Kants Virtue Ethics PDF
Kants Virtue Ethics PDF
Kants Virtue Ethics PDF
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
http://www.jstor.org/stable/3750390?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
Royal Institute of Philosophy, Cambridge University Press are collaborating with JSTOR to
digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy
This content downloaded from 103.231.241.233 on Mon, 20 Mar 2017 13:12:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Kant's Virtue Ethics
ROBERT B. LOUDEN
This content downloaded from 103.231.241.233 on Mon, 20 Mar 2017 13:12:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Robert B. Louden
which the notion that morality is anything other than obedience to rules
has almost, if not quite, disappeared from sight'.2 Philippa Foot
chastises Kant as one of a select group of philosophers whose 'tacitly
accepted opinion was that a study of the topic [of the virtues and vices]
would form no part of the fundamental work of ethics ...'.3 On her
view, Kant should bear a sizable part of the responsibility for analytic
philosophy's neglect of virtue. And Bernard Williams is equally critical
in his insistent claims that Kantian moral theory treats persons in
abstraction from character, and thus stands guilty of misrepresenting
not only persons but morality and practical deliberation as well.4 The
underlying message is not simply that Kant is an illustrative represent-
ative of the deontological rule ethics perspective, but that his ethics is
the worst possible sort of deontological rule ethics, one which is pri-
marily responsible for the eclipse of agent-centred ethics.
Yet some readers of Kant feel that the conceptual shape of his ethical
theory has been distorted by defender and critic alike, that his ethics is
not rule ethics but virtue ethics. This reading of Kant has had its
defenders in the past (he did after all write The Doctrine of Virtue), but
Onora O'Neill has recently placed it in the context of the contemporary
virtue ethics debate. In 'Kant After Virtue' (a reply to MacIntyre's
book), she states confidently that 'what is not in doubt . . . is that Kant
offers primarily an ethic of virtue rather than an ethic of rules'.5 So
whose Kant is the real Kant-hers or the more familiar one of MacIn-
tyre & Co.?
The real Kant lies somewhere in between these two extremes. He
sought to build an ethical theory which could assess both the life plans
of moral agents and their discrete acts. This is to his credit, for an
adequate moral theory needs to do both.
474
This content downloaded from 103.231.241.233 on Mon, 20 Mar 2017 13:12:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Kant's Virtue Ethics
Agents v. Acts
One hallmark of virtue ethics is its strong agent orientation. For virtue
theorists, the primary object of moral evaluation is not the intentional
act or its consequences, but the agent. Utilitarians begin with a concept
of the good-here defined with reference to states of affairs rather than
persons. Duty, rights, and even virtue are all treated by utilitarians as
derivative categories of secondary importance, definable in terms of
utility maximization. Similarly, deontologists take duty as their
irreducible starting point, and reject any attempt to define this root
notion of being morally bound to do something in terms of good to be
achieved. The good is now a derivative category, definable in terms of
the right. The good that we are to promote is right action for its own
sake-duty for duty's sake. Virtue also is a derivative notion, definable
in terms of pro-attitudes towards one's duties. It is important, but only
because it helps us to do our duty.
Virtue ethics begins with a notion of the morally good person which
is primitive in the sense that it is not defined in terms of performing
obligatory acts ('the person who acts as duty requires') or end-states
('the agent who is disposed to maximize utility through his acts'). On
the contrary, right and wrong acts are now construed in terms of what
the good agent would or would not do; worthy and unworthy ends in
terms of what the good agent would or would not aim at. It is by means
of this conceptual shift that 'being' rather than 'doing' achieves prom-
inence in virtue ethics.
475
This content downloaded from 103.231.241.233 on Mon, 20 Mar 2017 13:12:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Robert B. Louden
Motivation
A third general area where we are likely to see differences between agent
and act ethics is in their respective views on moral motivation. This
complex issue is particularly important in any reading of Kantian ethics
as virtue ethics. For the duty-based or deontological theorist, the
preferred motive is respect for the idea of duty itself, and the good man
is the one who does his duty for duty's sake. This does not entail that the
agent who does his duty for duty's sake does so grudgingly, or only in
spite of inclinations to the contrary, but simply that the determining
ground of the motive is respect for duty. For the goal-based or
utilitarian theorist, the preferred motive is a steady disposition to
maximize uti lity.
In virtue ethics the preferred motivation factor is not duty or utility
but the virtues themselves. The agent who acts from dispositions of
friendship, courage, or integrity is held higher than the person who
performs the same acts but from different motives. For instance, a
virtue theorist might call a man courageous only if, when in danger, it
was clear that the man did not even want to run away (and thus showed
signs of being 'directly moved' to act courageously), while the duty-
based theorist would only call a man courageous if he did not run away
out of sense of duty (but perhaps wanted to anyway-though the 'want'
is here irrelevant). As the example suggests, matters become trouble-
some when we bring in reason and inclination. I have not said that one
theory asserts we are motivated by reason, another by desire. However,
reason and inclination do enter into the motivation issue (particularly in
debates over Kant) in the following way. Virtue ethics, with its 'virtue
for virtue's sake' position on motivation, is also committed to the claim
that our natural inclinations play a necessary role in many types of
action done from virtue. Acting from the virtue of friendship, for
instance, would require that one possess and exhibit certain feelings
about friends. Kant, on the other hand, holds (from the Foundations
on) that the sole determining ground of the will must be respect
(Achtung)-a peculiarly non-empirical feeling produced by an intellec-
tual awareness of the moral law. Kant thus appears to deny natural
inclinations any positive role in moral motivation, whereas virtue ethics
requires it.
476
This content downloaded from 103.231.241.233 on Mon, 20 Mar 2017 13:12:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Kant's Virtue Ethics
477
This content downloaded from 103.231.241.233 on Mon, 20 Mar 2017 13:12:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Robert B. Louden
always possess inclinations which may lead them to act against reason.
Their wills are thus in a perpetual state of tension. Some wills are better
than others, but only a holy will (who has no wants that could run
counter to reason, and who can thus do no evil) possesses an absolutely
good will. This is why Kant holds that 'human morality in its highest
stages can still be nothing more than virtue'. 12 Virtue is only an approxi-
mation of the good will, because of the basic conflict or tension in
human wills. Kant's virtuous agent is a human approximation of a good
will who through strength of mind continually acts out of respect for the
moral law while still feeling the presence of natural inclinations which
could tempt him to act from other motives.
Now if virtue is the human approximation to the good will, and if the
good will is the only unqualified good, this does imply that moral
virtue, for Kant, is foundational, and not (as one would expect in a
deontological theory) a concept of derivative or secondary importance.
('Everything good that is not based on a morally good disposition ... is
nothing but pretence and glittering misery.') As Harbison notes: 'the
essence of [Kant's] moral philosophy is quite different from what it has
commonly been supposed to be, for on the basis of this enquiry one
must conclude that it is the concept of the good will that lies at its
foundation'. 13
But there remains a fundamental problem for this particular argu-
ment in favour of a virtue ethics reading of Kant. Both the good will and
virtue are defined in terms of obedience to moral law, for they are both
wills which are in conformity to moral law and which act out of respect
for it. Kant begins with the good will in order to uncover 'the supreme
principle of morality' -the categorical imperative. Since human virtue
is defined in terms of conformity to law and the categorical imperative,
it appears now that what is primary in Kantian ethics is not virtue for
virtue's sake but obedience to rules. Virtue is the heart of the ethical for
Kant, in the sense that it is the basis for all judgments of moral worth.
But Kantian virtue is itself defined in terms of the supreme principle of
morality. The conceptual commitment to agency and long-term char-
acteristic behaviour rather than atomic acts and decision procedures for
moral quandaries is evident here, as one would expect in virtue ethics.
But what Kant prizes most about moral agency is its ability to act
consistently from respect for law, not in the sense of following specific
rules for specific acts, but in the more fundamental sense of guiding
one's entire life by respect for rationally legislated and willed law.
12 Kant, The Doctrine of Virtue, 41, Ak. 382. See also the Critique of
Practical Reason, trans. Lewis White Beck (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill,
1956), 86-87, Ak. 84-85, and the Foundations, 30-31, Ak. 414.
13 Warren G. Harbison, 'The Good Will', Kant-Studien (1980), 59.
478
This content downloaded from 103.231.241.233 on Mon, 20 Mar 2017 13:12:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Kant's Virtue Ethics
Re-reading Maxims
479
This content downloaded from 103.231.241.233 on Mon, 20 Mar 2017 13:12:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Robert B. Louden
intentions for the future, yet Kant frequently asserts that we never
know the real morality of our actions. This suggests that maxims and
specific intentions are not the same. (2) Sometimes we act without a
specific intention (e.g. when we act absentmindedly), but Kant holds
that we always act on some maxim. All action is open to moral assess-
ment. This again suggests a difference between maxims and specific
intentions. i7
Now if Kantian maxims are best seen as underlying rather than as
specific intentions, we do have a strong argument for a virtue reading of
Kant's ethics. For our underlying intentions tie in directly with the
sorts of persons we are and with the sorts of lives we lead. And the sort
of person one is obviously depends upon what virtues and vices one
possesses. One's specific intentions, on the other hand, are not always
an accurate guide to the sort of person one is 'deep down inside'. This
connection between underlying intentions and being a certain sort of
person is stressed by both O'Neill and Hdffe.18 However, two basic
problems confront this interpretation. First, O'Neill's use of the phrase
'underlying intentions' is ambiguous. At one point, she states that
adopting maxims is a matter of 'leading a certain sort of life, or being a
certain sort of person'; elsewhere she asserts that maxims (or underly-
ing intentions) 'need not be longer-term intentions, for we remain free
to change them'.'9 This distinction between underlying and longer-
term intentions does not sit well with the asserted identification
between underlying intentions and being a certain sort of person. For
becoming a certain sort of person is a long-term process. One cannot
decide at noon on Monday to be courageous and saintly, and then
suddenly become so by Tuesday. And in what sense do we 'remain free
to change' the sort of person we have become? I believe there is a strong
sense in which such a change can be undertaken, but the effort and time
required to carry it out are certainly much greater than are the effort
and time required to change one's specific intentions at any given
moment. In short, the more 'underlying' intentions are untied from
'longer-term' intentions, the less plausible it becomes to assert that
maxims (in the sense of underlying intentions) have to do with leading
a certain sort of life and with virtue. For the latter are long-term
ventures. One does not initiate, abandon or change them on a daily
basis.
One reason for O'Neill's odd insistence on the underlying/long-term
intention distinction is perhaps traceable to Kantian texts. In several
places, Kant warns that we must not construe virtue as a 'mere aptitude
480
This content downloaded from 103.231.241.233 on Mon, 20 Mar 2017 13:12:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Kant's Virtue Ethics
20 Kant, The Doctrine of Virtue, 41-42, Ak. 383, 69/407. Cf. Anthropol-
ogy, 26-27, Ak. 153.
21 Kant to the contrary, Aristotelian virtue is not a mechanical habit but
rather a state of character determined by a rational principle (Nicomachean
Ethics 1107al).
22 Kant, The Doctrine of Virtue, 42, Ak. 383.
481
This content downloaded from 103.231.241.233 on Mon, 20 Mar 2017 13:12:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Robert B. Louden
482
This content downloaded from 103.231.241.233 on Mon, 20 Mar 2017 13:12:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Kant's Virtue Ethics
24 Kant, The Doctrine of Virtue, 46, Ak. 386. Other components of the
duty of self-perfection include the cultivation of one's 'natural powers'-
powers of 'mind, soul, and body'.
25 Kant, The Doctrine of Virtue, 80, Ak. 416. Cf. 17/218: 'All duties,
merely because they are duties, belong to ethics'.
483
This content downloaded from 103.231.241.233 on Mon, 20 Mar 2017 13:12:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Robert B. Louden
While virtue has far greater prominence in Kant's ethics than many of
his readers suppose, it is nevertheless overstating matters to assert
baldly that Kantian ethics is virtue ethics. Significant aspects of both
the agent and act perspectives are present in his ethical theory, though
the former does dominate. Kantian ethical theory seeks to assess not
484
This content downloaded from 103.231.241.233 on Mon, 20 Mar 2017 13:12:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Kant's Virtue Ethics
only atomic acts but also agents' ways of life. And while the sort of
person one becomes (rather than the specific acts one may perform and
the short-term intentions one may adopt) is central in Kantian ethics,
his conception of moral personhood is defined in terms of obedience to
law. The Kantian agent commitment is inextricably fused to a law
conception of ethics. Each of the three arguments outlined earlier
points to these same conclusions, which is not surprising, since they are
closely related to begin with. The later material from the Tugendlehre
regarding morally necessary ends (of which the duty of moral self-
perfection is the most important) restates and deepens the earlier
material from the Grundlegung concerning the good will. The section
on maxims establishes that while not all Kantian maxims refer to
underlying intentions and agents' life plans, the most significant ones in
ethics (maxims of ends) do.
One notorious roadblock to a virtue interpretation of Kantian ethics
remains, and it requires an unconventional but (I believe) Kantian
reply. Virtue theorists part ways with their deontological and teleolog-
ical opponents over the issue of moral motivation. In virtue ethics agents
are expected to act for the sake of virtue; in deontology, for duty's sake;
in utilitarianism, for utility's sake. Now at first glance it would seem
impossible to argue that Kant espouses a virtue ethics position with
respect to motivation, since he holds that only action from duty can
have moral worth. However, as my earlier arguments indicate, Kant's
notion of action aus Pflicht means in the most fundamental sense not
that one performs a specific act for the sake of a specific rule which
prescribes it (and likewise for other specific acts one performs) but
rather that one strives for a way of life in which all of one's acts are a
manifestation of a character which is in harmony with moral law.
Action aus Pflicht is action motivated by virtue, albeit virtue in Kant's
sternly rationalist sense.
But it is precisely on the issue of rationalism and moral motivation
that Kant has come under such severe criticism. The motivation pro-
blem has been a favourite target of Kantian critics from Hegel onward,
and to cover all of its dimensions is far beyond the scope of this paper.
The following brief remarks focus instead on Kant's position regarding
the role of emotion in action from virtue.
It is generally acknowledged that, from a moral perspective, the most
praiseworthy acts are often those which agents truly want to perform.
As Foot remarks: 'Who shows most courage, the one who wants to run
away but does not, or the one who does not even want to run away? Who
shows most charity, the one who finds it easy to make the good of others
his object, or the one who finds it hard? ... The man who acts charit-
ably out of a sense of duty is not to be undervalued, but it is the other
ti.e. the one who is directly moved and who thus wants to act charit-
485
This content downloaded from 103.231.241.233 on Mon, 20 Mar 2017 13:12:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Robert B. Louden
ably] who shows most virtue and therefore to the other that most moral
worth is attributed.'26 The sense of 'wants' here needs to be clarified,
and I will attempt to do so in a moment. But first, a restatement of the
underlying anti-Kantian argument: acting from virtue is (at least some-
times) action motivated by altruistic emotion or desire. Kant, however,
holds that action aus Pflicht must be defined independently of all
natural emotions and desires. Therefore, there is no place in Kantian
ethics for acting from virtue.27
Now back to 'wants'. Does Foot's agent who does 'not even want to
run away' act this way by nature or because he knows (in addition,
perhaps, to being naturally inclined in this direction) that it is noble to
do so? In Aristotelian terminology, does he act courageously out of
'natural virtue' or from 'virtue in the strict sense', the latter of which
involves phronesis, a rational understanding of what one is doing?
Aristotle and Kant agree on this fundamental point: acting from virtue
in the strict sense means acting rationally. But Aristotle also holds that
practical choice is 'reason motivated by desire (orektikos nous) or desire
operating through reason (orexis dianoetike)'.28 Desire and reason are
both necessary factors in moral choice, but neither on its own is
sufficient. How about Kant? Does acting from virtue, as he under-
stands it, entail acting from desires (in addition to reason)?
Kant has so often been tagged as enemy-of-the-emotions that it may
seem foolish even to ask the question. On most interpretations, Kant
allows room for one (and only one) desire in his account of moral
choice-respect or reverence (Achtung)-a unique 'a prwio feeling',
generated by a pure judgment which acknowledges the claim of the
moral law, and then in turn acts as the phenomenal spring to action
from appreciation of that law. But the role of emotions and natural
inclinations in Kant's understanding or moral motivation is trickier
than is often assumed. On the one hand, he does assert unequivocally
that 'what is essential in the moral worth of actions is that the moral law
should directly determine the will'.29 This way of talking is often
construed as meaning that reason is not only a necessary but also a
sufficient ground for moral choice, and that natural emotions (with the
sole exception of Achtung, which again is an a priori feeling and thus not
natural) have no positive role to play whatsoever. But while determina-
486
This content downloaded from 103.231.241.233 on Mon, 20 Mar 2017 13:12:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Kant's Virtue Ethics
30 Karl Ameriks, 'The Hegelian Critique of Kantian Morality', 11. (MS. read
at the 1984 American Philosophical Association Western Division
Meeting.)
31 Kant, Critique of Practical Reason, 75, Ak. 73. Here I am following
Ameriks, 12.
487
This content downloaded from 103.231.241.233 on Mon, 20 Mar 2017 13:12:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Robert B. Louden
for we do not love it but rather shirk as much as we can the occasion
for practising it'.32 Here and elsewhere Kant addresses the need to culti-
vate an 'habitually cheerful heart', in order that the feeling of joy
accompanies (but does not constitute or determine) our virtue. A
parallel passage occurs near the beginning of the Religion: 'Now if one
asks, what is the aesthetic character, the temperament, so to speak, of
virtue, whether courageous and hence joyous or fear-ridden and
dejected, an answer is hardly necessary. This latter slavish frame of
mind can never occur without a hidden hatred of the law. And a heart
which is happy in the performance of its duty (not merely complacent
in the recognition thereof) is a mark of genuineness in the virtuous
disposition. ...'33
These and other related passages state explicitly that the enemy-
of -the-emotions reading of Kant favoured by so many is a gross misun-
derstanding. Kant's position is clear: pure practical reason needs to be
always 'in charge' of the emotions in a truly virtuous life. The Bestim-
mungsgrund of moral choice must be reason, not feeling. But an
integral part of moral discipline or what Kant calls 'ethical gymnastic' is
training the emotions so that they work with rather than against reason.
Acts in which empirical inclinations of any sort are the Bestim-
mungsgrund lack moral worth, but it doesn't follow that a harmonizing
sentiment must cancel all moral worth. On the contrary, Kant insists
that it is a good thing.
Kant then would agree with Foot's claim that the agent who does not
even want to run away shows more courage than the one who wants to
run away but does not, provided that the 'want' in question is a rational
want with which the agent's desires are trained to be in harmony. More
generally, acting from virtue, on Kant's view, does entail disciplining
the emotions through reason so that one comes to want to perform the
same external act that reason commands. But again, as Kant warns,
there is a risk, for in training the emotions in such a manner it becomes
more difficult to assess one's motives for action. One is perpetually
flirting with the possibility that one's conduct is not autonomously
willed but merely a product of heteronomy, but cultivation of virtue
requires that the risk be taken.
Kant's position on the emotions and their role in action from virtue is
not inconsistent with a virtue ethics view. It is remarkably close to
Aristotle's view, the major difference being that Kant was much more
488
This content downloaded from 103.231.241.233 on Mon, 20 Mar 2017 13:12:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Kant's Virtue Ethics
489
This content downloaded from 103.231.241.233 on Mon, 20 Mar 2017 13:12:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms