What The Skeptic Still Can't Learn From How We Use The Word Know'
What The Skeptic Still Can't Learn From How We Use The Word Know'
What The Skeptic Still Can't Learn From How We Use The Word Know'
What the Skeptic Still Can’t Learn from How We Use the Word ‘Know’
Wai-hung Wong
Not only rules, but also examples are needed for establishing a practice.
Our rules leave loop-holes open, and the practice has to speak for itself.
One is often bewitched by a word. For example, by the word „know‟.
Since its publication more than twenty years ago, Barry Stroud‟s The Significance of
Philosophical Scepticism has been widely read and discussed by philosophers who are interested
in skepticism about our knowledge of the external world.1 Some of his later writings on the topic
(such as Stroud (1989) and (1994)) are considered essential reading too. This does not, however,
mean that what Stroud says about skepticism2 has as much impact on the discussion of
skepticism as it deserves. It seems that his insights into the nature of skepticism have been
largely misunderstood or missed. Although Stroud has never argued for skepticism or claimed
that skepticism is true, he has been referred to as a “contemporary skeptic” (Huemer, 2001,
p.37). The main theme of The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism is, as the title says so
clearly, that skepticism is philosophically significant and should be considered seriously, but
skepticism is still felt by most philosophers, including those who write about the topic and
related issues, “to be even less worthy of serious consideration than, say Ptolemaic astronomy or
1
In what follows I will use „the external world‟ and „the world‟ interchangeably.
2
Hereafter „skepticism‟ refers to skepticism about our knowledge of the external world.
1
the account of creation in the book of Genesis” (Stroud, 1977, p.39).3
One way of taking skepticism seriously is to see it as a real threat to human knowledge of
the world4 in the sense that the Darwinian theory of evolution is a real threat to the belief in
divine creation. Philosophers who take skepticism seriously in this way think that because of the
force of the skeptical argument5 we need to show that we do have knowledge of the world, and
that we cannot show that unless we can refute skepticism. That is, they think we have to
conclude that we do not know anything about the world if we cannot refute skepticism. Many
philosophers who discuss skepticism, however, do not take skepticism seriously in this way.6 A
widespread attitude among philosophers towards skepticism is that it presents us with no more
than a paradox: the skeptical argument is an apparently valid argument with true premises but a
conclusion that is obviously false. For them, it is intellectually challenging to solve the paradox
in the way that a logical puzzle is solved, but human knowledge is not really threatened by
skepticism even if we don‟t know how to solve the paradox. Achilles can easily overtake the
Tortoise even if Zeno‟s paradox cannot be solved; likewise, these philosophers think, it is
obvious that human beings have knowledge of the world even if the skeptical paradox cannot be
solved.
Stroud can be read as not taking skepticism seriously in this way, for he has never
3
Stroud wrote this in an article published in 1977, but what he said remains true today. Stewart Cohen, for example,
remarks in an article published in 2001 that “[a]fter all, in the end, skepticism is crazy” (Cohen, 2001, p.96). Indeed,
Cohen‟s remark suggests that skepticism is even less worth taken seriously than Ptolemaic astronomy or the account
of creation in the book of Genesis, for the latter, though false, is at least not crazy.
4
For simplicity I will use „human knowledge‟ to refer to human knowledge of the external word.
5
There is no one single argument that can be referred to as the skeptical argument. I am speaking loosely of the
kind of argument that is well-known in the discussion of skepticism, such as the dream argument, the evil demon
argument, and the brain-in-a-vat argument.
6
One can see skepticism as a real threat to human knowledge without conceding that one will accept it as true if it
is not refuted. As Stroud remarks, “philosophical scepticism is not something we should seriously consider adopting
or accepting” (Stroud, 1984b, p.1). I argue in Wong (2005) for the stronger thesis that no one can live a human life
as we understand it without believing that she herself and others know many things about the world.
2
attempted to refute skepticism or argued that we have to conclude that we do not know anything
about the world if we cannot refute skepticism. But this does not mean that he does not think
skepticism needs to be answered in some way. As a matter of fact, he does offer an anti-skeptical
strategy in some of his more recent writings, such as Stroud (1999) and (2003), which consists in
showing that the possibility that our beliefs about the world are mostly false “is not a possibility
that we could consistently believe to be actual” (Stroud, 1999, p.199).7 And although Stroud
thinks skepticism is comparable to Zeno‟s paradox, the liar paradox, and Russell‟s paradox,8 he
does not think skepticism is no more than a paradox in the sense that the study of skepticism will
not reveal anything important about human knowledge (just as the study of Zeno‟s paradox will
Indeed, another way of taking skepticism seriously is to have the understanding that the
study of skepticism can “reveal something deep or important about human knowledge or human
nature or the urge to understand them philosophically” (Stroud, 1984a, p.ix). This is clearly
Stroud‟s way of taking skepticism seriously. When we take skepticism seriously in this way, we
do not have to think we have to conclude that we do not know anything about the world if we
cannot refute skepticism. We may even think that although we do not know how to refute
skepticism, we do have good reason to believe that we have knowledge of the world. But we
may still see skepticism as threatening. Here is how Stroud describes that threat:
We want an account of our knowledge of the world that would make all of it intelligible
to us all at once. We want to see how knowledge of the world could come to be out of
something that is not knowledge of the world. Without that, we will not have the kind of
3
and perhaps always did represent, the possibility that such an explanation is impossible;
that we cannot consider all our knowledge of the world all at once and still see it as
knowledge. Given that project, the threat is that skepticism will be the only answer.
On this understanding of the threat of skepticism, even if skepticism does not threaten our
knowledge of the world, it still threatens “a certain kind of understanding of our position in the
Stroud wrote in the 1970s that one of the reasons why skepticism was not taken
seriously9 was “the rise of „linguistic‟ philosophy in the 1950s, as a result of which scepticism
and the arguments thought to lead to it came to be regarded as little more than a mess of false
analogies, definite errors, and even identifiable fallacies which had bewitched the intelligence of
earlier philosophers through insufficient attention to the complexities of language and to the
general conditions for the significant functioning of our actual conceptual scheme” (Stroud,
1977, p.38). The heyday of ordinary language philosophy has long been gone. There are
philosophers who still think linguistic or conceptual analysis is useful and important, but even
among them there are not many who think that a philosophical problem can be solved (or
dissolved, as it was put in the old days) simply by considering carefully how we use some
particular words. Recently, however, there have been revived attempts to solve the problem of
skepticism about our knowledge of the external world by analyzing how we use the word „know‟
(and its cognates).10 This is part of what has been referred to as „the new linguistic turn in
9
Apparently Stroud spoke of the second way of taking skepticism seriously here, but what he said was also true
with respect to the first way of taking skepticism seriously.
10
Philosophers who offer such an analysis presumably do not intend it to be an analysis only of the English word
„know‟, but intend it to apply to the counterparts of „know‟ in other languages.
4
epistemology‟.11 Those who witnessed the flourishing of ordinary language philosophy and
particularly the influence of J. L. Austin may feel a sort of philosophical déjà vu when they see
again so many philosophers writing and debating so spiritedly about the semantics of the word
„know‟. Although some philosophers who participate in this new linguistic turn certainly have
said something new about the word „know‟ and contributed much, and probably will contribute
even more, to a better understanding of how we talk about knowledge, it is not clear that they
have done a better job of illuminating the nature of human knowledge than ordinary language
In his discussion of Austin‟s way of dealing with skepticism, Stroud concludes that “no
anti-sceptical conclusion to the contrary could be drawn simply from the fact that we use the
expressions „I know …‟, „He knows …‟, etc., as we do in fact use them” (Stroud, 1985, p.75).
This conclusion still holds with respect to the new linguistic turn in epistemology. In what
follows I will substantiate this claim by examining how contextualism about knowledge
attributions, which has been the main impetus for the new linguistic turn, fails to solve the
problem of skepticism. Although I focus on contextualism here, most of the points I am going to
make are applicable, mutatis mutandis, to other attempts to solve the problem that make use of
the idea that epistemic standards (i.e. standards for true knowledge attributions) vary in different
particular cases. Sensitive invariantism, for example, shares with contextualism the idea that
epistemic standards vary, though it disagrees with contextualism on how epistemic standards
vary, or more precisely, on what the mechanism is by means of which epistemic standards are
raised or lowered in different cases; and an anti-skeptical strategy similar to the one offered by
11
See Ludlow (2005).
5
contextualists can be formulated in terms of sensitive invariantism.12 I focus on contextualism
developed with an eye toward providing a response to philosophical skepticism” (DeRose, 2002,
p.168) and because the anti-skeptical strategy based on contextualism has been quite fully
developed by Stewart Cohen and Keith DeRose. Besides, it seems to me that contextualism,
particularly Keith DeRose‟s formulation of it, is the most convincing among the theories
concerning the semantics of knowledge-attributing sentences that have been suggested.13 Since
what I try to show is that we won‟t know how to solve the problem of skepticism even if we have
better choose as my target of criticism a theory that is true or most likely true.
I am certainly not the first to criticize the contextualist anti-skeptical strategy. Earl
Conee, Richard Feldman, Peter Klein, Hilary Kornblith, and Ernest Sosa, for instance, have
made good points about how contextualism fails to solve the problem of skepticism;14 what I am
going to say may overlap some of their points. What I think is new in my criticism is that it is
based on two of Stroud‟s insights into skepticism: first, skepticism “is a general theory of human
knowledge” (Stroud, 1994, p.141, italics added) and “[a]ll of [our] knowledge of the external
world is supposed to have been brought into question at one fell swoop” (Stroud, 1984a, p.118,
original italics); and second, “the considerations that can make that conclusion [i.e. the skeptical
conclusion] look plausible, perhaps unavoidable, always depend on certain ideas about sense-
12
For sensitive invariantism, see, for example, Hawthorne (2004) and Stanley (2005). MacFarlane (2005) offers a
helpful categorization of views on the semantics of „know‟ that develop the idea that epistemic standards vary in
different particular cases. MacFarlane criticizes both contextualism and sensitive invariantism, but he develops that
same idea in his own way and calls his view „relativism‟. The difference between MacFarlane‟s relativism and the
other two views has, again, to do with how epistemic standards vary.
13
The semantics of knowledge-attributing sentences suggested by contextualists has been seriously criticized, such
as by Schiffer (1996) and Stanley (2004), but DeRose does a great job of clarifying and defending contextualism,
most impressively in DeRose (2002) and (2005).
14
See Conee (2005), Feldman (1999) and (2001), Klein (2000), Kornblith (2000), and Sosa (2000).
6
perception and its role in knowledge of the world” (Stroud, 2009, p.559). I will argue that it is
because contextualists lose sight of these two important aspects of skepticism that they have
The problem with the contextualist anti-skeptical strategy is not that it fails to refute
skepticism, for contextualists do not aim at refuting skepticism. The problem is that they have
changed the subject without even noticing it. Contextualists may have solved „the skeptical
paradox‟ in their own terms, but such a solution cannot in any way make skepticism, that is,
It may not be fair to contextualists if we consider the contextualist anti-skeptical strategy only in
completely general terms, for how forceful such a strategy is depends on how it is formulated in
detail. I think the best formulation of the strategy is DeRose‟s in DeRose (1995), which we will
look at in this section. Since DeRose‟s formulation has all the features of contextualism that I
want to criticize, and these features are shared by other formulations, my argument should be
understood as an argument against the contextualist anti-skeptical strategy generally rather than
The central idea of contextualism is that epistemic standards vary in different contexts of
knowledge attribution.16 According to DeRose, epistemic standards determine how strong one‟s
15
And not just against the contextualist anti-skeptical strategy generally, but also, as I have pointed out, against
other attempts to solve the problem that make use of the idea that epistemic standards vary in different particular
cases.
16
Note that the contextualist idea is not just that epistemic standards vary in different contexts, which most
epistemologists would grant (that is, except strict invariantists; see MacFarlane (2005)), but that epistemic standards
7
epistemic position with respect to a proposition has to be in order for one to be truly described as
knowing that proposition. He explains the strength of one‟s epistemic position in terms of how
well one‟s belief tracks the truth. To track the truth, one‟s belief concerning p has to match the
fact as to whether p not only in the actual world, but also in some of the nearby possible worlds;
the further away the possible worlds are in which one‟s belief concerning p still matches the fact
as to whether p, the better one‟s belief tracks the truth. The strength of one‟s epistemic position
with respect to p is thus a matter of how remote (from the actual world) the remotest possible
worlds are to which one‟s belief concerning p tracks the truth the remoter these possible
worlds are, the stronger one‟s epistemic position is with respect to p.17
One‟s epistemic position (under the same circumstances) with respect to different
propositions can have different strength, and DeRose suggests that such differences can be
expressed by comparative conditionals. That is, the fact that S‟s epistemic position with respect
to q is at least as strong as his epistemic position with respect to p can be expressed as follows: if
S knows that p, then S knows that q; and if S does not know that q, then S does not know that p.
For example, my epistemic position with respect to „I am not a brain-in-a-vat‟ is at least as strong
as my epistemic position with respect to „I have hands‟, for if I know that I have hands, then I
know that I am not a brain-in-a-vat; and if I do not know that I am not a brain-in-a-vat, then I do
Another central notion in DeRose‟s account is the sensitivity of beliefs, which can also be
vary in different contexts of knowledge attributions. That is, it is the knowledge attributor‟s context that determines
the epistemic standards used.
17
This account of epistemic standards is externalist in the sense that one does not have to know what epistemic
position one is in to be in that epistemic position and to satisfy or fail to satisfy the epistemic standards concerned.
Cohen suggests, by contrast, an internalist account of epistemic standards: to have different epistemic standards is to
be more or less demanding on how good S‟s evidence to believe that p has to be in order for „S knows that p‟ to be
true (see, for example, Cohen (1987), (1988), and (1999)). In other places than DeRose (1995), however, DeRose
seems to adopt an internalist account of epistemic standards (see, for example, the bank cases discussed in DeRose
(1992) and (2002)).
8
explained in terms of truth-tracking. One‟s belief that p is sensitive if it tracks the truth as to
whether p to at least the closest possible worlds in which p is false; or more intuitively, one‟s
belief that p is sensitive if it is not the case that one would still have that belief even if p were
false when not much else had changed. One is presumably in quite a strong epistemic position
with respect to p when one‟s belief that p is sensitive, and one is always in a stronger epistemic
position with respect to p when one‟s belief that p is sensitive than when it is insensitive.
It is important to note, however, that how strong one‟s epistemic position has to be for
one‟s belief to be sensitive depends on what the proposition is that is the object of one‟s belief,
for what the proposition is determines how far away from the actual world the closest possible
worlds are in which the proposition is false. It is thus possible for one to be in a stronger
epistemic position with respect to q than with respect to p even if one‟s belief that q is insensitive
while one‟s belief that p is sensitive. To use the standard pair of examples again, I am in a
stronger epistemic position with respect to „I am not a brain-in-a-vat‟ than with respect to „I have
hands‟, but this does not imply that my belief that I am not a brain-in-a-vat must also be sensitive
Let us now look at how DeRose uses the above account of epistemic standards to „solve‟
the problem of skepticism. The work is done by what he calls the „Rule of Sensitivity‟, which is
a conversational rule governing the change of epistemic standards. Here is the rule: when it is
asserted that S knows that p, epistemic standards will be raised to such a level that S‟s belief that
p has to be sensitive for „S knows that p‟ to be true.18 In a philosophical context in which the
skeptic proposes a radical skeptical hypothesis h and asserts that we do not know that not-h, the
Rule of Sensitivity is applicable; no one in that context can then know that not-h unless his belief
18
See DeRose (1995), pp.205-206.
9
that not-h is sensitive.19 Since our belief that not-h is insensitive (we would still believe that we
are not brains-in-vats even if that belief were false), the application of the Rule of Sensitivity to it
results in the skeptical conclusion that we do not know that not-h. This skeptical conclusion can
then be used, in conjunction with the principle that knowledge is closed under known entailment,
to show that we do not know a particular proposition about the world provided that the
proposition is incompatible with h. If h is radical enough, such as the hypothesis that we are
brains-in-vats, then most of the propositions that we believe about the world are incompatible
with h; the final skeptical conclusion the skeptic arrives at, a conclusion we have to rationally
accept in such a context, is that we do not know most of the things we believe we know about the
world, including those that we strongly believe we know, such as that we have hands.20
conclusion true only in philosophical contexts, for it is in such contexts alone that a radical
skeptical hypothesis is proposed and claimed not to be known by us to be false. And when the
Rule of Sensitivity is applied to our belief that a certain radical skeptical hypothesis h is false, the
epistemic standards it induces are indeed extraordinarily high: in order for us to know that not-h,
our epistemic position with respect to not-h has to be so strong that none of us can ever be in
19
In DeRose (2004), DeRose argues that the skeptic does not always succeed in raising epistemic standards, such as
in a case in which “our skeptic has executed a maneuver […] that has a tendency to raise the epistemic standards,
and that her opponent has responded by executing a maneuver that has at least some tendency to keep lower,
ordinary standards in place” (p.4). His view is that neither of them succeeds. It seems that this view does not accord
with his formulation of the Rule of Sensitivity in DeRose (1995), but I am not going to pursue the issue here.
20
If this is the skeptic‟s argument, and if the skeptical conclusion is that we do not know anything about the
external world, then, as DeRose points out, the skeptic may need a principle stronger than the principle that
knowledge is closed under known entailment. The proposition that I am in Houston, for example, does not
contradict the skeptical hypothesis that I am a brain-in-a-vat. See DeRose (1995), note 33. For a related discussion,
see Stroud (1984a), pp.25-30. As we will see, there is a way of understanding how skepticism attacks all our
knowledge of the external world that is independent of understanding how this skeptical argument should be refined.
It should be noted that the evil demon argument does attack all our knowledge of the external world, for whatever
we believe about the external world is incompatible with the skeptical hypothesis that we are being deceived by the
evil demon. I will explain in section 4 why the evil demon argument may not be the best argument for bringing out
the force of skepticism.
10
such an epistemic position. However, in everyday contexts when nothing like radical skeptical
hypotheses are considered, our epistemic standards are set much lower (i.e. our beliefs don‟t
have to track the truth to remote possible worlds), so low so that we often meet them our
epistemic position with respect to most propositions about the world is strong enough for our
knowledge attributions, but most of these claims and attributions survive the test of the rule, for
most of our beliefs about the world are sensitive. I do not, for example, believe that I have hands
in the closest possible worlds in which I do not have hands, such as the possible worlds in which
(falsely) believe that I have hands, but, DeRose suggests, my belief as to whether I have hands
does not have to track the truth to these extremely remote possible worlds in order to be
sensitive. So our knowledge claims or attributions are mostly true in everyday contexts. Indeed,
since our knowing things about the world implies our knowing that radical skeptical hypotheses
are false, in everyday contexts we can be taken to know that radical skeptical hypotheses are
false (though it seems that the Rule of Sensitivity makes it impossible to assert that we have such
Contextualists like DeRose are quite willing to surrender the philosophical territory to the
21
David Lewis makes a similar point when he compares the epistemologist‟s situation with that of a person who
wants to say of a silent group of which he is a member that „All of us are silent‟ (see Lewis, 1996, p.238). DeRose
remarks, however, that he “would find it a bit embarrassing if we could never claim to have such knowledge [i.e.
knowledge that radical skeptical hypotheses are false] by means of simple knowledge attributions”; he thinks that
“in special conversational circumstances, it seems we can truthfully claim to know that not-H, despite the fact that
our belief that not-H is insensitive” (DeRose, 1995, note 36). On this point he gets a helpful interpretation of his
view from Hilary Kornblith: “It is important to recognize that on DeRose‟s view, the mentioning of skeptical
possibilities does not automatically raise the standards for knowledge attribution; it merely creates some pressure in
that direction, to which the otherwise anti-skeptical partner may or may not accede… Attempts to raise the standards
for knowledge, like attempts to change the topic of conversation, require the engagement of both conversational
partners” (Kornblith, 2000, p.28).
11
skeptic and fight only for (re)claiming the non-philosophical territory. This is because they admit
that they do not know how to refute skepticism; indeed, they find skepticism persuasive and want
to “explain the persuasiveness of the skeptic‟s attack” (DeRose, 2002, p.168). On the other hand,
they do not think that we should accept skepticism, which is why they attempt to explain the
persuasiveness of skepticism “in a way that makes it unthreatening to the truth of our ordinary
claims to know” (ibid.).22 Contextualists see having knowledge as, in many cases, a piece of cake
(such as when you look at your hands and know that you have hands); but since they do not
know how to refute skepticism, they try to have the cake and eat it too try to show that we do
3. Non-Threatening Skepticism
What makes skepticism a threat to human knowledge and our understanding of it is its
generality: all our (putative) knowledge of the external world is subject to the attack of the
skeptical argument. It is impossible for us to make use of any particular piece of knowledge of
the world to answer skepticism or to explain the possibility of human knowledge because that
very piece of knowledge is subject to the attack of the skeptical argument in the same way as the
rest of our knowledge. This is a point that Stroud emphasizes over and over again in his work on
skepticism. In the light of this understanding of the threat of skepticism, we should see that any
„skepticism‟ that attacks only particular pieces of knowledge rather than all our knowledge of the
external world at one fell swoop is not a real threat to human knowledge. Let us call such
22
Cohen expresses a similar understanding of the contextualist anti-skeptical strategy when he remarks that by
means of contextualism we can have a solution to the problem of skepticism that “preserves our belief that we know
things” and at the same time “explain[s] the undeniable appeal of skeptical argument” (Cohen, 2000, p.100).
12
skepticism that was first clearly formulated by Descartes and has been a worry of epistemologists
since then.
in my driveway. If I know that, then I also know that my car was not stolen two minutes ago. But
I do not know that my car was not stolen two minutes ago. Therefore, I do not know that my car
is parked in my driveway. Following John Hawthorne, let us call „My car was not stolen two
minutes ago‟ a lottery proposition, which is “a proposition of the sort that, while highly likely, is
2004, p.5). Obviously this argument is only about my knowledge that my car is parked in my
driveway and has no implication for my other knowledge of the world. Of course, what makes
the argument philosophically interesting is that it can be generalized: for many ordinary
propositions like „My car is parked in my driveway‟ we can find some lottery propositions and
form arguments like the one above (call them lottery arguments). This is why Hawthorne claims
that “[t]hese considerations generate powerful pressure towards a skepticism that claims that we
know little of what we ordinarily claim to know” (ibid.). Even with such generalization,
In most lottery arguments, the subject does not know the lottery proposition concerned
simply because of the particular epistemic position she is in with respect to that proposition. Her
not knowing it does not rule out the possibility that another subject in a different epistemic
position may know the proposition a lottery proposition to one subject may not be a lottery
proposition to another subject. Yes, I do not know that my car was not stolen two minutes ago
because I am in my study and cannot see my car from there, but my neighbor Chris may be
standing outside his house and looking at my car, and hence know that my car was not stolen two
13
minutes ago. Indeed, if I go out now and see my car, I will also know that my car is still parked
proposition to her at another time because her epistemic position with respect to the proposition
may change.
For those who think that lottery arguments are the basis of skepticism, lottery arguments
threaten human knowledge in general because for every ordinary proposition about the world
there is at least one lottery proposition, and hence at least one lottery argument by virtue of
which a person, no matter what circumstances she is in, can be shown not to know that ordinary
proposition. Even if the same proposition p is a lottery proposition to person A but not to person
B, it may, as the suggestion goes, still be the case that for B and p, there is a different lottery
proposition and a lottery argument that can show that B does not know that p. It is difficult to see
how this suggestion can be established. Perhaps it can be argued that Chris does not know that
my car was not stolen two minutes ago because he does not know that my car was not stolen two
minutes ago and was replaced with one that looks exactly like my car. But what if my brother
has been fixing my car for me the whole day? Isn‟t it clear that he knows that my car was not
Although contextualists focus on cases in which a person‟s epistemic position remains the same
with respect to a particular proposition in order to explain how epistemic standards determine
whether a knowledge attribution is true or false, they assume that people can be in different (i.e.
stronger or weaker) epistemic positions under different circumstances, whether with respect to
the same proposition or different propositions. When contextualism is used to explain why a
knowledge attribution is false, that is, why a subject does not know a particular proposition, it
14
leaves open the possibility that another subject under different circumstances may know the
proposition, either because the subject‟s epistemic position is different, or because the epistemic
of the skeptical argument, we are all in the same epistemic position with respect to a proposition
that expresses the negation of a radical skeptical hypothesis (such as „I am not a brain-in-a-vat‟),
and the same extremely high epistemic standards are used for assessing whether we know that
proposition, the result being that none of us knows it. But the very idea of contextualism is that
which the attributions are made. Even if there are contexts in which each of us is correctly
assessed as not knowing „I am not a brain-in-a-vat‟, contextualism leaves open the possibility
that there are other contexts in which we may be correctly assessed as knowing it. Indeed, as I
mentioned above, contextualists can argue that since in some contexts I can be correctly assessed
as knowing that I have hands, and since „I have hands‟ entails „I am not a brain-in-a-vat‟, in
construal of skepticism has the built-in feature of being non-threatening because contextualism
Skepticism, by contrast, assesses all our putative knowledge of the external world at one fell
swoop. When the skeptic considers a particular knowledge claim or knowledge attribution, he
uses it only as a representative example of our putative knowledge of the world, such as
Descartes‟ example of his putative knowledge that he is sitting in his room by the fire in his
15
dressing gown with a piece of paper in his hand,23 which is, as Stroud points out, “a best-possible
case” that “serves as the basis for a completely general assessment of the senses as a source of
knowledge about the world around us” (Stroud, 1984a, p.9). No such completely general
As we will see in the next section, the generality of the threat of skepticism consists not
only in its attacking all our beliefs about, and all our putative knowledge of, the external world at
one fell swoop, but also in its showing that we are in the exact same poor epistemic position with
respect to any proposition about the external world (at least any proposition about the world that
different epistemic positions with respect to the same proposition or different propositions, any
skepticism put in contextualist terms cannot be threatening in the way in which what Stroud calls
philosophical skepticism is. The way contextualists make skepticism “unthreatening to the truth
of our ordinary claims to know” (DeRose, 2002, p.168) is by replacing it with a straw man,
It should be noted that this criticism of the contextualist construal of skepticism is not a
is correct, the criticism still stands. Although the skeptical conclusion as construed by
contextualists is in a sense general, that is, the content of it is about all our putative knowledge of
the world, the truth of the conclusion is supposed to be always tied to a particular context in
which a particular human being has made a particular knowledge attribution. The skeptic, by
contrast, does not understand the truth of the skeptical conclusion as being tied to any particular
context. Contextualists may think this means that the skeptic does not understand the semantics
23
See Descartes‟s First Meditation.
16
of knowledge-attributing sentences. But the point here is, as far as his skepticism is concerned,
the skeptic is simply not in the business of assessing particular knowledge attributions made in
particular contexts. Contextualists may insist that the skeptic cannot arrive at the skeptical
this has to be established by an argument other than a mere formulation of the semantics, an
argument which contextualists have not offered. Unless there is such an argument, comparing the
attributions made in particular contexts is like comparing an atheist‟s argument against miracles
threatening. It is clear that DeRose‟s contextualism assumes that the world is in the main how we
believe it is, that is, that most of our beliefs about the world are true. Without such an
assumption, neither our different epistemic positions under different circumstances nor the
sensitivity of our beliefs can be determined in the way DeRose suggests to determine how
well our beliefs track the truth, we have to assume where the tracking starts. And it is not only
DeRose‟s version of contextualism that needs the assumption that most of our beliefs about the
world are true; all versions of contextualism need it. Contextualism appeals to the idea that in
some contexts we can truly be said to have knowledge of the world because epistemic standards
are low enough in those contexts, but this idea makes sense only on the assumption that the
beliefs in question are true. For if our beliefs are false, then no matter how low epistemic
standards are, meeting those standards will not turn our beliefs into knowledge — false beliefs
cannot be knowledge; and no matter how high epistemic standards are, it is not because of our
not meeting those standards that our beliefs are not knowledge — false beliefs are not knowledge
17
anyway.
DeRose admits that he assumes in his argument “certain things that we believe but that
the skeptic claims we can‟t know” (DeRose, 1995, p.215). He does not think this is problematic:
I‟m ready to admit to the skeptic that if I am a BIV [i.e. a brain-in-a-vat], then I don‟t
know I have hands, according to any standards for knowledge. But, of course, as I firmly
believe, I‟m not a BIV. Is it legitimate for me to use this conviction in a debate against
the skeptic? Not if we‟re playing King of the Mountain. But if the skeptic is marshalling
deeply felt intuitions of ours in an attempt to give us good reasons for accepting his
skepticism, it‟s legitimate to point out that other of our beliefs militate against his
position, and ask why we should give credence to just those that favor him. (ibid.)
This may sound reasonable given that DeRose (and other contextualists) is not trying to refute
skepticism. Since skepticism does not imply that all our beliefs about the world are false or that
skepticism when they assume that some or even most of our beliefs about the world are true.
This does not, however, mean that the assumption is unproblematic. Although the skeptic
does not argue that our beliefs about the world are false, his conclusion that we do not know
anything about the world does imply that our beliefs about the world are doubtful. Now the
problem is not merely that contextualists assume that some of our beliefs about the world are
true, but also that their account of knowledge attribution applies exclusively to cases in which “a
speaker A (or „attributor‟) says, „S knows that P,‟ of a subject S‟s true belief that P” (ibid., p.185;
italics added). Accordingly, when contextualists say that in philosophical contexts the skeptic is
right that we do not know anything about the world, what they really mean is that in those
contexts the skeptic is right that even our true beliefs about the world are not knowledge. But the
18
skeptic‟s question is never „Are our true beliefs about the world knowledge?‟; it is simply „Do
we know anything about the world?‟ or „Are our beliefs about the world knowledge?‟. The
skeptic‟s negative answer to the question, namely, that we do not know anything about the
world, does not mean „Even our true beliefs about the world are not knowledge‟. „Even our true
beliefs about the world are not knowledge‟ cannot express the doubts that the skeptic argues we
have good reasons to have. What the skeptic thinks we have good reasons to doubt is not that we
have knowledge of the world; for him this is not a matter of doubt he believes he has shown
that we do not have knowledge of the world. What he thinks we have good reasons to doubt,
reasons he believes he has given us by showing that we do not know anything about the world, is
that our beliefs about the world are mostly true. Any skepticism that does not imply such doubts
hypothesis is merely a remote possibility that we cannot rule out. From the perspective of what
we already believe, or believe that we know, about the world, a radical skeptical hypothesis is
indeed a very remote possibility, but what makes the skeptical argument so persuasive is not that
the radical skeptical hypothesis used in it is a possibility that cannot be ruled out. A radical
skeptical hypothesis that brings forth the threat of skepticism is one that effectively reveals to us
the difficulty of understanding, as Stroud puts it, “how we could get any knowledge of things
around us on the basis of sense-perception, given certain apparently undeniable facts about
sense-perception” (Stroud, 1984b, p.5). Whether it is the dream hypothesis, the brain-in-a-vat
hypothesis, or the evil demon hypothesis, the difficulty revealed is the same. Here is how Stroud
19
explains the difficulty:
There have been many versions of that fundamental idea. But whether it is expressed in
stimulations‟, or whatever it might be, the basic idea could be put by saying our
experiences or whatever they might be that serve as the sensory „basis‟ of our knowledge,
it does not follow that something we believe about the world around us is true. (ibid., p.6)
What we are led by a radical skeptical hypothesis to see is, in a nutshell, that we do not actually
perceive that the world is the way we believe it is and that, as a result, we are in the exact same
poor epistemic position with respect to any proposition about the world that we believe on the
basis of sense-perception.
I am not going to rehearse the details of any particular skeptical argument here; the point
I want to make is merely that the persuasiveness of skepticism has everything to do with the
problem of sense-perception I have just mentioned and has very little to do with a radical
skeptical hypothesis being a (remote) possibility that we cannot rule out. Even if it is possible to
solve the problem of skepticism without refuting the skeptical argument, any „solution‟ to it that
does not address the problem of sense-perception, such as the contextualist „solution‟,24 is no real
solution; this is because without addressing the problem of sense-perception, such a „solution‟
cannot help us understand how human knowledge is possible, and it is such understanding that
20
hypothesis makes skepticism so persuasive is that it is based on some “apparently undeniable
facts about sense-perception” (ibid., p.5). One such apparently undeniable fact is that in
hallucination a person can have sensory experience of something that is not really there. Another
is that a dream can be so vivid and realistic that the sensory content of it is indistinguishable
from what we would experience if it was not a dream but was what really happened in our
waking life. The latter fact (if it is a fact) is, of course, the basis for the famous dream argument
offered by Descartes.
In order to lead us to see that there is a general problem of sense-perception, the problem
that our knowledge of the world is underdetermined by our sensory experience, a skeptical
hypothesis has to be radical enough to make it impossible for us to rely on any particular sensory
experience. However, if the skeptical hypothesis is too radical, it may lead us so far afield that
we do not see that it is about our actual situation. This may be why Stroud focuses on the dream
hypothesis rather than the evil demon hypothesis when he discusses Descartes‟s skeptical
argument, though the dream hypothesis is, as Penelope Maddy points out, “the functional
equivalent of the Evil Demon hypothesis” (Maddy, 2007, p.23): we all have the experience of
dreaming, but we do not believe that we have the experience of being deceived by the evil
demon (even though the very point of the hypothesis is that all our experiences are the evil
demon‟s tricks). The brain-in-a-vat hypothesis, which DeRose focuses on, is in this respect more
like the evil demon hypothesis than the dream hypothesis we do not believe that we have the
major traditional problem in epistemology and most contextualists are epistemologists who have
studied the problem and its history. So why don‟t they see that a radical skeptical hypothesis
21
points to precisely this problem? Why do they treat it instead as nothing more than a remote
possibility? The answer cannot simply be that they focus on skeptical hypotheses that are too
radical, such as the brain-in-a-vat hypothesis, for some of them do discuss the dream hypothesis.
I am going to suggest an explanation of this oversight that, I think, may tell us something about
We have seen in the last section that contextualists assume that most of our beliefs about
the world are true. The word „assume‟ may, however, be too weak to convey the fact that
contextualists examine skepticism from the view of the world that they actually have the view
of the world that we all have, the view that is constituted by the beliefs we share about the world,
such as that there are trees and mountains, that most of us have hands, that we are not brains-in-
vats, etc. This view of the world would not be possible if we did not have the following central
belief that constitutes part of the view: our most direct and reliable access to specifics of the
world is through our senses, our perceptual experiences. As P. F. Strawson puts it, “we think of
perception as a way, indeed the basic way, of informing ourselves about the world of
independently existing things: we assume, that is to say, the general reliability of our perceptual
experiences” (Strawson, 1979, p.103); and more importantly, such a belief about the relation
between perceptual experiences and the world “so thoroughly permeates our consciousness that
even those who are intellectually convinced of its falsity remain subject to its power” (ibid.,
p.106). Whether contextualists are (and they probably are not) intellectually convinced of the
falsity of the belief that we have perceptual access to the world, they are, like the rest of us,
subject to the power of the belief. Unless we adopt persistently a detached attitude towards the
belief, we cannot help seeing things through it. A plausible answer to the question of why
contextualists lose sight of the connection between the problem of skepticism and the problem of
22
sense-perception even though they are familiar with the problem of sense-perception is thus this:
when they deal with skepticism, they are not able to, as it were, free themselves from the grip of
The difficulty of philosophy that this explanation reveals is the difficulty of maintaining
the detached attitude required for doing philosophy, that is, the detached attitude towards the
beliefs that we have and that we are also philosophically examining.25 On the one hand, we do
have the beliefs in question; one the other hand, our task is to examine the beliefs without
employing or being affected by the beliefs. The detachment required is particularly difficult in
the case of the belief that we have perceptual access to the world because the belief “thoroughly
permeates our consciousness” and because all other beliefs about the world that we acquire on
the basis of this very belief and they are numerous fortify it.
When contextualists discuss knowledge attribution, they focus on epistemic standards and
contexts. Suppose they are right about the mechanism; this does not, however, mean that
complex human practice that is intertwined with other practices we have, with how we interact
and communicate with one another, and with how we make evaluations about ourselves as well
as people and things around us. In this section I will discuss some important aspects of the
practice of knowledge attribution that can help explain further why contextualists can neither
take skepticism seriously nor solve the problem of skepticism. I will try to establish two points:
25
For a detailed discussion of philosophical detachment, see Wong (2002).
23
first, the more we can make sense of particular knowledge attributions, the less we can take
skepticism seriously; and second, the practice of knowledge attribution as we understand and
The two points are, of course, related. Let me begin with the second point. When
knowledge-attributing sentences are uttered. But the practice of knowledge attribution is more
not aware of the fact that utterances of knowledge-attributing sentences are closely related to
practical concerns that we have in our everyday life. DeRose, for example, is clearly aware of
that when he suggests, in his initial formulation of contextualism, that “requirements for making
a knowledge attribution true go up as the stakes go up” (DeRose, 1992, p.915, italics added). He
makes this remark with respect to the bank cases he discusses (ibid., p.913); he refers to these
cases again in DeRose (2005) and relates them to “the practical concerns involved” (DeRose,
2005, p.176) and “the actual practical situation that a speaker faces” (ibid., p.177). Nevertheless,
when contextualists do speak of practical concerns, they mean no more than practical concerns
that an individual has under some particular circumstances. They overlook the fact that the
practice of knowledge attribution is a collective practice in the sense that its existence requires
that, first, most of us engage in the practice; second, we have some common understanding of the
practice; and third, we have some common purposes when we engage in the practice.
It is not possible that there should have been only one occasion on which one obeyed a
rule. It is not possible that there should have been only one occasion on which a report
24
was made, an order given or understood; and so on. To obey a rule, to make a report,
to give an order, to play a game of chess, are customs (uses, institutions). (Wittgenstein,
The practice of knowledge attribution is, I think, in the same sense a custom or an institution: it
is not possible that there should have been only one occasion on which a knowledge attribution
was made. The development of the practice of knowledge attribution took a long time and
depended on many factors; it is, like “[c]ommanding, questioning, storytelling, chatting”, “as
much a part of our natural history as walking, eating, drinking, playing” (ibid., §25).
The collective practice of knowledge attribution would not have been developed if there
had never been cases in which human beings agreed that what they did in attributing knowledge
to themselves and others was done sincerely and successfully. Indeed, when we learn to engage
between sincere and insincere attributions as well as between successful and unsuccessful
attributions.
knowledge acquirer is to acquire knowledge by finding someone who knows what one wants to
know, someone who can provide one with the knowledge concerned;27 to be a knowledge
examiner is to examine whether someone who claims to know something really knows it. For a
knowledge acquirer, positive knowledge attributions are more important than negative ones; a
26
This distinction between knowledge acquirer and knowledge examiner is inspired by Bernard Williams‟s
discussion of what he calls „the examiner situation‟ in Williams (1970) and Williams (1972).
27
We sometimes say that we can acquire knowledge by finding something, such as a book or a fossil, that contains
the knowledge that we want, but it is clear that this is a derivative use of the word „knowledge‟ a book does not
know anything, only the author does; and a fossil cannot contain any knowledge unless it contains something that
has already been known by someone.
25
positive knowledge attribution is an expression of his judgment that the knowledge provider has
been found. By contrast, a knowledge examiner may, so to speak, pass or fail someone in a
None of this implies that there cannot be particular contexts of knowledge attribution in which
there is no knowledge acquirer or knowledge examiner, but these are atypical cases which would
not be possible without typical cases in which there is a knowledge acquirer or a knowledge
examiner.
or the knowledge examiner is qualified, that is, the knowledge acquirer finds her knowledge
provider or the knowledge examiner possesses the knowledge about which she tests others.
Again, this does not imply that there cannot be particular contexts in which a knowledge acquirer
fails to find her knowledge provider. A knowledge acquirer may fail for various reasons;
sometimes it is because the knowledge provider looked for simply does not exist (that is, no one
has the knowledge). But if there had never been any knowledge provider, there would not have
been any knowledge acquirer either. There may also be particular contexts in which a knowledge
examiner does not possess the knowledge about which she tests others. Sometimes we can tell
whether someone knows something even if we ourselves do not have the knowledge. But if no
one had ever known anything about the world, it would not make sense for any of us to test
that we have knowledge of the world. Some may object that what it takes for there to be such a
practice is that we believe that we have knowledge of the world rather than that we do have such
knowledge. Yes, such a belief is required, but it is important to note that I am speaking of the
26
practice of knowledge attribution as we understand and engage in it. There is no such thing as
anything about the world. It is in this sense that the practice presupposes our knowledge of the
world, and it is from the perspective as practitioners of knowledge attribution that contextualists
are unable to take skepticism seriously. An analogy may help here. The practice of prayer as
religious believers understand and engage in it presupposes the existence of a personal God. We
could say that what it takes for there to be the practice of prayer is that religious believers believe
that a personal God exists and listens to their prayers, but this would not be the practice of prayer
as religious believers understand and practice it. There is a sense in which there is no such thing
knowledge attribution. It is because of our having learnt to attribute knowledge under different
circumstances, and because of our understanding of the practice as a result of such learning, that
we are able to make sense of particular knowledge attributions by ourselves and others. The
more we are able to make sense of particular knowledge attributions under different
circumstances, the more we are part of the practice or custom of knowledge attribution,
and the more difficult it is for us to take skepticism seriously. Since contextualism applies only
contextualists to detach themselves from the practice of knowledge attribution when they devote
their attention to how contextualism works in particular knowledge attributions, and hence very
Should we then say that contextualists beg the question against skepticism by assuming,
qua practitioners of knowledge attribution, that we have knowledge of the world? The answer is
27
more complicated than a straightforward „Yes‟. For one thing, contextualists do not attempt to
refute skepticism, so there may not be a problem of begging the question even though they do
assume that we have knowledge of the world; for another, contextualists may be willing to grant
that skepticism is true in philosophical contexts. Now even if contextualists do not beg the
question against skepticism, they are in no position to solve the problem of skepticism if solving
it involves explaining in the most general way how we have knowledge of the world. As for
philosophical contexts, it is not clear how they should be understood with respect to the practice
of knowledge attribution. If they are contexts in which knowledge attributions are made in the
normal way, then they cannot be contexts in which we can understand ourselves as knowing
nothing about the world. But if they are contexts in which knowledge attributions are supposed
to be made independently of the normal practice, then we may not be able to make sense of such
fantasy of contextualists.28
6. What the Skeptic May Learn from How We Use the Word ‘Know’
Contextualists have not shown that skepticism is not a real threat to human knowledge of the
world, nor have they shown how human knowledge is possible. The skeptic thus has nothing to
learn from them. Although Stroud has never criticized the contextualist anti-skeptical strategy
directly, what he says below is close to my conclusion that the skeptic has nothing to learn from
Identifying the assumptions about sense-perception that are responsible for the ease with
28
For a discussion of the difficulty of understanding the notion of a philosophical context, see Wong (2006),
sections V-VII.
28
which a sceptical conclusion can be reached, and learning why those assumptions are
unacceptable and what should be put in their place, would be a rich reward for taking the
traditional sceptical reasoning seriously and trying to get to the bottom of it. We could
would be a substantial, positive payoff: much better than what is offered by those who
see in the sceptical reasoning nothing more than arbitrary insistence on impossibly high
This does not, however, mean that the skeptic cannot learn anything from how we use the word
„know‟. How we use the word „know‟ is not just a matter of how truth conditions of knowledge-
attributing sentences are determined. By considering the important roles that the practice of
knowledge attribution plays in our lives and in our understanding of the world around us, the
skeptic may realize a grave difficulty in being a skeptic, a difficulty that he has not been aware of
so far. The difficulty is that the skeptic cannot avoid engaging in the practice of knowledge
attribution even though he believes that skepticism is true. The more general lesson the skeptic
may learn is that, as Stroud puts it, “we can understand ourselves as perceiving and believing and
knowing things only from within whatever position we already occupy in understanding the
world, and so only as part of understanding everything else that is so in the very world we all
29
I am grateful to Jason Bridges and Niko Kolodny for very helpful comments.
29
References
Cohen, S. (1987). Knowledge, context, and social standards. Synthèse, 73, 3-26.
DeRose, K. (1995). Solving the skeptical problem. Reprinted in K. DeRose & T. A. Warfield
1999.
DeRose, K. (1999). Contextualism: An explanation and defense. In J. Greco & E. Sosa (Eds.),
DeRose, K. (2002). Assertion, knowledge, and context. Philosophical Review, 111, 167-203.
DeRose, K. (2005). The ordinary language basis for contextualism, and the new invariantism.
30
Ellis, J. (2010). Stroud‟s proposal for removing the threat of skepticism. In this volume.
91-114.
Feldman, R. (2001). Skeptical problems, contextualist solutions. Philosophical Studies, 103, 61-
85.
Huemer, M. (2001). Skepticism and the veil of perception. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Klein, P. (2000). Contextualism and the real nature of academic skepticism. Philosophical
Kornblith, H. (2000). The contextualist evasion of epistemology. Philosophical Issues, 10, 24-
32.
Ludlow, P. (2005). Contextualism and the new linguistic turn in epistemology. In G. Preyer & G.
University Press.
Maddy, P. (2007). Second philosophy: A naturalistic method. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
31
96, 317-333.
Stanley, J. (2004). On the linguistic basis for contextualism. Philosophical Studies, 119, 119-
146.
Strawson, P. F. (1979). Perception and its objects. Reprinted in J. Dancy (Ed.), Perceptual
Press.
Reflections and replies: Essays on the philosophy of Tyler Burge (pp.15-27). Cambridge,
Stroud, B. (2009). Scepticism and the senses. European Journal of Philosophy, 17, 559-570.
32
Williams, B. (1970). Deciding to believe. Reprinted in B. Williams, Problems of the self (pp.
Williams, B. (1972). Knowledge and reasons. In G. H. von Wright (Ed.), Problems in the theory
Wittgenstein, L. (1969). On certainty (G. E. M. Anscombe & G. H. von Wright, Eds.) (D. Paul &
Wong, W. (2006). Moore, the skeptic, and the philosophical context. Pacific Philosophical
33