??ec acZ speciem nee ad usum alium] nee speciem
nee ad usum alium B, ?;cc speciem nee usum alium HKLMNORV, nee nsnm alium
nee .speciem C. popUtibus] poll. K, pollicibtts LN. feminibus] femoribus
HNO. pulmones] pulmo VO.
100 XXXVI. ct] at HCRV. hnrum] eorum LO. vieissitudinesque] quc
om. L. ejf eeiaget] BK, fccisset others. ^crra?if] aberant BHN, n&er-
rarent ILO. roH/t fti/c] Z. exsc rfeos] dcos esse H. habebam]
habemus H 2
,
habeo LO. iw^j/iA ]
1
101 f(//c- e.t C, es.se oin. MRV, rest. Vr tribuant] BKHMCRV, tribuunt LO.
riJ<?nt]
uidet BK. j7 .s]
Hides H2 Libyae] Libiae BKC.
,
I &cs gwac C.
B, al.
rvzfr o CB. spo?i a<] e.rpoliat 0. mertu] wt/ft B, metu LO. ne] nee
MCRV, text Vr deinde} demum H. et} C, om. BKLM, wt HV, out 103
N, ac R. inundet} KB, inundat HLMOV, text V r superior aeri
aetheriis} superi ether BK, superior aether HINO, supenor et haec alius aer L,
supremum ether MR, supremus aether et C, supinum aether V, superior aer V r
ora] ftora BO. awtem] om. K, quidem LO. sw?zf] sznf BKC. igne}
BK, jr/wi LMORV. volitantes} uoluntates B. moveat} moneat B. pom)] 104
postremo Z. sit} om. K. appetant] appareant B. rai/o?ie] OC,
rationis BK. attigeris} C, attigerit BHIKMRVO. reperire} repperire
BK, invenire 0. eo<7e]
eo H. 105
XXXVIII. Hippocentauro} yppoc. B, hypoc. H, fpoc. C. conformationem}
confirmationem HMCV, text V : rocant] uacant B. atifem] om. C. .
introitum} intitum, o written above latter i B. Ti.] titum BKC, Tilerium 106
LN, T;/. R. Gracchum} grassum graccum L, Grachum C. videor} uideo
LOV, text V1( uidero N. Jl/.] Marco BK. sitellam} om. H, si cellam N,
socutellam C. turn] tamen HC. tu] cwm BN, ti;i KMO. Ociaun ] octaui
BHK. pervenerint} Z. him} tamen CO. referantur} perferantur H.
j n deo]deo uideo C.
ZTI esse] etiam esse C. fccati atque aeterni intellegantur}
beatus atque etcrnus intelligatur C. dum taxat} B (see Corssen n. 882). 107
ofo cffur] BHKLMN, obiicitur others. num} nunc Z. omnino haec} omnis
hie C. reprehensus a multis] a. m. r. HC. uacillat} vaccillat L (see
Munro on Lucr. in. 504). quam} MNCRV, om. BHIKLO. omnium in}
hominum in N. ea} ex Z. BKR, ergo illi CV.
illi ergo} Cercopis}
certonis BHCV, Cerconis KL M, :
L N, Crotonis E, cerdonis VjO.
Critonis 1
id
titiUatio] totiUatio B, titilatio CV. Mrtt ctiam] nam enim BHKMN, nain
LORV, non I liiin
(omitting non below) C. Us] R, his others. verv] autem
H. sapientiue] saj)ientior MCRV.
mnlta] utulto C. impudentiora]
impnid. LNO. Timocratem] timotheum H. ad beatam] abcatam B.
alia est ca quacstio] om. C.
114 XLI. at] BK, a HNCO. at dolore vacant] adolere uocant L. satin
est] sat itu st K. eat id] est idem 0, enim H, cst MCR. abundantem]
habitndantem BHK. cogitat] cogitant LO. pulchrc] CHLO, pulcliro
BIKMRV, text Vr
non ucrcatur] ILO, vidcatur MCRV, non moucatitr B,
ncc ucrcatur H, utatur N. lie intcrcat] om. Z. wi!/] om. H. affluant}
115 eflluant 1C. 27] om. 2. CoruTicaniwrre] Corumcanium B, Coruncamnn
HC, eorum comain I, Corruncanum MRV. P. /S crt H, psceuolam B,
-
o/<m]
d/c<?re
voh^tatc] L. LMNRVO, uoluntate BHIC. tfc^ r/] dcterc B.
adrmu/n] aducrsus CR. 5i
t] s?<?if MO.
117 Ubcrari]XLII. C, libcrare BHMNO. TZC] 7!cr B. Protayoram]
protulerim HN. licncrit] libuerit MCRV. reUfjioncm quac] relif)ionem-
118 (
l ue C. ^i/(Vi ] 7*i itero HN, g; </o ILO, quid ii duo V. Prodi-
cm] Prodigus BNC, prodifjiis HI. C/(/.<] V,, c///<iw BLO, c/(n/.s HIMNCRV.
119 "]
om< H. reliquit] reliquid BL, relinquit N. xo/c riwu/.s] solemus H.
] quicumque C. /H imbed) -
r<?
egentes] HO, ^u/ JH ?;. re egcntcs B, (/in / n. re eg. sunt MR, quia in n. ><
subject ; some
variety of opinions asserting the existence of the gods,
;
some doubting, some denying it. Those who believe in their existence
differ as to tJieir nature ; the Epicureans denying that they pay any
Cum sint turn est. Heindorf with some of the less important MSS
reads sunt, sermonis legi convenienter ; but both constructions are allow
able, see Madv. Fin. I 19, Roby Gr. 1734, 1735. The Ind. which is
found in the very similar passage Divin. i 7 cum omnibus in rebus temeri-
tas turpis est, turn in eo loco maxime which concerns religion, is more
naturally used in comparing particular cases ( as so both and ) the ;
tit mujidum ex
quadam parte mortalcm ipse deus acternus, sic fragile
(TOW yep KOI ytvos etr/xei , TrarTjp dvSpwv re re) or as capable of being 6fu>v
made like to God (Plato s o/ioioxrt? $e), it is evident that the inquiry
TO>
into the divine nature will throw light upon our own, and will at the same
time raise our ideas as to the dignity of man. See on the general subject
the introductory Sketch of Greek Philosophy and Krische Die theologischcn
Lehren dcr Griechischen Denker p. 7. The word agnitio is not used else
where by C. On the distinction between it and cognitio (read by Wolf and
others) see Schumann s Opusc. in 291, Heidtmann zur Krit. d. N. D.
Neustettin 1858.
pulcher : for spelling, see Orator 160 cum scirem ita majores locutos
esse ut nusquam nisi in vocali adspiratione uterentur, loqucbar sic lit
pulcros,
Cetegos,triumpos, Kartaginem dicerem: aliquando, idque sero, convicio
aurium cum extorta mihi -eeritas esset, usum loqucndi populo concessi, scien-
tiam mihi reservavi. Roby Gr. 132. [
That the c passed into ch in
pulcer and not in ludi-cer no doubt due to the I as in sepulchrum\ J. S. R.,
is
(cf. Chans, p. 73, 17 K) et Kcaurm (p. 2256 Pu.}, probaverunt Probus (cath.
14, 38 K) Santra (ap. Scaurum 1. 1.} qui vocabidum a Graeco rroXu^poor deri-
vandum esse censet, Velius Longus (2230 Pu.\ Marius Victorinus (2466 Pit.)].
ad moderandam religionem : for regulating religious observances.
These vary according to the idea we have of God contrast the
will :
religio propaganda cst quae est juncta cum cognitione naturae, sic supersti-
tionis stirpes omnes cjiciendae. C. lays down rules for religious rites in
Leg. n 19 22, and Seneca in Epp. 41 and 95 (primus est deorum cultus
deos credere, satis illos coluit quisquis imitatus est, &c.) and other passages
cited byZeller Stoics, p. 326 Eng. tr. See for Epicurean view Lucr. v 1198
nee pietas ulla, &c.
de qua the relative refers to the remoter antecedent quacstio. Heidt
:
mann, who would himself omit quae nccessaria, quotes exx. from Loci.
76, 97, 100. Cf. Dictsch ad Sail. Cat. 48.
tarn variae inscientiam. The Jiss are very corrupt here A and B
1
:
lastly all but one appear to have scientiam for inscicntiam. Wyttenbach
followed by Heindorf and Creuzer omits the clause id est principium
(cf. Ac. 1 44). If we retain the ordinary reading, I think it is best to take it
as giving the sceptical view, the cause and origin of this whole windbag of
philosophy is ignorance ,
cf. Sext. Emp. Math, ix 29 ro noXyrponov rf)s
opinions proves that they all sprang from ignorance, and that the Aca
demics are right in refusing to make any positive assertion The interpo .
lation of the clause omitted by him would be easily accounted for by the
apodosi, but this is awkward after cum multae ; and it is also more natural
to introduce the discrepancy of opinion as a distinct statement to be
proved by what follows, velut in hac quaestione, rather than to refer to it as
already known. Orelli follows Ernesti in inserting id before
magno, an
1
Magna est suspicio eum virum quae sibi placerent fmxisse , Moser, Pracf.
ad Tusc. p. xvin ; Ursini codices, qui ubicunque haescrat praesto erant, commemo-
rarenihil attinet , Madv. Praef. ad Fin. p. xxxix.
5- -2
68 J .OOK I en. i 1.
demici). [Some distinguished between the strictly a&rj\a and the Tndavd,
Cic. Ac. ii 32. J. S. II.]
assensionem :
quam Gracci o-vyKaTadfa-iv vacant Cic. Ac. 11 12 27.
Carneades is said ex animis extraxisse assensionem lit
feram ct immanent
bduam. Ac. n 108.
of the Sceptics and Academics, Ac. 11 59.
ass. cohlb. the eVox /
foedius, but Sch. (Opusc. Ill 358) points out that this word, which implies
something shocking or disgusting, would be far too strong for the occasion.
Turpius is used in similar passages, e.g. I 70 hoc dicere turpius est, Ac. i 45
esse et
(Arcesilas negabat} quicquam turpius quam cognitioni perceptions
adsensioncm approbationemque praecurrcre, Dioin. I 7 omnibus in rebus
temeritas in adsentiendo errorque turpis est.
ciple already stated, cf. 101 velut ibes, ii 124 veluti crocodili.
quod trahimur relative clause explained by the following dens cuse.
:
figuris :
e.g. round or in human shape, 46 ;
locis regions , e.g. the
intermundia ;
sedes implies a closer connexion, as of Neptune with the
sea, of Juno with Argos, see 103.
actio vitae : verbal from agere vitam; see 17, 45, 103, Div. II 89, actio
rerum Ac. with Eeid s n. [and cf. actio vitae Off. I 17 actio rerum
II 62, ; Off.
I 83, 127, 153; agitatio rerum De Or. ill 88; actus rerum Suet. Claud. 15,
continet : constitutes
Naegelsbach Stil. 112. . Cf.
note, Ov. Fast, iv 669 ; and the exx. in Sch. s note here. [As error is
coupled here with ignoratio, so with inscientia in Sull. 40. J. S. B..]
Ch. ii. 3. fuerunt qui censerent the proper Perf. is strictly fol :
lowed by the Pres. or Perf. Subj. but the fact that the same form stands
for Perf. and Aor. in Latin often leads to a confusion in the construction ;
Hugo Lieven Die Consecutio Temporum des Cicero Riga 1872 esp. exx. in
p. 45 (2). J. S. R]
pietas duteous affection towards those to whom we are in any way
:
pure atque caste a phrase properly used of the white garments and
:
ceremonial washings of the sacrificer, but also of the mind, as in Dio. i 121
cast us animus purusque, Leg. n 24 caste jubet lex adire ad deos, animo
videlicet in quo sunt omnia.
tribuenda not a very appropriate word in reference to what precedes
:
(sanctitas, &c.) but the antithesis requires that the same word should be
used of man aud of God see the following tributum and cf. in 24.
;
the supposition &c. See Holden on Off. 13 cetera ita legcre si ca virtuti m
non repuynarent, Mayor s Second Philippic p. 128, and Alanus (Allen) on
Div. I 10 ita exponam si vacas animo. Also cf. n. on ita ut 54.
permanare :
strictly to percolate ,
to find its way from some Epi
curean inter mundia to the earth.
quid est quod: what ground is there for ,
lit. what is there in
respect of which 22 quid erat quod concupiscent ? and 74, 117
. Cf. so ;
nihil cst quod 16, quid est cur 115, in 7. The answer of the Epicureans
is given 45 we naturally adore the divine perfections without thought of
:
for the other virtues For . ut item see Madv. Fin. ill 48, Acad. n 110.
For the negative understood in the first clause from the second, see N. D.
ill G8 huic ut scelus, sic ne ratio quidem defuit.
ing its strong force, and indeed . On the general phrase, cf. Ac. 99 with n
Reid s n.
is based more on the sanctity of oaths, and the fear of divine vengeance ;
more pleasing to God than a life devoted to the good of our fellow men,
that it is the path of justice and piety which leads to heaven 1 If such .
Phil. p. 127. So Aristotle Eth. V 1 15 justice in the -wide sense dper^ ,ueV
e crri reXei a, dXX ou^ aTrXco? dXXo Trpos erepov /cat 8ia TOVTO TToXXaKij Kparicmj
ra>v
aperatv 8oKfl r\ 8iKaio(rviT), K.r.X. Cf. Off. I 20 justitia, in qua virtutis
splendor est maximus, ex qua viri boni nominantur ; in 28 omnium est
domina et regina virtutum.
used impersonally in the passive, like noceo, persuadeo, &c., see Roby
1422.
1
See more on this subject in Nagelsbach Nach-Homerische Theologie pp.
191318, Pint. M. 1125.
72 15OOK I CH. II 4-.
colligunt : adduce ;
so Die. II 33 multa Staid colligunt.
Ms libris : see n 151168.
fabricati one might almost say, to have constructed these
paene :
man
precise things for the good of The word is used with a sneer at any .
thing which implies personal agency on the part of the Creator in 19,
where see n., and Acad. n 87 (see too 30 and 119) natura quae finxerit,
cd ut tuo verbo utar, quae fabricata sit, hominem. Cf. N. D. I 20 mundum
inanu paene factum.
ita to be taken with disseruit, not with multa, alleged many argu
:
sistent with C. s own belief, cf. Leg. I 47 perturbat nos opinionum varietas,
sparsam per singidos, per sectas diffusam colligeret in unum, is profecto non
disscntirct a nobis, as he then proceeds to show in detail.
different tenetsof each school, without stating his own opinion, was
intentionally adoplfd in order to provoke thought. The Academic
BOOK I CH. Ill 6. 73
school to which he belongedwas unfairly branded as sceptical. It
simply maintained the doctrine of Probability in opposition to Stoic
dogmatism, in 5 v 12.
Ch. in. 6. fluxisse video : I observe that a rumour has spread far and
wide : so Tusc. iv 2 Pythagorae doctrina flueret, and manare frequently.
[Cf. Nagels. Stil. 131, 4. J. S. R]
brevi tempore C. s purely philosophical works all belong to the
:
intervalbetween the death of his daughter Tullia, Feb. 45 B.C., and the
end of 44 B. c. Teuffel arranges them chronologically as follows de con- :
death occurred about the time of the publication of the present work,
March, 44 B.C., and that C. was much occupied with politics from that
time until his death, at the age of 65, on Dec. 7, 43 B.C.
quid certi haberemus what positive belief I held
: . So aliquid certi
liabere 14. Livy seems to make certi predicative (complement) in v 33
si quicqtiam humanorum certi est, capi Roma non potuerat cf. the use of ;
J. S. B.]
earn potissimum : that rather than any other , precisely that . Cf.
hanc potiss. 9 and 11.
quae lucem eriperet : which in their view &c. The charge is one
continually madeagainst the Academy : see Acad. n 16 Arcesilas conatus
est clarissimis rebus tenebras obducere ; 61 earn philosophiam sequere quae
confundit vera cum falsis, spoliat nos judicio : ... tantis
ojfusis tenebris ne
scintillulam quidem ullam nobis ad dispiciendum reliquerunt; 26 si ista vera
sunt, ratio omnis tollitur quasi quaedam lux himenque vitae 30.
desertae et relictae : so Ac. i 13 relictam a te veterem, tractari novam,
n 11 prope dimissa revocatur. Cf. 11 and Ac. n 129 omitto ilia quae
rdicta jam videntur, ut Herillum. Des. refers to desertion by an adherent,
such as Antiochus ; rel. to general neglect.
qua quidem in causa: Heindorf and Schomann have in vain done
their best to find some reference for these words in their ordinary position
at the beginning of the chapter; and the sentence beginning multum autem
1
Eeicl (Introd. to Laelius p. 9) more correctly puts Hortcnsius first, B.C. 46,
then the Comolatio and next to that the Academica.
74 BOOK i en. in C.
37, Post red. 14, Pro domo 47, Cad. 3942, Mur. 63, Phil, xi 28, Dciot. 37,
Marfdl 19. J. S. E.]
aim
(cf. Fin.
ill 4 ars cst philosophia vitae, I 42 Madv., Tusc. iv 5,
practical
v 5), I can point to my life as a proof of my philosophy The interest in .
an example of the Perf. Subj. after proper Perf. praestitisse, see n. on cen-
serent 3.
ipsius rei publicae causa : cf. Div. n 1 seq. quaerenti mihi multumque et
Draeger Hist. Synt. 126, also n. on 3 qui censerent. [The exx. of this
sequence quoted by Lieven from N. D. are I 6, 8, 10, 16, 58, 60, 63, 85, 90,
n 8, 72, 96, 150, 153, 157, in 12, 20, 50, 54, 70, 84, 88. J. S. R.] On the
general subject of translation from Greek into Latin, and the comparative
merits of the two languages at this time, see Munro s Lucretius (Introduc
tion p. 100 seq.) in his day the living Latin for all the higher forms
of composition both prose and verse, was a far nobler language than the
7G BOOK i on. iv 8.
living Greek. ... When Cicero deigns to translate any of their sentences
(Epicurus, Chrysippus, &c.) see what grace and life he instils into their
clumsily expressed thoughts ! How satisfactory to the ear and taste are
the periods of Livy when he putting into Latin the heavy and uncouth
is
given to a word in common use? he can always meet Xoyos or tl8os with
ratio or species is it a newly coined word? his qualitas is quite as good as
:
9. fortunae
injuria: his daughter s death, [so Ac. i 11 fortunae
gravissimo perculsus vulnere. J. S. R.]. See the letters written in the
following months, Att. xn 14 (March 45 B.C.) omncm oonsolationem vincit
dolor, XII 20 (same month) quod me hortaris ut dissimulem ine tarn gravi-
tcr dolere, possumne mag is quam quod totos dies consumo in litteris ? ; XII
40 (May 45 B.C.) quod scribis te vereri ne et gratia et auctoritas nostra
minuatur, ego quid homines aut repreJiendant aut postulent nescio : ne
doleam? qui potest? ne jaceam? quit unquam minus? Legere isti laeti qui me
repreliendunt tain multa non possunt quam ego scripsi; xm 26 (same month)
credibile non est quantum scribam, qui ctiam noctibu-s, nihil enim somni ; cf.
too Fam. iv 5. 6, v 15. Some of the fragments of the Consolatio preserved
by Lactantius illustrate C. s language in this treatise, e.g. fr. 5 Orelli, if
we are right in believing that human beings have been exalted to heaven
and in raising shrines to their memory, the same honour is assuredly due
to rny Tullia, quod quidem faciam, toque omnium optimam doctissimamque
adjectii-i
which I know is in Kiihner Ausf. Gramm. vol. II p. 168-.
J. S. R.]
aptum, jV. D. in 4 apta inter sese et cohaerentia, Leg. I 56, Tusc. v 40.
Ch. v. 10. qui requirunt.. curiosius faciunt: those who want to
know my own private opinion on each point, show themselves more inqui
sitive than there is any need for . See Madv. Fin. I 3.
tates contemnis, ratione pugnas, Leg. Nan. 51 and Leg. I 36 et scilicet tua
libertas disserendi amissa est, aut tu is es
qui in disputando non tuum judi-
cium sequare, sed auctoritati aliorum pareas. We find the same sentiment
in Min. F. 16 and in Jerome as there quoted by the editors.
momenta weight of argument lit. what turns the scale
: Cf. Ac. i ,
.
as avTos by his disciples in the Nubes 196, cf. Diog. L. vm 1, 46. Both
the Greek and. Latin pronouns are used colloquially by slaves of their
masters. Bentham coined the word ipse-dixitism to express excessive
deference to authority. It was the boast of the Academics to be nullius
addicti jurare in verba magistri, see Tusc. v 83, Ac. n 8, 120, Grote s Plato
i 238 foil.
demica p.foil. There were two editions, the first appeared in two
xxxi
books, entitled Catulus and Lucullus, in the spring of 45 B. c., the second,
which was divided into four books and dedicated to Varro, was published
in the following August. We possess only the Lucullus and chapters 1 12
of the first book of the second edition.
lucem desiderant the doctrines do not perish though they want the
:
the Socratic flpuvtia. See Angustin Ac. in 43 ait Cicero Academicis moron
fuisse occultandi sentcntiam suam ncc cam cuiquam nisi qui secum ad
So we read (De Oral. I 83) of
tenectutcm usque vixisset aperire consuesse.
Charmadas who spoke non quo aperiret sentcntiam suam, for negative
criticism is the mos patrim Academicis; and Ac. II 139 of Clitomachus who
confessed his ignorance of the real opinions of his master Carneades.
[Cf. Ac. ii GO quae sunt tandem ista mysteria? seq., Euseb. Praep. Ev. xiv
8 of the dnopprjra of Carn., also xiv 6, Sext. Emp. P. II. i 234, Diog. L. iv 33,
August. Ep. 118 1G. This notion of Academic mysteries was no doubt
fostered by Plato words an-opp^ra (Phaedo 62 B),
s half jocular use of the
merely as a weapon against the Stoics, and Aug. believes that they still
held, as an esoteric doctrine, all that Plato had taught about the ideal
world, in which exists the real truth of which the shadow alone, the veri
simile, is to be found on earth (Ac. in 37 seq.). Though C. professes here
to practise the same reserve, he states his views plainly in his Aristotelian
dialogues and even in the Heraclidian dialogues like the present (see n. on
;
Heraclides 34) he lets it be seen to which side lie thinks the probability
inclines (see in 95). However it must be owned that he succeeded in
mystifying Abp. Whately in regard to his belief on such an important
matter as the immortality of the soul, (see W. s Essays on Peculiarities of
tJie Christian Religion, App. B. on Cicero}.
orbam after Philo s death.
: Cf. Ac. n 17 Philone vivo patrocinium
Academiae non deficit; and for the metaphor, Brutus 330 post Hortensii
mortem orbae cloquentiae quasi tutores relict i sumus, Plato Theact. 164 E (of
the doctrines of Protagoras) e lnfp o jrar^p TOV fj.vdov er/, ?roXXa av Tjfiwf vvv
fie
op(pavov avrov r/p.fls TrpOTr^XaKi^o/iei/.
singulas disciplinas percipere: to master each system separately .
Cf. 95 utrumque omnino durum sed ..., 107, Off. I 83, 120, n 62, 71, Plin.
Ep. ii 4 omnino autem Lad. 98; omnino tamcn Plin. Ep. vi 15; also
;
non enim sumus nota. The Stoics held that we could distinguish
true from false sensations (fpavraa-iai, visa) by an infallible criterion (a-r^it iov,
nota, also translated signum and insigne Ac. u 34, 36) termed by Chrysip-
pus KaraXijTrrtKr} visum comprehendibile, a sensation in which
<t>avTaa-ia,
ex quo exsistit regeretur : from which fact (viz. the close resem
blance between true and false sensations) follows the conclusion stated in
the Academica, that there were many things of a probable nature, such
that though not amounting to a full perception, they could nevertheless,
since they had a marked and distinct appearance, serve to direct the
conduct of a wise man . Heind., who is followed by Or. and Ba., proposed to
omit this sentence as unsuited to the context, and un-Ciceronian in language.
The first difficulty of construction arises from the change of case in the
relative clause (quae Us) which may probably be explained by the wish to
substitute the weaker Pass, for the personifying Act. (regeretur for regerent}.
It may be said, "Why not then begin the clause with the Abl. quibus instead
of quae, omitting iis and understanding ea before perciperentur ? The
answer is that in these complex relative clauses, in which the verbs require
different cases, we commonly find the relative attracted to the subordi
nate clause (as quae here to perciperentur for quibus}, see Madv. 445,
Zurnpt 804, where this passage is quoted. The case of the second verb
is sometimes expressed by the demonstrative as Fin. n 1,
qui mos cum
a posterioribus non esset retentus, Arcesilas eum revocavit, sometimes under
stood from the relative, as fl.D. in 35 Heraclitum non omnes interpretantur
uno modo, qui quoniam intellegi noluit, omittamus (sc. eum}, Sail. J. 102
qui quanquam acciti ibant, tamen placuit (sc. iis) verbafacere ; see Dietsch
on Sail. J. 93, Nagelsbach Stil. 164. The second difficulty is the Subj.
regerentur: if we take quae to be merely connective = et ea, and suppose
the clause in oral. rect. to be multa sunt probabilia, quae...percipiuntur...
habent...regitur, we should have expected regi in orat. obi., cf. Roby 1781.
But the construction is not always used in. these cases, see
Inf. 106 tu
autem imagines remanere quae cum pervenerint turn referantur for eas
(dicis)
tion by instancing similar double forms, but the fact is that we want hero
a distinct word for a distinct thing. ixi(m is a particular effect of the
\
abstract visits, which has both the active and passive force of our word
look .Ilabco could only be used with the latter (cf. hab. vencrationcm
45) not with the n. visum. Of course -visus has here a wide sense given
to it corresponding to the use of rinuin for sensation in general. Lastly
H. alleges that the clause is superfluous and too technical. Kl. rightly
answers that without the thought would be left incomplete.
it It is not
enough to say that true and false impressions are almost indistinguishable :
that by itself would confirm the opponent s charge that the Academics
leave themselves no grounds for action you must go on to affirm the
:
et ill ust rio rib us cokibes assensioncm, Fin. n 15 A/mv/v/x nee d>\ re obwitra, ut
BOOK I CH. VI 13. 81
apa TO) O.TTO evapyeias Trddet rfjs ^vx^js fynjrcov e errt TO Kpirtjpiov, and 171
where he distinguishes between the ap.v8pa (pavraa-la and that which
(T(po8pov txovcra TO (paiv(o-0ai CLVTT/V d\r)6rj Tr\T]KTiKa>Tfpav (insigneni) to^ei
(pavrao-iav, also Similarly Descartes (Meditation 4) made the clear
257.
ness and distinctness of the idea his criterion of certainty, see Locke bk
ii ch. 29.
Ch. vi. 13. invidia liberem: to free myself from the odium of
maintaining the Academic or negative position that we can know nothing
about the Gods, I will lay before my readers the positive views of various
schools On the invidia attaching to the Academics see Ac. II 105 sint
.
falsa sane, invidiosa certe non sunt: non enim lucem eripimus; Augustine Ac.
II 12 hinc Us invidia magna conflata est : videbatur enim esse consequens ut
nihil ageret qui nihil approbaret ; on the contrary they affirmed nullo modo
cessare sapientem ab cfficiis cum haberet quid sequeretur ; Lact. in 6 if
Arcesilas had confined his scepticism to physics et se ipsum calumniae
invidia liberasset etnobis certe dedisset aliquid quod sequeremur.
tum demum procax : then only shall I allow that the Academy is too
saucy (wanting in respect for the other schools) if someone shall have been
found to have discovered the truth So in Leg. I 13 the Academy is said
.
cum tarn perspicuum sit, nan concedamus, Rep. in 9 Carneades saepe optimas
M. C. G
82 BOOK T cir. vi 13.
E. L. 95. The metre of the lines quoted is troch. tetr. cat. As regards
the reading I have preferred to insert est after tit 1 as in Tusc. in 21 fit cst in ,
Mdanippo, rather than adopt the of Ursinus, which seems to me less illo
suited to the following ut queritur Hie. [Ut cst may also be the true read
ing in Tusc. I 31 ut ait in Synephcbis, where edd. supply ille. J. S. II.]
fidem protection
: lit. good faith He who forgets the common
,
.
pliant.
in civitate non vult . the lines may be reduced to metre by a slight
alteration, e.g.
hie in civitate fiunt fdcinora capital ia :
the image, whether of a God or hero, which was placed there. Ace. to its
etymology (luo cf. lustrum, pollvhrum) it must originally have meant a
place of expiation. See Diet, of Ant. under Tempi um.
arcessitu found only in the Abl. like many similar verbals, e.g.
:
1
Since writing the above I find that this is the reading adopted in the text
of C. F. W. Miillor.
BOOK I CH. VII 16. 83
80) but more frequently of considerable size with semicircular apses and
stone seats along the walls. Vitruvius in his description of the palaestra
or gymnasium, such as were attached to Roman villas of the higher class
(Att. I 4, Fam. vn 23, De Orat. I 98, Divin. I 8) recommends that in three
of the cloisters surrounding the court there should be exedrae spatiosae in
ad quern C. often uses ad after defero, otherwise the Dat. would have
:
primas : sc. partes, Trpwra-ywi io-rf Ic, a metaphor from the stage frequently
used with agere, ferre, dare, concedere, tenere, &c. Secundas is similarly
used by Seneca.
progressus habebat: so progressus facere Tusc. iv 44.
Ch. vn. 16. Piso M. Pupius Piso Calpurnianus consul in B. c. 61. We
:
learn from Asconius that C. in his youth was taken to him by his father
to receive instruction in oratory. His style of eloquence is described in
the Brutus 236, where he is said to have been maxime omnium qui ante
fuerunt Graecis litteris eruditus. He was instructed in the Peripatetic
publicae quia non vult ; nihil metuas mali quia non audet, Att. I 13; uno
vitio minus quod iners, quod somni plenus, I
vitiosus 14. He died be
fore the writing of the N. D. as is shown by Att. xni 19. Krische p. 19
thinks that C. s omitting the Peripatetic school was the
reason for
G 2
84- BOOK i en. vii 1G.
Academy, which has been just spoken of as orba and rclieta, cannot be
included in the schools quae in honore sunt ; to which Heidtmann replies
(p. 28 foil.) that different times are referred to : at the supposed date of
the conversation, while Gotta and perhaps Philo were living, the Academy
was still flourishing the case had altered when C. wrote twenty or thirty
:
particular had been overtaken by the usual fate of merely negative schools,
Academici et vctcres et minores nullum antistitem rcliquerunt.
missus est : addressed to ,
cf. Sencct. 3, Die. n 3, Reid on Lad. 4.
nihil est quod desideres: you have no reason for regretting the
absence of. See n. on 3 quid est quod.
re verbis :
really nominally ,
124 re toll it, orationc rclinqv.it dcos.
say non verbis Stoicos a Peripateticis, sed univcrsa re ct tota scntentia dis-
sentire.The relation of the Stoics to the Peripatetics and the old Academy
isdiscussed in the 3rd and 4th books of the De Finibus and Leg. I 54 foil.
On the eclecticism of Antiochus see Introduction. For the musical meta
phor contained in concinere and discrepare cf. Off. I 145, in 83 (of Jionestas
and utilitas) verbo inter se discrepare, re unum sonare, and Fin. iv 60. [So
(TvvaSfiv Plat. PJiacd. 92 C, TO. anadovra Sext. Emp. P. H. I 200. J. S. R.]
egone cf.
: in 8. Sch. quotes Leg. I 14, Fin. in 11.
.sure I will , cf. in. 65, Div. n 100, Fat. 3, Lad. 16, Ac. I 4 &c.
(alo-Tf ) non. Later writers use ne by itself for the earlier ut ne. C. uses
either form, the fuller where he wishes to separate the connective and
negative force of the conjunction this is seen most clearly when several
:
BOOK I CH. VIII 18. 85
words intervene between lit and tie, as in this instance. Cf. Zumpt 347,
Madvig 456 and Fin. II 15 n.
me intuens with a glance at me
: Sch. refers to . n 104, Brut. 253.
nihil scire :
referring to the Academic doctrine of human nescience,
anarahrj-^fia. So Fin. v 76, would you send a youth to receive instruction
in doctrines quae cum plane perdidicerit nihil sciatf
Gotta viderit : that is Cotta s business ,
lit.he will have looked (must
look) to that , i. e. I leave it to him to show whether we have learnt anything
or not. Cf. in 9 quam simile istud sit tu videris, Fin. I 35 quae fuerit causa
mox videro, Liberius in Gell. xvi 7 duas uxores ? hoc herde plus negoti est,
Subj. in the 2nd and 3rd persons, but see Madv. Opusc. pp. 92, 96, Roby n
1593 and 1595 (where exx. of the simple Put. similarly used are given)
and Pref. cv. foil., cf. also Mayor Sec. Phil. p. 158.
noloauditorem. Both the Romans and Greeks preferred to negative
the principal verb where we should join the negative particle with the Inf.
as in the well-known instances of nego, ov c/7/xi so here nolo adjutorem :
Off. in 20. On the contrary the Epicureans are charged with a slavish
adherence to their master s teaching, 66 and 72, Fin. II 20 quis enim
vestrum non edidicit Epicuri Kvptas 86as 1 Seneca Ep. 33, contrasting
Stoic freedom with Epicurean subjection to authority, non sumus sub
p. 394 foil.) [But C. does not spare the Stoics either, cf. Ac. II 120, Tusc.
v 33. J. S. R.]
Bentham, a Comte, who see clearly because their field of view is limited.
Those who have had a deeper feeling of the littleness of man in contrast
with the vastness of the universe have been fain to take refuge in a docta
ijnorantia, professing with Socrates that they know nothing, or with
Plato seeking to find the best of human reasonings and use it as a raft
for the voyage of life, et fit]
ris 8vvaiTO acr^aXtarfpov KOI aKivdworfpov
67ri fiefiaiorepov o^rj/naros
1
Compare the manner which the latter enters upon the discussion of
in
this subject in the Timaeus as translated by C. (c. 3) si forte de deorum
natura ortuquo mundi disserentes minus id quod avemus consequcmur,
haud sane erit minim, contcntiqiie esse debebitis si probabilia dicentur.
Aequum est enim meminisse et me qui disseram hominem esse et vos qui
judicctis. It is probable that in his representation of Velleius C. had
in Ids eye the sophists of the Platonic Dialogues, such as Thrasymachus,
and intended to exhibit him rather as the butt of the company but the ;
what is said of Zeno and others 93, and Hir/el p. 28 foil. On C. s own
position with regard to Epicureanism see Introduction.
ex deorum concilio : see n. on 43 vencrari Epicurum. It is curious
that C. was attacked for using the same phrase of himself, probably in liis
caeli desert us, sine animali, sine homine, sine re, ruinas mundorum supra
se circaque se cadentiumnon exavdiens vota, ncm nostri curiosus. It
evitat,
is to these Lucretius alludes in 18 apparet divum numen
sedesque quietae,
v 147 illud item non est lit possis credere, sedes esse deum sanctas in mundi \
effutio to babble 84; II 94, see Vanicek Etym. Wort., Koby 878.
,
opifex. J. S. R.]
de Timaeo. Heind. following Walker, reads in for de as in Tusc. 1 63.
Sch. understands Timaeo of the Locrian philosopher who is said to have in
structed Plato in the tenets of Pythagoras (Cic. Rep. 1 16). But the particular
doctrine here referred to not especially Pythagorean we find it attributed
is :
to Socrates by Xenophon (Mem. I 47) TTUVV eoiKf ravra orcxpov rivos drj/juovp-
19. quibus enim oculis. The reading animi after oculis is doubt
lessa gloss intended to be an answer to the question in the text ; Sch.,
who retains it, translates mit was fur Geistesaugen but such a guarded ,
only have been used if an objector in reply to the simple question with
what eyes could he have seen it ? had already answered the eyes of the
mind Then the latter phrase might have been attacked as itself in
.
congruous, TTOLOIS ^vx^s o/i/zao-ii ; but Veil, is made far too simple-minded
to guard himself beforehand against any such answer. On the correctness
of the phrase oculis animi instead of oc. mentis, see Sch. and Heidtmann
p. 31, Klotz Adn. Cr. n 3, Wytt. on Plut. jYum. Vind. p. 94. In Rep.
i 5G we read that the Stoics tanquam oculis ilia viderunt, quae nos vi.v
a udiendo coanoscirnus.
vester Plato addressed not only to the Academics C. and Cotta, but
:
li ti
operis effcctum as in painting and architecture we look to the general
effect (so more generally n 138 incrcdibilis fabrica naturae and l)iv. i IK!
,
be little doubt that they arc figurative like the myths in the Goryias and
BOOK I CH. VIII 19. 89
Phaedrus, cf. Grote s Plato Vol. in ch. 36 p. 282 foil. Ambrose objecting
from the Christian side, says (Hex. I 3) the Creator had no need of art
qui momenta suae voluntatis majestatem tantae operationis inplevit, ut ea
quae non erant esse faceret tarn velociter, ut neque voluntas operation* prae-
curreret neque operatio voluntati .
mol. ferr. vect. mach. His mode of building, tools, levers, scaffold
ing .
required sense. Thus we read, with regard to the origin of sensation and
the manner in which it affects the reason, Tim. 64 68 such parts of the
body as are composed of the finer particles of air and fire readily propagate
the impulses from without fj.e\pi ?rep
av eVi TO f^povifjiov tXdovra t^ayytiXr)
TOV Troi^aavros TTJV 8vvap.iv cf. also Tim. 42 c speaking of the irrational
:
accretions which gather round the soul from fire and water and air and
earth. The only defence for efficiendum would be that it is a simple mis
understanding of Plato, which would be natural enough on the part of an
Epicurean, as we shall see when we come to the historical section, but
C. had just been translating the Timacus and he could scarcely havo
inserted a palpable blunder without correction or notice. Add that the
incongruous with, our idea of the sun] So just below infiguram cadere.
We are now in a position to reply to the off-hand Vnde of Velleius. The
five solids are all generated according to Plato (Tim. 53) out of two sorts of
right-angled triangles, ras 8 ert rovrcav dp%as ava>6ev 6fos oi$e KOL dvftp&v oy
av fKfiva> (friXos ?/, that is, they belong to the ideal, supersensual world, from
which the Deity took his pattern for making the sensible world, and of
which the rational soul is cognizant, unless it has been so much steeped in
sense as to have lost its original faculties.
tiiiiian optata funosorum videntur? Ac. II 121 somnia censct hacc esse
BOOK I CH. VIII 20. 91
Democriti non docentis sed optantis ; Fat. 46 optare hoc quidem est non
disputare, Tusc. n 30, Lael. 18. Cf. the use of fvxj as in the phrase
(vxa ts o/ioia Plato Rep. VI 499.
20. sed ilia palmaria but the prize for absurdity is due to what
:
we have still to notice . Pal. has the same ironical force in the only other
passage in which it is used by C. sed ilia statua palmaris, Phil, vi 15. It
has been vainly sought to defend the us reading palmaris by a reference to
the sententias of 18. On the use of the plural where only one proposition
follows, we may say with Sch. that it may be intended to imply Plato s
expression of the same thought under various forms (e. g. Tim. 32 c, 33 A,
41 A), or we may be satisfied with the more general explanation given by
Madv. (in Orelli), ilia Cicero posuit tanquam plura eadem orationis figura
enumeraturus. Vid, Opusc. Acad. I 360 not. et illis
quae ibi collegi add.
N. D. II 147 quanta vero ilia sunt quod et sensibus....Phil. v 17 an ilia non
gravissimis ignominiis sunt notanda quod. See also Ac. u 86 jam ilia . . .
Pref. iv objects to the Subj. dixerit which Draeger explains ( 151 5b) as
an attraction to the preceding introduxerit. I should be disposed to
regard it as an instance of the ordinary confusion by which the verb of
saying is put in Subj. instead of the thing said (Roby 1742, 1746).
Omitting dixerit we should necessarily have had sempiternus futurus sit to
show that this was a supposition of Plato s.
manu paene factum see n. on 4 fabricati paene.
:
primis labris gustasse to have the slightest taste of, lit. with the
:
express not the first of a number of similar things, but the foremost part of
one thing, as Fam. in 6 prima provincia the nearest part of the province ,
Catull. II 3 primus digitus the tip of the finger The more common form .
distinctly stated that that alone is eternal which has in itself the principle
of self-movement, r* OVK ano^flirov eavro, while that which is moved by
pounded is especially liable to this law, see Tim. 41 A TO dtdev -nav \VTOV,
and Phaedo 78 C TO>
/xti/ ^vvdera ovn (pvcrfi npocrri<fi
TOVTO Trdcrxtiv,
pounded and receiving its principle of movement from without, and there
fore essentially mortal, escape dissolution ? Because the First-Mover and
Compounder eternally wills to keep it together as a living unity, and his
will is stronger than any band, Tim. 32 c, 33 A, 41 A B. This Platonic
principle is of course the only ground for the Christian belief in the con
from maintaining, as some have done, that each individual soul possesses
an inherent immortality a priori, so as to render its extinction impossible
even to the Almighty. The argument here used by Velleius is taken from
Aristotle De Cado I 10 where he maintains the eternity of the universe in
opposition to the Platonic doctrine of creation. [Cf. for the whole passage
Ac. II 119 and Bernays Die Dial. d. Arist. 99114. J. S. E.]
equivalent to the opposition of clauses by the use of ^.tv and fie in Greek ;
see just below sapientes leniant, stulti nee vitai e possint. In both instances
the first clause is introductory to the second and would be unmeaning
without it. For other examples of coordinate propositions, where we
should have expected one proposition to be subordinated to the other, see
23, Eoby 1027, Xiigcls. 160, Madv. 43S, and his Gr. Gr. 189 b,
also indices (under Coord.} to Mayor s edd. of Juvenal and the Second Phi
lippic of C. Logically such clauses would come under the head conjunc-
tionum negantia Cic. Top. 57, Fat. 15, cf. Heidt. 1. c. 34 foil. On the
repetition of sit cf. Tusc. I 76 rercor ne homini nihil sit non malum aliud,
ccrte sit nihil bonum potius, Tusc. iv 50 vereor ne fortitudo minime sit
I asked about before, the agents, engines, &c. There does not seem to be
any need to insert a second eadem, to be the object of requiro, as most of
the recent edd. have done (see Sch. Opusc. ill 283). Klotz, on the other
hand, retaining the MS reading, makes restra predicative, which gives no
meaning, for there has been no allusion to any but the Stoic Pronoea, who
is here compared with the Platonic Demiurgus. The difference between
BOOK I CH. IX 21. 93
them 13 that the Demiurgus is pure spirit and exists apart from the
exstiti.
conformable to God s nature should at any time have been wanting 1 Why
should not those attributes which belong to the very essence of the Deity,
his almighty power and goodness, be always active ? a transition from the
state of non-creating to the act of creation is inconceivable without a
the lights to which the division of night and day is owing. Plato would
not have allowed that time existed even as indefinite duration before
the universe came into being. With the rotation of the Kosmos began
the course of time, days, months and years anterior to the Kosmos :
ytwrjTui (the material copy of the ideal world) TravreXws irpoaamfiv OVK
rjv Svvarov fiKca 8 fnwofl KIVTJTOV nva aluivos Troifjcrai, KOI fticiKocrnuiv apa
ovpavuv TTOifl fj.fi
ovTos alatvos ei> eVl KCIT npid^ov lovarav alwviov eiKova,
TOIITOV ov Si) vpovov uivo^.aKa^.ev...Ka\ TO T r)v TO T forai, xpovov yeynvora
before potcst with all the best MSS, and followed Heidt. p. 36 in regarding
the words quod nc csset as a gloss. The meaning of the passage is then
simple and consistent, what was the creator doing during all the ages
which preceded the making of the world ? For though time was not then
portioned out by the movements of the heavenly bodies, yet there must
have been a boundless eternity which we can conceive as extended. Well,
I ask why was your Pronoea idle in all that vast extent of time? But
with the ordinary reading (defended by Sch. in his note and also in Opusc.
in 299) we have a thought introduced which is not only out of place, but
totally inconsistent with the argument. It is not for Veil, to dwell upon
the difficulty of conceiving the existence of time prior to creation that is :
a point for his opponents to press. According to the reading which I have
adopted he merely alludes to it to show that it does not invalidate his
argument, and proceeds with an igitur which would be very ill-suited to
the other reading. The particle tamen just above would be equally in
appropriate after quam nulla mctiebatur: there is no opposition between
the clauses if we read intdlegi non potcst, and it is harsh to carry back the
opposition to the previous sed fuit quaedam. Independently of the in-
appropriateness of the proposition in the mouth of Veil, the language is
too verbose for the short staccato style of the rest of his speech. Yet
again, the sentiments in themselves are non-Epicurean. Infinite time and
infinite space are not unintelligible to an Epicurean. Lucretius has no
what was the state of things before the atoms hap
hesitation in telling us
pened on the existing cosmos with its sun and moon and stars. Sch. s
references to Aristotle and Sext. Em})., as proving the inconceivability
BOOK I CH. IX 22. 95
just before, (saecla dorm.} Because in that case the sleeping is viewed as
1
extending right through the ages, while here the action is viewed as con
fined within this time, not extending over it so in tempore infinito just;
below, cf. hoc spatio (in the interval) conclave concidisse (De Orat. II 353),
casus autem innumeris paene saeculis in omnibus plura mirdbilia quam in
somniorum visis effecit (Div. n 147). The same difference is found in Gr.
between the Ace. of duration and the (inclusive) Gen. of time. Practically
of course the two very much overlap, see Roby 1182, 1185. Or we might
take spatio as the Abl. of Attendant Circumstances, though there was all
that time , Eoby 1248.
at iste parerent. Heidt. (p. 38) has called attention to the ap
parent inconsistency of this sentence with the tenets of the speaker. That
we cannot connect the idea of toil with our idea of the divine nature is of
course of the essence of Epicureanism ;
but this is bound up with the idea
of the divine inactivity, whereas here it is assumed that the work of creation
the repeated isto, iste, ista. To this H. opposes the language used by
Balbus of the labour of creation n 133 tantarum rerum molitio, tantum
laborasse: the answer to which is that B. there speaks rhetorically in a
manner opposed to the general spirit of the Stoic philosophy to which Veil,
here appeals.
00 BOOK I CH. IX 22.
geremus.
gurgustio : a hovel ,
den ,
cellar ; used of a low tavern, Piso 13
meministine nescio quo e gurgustio te prodire involuto capite, soleatum ? et
cum isto ore fetido taeterrimam nobis popinam inhalasses... which is referred
to again in 18 tu ex tcnebricosa popina extractus ; of a miser s dwelling, Apul.
Met. I 71 brcvitatem gurgustioli nostri ne spernas pcto; of the poor cottage
in which Valerius Cato ended his days, Suet. Gram. 11; of a close bower or
BOOK I CH. IX 22. 97
sol meridianus
arbour, Ambr. Hex. I 8 32 ut si quis in campi medio, quern
illuminat, locum aliquem obsaepiat et densis
ramorum frondibus tegat:
twnne quo splendidior foris species loci ejus e/ulgeat, hoc horrenti desuper
scena gurgustium ejus intus obscurius fit ? where gurg. ejus seems to mean
the hollow depth of the arbour, agreeably to Vanicek s account (Etym.
Wort. p. 50) where he connects it with gurges, voro, &c. and supposes it to
mean a swallow abyss , hole and then a dark mean dwelling .
quod apud Ciceronem quaerit Hortensius : si deus unus est, quae esse beata
solitudo quea.t? The Epicureans following Aristotle made the happiness
of God consist in the contemplation of his own perfection 51, which is
not however inconsistent with a delight in his perfection as reflected in
the creation.
23 ut fere dicitis. The Stoic belief that the universe was made for
man is stated at length II 133, 154 foil, where see notes.
sapientiumne. The earlier Stoics divided all mankind into the wise or
virtuous (for Zeno summed up all virtue in practical wisdom cfrpovrjcris} and
the fools or wicked, allowing of no mean between these extremes, cf. Ac. II
136, Parad. 5, 6, N. D. in 79, Fin. iv 74 : the later Stoics confessed that
the Sage was merely an ideal not to be found on earth, and introduced an
intermediate class of the irpoKoTTTovres, those who were on the way to
wisdom.
propter paucos : the universal complaint, or boast, of philosophers,
see in 79 sapientiam nemo assequitur, Div. n 61 si quod rarofit id portentum
putandum est, sapientem esse portentum est, Zeller Socrates tr. p. 313, Stoics
tr. p. 254, Luciaii Hermotimus 1, Mayor s Juvenal xm 26 n.
de improbis bene mereretur. Absence of compassion, contempt for
ignorance and weakness, despair of reformation, were characteristic marks
of the old aristocratic philosophies, in contrast to the new religion which
was to be preached in the first instance to the poor. The Epicurean here
thinks impossible that God should do a kindness to bad
it men or fools,
who in the same breath are spoken of as most miserable
the Gospel :
recognizes human misery and sin as the strongest claims to the divine
compassion. Cf. Orig. c. Cels. in 59 and 62.
deinde quod the 2nd deinde is opposed to maxime, the 1st to
:
primum.
ita muTta = o: so Alt. vi 2 8 inclusum senatum habuerunt ita multos
dies ut interierint nonnulli. Cf. tarn multa quam multa N. D. I 97.
ut ea sapientes leniant, stulti nee vitare possint there are so :
many troubles in life that all the wise can do is to alleviate them by a
balance of good, the foolish can neither avoid their approach nor endure
M. C. 7
98 BOOK I en. ix 23.
naturam Iwminis dicam, hominem dicere me; nihil enim hoc ditfert, Niigelsb.
Mil. 50 4.
Most of the edd. place a colon after hactenus, to which Heidt. p. 44 rightly
objects that, wherever hactenus is used thus abruptly with the verb omitted,
it implies a change to a new topic, so much for that, and now to turn to
another point cf. Tusc. iv G5, Off. I 91, 1GO, in G, Parad. 41, Divin. n 53.
,
He further points out that nunc must be taken with admirabor, if that is
to refer to the immediate present, and ends with the ingenious suggestion
that hactenus simply the marginal note of a reader to mark where he
is
take animans as a Subst. Veil, had previously stated that the Stoics con
;
sidered the -world to be alive; here he adopts their view and shows its
absurd consequences. Velint subj. after qui=quod ii, Roby 1740; neget
subj. as dependent on subjunctival clause.
Plato Tim. 33 B, cf. N. D. II 46 foil, where Balbus criticizes Veil.
:
celeritate. As
the earth was generally assumed to be at rest in the
centre of the universe it was supposed that the heavens made a complete
revolution aboutit every 24 hours. Aristarchus (280 B.C.) propounded the
72
100 BOOK i cn. x 24.
some such clause as molestum autcm est in nostro corpore nimio affici aut
calore aut frijore. lie would therefore omit quodque etiam dci alto
gether, considering the first part a gloss on the preceding sentence, and
the latter part a gloss to give precision to the argument of the following
quoniam mundi paries sunt ; (it would also be necessary to change the
in 284, 303) sic afficiatur only adds an obscurer sic to the obscure
(Ojjusc.
correct.
minima ex parte : in the slightest degree .
On
inhabitabiles. the frigid and torrid zones see Tusc. I GS, Rep. vi 21.
appulsu :
by the sun s rays beating upon them ,
cf. n 141 frigoris et
caloris appulsus.
a<p6apToi>
KOI flOKaplOV vopifav, air 77 Koivrj TOV 6tov vorjcris inreypd(f)rjy fj.rjdtv
BOOK I CH. X 25. 101
5oav). All opinions which are inconsistent with this are ridiculed as
as we read in Philodemus p. 96 the Epicureans condemn all
1
absurdities :
who differ from them o5r av vrrevavria rrj TrpoAr^et 5o-yfxrmcWa>i/ Further .
repetetur; and, in the second place, all these readings are inconsistent with
the fact that a large part of the subsequent polemic is directed against
the Stoics. I am inclined therefore to retain the old reading, translating
Such is a general statement of the Stoic doctrines I will now proceed :
to show how they are related to the older philosophies more literally ;
to show what their character is, I will trace back their history to its
earliest source Probably there may have been some Stoic history of
.
d\ij(j)fL ai>
avrfjv tl prj VTTO TOV \onrov d^pour/iaror (i.e. the body) eoreya-
1
On
the historical section compare throughout Zellcr s History (Germ. Vol. i
4th ctl. 1877, Vol. ii 3rd eel. pt. 1, 1875, pt. n 1879, Vol. in in two parts, 1809 ;
the parts treating of Socrates, of Plato, and of the Stoics and Epicureans have
been translated into English), and my introductory sketch of Greek philosophy.
I have thought it worth while to add special references to Krische, as his
valuable book is in the most repulsive German form, without headings or index
or table of contents.
BOOK I CH. X 25. 103
fv eavToi TavTr]v eKeKTrjro rrjv Sui/a/xtj/ K.r.X. from which it appears that the
fineatoms which form the soul and especially its purest part, the mind or
reason, which has its seat in the heart, (I.e. 66) are the true source of
sensation, but that they can only act when confined within the body, on
leaving which they are immediately dissipated and no longer exist as soul.
Body by itself, i. e. the compound of grosser atoms known to us by the
name of body, is incapable of sensation, but when united with the finer
atoms of mind, it becomes sensitive to a certain degree. On the general
subject of the relation of soul and body, cf. Lucr. in esp. 230 287, where
he shows that either by itself is alike incapable of sensation. Taking this as
our clue, I think the only satisfactory way of getting over the difficulties of
the sentence is to suppose that the apodosis to the 2nd protasis has been
lost. This was the view of Lambinus who inserted the clause cur aquam
menti before adjunxit, changing et mente into mentem. Most of the modern
editors have followed in the same track. The text which I have given is
that of Baiter except that I go with Lamb, in omitting et mente, which
seems to have arisen simply from a misreading of the abbreviated mente:
when this was once taken as an Abl. it would naturally be joined with the
preceding sensu by an et. Sch. s reading runs the first question too much
into the second ; the first cur must certainly be followed by an adjunxit:
and it is also easier to account for the loss of the 2nd clause, if its end was
an echo of the 1st. How then will the argument stand ? The dogma
attacked is, in its most general form, that the first principle is divinely
animated water to which it is objected that we have here an unnecessary
;
add mind ? Why may not simple water stand for the first principle ? On
the other hand, mind is capable of existing alone, unconnected with any
if
from the ambiguity in the use of the word god If by god is meant the .
first principle, then the Epicureans would have allowed that this may
exist sine sensu. In their view senseless atoms are the first principles, and
they could have no a priori objection to senseless water holding the same
office. On the other hand, if the name god implies personality, then it is
plain that the first principle of Thales was not a god. Divine persons such
as those whom the popular religion recognized were as subordinate in his
philosophy as they were in that of Epicurus, but they are certainly not
more opposed to the former system than to the latter. The point of the
objection seems to be that a dynamical principle, like that of the older
Ionic philosophers, as opposed to the mechanical principles of Democritus,
is an irrational blending of two contrary principles, the materialistic and
the idealistic. In this objection Plato and Aristotle would concur, both
holding that the universe took shape under the influence of eternalj self-
104 BOOK I en. x 25.
that T. copied the Mosaic account of the Spirit of God moving upon the
face of the waters. We may therefore conclude that this form is due to
C. himself, and that the author whom he follows could have said nothing of
mind making all things out of water but only described in general terms
;
the combination of two principles. The use of the plural di after the sing.
deus may be intended to heighten the supposed absurdity of the dogma, or
it may be an allusion to the words already quoted irdvra ir\jpr) 6fa>v.
the repetition of the protasis would be only admissible here, if the 2nd
protasis were really a restatement of the 1st, (see Madv. Fin. I 7, who calls
this passage graviter mendosus) we should then have to take mens as ex
plaining di, and sine corpore as explaining sine sensu, interpreting as fol
lows, if the gods, i.e. pure mind, can exist apart from feeling, i.e. from a
human body (we must take corpus thus if it is essential to sensation, for
body in the wide sense, including the elements, is sine sensu; see below on
Empedocles and Diogenes) why did he add mind to water ? But it is plain
that there is no logical connexion here between protasis and apodosis.
Nor is anything gained by reading motu for mcnte with Moser, Krische,
Klihner. Kr. defends the change by a reference to the polemic against
Anaxagoras just below, and to a passage in Philodemus p. 88 1. 30, where
allusion is made to philosophers who deify TUVS ov S firiKivrjdrjvcu Swap-evovs
Lastly it may be worth mention that three of the best MSS read sic for
si, on which Davies followed by Allen founds the text, sic di 2^ossunt csso
sine sensu. At mentem cur aquae, &c., and similarly Becker Comm. Crit.
p. 14 sic di sensu! sed mentem corpore? Krische points out the ob
jections to this. See for a discussion of the whole passage his Thcol.
LcJiren pp. 34 42, and Sch. Opusc. in 359. Other suggestions are given
by Fortsch Quacst. Tull. 5 8, and Stamm De libr. de N. D. interpola-
tionibus 16 21.
have been identified with God, since we learn from Aristotle (Phys. in 4)
that A. considered this to be TO 6dov and to govern (Kvfifpvav) all things.
True, the aneipov was impersonal, but so was vdcop and therefore Augus ;
tine (G. D. vm
2) is justified in saying that neither
A. nor Thales were
theists in the proper sense. It seems however that later writers gave a
more mechanical aspect to the physical theory of Anaximander, which
they regarded as differing from that of Anaxagoras only in the fact that
the latter recognized vovs where the former had seen only an didtos KIIVJCTIS,
cf. Eitter and Preller 18 foil, with the notes from the Aristotelian com
mentators. So Plutarch (Plac. Phil. I 3, 4) finds fault with Anaximander,
but not with Thales, for making no mention of an efficient cause.
natives lliundos SO Stob. Eel. I 56 Ava. dirf^varo TOVS dneipovs
:
ovpavovv 6toi.s, and Plut. Plac. Phil. I 7 TOVS avripas ovpaviovs deovs, cf.
Zeller I 4 211. The words orientes occidentesque are to be understood of
the worlds which are continually being evolved out of the airtipov and
again absorbed into it.
deum intellegere : we can only conceive of God as eternal ,any other
supposition being opposed to the Epicurean TrpoXr^ts, cf. 43, and on this
use of intellegere 21 n.
26. AnaximeneS depa aireipov e$?7 TT/V dpxTjv tlvai, f ov Ta yivopeva,
:
TO ytyovoTa, KOI ra Kal Oeovs Kal dela yivfcrdai, TO. fie Xotrra e /c
cro/iei>a,
r<av
with Aug. D. vin 2 omnes rerum causas infinite aeri dedit, nee deos
C.
negavit aut tacuit (in contrast to his predecessors), non tamen ab ipsis
aerem factum, sed ipsos ex aere ortos credidit ; also Plut. Plac. Phil. I 3
ec TOVTOV TO. rrdvTa ylvfadai KOI ds avTov TrdXiv dvaXvecrdai otov fj ^vx^l
rj yfjLfTepa, df)p ovo-a, crvyKparfi /^ay, Kal o\ov rov Kocrp-ov irvfiifia Kal drjp
TTfpif xti.Stobaeus (Ed. I 56) further tells us that he gave the name of
God and he adds the explanation that when the elements are thus
to Air,
deified we must understand that divinity is attributed to the power which
has its seat in the element. How then are we to account for C s extra
ordinary assertion that the air from which all things proceed and into
which they are absorbed is not itself eternal, but had a
beginning in time
(gigni] ? Kr. p. 55 holds that it arises from a confusion between the divine
air and the subordinate Gods who are produced from this air a more :
dr;p -rravra yiyvtTai passes into all forms [Mr Reid indeed thinks C. meant .
consistent with the following quod ortum sit.] I believe that C. is here
giving the view, which is stated more at length by Lucretius v 318, (of the
ether) denique jam tuere supraque quod omnem
hoc, circum continet \
que perempta, \
totum nativum mortali corpore constat ; cf. what is said of \
air L 279, kaud igitur cessat gigni de rebus et in res \ reccidere, assidue
10G EOOK I cn x - 26-
quoniam Jlucre omnia comtat. In the Acad. II 118 the doctrine is correctly
stated infinitum aera, scd ca quae ex co orcrcntur definite: ffiyni autcm
terram, aquam, ir/nem, turn ex his omnia. See Krische pp. 52 GO.
Semper in motU :
Kivrfcriv 8e KCU ovros dt Stov Troiei 8t rjv KOL TTJV fj.era-
quasi by itself has the ironical force, e.g. Vcrr. v 169, Plane. 62.
cum praesertim as if formless air could be a God, whereas it is
:
cum sint ilia pcrfecta quam sollcrtius, and see Madv. (Fin. n 25)
haec simulata
and Mayor (2 Phil. 60) on this use. Literally it means particularly
when we consider that ,
but this often refers to a thought unexpressed,
as here the logical form of the preceding clause would be as if we could
possibly believe air to be a God .
f.
145) also in Arist. Met. A 3,vovv tttrtv fivai, Kaddnep iv TO IS fwoir, KOI
(V rr/ (frvcrfi TOV ainov TOV Kocr/Jiov KCU TIJS rri^fcoj Tracer. Apparently C.
meant to paraphrase SifKoo-fj.^ by the words discriptioncm ct modum
desifjnari ct conjici, the order and measure of
all things was marked out
and effected by the power and the wisdom of the infinite mind But .
BOOK I CH. XI 26. 107
though this reading is supported by all the MSS, yet most of the later
editors have followed Rigalt and Davies in substituting motum for modum,
in order to suit the following motum sensui junctum. In confirmation of
this emendation they quote Arist. Phys. VIII 1, (frrjvlv
A. o/xoO TTOVTCOV
<jvTo>v Kal rfpfpovvraiv Bouhier, Heind.
Kivr]<riv fpiroifjcrai, TOV vovv, but as
and Lengnick point out, the original motion by which the cognate par
ticles were brought together was certainly not accompanied by feeling, and
therefore cannot be alluded to in C s phrase TO. s.j. In the Acad. II 118
C. goes into particulars with regard to the o/ioio/^epeuu, A. materiam
more
infinitam sed ex ea particulas, similes inter se, minutas, eas primum con-
4
fusas, posted in ordinem adductas csse a mente divina cf. Zeller I 880.
discriptionem. Blicheler has shown (Rh. Mus. n. s. xui 600) that the
word formerly written descriptio should be written discr. whenever it
implies distribution or arrangement, as in Senect. 59 where it is equivalent
to the 8taraa-<rtiv of Xenophon.
rational life, cannot have its seat in what is infinite, nor is feeling possible
without impact This is again an appeal to the Epicurean assumption,
.
Simpl. in Phys. 336. The last sentence reminds one of the fragment of
f.
Philodemus p. 66, where we read that mind was, and is, and will be
hereafter and that it rules and governs all things and superintends their
,
(sensifer unde oritur primum per viscera motus, Lucr. in 272). Thus
Aristotle says (Anim. I 2) that the ep,^v^ov is thought to be distinguished
from a^fvx,ov by two marks Kivja-e nal alo-davfo-dai. i ru>
time or space. Taking it in the latter sense it will refer to the one all-
compares Cleomedes Met. I 1 dirdpov yap ovdevos tlvm tiwaTov fiei <pv<rii>
by pulsa. Sch. makes natura pulsa Abl. Abs. (rightly, as I think) and
governs quo by sentiret he proposes also to substitute ipsius for ipsa.
:
The meaning then would be a feeling with w hich it would feel without T
its own nature being moved . Heind. inserts tota from the quotation in
August. Ep. 118 and takes sensus of the infinitus Hie sensus mentis divinae
which penetrates all things, a quo sensu si pelleretur natura tota ipsa sensum
acciperet. Hirzel p. 95 agrees with him in making ipsa natura pulsa Nom.
and opposing it to the mcns infinita. It is denied ,
he says dass es
iiberkaupt eine andere Empfindung als d le in der Natur seller lebendig ist, in
der Welt gabe ; and to prove that natura may be thus opposed to the
divine Mind, he quotes 53 natura effectum esse mundum. Comparing the
objection to the pantheism of Pythagoras 28, cur autem quicquam igno-
raret animus hominis si esset deus ?, he considers that the present objection
isequivalent to saying dassjedes Wesen nur ein einzigcs Empfinden, nicAt
neben dem einigen noch ein frcmdcs, das gottliche, in sich haben bonne.
None of these explanations seem to me satisfactory Sch. and Ku. give a :
very harsh construction, and the latter s quo (sc. sensit) pulsa makes sensus
the cause, not the result of impact. Hirz. agrees with Sch. in retaining
the awkward construction quo (sensu) sentiret, and his explanation seems to
make the Epicureans attribute feeling to inanimate nature, a conception as
abhorrent to them as that of a soul of the universe. Heind. gives a good
sense, if there were an all-pervading mind then every thing would be
sensitive ,
but if that were what C. meant, he would hardly have expressed
it so obscurely. I think a clause is wanted to balance in infinite, and
BOOK I CH. XI 26. 109
should propose to insert in eo after omnino and to change quo into quod 1 }
translating nor did he see that feeling of any kind is impossible unless
the feeling subject is of such a nature as to be capable of tangible impres
sion , lit. nor feeling at all in that which did not feel from its very
nature receiving a shock In eo sentiret is a general expression for that
.
clothed with a body. Since he objects to this, we are left with nothing
but bare unclothed mind, unprovided with any organs of sense, a notion
which it passes the force of our understanding to grasp Epicurus speaks .
In Lucr. ill 136 144 we read that mens or animus has its seat in the
breast, while the rest of the soul (anima} is disseminated throughout the
body ; in 230 foil, one ingredient in mens is said to be a nameless element,
not found in the anima, nam penitus prorsum latet haec natura subestque \
nee magis hao infra quicquam est in corpore nostro aique anima est animate \
78). He held the soul dddvarov flvai 8ia TO eotKtvai rols ddavdrois, TOIITO
1 The two words are constantly confused in the MSS, see C. F. W. Miiller
Fleck. Jahrb. 1864.
110 BOOK i CH. xi 27.
8 virdp\fiv avry coy del Kivovfiitrg KiviicrQai yap KOI TO. 6fia naura crvi/tx^s dei,
rovs d&Tfpas KOI TOV ovpavuv oXoi/, Arist. An. I 2. 17.
vfKrjvriv, TjfXioi , As
usual the criticism consists merely in the assertion of the irreconcilability
of the doctrine criticized with the Epicurean assumptions. Epic, held that
the stars and the soul were compounded of atoms and therefore dissoluble ;
Ale. held that they possessed the property of self-movement and were
therefore immortal.
nam Pythagoras. On the elliptical use of nam in passing from one
point to another, like autem, quid, jam, see Nagels. Styl. 196, Draeg.
348 4. Mayor on Juv. x 204. Here the thought omitted is why speak of
his friend P. for he is guilty of even greater absurdities . Cf. nam Par-
inenides just below; namAbderites 63, in a list of irreligious philosophers;
nam Phaedro of Epicureans; nam justitia...nam furtis in
93, in a list
a list of his writings Div. n 3; nam de angue, nam Dionysi equus, nam quod
Stellas aurcas in a list of portents Div. n 65, 67, 68, nam titrato Ac. I 34.
of transition.
animum carperentur. See Krische 78 86, Zeller i 3S5 4 foil. 412
Heinze Logos 179. This doctrine is also ascribed to P. in Senect. 78
foil.
religious ideas of the Pythagoreans see Zeller I 418 foil, and cf. C. Leg. n 26
bciie dictum cst ab co turn maxime et pietatem et rcligioncm versari in animis
cum rebus divinis operam darcmus. The most complete account of the
divine soul, then (1) the separate existence of human souls must cause a
laceration of the universal soul, (2) when the individual soul is conscious of
pain, a part of divinity is in pain, (3) each soul must partake in the infinite
knowledge of the universal soul, (4) it is impossible that an incorporeal
soul could be united with a material world. For obj. (1) cf. 24 dei membra
ardcntia: it is of course merely straining the metaphor of carperentur.
Both this and the following obj. are based on the Epicurean assumption of
perfect happiness as essential to divinity. On the Epicurean pessimism
(quod plerisque contingerei) see 23 n. Obj. (4) is inapplicable the writers :
who attribute to P. the derivation of the human soul from the divine
represent him as materializing both under the form of fire or aether.
distractioneBa. adopts Euhnken s conjecture detractione referring
:
to the separation of each soul from the universal soul ; but the MS reading
infinity of the universe Arist. (Met. A. 986 b.) distinctly tells us that while
Parmenides made the One Treirfpacrp.fvoi>, regarding it from the ideal side,
and Melissus, regarding it from the material side, made it uneipov, Xeno
phanes ovSev dXX tls rov o\ov ovpavov a7roj3Xe\//-a? TO tv tlvai
8iecra(pTJi i(rfv
the rational universe to be not only infinite but God he allows however ;
belonging to the subject ; Veil, objects not to TO irav being called uirttpov,
but to TO anfipov being called Beov. And the same appears from the
quotation in Minucius c. 19 Xen. notum est omne infinitum cum mcnte dcum
tradero. I believe that C. is translating some such original as TO irav,
\oyiKov ov Kal aKtipov, 6tov flvai, and that he has here turned a quality
into an independent substance, as was done above in the case of Thales, and
also of Democritus ( 29). Then praeterea quod esset (or perhaps praeterea
alone) seems to me a gloss intended to soften the apparent contradiction
in the idea of TO irav in which mind is not included. For omne TO irav, =
cf. Die. 103 quod in natura rerum omne esse dicimus, id infinitum esse.
II.
that the true reading here is propterea, not praeterea X. s God was God
just because he had no definite organs (ov\os 6pa &c.) like the anthropo
morphic Gods. J. S. R]
de ipsa potest esse. Epicurean polemic as regards the divinity of :
mind, Xen. is open to the same criticism as Thales and Anaxagoras (for why
did he combine mind with infinity ? and if it is unbodied mind, how can
that feel ?) as regards the divinity of the infinite, he is even more to
:
blame, for vacancy is the only infinite, and in this there can be no feeling
and no connexion with any thing external (such as mind) since it includes
all things in itself. There seems no ground for Kr. s supposition that
conjunctum is used in the Lucretian sense (i 450) of a property for void, ;
no less than the atoms, has conjuncta in this sense nor again for Hirzel s ;
but names, and finding the word 6tos occurring frequently in P. s popu
lar account of the phenomenal world, he confines his attention to this,
regardless of the fact that, whether named or not, the idea of divinity
is as much involved in P. s higher philosophy as in that of many of
his predecessors, and also forgetting that the cosmical system of Par
menides is in the main taken from Pythagoras and should have been
criticized under his name. The doctrine here alluded to is given by Stob.
cl. I C. 22, II. crTf(f)ai>as
dvai TTfpnrtTrXcyfjLti as tVaXA^Xovr, TTJV p.ti>
e /c ToO
BOOK I CH. XI 28. 113
dpmov (the fine element of fire) rr]v 8e t< TOV TTVKVOV (the gross element,
earth,) HIKTOS 8e XAus e/c
(pa>To$
KOI crKorovf fj.(Taf-v TOVTMV Kal TO irfptf\ov
8e Tracras Tfixovs crrfpfov vrrapxetv, v(fS
8iKT]i>, TruptuSr/s <u
<TTf(pavr)
Kal TO
irao-aiv (is solid also) Trepl ov naXiv TrupcoSr;? ra>v 8e crup./urya>i> Trjv
X*W) rjvTiva Kal 8aip.ova Kal KvficpvrjTiv KOI K\r]8ovxoi> 6vo[j.dfi, 8iKT)v Tf /cui
dvuyKTjv. From
this it is plain that C. is mistaken in ascribing divinity to
the orbcm qui cingit caelum. It is the innermost fiery circle surrounding
the dark globe of the earth which is divine according to P. Probably C.
in his haste confused this with the ninth all-embracing sphere of the
Somn. Scip. 4 summus ipse deus, arcens et continens ceteros, in quo infixi
sunt qui volvuntur stellarum cursus sempiterni. In Ac. II 118 we read
illi
one of the leading disciples of Epic., wrote against Parm. as we learn from
Plut. N. p. 1113 foil., but there is no resemblance between the criticisms
which we find there, and those contained in this passage.
nam : see n. on 27.
commenticium see 18. It suggests the more fanciful character of
:
tion as to the human form of the Gods and the impossibility of sensation
except through the medium of bodily senses.
multaque monstra modi is inserted after ejusdcm by most edd. and
:
no doubt the omission would be easy before monstra, which in that case
would be the Ace. governed by efficit. The monstra however which follow
(helium, &c.) are hardly ejusdcm generis with the a-Tffpafrj and the recur ;
M. C. 8
] 14 r.ooK i CH. xi 28.
Though the contrary principle belluin did not play so important a part in
P. s system as Empedocles, yet it may easily have been introduced
in that of
05), TOV Tf TTpWTOV OfOV a\j/V)(OV TTOielf, TOVS T y(Vl O)fJ.(VOVS tlTTO TOVTOV T(l
cetera :
e.g. 1*77
and avnyKrj mentioned in Stob. 1. c.
ad deum revocet brings them under the head of deity i.e. makes
:
,
livrpuiv but we are not told elsewhere that lie attributed divinity to them.
On the omission of dt cit (with eadnrii) cf. 17 n. The reference is to ad
deum reroct t. In alto i.e. in the case of Alcmaeon.
ch. xn 29. Empedocles : see Krische 110 130. The fragments are
collected and explained by Karsten (very full notes), Mullach and others.
Lucretius I 71(! 733 speaks in a very different tone of the glory of Sicily
whose inspired verses set forth his discoveries in such wise -ut, ci.v humana
videatur stirpe crcatus but we learn from .V. J). i 93 that Epicurus and
,
gods and daemons of the popular religion, the souls of good men. The
criticism is equally careless.
peccans among other blunders
:
,
cf. 31.
deorum opinio :
<>bj. gen. in his religious belief, so opin. cjus below,
diciiiatioiiis opin. ]>elief in divination l)ic. ir 75; but op. de dix X. J). in
11, cf. Draeg. 203, Koby 1318.
naturas : cf. 22 n.
same objection, but E. himself distinctly asserts the opposite, (pvais oi!Si/oj
BOOK I CH. XII 29. 115
<as ov< flcrlv TroXXa yap TO. KaiXvovra eZSeVcu, fj re a S^Xorjjy Kai /3pa^i>?
<av 6
probable that Philodemus reported the doctrine in this form, for though
there is no direct mention of Prot. in the existing fragments, yet in the
haberem aliquid quod liqueret, Ac. n 94, and the legal j.\r L. (Cluent. 76). .
Democritus see Krische 142 163, and nn. on ^V. D. i 120 where his
:
and void are of course eternal to D. as to Epicurus, but the former had
not thought of saving his Gods from wasting and disturbing influences by
82
11G BOOK I en. xii 29.
fjLtv, OVK. atpdapra 8t (Sext. Emp. ix 558) and cannot pass the Epicurean
test.
avfiTrrei, and spoke of o tWoy drjp (the breath or spirit of man) as fjm<pi>i>
quern sensum del: reiteration of the old polemic, see under Em-
pedocles, Parmenides, Anaximenes for sennit m, under Parmenides an 1
Anaximenes forfiffuram.
30. jam a transitional particle like na/n,
: which some read here :
lit.
by this time next we come to Plato.
Plato Krische 181 204. The fact that we have, in this 2nd criti
:
"With the
exception of Sch. all the edd. seem content to understand incoii-
stuntia of the first two assertions, that God cannot be named and that he-
evidently quite consistent, Sch. holds that the opposition lies between them
on the one hand and the assertion of the incorporeal nature of God (rji>
I,
vero do-co/Liaro!/)
on the other. He allows that the grammatical connexion
of the two sentencesis very different from what we should have expecte 1
ifthey were intended to have this relation to one another, but offers no
the 1st (MS) sentence and the variety of positive assertions as to the Deity
in the 3rd (MS) sentence, is much more glaring than the opposition
between the 1st sentence and the one negative assertion of the 2nd
sentence. Besides the idea of inconsistency runs through the 3rd sen
tence, -whereas it is entirely absent in the 2nd. I think also that the
lies between the 1st and the 3rd sentences,! have little doubt that the 2nd
and 3rd have got misplaced. Compare the transposition in 5 of the
sentences beginning qua quidem and multum autem, that in 88 and
97, and many similar instances in Muuro s Lucretius, see his Intro
duction p. 20 foil. ed. 1, also Miiller in N. Jahrb. for 1864, p. 144. In the
present case and also in 5 the transposition may be explained by sup
posing the misplaced clauses (Sunt vero and Qua quidem} to have been
added on revision by C. himself, but wrongly inserted by the scribe. See
below on idem in Timaeo.
longum est : see 19 n.
inconstantiaGrote (Plato n 161) applies this censure more generally.
:
evpelv re fpyov Kai fvpovra els iravras dfivvarov \eyfiv, translated by C. Tim.
2 atque ilium quidem quasi parentem hujus universitatis invenire difficile,
etcum inveneris indicare in vulgus nefas. The passage was much quoted
by the early Christian writers, e.g. Minucius c. 19 Platoni deus est mundi
parens, artifex animae, caelestium terrenorumque fabricator, quern et invenire
difficile prae
nimia et incredibili potestate, et cum inveneris in publicum
dicer e impossibile praefatur. Eademfereet ista quae nostra sunt. On the
other hand Celsus made use of it against the Christian preaching of the
Gospel to the poor, to which Origen (vn 42) replies that the Christians not
only affirmed with Plato that it was difficult to discover the Creator, but
that it was even impossible for man to do this, except for those to whom
the Son revealed Him. Clement of Alexandria, commenting on the words
of Plato, says that, in using of the Ineffable such names as ev fj rdyadov f/
vovv 77 aura TO ov f) TTdTtpa rj Qeov rj drjpiovpyov rj nvpiov, we do not profess to
name Him truly, but employ various terms as a help to the feebleness of
our own understanding, Strom, v 12 83.
in legum censeat. As we have had occasion to suspect misrepresenta
tion in cases whereit was difficult to arrive at
complete certainty in regard
to the doctrines referred to, it is a satisfaction to be able here to con
front the accused with the accuser, and prove the groundlessness of the
118 BOOK I CH. XII 30.
plain that the word (pap.ev introduces, not a sentiment of Plato s, but that
of the Athenian public, who had banished Anaxagoras and put Socrates to
death on a similar charge. Plato s own view comes out still more clearly
in bk xn 9G6, where he argues that astronomy rightly studied is the foun
dation of true piety.
non censeat negative used as in ov (frijui, cf. Off. I 39 Rcgulus captivos
:
(
but yet ) yloriae jacturam ne minimum quidcm faccre vcllent. After the
dislocation had taken place, the sentences would naturally be altered so
far as to enable them to stand alone.
as opposed to the earth. Beside the passages already quoted, showing the
divinity of the stars, see Tim. 40, where the Demiurgus is said to have
made the earth, our nurse, the guardian of day and night, the first and
oldest of the gods oaoi evrus ovpavov ytyovao-i. In the same passage Plato
affirms his belief in the deities of the traditional religion (cos quos majorum
institutes accepimus) the children of Heaven and Earth, and tells us that
they, like the celestial deities, acted as subordinate agents in the creation
of man and the other animals, receiving from the Demiurgus a separate
divine particle to be the nucleus of each human soul (41 c. foil.) But
when C. says that Plato deified animos, he probably alludes to Leg. X.
892 foil, where it is proved that soul, as the self-moving substance, must bo
prior to body, and then (899 B) the conclusion is drawn that, since soul or
souls have been shown to be the cause of all movement, and since they are
BOOK I CH. XII 30. 119
genuineness of these words, as Heind. and Ba. have done see n. on pkysio- ;
logiam 20. There is a special reason for adding the Greek here, as the
Latin equivalents were not introduced till later, incorporalis appearing
first in Seneca, incorporeus in Gellius. The doctrine that all that is
corporeal is in its own nature mortal, yevvtjrov Kai runs through <p0apToi>,
the whole of Plato (see 20 n.) and we find the unseen, which is eternal,
contrasted with things seen and temporal in Tim. 28 ; but it is only the
Demiurgus who is essentially incorporeal; many of the inferior deities
are clothed in bodies.
id intellegi non potest a divine incorporeity is inconceivable cf.
:
,
speaking of those qui nequeunt qualis animus sit vacans corpore intellegere et
cogitatione comprehendere, he says quasi vero intellegant qualis sit in ipso
corpore; and a little further certe et deum ipsum et divinum animum corpore
liberatum cogitatione complecti volumus. Again Tusc. I 71 dubitare non
possumus quin nihil sit animis admixtum, nihil concretum, nihil copulatum,
nihil coagmentatum, nihil duplex. Quod cum ita sit, certe nee secerni nee
dividi nee discerpi nee distralii potest, ne interire quidem igitur. Plato
argues against those who identified matter and existence, TCLVTOV KO\ <ra>na
oixr iav opi&nevoi in the Soph. 246 foil, where the term daa>p.aTov occurs.
that of the Epicurean critic here, who would identify this with the view
just before attributed to Plato (deum nominari non posse, anquiri ncn
deberc). The next assertion et solem et animum, deum is founded upon
the same passage of the Memorabilia, where Socrates illustrates our
inability to look upon God by the parallel case of the sun, d TTOO-I
(pavtpos 8ouv fivai 77X10? fTTirpeVet TOIS dv&pa>irois tavrov aKpiftcas opav,
ov<
dXX tav TLS avrov dvai8u>s (y^fipij dtaadai TTJV u^riv afpatpflrai, and of the
soul dvdptairov yt ^v\^, fj tijrep TI KOI aXXo TUV avdpcoTriKav TOV deiov
cessary to say that in neither case does X, make the assertion attributed
to him in the text. Thirdly it is stated that X. speaks of God at one
time in the singular, at another time in the plural. This no doubt is true,
1-20 LOOK i en. xn ,31.
p. 363 13 it is made the sign to distinguish between the esoteric and exoteric,
Ttjs /j.eif yap cmovSaias e7ri(rroAf}r6tos np^tt, 6eol fi rfjs T)TTOV) and in their
more scientific treatises, where they speak, now of the Supreme Deity
himself, now of the subordinate gods who are his agents. This distinction
appears in the same passage of the Memorabilia, ol re -yap a XXoi ij/nti/
Ttiyada di8ui>Tfs ovfief TOVTU>V ds luvra fiiSoatri, Km 6 TUV oXoi/ Tovp.<pai>fs
Pythagoras.
33 Aristoteles: cf. Krische 259 311. The treatise here referred to
isno longer extant. It is also cited by Philodemus p. 72, but unfortu
nately the fragment gives no more
than the words Trap Apto-rore Xet 6 V
rpira) n-ept
TU> ar. Diog. L. v 22 tells us it consisted of three
<ptXo<ro(pt
to have belonged to this. The 2nd book dealt with the earlier philo
sophers, including Plato; the quotation in Tusc. 68 is probably taken m
from it. The 3rd book, in which Aristotle gave his own viewr is largely ,
templation of himself, who himself unmoved has from all eternity moved
allother things by a divine attraction (Kivel coy (pvufvov, cf. Gen. et Corr. n
10 (v unao-iv d(i TOV /SfAri oros optytrai rj (Averts). Noble as this view is, it
yet presents some points of contact with the Epicurean theology, which
might have been taken advantage of, if the critic had had any other object
also Met. xn 8 it has been handed down in mythical form from ancient
times that the mover, and the world which it sets in motion, are Gods,
first
and that all nature is encircled with divinity but this high doctrine was :
of which the heaven itself and the heavenly bodies are composed, but this
is the ardor of the next clause besides, Aristotle never represents it as
:
TOV vovv dnadrj (pdaKtuv Kal dpiyfj fivai, tVftSrjrrfp KLVijcrfO)! dp\rjv O.VTOV Troitl
fivai OUTCO yap av p.6fu>s Kivoirj aKivr/Tos /cat KpaToirj
dp.iyfjs and C. 10,
u>v
<av,
TO.TU)dfov ^uptOTOv eidos, o/JU>ios n/\.ari>(, eVi/Se^Kora rfj cr(paipq TOV TravTos,
Zellcr 3
m
p. 858 foil.
retrograde movement of the planets see Met. ~s.ii 8 where Aristotle explains
:
of which Arist. says Eth. vi 7 that there are many tilings of a diviner
BOOK I CH. XIII 33. 123
ubi tot di: Heind. (followed by Sch. Opusc. in 311) thinks that, as tot
cannot apply to the four above mentioned (which in reality are only two, the
KIVOVV and Kivovftevov}, something must have been lost from the text and ;
as Arist. is said non dissantire from his master, he suggests that the lost
clausemay have corresponded with 30 quos majorum institutes accepimus.
But why may we not give the same meaning to illi tot viz. all those many
Gods of the popular religion without supposing an omission? (So Allen.)
,
The Epicurean objection would then be that these gods are supposed to
exist in heaven, but if heaven itself is God, how can one god live in
another ? If we accept
Sch. s conjecture that the lost clause referred to
the stars, the objection would merely be a repetition of caelum mundi esse
partem: they are already included in caelum, how can they be separate
and independent Gods ?
irpocrayopevei KOI Zijva Kal jrepiTrov Kal vovv, ocrrts tcrrlv aOrw Trpcaros deos rijv
St df&v diKrjv (Zeller notices that Philolaus also gave the
a)5 QrfXtlav, fj.r)Tpos
name of Rhea
to the dyad) rrjs VTTO rov ovpavov X^ecas
qyovptinjv ( presiding
over the middle region or province ) 6eov fie eii/ai /cat TUV ovpavov, KOI rovs
acrrtpas jrvpuiofis OXvfLiriOVS Oiovs, Kal IrtpOVS imoathr)vovs, 8aip.ovas dopurovs.
Some of these last were of a malignant character, <pvo-fis *v TW Trepte^ovTi
peydXas fj.fv KOI l(T%vpas, 8v(rTp6irovs 8e KO\ ffKvdpcairds (Plut. Is. et Os. ch. 26
p. 361) whose wrath had to be propitiated by sacrifices. Xen. also gave
] 24. BOOK I C1I. XIII 34.
the name of Poseidon, Dcmetcr, &c. to the divine power pervading each
element.
nulla species divina no divine form i.e. no anthropomorphic God. :
is opposed to cum alia juncta atyue conexa. The phrase mundi membra
occurs again 100.
was the principal interlocutor (as in the Tusculans). C. speaks of him with
respect as vir doctus in primis (Tusc. V. 8), and quotes from him Die. I 46
and 130. The views here ascribed to him are common to the Platonic
school. We are further told that he held with Ecphantus, the Pythagorean,
that material objects were compounded of atoms, and that the apparent
all
modo mundum turn mentem cf. 31 modo unum turn autcm plures, :
matter, such as the stars are composed of, is separately capable of feeling :
and to suppose that the moon and planets with their changing phases are
divine, is to deny the immutability of the divine nature ,
cf. Plato llcp. II
381, St James I 17 rov irarpos raiv (pcorcoi/, Trap co OVK CVL TrapaXXayrj rj rporrfjs
(inner Kiacr pa.
mvjkcit, Cic. Fin. v 9 foil. He appears to have carried further his master s
investigations upon particular points without diverging from his general
principles. C. charges him with assigning too much weight to fortune as
an element of happiness, Ac. i 34 and elsewhere. Gomperz thinks that
the words dtav, found in a fragment of Philodemus p. 73, refer
cyjco>/4i
a> TU>V
unnecessary.
signis sideribusque a pleonastic expression star-clusters (sidus)
:
head of the Lyceum B. c. 287, and changed the theism of Aristotle into a
system variously described as pantheistic or atheistic. Cudworth calls him
the first asserter of hylozoic atheism and says that while nature according ,
species 34
but, as Strato, according to Plutarch adv. Col. c. 14, denied
;
that the world was a living creature, careat sensu is probably correct in
this case. Strato s deus seems to have been much the same as Prof. Tyii-
dal s Matter containing the promise and the potency of all existence .
ch. xiv 36. The absence of any allusion to the previous criticism
of the Stoic philosophy in 18 24, just as in the parallel case of the
Platonic philosophy 30, is an instance of the carelessness which charac
terizes the composition of the whole treatise, and particularly of the present
(historical) section.
Zeno :
(Krische 358 404, Brandis in Diet, of Biog.\ He is quoted
N. D. II 57 (definition of nature), 20 (arguments to prove the rationality of
the world), also in i 70, n 63, in 18, 22, 63.
naturalem. legem. Heraclitus was the first who expressly identified
the law of nature with the word and will of God cf. Fr. 91 By water, vvov ;
oKOHTTTfp v6p.a>
TroXis KOI TTO\v lo~)(vpoTep(i)S. Tpe(povTai yap TrdvrfS ol di>0pta-
TTftOt VUJJ.OI V1TO fl>OS TOV SfLOV KpCLTffl y<lp
TOO~OVTOV UKO(TOV e$Xfl Kai f^apKffl
Trutri jcal TTtpiytvfrai. fr. 92 TOV Xoyou S eovTos vvov, u>ovai.v ol TroXXot (as
ediXfi, Zrjvos avvoptL This view, popularized by the Stoics, was passed on
by them to the Roman jurists and so to their modern successors. Thus
120 HOOK i CH. xiv 3G.
C. Lfg. I 18 lex est summa ratio insita in natura quacjubet ea quae fadenda
prohibetque conlraria ; also
sint, 42, and more explicitly n 8, the wisest
have held that law is no device of man, but that it is actcrnum quiddam
quod universum mundum rcgcret imperandi proJtibendiquc sapientia. Ita
principcm legem illam ct ultimam mentcm esse dicebant omnia ratioiie aut
cogentis aut rctantis dci ; and 110 erat enim ratio profecta a rerum natura
...quaenontum denique incipit lex esse cum scripla cst, scd turn cum orta.
orta autcm est simul cum mente divina.
cst ; Quamobrem lex vera atquc
princeps, apta ad jubendum ct ad vctandum, ratio est recta summi Jovis.
Stobaeus Ed. n 6 p. 204 gives the Greek definition (6 vofios) Aoyor opdos
tern TrpocrraKTLKo ; ptv a>i>
regarded as the common source of the natural and the moral law. Pro
bably Zeno would not have objected to a definition of God with which we
have been made familiar of late, a stream of tendency which makes for
righteousness .
eamque vim obtinere = eVpyfT, it (the law of nature) has its force in
commanding its function is to command
,
so rim habere Leg. n 9 (of law, ,
quae vis cst acqualis, coeval with illius cadum atque terras tuentis ct ,
regent is dci).
animantem. But the Stoic lays it down as the first attribute of Deity
ut sit animans T
J\ . D. n 45. The use of the abstract name Nomos is no
more inconsistent with the idea than the similar use of the of a living God,
abstract Logos. Compare the misunderstanding of the term npovoia 18.
aethera the physical, as Law is the moral manifestation of God,
:
cf. Munro on Lucr. II 646, Sch. Opusc. Ill 330 and 361. Pertinentem =
SnJKovTa as in M. Aurel. v 32 (5 fim rfjs ova-las &tr;Ka>j> Xoyor. Virgil gives it
a poetical form Gco. iv 220 foil, dcum namque ire per omnes terrasque trac- |
tusque maris caclumquc profundum, and Acn. vi 724, cf. Heinze Logos
p. 85 foil.
vi divina esse aflfectam. Sch. Opusc. in 313, doubts the correctness
of the phrase, thinking such a use of afliccre unfitted to express a natural
BOOK I CH. XIV 36. 127
attribute ;
nor is this disproved by the passages quoted by Klotz Adn. Cr.
among other extravagant conclusions drawn from the Stoic axiom all that
exists is material the statement attributed to Chrysippus that the voice
,
was a body, that qualities are bodies, nay rational creatures (Plut. Comm.
Not. 45), that diseases, vices and virtues are bodies (Seneca Epp. 106, 117,
and especially 113 animal constat animum esse. Virtus autem nihil aliud
estquam animus quodam modo se habens: ergo animal est). He quotes also
the words of Chrysippus (ap. Plut. I. c.) in which it is distinctly asserted
that night and day, the month and the year, summer and autumn, &c., are
bodies, adding that by these unfortunate expressions Chrys. appears to
have meant little more than that the realities corresponding to these names
depend on material conditions, e. g. by summer is meant the air heated by
the sun .
Scriptures in order to bring them into harmony with his own Platonism, so
the Stoics allegorized the Hellenic Scriptures (Homer and Hesiod) with the
view of hiding the divergence between their own philosophy and the
popular religion, cf. Heraclides All. Horn, proern. "Ouypos rja-efirjo-fv ei p.r/
ij\ \r]y6pr](Tfv, Orig. c. iv 48 (where Gels, says the more respectable
Cels. i 17,
Jews and Christians take refuge in allegory, being ashamed of the literal
sense of their sacred books, to which Or. replies in the following chapters),
Lobech Agl. pp. 133, 155 foil., Zeller Stoics tr. ch. 13, p. 334 foil. Plato
alludes to the allegorizing process as already rife in his time, Rep. n 378,
Phaedrus 329. For Stoic exx. see below 41 seq. n 63 scq.
usitatas perceptasque : the ordinary well-understood notions of
gods =usu perceptas n 91, Fin. v 3. See Sch. Opusc. m
314 who defends
this reading against Lambinus emendation insitas perceptasque.
neque enim appelletur neither (the actual) Jupiter nor any one
:
Schomann, reads appellatur against the best MSS. I understand the Subj.
in its limiting force cf. Madv. 364 obs. 2, Eoby ,
1692.
significatio = i57roj oia, Plato Rep. n 378, a figure of speech quae plus in
suspicione relinquit quam positum est in oratione, Herenn. iv 53, where
more is meant than meets the ear.
ground that logic was a spider s web, curious but useless, and that physics
were beyond our faculties Stob. Floril. 80, 7 irpos faus p.(v flvai ra qOtKi : t,
p.?] irpos j/p.ns ra Sia\fKri<u fjifj yap cru/J/SdXXeo pai irpus fTravopdoxrtv fBiov VTTC,)
Epicurean reporter.
Cleanthes Krische : 41."> 43f>. He is referred to JV. D. n 13, in 16
(the four grounds of religious belief) n 24 and 40 (all-pervading heat) ir (53,
none of the doctrines here mentioned are peculiar to him: one in fact is
wrongly ascribed to him. While holding with the rest of his school that
the universe was divine in virtue of the aetherial soul by which it was
animated, he placed the source and seat of aether in the sun, and not as
the others (agreeing with Aristotle) in the furthest heaven, cf. Ac. n 12(5
Zenoni ct rdiquis fere Stoicis aether videtur summus dcus, mente pracditus
qua omnia regantur ; Cleanthes, qui quasi majorum cst gentium 8t<
<-d.*,
nearly the same Hep. VI 17 novem tibi orbibus concxa sunt omnia, quorum
unus cst caelestis, extimus qui rdiquos omncs complcctitur, summus ipse dc/ .s
arcens ct continent ccteros.
quasi delirans voluptatem. The word del. is properly used of
dotage, as in Senect. 11 ista senilis stultitia quac deliratio appellari solet :
so anus dclira Div. II 141, Tusc. i 48. For the tropical use see 42.
Yell, waxes vehement as he thinks of the attack made upon the Epicureans
in Cle. s treatise ntp\ ^Sovf/s Diog. L. vii 37, 17o.
vestigia Tusc. I 61 cf. also Orator 19 and 133 (in reference to a speech of
:
Ch. xv. 38. Persaeus : see Krische 436 443. What is here said of
his opinions agrees with the account in Philodemus pp. 76 Hepa-alos 8e "75,
Madv.), Orat. I 169 quid ergo hoc fieri turpius potest quam. .ita labi; see also .
turpius, quam
praecurrere. Parallels in Greek are common.
J. S. R.] We
have had similar exx. of quod explained by a succeeding clause, 2 n.
res sordidas. The Stoics, sensible of the mischiefs which might arise
from disturbing the religious beliefs of the vulgar, endeavoured to find a
place for these in their philosophy, explaining each divinity as a separate
manifestation of the one supreme God, and getting rid, as far as they
could, of immoral or degrading superstitions by the free use of allegory. But
itwas scarcely possible to do this with the mass of the inferior deities,
Epona, Cloaciua, and others such as Augustine sums up, C. D. vi 9, and to
M. C. 9
130 BOOK r cn. xv 38.
r
which Pliny alludes A If. n 5 gcntcs vcro quacdam animalia ct aliqua .
ctiam obscena pro dis habent, ao multa dictu magis pudenda, per fetidas
ccpas, allia ct similia jurantcs.
A similar charge is made by Clemens
I 295 C (01 SrcotKoi) o-u>/j.a
ovra TOV Qeuv 8td TTJS drifioTUT^s vXqs
\tyov(nv ov KaXcov.
evai
i,
to put them among the Gods as their right ,
cf. revocct 28.
raised to the rank of Gods, must have borne exclusively the character of
6eovs vop.i^ovo-1, p.r] Gprjvf iv, tl 8e dprjvovcri, Geovs UTJ vofJLlttv (told with slight
variations by Arist. llhct. II 23) and the remarks in the First Philippic 13
on the Supplicatio to Caesar, an me censetis decreturum fuissc ut parcntalia
cum supplicationibus misccrentur ? ut incxpiabiles rdiyiones in rcm publicam
induccrentur ? ... adduci non posscm ut quemquam mortuum conjungcrem
cum immortalium rdigione ; ut cujus scpulcrum nusquam cxtet, ubi parente-
tur, ci publice supplicctur. The use of mourning garments at a supplicatio
was entirely forbidden, see Vatin. 30 foil. During the Feralia and Lemuria
the temples of the Gods were closed, Ov. Fast. II 5C3, v 491. The worship
of Zagreus, Adonis, and Osiris might fairly be described as a cultus in luctu.
39. Chrysippus :
(Krische 443
481) called the second founder of the
Stoic school, tl fjLrj yap r^vXpiKrnnros OVK av ?}v a~Tod. His importance is marked
,
by the emphatic jam vero with which the sentence begins. Philodemus says
of him (Gomp. p. 77 foil.) dXXa fj.fjv
KCU \pvcrimros [TO irav tVt Am dvacpepaiv
1
]
(V ru>
Trpcorw Ttfpl 6fu>v Am
TOV aTravra ftioiKovvra Xoyoi/ KII\ rrjv TOV
(^JJCTII/
fivat.
2
oXou \^v^tjn, KOI TTJ TOVTOV p.ev [fay TTCIVTO. f/ v ] KOI Tovt \idovs, Sio KOI Zfjva . . .
KtiXdcrBai, Aia fi on Trdinatv alrios KOI KVpios TOV re KOCT^IOV e/j.\^u^oi tivai KOI
KOI TO TJyfpoviKov Kal TI/V oXov \lsvxi]i>.
6t(>v TOJ/ Aia /cat 717^ KOIVTJV iravrov . .
(pixnv Koi flfiapftfVTjv KOI dvdymriv Ka\ T^V avrrjv dvai KOI evvofiiav KCIL biKi]v
kai opovoiav KOI flpjvrjv Kal At^poSir^f KOI TO irnpmi^rjcrinv TTO.V. KCU pr/ .vm
Bfovs apptvas p-^8f ^^Xei a?, cos n^Sf TroXftj fjLT)8 nptrds, oi>ou.d(o-Qai Se fj.6vov
1
This is tho emendation suggested in the excellent article on the Hcrcu-
lanean Fragments which appeared in the Quarterly Jicriew, Feb. 1810. German
writers who have referred to this, have attributed it to Elmslcy and others. I am
informed by tho present Editor of the Q. Ji. that it was really written by that
extraordinary man, Dr Thomas Young, and indeed it is so stated by Dean
Peacock in liis memoir.
2
Sauppe suggests pi /i?? Toi/ra diaxtwOai, comparing C. sfuswnem univcrsam.
DOCK I CH. XV 39. 131
6a\aTTt)s IlofreiScS. Kal TOUS aXXous 8e deovs o^t^ots, toy Kat TOVTOVS, crwot-
Kfiol Kal TOV rj\tov Kal TTJV (reX^ j^v Kal rovs aXXouy OOTtpas 6fovs ottrai Kal
rov vop.ov Kal dvdpatrrovs (is 6tovs (pTjai p.era/3dXXetv. ev 8e 8evTpa>
TO. re T<M
<ts
Opc/>e
a at MoticraToi/ dva<p(p6/j.eva
Kal TO. Trap O/irjpw Kal H(no6\ Kal
EtipiTTiS?/ Kal TroirjTois aXXoty, coy Kal KXeaV^s, TTfipcirai (rvvoiKfiovv TaTy
8oaty avrwv aVavrd r* eortv aldrjp, 6 avros a>v Kal irarfip Kal vios, &5y K.O.V rw
TTptoro) /xi) /ia^ecr^at TO TTJV Peav Kal /xr;r/pa TOU Aioy etVai Kal Qvyarepa. ras
8e auras Troietrai Kav TW TTepl Xapt rcoi/. Kal TOI/ At a vopov
crut OiKetwcrft?
<f>T)crlv
tivai Kal ras Xaptra? TO? ypeTepas Karap^as Kal ras oWaTroSoo-etr TUIV
1
*cal TOV HpaKXeirop o-vi oiKet&Ji [/cal P.TJV ] roi Trpcorw TI)I>
Tv6fj.fvov dfols Kal dvupcaTTois, Kal rov 7roXe^.oj/ Kal TOV Ai a TOV OUTOV etVat,
Kaddnep Kal TOV HpaxXetrov Xeyeti eV Se rai TTe/iTj-na Kal Xoyous eV^Krat
2
Travras TOV Koo~/iov fwov etVat Kal Xoytxov Kat (ppovovv Kal 6eov. Kav TOIS Trepl
irpovoias /xevrot TO? avray tKridrjcriv avvoiKficacreis rfj ^v^f) TOV Travroy Kal ra
TOJV ^ecuv dvo/Ltara c<papp.oTTfi, rfjs 8pip.vTrjTos (C. vaferrimus, cf. Wytten-
bach ac^ Plut. jRectf. Jlzic/. ^a?. p. 48) aVoXauwv aKOTrtartay. I have given
the whole passage as au illustration of the connexion between Philodemus
and the N.D. The points of agreement to be marked are (1) the citations.
In both, Chrysippus 1st book, TT. is referred to for the general statementOeu>v,
of his theology, and the 2nd book for his explanation of the old poets.
(2) As to the subject-matter, all that C. says is contained in the quotation
8, 34, with (MvOovs and Soas, Plut. u 975 E. For the use of irdvTas cf. irdtraj
Plato Rep. \ 475.
92
132 BOOK i c:r. xv 39.
aixiyKrjv. On the reading sec Seh. Opttac. ill 362 : Svvainson (Journal of
innbram is right. The scribe probably wTote naturam by error from the
line above, then made the correction rim over it, thus umbram would easily
arise. J. S. R.]
may be followed either by the Pres. Subj. as in qui vcrsctur above, or the
Impcrf. as in appcllarcnt just below see Madv. : 382 obs. 4, and exx. in n.
on 61. [Many exx. of the Imperf. are given by Motschmann Dctemporum
consccutione ap. Ciceronem, p. 11 (Jena 1875). J. S. R.] The doctrine of
the perpetual change or flux of the elements came to the Stoics from
Heraclitus, cf. N. D. ill 84, Cleomedes Ci/cl. Th. I 1 (j ovcria) ^to^vri /can/
TIIS (pvcriKcis tavTTJs nfTa(Bo\( i?, <iXXoTe
^iei/ tls rrvp xfop(i>T),
r"XXoT fie KOI eVt
KO(Tfj.oyovLav op/icocra,
and Stob. Ed. I 10. 16 TO fie irvp K(IT f^o^v trroi^eToi/
^.lyfuOaL fiia TO e avrov npcarov TCI XoiTTa crvvicrTcKrOai Kara fj.fTafBo\rjv Kai
fls avro far^aroi>
Travra ^fofifi a 8ia\vfadai r .. 7rd\iv fie OTTO TaiiTrjs (y^r)
fiiaXuo/i/j^y Kal 8ta^fOfj.fvr]s TTpwTrj fj.ei> yiyvfrai ^Oo~tf (Is dfvrtpa fie
v8a>p,
ground that the flux was confined to aquam ct aera. Krische thinks that
C. touches on this point here merely to make the whole theory more
ev S vfiari TTVf vp.a, ei> fit TOI;TW TtcivT\ dep/jLuTrjTa (//I ^t/a/i coore Tpi mov TIVU Tfcivra
,
reddi ab his cernat?} the fact that fishes hear and smell (super omnia
eum ;
est, quod auditum et odoratum piscibus non erit dubium ; ex aeris utrum-
esse
que materia). In the Times for Sept. 13, 1879 there is a short notice
of the investigations made in the Challenger and other expeditions, to
determine the amount and composition of the air in sea-water.
terrain quae Ceres cf. n 67, 71. :
leius is here dealing with the Stoic misuse of mythological names. [Cf. the
parallel passage in Ac. I 29 deum omniumque rerum, prudentiam...quam
eandem necessitatem appellant. J. S. R.]
sempiternam veritatem : cf. 55, in 14, Div. i 125 fatum id appello
quod Graeci (ip.app,fi>7]i>,
id est, ordinem seriemque causarum cum causaa
causa nexa rem ex se gignat. Ea, est ex omni aeternitate fluens veritas sempi-
terna; Zeller Stoics tr. p. 141 foil.
<jui suspicati sint : Sch. Opusc. in 310 argues against the Subj. here,
but qui is characteristic, not merely connective, though they never
dreamt of such a thing .
Ko(Tfj.ov ypd<pfi
rw
Atl TOV avrbv vrrdp^fiv TJ Trtpie^eiv TOV Ai a Kaddnep avdpanov
fyvxnv then, after describing how different names were given to different
parts of Zeus, he says that the part which was manifested in the aether was
Called Athene, roOro yap \fytcr6ai TO eVc TTJS KfpaXfjs, /cat Zevs apprjv Ztvs
eytvtff TI <ppoi>rj(TiSj
Kal A.0r]vav fiev oiov A.6prjva.v dprjcrOat) Tprram Sa fie KOI
disjungit : this form seems more suited to the metaphorical sense than
the dejungit of the MSS. Miiller Adn. Crit. p. iv. cites other passages in
1
So in the facsimile, but, as a compliment to Diog. would be quite out of
place, I should emend either /caTaxpr/oriKw? (employed by Sext. Emp. P. II. i 191
in treating of the improper uses of words)
134 BOOK i en. xv 41.
which do- is wrongly read for e/t-, e.g. degrediens N. D. u 103, dcmctata n
110, ddabi Off. n 64.
Ch. xvi. 42. The follies of the popular mythology form the subject of
the sixty pages in
first Gomp. s ed. of Philodemus. read there of the "\Ve
adulteries (pp. 10 12) and wars (pp. 28, 32, 40, 45) of the Gods, of their
frauds, cruelties, weaknesses, sufferings, their enslavements to each other
and to men. Compare Plin. J\r. II. n 7 super omncm impudcntiain cst
adultcria inter ipsos fingi, mox ctiam jurgia ct odia, atque ctiam furtorum
csse ctscclcrum numina.
ill
quids arbitrctur aut mine Christianas pJiilosophos esse aut phUosophos
fuissejam tune Christianas.
delirantium 37, 92, 94. somnia: 39, Ac. ii 121. Yarro Eumcn- :
idcs (ap. Nou. s. v. infans) postremo nemo aegrotus quicquam somniat tarn |
"Op.rjp6s
6 Hcr/oSoy Tf \
ocrcra Trap dv6f>u>Troi<Tiv
dveiftfa K<U
"^uyos
(UT LV. \
cos
( great ones ,
Sans, magha, Lat. nuignus) were the priestly caste of MeJia.
BOOK I CH. XVI 43. 135
Their religious system was the Zoroastrian dualism of the Iranian con
quering race, modified to suit the subject Turanian population. The
serpent God of the latter was identified with Ahriman, who was then
raised to an equality with Ormuzd, both being viewed as emanations from
the absolute first principle, Zerwan-Akaran, i.e. eternity. In course of
time the Magian religion incorporated many polytheistic elements, as
the worship of the Planets, of Mithras, and of Mylitta, also known as
the Phrygian mother of the Gods. The religion of the Persians was pure
Zoroastrianism and, as such, opposed to Magianism, as is shown in the
overthrow of the Magi by Darius Hystaspes ; but it was confounded with
the latter by Herodotus and other writers. See Lenormant Manual of
Ancient History, tr. n 21 47 ; Rawlinson s Herodotus I Essay 5, on the
Religion of the Ancient Persians Hardwick, Christ and other Masters, Pt. IV.
;
dite, Fire, Earth, Winds and Water. On the Egyptian religion, see 101,
Juvenal Sat. xv, Herodotus II 37 76 with Rawlinson s notes and Append.
ch. 3, also Hardwick and Lenormant.
veritatis ignoratione : causal ablative, cf. 1.
qui consideret debeat whoever (=if any one) should consider this
:
would be bound to pay honour to Ep. and hold him as a God On the .
hypothetical use of qui with Subj. see Madv. 367, who quotes N. D n 12
haec qui videat, nonne cogatur confitcri deos esse ? (repeated almost in the
same words 44), also Draeg. 493 and Roby 1558. On the extravagant
terms in which the Epicureans spoke of their founder see Tusc. I 48 quae
quidem cogitans soleo saepe mirari nonnullorum insolentiam philosophorum,
qui naturae cognitioncm admirantur, ejusque inventori ct principi gratias
cxultantes agunt eumque venerantur ut deum, liberatos enim se per cum
dicunt gravissimis dominis, terrore sempiterno et diurno ac nocturno metu ;
Fin. I 14, 32, 71 ;
In Pis. 59 ;
Lucr. v 8 deus ille fuit, deus, inclute
Memmi, qui princcps vitae rationem invcnit cam quae nunc appellatur
\ \
sapient ia; and in 15 nam simul ac ratio tua coepit vocifcrari naturam I
136 BOOK I CH. XVI 43.
rcrum, divina mcnte coorta, \ diffugiunt animi terrores ; Pint. adv. Colot. 17
(Metrodorus speaks of) T ErriKovpou coy <iX?;dco? deufpavra upyia ; ib. Colotcs
kneels and adores Epicurus Epic, himself writes to a disciple irt^-m ovv ;
to his memory, not only his birthday, but the 20th day of every month, in
accordance with the instructions in his will, Diog. L. x 18, Fin. n 101,
Zeller Stoin tr. p. 394.
primum esse deos : the 2nd point is given below, ut dcos bcatos ct i/n-
mortalcs putcmns.
in animis impressisset : this is the usual construction, like imculpsit
in mcntibus just below, but we find imprim. with Ace. in Ac. II 58.
quae est enim gens universal belief was alleged by the Stoics, no less
:
than by the Epicureans, as the strongest proof of the existence of the Gods,
see II 5, 12, Seneca Ep. 117 6 multum dare solcmus pracsumptioni omnium
hominum: apud nos argumcntum veritatis est aliquid omnibus vidcri: tan-
quam deos esse inter alia dis opinio insita
sic colligimus, quod omnibus de
est,nee ulla yens usquam est adeo extra leges moresque projccta, ut non aliquos
deos crcdat; and so of the immortality of the soul. It is often urged by C.
as in Leg. I 24 nulla gens neque tarn mansueta, ncque tarn fcra, quae non,
etiamsi ignorct qualem habcre dcum deceat, tamcn habcndum sciat; Tusc. I 30
multi de dis prava sentiunt ; id enim vitioso more effici solet ; omncs tamen
esse vim ct naturam divinam arbitrantur...omni autem in re consensio om
nium gentium lex naturae putanda est ; and by Pint, adv. Colot. 1125 D.
The same argument is employed in defence of divination Div. ill, and met
in the following book (n 39) by a reference to the universality of the desire
for pleasure as the chief good, quasi i-cro quicquam sit tarn valde quam nihil
sapcre vulyare! Cf. the objections in ^V. D. I (!2, in 11. Aristotle con
the justification is given Hth. End. I G /cpdncrroj/ pfv Ttdvras avflpamovs 0ru-
i>a6ai
avvop.oXoyovi Tas rots pridrjirop.d ois, fl 8f /J.TJ, rponov ye nva Trdj/roj, uTTfp
fjLfTaflifia^o^voi TTOi^Voucrti/ f%fi yap fKnarros oieldf n Trpos TTJV aXyOfiav ...
fK yap T(i>v
uXrjdus fJ.iv Xeyo/xeYcoi ,
ou traf/)cos ^/, Trpoioixriv tdrai KO\ TO (rancor,
religious ideas), and the very fair and able discussion in Jellett a Efficacy of
Prayer p. 70 foil, and App. on General Consent. The analogous ecclesiasti
cal doctrine formularized by Vincent of Lerins in the words quod ubiquc,
quod semper, quod ab omnibus creditum est, or in the more sounding phrase
of Augustine securus judicat orbis terrarum, is of far more doubtful value,
as it refers not to the primitive instincts of mankind, but to abstract
uttering the word man, the type at once rises up Kara (i. e. prior irp6\T)\lsLi>
ovn {rjTflv ovre airopfiv avtv Tvpo\rjt\ffa>y Sext. Enip. Math. I 57 (sine qua...
potest), cf. Clem. Al. Strom, n 157. Chrysippus appears to have borrowed
the word from Ep. (see 54), defining it as cvvoia fyvaiKr) raw Ka66\ov
Diog. L. vn 54. In an interesting chapter of Epictetus (Diss. I 22) we read
that 7rpo\il\l/fis, general principles, are common to all men, and consistent
with each other differences arise when we attempt to apply them, e.g. all
:
Clem. 1.
c.} it was identified with Faith. Besides the terms informatio,
praenotio and anticipatio, C. uses for it notio and notitia, which are properly
equivalents of the more general Woia, cf. Ac. II 30 notitiae rerum quas
Graeci turn eWoi a? turn TrpoX^ety vacant ; Tusc. I 57 (of the Platonic
doctrine of reminiscence) nee fieri ullo modo posse ut a,
pueris tot rerum atque
tantarum animis notiones, quas evvolas vacant,
insitas et quasi consignatas in
informatio :
shaping ,
outline ,
then conception .
locutio hominum effecit, non institutis opinio est confirmata, non legibus, i. e.
01; I/O/KB dXXa (piio-ei. So Philod. p. 128 (we worship the Gods) ou p6vov
8ia TOVS vopovs dXXa 8ia (pvcriKay airiaj, Diog. L. X 123 $eo! jj.ev yap dcriv
evapyrjy p,ev yap ftniv aiiruiv 77 yvuxris*
ad unum omnium all without exception : .
ing syllogism We all : have from nature an idea of Gods what all men s :
quod beatum essent omnia: quoted from the Kvpiai &om, an epitome
of the ethical principles of Epicurus, which he intended to be committed
to memory by his disciples, see 85, fin. II 20 quis cnim vest rum non
cdidicit Epicuri Kvpias Soaj 1 Diog. L. x 35. It is preserved by Diog.
x 139, and commences with the words here translated TO paKapiov KOI
u(pdaprov ovre avro TT
paypara ?x fl ^ rf uAAfi) Trape^ei, cScrre ovrf opynls ovre
>
^aptcrt owfxerat tv arrdevd yap irav TO TOIOVTOV, cf. Philod. p. 123 xajpi?
cpyfjs Kal xpiro? da-devova-rjs, Lucr. II G46 omnis cnim per so divom natura
ncccsscst immortali aevo summa cum pace fruatur scmota ab nostris rebus
\ \
scjunctaque longe ; \
nam
privata dolore omni, privata pcriclis ipsa suia \
pollens opibiis, nihil indiga nostri, ncc bene promcritis capitur, ncque tan-
\
gitur.ira. The argument in full is the Gods are happy happiness con
:
;
upon another ; therefore the Gods neither feel nor cause trouble ; hence
the motive of anger, which might lead to their infliction of trouble, and the
motive of favour, which might lead to their taking trouble for others, are
alike manifestations of weakness, and inconsistent with our idea of the
Divine majesty. The answer to which is that (1) the word trouble is
unmeaning in reference to our idea of God : if we suppose him to bo
(2) while it is true that passion and caprice are marks of weakness and, a,s
good and powerful God. When Seneca says dcos nemo sanus timct (Dcnef.
iv 19) it is not from any notion of the Gods being indifferent to the actions
of men, but he is simply asserting the Platonic doctrine that God never
harms any (Rep. u 379 foil.), that His acting is always for the best both to
the universe at large and to each individual in it. In Philod. p. 94 we read
that it was charged against the Epicureans, that their doctrine deprived good
men of their religious hopes, TrpocrfnKJifpovcriv Se /cat Start dyaduiv Kal TU>V
Epicureans) :
p. 124 /cat cra>T^ptaf dvdpunrois 8id TOV deov KaraXeiTJTeoi/ imo-
ypucpet (i.e. Epidurus) 8id irXeiovwv, ei> de T<O
rptcncatSe/ccrna Trept rfjs oiKfioTr]-
TOS r)v Trpos nvas 6 deos e^et Kal rrjs aXXorptor^Toy :
p. 125 with the favour
of heaven (6fu>v
l\tav O J/TCO>)
we need not fear war, with the favour of
heaven w e shall pass our
r
lives in purity :
pp. 86 89 the Stoics deny that
the Gods are the authors of evil to men and thus take away all restraint on
iniquity and degrade men to the level of the brutes (for who would be
balked of the injustice for which he craves, from the fear of air or aether ?),
while we say that punishment comes to some from the Gods, and the
greatest of good to others also p. 145. It is difficult to see how this
:
approach to the common opinion (which goes much beyond what Lucr.
allows vi 70) can be reconciled with other positive statements of Epicurus
or with his general principles as given in the text. See the Academic,
or rather Stoic, criticism in 121. For the form of expression (nee habera
ipsum nee exhibere alteri] we may compare St James I 13 d yap 6tos aTrei-
paaTos eari KaKaii , Tretpa^et Se airos ou SeVa, Plut. Mor. 1102 E Kal (pavXov
oi/ Sef Trotfti aurw De Ira, II 27 natura Hits
dtpis, (Scnrtp ov8e Trda^tiv, Sen.
(dis) mitis et placida est, tarn longe remota ab aliena injuria quam a sua.
sit essent essent the Pres. Subj. is allowable because it is a general
:
proposition having no more reference to the past than to the present : the
Imperf. is afterwards used in order to remind the reader that this a is
statement made in the past by Epic., not necessarily adopted by the writer ;
see Dracger 131, and (on the mixed construction) 124 B c, where it is
pointed out that when there are two subordinate clauses, standing in
different degrees of subordination, the more remote subordination is fre
quently expressed by the Imperf. the less remote by the Pres. Subj. Com
pare for the corresponding use of the Subj. and Opt. in Greek, Jelf 809,
Arnold on Thuc. in 22, p. 370.
talia imbccilla : Seneca De Ira i 20 ira muliebre maxime ct
puerile
vitium cst, Juv. xin 190 with Mayor s u.
140 BOOK I en. xvii 45.
si nih.il erat dictum : if \vc had had no other aim beyond that of
piety in worship and freedom from superstition, we might have ended
here On the Ind. in npodosi see 19 tonyum cst, n.
.
cum aeterna esset wo need not (with Dracg. 151. 3) explain the
:
the way in which the Romans supplied the absence of a Pass., and com
pares Orat. Ill 11, Phil. I 7, Marcell. 26. [cf. aivdrjcnv Tvapf\fi.v
which
is the regular passive of ala-6dvfcr6ai. J. S. R.] Sch. in his note cites other
phrases in which habeo has the same force, e.g. lactitiam, spem, timorcm
habcre to inspire like the Gr. ex flv== Ta P*X flv
,
On the grounds of the -
Epicurean worship cf. 56 and 116, and Philod. 128 Trpoo-ev^eo-^at yap tv
TOO TTf/n (prjCTtV, ov% ws \viroiifj.evri)i> rasv
6e<av fi fj.rj TroirjcTQ^fv, dXXa Kara Gfu>v
Defective as was the Epicurean conception of God, it was so far right that
they could see in Him an ideal perfection worthy of the reverence and
imitation of men, see Zeller Stoics tr. p. 439, Philod. p. 148.
metus a vi cf. 42 concubitus cum gcnore. Allen quotes Liv.
: xxm 15
mctus a praetore, where see Weissenborn, also Madv. 298. 2, on verbal
substantives followed by prepositions. The verbs timco and mctuo are used
absolutely with ab.
quibus impendere : on the Inf. with relative in Orat. Obi. see n. on
12 ex quo cxsistit.
occurrit. For exx. of such appearances see Ov. Met. vin 626 foil.,
Liv. xxi 62, xxiv 10, Dion. Hal. A. E. n 68, Niigclsb. X. Theol. p. 2,
and nn. on Acts xiv 11. Celsus up. Or. vn 35 says that in the sanc
tuaries of Amphiaraus, Mopsus, and Trophonius avdptoTrodftfls Geupiicrdai.
6fovs, ov \ls(v8op.(i>ovs dXAa Kat tVapyeis-, and (in 24) that there were many
living in his time to whom Asclepius had appeared, and granted healing ;
again (vin 45) all life is full of such divine manifestations Cf. also 36, .
II 6 sacpe voces cxauditae, saepe visae fonnae deorum, 166, and Lucr.
V 1161 nunc causa deum per magnas numina gcntcs pcrculyarit
<juae |
ct ararum complement urbcs, ...non ita difficile cst rationem rcddcre ver-
\
bis. quippe etenim jam turn divom mortalia saecla cgrcgias animo fades
| |
umbras inter vivos volitare , and in 722 foil, he shows how such simulacra
\
may arise spontaneously in the air. It seems therefore that these images
can only be trusted in so far as they are supported by abstract reasoning.
Compare also Sext. Emp. Math, ix 25 (quoted by Munro) ETrixovpos Se tic
riov Kara TOVS VTTVOVS (f>avTao~ia>v
oierai TOVS dvdpanrovs tvvoiav f&naKfvai dfov
fj.fya\a>v yap fl8co\cov, (prjcri, Kal dvdpcorrofJiopcpoov Kara TOVS VTTVOVS rrpocnvnrTov-
ra>v
\nrf\aftov *cat rats dXrjdeiais virapxfiv rivas TOLOVTOVS 6eovs avdpunrofiop-
(povs. The
Stoic Balbus is in agreement with Epic, on this point ; and
Aristotle (quoted by Sextus 1. c.) made these appearances one of the two
causes to which he traces the origin of religion, dn-o 8volv dpx&v ewoiav 6ea>v
pa>v,
the former owing to TOVS fv rois VITVOIS yiyvop-fvovs ravrrjs evdovo-iacrnovs
1
Kal ras jUiVTttas orav yi ip, (frrjcriv, tv rw VTTVOVV Kaff eavr?)V yevrjrai rj ;
X V" ?>
uvQpanroi eivai TI 6eov ro Kaff eavrov toiKos rfj ^Isvxfj Ka\ navruiv eVicrT^/ioviKQ)-
we must explain the causal clauses vel quia and cum et aeterna by a reference
to praestans.
modo hoc, modo illud: so (Tusc. v 33) when charged with contradicting
what he had said in the De Finibus, C. replies in diem vivimus; quodcumque
nostros animos pcrcussit, id dicimus, itaquc soli sumus libcri, cf. Alt. xm 25
Academiam volaticam ac sui similem, modo hue modo illuc, also Die. I
62; and, of the Socratic irony, Lad. 13 qui non turn hoc turn illud, itt in
plcrisque, scd idem semper. [Add Ac. II 121, 134, Tusc. I 40, Att. II 15,
Parad. 14, Die. I 120, n 145. J. S. 11.] For omission of verb, see 17 n.
ratio hominis figura: cf. <a\ d Aoyicr^oi OVK fx n ilfv *v "XX?; MP0, /
^ Xn
TTJS dv6p(a7rov, (fravepuv cos teat TOV 0eoi>
ayppcoTro^op^oj/ ^pr) KaraAe intiv Iva crvv
2 p. 21 (conjecturally assigned
Xoyto-^o rr)v imovTaviv f\rj Vol. Here, vi pt.
to Metrodorus). Here as elsewhere the Epicurean refused to go beyond
his own experience :
l
numquam vidi ( 87) thought apart from a human
body , or as it would now be worded, apart from brain .
specie suntet colore tauri, and Liv. xxi 62 quoted below under nee soliditate.
This arg. is criticized in 89.
49. quasi corpus like the el SwXa of Homer and the ghosts of later
:
sec the passages quoted in n. on intermundia 18, and the criticism by Cotta
in 71, 75, by Balbus in II 59. Hirzel (p. 77 foil.) thinks that C. con
founded the images which reveal the Gods to us with the actual Gods and ;
that the latter had more approach to substance than he allows them, as
Philodemus (quoted by Zeller Stoics tr. p. 441) speaks of their taking food,
and conversing together probably in Greek, cf. also Sch. Opusc. iv 336
359. The subject is discussed below. For the expression cf. Sen. Contr.
II 12 11 quasi dissertus es, quasi formonsus cs, quasi dives cs; unum tan-
turn es non quasi, vappa (quoted in Roby 1583), PL Stick. 552 foil., Plin.
Ep. vin 16 quasi testamcnta, quasi cioitas, and the legal fictions quasi pos-
scssio, quasi pignus &c.
Ch. xix. quivis = o rvx^v, every one .
qualia sint possumus suspicari, sic adfirmat ut oculis ca ccrnere videatur aut
tractare plane manu; Brut. 277 cum indicia mortis so comjwrisse ct manu
BOOK I cn. xix 49. 143
dccet earn esse vim aeterna. This extremely difficult passage has
been discussed by many writers, esp. by Sch. Opusc. in 315 l , and Neue
Jahrb. for 1875 pp. 687 691, as well as in the notes and app. to his ed. ;
lehrt die Natur der Gotter sei der Art, dass sie erstens nicht mit den
Sinneu, sondern nur mit dem Geiste erfasst wird, und dass sie ausserdem
weder Soliditat noch individuelle Identitat besitzt, wie die sogenannten
vielmehr gelangten wir zur Erkenntniss des Gottlichen (denn das
a-TfpffjLvia ;
besagen die Worte quae sit et beata natura et aeterna) durch Bilder, die
wir wahrnehmen &c. I had long taken the same view of the construc
tion of capere, and of the needlessness of Sch. s emendations cernantur,
cumque, beatae naturae. The clue to the right interpretation is to be found
(1) in 105, where the account here given is criticized by Cotta, and (2) in
Diog. L. X 139 ev aXXots 8e (prjai rovs 6fovs Xoyw dfuprjrovs, ovs p.ev KO.T
dpi6p.ov w^ecTTcorar, ovs Be *a$ op.ofi.8iav (K rfjs crvvexovs (nippvcrtcas TUIV
ofJLoicaif fl8a\cov eVi TO avTo aTroTCTfXfO p.fVtoV dt>$pco7roeiSa>s.
Philodemus
seems to have treated of the subject in his Trepi cvovjScuw, but unfortu
nately the passages relating to it are too corrupt to afford much help.
See p. 110 8vvaTai yap <
T)
TU>V
op.oiu>v aroi\fl(f>v fvoTr/rfs aTroreXflcr^at bvvavrai. Gomperz despairs
of the passage (see his n. dieser mir zum kleinsten Theil verstandlichen
Columne ,) but it would appear to be a comparison between our ordinary
modes of perception and the mode in which we arrive at a consciousness of
deity just as in the next page it is said if opponents charge Epicurus
;
with denying the existence of the Gods, why might they not on the same
ground charge him with denying the existence of horses and men, Kal -na.v&
aTrXwr TO Kara p.epos alfrdrjTa. re Kal vor^-ra. (pvcreutv f i8r) ? The same subject is
discussed in pp. 132 138, but only occasional phrases are legible, as rf)v
KUT dpi.6p.bv vi/yKpicriv (C. s ad numerum) in pp. 134 and 138, p,ijre yap
p.r)re uvvBtrovs p. 136, apparently an exhaustive
drop-ovs vofjiifiv TOVS 6foiis
argument to prove the atheism of Ep. his Gods are neither atoms nor
compounds of atoms, and what other entities are admitted by him ?
non sensu sed mente cernatur cf. Lucretius quoted on quasi corpus, :
and 105 speciem dei percipi cogitatione non sensu. Sch. points out that
while L. speaks of the tennis natura and Cotta of the species, both referring
only to the fine etherial body of the Gods, Veil, speaks more generally of
vis et natura. This is because he is about to refer, not merely to the
1
He calls it locum omnium difficillimum crtjus ccrtam omnibusque numeris
absolutam interpretationem vix quisquam, ego certe 7wc tempore proponcre non
possum.
144 BOOK I CTI. XIX 49.
immediate sensuous impression produced on the mind when its fine atoms
are struck by the cognate atoms which constitute the divine imagines,
atoms which pass unperceived through the coarser sieve of the bodily
senses, but also to the conception of blessedness and immortality to which
the mind attains by reflecting upon the impressions it has received. It is
the latter process which is properly expressed by cogitatio.
nee soliditate appellat. At first sight it seems natural to take sol. as
an abl. of cause after cematurand so Sch. explains it by a reference to
;
the distinction between the imagines thrown off from solid bodies (the o-re-
pffivia), which imagines are described in Diog. L. x 40 as diroppotat TTJV (rjs
6e(Tiv KOI ra;.i/ Starr^povcrai, ffVTTfp KCIL tv rolt ffTfpffivtoiS (?X OV anc^
>
a fi ncr
class of imagineswhich reveal to us the shadowy form of the Gods. The
expression would not be quite accurate, for even the finest images must in
the end consist of atoms (since all that exists is summed up under atoms
and void, according to Epic.) and solid itas is essential to atoms of every
kind; still in popular language (quadam = ut ita dicam) it might be said
that the images perceived by the bodily senses were perceived in virtue
of a massiveness which was not shared by the images which were per
ceptible by the mind alone. The objections to this interpretation are
(1) that it really addsnothing to what has been already said in the
previous clause, though apparently contrasted with it by the word primum,
(2) that it is difficult to connect it with what follows, (3) that it is incon
sistent with the words of 105 nee csse in ea (specie) ullam soliditatem,
neque eandem ad numerum pcrmanere, in which the absence of solid itas is
predicated of the divine form itself, not of the image, as distinguished from
the form, in virtue of which negative property the image is perceived in a
particular way. Accordingly Peter (Commentatio de N. D. Saarbrlicken 1801)
and Hirzel take soliditate quadam as a predicative Abl. of quality, of which
the former cites several exx. (Ar D. I 12 veris falsa adjuncta lanta similitu-
.
Abl. with cernatur, and I think it possible that sit may have been lost after
numerum before ut. The term o-Ttptnviov occurs repeatedly in the frag
ments of Epic. TTfpl (f>v<Tfa>s
and in his Epistle to Herodotus preserved in
Diog. L. x.
We come now to the more difficult ad numerum, which must evidently
BOOK I CH. XIX 49. 14<5
ev or ravrbv /car eiSos the same in kind see Arist. Met. IV p. 101 6 b, ,
Whately s Logic App. (on the ambiguity of the word same ). But will KUT
apidfjiov carry this meaning by itself? For proof of this Hirzel refers to
Bonitz s Index Aristotelicus s. v. api$/xoy, see particularly Anal. Post. I c. 5,
p. 74 where the phrase KOT dpidpov is used of argument which applies only
to a single individual triangle, as opposed to proper geometrical reasoning
which deals with the triangle, qua triangle, universally. Similarly we have
icarapid^ov i50eoT<uruy in the passage already quoted from Diog. L. It
isimpossible however to suppose that ad numerum standing alone could
convey this meaning to a Roman ; and though it is conceivable that C.
may have put an unmeaning phrase into the mouth of the Epicurean advo
cate, it seems hardly credible that he should, without remark, have
supplied the interpretation afterwards through the mouth of the Academic
critic. I believe therefore that eadem has been lost between neque and ad.
and that the true reading is neque eadem ad numerum sit. I postpone to
the end of the paragraph the question, how we are to conceive of Gods not
l
possessed of personal identity or individual existence [Soliditate cannot .
fj.ivu>v dvdpanrofiSus ;
Lucr. v 1175 (men attributed to the Gods) aeternam
vitam quia semper eorum | suppeditabatur fades et
forma manebat |
. Com-
A. Becker (Comm. Crit. 1865) gives a careful analysis of the passage and
1
M. C. 10
BOOK I CH. XIX 49.
pare also the very similar language used of perception and images gene
X 48 ptvcris CJTTO rcav crw/j.arcoi TOV fTrnrd\fjs (TVV(\T]S trvfifiaivft
rally, Diog. L.
OVK tiri8n\os aladijtrfL Sta TTJV avravanX^pcocnv, Lucr. IV 26 foil. csp. 87 out
lines of shapes about so exquisitely fine as each by itself to be invisible
flit ,
104, 256 the things themselves are seen, though the images which strike
the eye are invisible 190 the images succeed one another like the rays of
,
light suppeditatur enim confestim lumine lumen, 714 (accounting for the
",
cularum ut possit suppeditare; and see the passages quoted from Philodemus
under docct cam esso vim. From these it would appear that the phrase
must mean when the images have become perceptible through their mutual
similarity and their uninterrupted succession Any one image would be .
too fine to attract the attention, but the repetition of similar images ever
hand transitio, lit. the passing before the eyes (as in Ovid Rcm. Am. 615
vnidtaque corporibus transitione nocenf) appears to me to be a translation of the
Gr. not (as Hirzel takes it) of avravaTr^puxris which is rather suppe-
<j)<>pd,
produced by the imagines (cf. 107 fac imagines csse .. .species dumtaxat
objicitur; Die.n 137 nulla species cogitari potest nisi pulsu imaginum; Fat.
43 visum objectum imprimit ct quasi signat in animo suam speciem} so that
I should have been inclined to keep the old reading, translating there
rises up a never-ending impression of exactly similar images produced
from countless atoms were it not for the following affluat, which is very
,
suitably used of the series imaginum flowing in upon the mind (cf. Div.
I.
c.}, less suitably of the species which springs up within the mind
but
itself asa result of the inflowing imagines. Still we have fluentium
visionum 109 where see n.
ex individuis so 110 effigies ex individuis corporibus oritur. The
:
images were composed either of the surface atoms of the (rrepepviov (Lucr.
IV 67 praescrtim cum sint in summis corpora rebus multa minuta jaci
quae possint ordine eodem quo fuerint at formal servare figuram) or of loose
\
ad nos: the MSS read ad deos which makes no sense possibly it is due 1
;
Comparing this with the parallel passage from Diog. L. w e shall see that,
r
2
supposing the latter to be correct C. here confines his attention to
,
the second class of Gods there mentioned, i.e. Gods who exist for us in
1
A writer in the Rev. de Philologie for 1877, p. 264 keeps the reading
ad and explains as follows. The atoms flow together vers le point ou ils
deos
constituent eux-memes par leur passage continue 1 existence des dieux...Les
images qui se detachent sans cesse des dieux, apres avoir forme un instant les
dieux eux-memes, sont bien celles qui se rendent ensuite vers nous, et qui nous
font connaitre.
2
Sch. altogether objects to the supposition of there being two classes of
Epicurean gods, and would accordingly change ous /uec, ois 5, reading ov ^v
(Gassendi s unsatisfactory suggestion) KOLT i>0rrcDTas, yvucrrovs KaO
api0fj.oi>
5<r
6/j.o(i5iav fK TIJS ffvvexovs eTrippvveus K.T.\. I see no reason for doubting the
genuineness of the passage. It simply asserts in definite, terms the conclusion
which an attentive consideration of C. s language forces on the reader, viz. that
there were two distinct systems of theology recognized in the Epicurean school,
one of a more esoteric nature, taken mainly from their great authority Demo-
critus, the other more suited to the popular belief; which two systems have been
not unnaturally confounded together by C.
102
148 BOOK I CH. XIX 49.
infinite whole that parts are exactly balanced one against the
all its
<$>v<Tis
Tracri, and the equilibrium of positive and
dncuTd rfjv Icrovo^Lav eV
and Empedocles cf. too Plato Theaet. 176 on the necessary existence of
;
perpetuo possunt servare creata. Since on the whole the destructive and
conservative forces are equal, and since the destructive prevail here, there
must be elsewhere a region where the conservative forces prevail, and what
can this be but the intermundia ? And, since mortals and immortals
are equally balanced, and here experience shows that all is mortal, where
can we find these immortal beings but in the Gods? In II 1105 foil.
Lucr. describes how a world gradually grows up under the shaping blows
of the atoms, and then how, when it has once attained maturity, the
destructive movements gain the upper hand, the constituent atoms fly
apart, the external blows no longer weld the mass together, but break
it
down in ruin, a process of which, he says, we may already see the beginning
in our earth. It is unkind to touch the card-castle of the Epicurean
philosophy, or one might be disposed to ask why there might not be suffi
cient employment for the conservative forces in the constant building up
of new worlds as the old ones perish, without finding a special seat for them
in the intermundia ; and how these auctiftci motus are to show themselves
in a place sacred from the intrusion of atoms.
et quaerere proceeding to a new topic : and then ,
so 100 et eos
vituperabas.
150 BOOK I CH. XIX 50.
Oral.I 160 quid cst? Cotta, quid tacetis? On the general question of the
mixture of Sing, and PL see below, deorum and Us followed by ay it, and so
frequently in speaking of the Gods, e.g., 101 deorum habct, 106, 114
(vacant cogitat], cf. 31 11. Madv. Fin. II 22 Davies in loc. gives illustrations :
51. nih.il agit. See Cotta s answer to this 110, 114, 116, also
Seneca Bcnef. iv 4 quae maxima Epicuro felicitas videtur, nihil ayit, Diog.
L. X 97 ?)
6fia (pvcris Trpos ravra fj.T)8apf] TrpocrayfcrBco tzXX aXfirovpyrjTos
(vacatione munerum below) Siar^peiVtfa) xai tv 770077 ^nKapia. That the
divine happiness consisted in self-contemplation was asserted by Aristotle
Met. xii 1072 b. see n. on 33. In accordance with this belief the wise
man of Epicurus withdrew as far as possible from public life (Zeller Stoics
p. 403).
nisi quietum nihil beaturn Ep. held that happiness consisted mainly
:
vicissitudines ordinesque :
hendiadys = r/c. ordinatas\ Sch.
ne ille est implicatus. Cf. n 1 ne eyo incautus. In Cicero s writings
ne is always followed immediately by a pronoun, and it usually occurs in
the clause of comparison and the principal clause, by the attraction of the
verb of the former into the construction of the latter the converse attrac :
tion is more common in Greek, esp. with ov\ ucnrep. In this way a
simile passes into a metaphor, as in Hor. Ep. I 10. 42 quoted by Sch. ; cf.
tive, Eoby 1302, Draeger 202. For the thought compare Lucr. I 958 foil.,
esp. 980 oras ubicunque locaris extremas, quaeram quid telo denique fiat. \ \
Fiet uti nusquam possit consistere finis \ cffugiumque fugae prolatet copia
semper ; also 1. \
72 and Fin. 11 102.
vis atomorum : so v. serpentium 101, v. auri Tusc. v 91, v. ranun-
culorum Fam. vn 18, v. lacrimarum Rep. vi 14. Cf. the Irishism a
power of ,
and the Fr. force .
quis non timeat : cf. Acad. n 121 (of Stnvto who explained the origin
of the world from natural causes) ne ille et deum opere magno liberat et me
timore. Quis enimpotest, cum existimet curari se a deo, non et dies et noctes
divinum numcn horrere et, si quid adversi accident quod cui non accidit ?
extimescere ne id jure evenerit ? To remove this fear was the professed
object of the Epicurean philosophy, as Ep. himself says in Diog. L. x 112
at nfpl TWV fj.erf(apa>v viro\l/iai T^yco^Xovi feat at Trept ffavdrov,
ft p.rjd(f rjfj.as
putare alicnaque pads eorum, delibata deum per te tibi numina sancta
\ \
saepe oberunt, and compare Div. n 105 negant id esse alienum majestate
deorum. Scilicet casas omnium introspicere, ut videant quid cuique con-
ducat, and 129 deosne immortales, rerum omnium praestantia excdlentes,
concursare circum omnium mortalium non modo lectos, verum etiam grabatos,
et cum
stertentem aliquem mderint, objicere us visa quacdam tortuosa et
obscura? Plin. N. II. II 5 irridendum vero agere curam rerum humanarum
illud quidquid est summum. Anne tarn tristi atque multiplier ministerio
non pollui credamus dubitemusve?
55. The Stoic doctrine of necessity was the
hinc vobis exstitit.
direct consequence Stoic pantheism. The divine force, which
of the
governs the world, could not be the absolute uniting cause of all things, if
there existed anything in any sense independent of it Zeller Stoics tr. ,
p. 166. Fate is nothing but the will of God, which reveals itself as the
reason and law of the universe, cf. 40 n.
primum taken up by sequitur fj.avTiK.rj below.
:
aeterna veritate. That which is fated always has, is, and will be
true, see Aristoclcs ap. Euseb. Pr, Ev. XV 14 rfjv fie TOVTVV (things past,
present and future) fVin-XoKiji/ *ai aKoXovdiav KOL d[i.appVT)v KU\ imoTJiujf KOI
dXrjdeiav KOI vu^ov tlvai TCOI/ OVTUV ddiadpacrTov Tiva (cat afyvnTov, Stob. Eel.
I De Fato 17, 29, 37.
180, Cic.
causarum continuatione = ftp/Lioj ainwj (as Chrysippus defined flpap-
p-fvrj, Pint. PI. Ph. 885 B) the chain of causation , see Heinze Logos
p. 125 foil.
[cf. Ac. I 29 continuationem ordinis sempiterni, Fat. 19, Div. I
125 and 127, Tac. Ann. vi 22 nexum naturalium causarum. J. S. R.]
aniculis the stock example of credulity and superstition both among
:
sequitur :
opp. to exstitit primum.
qua tanta colendi through which, if we had been willing to listen
:
Vanicek) foretold the future from the appearance of the entrails in sacri
fices and from the phenomena of nature aug. from the appearance and
;
movements of animals, esp. from the flight of birds. These two were
regarded as scientific modes of divination, in contradistinction to the un
scientific, uttered fi.aivop.fvq> oro/xari, such as the Sibylline prophecies, and
hariolorum et vatum (on this word see Munro Liter, i 102) furibundas prae-
dictiones,and dreams, cf. Div. I 3, and Marquardt Rom. Staatsv. in pp. 90,
393 foil. On the meaning and etymology of the word superstitio see II 72 n.
si vos audire vellemus. The Stoics strongly maintained the truth of
divination, and urged the fact of its existence as one proof of the existence
of the Gods, quorum enim interpretes sunt, eos ipsos esse certe necesse est.
C. argues against them in his treatise on the subject.
56. his terroribus soluti see n. on 54 quis non timeat and Zeller
:
Stoics tr. p. 399. Cotta charges Ep. with imputing his own fears to others,
86.
in libertatem vindicati claimed for freedom
: cf. Liv. ,
m 45 fin. ;
atqui :
nay .
te audierunt cum diccres ; for the use of de, Brut. 100 audivi de majoribus,
and Draeg. 286. 2 for the postponement of the cum- clause, see Roby
;
BOOK I CH. XXI 58. 155
1722, and for its use as a secondary predicate 1724, also Draeger 498,
who says that it is usually preceded by saepe, as in Fin. v 54, De Orat.
II 22, 144, 155. [His exx. are confined to C., add Virg. Aen. in 623 mdi
egomet cumfrangeret. R]
sine dubio. On the substantival use of the Neuter Adj. with prep, see
Nag. Stil. 21, Draeg. 23 foil.
dilucide, copiose. Similar compliments are paid to the speaker in
Fin. iv 1, 7, Ac. I 43, II 63. As Zeno is praised for the same merits below,
and is
equally censured for asperity in 93, it has been supposed that C.
intended Veil, to represent Zeno.
quam solent vestri sc. dicere understood from dictum est. Epic, was
:
Latin form does not seem to occur elsewhere in the Classical writers.
cum Athenis essem. Though C. introduces himself to us at the
beginning as an impartial auditor ( 17) and though at the end (in 95) he
says that his sympathies are more with Balbus than with Cotta, yet it is to
the latter that he ascribes his personal experiences both here and in 79,
93. So we learn from Att. xin 19 that he had some thought of trans
ferring to Cotta his own part in the Academica.
audiebam attended lectures
: .
theology.
quid non dixerim cf. Lact. List, ir 3 falsum intellcgere est quidem
sit :
sapientiae sed humanae: verum autem scire divinae est sapientiae. Jta philo-
sophi quod summum fuit humanae sapientiae assecuti sunt, ut intcllegerent
quid non sit : illud assequi nequivcrunt ut diccrent quid sit.
Ch. xxil. Simonides the lyric poet of Ceos, B.C. 550 470, one of the
:
know its effects we can argue back from their qualities to its qualities, with
a confidence proportioned to the number and variety of its ascertained
effects. A child may be incapable of forming a general estimate of his
father s character, but he is not thereby precluded from trusting and loving
him as faithful and good. The opposite view leaves men helpless victims
to any superstition, agnosticism being merely an exceptional and superficial
phase, possible in the study or laboratory, impossible to retain and act
upon amid the trials and difficulties of real life.
doctus traditur sc. fuisse. On such
:
ellipses cf. Draeger 116,
P. S. Gr. p. 346, arid Reid s Lad. index under ellipse .
Tusc. in 37 ;
so Carneades Div.
i 23, Cratippus Div. 11 108, 109.
protasis, which, if it had been used, would have been unworthy of a man
of ordinary understanding I
etiam pauciora with Allen s n. and Eoby 2240. For exx. of non modo in
the 2nd clause Mayor s Second Philippic 107.
cf.
giving the famous division of religion into mythical (of poets), natural (of
philosophers), political (of statesmen) a division which we may compare
with Gibbon s language the various modes of worship which prevailed in
the Roman world w ere all considered by the people as equally true, by the
r
LII 36, where the maintenance of the national religion and the prohibition
of strange rites are recommended as the best protection against political
revolution or conspiracy. But the attempt to retain religion simply as an
158 BOOK I CH. XXII Gl.
ego is. On the use of is in reference to the First and Second Persons
see Draeg. 40.
non opinione sed ad veritatem not as a matter of faith merely (lit. :
cf. the opposition of Kara 8ugav and irpbs dXydeiav o-vXXoyieo-0ai Arist.
Anal. Post. I 19 p. 81 b.
nulli esse : not to exist at all . So G5 quae nullae sunt, 97 nulla
csse dicamus, cf. Madv. 455 obs. 5.
G2. placet mihi deos esse. So we read of the Sceptics tvptdrja-e-
TM 6 SKfTTTiKos Kara fj.fi>
TU naTpia edrj KOI TOVS vo^ovs \ty<av
eiVat 6tovs KOI
TTJ 0iXocro(/>(i) rjTijo-(i /zTjSeV 7rpoTrfT(vofj.(vos, Sext. Emp. Math. IX 49. The
Academic sacceptance of the traditional creed on the authority of our
ancestors (majoribus nostris etiam nulla ratione reddita credere debeo, N.D.
Ill 6) reminds one of Hume s scoffing patronage of Christianity against
those dangerous friends who have undertaken to defend it by the princi
ples of human reason . Our most holy religion he says, is founded ,
but Simp, says this is the only exception to the universality of belief.
Cotta s classification of atheists agrees with that given by Clarke Being
and Attributes ch. I, Atheism arises from stupid ignorance i.e. from ,
BOOK I CH. XXIII 62. 159
lectual development (Diagoras, &c.) Plato Leg. x 886 A foil, assigns the :
two latter causes for the educated unbelief of his time, (1) a/spare ta rjSovav
re KOI tmdvfjiicav eVt TOV Vf/3^ fiiov op^aadai ras /
had known many who had professed atheism in youth, he had never met
with one who retained this opinion in old age.
suspicio deorum cf. opinio deorum 29 n. :
rum immania.
efferatam, Tusc. iv 32 efferata et
63. Diagorasin 89. He was a native of Melos (hence
: cf. 2, 117,
the epithet 6 MT?XJOS = atheist, used by Aristophanes of Socrates Nub. 830),
a disciple of Democritus, resided in Athens for several years, but fled from
it to avoid an action for impiety in 411 B.C. a price was set on his head ;
for divulging the mysteries, on Arist. Av. 1073 and Stahr s Art. in cf. Schol.
Diet, of Biog. Philodemus p. 85 maintains that he was a better theist than
the Stoics, and says that any supposed writings of his which appear to show
the contrary are either spurious or mere jeux d esprit ; in proof of this he
1
quotes the following from his genuine poems, $eor, deos irpo TTO.VTOS f pyov
PpoTfLov vaifjia (ppeva iiirfprarav and Kara 8aip,ova KOI TI/XOV ra Ttavra fipo-
TO KTIV. Sext. Emp. Math, ix, 53 says that he lost his faith after this was
written, d8iKr]6f Is inro TWOS erriopK^Vairor, see Fabricius in loc.
Theodorus : see Introduction under Aristippus, Zeller s Socrates tr.
pp. 342, 376 foil, and Diet, of Biog. Many striking sayings of his are
recorded, as that on his banishment from his native country, KOKWS 7roIre
avftpes Kvprjvaioi rijs Aiftvrfs els EXXaSa /ne f^opi^ovres Diog. L. II 103,
e*K TT]I>
*
need not ask the question about Prot. for he was condemned on that
I
taken by Sch. in loc. and by Draeg. 408, who calls it ganz vereinzelt
but classes it with such essentially different uses as pugnare ut N. D. l 75,
retinendum esse ut 95.
habeo dicere. This construction instead of the usual habeo quod dicam
is said (Draeg. 413) to be found only in Cic. Suet, and Gell., but Allen
quotes Hor. Epod. XVI 23 melius quis habct suadere, Ov. Trist. I 1. 123
plura mandare habcbam, [to which add Metam. ix 658 dare habebant,
Pont. Ill 1. 82 lacdcre habct, Lucr. VI 711 dicere habebam. J. S. R.] See
N. D. in 93 liaec dicere habui de natura deorum (compared with haec habui
quae dicerem, Lad. 104 ; Cato 85), and other exx. in Draeg.
So Diog. 1. C. Sta ravrr^v fie
rfjv apx^v TOV
Trpor A.0T]Vato)V Koi TO /3i/3Xi a avTov KartKavcrav iv TTf
n yopa, see the nn. in Hiibner s ed. We find the same names mentioned
by Sext. Emp. Math, ix 51 foil, in a list of atheistical philosophers, but he
adds Prodicus, Euhemerus and Critias, all of whom are introduced, the last
without name, by C. in 117 foil. w here see nn. Fabricius in his note on
r
charge was brought. Clem. Al. Protr. 2 p. 7 Sylb. gives a similar list, but
will not allow the justice of the charge the true adtoi are not those who
:
deny but those who deny the true and worship the false
false gods, This .
is a retort upon the heathen, whose name for the Christians was adeot, but
Clemens fails to distinguish between the denial of what was false in the
heathen religions, and the denial of religion in itself. There can be little
doubt that in some cases, e.g. that of Theodoras, the denial was of the
latter kind.
Tubulus :
(L. Hostilius) eum unum ex omni memoria scderatissimum et
Carbo :
(C. Papirius) the partisan of the Gracchi who suddenly changed
sides after the death of C. Gracchus, and defended his murderer Opimius ;
same letter C. says that with one exception all the Carbos had shown them
selves bad citizens.
/3ovXour yfvofj.tvov$, cos TOV KuKXcoTra KOI rovt Aaiorpuyofar *cat rovs AXou Sor,
noa-eiSaJi/oy f ^dcuauv ( KJOVOVS tlvai. Welcker Gotterlehre II 678 adds the
names of Procrustes, Sim s, Arnycus, Antaeus, Busiris, and refers to the
various sea-monsters of fable he also cites the phrase Neptuni nepos used
:
dmjvri? |
II. xvi 34. Mr Gladstone
(Juventus Mundi 241 251) connects this
with his theory of the Phoenician origin of the worship of Poseidon, and
suggests that there may be some allusion to the rough manners of a sea
faring and buccaneering people For the form of expression we may .
compare fortunae filius, ^wypdc/xai/ Tratfier, and the Hebraistic viol 0wr6r &c.
(Winer s Gram. p. 298 ed. Moulton.)
Lucilius on the date of his birth see Munro I. c. the best ed. of his
: ;
fragments is by L. Muller, 1872, who has also written on his Leben und
Werke 1876.
explorata :
clearly made out, 1, 51.
65. unda : their origin from atoms ; ubi their abode in the inter-
mundia 103 foil. ; quales corpore human shape 76 foil. ; animo
perfection of rationality and virtue 87 foil. ; vita a blessed and ever
lasting repose, 102, 111. The confused order of the book is shown in the
M. C. 11
1G2 BOOK i en. XXIIT G5.
nihil est enim corpore. Lambinus saw that some words must
have been between cnim and quod, and the gap has been supplied
lost
as follows by Sch. (partly from the parallel passage in Ac. I 27) quae
primum nullae sunt: nihil cst cnim in rcrum natura minimum quod
dividi nequeat to which he adds deinde, ut sint, moreri per in-me non
,
autem, &c. On the existence and indivisibility of atoms see Lucr. i 483
635 on the existence of void as essential to motion 329 397. For the
;
aliquid essc minimum, Fat. 24 p/tysici quibus inane csse nihil placet, Ac. n
125 tune out inane quicquam putcs essc, cum ita complcta et conferta sint
omnia, ut et quod movcbitur corporum cedat, et
qua quidque ccsscrit aliud
ilico conscquatur ? The majority of the ancient physici 1 followed Aristotle
in (1) affirming the infinite divisibility of matter, Pity*, vi 1 nav arvvtxts
SiaififTuv is lid SiaipfTu, Cad. in 4 (of Democritus and Leucippus)
dvuyxr]
rats nadr/^aTiKals ejriOTiJ^ais aro/m a&j/xara Ae yoiTaj, Gen. ct Corr.
1
The Flatonists however showed some tendency towards atomism; com
pare the indivisible triangles of 1 lato, the dro/uoi ypa^^al of Speus-ippus, and the
6yxoi of Hcraclidcs J. S. E. .
BOOK I CH. XXIV G6. 103
I 2 WOT ecri KOI SiaKptcri? /cat (rvyKpicns aXX OUT els aro/ia KOI ( aToficav,
TroXXa yap ra aSwara and (2) denying the existence of vacuum, Phys. iv
:
respecting the constitution of the universe ; cf. also Veitch Lucretius and
the Atomic Theory and Clerk Maxwell s Art. on Atom in the Encyc. Brit.
As to the existence of vacuum the results of modern science are thus stated,
the undulatory theory of light supposes the whole of the celestial spaces to
be filled with the luminiferous ether. The astronomical argument therefore
in favour of absolute vacuum has fallen ;
but the views of the constitution
of matter which have grown with the rise of the molecular sciences of
chemistry, light, heat, electricity, &c., have supplied its place with much
more effect. The inference to w hich the modern philosophy w ould give
r r
portenta, &c. 18 n. one may excuse such scurrilities in the mouth of the
:
Dogmatists, but they are scarcely appropriate for an Academic. The con
struction is resumed in hanc opinionem.
sive etiam ante Leucippi. C. expresses himself doubtfully because
Epicurus denied that Leucippus had ever existed, Diog. L. x 13, Hirzel
p. 184.
corpuscula adunca. Lucretius n 333 foil, shows how the qualities of
bodies are derived from the various shapes of the constituent atoms, some
levia and rotunda, some aspera and hamata, mucronibus unca or angellis
p. 217) ATj/ioKptroj Se cr^/xa rrtpiTide Is eKacrrw y\vkvv fj.fi- TOV crrpoyyuXoj/ /cat
(VfJ.cyfdrj TroieT, (rrpv^vuv 8e TOV /ifyaXotr^Tj/xoi rpa\vv re /cat TroXvyamop KOI
112
1G4 BOOK I CH. XXIV GG.
f\ovra ota(f)opdr, a point in which he differed from Epic, who made the
atoms infinite in number, but limited the variety of shapes, see Lucr. I.e.
The text here is extremely doubtful. Heind., who re-writes the sentence,
pertinently asks what is the force of quasi before a simple word such as
adunca. Any. tindpyr. are both air. Xey.
quaedam alia partim quaedam : cf. 103 Tusc. v 38. Similarly
we have modo and turn irregularly combined for the sake of variety in 34.
[I think it is necessary
to insert another alia before levia. Quaedam
merely marks the unfamiliarity of corpusculum to translate oVo^oj (so first
used by Amafmius, see Ac. I 5). Also the pause seems to come after
quaedam. J. S. R.]
nulla cogente natura, sed concursu quodam fortuito. This is a cor
rect statement of the theory of Epicurus, but is inapplicable to Democritus,
who spoke of chance as the fiction of human inconsiderateness (ui/$pa>7rot TV-
%r]s eiScoXoi/
eVXdcrai To Trpocpacrti ISirjs d/SovXt r;? Mullach p. 167) and said that
nothing was made at random (ouSeV xpf/^a fjLarrjv yiyvfTai, dXXa navra en
\6yov -re Kai vn dvdyKrjs Mullach p. 22G). So Arist. Gen. An. \ 8 A^oKpiror
fie, TO oil evfKa \tyfiv, iravra dfdyei (Is avaynrfV ols xpf/rai
d<pf\f cfrixris,
and 77
yiyvfTCU,
OVK opdas e^ei ^ 7I"Xo/3eti o Ar^^i. avdyti ras wtpl (pixrfaiy alrias,
, e<fi
ovTO) K.ai TO -n-porepov f yivtro, which (in Phys. II 4 and 5) he treats as equi
u>s
prosecution (dc vitae mcae statu dcducercnt ut ego istum accusarem}. Dejicere
dc, Ktatu (Orator 129) is a metaphor borrowed from the ring to knock a man
out of his attitude It would be easier to make you change your whole
.
Philodemus (quoted by Hirzel p. 107) says that Epicureans who are guilty
of schism ov iraw p.aKpav TTJS TrarpaXotcoi /caraSt /cr;? d^earijKacrti
TO>V Hirzel .
however has shown (pp. 98 190) that there was more of movement and
variety in the Epicurean school than has been generally recognized. Quin-
tilian xn 2 says the same of philosophers in general, haec inter ipsos qui,
velut sacramento rogati vel etiam superstitions constricti, nefas ducant a sus-
cepta semel persuasione discedere.
quid enim mereas
67. what would tempt you to abandon the
:
system ? what would you take as pay, what bribe must one offer you ?
lit.
ista est veritas : for the attraction of istud see 77, 122, and Roby
1068.
nam de vita
langueat as to happiness I make no objection your
:
;
intelligent agent, here it is used rather in the Stoic sense and opposed to
the capricious movements of the atoms, cf. Sch. s n. here and my n. on
65.
Ep. with other philosophers, including therefore his atomic doctrine so far
as it was the same with that of Dem. cf. Fin. I 18 scd hoc commune vitiutn
;
(the general atomic doctrine), illae propriae Epicuri ruinae (the declinatio).
G8. sint sane ante quam nati. For the ellipse of the verb with
acterni, nulli dei, and especially in the subordinate clauses quod ex atomis,
si natum, see Draeg. 116, (who compares ut tu Velleius and quot hominum
linguae 84) and Roby 1443, who cites 110 sine virtute certe nullo modo
foil.
ffroixf la, Pint. Plac. Phil. p. 882 A, Stob. Eel. p. 66 but if we arrived at a ;
right conclusion in our discussion of 49, this 3rd principle consists only
of a subordinate class of atoms composing the divine images which are
always streaming in upon the soul. It might be argued that these have
nothing concreti about them, but merely produce an impression of a con
tinuous form by their ceaseless repetition that they have never coalesced ;
ences ).
To which it is replied that goodness has nothing to do with the
quod cum efficere vultis : for when you would prove this (that the
divinity is possessed of such attributes).
in dumeta
correpitis you hide yourself in the thickets
: Cf. Ac. n .
112 cum enim campus in quo cxsultare possit oratio, cur earn tantas
sit
?
iii
angustias et in Stoicorum dumeta compellimus So often spinae and .
dicimus, velle aliquid sine causa, Tusc. I 71 ita dicebat, duas esse vias, III 41
ilalaetitiam esse, see Madv. Fin. n 13, 17, in 53, v 77; and compare the
use of the epexegetic clause after a demonstrative or relative, Draeg. 484.
BOOK I CH. XXV 69. 167
Ch. xxv G9. hoc persaepe facitis possit. Three examples follow, (1)
the declination of atoms, (2) the denial of the disjunctive judgment ( 70
idem facit contra dialecticos], (3) the assertion of the infallibility of sensa
tions ( 70 omnes sensus veri nuntios), all preparing the way for (4), with
which we are here concerned (71 idem facit in natura deorurri). The
same points are criticized elsewhere by C. e.g. (1) in Fin. I 19, Fat. 22,
46 ; (2) in Ac. n 97, Fat. 18 foil. ; (3) Ac. II 79, see the following notes.
ut satius fuerit. Satius est being used in the Ind. like aequius est,
melius est, where we might have expected the Subj. (see n. on longum est
19), satius fuit would mean would have been better It is here .
si atomi suopte pondere. This was the only natural and necessary
movement of the atoms according to Dem. but since the larger and heavier ;
dro/iour).
nihil fore in nostra potestate. Epicurus ap. Diog. L. x 134 speaks of
the blessedness of the man who has learnt that necessity, to which others
assign a despotic power, is only a name for the results of chance or of
man s free will, eirel Kpflrrov TJV rw ire pi 6ta>v
[J.ii6a) KaraKoXovdelv fj rfj ra>v
dia Tifj.fjs, i] 8e a.irapalrr]Tov fx.ei TTJV dvdyKrjv. The same reason is Assigned
for the introduction of the clinamen in Fat. 22 foil. (cf. 46 foil.) Epicurus
eeritus atomus gravitate ferretur naturali ac nccessaria, nihil
est, ne, si
semper
liberum nobis esset, cum ita moveretur animus ut atomorum motu cogeretur,
to which the Academic disputant replies (1) that the single downward
movement does not necessarily involve the doctrine of necessity, and (2)
that in any case the supposition of the clinamen would not avert such a
(causal use of irapa) dXXa Set irpocrenio fl^cu KOI TO /x^Sa/itoj erepco paxfcrQai
TUV eVapycoi/. Accordingly we find another reason given in Fin. I 19 viz.
that as all atoms move at the same rate in vacuo (ovre yap TO. /3apea OOTTOV
ol(70^(TfTai, (jiiKpcov Kal Kov<pa>i>,
orai/ yt 8f/ fjirjdev OTravrq avTols Diog. L. X 61)
a point in which Ep. corrected the erroneous doctrine of his predecessor
there was no possibility of one overtaking the other, but all must move
168 BOOK I CH. XXV GO.
70. hoc dicere turpius est cf. Fin. i 19 ait enim dedinare atomum :
sine causa ; quo nihil turpius physico, quam fieri quicquam sine causa dicere,
and Fat. 18.
dicitur, iste vester (Epicurus) plane inermis ac nudus est ; Fat. 1 tota est \oymr),
p. 69 foil.
ita elf abimur aut vivet eras Hermarchus aut non vivet\ cum dialectici sic
statuant omne quod ita disjunctum sit, quasi aut etiam aiit non, non modo
verum esse sed etiam necessarium ; (vide quam sit catus is quern isti tardum
putant. Si enim, inquit, alterutrum concessero necessarium esse, necesse erit
eras HermarcJium aut vivere aut non vii-ere. Nidla autem est in natura rerum
talis necessitas} cum hoc igitur dialectici pugnent, id est Antiochus et Stoici ;
totam enim evertit dialecticam. Nam si e contrariis disjunctio (contraria
autem ea dico cum alterum aiat alterum negef) si talis disjunctio falsa potest
esse, Top. 56 dialecticorum modi plures sunt qui ex disjunc
nulla vera est ;
tionibus constant : aut hoc aut illud: hoc autem: non igitur illud. Itemque,
aut hoc aut illud: non autem hoc: illud igitur. Quae condusiones idcirco
ratae sunt, quod in disjunctione plus uno verum esse non potest. It is the
principle now known as the Law of Excluded Middle (see Hamilton Logic
vol. I pp. 83, 90 foil., Ueberweg Log. tr. pp. 235284, Mansel Prol. Log.
much favoured by Plato (e.g. Sophist, p. 282 foil.) and in later times by
Bentham. For an account of the Disjunctive Judgment see Mansel Prol.
Log. p. 236 foil., Hamilton I 239. The Stoics, who prided themselves on
their logical refinements and were especially distinguished by the name
o~vv8fo~/j.os OVTOS TO erepov TGOV d^ico/iarwi ^l/evdos elvai. For etictm cf. Madv.
45 (on affirmative and negative answers).
pertimuit ne fieret necessarium. The Stoics held that their prin
ciple of Necessity was involved in the Disjunctive judgment applied to
future events, asmay be seen argued at length in Fat. 20 foil., e. g. Since
it is
absolutely necessary that a man now living must at a given date in
the future be either dead or alive, whichever of the two proves eventually
to be true must be now a necessary truth though unknown to us ; or, more
shortly, his existence or non-existence at that date is a necessary truth ;
which of the two it is, will be made apparent by the event. Aristotle dis
cussed the point in his treatise De Interpretations ch. 9 foil. in regard to
the present or past, affirmative or negative judgments of existence are
necessarily true or false ; but it is not so with regard to the future,
otherwise all future events would be fixed by necessity (wore ei eV airavn
ov fj.rj
etVai OTUV ov prjv ovTf TO ov airav dvdyKrj fivai, ovTe TO fj,rj
fj,f) 77, dvdyKr)
ov fj.^ fivai...K.al tVt TTJS dvTLffrdcrfias 6 avros Xo-yos fivai peis fj [JLTJ elvai airav
dvdyKrj, Kal errecrdai ye rj p.rj ov fjLtvroi StfXoi/Ta ye dneiv Qdrepov avaynaiov (i.e.
the necessity belongs to the compound judgment not to its parts taken
separately) ; Aeyw 6e oiov dvdyKrj p.ev fo~fo~dai vavfia%lav avpiov r/ p,f) eo~fo~6ai,
ov iifvroi fo~fo~dai ye avpiov vav/J.a^iav dvayKalov ov8e /JLTJ yfvfo~dai. Ill the De
Fato 21, C. says that he would rather accept the teaching of Epicurus et
negare omnem enuntiationem aut veram esse aut falsam than allow that all
things happened by necessity, but he cites Carneades to prove that no such
consequence as necessity is really involved in the Disjunctive Judgment.
In reality Epicurus seems to have taken much the same view as Arist., see
Fat. 37 nisi forte volumus Epicureorum opinionem sequi, qui tales enun-
tiationes nee veras nee falsas esse dicunt (i. e. not yet corresponding to fact
but only capable of becoming so) aut, cum id pudet, illud tamen dicunt,
quod est impudentius, veras esse ex contrariis dijunctiones, sed quae in his
enuntiata essent, eorum neutrum
esse verum and cf. Zeller Stoics tr. p. 435,
negavit. For the asyndeton after pertimuit cf. the next sentence
iirguebat Arccsilas timuit Epicurus dixit, and 100 motum dico csse
inanem, tu imagines remanere quae referantur hoc idem fieri, 121 cum
dicat negat idem csse tollit id. The effect is to give rapidity and energy
to the sentence and to heighten the antithesis.
Arcesilas : the regular Doric and Aeolic contraction for ApKeaiXaos,
cf. Ahrens Dial. Dor. p. 199. On the Stoic and Academic theories of per
ception see 12 n. Ac. i 40 foil., n 79 foil. the controversy between Arc.
:
may is falsa esse quam vera. But possibly Cic. uses the word falsus in the
sense of fallacious ,
as often in the Academica. J. S. R.]
omnes sensus veri nuntios. Cf. Madv. Fin. i 22, Ac. n 79 eo ran
demittit Epicurus, si v.nus sensus scmel in vita mcntitns sit, null!, vmquam
cxse credendum ; Zeller Stoics tr. p. 402 foil. to avoid doubt we must allow
causes of these deceptions not lying in sensation as such, but in our judg
ment about sensation . Lucretius iv 4G3 after instancing a number of
optical illusions, says that they seek in vain to shake the credit of the
senses quoniam pars horum maxima fallit (propter opinatus animi quos
addimus ipsi] pro visis lit sint quae non sunt sensibus cisa. Here too Ep.
might quote Ai ist. on his side, cf. De Anima in 3 3 p.tv aiadrjiris ruv ij
of valde, which is substituted for callide in some of the Jiss here, but in
later writers it can only bear this force when combined with a negative.
[For the form of sentence, cf. Orator 82 nildl horum parum audacter.
Moser ms.]
plagam accipiebat so Fat. 21 (of the denial of Disjunctive Judgments)
:
Past Part, concretus, which implies the completion of the process, to the
verbal, implying the process itself and besides, the reference is plainly to
;
the sint sane ex atomis of 68, where it was shown that any such com
pound must be liable to interitus: to avoid this danger Ep. had recourse
to his quasi-corpus 69 : then came the parenthesis illustrating hoc per-
saepe facitis, and now in is resumed in the words ind. corp.
71 the subject
concr. fug. he tries to escape from the aggregation of indivisible particles
(with its consequences as above pointed out) The only concretio implied .
in the Gods of 49 was that of the images, involving superficial area but
not depth, cf. monogrammus n 59. The tamquam sanguis was probably
suggested by the Homeric ichor, 11. V 340 pe e 8 upfipoTov at/za $eo7o, t^cop, |
sense 110 ne beatus quidem, 113, II 87, ill 23, 43, 47, 49, 68, 86, see
Madv. Fin. Exc. in p. 816.
72. quasi dictata redduntur :
you repeat your lesson like parrots .
172 BOOK I CH. XXVI 7 2.
l
Cf. Fin. ii 95 ista vestra si gravis brevis, si longus levis\ dictata sunt ; Fiii.
iv 10 isdem de rebus semper quasi dictata decantare ncque a commentariolis
suis discedere ; Fin. II 20 quis vestrum non cdidicit Epicuri Kvpias 8oas I
ing seems to suit better the old etymology connecting it with dAvco),
properly used of a mooning dreamy state, as in Col. vn 3 ne fur aut bestia
halucinantem pastorem decipiat ; then of idle random talk as here and
(without blame) Q. Fr. nil epistidae nostrae debent intcrdum halucinari
1
descend to prattle Seneca uses halucinatio of silly abuse, Vit. Beat. 26.
;
sense (=^etiani) by C., but, if we allow any weight to MSS, we must admit the
use not only here, but in 83 age et his vocabulis, in Tusc. in 28 ct ilia
laudantur, Leg. I 33 ergo et lex, Fin. in 27 ergo et probandum, Dio. i 34 et
auctoritatem.See further Draeg. 312 (some of whose exx. however are
more properly explained on the principle of anacoluthon treated of in
Madv. Fin. Exc. i), Roby 2198, Moser on Tusc. 1. c., Munro s Lucr. ind.
under ct, Dumesnil on Leg. I 33, and a copious list of exx. in Kuhnast s
Liv. Ki/nt. p. 371 foil.
against Klotz. Compare the similar uses of redoleo, sapio, odor (urbanitatis
Orat. Ill 1G1, dictaturae Att. iv 11), and Gr oo>.
lem equidcm aut ipse doctrinis fuissct instructior (cst enim non satis politus Us
BOOK I CH. XXVI 72. 173
runt ? as he shows in detail in the same epistle. That the liberal arts
were not entirely neglected by the followers of Epicurus appears from the
largenumber of treatises on rhetoric, music, poetry and dialectic, which
have been found among the Herculanean papyri. But Philodenius, to
whom most of them are assigned, shares his master s contempt for a pro
fession of universal knowledge (such as was made by Hippias), comparing
the polyhistors of his time to the Homeric Margites, see his De Vitiis
x col. 20 Ussing p. 55, Rhetorica Gros p. 52. See more under inscitia
loquendi 85, dialecticorum novit 89.
Xenocraten : see 34 n. and Zeller I.e. p. 383. C. always speaks in
the highest terms of him, cf. Tusc. v 51 Xen. ilium gravissimum phtto-
sophorum, exaggerantem tanto opere virtutem, extenuantem cetera, R. P. i 3
nobilem in primis philosophum.
credo plus nemini. On this use of plus (=magis) see Madv. Fin. I 5.
conquest of Samos by Timotheus 366 B. c. cf. Grote ch. LXXIX vol. x p. 406,
Boeckh Publ. Econ. of Athens, Bk. in ch. 18. The word is apparently
peculiar to C., who uses it (Att. xv 29, xvi 1) of the soldiers of Caesar to
whom lands were assigned in Epirus after the Civil War.
ludi magister fuit turned schoolmaster
: I do not . remember any
other instance of this particular use of fuit, but it may be compared with
such cases as Att. x 16 commodum ad te dederam litteras, cum ad me bene
174- r.ooK i CH. xxvi 72.
[Weissenborn (Lett.
ich bin geworden , Liv.
Gr. 182 n. 2) quotes, for/i =
xxxiv 21 locvpletior indies provincia fuit, Sail. Cat. 20 7 volgus fuimtts
sine gratia, and compares the Fut. Perf. in Fain, xiv 7 f undo Arpinati bene
p. 352 ed. 2)has a discussion on the same point and Brix on Mil. Glor. ;
102 legatus fuit, quotes exx. where the sense would be naturally expressed
by the Eng. became But in reality fui merely denotes past time ab
.
compare the use of f/Sao-i Xfvcra I became king I doubt however whether ;
Xerro, /ifiXto Ta 8e prjropiK^ yfv6fj.evos ovv TOVTOV fiadr/rrj! 6 E/r. vnep TOV
doKflv avTodidciKTOs (ivai /cat avTOfpvrjs (t>L\oa~o(J3Os, rjpvflTo f< nairos rponov,
TJV rf Trepl CIVTOV (j^^rjv {a\(i(j)fiv fcrrrevSe, TTO\VS
Tf fyivero TOIV padrjuaTatv
narriyopos, Sext. Emp. Math, i p. 216. It was also asserted that the canon
of Ep. was copied from the Tripod of Xaus. Diog. L. x 14.
Democriteo. Elsewhere (Diog. L. ix 64, 69, Sext. Emp. 1. c.) he is
called a disciple of Pyrrho, who was however himself reckoned among the
followers of Dem.
vexat contumeliis : cf. Diog. L. x 8 TrXeu^ora (
a mollusc ,
Plat. Phileb.
21 c) avrbv e/caXet KOI dypdfj.fj.aTov *cal aTrareuva /cat Tropvov, also 7 and Sext.
Emp. 1. C.
1
So Hirzcl p. 110 n.
BOOK i en. xxvi 73. 175
abrupt and disjointed style. There seems no reason for Heindorfs suppo
sition that the text is corrupt.
efficere ut male moriar, ut non moriar non potestis and Corte on Lucan I
200 for quid quod
;
3 n. and 117 for the thought, Fin. II 12 hoc fre;
egone non intellegam quid sit jSovrj Graece, Latine voluptas ? utram tandem
linguam nescio ? Deinde qui fit ut ego nesciam, sciant omnes quicunque
ejus qui ita loquatur ut non intellegatur. Quod duobus modis sine reprelien-
sione Jit, si aut de industria facias, ut Her. cognomento qui a-Koreivus pcr-
fTnTTjddjcras dacXpeaTtpov ypa^ai orruis ol 8vvd/j.(voi Tvpocrioiev avTo> KOI prj e<
TOV 8ijij.(adovs fvKara<pp6vi]Tov TJ, Lobeck Agl. p. 160 foil. The real cause cf
his obscurity is the difficulty experienced by all early writers in attempt
Ter. Hunt, v 2 20 here licetne? and Liv. vn 13 si licet (for scilicet, Madv.
emend.} the fuller phrase liceat dicere occurs
; 80 and Att. n 4. Klotz
Adn. Crit. n 8 points out the error of Hand s interpretation entre nous ,
in 62. Cf. the similar metaphorical use of vinco and repugno. For the
Ace. of Extent (illud) see lloby 1094.
water is said concrescere pruina n 26 expr. of that which has had a pattern
;
ing muscle sloped, as slopes a wild brook o er a little stone ) em. of any ;
change from the direct to the indirect construction after dicemus marks the
difference between the actual and the supposed description.
adumbratorum : shadow-deities : so o-/aaypa$uz a silhouette ,
see
Cope on Arist. lihet. Ill 12 and quotations under nihil concreti above.
seems to men tJie most, beautiful, that is merely the prejudice of race.
If it is said that experience shows rationality to be confined to that
form, on the same ground we might attribute all the properties of man
to the Gods ; but reason shows the danger of drawing negative conclu
sions from our limited experience, and it shows also that a body which
is suitable for man is unsuitable for such a being as God is supposed
to be. Ch. xxvii 76 xxxvii 102.
76. hoc loco velitis here you are at no loss for arguments by
:
our minds (i.e. the TrpoXrj^is, cf. 43, 45, 100) that in thinking of God a
human form presents itself to us .
nee esse pulchriorem for the loose infinitive after non deest copia
:
rationum cf. res esse after dicemus just above the infinitive clause here ;
in 7, Ac. n
49 with Reid s n., Madv. Fin. II 105 ; most MSS have the archaic
quicquid, which is used by Lucretius in this sense, see Munro s n. on I 389.
arripere vestro jure rem nullo modo probabilem you act as if :
in the same way v 247 illud in his rebus ne corripuisse rearis me mihi \
quod terram atque ignem mortalia sumpsi, which Munro illustrates from
Sext. Emp. Hyp. I 90 irp\v ap^aa-dai rfjs Kpureoos TO. (paivop-tva vvvapTra&vviv,
eauroTf rr)v Kpia-iv fTriTpewovTes. The phrase suo jure (nearly equivalent to
suo arbitrio) means properly of his own right i.e. on his own authority, ,
M.C. 12
178 BOOK I CH. XXVIII 77.
temples) cst enim quacdam opinions species deorum in oculis, non solum in
mentibus ; Sch. compares the complaint of the Sicilians in Verr. Div. 3
sesejam ne deos quidem in suis urbibus ad quos confugiant habere, quod
eorum simulacra sanctissima C. Verres e delubris religiosissimis abstulisset ;
Pint. J/. p. 379 reprobates those who thought the images to be not dydX-
Hara KOI rt/iaj d\\a deovs- See Niigelsb. ^ach-llomerische Theol. p. 5.
6(<0>v
representation of divine activity under any other form than that of man .
accessit. .quod .videatur. The Subj., which is found in all the MSS, is
. .
too the idea to which you referred ( 48) may have contributed to this
result, I mean man s belief in his own superior beauty Vidcrctur would .
have been more regular after accessit; the Pres. is used in order to denote
that the proposition is of general import, not limited to the time of its
original utterance. For the pleonasm with opinio cf. Na gelsb. Stil. 186 2.
physice. So Metrodorus, in the ep. alluded to 113, addresses his
brother as to (frvvioXoye, and Timon (ap. Diog. L. X 3) styles Epic, voraror
av fyvviKuiv KOI KVVTOTOS. The Epicureans prided themselves on their
physics as the Stoics on their dialectics, see 83, n 48, Fin. ir 102, I 63 in
physicis plurimum posuit Ep., Pint. Def. Or. p. 434 D EniKovpftovs 8ia
TTJV KaXfjv 817 (pvcrtoXoyiav tvvj3pioVTaf, coy avroi Xf yovcrt, rols TOIOVTOIS
(oracles) ;
Zeller Stoics tr. p. 399, and esp. Hirzel p. 157 foil.
quently.
earn esse causam putaremus. Madv. thinks that this clause was
added by a reader who misunderstood the construction mirum si (?} and it
has accordingly been bracketed by later editors. The objections as stated
by Sch. Opusc. in 317 foil, are (1) that it is superfluous in sense we had ;
already been told that man s self-admiration was one of the grounds of
anthropomorphism (2) that in reading the sentence, we naturally take si as
;
referred to, a lion has courage, God has courage, therefore Cod should be
in the shape of a lion. [Quasque is used not quamquc, because it is
equivalent to quodque genus, R.]
at mehercule would be more suitable here if we retain at it must
: et ;
the comparison should lie between man, on the one side, and all other
animals, on the other whereas, if we give the ordinary force to the plural,
;
it seems to me that the use of the word nostris here draws our attention to
like bodies, between or upon which the man appears to ride, as in the
beautiful painting at Herculaneum (Roux Aine* Rccueil General vol. v 36,
M. Borb. vin 10). It is to the latter form that C. alludes, and also ApolL
Eh. IV 1608 1614 avrap VTTOI Xayopcoi/ StKpaipa ol evda Kal fi/da KiJTfos \
o\Kair] prjKvveTo, &c. Cicero would be familiar with the Triton which
formed a vane on the top of the horologium of Cyrrhestes, the tower of
the winds at Athens, cf. Miiller Anc. Art
,
402. For the intransitive use
of the participle cf. R. P. in 14 invehens alitum anyuium curru, Phil, in 32
phosed into a Triton, would you refuse ? Otherwise surely the opposition
must have been more strongly marked, and yet one would object to a
change even into the still more beautiful Triton As to construction, I .
think qualis refers to the preceding formas, and that we must supply tali
forma with esse.
homo nemo no one who is a maw not simply =nemo or null us homo.
: ,
(iv 77, 81), and of foresight (ib. 83), and argues that in the sight of God
the two must be much on a level (ib. 85).
and the comic poets. Grex here just corresponds to the Cretan dye\ij : it
is technically used of a company of actors.
my weakness
arriseris: you smile at the confession of .
where Madv. quotes Diog. L. VII 129 *ai fpaa-6ija-eadai TUV cro0uj/ reap via>v
illi lumen the mole seemed to him a beauty cf. P. red. in Sen. 8
:
,
35 lumen cicitatis with Eeid s n. for its rhetorical use see Piderit s index
:
to the De Oratore s.v. On the general subject see Plato ltcp. \ 474 D
ov\ ovrci) TroieTre irpos TOVS KaXovs ; 6 fiiv, on crt^ios, eiri\apis K\rj6els eVat-
vtOijo-tTai foil., Lucr. iv 11541170, Hor. Sat. I 3 38 foil., Ov. A. A. n G57.
Catulus. Both the father, Q. Lutatius Q. F., and the son, Q. Lutatiua
Q. F. Q. N., were highly respected members of the party of the Optimates
and special objects of C. s admiration. The former was a colleague of Marius
in the consulship and joint-commander in the war against the Cimbri
B.C. 102. His death in the Manun proscription (B.C. 87) is mentioned
Ji. D. in His uprightness of character is witnessed to by the saying
80.
132). He is one of the speakers in the De Oratore, where some of his witty
sayings are reported (Orat. II 220 and 278). Gellius xvm 9 quotes with
extravagant praise a jaw-breaking epigram addressed by him to the beauti
ful youth Theotirnus. The younger Catulus was a warm supporter of C.
against Catiline and was the first to salute him as pater patriae. He died
B.C. 60. He was one of the interlocutors in the 1st ed. of the Academica,
but Atticus persuaded C. that the subject was too technical to suit him,
and C. took his part himself in the 2nd ed. See lleid s Introd. to the Acad.
avus hvjus adolesccntis and Off. Ill 66 Cato, hujus nostri Catonis pater ; so
N. D. I 107 hoc Orphicum carmen, the hymn which now goes under the
name of Orpheus his moribxs, in the present state of morality
, [Add .
62B.C.
Auroram salutans. On the habit of praying at sunrise see Plato Leg.
X 887 E dvareXXovros T( rjAi ou KOI creXr/i/^s KOI irpos 8vcrp.as lovruv irpoKvXio fis
turning to the East at the Creed, see Tylor I 260 271. For saluto in the
sense of worship cf. Rose. Am. 56 deos salutatum venerint, Cato R. R. i 2
paterfamilias ubi ad villain venit, ubi larem familiarem salutavit, fund urn
circumeat, Seneca Ep. 95 47 vetemus salutationibus matutinis fungi et
foribus assidere templorum: humana ambitio istis ojficiis capitur.
BOOK I CH. XXVIII 79.
is lebhafter als das Fut. oder Conj. dub. mit dem Gedankeu dass die
The anonymous translator, Lond. 1683, is not behind the Latin in his racy
vernacular shooing-horn-nosed, bangle-eared, jobber-nolled, bittle-browed .
It will be noticed how many Latin names are borrowed from personal
defects, cf. Roby 851 a, b.
quae sunt: (defects) which are found amongst us men Sch. com .
them .
una necesse est. The ground of the Academic scepticism was that
every true sensation has side by side with it a false one indistinguishable
from it. One who has mistaken P. for Q. Geminus could have no in
fallible mode of recognizing Cotta Ac. II 83; cf. 55, where the Acade
,
tamenne : so Flac. 21, Ac. n 26 and without ne, Farm, ix 19; see
Lewis and Short s. v. n c ;
for the position Div. in Caec. 21, Att. iv 16.
ea facie novimus Abl. of Quality, cf. 49 soliditate quadam cernatur
:
M^Sous KOI liepaas avroly eoiKuras, Kal PCiyvirriovs eacravrei)?. Cf. Tylor
<r(pi(riv
Prim. Cult. I p. 278 the South- African, who believes in a god with a
crooked leg, sees him with a crooked leg in dreams and visions (quoted
from Livingstone) when the Devil with horns, hoofs and tail had once
;
become a fixed image in the popular mind, of course men saw him in this
conventional shape .
82. fana spoliata : cf. Sail. Cat. v 6 of the evil effects of Sulla s
diroKTtivfli rj.vptv fwav, ddvaroi ij CVM 7?? ^e dfKcav, anorivfi r)[j.{r)v TTJV av ol
?"
IpffS Ta.u>VTai os 8 av i/3ic fj iprjKa airoKTflvr), rjv re rfv re dcKO>f, Te&vavai Ku>v
vi c. 9. See also Diod. I 83 and the quotations from the comic poets in
Athen. vn 55, esp. that from Timocles, which is given also in Philodemus
p. 86. Different animals were counted sacred in different parts of Egypt
as appears from Juvenal Sat. xv ; see the very full notes, and reff. on the
Egyptian religion generally, contained in Mayor s ed,, and for the crocodile,
his n. on crocodilon adorat. In Wilkinson s Ancient Egyptians (ch iv. small
ed.) there a list of the sacred animals, mentioning where they were
is
worshipped with what deity each was associated. The later mythology
explained this animal-worship by the transformations which the Gods
underwent in their fear of Typhoeus, cf. Ov. Met. v 325 hue quoque (to
Egypt) terrigcnam venisse Typlioea narrat et se mentitis superos celasse
figuris, Jupiter in the ram, Mercury in the ibis, &c. For the modern views
see Tylor P. C. n 208224.
186 BOOK I CH. XXIX 82.
quid censes nonne deum videri ? For the form of sentence cf.
78 n. For Apis see Diet, of Biog.
illam vestram Sospitam. The temple of Juno Sospita or Sispita,
the Saviour at Lauuvium, was one of peculiar sanctity, being visited
,
annually by the consuls like that of Jupiter Latiaris. Livy often speaks of
prodigies occurring there, and C. (Div. I 99) tells us that the outbreak of
the Marsic war was signified by mice gnawing the shields suspended there.
It was rebuilt in obedience to a vision B.C. 90 (Div. i 4). For the special
ceremonies belonging to it see Art. on Lanuvium in Diet, of G eog., and
Preller Rom. Myth. p. 246 2 For the attraction quam Sospitam instead of
.
quam Sospita videtur cf. 86 tarn aperte quam te, and Zumpt 603 b.
cum repandis. Preller 1. c. quotes an inscription relating to a
pelle
priestess quae in acde Junonis Sospitae Matris Reginae scutulum et
clypeum et hastam et calceos rite novavit voto. The Goddess appears in this
garb on the coins of the Roscii and other families connected with Lanu
vium. See Muller Anc. Art. 353. The goat-skin, which Preller consi
ders to be a symbol of fertility, and connects with that worn by the
Luperci, covered the head and breast the scutum was oblong as opposed
;
to the round clypeus ; an engraving of the shoe with the upturned toe,
calceolus rcpandus (pandits ), is given in Rich s Comp. to Diet. p. 99 I ;
think the diminutive implies a low shoe, not (as Rich) one worn by a
female, as we read of calcei muliebres in Varro L. L ix 29 and elsewhere ;
the hasta marks protection, it was also borne by the Juno Curitis. Moser
(ms.) notices the recurrence of the termination -am seven times in ten words.
alia nobis added by Ursinus, and seems required if the preceding
: is
sentence but Sch. Opusc. in. 287 denies the existence of a Romana
is right,
Juno distinguished as such by special attributes, and thinks that nee Romana
may have been added by some reader who stumbled at the omission of any
reference to the Juno
Capitolina. On the other hand Klotz Ada. Crit. I (>
pupil of Phidias. It was made of ivory and gold, and represented the god
dess seated on a throne, her head crowned with a garland, on which were
worked the Graces and the Hours, the one hand holding the symbolical
pomegranate, and the other a sceptre, surmounted by a cuckoo, a bird
sacred to Hera, on account of her having been once changed into that form
by Zeus (Puusiui. II 17 quoted in Diet, of /;.). It does not appear that
BOOK I CH. XXX 82. 187
there was any single type known under the name of Juno Romano, ; C.
probably refers to the general difference between the Greek Hera and her
Roman counterpart ;
cf. Muller A. A. 120.
Ch. xxx 83. physicum : see 77 u. and Wilkins on Orat. I 217, where
the Gk. form is used.
venatorem : cf. the metaphorical use of drjptveiv in Plato, and espe
cially the view-hollo on the discovery of justice, Rep. iv 432 c; so Hume
there cannot be two passions more nearly resembling each other than
dicitur, and compares (index s. v.) the poetical construction with Ka\ela-dai
= et rat, as in Soph. Track. 639.
Alcamenes a pupil of Phidias and one of the greatest of Greek
:
Some of these have been lately discovered at Olympia, casts of which may
be seen in the Fitzwilliam Museum at Cambridge. The Vulcan is thus
described by Val. Max. vm
11 tenet visentes Athenis Vulcanus Alcamenis
manibus fabi~icatus. Praeter cetera enim pe/fectissimae artis in eo prae-
currentia indicia etiam illud mirantur, quod stat dissimulatae claudicationis
they have also the same names as those by which they are known to us 1
The first Abl. is that of Description (Roby 1232) the second that of Man
ner (Roby 1234). On age Orelli quotes from Madv. Op. Ac. n 40 de
interrogation praeposito, cf. II 120 Tusc. in 49 Phil, v 28
"age"
see ;
Roby 1609. On the adverbial use of et see 72 n., and Hand n 513, 517,
Kiihner on Tusc. in 28 referred to by Sch. Many exx. are given by
Dumesnil on Leg. I 33. The argument as to names is added as a sort of
corollary to the previous argument on the appearance of the Gods. That
was a fair enough criticism on the prolepsis, and this, though, at first sight,
a mere reductio ad absurdum, is to some extent justified by the Epicu
rean doctrine that names existed 0uaei ov deem.
quot hominum linguae sc. sunt; ut tu Velleius: sc. eris; cf.
84. :
and Draeg.
68, 90, 116.
idem Vulcanus you are always Velleius, but Vulcan (i. e. the God of
:
fire) does
not bear the same name in Italy as in Africa or Spain Four .
in pontificiis, sc. libris, cf. the similar ellipse with annales. The pon
tifical records included nine different kinds of books, according to Mur-
dependent upon another having the same subject Madv. 401, cf. Roby 134G
Krueger Unters. in 337 foil, who quotes N. D. I 109 puderet me dicere non
intellcgere; the same construction is found with confiteor, Eosc. Am. Gl.
cf. Ac. n 126 licetne per vos ncsciro
[nescire, quod nescires :
quod
nescio? J. S. R.] Tusc. I GO nee me pudet, ut istos fateri me nescire quod
ncsciam.
nauseare : Forccllini and Freund take this to mean c
to litter : the
former compares Phil, v 20 orationem ore impurissimo evomuit, and Fam.
xn 25 vinolentum furorcm ejfimderct. As both passages refer to Antony,
(of whom nausea is also used in its literal sense 2 Phil. 84, and Fam. I. c.
quern ego ructantem et nauseantem conjeci in Octaviani plaffas), there is some
excuse for violence of language there here, in a quiet discussion with a
:
friend, such a use of the term (even if possible elsewhere, which I doubt,)
seems almost beyond Roman bad taste. May it not mean to feel disgust
at having to utter such nonsense as Epicurus puts in your mouth ? So
Ilcind. takes it, and would even omit the following words as a gloss.
Phaedrus iv G 25 has si qui stulte nauseant of over-critical readers who are
disgusted with everything, which Lewis and Short wrongly translate to
cause disgust (the reading is however doubtful).
;
sibi displicere : the change to the 3rd person is allowable, as the use of
BOOK I CH. XXXI 8-1. 189
the 2nd person was merely indefinite to confess one s ignorance : cf. for a
similar change from the 1st to the 3rd, 122 utilitatum suarum.
an sapientia Or (am I mistaken in supposing you to be dissatisfied
:
with your position?) do you really believe God to be a man like you or me?
That is impossible. Then am I to call the sun or moon God ? But you
Epicureans have yourselves shown that the divine attributes of happiness
and wisdom are incompatible with such deities .
and motion, as in Lael. 48, where see Seyffert, and Juv. vin 53 trunco Iler-
mae with Mayor s n.
haec vestra this may : refer to such passages as the criticism on Zeno
36 rebus inanimis et mutis.
85. visu : cf. 12 n. and Ruhnken on Paterc. II 94. On the omis
sion of the verb, see 68 n.
tali aliquo if the reading is right, this must refer to the heavenly
:
itaque: the particle properly refers to the sentence beginning in hoc ita
exposita, to which this should have been subordinated. For exx. of
similar looseness of construction, which makes two separate and inde
offendii ; nam et complectitnr verbis quod vult, et dicit plane quod intellcgam,
and Seneca speaks of a nob His sententia, apertior quam ut interpretanda sit,
et disertior adjuvanda Ep. 21. Gcllius n 9 defends his style from
quam ut
some attacks [Theon the rhetor blamed Epic, for an excessive
of Plutarch.
attention to rhythm, see Blass Die AttiscJie Beredsamkeit, p. 52. J. S. R..]
homine minime vafro cf. Tusc. n 44 vcnit Epicurus, homo minime :
a reader who misunderstood the sense, see Sch. Opusc. in pp. 318, 366.
non animadvertunt hie sed they do not observe that, though he :
spe:iks ambiguously here &c., cf. the use of (itv and Se, and see nn. on
20 a/jus principium, 23 at ca sajpientis,
Metrodorum : see 93 n.
Upicureos, pp. 1101 1107, of which the purport is given in the following,
ft(\rioi> yap (Wirdpxtiv TI Kal (TvyKfKpacrQtii. TIJ irtpl 6(u>v
86rj KOIVW nldovs
Ktii (jx iftov irados, fj
TOVTO (fxvyovTas ptjr (\ni8a /i /rf \o-piv iavrdis
BOOK I CH. XXXI 86. 191
the sacrilegious do not fear the religioncm templi any more than robbers
fear death, cf. Fin. I 64 quoted above. Religiones, the reading of most MSS
defended by Klotz (Adn. Grit. II 11), would be rather awkward after the
Sing.
87. cum ipso Epicuro loctuar : see 67 n.
fining hismotion within the limits of the ecliptic at either solstice (lit. by
the two extreme points of one circle ), cf. II 49, 50, 101 foil.
ab isdem principiis starting from the same point they finish their
:
course in longer or shorter time For the PL cf. Orat. I 121 exalbescam in
.
principiis dicendi.
numne : found also in Lad. 36, where see SeyfFert.
88.
ergo on this principle of experience we must disbelieve every
:
mindedness is this cf. 90 quis iste tantus casus? and Virg. Gco. iv
!
495 quis tantus furor ? Heind. following Davies and Walker took quae
as the relative and joined these words to the following sentence, but the
exclamation is more Ciceronian here, and the connexion tantae ut putares
would be very harsh, especially coming after the comparison as to the
mediterranei.
ut non crederes in like manner (lit. just as), supposing you had
:
been born in Seriphus and had never seen any animal larger than a fox,
you would never have belie ved in the existence of lions Sell, compares II .
Empire, proverbial for its insignificance and the borne tone of its inhabi
tants, cf. Mayor on Juv. x 170, Ael. H. A. in 37, Plato Rep. I 329 (the
famous story of Themistocles and the Seriphian, which is also given by C.
JSenect. 8).
while here, on the contrary, it serves to round off what was previously
abrupt, and makes an easier transition to the new topic introduced in et tu
quae gignantur there is no occasion for reading the Ind. with Sch., or
:
for any elaborate explanation, such as Miiller gives Adn. Crit. p. vi the :
rubro mari Indiave : a sort of hendiadys for the tpvdpa daXaa-a-a of the
Greeks, which comprehended the Indian Ocean together with the Ked Sea and
Persian Gulf. The allusion is probably to the whales, of which Pliny says
(N. H. ix 2) plurima et maxima in Indico mari animalia, quibus
e balaenae
of Cadara, rubri maris paeninsula ingens, he says that hujus loci quiets ad
immobilem magnitudinem beluae adolescant; so Strabo xv 2 12 mentions
among the difficulties experienced by Nearchus, in his voyage from the
mouth of the Indus to the Euphrates, the shoals of enormous whales
he continues Xtyoucrt peis ovv Ka\ 01 viv irKeovres els "lv8ovs
(<pvrrr)Tripa>v) ;
multitude, cf. Orat. 108 nemo orator tarn multa scripsit, quam multa sunt
nostra. For the substantival use tarn multa is more common than tot,
which is so used however in Gael. 66 tot unum super are possent.
negemus vidimus: cf. Locke s story of the
esse, quia numquam
King of Siam, who refused to believe the Dutch Ambassador s description
of the ice in Holland and the controversy on the value of experience, as
;
Epicurean, experience shows that a rational soul can only exist in human
form which the Stoic meets by a reference to the limited nature of our
;
experience, and the vastness of the universe, pointing out the erroneous
conclusions which would necessarily flow from the assumption that there
can be nothing in the infinite unknown but what is a repetition of the
infinitesimal known. In point of fact the Epicureans did not themselves
adhere to this principle their doctrines of atoms, of images, of the gods, of
:
the origin and growth of the world, were anything but matters of ordinary
experience (as Lactantius points out De Ira 10 quis ilia vidit ? umquam
foil.) nor did they care about their scientific truth, except in so far as
;
us a syllogistic proof of
anthropomorphism see this in 48. ;
non vestro more, sed dialecticorum. Cf. 70 n. Hirzel p. 177 foil, argues
that Zeno is here alluded to, and that there was an
important section of the
Epicurean school, commencing with Apollodorus 6 KrjiroTvpavvos, who set a
M. c. 13
19-i BOOK I CH. XXXI 89.
higher value on logic and on literary culture generally than Epicurus did ;
that C. (Fin. I 30 foil.) contrasts the procedure of Ep. himself, who held
that his doctrine of plea-sure was self-evident and needed no proof (negat
opus esse ratione neque disputatione, quamobrem voluptas cxpetenda, fugi-
cndus dolor sit : sentiri hoc putat ut calere igtiem), and that of some of his
followers who, having regard to the criticisms of other schools, non ex-
istimant oportere nimium nos causae confidere, sod et argumentandum ct
accurate disserendum et rationibus conquisids de voluptate et dolore dispu-
tandum putant.
quae agrees with the neuter dialectica, implied in the preceding
masculine. The neuter is also found Off, i 19 al. elsewhere we have the :
feminine, both in a Gr. form, dialectice, and in the Latin, see Fin. II 17
dialecticam pugni similem esse dicebat, in 41 &c. Sch. illustrates the con
struction from Tusc. I 4 in Graecia musici floruerunt discebantque id omncs,
cf. also ib. iv 48 gladiatorium id quidem ; quamqua?n in iis ipsis videmus
quibus CatUina fuit; de qua dicam, where see Dietsch. [Perhaps however
it is better, as Mr Roby suggests, to refer quae to argument, translating
and you V., deviating from the custom of your school, have logically
stated your opinion in arguments of the Dialecticians, totally unknown to
ambigua secernere, falsa sub specie veri latentia coarguere, ipsi quoque locum,
quern de judicio et regula appellant (N. D. I 43) alio nomine rationalem
induxerunt ; sed earn accessionem esse naturalis partis existimant. We
may take Gellius statement (u 8) that Ep. inverted the order of the syllo
gism, as a sign that he had treated the subject with his usual independence
and originality of thought ; and the treatise of Philodemus rrept (rr)ii.t uav
Ka\ shows that the Inductive Logic at any rate was deeply
<jr]^(ica<jfu>v
sententiae, see his Opusc. in 289 and 328. Madv., it is true, denies the
possibility of this reading, see his note on Fin. i 30 Latine rationem, argu-
mentum concludere dicimur, etiam aliquid concludere ut accusativus pro-
nominis addatur; l sententiam rem non magis concludere dicimur quam
1
rem negare aut veritatem rei But negative statements of this kind are
.
to be received with very great suspicion even when made about the writer s
own language, and the correctness of the expression is, I think, shown by
the citations in Muller Adn. Cr. v, e. g. Ac. 1 32 itaque tradebatur omnis dia-
lecticae disciplina, id est, orationis ratione conclusae, which Reid translates
speech drawn up in syllogistic form ; cf. too Div. I 82 quam (divina-
tionem) esse re vera hoc Stoicorum ratione conduditur, where we might
surely have had quae sentontia rat. concluditur. The phrase occurs in the
more general sense of rounding off in Brutus 34 ipsa natura circum-
sophism by C., unless we except the doubtful passage in Fin. IV 50. The
simple syllogisms of which the sorites is composed are as follows, (1) All
that are blessed are virtuous, the gods are blessed, therefore the gods are
virtuous ; (2) all that are virtuous are rational, the gods are virtuous,
therefore rational ; (3) all that are rational are in the shape of man, the
any one s leave but, though the Inf. with poteram sometimes stands
;
where we might have expected the Plup. Sulij., is there any instance of the
converse? On tuo jure see 77 arripere vcstrojurc n.
quid est istuc gradatim what do you mean by this phrase of :
yours? In the MSS these words stand before sumpsisses, and Walker
followed by Dtivies and Ernesti omitted them as an expression of bewilder
ment on the part of some ignorant fratercidus, but gradatim is not a
particularly puzzling word and the clause comes in quite naturally with
;
by quid cf. JV. D. in 21 cum mundo negas quicquam csse mclius, quid dicis
;
melius ? (Allen).
praecipitare istuc quidem : that is not a step, but a plunge hcr- ,
assensio, tie praeoipitet si temere processerit. On the fallacy known as the sal-
tus or hiatus in demonstrando see Hamilton Logic II p. 51. For the form of
expression cf. Tusc. n 30 optare hoc quidem est, non docerc (Heind.). The
Nom. and Ace. N. both in S. and PI. of the archaic istic are found in C.,
cf. Ac. I 13 istuc quidem considerably Dio. n 35 istuc quidem dicunt, Alt.
xiv non posse istacc sic abirc.
1
quaeres.
video : I see your point ,
almost equivalent to granted .
formam nostrum reliquamque Jiguram in qua csset species Jtonesta, where see
Iloldcn.
nati numquam sunt. Immortality was the most universally accepted
of the divine attributes, but tliis was not understood to mean eternity. On
the contrary, detailed accounts of the birth of the reigning gods of Olympus
were to be found in the poets, and even the primaeval gods were supposed
to have sprung from Earth and Chaos. Yet we find traces of the higher
doctrine, as in the oracle of Dodoua reported by Pausan. x 12 5 Zei/r iyj/,
Z(iis ea-riv, Zfvs facreTai, to /neydXe Zfv ; and Plut. Stoic, licp. 38 p. 1051
treats this as the universally accepted opinion, (frBaprov x.a\ yewrjrov ovSeis,
ws eVros eiVZi>, Siavoelrai (Niig. N. Horn. Theol. pp. 9, 71).
6f6i>
siquidem aeterni sunt futuri : that is, if they are to be eternal (as
you Epicureans hold, cf. 45, 49, 107, 109). The Fut. Part, is used
because the question whether the gods are in future to be called acterrd
BOOK I CH. XXXII 90. 197
would be decided by the fact of their having been born in the past, cf.
103 n.
Moser and Seibt, and, if one may judge from the punctuation, by Scho-
mann, but this seems to me extremely harsh the only possible construc ;
tion is
quam homines ea (forma erant} qua erant forma di.
nostra divina : on the difference between this and the Christian doc
trine, that man is made in the image of God, see below 96 virtus quam
fyura, n.
illud : that other point , used, like e/celi/o, of that which follows, Madv.
485 b.
caeli, quam satus lapeto mistam fluvialibus undis finxit in effigiem mode-
| \
tarn facile vera invenire : see 57, GO with nn. on quid non sit and
Simonides.
Ch. xxxili. etenim commences the refutation, showing how easy
it isfalsa convincere. Like itaque in 85, its force spreads over to the
sentences which follow.
memoriter: exactly = iwqpoviK&s in Plato Polit. 257 B, see Host and
Palm s Lex. Madv. in his n. on Fin. I 34 shows that this is the only
wonder was a matter of choice, and Cobet ( Var. Lcct. p. 4G1) proposes, with
Moser, to read subiret = epoiye 6avpaeiv eirrfkOfv ; but perhaps we may
u>(rr
92. omnesne delirare visi do you mean to say that you thought
:
them all out of their senses] Almost the same thing is said in 94. See
above on the use of ne and cf. istisne 93. On delirare see 42 n. and Ac.
fr. 34 Orelli, roga nunc Stoicum quis sit melior, Epicurusne, qui delirare
ilium clamat, an Academicus.
qui decreverint for deciding even without this causal force, qui,
:
;
special conveniences and adaptations of the limbs in man, are you still
unconvinced (lit. does not even this incline you to judge) that the gods
have no need of human limbs? Hoc is explained by considemnte.?, the
participle here taking the place of
an infinitive or noun in apposition.
The same thought (deos non egere membris) appears in the Timaeus c. 6,
where the formation of the world by the Demiurgus described, nee enim
is
oculis egebat, quia nihil extra, quod cerni posset, relictum erat, nee auribits,
quia ne quod audiretur quidem... nee manus affixit, quoniam nee capiendum
quicquam erat, nee repellendum, nee pedes aut alia membra, quibus ingressum
corporis sustineret.
ingressu the act of walking , so in
: 94 ; incessus is used Off. I 128.
discriptione see 26 n. :
nihil supervacaneum occurs also in 99, n 121 the form super va- ;
nulla manus, nemo opifex consequi possit imitando ; cf. 142 quis vero o^ifex
praetor naturam, qua ni/ul potest esse callidius, tantam sollertiam persequi
potuisset in sensibus. So Aristotle contrasts nature with art, Part. Anim.
BOOK I CH. XXXIII 92. 199
I 1 fia\\ov 8 fVri TO ov tvfKa KOI TO xaXoc ev TOIS TTJS (f)ixTf(os tpyois fj ev rots
rfjs Tfxvrjs, and is never weary of repeating that nature ovdtv TTOKI ntpifpyov
ov8e paTTjv. Not unlike is Bacon s famous aphorism (Nov. Org. i 10),
subtttitas naturae subtilitatem sensus et intellectus multis partihus superat.
habebit igitur loquetur : but in the treatise by Philodemus nrep} rfjs
TO>V
evaro^ov/iej Tjy diayvyfjs Kara ZTJvatva (Here. vol. VI, Naples, 1839)
6ea>v
we read that the gods \eyovrai pr) TroXu 8uxp(povcrais Kara ras dpSpcacrtis
XP*)a6at, <pa>vais,
Kal p6vov oi 8a/zei/ yeyovoTas 6eovs EXXTjz/iSi yXcorr?; xpafMf-
vovs, quoted in Zeller Stoics tr. p. 442. From the fact that the author
here followed by C. takes for granted that the gods are not endued with
the faculty of speech, and that Carneades (ap. Sext. Emp. ix 178) introduces
the idea of their speaking either the Greek, or any other language, as an
absurd consequence which would flow from the assumption of their having
such a faculty 1, Hirzel (p. 172) argues that the dogma reported by
Philodemus must have been a late development in the Epicurean school,
and that it may possibly have been suggested to Zeno by the very argu
ment which Carneades directed against the attribution of speech to the
gods.
93. istisne dixerunt Was it in such dreams as these that they :
put their faith when they spoke against Pythagoras &c. ? For somnia cf.
39, 42.
Metrodorus the most distinguished of the disciples of Epic. d. B.C.
:
277. His fragments have been collected by Duening (Teub. 1870), cf.
H3.
Hennarchus of Mytilene, the successor of Ep., cf. Madv. Fin. n 96.
:
fairly we must remember (1) the strict seclusion imposed upon Athenian
matrons, (2) the esteem in which such a man as Socrates held the Hetaerae
argument of Carneades, as given in the 9th book of Sext. Emp. and yet have ,
believed that Cicero s critique on the Epicurean theology was borrowed from
him. Cam. is impartially destructive ; his opponent is welcome to choose any
view, and he will show that on that view, whatever it may be, the existence of a
deity is impossible Cic. on the contrary is fundamentally Stoical with a slight
:
Academic varnish.
200 BOOK i en. xxxin 93.
Garden indulged : tantum often sums up, or gives the moral, like adeo in
Juvenal.
et soletis
queri and then (after abusing others so freely) you
:
name fathered spurious letters on Ep. with the view of discrediting his
moral character, Diog. L. x 3. For Zeno see 59 n.
Albucius :
praetor in Sardinia B.C. 105, condemned on a charge re-
been educated, and devoted himself to philosophy. His name often occurs
in C. s writings, e.g. Brut. 131 doctus ctiam Graecis T. Alb. vcl potius pacne
nothing could be more refined or courteous, still he used to lose his temper .
Cf. Ac. II 11 Antioclt is, homo natura lenissimus, stomachari tamcn cocpit.
Fam. xin 1 nob is cum pueri essemus, antequam Pliiloncm coynovimus, ralda
ut jrfiilosophus, postea tamcn ut vir bonus ct suavis ct ojiciosus probabatur.
BOOK I CH. XXXIII 93. 201
This was at Rome about B.C. 88, but in 79 C. in company with Atticus
attended lectures at Athens by Zeno and Phaedrus, Fin. I 16 eos cum
Attico nostro frequenter audivi, cum miraretur ille quidem utrumque,
Phacdrum autem etiam amaret, cf. v 3, Leg. I 50, and see Introduction.
Fin.
cum Aristotelem vexarit and yet Epic, attacked A.
: cf.
Eoby ;
ing of Ep. and Metr.) TO. tv avdpanois at o^toTa p^ara, /Sco^oXo^t a?, \TJKV-
6i(Tfj.ovSi a\aoveias,...crvvayay6vTes, ApioroTe Aous Kal SeoKparous Kal ttvdayopov
1
KOI UpaiTayopov KOI Gecxppacrrot; Kal HpaK\fi8ov Kal iTnrapxov, KOL rivos yap
ou^i rtav f rrt^avmv Karfo-KeSao-av
; similarly Plut. (M. 1108) describes the
treatise of Colotes, entitled irepl rov OTI Kara TO. Soypara
ru>v
<iXoo-6(/>o)i>
bodily and mental pleasure, but pleasure which originates ab intra with
that which originates ab extra, but see Hirzel p. 165 foil. Other grounds
of quarrel are mentioned by Duening p. 24. After this breach Tinioc. seems
to have used every effort to injure his former associates, charging them
with debauchery of every kind in his Euphranta, as well as inveighing
against them in public, cf. Alciph. Ep. II 210 TI iroiels, EniKovpt ; OVK
olcrQa OTI StctKco/iwSet ere Tt/ioicpar^s or! TOVTOIS tv rats cK/cA^cri mr, ev rois
202 BOOK i CH. xxxin 93.
qui cum unum secutus esset, nollem vituperatum. Both Metr. and Ep.
wrote against Democ. but this was probably to make it evident where
their system differed from his, as opponents charged them with being
mere plagiarists (Duen. p. 36). Plutarch, in reporting the charges
brought against Democr. by Colotes, mentions that Epicurus long
called himself a follower of Democr., and that Leonteus, one of his most
p. 47, and cf. the phrase ypa/^/xartKi) ypaokoyla Sext. Emp. Math. I 141 ; so
Zeno is styled \ixvoypavs by Timon ap. Diog. L. vn 15.
94. tamquam senatum recitares : like the censor when he reads
out the of the senate, cf. Liv.
list 23, xxix 37, Pro Domo 84 Sch. xxm .
fjiopcpcov, a>(rn-fp
KOI xpei a? /cat Sandvas, and col. xiv if God has the eyes of a
Scip. i and Apul. Dog. Plat. II 10, but both writers take care to use the
8,
preferable form within a few lines of the other; see Nagels. Stil. 33 u.
In 100 we have beatum used to express the same idea. [Beata vita is C. s
usual equivalent for ev&upoyub J. S. R.]
[usu mollienda : cf. Ac. u 18 visumjam enim hoc pro (pavracria, ver-
bum satis hesterno usu trivimus. J. S. R.]
verum resumptive after parenthesis, Madv. 480.
:
quae sola divina natura est: for this blessed and eternal nature
alone possesses the attributes of deity Cf. 4!)
quae sit beata natura. .
Sch. in loc. (and opusc. p. 319) strangely takes quae as a neuter plural
predicate, and sola divina natura as feminine singular subject. Can there
be a doubt that quae is Xom. Sing., referring to the preceding beata et
aetcrna natura, and forming the subject to the divina natura following,
which is also Xom. I
compound nature (i. e. the body) nor in both parts, for then God too would
be compound, but in the inue r man -netftvm Ti yiyvftrQai HOT eucoca rov
Ch. xxxv. 97. ipsa vero similitudo: how little to the point is
even the argument from likeness of w hich you make so much ipsa con
r
;
trasts the general theory with the special instance in dispute, viz. the
resemblance between man and God. I understand here a reference to the
Epicurean logic of induction, cf. nn. on 70, 87, 89.
simia quam similis cf. Plin. N. II. xi 100, Arist. Hist. An. II 8, and
:
av6pu>na>v
o cro^curaroy Ttpos 6f!>v
7ri0r]Kos (fravtlrat Kcii crcxjbi a KOL KaAAft KOI
mis- (fAXoij Trncriv. [And Pindar Pyth. II 131 ndXos TOI irlQuiv Trapa TraitrtV,
vastior
ungainly clumsy cf. J)e Orat. i 115 (of awkward speakers)
:
, ,
sunt quidam ita vultu motuquc corporis vasti atque agrestes ; \\1vastmn
hominem; Orator 153 vcster Axilla Ala foetus cst fuga litterae vastioris
(the awkward x).
98. moribus paribus. I think Klotz s suggestion paribus is better
than similliinis, which is usually supplied, not only because it would be
BOOK I CH. XXXV 98. 205
more easily lost after moribus, but because it makes a better antithesis to
simillimis dispares.
quodsi obsistis if you are proof against all these inferences (lit.
:
hold your ground in all these cases), why should you be shaken by the
figure only ? i. e. why allow that inference to weigh with you ?
his adjunctis videbas you never saw human reason except in
:
considered, though to little purpose). For the ironical nisi forte cf.
117.
uno digito plus: a single finger too much ,
Abl. of Measure. Cf.
II 92 sol multis partibus major quam terra, Liv. n 7 uno plus Etruscorum
cecidit, Eoby 1204. We may understand quam satis est, as often, for the
second member of comparison.
quia nee desiderant : because the five leave no need for (lit. do not
miss) another, either in respect of beauty or utility .
capite cruribus :
repeating 92.
ut immortalis sit if he has these limbs
(v. subaud. from redundat
:
si,
as from quaeres 90) in order to make him immortal cf. for omission of ;
vultus.
vitae firmitatem :
vitality ,
so we find firm, joined with corporis,
capitis, valetudinis.
Ch. xxxvi 100. et eos vituperabas. The reference is to 53.
For the et indignantis cf. et nunc 91 n.
aberrant a conjectura miss their aim This is the reading of all the
: .
MSS, but Sch. following Walker omits the preposition, and translates go
wrong in their guessing In his Opusc. in 321 and 307 he stoutly maintains
.
(against Wopkens, Heind. and Klotz^lo??i. Crit. n 12) that the other reading
makes nonsense and he would therefore correct 12 Phil. 23 mine, quaeso,
;
attcndite num abcrrct a conjectura suspitio periculi mei, and Att. xiv 22 vercor
ne nihil a conjectura aberrem, where Wesenberg keeps the preposition. I have
myself very little faith in these a priori reasonings as to the impossibility
of a word acquiring any particular use. It seems to me more improbable
that the scribes should in several passages have inserted the preposition,
without any inducement that I can see, than that conjectura should come to
mean hitting the mark as in fact Quintilian says ill G 30 conjectura dicta
,
appears to consider utility the main cause Pint. 1. c. laughs at the story of;
the transformation of the gods in fear of Typhon, and says the real causes are
TO xpfioiSes KOI TO (TVufBoXiKov, evia darepov, TroXXa np.(pulv p.fTf(T\r]K
a>v
;
ra rotavra SiSacrKoxrii/ ,
and Arnobius uses similar language, Aegyptiorum
mdetis aenigmata quod mutorum animantium formas divinis inseruerint
causis, in 15.
quam caperent :
Subj. after Indefinite Eelative.
velut : cf. 2 n.
ibes cf. Juv. xv 3 saturam serpentibus ibin with Mayor s n. and the
:
Herod. (Vol. n p. 125) it is stated that the Turks still consider it a sin to
kill an ibis, and that Cuvier found the skin of a snake in the stomach of a
mummied ibis. Plut. 1. c. mentions another reason for gratitude to the ibis,
to which C. also alludes II 126.
vim serpentium see : 54 n.
cum sint being tall : birds , &c., explains how they were able to kill
the snakes, Eoby 1728.
cum interficiunt. The Pres. and Perf. Ind. are used with cum to
express identity of action (Roby 1729). In killing the snakes they are
averting the plague.
volucres angues Herodotus (1. c. and in 107 foil.) tells wonderful
:
ix 6), and that it enters the mouth of the sleeping crocodile and devours
its heart and entrails (Strabo, xvn 39).
crocodile had rendered a service to one of their ancient kings ; Plut. on the
other hand explains their worship as symbolical the crocodile is ni^na ;
6eov as being 5-yXaxrcroj and therefore silent, and as watching his prey,
208 BOOK I CII. XXXVI 101.
o-vn(3epr)Kti>,
Isid. c. 7"), p. 381.
faelium : see Herod, n GO, G7 with the notes in Rawlinson s ed. and the
exhaustive note in Mayor s Juvenal, xv 7. The word appears to be used
for a kind of weasel in Varro and Columella, Init in other writers it stands
for the Gr. aiAovpor, the tame cat of the Egyptians see the graphic descrip ;
tion in Plin. N. If. x c. 94 fades quidcm quo sifcntio, quam levibus vestigiis
proper contrary of negotium, and Ep. did not deny that activity might be
essential to human happiness, cf. Plut. Tranq. c. 2, p. 4G5.
Ch. xxxvii. exercitatione ludicra some active game :
,
see Madv.
Fin. i G9. [Is it not rather some game which simulates real life 1 J. S. E.]
deum possit : in or. rect. this would be dcus sic torpet ut, si se com-
movcrit, beatus csse non possit such is the nature of the divine inertia that
movement would destroy the happiness which is of the essence of deity .
In order that this may be stated as an opinion, not a fact, volumus is added
to the 1st clause, and vcrcamur to the 2nd, but the latter is improperly
made the governing verb, so as apparently to give the measure of sic,
whereas it ought to have been introduced parenthetically (qucm ad modum
(deum contrasted with pueri) see Zumpt 781. For the Ind. volumus see
80 n. on arbitramur.
ne non used rather than ut after vereamur, because of the ut pre
:
At any rate where is he ? How does he spend his life 1 What are the
sources of the blessedness you attribute to him ? E,.]
actio vitae cf. 2, n. 45. :
Sci. i 35 foil.
infimum : i. e. the centre, cf. n 84, 116 (medium infimum in sphaera est),
Arist. Gael, iv 4.
inundet : more commonly used of excessive floods.
doubt as to the origin of the MS reading the eye of the scribe passed :
from the eri of superior to the same letters in the following word. On the
ig. aeth. cf. n 101 foil.
M. C. 14
210 BOOK I CTT. XXXVII 103.
trvpos 77-7780
KCI\ /3n<VVt ;
then to prove that some animals can exist in firo
wai TO TTi-p. Pliny (^V. //. xi 42) calls this fire-born creature pijrausta or
py ralis : he has many wonderful stories about the .salamander (x 8G, xi
116, xxix 23) but never speaks of itsbeing produced from fire, while Aelian
ovde e CIVTOV TiKTfTai, caanfp ol KaXovp.evoi nvpiyovoi, 6appfl fie avro, &C.
In ii 42 the stars are said to be the denizens of aether.
naturae accoinmodatum=oj\-Toz/. On this Stoic doctrine cf.
104.
Maclv. Fin. in 16, v 24 (omni animali illud quod appctit podium, est in eo
quod naturae cst accommodatuni], Exc. iv, Ac. n 33, N. D. ill 33.
denique postremo so Ayr. n 02 rcgna denique, postrcmo etiam
:
vcctigalia, Cat. n
25 dcnique acquitas, tcmperantia certant cum iniquitate,
postremo copia cum cffestate,... bona dcnique spcs cum desperatione, N. D. m
23 omni denique doctrina eruditus, postremo p/tilosopkus crit mundus.
ulcus est it will not bear handling , is
: unsound ulcus like vidnus ;
ratione docentur ct via, primum constituendum cst quid quidque sit; nisi
cnim inter cos, qui disccptant, convcnit, quid sit illud de quo ambigitur,
nee rccte disseri, nee umquam ad exitum pcrveniri potest (see Schutz Lcx.\
also N, D. ill 36 vidcamus exitum, I 107 exitum repcritis, 53 explicare
arguments exitum. [Add Ac. II 36 exitum non habebunt. J. S. R.]
105. sic enim dicebas : cf. 49 with the notes.
for the production of mental (as opposed to visual) images (lit. only for
the thinking faculty).
eminentiam : sec n. on eminentis 75.
in Lat. and Gr. thus we find imroKtvravpos used by Plato and Xenophon,
;
motum inanem : the Kfvonddeia of Sext. Emp. Math. VIII 184, cf. Ac.
n 47 conantur ostendere multa posse videri esse, quae omnino nulla suit
cum animi inaniter moveantur, and 34 with Reid s nn.
106. ut igitur Ti. Gracchum intellegantur. I am disposed to
agree with Klotz (Adn. n 15) as against Madv. ap. Orelli (who is followed
by Sch. Baiter and Miiller) and should translate the passage as follows In :
the same way then as, when I imagine myself to see Gracchus in his speech
presenting the voting urn about (to decide the case of) Octavius, I at the
time assert this to be a mere groundless fancy, while you on the contrary
assert that the images of the two men continue to exist, and after arriving
in the Capitol are then carried on to me, so (you assert it to be) in the
case of God, whose recurring likeness strikes upon the mind and leads it
to recognize the divine blessedness and eternity . The simple framework
of the sentence would be ut Ti. Gracchum cum videor videre... motum animi
dico esse inanem, tu autcm imagines ad animum meum referri ; sic in deo
dicimiis ego motum inanem fieri, tu crebra facie pelli animos, but C. after
giving both the Academic and Epicurean views in the compared case
of Gracchus, omits the former, as obvious, in the case of the gods, and
so confuses the construction. Madv. omits igitur, which connects the
special application with the general principle, takes ut=velut, as in 88
ut Serif hi, and changes pervenerint into pervenerim, making hoc fieri a
sort of corollary depending on dicis understood, instead of the apodosis of
the sentence. Sch. (N. Jahrb. 1875, p. 691) points out that there is no
occasion for pervenerim, the scene might be imagined without going to the
Capitol, though it is true a visit there might suggest it on the other hand ;
was stopped by the veto of Octavius his colleague in the tribunate after a :
vain attempt to induce him to desist from his opposition, G. proposed his
deposition by the tribes. When 17 out of the 35 tribes had voted for the
motion, G. once more urged 0. to yield, but he answering complete what
1
thou hast begun ,
the voting was continued and 0. deposed.
in Capitolio. We read of the Comitia Tributa being held in the
Capitol in Liv. xxv 3 cum dies advenisset, conciliumque tarn frequens plebis
adesset ut multitudinem area Capitolii vix capcret, siteUa lata est ut sortiren-
tur ubi Latini suffragium ferrent, xxxm
25 ea rogatio in Capitolio ad
phbem lata est, XLIII 16 ex Capitolio ubi erat concilium (plebis} abiit, XLV
36 cum in Capitolio rogationem tribunus plebis ferret, xxxiv 53 ea bina,
comitia Cn. Domitius praetor urbanus in Capitolio hab.uit, App. Bell. Civ.
I 15 (Gracchus) Kare Aa/3f TOU KaTrerwX/ou rov vav, evda xfiporovrjcrfiv
e/ieXXov, Plut. Ti. Gracch. 17 Trpo/yft fie O^LOK TOV dfj^ov rjOpoiadai
az>co,
142
212 LOOK I CTT. XXXVIII lOo.
The Comitia Tributa were also held in the Campus Martins (Fam. vn 30),
and the Circus Flaminius (Liv. xxvn 21) as well as in the Forum.
sitellam :
(dim. of situla a bucket
with water (vfyn a) in )
an urn filled
which were placed the wooden lots to determine the order of voting of the
tribes. The neck was made so narrow that only one lot could come to the
surface, see Diet, of Ant.
remanere : so Plat. Dcf. Or. 19 p. 420 speaks of TO. ( WcoXa aTrXeVovr eVcSf
intcllcgant. For the pi. beati after s. deo cf. 50 Balbe solctis n.
images of men, Homer &c., should be coming in contact with me, yet
all
not in the shape which they had when alive ? I have here accepted the
emendation quam before omnium, but the reading of the liss is tenable
if we put a mark of interrogation after
possit, and take omnium incidere as
an exclamatory Inf. This would justify the rather exaggerated omnium,
which is placed in sharp contrast with me : there is no excuse for Baiter s
feeble hominum. In denying the resemblance between the image and the
object, C. anticipates the result of the reasoning which follows: we see
the images of that which is non-existent, and impossible, of scenes and
persons unknown to us and these images differ for different people
; ;
BOOK I CH. XXXVIII 107. 213
quo modo illi ergo : sc. inciderunt, how then (if there is no resem
blance between the images and their originals) did the originals come into
3
my head?
et quorum imagines. Allen considers the passage corrupt, as it has
been already stated that the images are those of Homer &c. I think it
may be defended as asking for a nearer definition of the omnium above,
and so preparing the way for the question which follows when you say :
say are Homer s &c. come, but are not like Homer s then two
real form,
[Accepting quam I would read omnino for omnium (a very common corrup
1
tion). Then the ex of MSS is evidently a mere doubling of the ec in nee. For
nee ex I would read nedum, which is very frequently written necdum in MSS. The
meaning would be what is more improbable than that phantoms of Homer etc.
should strike on my senses at all, to say nothing of their retaining just the shape
those persons had when alive? Then for illi I should read illae, referring on to
Orpheus Scylla, etc. The e would be easily dropped before ergo, and the unin
telligible ilia would be altered to illi which the scribes referred to Homer etc.
wrongly. Thus the argument rises from one stage of difficulty to another,
putting aside the cases of Homer etc. all of whom we admit to have once
existed, what have you to say about persons and places which never existed at
all? It is quite in Cicero s style to break the continuity of the argument by the
insertion of quid quod tuum. The De Finibus contains many things of this
kind. J. S. It.]
214 BOOK i cir. xxxviii 107.
is probable that different treatises may have been cited in it, some of
which were attributed Onom. as the Xpr/cr/ioi and TtXerm, and some to
to
Cercops as the Itpos Xdyoy and (G^ae cos) Kora/3a<7is fls afiov, see Clem.
Strom. I 397 and Suidas quoted in Lobeck 1. c. On the Orphic doctrines
generally, and on the connexion
between the Orphic school and the Pytha
compare Lobeck I.e. Zcller I p. 71 foil. Dollinger Gentile and Jew
goreans,
I bk. 3, p. l-.">,
tr. Herod, n 81 (on the prohibition of woollen garments)
o/ioXoyeouo-i fie raura rolcri Op(iKoi(Ti KuXeo/ieVois Kai BUK^IKOUTI, e oCcrt fie
AlyvnTioi<Ti
Kai Hvdayopfioun. The mass of what has come down to us
under the name of
5
108. quid, quod ejusdem Chimaerae cf. n 5, find Die. n 138 : istac
imagines ita nobis dicto audicntes sunt, ut, simul atque vclimus, accurrant?
etiamne carum rerum quao nullae sunt? quao est cnim forma tarn invisitata,
tarn mdla, quam non sibi ipse fingcrc animus possit ? ut, quae numquam
vidimus, ca tamen informata habeamus, oppidorum situs, hominum figuras ?
num igitur cum aut muros Babylonis aut Homeri facicrn cogito, imago illo-
rum me aliqua pellit? omnia igitur, quae volumus, nota nobis csse possunt.
Lucretius iv 732 meets these and similar arguments. Centauros itaque ct
Sci/llarum membra videmus Cerbcreasque canum fades simulacraquecorum\
\
quorum morte obita tcllus amplectitur ossa : omne genus quoniam passim \
simulacra feruntur, partim sponte sua quae iiunt acre in ipso, partim
\ \
figuris, as the Centaurs from the mingling of human and equine images.
\
quas numquam vidimus : this argument, of which Sch. failed to see the
force, is more fully stated at the end of the passage from the DC Div. given
above.
simul ac mihi collibitum So Lucr. iv 779 quaeritur in primis est.
locis in quisque parata. but because they are so fine, the mind can only
\
see those which it strains itself to sec, 802; cf. Fain, xv 10.
ad dormientem Lucr. iv 757. :
inculcatis you cram these images into our minds as well as into our
:
eyes , cf. Fat. 6 quid attinet inculcare fatum, cum sine fato ratio omnium
rerum ad naturam fortunamve referatur ? Cotta in his jaunty way treats
this quite as a new idea, but it has been assumed throughout the discus
sion ;
cf. 105 intenta mens, ad cogitationem, adventum in animos,pellantur
animi &c. It is one of the many marks of haste which disfigure the book.
quo modo aeternae : the omission of sunt makes the change of con
struction unusually harsh.
suppeditat there is an endless supply of atoms
: .
opponi fingirnus, sive id ab uno seu pluribus, sine ab absente seu praescnte
fiat, adding many exx.
num. sempiterna do you mean to say then that everything will be
:
eternal for the same reason ? The infinity of the atoms is given by Veil.
1. c. as an
explanation of the continuous stream of images, and apparently
as suggesting the eternity of the Being revealed to us in them ; so Philod.
p. 110 the divine individuality (iSioT^s) having its origin in the resem
blance of the images may exist in perfect blessedness for ever . Sch.
denies this, and says that the Epicurean argument for the eternity of the
Gods is (1) the TrpoA^i? (2) lo-ovopia. But the TrpoAjj-v//-!? is simply the
unconscious effect of experience,
i. e. of the
impression of the images on the
mind, and Ivovopia is mentioned in 50 as the ground of the infinite
number, not of the infinite duration, of immortal beings. It is probable
however, as stated in the note there, that C. has wrongly spoken of beings
instead of forces, and we may therefore allow lo-ovopia to stand as one of
the arguments. A
third argument (denied by Sch.) was the fineness of the
atoms of which the Gods were composed, see 71 n.
aequilibritatem cf. 50 ; the word appears to be
: OTT. Xfy. though
Vitruvius uses aequilibris.
isto modo sint aliqui immortales according to that, since men :
et quia sunt sentio and since there are destructive forces, there
:
are also (or reading sint with some of the best MSS., let there be also )
216 BOOK I CH. XXXIX 109.
Gods whereas the Epicurean Gods were confessedly free from the toils of
;
debcro.
110. omnis tamen oritur : however (to leave the Gods and return
to the question asked in 107), how do you explain the origin of your
object-pictures generally out of the atoms ?
effigies oritur is a loose expres
sion for effigiatus (or cffictio) fit.
etiamsi essent, quae nulla sunt cf. Liv. n 71 ut sint auspicia, quae :
sine virtute vita for the omission of the verb in these short clauses
:
moral and intellectual virtues (Part. Or. 76) est igitur vis virtutis duplex :
aut enim scientia cernitur virtus, aut actione. Nam quae prudentia...appel-
latur, haec scientia pallet una: quae vcro moderandis cupiditatibus regen-
disque animi molibus laudatur, ejus est munus in agenda, and it is the
former virtue only which belongs to divinity, according to Aristotle, T 8f/
feopTi TOV irpaTTfiv affoaipovntvov, tri 8f fiaXXov TOV TroifiV, T I AeiTrerat ir\fjv
6fa>pia
wore ij TOV 6(uv eWpyeta, /laKapior^ri SirKpepoucra, 6(a)pr)TiKr) av tlr],
;
E. N. x 8.
vowel after actuosa, and change into ct] as it introduces a minor premiss in
a quasi-syllogistic argument. But where one syllogism is subordinated to
another (as in this passage virtus autem igitur represents the minor
premiss in the syllogism of which sine virtute nullo modo is the major, and
ne beatus quidem the conclusion) it is not uncommon to omit the signs of
opposition between the propositions of the subordinate syllogism thus, :
A, none are happy without virtue B, but virtue is active and your God ;
tas animi et molestiam dolor aferat, eorum tamen utrumque et ortum esse e
see Madv. in loc. and on n 7 and 92, also Plut.
corpore et ad corpus referri,
J/. p. 1089 TO pfv rj86fj.fvov TTJS <rapKos
T xat poi/Ti T V S ^ V X*I S vTrepeidovTts,
avdis 8" (K TOV xa l
P ovroy e s T jdofjievov rfj i\Tridi reXeimuirer quoted by
ZeUer Epic. p. 452 tr.
quos pudeat most of the editors spoil the irony of the passage by
:
quod sit ullum bonum praeter illud, quod cibo et potione et aurium delecta-
cf. Epic. Trepl TtXovs quoted by Diog. L. x 6 and more fully by Athen. vn
p. 280 ou yap lycoye e^o) Tt J/OTJCTCO rdyadov, dcpaipav ray 8ia ^vAcoi ySovas, /iei>
dfpaipcav Se Taj Si a^>poSt(rica , Kai ras 81 (cat Tar 8ta fjiopfpfjs, d<poa[j.dTu>i>
which translated in the Tusc. in 41, see Fin. n 29, Ac. I 7 with Reid s n.
is
112.
perfundas voluptatibus to steep them in pleasure , cf. :
of the question as to food and drink quidem of course points the contrast ;
the general sense cf. Tusc. i 65 non cnim ambrosia dcos aut ncctarc aut
Juventate pocula ministrante lactari arbitror, nee Homcnnn audio, qui
Ganymcden ab dis raptum ait propter formam ut Jovi bibere ministraret,
113. at has sensibus :
your answer is that you count these as
inferior pleasures which merely tickle the sense . Titill. is C. s translation
for Epicurus yapyaXttr/xoi aw/iarov (Clcomccles 91, Athen. Cyd. Thcor. II 1
xn 54(5) ;
he uses always with the apologetic quasi (Fin. 1 39, Tusc. in 47,
it
i 47 he
Off. II 63, Scncct. 47) in employs the phrase dulcedo haec ct
; Lc<j.
such) for Ph. too could not stand Epicureans affecting to repudiate effemi
nate pleasures he would quote verbatim many sayings of Ep. to the same
;
effect . For ludis cf. 123: nam refers to pronuntiabat in the second
clause, the first clause taking the place of some such form as indiynatus,
cf. n.on itaque 85. Etiam implies I am not the only one to feel impa
tience at this shuffling For Philo see .
6, 59.
Metrodori : cf. 93 and Duelling pp. 47 51, where the following
fragments occur, irepl yaarlpa yup, &j (^uuioXdye Ti/io*pare r, TO dyndov (Plut.
M. 1098 B), TTfpl yaore pa, (fovcrLoXoye Ti/4., Trepl yatrrtpa 6 Kara a>
<j)v<Tiv
/3atb>i>
anacrav f%(i tnravbqv (Athen. VII 280, XII 546), ra KaXa
Xoyo? rfjv
Travra Kai cro(pa KOL TrepiTTa rfjs "^vxrjs (^(vpr^icna rrjs Kara crdpKa ijdovfjs eW/ca
K.a.1 TJJS f\Trios TTJS
VTttp TavTrjs (rvvftrravai KOI Trav dvai Ktvuv epyov, o ^JLTJ i$
TOVTO KClTdTflVfL (PI lit. M. 1125 B), OK KOI f)(ClpTJV KOI f6pa<TVVn^LT]V,
OTl ffJ.a6oV
TOVS "EXX^rar, oiJ5 eVi (ro0ia aT(f>ava)v Trap* avru>v rvy\avfiv, dXX ((rditiv
Kal Trivfiv oivov, TifjiuKpuTfs, a^XajSwf TT) yaarpl Kai Ace^aptcr/ieVcoy Plut. M.
<S
1125 D, also Plut. N. 1087, 1108, and Hirzel p. 165, Tusc. \ 27, Fin. II 92.
collega sapientiae so Fin. n 92 paene alter Epicurus. The two were :
cf. Deniosth. Cor. p. 324 rrj yaarpl ^.trpovvrfs Kal ruls atcr^tOTotj TTJV euSai-
fioviav. Allen quotes Varro ap. Non. i 273 quibus modulus cst vitae culina.
Dubito in this sense is generally followed by the Inf. in a negative sentence,
more rarely in a positive sentence Draeg. ( 424 8 d) cites Curtius as the ;
earliest instance of the latter, but, besides the present passage, Reid on
Lad. I quotes Sail. Cat. 15. [See also Att. x 3 a, venire dubitarint quoted
by G. Miiller, Progr. d. Gymnas. zu Gorlitz 1878. Iv,]
ne beatos qiiidem wanting in happiness also (as well as :
pleasure),
cf. 72.
Ch. XLI 114. abundantem bonis : cf. omnibus bonis afflucns 50.
cogitat : on the sing, following pi. vacant cf. 50 Balbe soletis n.
mini pulchre est : a colloquial phrase how jolly this is cf. Mur. 26 !
but there was in all probability a party among the Epicureans who had
accepted a modification of the less vulnerable Democritian theology ( 120).
This latter is apparently the view propounded in 49, but the criticism
here is directed against the former.
ex ipso imagines affluant : cf. Lucr. vi 76 nee de corpore quae sancto
simulacra feruntur \
in mentes hominum divinae nuntia formae, &c.
piety. Yes, but how 1 In a manner entirely inconsistent with his general
theory, so thatyou might fancy yourself listening to C. or S. Diog. L. x
27 mentions a treatise of Ep. Trepi oo-toY^roy, and Philod. often refers to his
teaching on the subject, as in p. 104 on p.ev opuois /cat eTrippiya-eo-ii* 6e<av
yu>yal ia(ra<povcriv, p. 120 (Ep. laid down the plain rule) on Set iravra
irfidfcrdai rols vop,ois Ka\ roly fdicrp.ois ecas av /juj
TL rutv acre/Scoi/ TrpooTarraxrti ,
wisdom with Lycurgus, Solon, Cato, &c. (De Oral, in 56), noticed as espe
cially beloved by the gods (JV. D. n 165), as an authority in religious
matters (in 5).
Scaevolam P. Mucius Sc. (father of C. s friend and patron the Pont.
:
Max. Q. Mucius Sc.) was consul in B.C. 133, the year in which Tib.
Gracchus lost his life, succeeded his brother Mucianus in the Pontificate
B.C. 131, so famed for his knowledge of law that he is called one of the
homines non colant: for the play on words cf. Ov. Met. 724 vm
euro, pii dis sunt ct qui coluere coluntur ; Sch. quotes Plaut. Poen. V 4 14
Juppitcr qui genus colis alisque homimim ; <T({3r6ai has a similar reciprocal
use in Aesch. Prom. 545 dvarovs Hyav affifi.
110. at est : cf. 45, and Philod. p. 128 quoted on 115.
cujus nullum meritum sit. The reason for this relative clause being
prefixed to the antecedent, is probably to give it greater emphasis, as the
climax.
TUIV dvBpanraiv Trpos re dXX^ Xous Kal Trpos deovs flcrij<Tat, d p.ij fieri. 0eoi,
ovSe 8i<aLocrvvij (rvarrja-fTai. The definition is attributed to the Stoics
by Stob. Ed. n 124, but it occurs (amongst others) in Plato Euthyphro 12,
where TO euo-f/3er ocriov (they are not distinguished) is explained as that
<al
part of justice (righteous dealing) which is concerned with 1-17 1/ ru>v 6fa>v
6fpd7r(iav, cf. Protag. 331. So we frequently find TO. Trpos TOVS avdpwnovs
SiVaia contrasted w ithra npos TOVS dtovs vena. If one may venture to say
r
so, C. seems to have been unfortunate in his translation of the Greek terms :
erga deos pietas nisi honcsta de numine corum ac mente ojiinio, cum expcti
nikil ab Us, quod sit injustum atque inhoncstum, arbitrarc, which approaches
more to Epictetus definition of evVt/Seia, Ench. 31, opQas vVoX^fir Trtpl
6ea>i>
(%fiv, (os ofTQiv Kai dioiKOvvTtov ra oXa KaXwj KU\ Sixatcos 1
common possession of reason, inter quos autem ratio, inter eosdcm ctiam recta
ratio est communis. Quae cum sit lex, lege quoque consociati homines cum dis
putandi sumus, and so we arrive at the grand Stoic description of the
world as the civitas communis deorum atque hominum 23; (3) their com
mon kinship, ut homines deorum ajnatione et gente teneantur, see Dumesnil
in loc.
sanctitas deorum so Sext.
Emp. c. tort yap eJo-e ,36ta rVrmf/ii}
: 1.
VII 119, borrowed however from Socrates, see Xeu. Mem. IV G 4 6 apa ra irep\
TOVS deovs i>6p.ip.a
flo cas 6pd<as
av r)p.~iv fvcrffirjs (opi.crp.evos f irj, and Plato
Euthyphro 14 (ocriorqra) fm.cmjij.riv riva TOV 6i,tiv re Kal fC^tcrdai. The
explanation of this rather inappropriate definition must be sought in the
Socratic and Stoical identification of virtue and knowledge (Zeller Socr.
p. 143 tr., Stoics p. 239). In the Plane. 80 Cic. asks qui sancti, qui religionum
colentcs nisi qui meritam dis immortalibus gratiamjustis honoribus et memori
mente persolvunt.
BOOK I CH. XLII 117. 221
Ch. XLII 117 quid est quod: see 3 n. and compare the Fr. qu est
actura sit in 116 and videantur in 55 but in both those passages the ;
adoring the gods when you leave nothing adorable in their nature? For
in doing away with the divine attributes, you do away not only with
superstition but with religion itself.
quod soletis referring to the following liberari.
: For the matter
see nn. 54 and 56.
cui neutrum licuerit cf. quod liqueat 29, : so deliquesce makes delicui,
Ov. Met. IV 253, vn 381.
and Euhemerus, as C. does here, and goes on to say that Critias, one of the
Thirty, must be classed among them, as he held that of rraXatol vopodtTai
eVuTKOTroc riva rQ>v
dvdpanrLvav KaTopd<j>p.aTa>v
Kal a/iapr^/iarcui/ eTrXacrai/
TOV 6eov, iiirtp TOV /z^Sti/a Xd$pa TOV irXijcriov dftiKflv, (v\a^oii[j.(vov rf]v VTTO
Tatv 6iu>v
rificapiav. In proof of this he quotes from the Sisyphus (a 5pa/xa
attributed by others to Euripides, cf. Plut. M. 879 E) rr*
i p.fv of VO/JLOI. \ djrfjyov avToiit epya HT/ Trpacrvfiv $iq, | Xa^pa
8 enpaffffov, rr^viKavra P.OL 8oKfl \
TTVKVOS TIS aXXo? *ral crofpos yv(op.r)v dvjp \
placed the Gods in the region of storms and lightning in order to make
them more terrible. Plato alludes to this theory of religion Leg. x 889 E,
6eovs flvai Trpcoroi/ (paariv OVTOI Tf^vrj, ov (pv cret dXXa ricrt vopois, KOI TOVTOVS
u\\ovs aXXoty, OTTT; txacrroi eavrols crvva>iJ.o\6yr](rav vop.o6fToi/p.fvot. Kai Si) KU\
TO Ka\a (ftixrfi fjitv dXXa eiVai, vop.a>
8f erfpa.
Prodicus: see Introd. and Art. by Brandis in Diet, of Biog. His name
appears in the fragments of Philocl. pp. 112 and 76 (quoted in n. on 38),
cf. also p. 71 and Sext. Emp. Math. IX 18 ITpoStKo? o Kelor, 17X101;, $770-1, KOI
Fel. c. 21. Pcrsacus ( 38) find other Stoics had the same belief (n CO, Flut.
M. 378).
habita: referring to the time when the worship was introduced.
119. fortes ad deos pervenisse. It has been already stated
( 38, 39) that Persaeus and Chrysippus held this view, which is also
maintained by Balbus (n 62), cf. Zeller Stoics, p. 330, Dollinger Gentile
and Jew I p. 343, II 32, 1(55 foil. but it would seem that C. has wrongly ;
identified with theirs the doctrine of Euhemerus, who ace. to Sext. 1. c. sup
posed this worship to have been instituted during the life-time of its founders,
ot Tr(piyfv6p.fvoi r<av aXXav la^vi Km avve<Tfi, coo-re Trpusra \ni aVTOV Kf\tvo-
fj.fva ifavras fiiovv, (nrovfti i^ovres /jLei^avos QuvfJ.a<T/j.ov Ka\ <rt
^.VOTTJTOS rv^fiv,
dvfTv\arrav TTtpl avrovs VTTfp/iiiXXoucrai Tiva KU\ Qfiav 8vvap.iii, tvOfv Kai. rols
TroXXoi? evop.iadr](Tav deol,
Euhemerus fl. 300 B.C., sent on an exploring expedition to the Red
:
temple of Zeus Triphylius, iil)i aurcam columnam positam csse ab ipso Jove
titulus indicabat ; in qua columna gesta sua perscripsit ut monimentum
cssct posteris rcrum suannn, Lact. i 11. Euhemerus is the chief repre
sentative of the pragmatizing or rationalistic mythologists, but traces of
the same tendency may be seen in Hecataeus and Herodotus, and much
more in Ephorus, and Dionysius of Miletus, whose Atlantis is described
by Diod. n 51, 55 foil. Cf. Keightley Mythol. c. 2, Dullinger I.e. i 345,
Zeller $oc. p. 343 tr.
/Ltvoraywyos came to mean no more than cicerone. But the form of initia
tion was always required, the uninitiated could only enter the temple at
the peril of their lives, as is shown by the fate of the two Acarnanians
whose death led to the war between Athens and Macedonia B.C. 200
(Liv. xxxi 14).
Samothraciam Lemni: these islands together with Imbros were
the seat of the Cabiric worship, on which see Doll. 1. c. p. 164 foil., Lobeck
Agl. p. 11091329, Preller Gr. Myth. I 660673. Herodotus n 51 is the
firstwho mentions the Samothracian mysteries. Preller thinks that these
were not of much importance till after the Persian War, and that they
were partly copied from the Eleusinia. Aristophanes (Pax 278) speaks of
the Samothracian initiation as a safeguard in danger especially at sea, as
;
we learn from other sources, cf. N. D. in 89. Under the Macedonian and
Roman rule (partly owing to the supposed connexion of Rome with Troy)
these mysteries were continually growing in importance. See Liv. XLV. 5,
Galen De usu part, xvn 1, Juv. in 144 jures licet et Samothracum et nos-
22-t BOOK I CH. XLII 119.
trorum aras. Lobeck denies that there was any difference between the
Samothracian and Lemnian mysteries 1 The latter are only mentioned
.
before his eyes, carried away with him no distinct ideas beyond the
suggestion of a future life of happiness which was iu store for the
initiated, the Stoics (as Dollinger says, p. 198) regarded them as symboliz
ing the truth that the gods were merely a portion of the material universe ;
the Peripatetics as showing that God had laid the foundation of civilization
in agriculture; the Euhemerists that the objects of worship were only
deified the Pythagoreans and New Platonists that the secret of all
men ;
religions was contained in the ancient theology of Egypt and the East.
Plutarch expressly says that he who would rightly understand and profit by
the mysteries must take with him Xo-yoi/ e* <iAoo-o0i as /iucrraycoyoj/ (Is. c. 68).
For exx. of the physical interpretation here referred to by C. cf.
Lobeck 1. c. p. 136 foil, who quotes Themistius Or. 29 for the view of
Prodicus that the mysteries only referred to the operations of agriculture ;
quas Plato appcllat ideas ; caelum Jovem, tcrram Junoncrn, ideas Nincrcam
vult intelligi ; somewhat different is the account given by the same author
in Ling. Lat. V 58, terra cnim ct caclum, ut Samothracum initia docent
sunt Dei Magni et hi quos did multis nominibus ; so Plut. (el ap. Delph.
p. 389) speaks of the Zagreus myth as symbolizing the divine soul of the
world which is ever clothing itself in new shapes.
1
See on the other side, Doll. p. 170.
BOOK I CH. XLII 119. 225
Ac. 8 (I recommend
i friends to study the Greek philosophers them
my
selves) ut ea a fontibus potius hauriant quam rivulos consectentur.
nutare to waver :
give an xmcertain sound cf. Fin. n 6 nunc
, ,
autem dico ipsum Epicurum nescire (quid sit voluptas] in eoque nutare.
turn enim censet: see Sext. Emp. ix 19 A^. fie ei ScoXa nvd $770-11
tp.7re\dfiv rots dv0p(ojrois KOI TOVTU>V TO. /xei>
flvai dyaOonoid, rd fie KaKOTTOid.
1
fv0ev Kal et xerai rv^f iv
euXoya>i>
eiSa>Xa)i>. eivai Se ravra /leyaXa re (cat
Tols dvdpwTrois, dfatpovufva Kal (poovds a0teVra, and ib. 42 TO 8e ei ScoXa final
(t> TO) TTfpif^ovTi VTTfpffrvr) Ko.\ di>6p(i)Tro(i8els e^oKTa fJiop(f)tis 7ravT\<as eVrt
1
Al. ev\6yxwi>.
M. C. 15
226 BOOK i en. xuii 120.
viros ct magna exempla daturas, vervccum in patria crassoque sub acre nasci
with Mayor s n. instance of its proverbial use is in Cic. Alt. iv
;
the first
10 6, /tii
(liomae) Abdcra non tacente me, and vn 7 4 id est AftBrjptTiitov.
Hirzel (in lli-rm. xiv p. 402) thinks that Abdera got its character from D. s
habit of ridiculing the follies of his neighbours thus we have several ;
concerned ,
cf. Att. xn (5 mihi quidem omncm dubitationem tolleret. So
we find a dative with aufv.ro, eripio, cxtorqueo, absolco (
Verr. II 2 22
J)ionem Veiieri absolvit, sibi condcmnat releases D. from his obligation to
Venus ).
The reference is to the Kvpia quoted on 45. Aristotle
8< >a
r
while allowing that God took care of men (Eth. i\ . x 8 et ns errt/ieXem TU>V
VTTO 6cov yivfrai, uxntfp douf i), denied that there could be any
av6pa>irivu>v
friendship between God and man, both on account of the inequality, and
because God has no need of a friend, Eth. N. 9, Eth. End. VII 12, J/. vm
J/. II 11 UTOTTOV
yap ai> t ir) fi TIS (^aLrf (piXtlv TOV At a.
imply the identity of the two actions, in asserting he denies For the .
KCU Krjftffj.oviKi iv K.n\ w(/>e Xi/ioi TrpoXa/x/Sfii/ffT^at <ai vofla-dai TOV dtov.
Arist. Eth. vm 7.
con etium quos numquam ridimus quodam modo diligamus with Seyffert s n.
who quotes Eurip. Fr. ap. 1 or.son Adt\ p. 27 yap avftpa, KCLV ficas <ro0oi/
quid mail datis: what mischief you cause (=mali quid afert ista
sentential Tusc. a colloquial expression, so haut paternum istuc
i 82),
dedisti Ter. Adelph. in 4 4, and malum dare frequently.
as iu Nagelsb. Stil.
32, cf. 3 2 d, Beier on Off. I 18 honesti naturam vim-
que; setting aside the Gods and their attributes .
true, that they would have been devoid of kindness, if it had not been for
their weakness?
nisi essent futures fuisse: oral. obi. for the direct nisi essentfuis-
sent, see Roby 1784, Madv. 381, 409.
ista amicitia on the attraction (ista for istud) cf. 67.
:
Xpfias yivfcrdai, 8dv fjifivoi TrpoKardp^fcr^ai, (Twia-Tacrdai tie avTr/v Kara KOI-
vwiav fv rais j/Soi/alj, Fin. I 66, II 78. In the parallel passage of Lael. 31,
we read neque cnim beneficium feneramur sed natura propensi ad liberali-
tatem sumus, where SeyiFert quotes fin. n 117 (kindness done from inter
ested motives a feneratio not a beneficium}, Sen. Ep. 9 ista, quam tu
is
describis, negotiatio est, non amicitia. On the change of person, wr here the
subject is indefinite (nos suarum), see 84 sibi displicere.
123. at etiam liber est :
recurring to 115.
non tarn faceto cf. n 46 hie quam volet Ep. jocetur, homo non aptissi-
:
mus ad jocandum, n 74 salem istum, quo caret vestra natio, irridendis nobis
nolitote consumere foil., Div. II 40 deosjocandi causa induxit perlucidos.
familiaris Posidonius. He was sent as ambassador from Rhodes to
Rome B.C. 86 ;
Cic. attended his lectures at Rhodes B.C. 78, where Pompey
also visited him on two occasions. Cic. in vain urged him to write a
f
omnino: summing up, in a word .
22S BOOK I CH. XLIV 124.
the Greek equivalent Att. vni 8 at ilia tibi, TroXXa x a ^P (lv r <p
*aXa>
diccns,
curiae.
quid enim propitius sit for why should I offer the usual prayer
: ]
Cf. the formula in Cato R. 11. 141 Mars pater, te precor quaesoque, uti sics
rol ens propitius mihi domo familiaeqm nostrae.
CATALOGUE OF
WORKS
PUBLISHED FOR THE SYNDICS
OF THE
Camtmtrcje
4 3/9
PUBLICATIONS OF
LIBRARY EDITIONS.
In five vols., or the Old Testament only, in four volumes.
6. Pica type, Demy Svo. Old Testament only, 4 vols., do. \. i2.v.
f.ondon: C. J. CLAY -
Sow, Cambridge University Press Warehouse,
Ave Maria Lane.
CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS BOOKS. 3
LIBRARY EDITIONS.
4. Pica type, Demy 8vo. prices from S/-
chief classic of the language, of having, in editor fame, and of the Cambridge University-
s
conjunction with Shakspeare, and in an im- Press. The noble English Version, to which
measurable degree more than he, fixed the our country and religion owe so much, was
language beyond any possibility of important probably never presented before in so perfect a
change. Thus the recent contributions to the form."
Der Zweck
dieser Ausgabe, den ganzen Beziiglich der Acccntc und Spiritus der Eigen-
in den erwahnten Hss. vorliegenden kritischen nanien sind die Herausg. ihre eigenen Wege
Stoff ubersichtlich zusammenzustellen und dem Deutsche Litteratiirzcitnng.
gegangen."
lieniitzcr das Nachschlagen in den Separat- .,
Th R ,., executcd in the very
, ; ; , ,
: best st le of
in compendi8sester Weise vortrefflich crreicht. >"
bridge Pointed Prayer Book" is used. Demy Svo. cloth extra, 3-$-. 6d.
cloth limp, cut flush. 2s. 6d.
THEOLOGY-(ANCIENT).
THE GREEK LITURGIES. Chiefly from original Autho
rities. By C. A.SWAINSON, D.D., late Master of Christ s College,
Cambridge. Crown 410. Paper covers. $s. 1
Jeder folgende Forscher wird dankbar Griechischen Liturgien sicher gelegt hat."
anerkennen, dass Swainson das Fundament zu ADOLPH HARNACK, Theologische Literatitr
siner historisch-kritischen Geschichte der Zeitung.
"In deni oben verzeichneten Ruche liegt graphische Facsimile s beigegeben, wie iiber-
uns die erste Halfte einer vollstandigen, ebenso haupt das ganze Werk von der University
sorgfaltig gearbeiteten wie schon ausgestat- Press zu Cambridge niit bekannter Eleganz
tcten Ausgabe des Commentars mit ausfiihr-
"
head of Hebrew non-canonical writings. It is credit to English scholarship, of? short treatise
of ancient date, claiming to contain the dicta from the Mishna, containing a series of sen-
of teachers who flourished from B.C. 200 to the tences or maxims ascribed mostly to Jewish
same year of our era. Mr Taylor s explana- teachers immediately preceding, or immediately
tory and illustrative commentary is very full following the Christian era. Conteinpo- . ."
THEOPHYLACTI IN EVANGELIUM
S. MATTH^EI
COMMENTARIUS, edited by W. G. HUMPHRY, B.D. Prebendary
of St Paul s, late Fellow of Trinity College. Demy Svo. 6d. "js.
THEOLOGY (ENGLISH).
WORKS OF ISAAC BARROW, compared with the Ori
ginal MSS., enlarged with Materials hitherto unpublished. A new
Edition, by A. NAPIER, M.A. 9 Vols. Demy Svo. ^3. y.
TREATISE OF THE POPE S SUPREMACY, and a
Discourse concerning the Unity of the Church, by ISAAC BARROW.
Demy Svo. js. 6d.
Arabic is a sufficient guarantee for his mastery Beha-ed-dm Zoheir is a very welcome addition
of the original, his English compositions are to the small series of Eastern poets accessible
distinguished by versatility, command of Ian- to readers who are not Orientalists." Aca-
guage, rhythmical cadence, and, as we have demy.
nach Assemani und Martin in Wright einen erscheint auch gerade zur rechten Zeit, da die
drittenBearbeiter gefunden, der sich um die zweite Ausgabe von Roedigers syrischer Chres-
Emendation des Textes wie um die Erklarung tomathie im Buchhandel vollstandig vergriffen
der Realitn wesentlich verdient gemacht hat und diejenige von Kirsch-Bernstein nur noch
. Ws. Josua-Ausgabe ist eine sehr dankens-
. . in wenigen Exemplaren vorhanden ist."
pilation of the present catalogue came to be dall has entitled himself to the thanks of all
placed in Mr Bendall s hands from the cha- ; Oriental scholars, and we hope he may have
racter of his work it is evident the selection before him a long course of successful labour in
was judicious, and we may fairly congratulate the field he has chosen." Athenaum.
shortly that it displays sound judgment and stalment of Professor Jebb s unequalled edition
taste, without sacrificing precision to poetry of of Sophocles too warmly, and it is almost a
expression." The Times. work of supererogation to praise it at all. It is
Jebb s edition of Sophocles is
"Professor equal, at least, and perhaps superior, in merit,
already so fully established, and has received to either of his previous instalments and when ;
such appreciation in these columns and else- this is said, all is said. Yet we cannot refrain
where, that we have judged this third volume from formally recognising once more the con-
when we have said that it is of a piece with summate Greek scholarship of the editor, and
the others. The whole edition so far exhibits from once more doing grateful homage to his
perhaps the most complete and elaborate edit- masterly tact and literary skill, and to his un-
orial work which has ever appeared." Satur- wearied and marvellous industry." Spectator,
day Review.
displays of learning. By far the more valuable in alien Schriftendes Aristoteles und grossten-
parts of the notes are neither critical nor lite- dcr neueren Litteratur zu densel-
teils atich in
thought, and of the connection of thought, in Teil der Arbeit ist der kritische Aber in . . .
the treatise itself. In this relation the notes are alien diesen Dingen liegt auch nach der Ab-
invaluable. Of the translation, it may be said sicht des Verfassers nicht der Schwerpunkt
that an English reader may fairly master by seiner Arbeit, sondern." Prof. Suscmihl in
means of it this great treatise of Aristotle." rhilologische Wochenschrift.
Spectator.
University of Cambridge. If an English student duties with marked ability and admirable tact.
wishes to have a full conception of what is con- In every part of his work revising,
taiued in the Rhetoric of Aristotle, to Mr Cope s supplementing, and completing he has done
edition he must go." Academy. exceedingly well." Examiner,
"
illustrating Attic Law, as that law was in- a most lucid and interesting introduction, Mr
flucnced by the exigences of politics ... As Wayte has given the student effective help
vigorous examples of the great orator s style, in his running commentary." Spectator.
ward that it may well win converts, and it may turday Review.
a very valuable contribution towards a more extremely valuable and important piece of
thorough knowledge of the style of Pheidias." work. Taking it for the illustrations alone,
. . .
Such editions as that of which Prof. Mayor way admirably suited to meet the needs of the
has given us the first instalment will doubtless student The notes of the editor are all that
. . .
do much to remedy this undeserved neglect. It could be expected from his well-known learn-
isone on which great pains and much learning ing and scholarship." Academy.
have evidently been expended, and is in every
historical developments of chemical thought has had to content himself with such works as
is immense." Academy. Dr Tilden s Introduction to Chemical Philo-
Theoretical Chemistry has moved so rapidly sophy an admirable book in its way, but rather
"
of late years that most of our ordinary text slender. Mr Pattison Muir having aimed at a
books have been left far behind. German more comprehensive scheme, has produced a
students, to be sure, possess an excellent guide systematic treatise on the principles of chemical
to the present state of the science in Die philosophy which stands far in advance of any
Modernen Theorien der Chemie of Prof. kindred work in our language." Atheturiim.
it is a :
foreign competitors. Nature.
work which will take its place as cosmopolitan : "The work forms an important contribu-
no more clear or concise discussion of the diffi- lion to the literature of the subject It will be
cult chemistry of metabolism has appeared eagerly welcomed by all students." Academy.
"The
LAW.
ELEMENTS OF THE LAW OF TORTS. A Text-book
for Students. By MELVILLE M. BIGELOW, Ph.D., Lecturer in the
Law School of the University of Boston, U.S.A. Crown 8 vo. \os.6d.
based on the original American edition, showing great grasp of subject ... A very full
"
It is
but it is an English Text-book with English index enhances the value of this book, which
authorities and statutes and illustrations sub- should take a prominent place among the really
stituted very generally for the American . The . . trust worthy text-books for the use of students."
style is easy and lucid, though condensed, Law Times.
A SELECTION OF CASES ON THE ENGLISH LAW
OF CONTRACT. By GERARD BROWN FINCH, M.A., of Lincoln s
the same kind of thorough and well-ordered haps surprised to find how abundantly the ex-
study which was brought to be:ir upon the notes tant fragments illustrate and clear up points
to the Commentaries and the Institutes . . . which have attracted his attention in the Corn-
Hitherto the Edict has been almost inac- mentaries, or the Institutes, or the Digest."
cessible to the ordinary English student, and Law Times.
We welcome here a valuable contribution the ordinary student, whose attention is dis-
to the study of jurisprudence. The text of the tracted from the subject-matter by the dif-
Institutes is occasionally perplexing, even to ficulty of struggling through the language in
practised scholars, whose knowledge of clas- which itcontained, it will be almost indis-
is
sical models does not always avail them in Spectator.
pensable."
dealing with the technicalities of legal phrase- notes are learned and carefully com-
"The
ology. Nor can the ordinary dictionaries be piled, and this edition will be found useful to
expected to furnish all the help that is wanted. students." Law Times.
This translation will then be of great use. To
DR BUSCH S volume has made people think feel very pardonable pride at seeing one of
and talk even more than usual of Prince Bis- theircountrymen undertake to write the his-
inarck, and Professor Seeley s very learned work tory of a period from the investigation of
on Stein will turn attention to an earlier and an which even laborious Germans are apt to
almost equally eminent German statesman.... Times.
shrink."
He was one, perhaps the chief, of the illus- In a notice of this kind scant justice can
"
trious group of strangers who came to the be done to a work like the one before us; no
rescue of Prussia in her darkest hour, about short resume can give even the most meagre
the time of the inglorious Peace of Tilsit, and notion of the contents of these volumes, which
who laboured to put life and order into her contain no page that is superfluous, and none
dispirited army, her impoverished finances, and that is uninteresting." Athenceum.
her inefficient Civil Service. Englishmen will
Dr Cunningham s book is one of excep- marshalling the varied facts in the vast field
tional interest and usefulness. It cannot be which has been traversed, and by singular
too highly praised. It is characterised by re- clearness and felicity of expression." Scots-
search and thought, by a remarkable power of man.
CHRONOLOGICAL TABLES OF GREEK HISTORY.
Accompanied by a short narrative of events, with references to the
sources of information and extracts from the ancient authorities, by
CARL PETER. Translated from the German by G. CHAWNER,
M.A., Fellow of King s College, Cambridge. Demy 410. los.
the internal organization of the University, its thoroughness in his work. Nothing could be
connection with national problems, its studies,
its social life. All this he combines in a lethod : and his style. ..is picture.Miue and
form which is eminently readable." PROF.
CKEIGHTON in Cont. Review.
quantity of minute and curious information ference. and as such it will be of permanent
about the working of Cambridge institutions in value for the historical knowledge of English
the last century, with an occasional comparison education and learning." Saturday Review.
of the corresponding state of things at Oxford.
MISCELLANEOUS.
THE LITERARY REMAINS OF ALBRECHT DURER,
by W. M. CONVVAY. With Transcripts from the British Museum
MSS., and Notes by LINA ECKENSTEIN. Royal Svo. 2is. (The
Edition is limited to 500 copies.}
GRAY AND HIS FRIENDS. Letters and Relics in great
part hitherto unpublished. Edited by the Rev. D. C. TOVEY, M.A.
\In the Press.
A LATIN-ENGLISH DICTIONARY. Printed from the
(Incomplete) MS. of the late T. H. KEY, M.A., F.R.S. Cr. 4to. 31-5-. 6d.
London : C. J CLA Y
. & SONS, Cambridge University Press Warehouse,
Ai>e Maria Lane.
24 PUBLICATIONS OF
London: C. J. Cr. A r 5
(S- ..SYw.v, Cambridge University Prest Warc/nnisc,
Ai c A faria Lane.
THE CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS. 25
Colleges.
GENERAL EDITOR : THE VERY REVEREND J. J. S. PEROWNE, D.D.
DEAN OF PETERBOROUGH.
"The modesty of the general title of this series has, we believe, led many to misunderstand
its character and underrate its value. The books are well suited for study in the upper forms of
our best schools, but not the less are they adapted to the wants of all liible students who are not
specialists. We
doubt, indeed, whether any of the numerous popular commentaries recently
issued in this country will be found more serviceable for general use." Academy.
"
One of the most popular and useful literary enterprises of the nineteenth century." Baptist
Magazine,
"Of great value. The whole series of comments for schools is highly esteemed by students
capable of forming a judgment. The books are scholarly without being pretentious: information
isso given as to be easily understood." Sword and Trowel.
College.
The Very Rev. II. D. M. SPENCK, M.A., Dean of Gloucester.
Rev. A. W. STREANE, M.A., Fellow of Corpus Christi College, Cambridge.
Preparing.
THE BOOK OE GENESIS. By the Very Rev. the DEAN OK
PETERBOROUGH.
THE BOOKS OF EXODUS, NUMBERS AND DEUTERO
NOMY. By the Rev. C. D. GINSBURG, LL.D.
THE BOOKS OF EZRA AND NEHEMIAH. By the Rev.
Prof. RYLE, M.A.
THE BOOK OF PSALMS. By the Rev. Prof. KIRKPATRICK, B.D.
THE BOOK OF ISAIAH. By Prof. W. ROBERTSON SMITH, M.A.
THE BOOK OF EZEKIEL. By the Rev. A. B. DAVIDSON, D.D.
THE EPISTLE TO THE GALATIANS. By the Rev. E. H.
PEROWNE, D.D.
THE EPISTLES TO THE COLOSSIANS AND PHILEMON.
By the Rev. II. C. G. MOULE, M.A.
THE EPISTLES TO TIMOTHY AND TITUS. By the Rev.
A. E. HUMPHREYS, M.A.
THE BOOK OF REVELATION. By the Rev. W. SIMCOX, M.A.
Now Ready.
THE GOSPEL ACCORDING TO ST MATTHEW. By the
Rev. A. CARR, M.A. With 4 Maps. 4^. 6d.
"Copious illustrations, gathered from a great variety of sources, make his notes a very valu
able aid to the student. They are indeed remarkably interesting, while all explanations on
meanings, applications, and the like are distinguished by their lucidity and good sense
"
is known of St Mark s life, an account of the circumstances in which the Gospel was composed,
an excellent sketch of the special characteristics of this Gospel an analysis, and a chapter on the
;
text of the New Testament generally . . . The work is completed by three good maps." Satur
day Review.
"A valuable addition has also been made to The Cambridge Greek Testament for Schools,
Dr Plummer s notes on the Gospel according to St John are scholarly, concise, and instructive,
and embody the results of much thought and wide reading." Expositor.
I. GREEK.
ARISTOPHANES AVES PLUTUS RANAE. With
English Notes and Introduction by \V. C. GREEN, M.A., late Assistant
Master at Rugby School. $s. bd. each.
"A
worthy representative of English Scholarship." Classical Review.
-
CRITO. With Introduction, Notes and Appendix.
By the same Editor, is. 6d.
"Mr Adam, already known as the author of a careful and scholarly edition of the Apology
of Plato, will, we think, add to his reputation by his work upon the Crito." Acadt iity.
"A scholarly edition of a dialogue which has never been really well edited in English."
Guardian.
Pretor s notes seem to be all that could be wished as regards grammar, geography, and other
matters." The Academy.
- BOOKS II. VI. and VII. By the same. 2s. 6d. each.
"Had we to introduce a young Greek scholar Xenophon, we should esteem ourselves
to
fortunate in having Pretor s text-book as our chart and guide." Contemporary Review.
II. LATIN.
BEDA S ECCLESIASTICAL HISTORY, BOOKS
III., IV., the Text from the very ancient MS. in the Cambridge University
Library, collated with six other MSS. Edited, with a life from the German of
EBERT, and with Notes, &c. by J. E. B. MAYOR, M.A., Professor of Latin,
andj. R. LUMBY, D.D., Norrisian Professor of Divinity. Revised edition.
7 J- &<*
BOOKS I. and II. In the Press.
In Bede s works Englishmen can go back to origines of their history, unequalled for
"
form and matter by any modern European nation. Prof. Mayor has done good service in ren
dering a part of Bede s greatest work accessible to those who can read Latin with ease. He
has adorned this edition of the third and fourth books of the Ecclesiastical History* with that
amazing erudition for which he is unrivalled among Englishmen and rarely equalled by Germans.
And however interesting and valuable the text may be, we can certainly apply to his notes
the expression, La sauce vant mieux que le poisson. They are literally crammed with interest
ing information about early English life. For though ecclesiastical in name, Bede s history treats
of all parts of the national life, since the Church had points of contact with Examiner. all."
[//; th /);vv(
we come to the commentary, we are only amazed by its fulness in proportion to its bulk.
Nothing is overlooked which can tend to enlarge the learner s general knowledge of Ciceronian
Latin or to elucidate the text." Saturday Review,
minute and thorough study of their Latinity, both in the ordinary notes and in the textual
appendices." Saturday Revieiv.
scarcely needs any commendation of ours. His edition of the speech Pro Sulla is fully equal in
merit to the volumes which he has already published ... It would be difficult to speak too highly
of the notes. There could be no better way of gaining an insight into the characteristics of
Cicero s style and the Latinity of his period than by making a careful study of this speech with
the aid of Mr Reid s commentary Mr Reid s intimate knowledge of the minutest details of
. . .
scholarship enables him to detect and explain the slightest points of distinction between the
usages of different authors and different periods The notes are followed by a valuable . . .
appendix on the text, and another on points of orthography an excellent index brings the work ;
own, which, in former generations, made it a favourite with English scholars, and which still
make it a popular text- book in Continental schools The reputation of Mr Heitland is a
sufficient guarantee fur the scholarship of the notes, which are ample without being excessive,
and the book is well furnished with all that is needful in the nature of maps, indices, and
appendices." Academy.
Mr Sidgwick s Vergil is we believe, the best school edition of the poet." Guardian.
"
Mr Arthur Sidgwick s Vergil, Aeneid, Book XII. is worthy of his reputation, and is dis
tinguished by the same acuteness and accuracy of knowledge, appreciation of a boy s difficulties
and ingenuity and resource in meeting them, which we have on other occasions had reason to
praise in these pages." The Academy.
"As masterly in its clearly divided preface and appendices as in the sound and independent
character of its annotations. There is a great deal more in the notes than mere compilation
. . .
This volume, which completes the Pitt Press edition of Virgil s Georgics, is distinguished by
"
the same admirable judgment and first-rate scholarship as are conspicuous in the former volume
and in the "Aeneid" by the same talented editor." Athcna-iim.
FRENCH. III.
respectively with periods of history which it is right should be known thoroughly, and which
are well treated in the Pitt Press volumes. The latter in particular, an extract from the
world-known work of Madame de Stael on the French Revolution, is beyond all praise for
the excellence both of its style and of its matter." Titties.
"Mr Saintsbury s clear and scholarly notes are rich in illustration of the valuable kind that
SAINTE-BEUVE. M. DARU
(Causeries du Lundi, Vol. IX.).
With Biographical Sketch of the Author, and Notes Philological and Histo
rical. By GUSTAVE MASSON. is.
SAINTINE. LA PICCIOLA. The Text, with Introduc-
tion, Notes and Map, by Rev. A. C. CLAPIN. is.
of Education.
IV. GERMAN.
BALLADS ON GERMAN HISTORY. Arranged and
Annotated by \V. WAC.NER, Ph. D., late Professor at the Johanneum,
Hamburg, is.
"It carries the reader rapidly through some of the most important incidents connected with
theGerman race and name, from the invasion of Italy by the Visigoths under their King Alaric,
down to the Franco-German War and the installation of the present Emperor. The notes supply
very well the connecting links between the successive periods, and exhibit in its various phases of
growth and progress, or the reverse, the vast unwieldy mass which constitutes modern Germany."
Times.
Zopf and Schwert by Mr H. J. Wolstenholme. These notes are abundant and contain
. . .
RAUMER. <Der
erfte tfreu^ug (THE FIRST CRUSADE).
Condensed from the Author s History of the Hohenstaufen ,
with a life of
RAUMER, two Plans and English Notes. By W. WAGNER, is.
"Certainly no more interesting book could be made the subject of examinations. The story
of the First Crusade has an undying interest. The notes are, on the whole, good." Educational
Times.
V. ENGLISH.
ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY. A SKETCH OF, FROM
THALES TO CICERO, by JOSEPH B. MAYOR, M. A. y. f>d.
"Professor Mayor contributes to the Pitt Press Series A Sketch of Ancient Philosophy in
which he has endeavoured to give a general view of the philosophical systems illustrated by the
genius of the masters of metaphysical and ethical science from Thales to Cicero. In the course
of his sketch he takes occasion to give concise analyses of Plato s Republic, and of the K.thics and
Politics of Aristotle: and these abstracts will be to some readers not the least useful portions of
the book." The Guardian.
"It was
originally written in Latin and does not find a place on ordinary bookshelves. very A
great boon has therefore been conferred on the general English reader by the managers of the
I itt Press Series, in the issue of a convenient httle volume of More s Utopia not in the original
Latin, but in the quaint English Translation thereof made by Raphe Robynson, which adds a
linguistic interest to the intrinsic merit of the work. All this has been edited in a most com
. . .
plete and scholarly fashion by Dr J. R. Lumby, the Norrisian Professor of Divinity, whose name
alone is a sufficient warrant for its accuracy. It is a real addition to the modern stock of classical
"This edition of a play that is well worth study, for more reasons than one, by so careful a
A separate reprint of Milton s famous letter to Master Samuel Hartlib was a desideratum,
and we are grateful to Mr Browning for his elegant and scholarly edition, to which is prefixed the
careful resume of the work given History of Educational Theories
"
in his Journal of
Education.
VII. MATHEMATICS.
EUCLID S ELEMENTS OF GEOMETRY. BOOKS I.
& II. Edited by H. M. TAYLOR, M.A., Fellow and formerly Tutor of
Trinity College, Cambridge. is. 6d.
-
BOOKS III. and IV. By the same Editor.
[/ the Press.
LOCAL EXAMINATIONS.
Examination Papers, for various years, with the Regulations for tht
Examination. Demy 8vo. 2s. each, or by Post 2s. id.
Vol. II. Part II. Vol. III. Parti. ;.f. M. Vol. III. Part II. -js.f,,/.
-;s.6</.
Vol. IV. Part I. \is.6tt. Vol. IV. Part II. los. Vol. IV. Part III. 5.*.
University of Toronto
^^
Library
9
sO
DO NOT
c
REMOVE
THE
2
o aJ
CARD
OJ p!
FROM
o
THIS
H
O
POCKET