EARLY SCHOLASTIC ANGELOLOGY
This paper surveys the doctrine on angels taught by theologians
in the first century of scholasticism (ca. 1130-ca. 1230). This topic
has received virtually no scholarly attention; but it is of interest
for the light it sheds on the concerns of school theologians during
this formative stage of their discipline. We can subdivide our tar-
get century into three parts, the first half of the twelfth century
closing with the Sentences of Peter Lombard, the second half of
the twelfth century, and the first quarter of the thirteenth century.
In the first of these three stages, scholastic theologians, for the
first time, faced the challenge of creating a syllabus for the teach-
ing of systematic theology and developed the sentence collection
as their genre of choice for that purpose. The question of where to
place angels within that context and genre, or even if they should
be placed there at all, was the single most heavily debated topic on
their angelological agenda. Another major matter on that agenda
on which agreement reigned as to the desired outcome, although
different masters proposed different itineraries to their common
destination, was the felt need to refute Origen’s claim that back-
sliding and conversion remained eternal options, so that Lucifer
and the fallen angels might even be saved.' Other issues that
attracted attention had to do with the psychology of angels and
their exercise of reason and will both before and after their fall or
confirmation in glory.
By comparison, the interest in angels displayed by scholastics
in the second sub-period is quite muted. The more speculative
among them were eager to make use of the logica nova now availl-
able, and focused on topics like Trinitarian theology and Christol-
ogy where theological language is critical and where, in their
view, this new technical semantic and logical equipment could
A shorter version of this paper was presented at the 29th Intemational Con-
gress of Medieval Studies, Western Michigan University. Kalamazoo, MI, 8 May
1994
1. For a general orientation on this issue, see Jean LecLeRco, Origene au Xile
siécle in Irénikon 24, 1951, p. 425-439; Jeffrey Burton RUSSELL, Lucifer: The
Devil in the Middle Ages (Ithaca, 1984), p. 110.EARLY SCHOLASTIC ANGELOLOGY 81
best be put to use. Since angelology seemed remote from this con-
cern, it shrank in importance in their eyes. With one notable
exception, most masters in our second sub-period, whether
express followers of Peter Lombard or not, were content to repeat
his teaching on angels for the most part, thereby attesting to the
swiftness with which his theology had become the consensus pos
tion on angels. On the other hand, the early thirteenth-century
scholastics developed angelologies remarkable for their amplitude
and detail. Their emphasis might rest on ethical, epistemological,
or metaphysical questions regarding angels. Either way, their
teachings reflect a notable interest in applying philosophy to
angelology, whether Neoplatonic or Aristotelian or both, a ten-
dency visible even in the case of theologians who have impressed
modem scholars as being cool to philosophical theology.
For the first generation or two of scholastics, the fact that the
angelological question par excellence was where to put angels in
a systematic theology is itself an index of the larger problem they
faced in developing coherent systematic theologies as such, a
problem that they were confronting for the first time. Did an
account of creation belong in a systematic theology at all? If one
provided an account of creation, whether in a systematic theology
or not, should one follow the Book of Genesis, which omits
angels, or some alternative cosmological model? Early in the cen-
tury, Anselm of Laon and his school took a decisive stand on these
questions. They chose not to place their creation account within a
systematic theology and they did not follow the Book of Genesis,
substituting a hierarchical cosmogenesis in which angels, as
purely spiritual beings, were created first, already in nine orders of
descending rarefaction, followed by human beings, animals,
plants, and inorganic creatures, While they ignore creation by
emanation and exemplary causes, the Laon masters otherwise
reflect an affinity to Platonism here.” But there was more than one
2. ANSELM OF LAON, Sententie divine pagine 4; Sententie Anselmi 2, ed,
Franz BLIEMETZRIEDER in Anselms von Laon systematische Sentenzen, Beitrige
zur Geschichte der Philosophie des Mittelalters 18:2-3 (Miinster, 1919), p. 12,
13-14, 29; Semences of the School of Laon no. 308, ed. Odon LorTN in
Psychologie et morale aux Xile et Xie siécles (Louvain, 1959), 5: 244; Deus de
cuius principio et fine tacetur, ed. Heinrich WeisWeiLeR in Recherches de théolo
gie ancienne et médiévale 5, 1933, p. 260.82 RECERCHES DE THEOLOGIE ANCIENNE ET MEDIEVALE
version of Platonism abroad in the land at this time. The major
proponents of this philosophy were the members of the school of
Chartres, with their project of reviving Plato’s cosmogenesis in
the Timaeus and with seeing how, or if, it squared with the cre-
ation account in Genesis. The Chartrains, however, were not inter-
ested in systematic theology. Nor were they interested in angels.
The only Chartrain even to mention them, Clarenbald of Arras,
does so in passing and in order to make a point, against other
members of the school who assigned creative roles to emanations.
or sub-divine entities, that God creates everything personally;
angels, although they are spiritual and intelligent beings, play no
role in the creation.*
Another master who gives his fullest position on creation not in
his systematic theology but elsewhere, in a commentary on Gene-
sis, is Peter Abelard. His Hexaemeron, which follows traditional
Genesis exegesis, omits angels; and while he mentions them
briefly in his Theologia christiana, or at least the ranks of angels,
archangels, and dominations, created first and before men and
other corporeal beings, he does so in defense of his larger argu-
ment for the claim that the Platonic anima mundi is a fabula stand-
ing for the Christian Holy Spirit. Only one of Abelard’s disciples,
the author of the Ysagoge in theologiam, mentions angels. He
includes them in his sentence collection, in a scheme of organiza-
tion unique to him. Beginning with man, the fall, the redemption,
ethics, and sacraments, he treats the rest of creation, including
angels and God, at the end.> The author of the Sententiae divini-
3. CLARENBALD OF ARRAS, Tractatus super librum Genesis 9-10, ed. Nikolaus
M. Harine in Life and Works of Clarenbald of Arras, A Twelfih-Century Master
of the School of Laon Toronto, 1965), p. 229-230. Cf. BERNARD SILVESTRIS,
Cosmographia, ed, Peter DRoNkE (Leiden, 1978)
4. A Critical Edition of Peter Abelard’s ‘Expositio in Hexameron’, ed.
Foster RomiG, Ph.D. diss., University of Southern California, 1981. A printed
edition incorporating Romic’s work and adding other MSS. to it is forthcoming
from CCCM. For a description of this work, see Romic’s preface and Eileen
Keaaney. Peter Abelard as a Biblical Commentator: A Study of His Expositio in
Hexaemeron in Petrus Abaelardus (1079-1142): Person, Werk und Wirkung, ed.
Rudolf THomas (Trier, 1980), p. 199-210; PETER ABELARD, Theologia christiana
LIL, ed. Bligius M. Buytaert, CCCM 12 (Turnhout, 1969), p. 118. For the
wider argument in which this point is made, see ibid. 1.68-122, p, 100-122.
5. Ysagoge in theologiam, ed. Artur Michael Lanparak in Ecrits shéologi-
ques de I’école d’Abélard (Louvain, 1934).EARLY SCHOLASTIC ANGELOLOGY 83
tatis, generally regarded as a follower of Gilbert of Poitiers, omits
angels from his sentence collection altogether;® while two other
early Porretans, like the author of the Ysagoge, place angels, and
the rest of creation, in the next-to-last of the fourteen books in
their sentence collections, sandwiched idiosyncratically between
the liturgy of Advent and Lent.”
None of these schematic decisions found favor with other mas-
ters writing between the late 1130s and 1160. A much more popu-
lar choice was to place angels in a creation account located closer
to the beginning of a sentence collection. At the same time, the
early scholastics achieved no consensus, before Peter Lombard, on
when the angels were created. Hugh of St. Victor illustrates this
uncertainty. He tries, unsuccessfully, to combine a hierarchical
account of creation, with exemplary causes and angels created
before the material world, with a hexaemeral account derived
from Genesis that perforce omits angels. Confusing matters still
further, he backpedals to include the deity, proofs of His exis-
tence, and Trinitarian theology in the midst of his creation
account. Hugh ends by seizing on Augustine’s doctrine of creation
simul as a life-preserver saving him from the intellectual ship-
wreck he has produced, and moves thankfully on to the creation of
man$
Robert of Melun is heavily dependent on Hugh's scheme of
organization and compounds its difficulties. He begins his Sen-
tences with the nature of biblical revelation, the interpretation of
the Bible, and the relationship between the data on God it provides.
6. Bemhard Geyer, ed., Die Sententiae divinitatis: Ein Sentenzenbuch der
Gilbertischen Schule, Beitrige zur Geschichte der Philosophie des Mittelalters
7:2-3 (Minster, 1909).
7. Nikolaus M. HARING, ed., Die Sententie Magistri Gisleberti Pictavensis
episcopi I, in Archives d'histoire doctrinale et littéraire du moyen age 45, 1978,
P. 83-180; IDEM, ed., Die Sententie magistri Gisleberti Pictavensis episcopi IL:
Die Version der florentiner Handschrift, in AHDLMA 46, 1979, p. 45-105.
8, HuGH OF St. VicroR, De sacramentis fidei christianae 1.1.2, 1.1.4-11,
15.2-3, 1.5.4-5, 1.5.6, 1.13.30, PL 176, 187C-188B, 189C-195C, 197B-206A,
247A-248C, 249B-C. On these inconsistencies, see Charlotte Gross, Twelfth:
Century Concepts of Time: Three Interpretations of Creation simul, in Journal of
the History of Philosophy 23, 1985, p. 325-334.; A. MIGNON, Les origines de la
scolastique et Hugues de Saint-Victor (Patis, 1895), 1: 321-328; Jakob KUGEN-
sTeIN, Die Gotteslehre des Hugo von St. Viktor (Wirzburg, 1897), p. 37-57.84 RECERCHES DE THEOLOGIE ANCIENNE ET MEDIEVALE
with that supplied by philosophy and the artes. He then discusses
the ages of the world, taking up this topic before the world’s cre-
ation. He then backs up to treat the divine nature and follows it
with an account of creation that moves from unformed matter to
formed matter to man, omitting angels. Robert then returns to the
issue of how the divine nature and the Trinity may be known.
After a lengthy consideration of theological language in that con-
nection, he finally introduces the creation of angels, thus present-
ing it as if it had occurred after the creation of man.’
‘Another sentence collector strongly influenced by Hugh who
emerges with a different, if equally problematic, answer to the
question of when the angels were created is the author of the
Summa sententiarum. While his schema is sui generis, he makes
a positive and important contribution to mid-twelfth-century
angelology of his own, which was taken up by Peter Lombard
and others. The author of the Summa sententiarum leads off with
the theological virtues, the Trinity, and the incarnation, before
treating the creation in Book 2 of his work. There, he rejects the
doctrine of exemplary causation in all its forms and presents a
modified version of creation simul, in which angels and
unformed matter are created by God ex nihilo, first, and at the
same time, and then followed by the creation of other beings in
the hexaemeral order of Genesis.'? While his schema is peculiar
in presenting Christ’s incarnation before the fall of man it was
meant to remedy, the author has indeed found a successful way
of combining a hierarchical with a hexaemeral account of cre-
ation that includes angels coherently. He makes another influen-
tial point in his explanation of how angels differ from God,
although they are pure spiritual beings and immortal. Unlike the
deity, he notes, angels live in time and are mutable, capable of
learning what they did not know already and of experiencing joy
and sorrow. And, while they are sent on divine missions through-
out the world, he points out that they lack the divine attribute of
ubiquity."!
9, ROBERT OF MELUN, Sententie, ed. Raymond-M. MARTIN (Louvain, 1947-
52).
10. Summa sententiarum 2.1, PL 176, 81A-B.
11. Ibid. 1.5, PL 176, S0C-51A.EARLY SCHOLASTIC ANGELOLOGY 85
Other authors, such as Robert Pullen and Roland of Bologna, !?
follow the Summa sententiarum in placing the creation of angels
along with prime matter at the head of a hexaemeral account of
the rest of creation, although they preface creation with a discus-
sion of the divine nature only and reserve Christology for a later
chapter of their sentence collections. But the scholastic who really
put this solution on the map was Peter Lombard. In Peter’s cre-
ation account, following on the heels of his treatment of the Trin-
ity and the divine nature, exemplary causes are likewise pointedly
ignored and God creates everything directly and ex nihilo; the
“heaven” and “earth” mentioned at the beginning of Genesis
stand for the angels and the primordial matter that are created first,
and simul, with all other creatures presented according to the
hexaemeral account. But, more than simply repeating the Summa
sententiarum here, Peter is also concerned with attacking Origen’s
view, as reported by Jerome, Augustine, and John Cassian, that
angels existed before the creation of time and that they, and not
Christ as the logos of creation, can be identified with the uncre-
ated wisdom of God referred to in Ecclesiastes 1:4.? The Lom-
bard thus yokes the question of when the angels were created, on
which he helps a new consensus to emerge, with the anti-Origenist
brief that informs the other major topics in his angelology and that
of his contemporaries.
Much less controversial, in the first half of the twelfth century,
was the theme of the angelic hierarchy. Everyone who mentions
angels, apart from Clarenbald and Abelard, agrees that they are
arranged in nine orders headed by the seraphim, to signify that
charity is the greatest of virtues. All are aware of the fact that the
two leading authorities on this subject, Gregory the Great and
Pseudo-Dionysius, while they agree on the placement of the
12, ROBERT PULLEN, Sententiarum libri octo, PL. 186; ROLAND OF BOLOGNA,
Die Sentenzen Rolands, ed. Ambrosius M. GteTL, (Amsterdam, 1969 [repr. of,
Freiburg, 1891 ed.)
13, PETER LOMBARD, Sententiae in IV libris distinctae 2. d. 1. ¢. 1-3, ¢. 6. 1-
5,4. 8. ¢. 16, d. 12. ¢, 1.2, 3rd rev. ed., ed. Ignatius M. Brapy (Grottaferrata,
1971-81), 1: 334-335, 336-341, 384-385. For more on this point, see Ermene-
gildo Berto.a, I! problema delle creature angeliche in Pier Lombardo, in Pier
Lombardo, 1:2, 1957, p. 33-54; Marcia L. CoLish, Peter Lombard (Leiden,
1994), 1: 347-353,86 RECERCHES DE THEOLOGIE ANCIENNE ET MEDIEVALE,
seraphim, disagree in their organization of the rest of the hierarchy.
The scholastics in this period may cite Gregory or Pseudo-Diony-
sius or both; but they reflect no felt need to make a preclusive
choice between the two hierarchical schemes offered by these two
authorities." That angels are purely spiritual in their makeup is also
a consensus position.'® There was some disagreement on when the
gradations in the angels’ spiritual nature were imposed on them and
in what it consisted. As noted, the members of the school of Laon
hold that the nine ranks of angels were part of the original creation.
Hugh of St. Victor thinks that, in the original creation, the angels,
although equally spiritual, were unequal in their degrees of reason
and will.!° The Lombard draws on both of these positions while
amplifying the point. In the original creation, he holds, the angels
were equal in their rationality, their nature as persons, their spiritu-
ality, their simplicity, and their immortality. But they had differing
degrees of wisdom and will. At the same time, he thinks that the
hierarchical ranking of the nine orders, while it has a metaphysical
substratum in the original creation, was not imposed on them until
the fallen angels had fallen and the good angels had been confirmed
in goodness. While adding his own twist to the theme of the grad:
tion of angels, Peter at the same time confirms the consensus pos
tion that the fallen angels are also ranked, which the author of the
Summa sententiarum is the only contemporary scholastic to reject.
Of far greater interest to the scholastics of this period is the
intellectual and moral life made possible by the angels’ possession.
and use of reason and free will. Their central concern here is to
refute Origen on the possible salvation of Lucifer and the fallen
angels. Agreed as they are on this position, the theologians yet dis-
agree on how best to defend it. In the late eleventh century, one
solution had been proposed by Anselm of Canterbury. In his Cur
Deus homo, Anselm argues that God could not have extended His.
chosen method of redeeming mankind to the angels, since each
14, Hua oF St. Victor, De sac. 1.5.33, PL 176, 262B-D: Sent. mag. Gisle-
berti 113.29, 13.37-47, p. 166, 167-169; Ysagoge in theol. p. 230; ROLAND, Sent
p. 103-104.
15. See, for example, Sentences from the School of Laon no. 305, 5: 243;
ROLAND, Sent. p. 85-86.
16, HuGH oF St. VicToR, De sac. 1.5.9-14, PL 176, 250D-252A.EARLY SCHOLASTIC ANGELOLOGY 87
angel is a genus unto himself, Had Christ assumed the nature of
this or that angel, the only angel who could have been saved
thereby would have been the individual angel whose nature Christ
had assumed. In any event, Anselm notes that, since angels are
immortal by nature, salvation, understood as salvation from death,
would be meaningless in their case.'* This Anselmian argument
was accepted by the monastic theologian Honorius Augusto-
dunensis and by the Abelardian author of the Ysagoge in theolo-
giam."° On the other hand, the Laon masters find Anselm’s argu-
ment unconvincing. Noting that, since God is omnipotent, He
would not have been constrained to save the fallen angels in a
manner analogous to the one He ordains for human salvation, they
argue that, unlike the sin of Adam, the sin of the fallen angels is
irremissible. This is so because, as purely spiritual beings, the
angels suffered no physical temptations and they were not tempted
from without, issues which the Laon masters think are mitigating
factors in man’s case but not in the case of the angels. This Laon
school position is also followed by the Porretans.”°
Related to this point is the issue of whether, in their state a
fallen or confirmed in goodness, the angels retain the faculty of
free will. There is some debate on this question. Robert Pullen,
arguing that the state of non posse peccare applies to God alone,
maintains that the good angels must have some capacity to sin,
even though they have become so habituated to virtue that they do
not actually exercise it.?’ On the other hand, Hugh of St. Victor
and the author of the Summa sententiarum, wishing to stress the
unchanging character of the angels’ states once fallen or con-
firmed, argue that, as a corollary of this point, both sets of angels
must have to undergo a serious limitation on their free will.” The
17, Perer Lomparp, Sent. 2. d. 3. ¢, 1.2-2.2, d. 6. ¢. 1-7, d. 9. ¢. 1-7, 1: 342,
352, 354-358, 370-76; cf. Summa sent. 2.5, PL 176, 85C-87D.
18. ANSELM OF CANTERBURY, Cur Deus homo 2.21, in Opera ommia, ed.
Franciscus Salesius Scumirt (Edinburgh, 1946), 2: 132.
19. Honorius AUGUSTODUNENSIS, Elucidarium 1.38-44, 1.48-49, 1.50-56, ed.
Yves Lefevre (Paris, 1954), p. 367-368, 369-370; Ysagoge in theol. pp. 227-228.
20. ANSELM OF Laon, Sent. div. pag. 4; Sent. Anselmi 2, p. 15-18, 50-54;
Deus de cuius p. 256-257; Sent. mag. Gisleberti I 13.74, p. 105.
21. ROBERT PULLEN, Sent. 2.3.6, PL 186, 719A-726A.
22. HucH oF Sr. Victor, De sac. 1.5.31-32, PL 176, 261A-262B; Summa
sent, 2.3.4, PL 176, 83A-85C.88 RECERCHES DE THEOLOGIE ANCIENNE ET MEDIEVALE
Lombard rejects Anselm’s claim that every angel is a genus unto
himself, He agrees with Robert Pullen that the confirmed angels
lack the absolute non posse peccare of the deity. He also rings
some changes on the Victorines’ position, although he is as eager
as they are to refute Origin. He does so by focusing on the defini-
tion of free will itself and by adding the factor of divine grace to
the equation. In describing angelic free will, he gives the same
definition that he later applies to human free will before the fall. It
is the capacity of the moral agent to will whatever he wills with-
out violence or constraint. Before their fall, he states, all angels
could use this faculty to will good or evil. But, in order to progres
beyond their natural innocence, to develop in virtue (proficere)
and not merely to stay as they are (stare) with their aptitude for
virtue unrealized, the angels needed operating and cooperating
grace, working in tandem with their free choice of the good. Now,
Peter continues, God gave this grace to the good angels and they
chose the good, in which they are confirmed. In that state, they
have no desire for evil. So, they continue to will the good freely,
without violence or constraint. As for the fallen angels, God
removed or subtracted His grace from them, Following Augustine
on this point, the Lombard notes that God’s reasons for doing so
are, ultimately, a mystery. In any event, lacking grace, the only
moral choice they can make is the choice for evil. And, they con-
tinue to will the rejection of God, freely. They continue to will
evil, and evil alone, without violence or constraint, Thus, they too
retain free will. In contrast with Hugh and the author of the
Summa sententiarum, the Lombard holds that the free will of the
angels after their confirmation in goodness and their fall alike is
not reduced but intensified, since both groups continue to will
good or evil, respectively, without conflicting desires. Hence, he
concludes, they continue to merit their rewards and punishments.
‘And, as confirmed or fallen, they continue to grow in virtue or
vice.
In developing this argument, Peter accomplishes several things
at once. First, he provides an explanation for the inability of the
23, PETER LOMBARD, Sent. 2. d. 3. ¢. S-d. 5. ¢. 1-5, d. 7. ¢. ba, 1: 348-
359-361, For the parallel with the blessed and damned human souls in the next
life, see Sent. 4. d. 49-d. 50. ¢. 1-4, 2: $47-557.EARLY SCHOLASTIC ANGELOLOGY 89
good angels to fall as well as for the inability of the fallen to
improve that is theologically much richer than the solutions pro-
posed by Anselm of Canterbury and Anselm of Laon and their fol-
lowers. At the same time, with respect to angelic free will and its
interaction with grace in the attainment of merit-bearing virtue,
and with respect to the capacity of spiritual beings to undergo
change over time, he combines the notion of angelic mutability
found in the Summa sententiarum with a broad treatment of the
psychological, ethical, and intellectual life of angels that has its
parallels in his treatment of human beings, the human Christ, and
the blessed and damned in the life to come. The foregoing analy-
sis also lays the foundation for the answer Peter gives to the ques-
n of whether the angels confirmed in good continue to grow in
knowledge and virtue, or whether they are perfected at their con-
firmation and undergo no further change. He supports the first
position while importing into it a distinction not found in the
Summa sententiarum. Since angels live in time and since they do
not have foreknowledge, he observes, the good angels can and do
grow in knowledge, since they will learn about events that occur
in time when these events come to pass. On the other hand, with
respect to their contemplation of God, the good angels are per-
fected and do not change. Likewise, the love and merit of the good
angels is not enlarged, over time, with respect to its quality. But,
since they live in time, they can grow in love and merit with
respect to the quantity of their virtues, in the unfolding of new
opportunities for their exercise. The Lombard here expands on a
point not dealt with to any noticeable extent by his immediate pre-
decessors, and one which connects his angelology organically
with other areas of his theology.
There are, finally, two other topics pertaining to angels which
some scholastics in our first period take up, although they inspire
far less general interest than those discussed above. Both concern
the interactions of angels with human beings. Are all angels sent
on missions to men, irrespective of their rank in the angelic hier-
archy, or are only some ranks sent? Hugh of St. Victor gives a
thorough review of the positions that have been taken on this issue
24, Ibid. 2. d. U1. c. 2, 1: 381-383.90 RECERCHES DE THEOLOGIE ANCIENNE ET MEDIEVALE
by the leading patristic authorities, without taking a stand on it
himself.?> But the author of the Summa sententiarum is certain that
all ranks are sent, a position which the Lombard confirms while
adding that angels in the highest ranks receive the choicest assign-
ments.” There is a thorough consensus on the point that one such
mission, which has its parallel among the demons, is to guard indi-
vidual human beings. All the theologians who mention this subject
agree, anchoring the point with the authority of Gregory the Great.
Since he thinks that these guarding and tempting missions must be
one-on-one, Hugh of St. Victor asserts that there must be the same
number of angels and demons in existence at any given moment as
there are human beings.” He ignores the metaphysical problem
which the expansion and contraction of the size of the angelic and
demonic hosts, driven by human population statistics, bring in
their train. The Summa sententiarum agrees with the general prin-
ciple that everyone has his personal guardian and tempter and
does not comment on the issue of numbers.’* Peter Lombard is in
accord with the consensus and resolves the dilemma propounded
by Hugh by observing that angels and demons are capable of
guasding and tempting more than one person at the same time.??
Drawing even less interest, in this period, is the question of
angels or demons acting as incwbi and the status of the bodies they
inhabit when interacting with human beings. The author of the
Summa sententiarum bears witness to the fact that earlier theolo-
gians had conducted a lively inquiry into these matters, debating
in particular about the metaphysical status of a child fathered by
an angelic incubus upon a human woman. He himself regards the
topic as frivolous and irrelevant.” The Lombard agrees, to the
point of not mentioning it at all. He does state, however, that
demons can enter the minds and bodies of men in tempting them.
When this happens, he emphasizes, they are present in human
beings in their effects, not substantialiter. As for the status of the
25. HucH oF St. Victor, De sac. 1.5.31-33, PL 176, 261A-262D.
26. Summa sent. 2.6, PL 176, 87C-88C; PETER LOMBARD, Sent. 2. d. 10. ¢. 1+
2, 1: 377-379.
27. HucH oF St. Victor, De sac, 1.5.31-33, PL 176, 261A-262D.
28. Summa sent. 2.6, PL 176, 87C-88C.
29. PETER LOMBARD, Sent. 2. d. LI. c. 1, 1: 379-381.
30. Summa sent. 2.6, PL 176, 87C-88C.EARLY SCHOLASTIC ANGELOLOGY 91
bodies taken on by angels in performing their missions, and what
happens to them when the missions are completed, he concludes
that the information at our disposal does not permit a clear resolu-
tion of these questions, irrespective of the certitude which some
authorities are willing to claim in this area.!
The repressiveness of the Summa sententiarum and the Lom-
bard on these metaphysical matters is an excellent index of the
aspects of angelology that ranked low on the agenda of mid-
twelfth-century scholastics, even though both masters see the
importance of providing a metaphysical answer to the question of
how the angelic nature differs from the divine nature. At the same
time, the keen interest they show in the question of where to posi-
tion angels in a systematic theology and in the angels’ psycho-
logical, intellectual, and moral attributes and destinies is likewise
an authentic index of the dominant place which these topics held
in the angelology of the day. On the matter of when the angels
were created, the popularity of the Lombard’s schema made his
solution a consensus position, whether or not later theologians
chose to include the exemplary causes he rejects. The fullness of
his angelology, in comparison with the angelologies of his imme-
diate predecessors and contemporaries, and the thorough integra-
tion of his doctrine on angels with other leading themes in his
Sentences, made it clear that angelology, by 1160, was there to
stay as a topic that systematic theologians could not afford to
ignore.
But if scholastic theologians after the Lombard found that they
could not ignore angels, the masters of the second half of the
twelfth century found them far less interesting than is true of the
Lombard, his contemporaries, and his immediate predecessors. In
our second sub-period, whether the masters are card-carrying
Lombardians or not and whether they write sentence collections,
abbreviations or commentaries on the Lombard’s Sentences, col-
lections of theological quaestiones, summae, or other types of the-
ological literature, they tend, for the most part, to accept the Lom-
bard’s angelology as a given and ring very few changes on it. Alan
of Lille is the exception who proves this rule.
31. Perer LomBarp, Sent. 2. d. 8. ¢. 1-2, ¢. 4, 1: 365-368, 369-370.92 RECERCHES DE THEOLOGIE ANCIENNE ET MEDIEVALE
Two of the Lombard’s abbreviators in this period are Gandulf
of Bologna and Bandinus, The latter ignores the creation of angels
and questions about their nature, except to say that they are not
corporeal, although he agrees that they can take on bodies in the
conduct of their missions and that there are nine orders of them;
he cites both Gregory and Pseudo-Dionysius as authorities.*? Gan-
dulf is a bit fuller. He retains the Lombardian idea that angels and
primordial matter were created simu/. Having made that point, he
proceeds at once to the angels’ fall or confirmation in goodness,
agreeing with the Lombard’s point that both groups are ranked
and retain free will, But he omits the Lombard’s analysis of the
angelic nature and psychology and the psychogenesis of angelic
moral choices.
Peter’s most influential disciples in the second half of the
twelfth century, who go well beyond his abbreviators as theolo-
gians, have little more to say on angels. But they do manage to
convey their views with somewhat more independence. In what
proved to be the last of the major sentence collections, Peter of
Poitiers, typically regarded as the Lombard’s most faithful fol-
lower, treats only a selected number of points in his angelology
and feels free to disagree with his master.¥ He adheres to the
Lombard’s version of angelic creation simul along with primordial
matter and the notion that, in the original creation, some angels
were more rarefied than others and that they differed in their wis-
dom and will. Agreeing with the substance of the Lombard’s
teaching but using his own vocabulary, he states that, as originally
created, angels were perfect secundum tempus but not secundum
naturam or simpliciter, to provide room for their later moral and
intellectual development and to distinguish them from the deity.
Peter of Poitiers follows the Lombard in both doctrine and lan-
guage in noting that angels needed operating and cooperating
grace in order to proficere and not just to stare in the state of inno-
cence. As for their retention of free will after their fall or confir-
32. BANDINUS, Sententiae 2. d. 8-9, PL 192, 1036D-1039A.
33. GanbuLr oF BoLoGNa, Magistri Gandulphi Bononiensis Sententiarum
libri quatour 2.6-46, ed. Johannes de WALTER (Wien, 1924),
34, Peer oF PorTiers, Sententiae 2.1-6, ed. Philip S. Moore, Marthe
DULONG, and Joseph N. Garvin (Notre Dame, 1961), p. 1-33.EARLY SCHOLASTIC ANGELOLOGY 93
mation in goodness, Peter of Poitiers, here disagreeing with the
Lombard, holds that free will remains in the good angels only, and
not in the fallen ones. At the same time, he argues that both sets of
angels continue to will good or evil, respectively, and hence to
merit their eternal glory or punishment, respectively, a position
which appears to imply the exercise of free will in both groups.
This inconsistency aside, he omits the Lombard’s point about the
subtraction of divine grace from the fallen angels as the reason
why their sin is irremissible. Peter of Poitiers agrees with the con-
sensus view that there are nine orders of angels, and, like theolo-
gians in the two preceding generations, is more interested in the
fact that Gregory and Pseudo-Dionysus concur in placing the
seraphim at the head of the list, and for the same reason, than he
is in taking a stand on the discrepancies between the two authori-
ties elsewhere on this subject. He departs from the Lombard and
harks back to the position of the school of Laon in affirming that
the nine ranks were part of the original creation of angels and not
a hierarchy imposed on them after their confirmation, on the basis
of the metaphysical, intellectual, or psychological gradations
which with they had been created. 5 He agrees that all ranks of
angels are sent on missions and that angels and demons can be
assigned to more than one human being at a time. All in all, Peter
of Poitiers is much less interested in the nature and inner life of
the angels than in the roles that they, and the demons, play in the
moral lives of men, a feature of his angelology that makes it of a
piece with a theology that gives much more space and attention to
ethics in general than is true of the Lombard’s.
Peter Comestor is another important follower of the Lombard in
our second sub-period. He is known to have written a commentary
on the fourth book of the Sentences, dealing with the sacraments
and last things, along with his more famous Historia scholastica
or handbook of biblical history. In addition, he produced theolog-
ical quaestiones, which were confused with those of Odo of
Ourscamp by Odo’s editor* several of which deal with angels.
35. Ibid. 2.5, p. 24.
36. The best and most recent guide to the works of PETER COMESTOR, super-
seding previous accounts, is James H. MoREY, Peter Comestor, Biblical Para-
phrase, and the Medieval Popular Bible, in Speculum 68, 1993, p. 6-35. OF the94 RECERCHES DE THEOLOGIE ANCIENNE ET MEDIEVALE
Comestor is not concerned with the timing of the angels’ creation
or in their nature. He agrees that they were perfected according to
their ranks and that they differ in their attributes. But he does not
comment on whether the nine orders, which he outlines in Grego-
ty’s hierarchy, were instituted before or after the confirmation of
the good angels.*” This aside, Comestor’s only other real interest
in this area of theology is the moral lives of the good angels, on
which subject he sometimes amplifies on the Lombard and some-
times mis-cites him. Comestor agrees with the Lombard’s view
that grace and angelic free will must interact in the development
of merit-bearing virtues in the
good angels, citing the master by name. He transfers the analogy
which the Lombard had developed to explain the relationship
between grace and free will in the moral lives of men to the psy-
chogenesis of virtue in angels. In this analogy, free will is com-
pared with the soil; grace is the rain or dew; virtue as a mental
disposition is the seed; and virtue as a conscious intention or
action grows like the fruit of that seed, as an attribute of the moral
agent in whom it inheres.* This amplification is certainly in the
Lombardian spirit. But elsewhere Comestor asks whether the good.
angels continue to grow in merit after their confirmation. In his
response, he states that the Lombard had left this question open,
which is not the case. He also omits the issue of grace here,
although the other questions he treats indicate his awareness of its
importance in the moral lives of angels in Lombardian theology.
And, in the same question, he states that, as with the blessed in
heaven, the merits of the glorified angels will not increase, claim-
ing that this conclusion meshes with the Lombard’s, a statement
that propounds an inconsistency even as it reflects an erroneous
reading of the Lombard.”
In addition to writing sentence collections and collections of
theological quaestiones, masters in the second half of the twelfth
‘quaestiones ascribed to Ovo that belong to ComesToR, MOREY has identified q.
288-334 in Prrra’s edition as CoMESTOR’S.
37. Oo OF Ourscame, Quaestiones magisiri Odonis Suessionensis q. 313,
ed, Joannes Baptista Prrra, in Analecta novissima spicilegii Solesmensis, altera
continuatio (Paris, 1888), 2: 138-144.
38. Ibid. p. 140,
39. Ibid. q. 322, p. 157-159.EARLY SCHOLASTIC ANGELOLOGY 95
century also produced summae and magisterial Sentence com-
mentaries as vehicles for the author's enunciation of his own
personal position. An excellent example of the latter of these two
genres of theological literature is the Sentence commentary of
Stephen Langton, dating to the turn of the thirteenth century.
While in this work, as in his biblical exegesis, Stephen is heav-
ily influenced by the Lombard, he feels no need to comment on
each chapter of the Sentences. Rather, he displays his own inter-
ests and emphasis, and disagrees freely with the Lombard. On
the creation of angels, he rejects the Lombard’s modified version
of creation simul and substitutes Augustine’s view that all crea-
tures were created simul. Stephen has a particular, and polemi-
cal, reason for making this move, one similar to the rationale
inspiring Augustine himself in his anti-Manichean Genesis com-
mentaries. Against the Cathars, Stephen wants to argue that
darkness did not exist from all eternity, as a negative metaphys-
ical entity, but that it only came into being when light was cre-
ated, as its absence.*” Also, in a major departure from the Lom-
bard and the
theologians of the mid-twelfth century, Stephen drops from his
agenda both the nature of angels and the reasons why the fallen
angels cannot be saved. His lack of interest in the latter of these
two topics is striking. The one other point his angelology
addresses is the angels’ ethical capacities, an interest he shares
with Peter Comestor, Peter of Poitiers, and the Lombard alike. He
agrees with these masters that the angels had a natural aptitude for
virtue before the fallen angels fell but that they could not activate
it without the collaboration of grace with angelic free will, needed
to produce virtues that are meritorious. But, taking a line opposed
to Comestor, Peter of Poitiers, and the Lombard, and to many
other theologians of his century, Stephen claims that this grace
was part of the original creation and not a gift given by God to the
angels after He had brought them into being. He ascribes the posi-
tion that he maintains on this point to the Lombard, although it
40, STEPHEN LANGTON, Der Sentenckommentar des Kardinals Stephan Lang-
ton, In 2 Sent. d. 12. ¢, 2-3, ed. Artur Michael Lanpcrar, Beitrige zur
Geschichte der Philosophie des Mittelalters 37:1 (Miinster, 1952), p. 84-85. On
the date of this work, see the editor's preface, p. xxviii96 RECERCHES DE THEOLOGIE ANCIENNE ET MEDIEVALE
contradicts what the Lombard and his more faithful followers had
taught.4!
Although he is regarded as a non-Lombardian and as an adher-
ant of the teachings of rival masters, Alan of Lille is actually more.
faithful to the Lombard on the moral lives of angels, and more
accurate in reporting his views, than are Stephen Langton, Peter
Comestor, and Peter of Poitiers. At the same time, he is the only
master in the second half of the twelfth century to display interest
in the intellectual life of angels, and moves this topic forward, in
comparison with his contemporaries. In Alan’s Summa, written
fairly soon after the last edition of the Lombard’s Sentences, he
offers an analysis of the moral state of angels that is thoroughly
Lombardian. Alan states that angels, as created, had a plenitude of
natural goods, They were perfect in the sense that thay possessed
everything they needed by nature to proceed to their glorification.
But, he continues, while the angels by nature could stare in their
state of innocence, they could not proficere without the grace
needed for virtues that are meritorious. Before receiving that
grace, the angels possessed natural goods only, the naturalia, but
not yet the gratuita, It was not their natural endowment alone but
its interaction with grace that enabled them to merit their confir-
mation in goodness.*? Alan does not pursue the the theme of the
ongoing moral lives of the good angels after their confirmation.
But, in several works, he does consider the state of angelic knowI-
edge. Alan agrees with the Lombard that, with respect to their
contemplation of God, the good angels have attained a cognitive
state that cannot improve and that does not change, a state he
describes as scientia in order to contrast it with the partial knowl-
edge of God by faith available to human beings in this life. As to
the nature of angelic scientia, drawing on John Scottus Eriugena
and Boethius, Alan describes it as theophanic. A theophany, as he
understands it, is the direct, simple, immediate, rational apperce-
41. Ibid. d. 3. ¢. 1-3, p. 72-73.
42. Philémon GLorieux, ed., La somme ‘Quoniam homines' d’Alain de Lille
2.1140, 2.1.142, in AHDMLA 20, 1953, p. 276-277, 278. The editor gives the
date as 1155-60, p. 116; Marie-Thérése d’ALVERNY, Alain de Lille: Textes
inédits avec une introduction sur sa vie et ses oeuvres (Paris, 1965), p. 64, gives
the date as 1170-80. See also ALAN OF LILLE, De sex alis cherubim 174, PL 210,
270C.EARLY SCHOLASTIC ANGELOLOGY 97
tion of the deity, not mediated by any sense data, mental images,
or concepts, and not involving a ratiocinative process. Contrasting
the angelic theophany with all forms of knowledge available to
human beings, Alan subdivides it into three types, each possessed
by one tercet within the nine angelic orders as outlined by Pscudo-
Dionysius. Epiphany is the theophanic knowledge of God enjoyed
by the seraphim, cherubim, and thrones; the next three orders of
angels enjoy hyperphany; while the lowest three orders enjoy
hypophany.” While it does not consider the ongoing moral lives
of the angels confirmed in goodness, and while it does not contrast
the unchanging theophanic knowledge of God unique to angels
with the expansion of the number of things they know in time,
Alan’s angelology does elaborate considerably on the angelic
epistemology, adding a Neoplatonic coloration to the Lombardian
position. As such, it reflects the appeal of the Lombard’s angelol-
ogy as a point of departure for theologians in the next generation
who were not his disciples.
On the other hand, a more preclusively ethical focus on angels
is found in the Summa theologica of Prepositinus of Cremona,
written toward the end of a teaching career that ended in 1206,
when he became chancellor of the University of Paris. Prepositi-
nus mentions angels only obliquely, to shed light on a different
topic, the ethical aptitudes of human beings before the fall. He
presents three positions on this question as current options.
According to the first, or Lombardian, view, Adam was created
with the naturalia and could have then received the gratuita,
According to the second, Adam was created with both the natu-
ralia and the gratuita. This second view is the one, we recall, that
was put forth with respect to angels by Stephen of Langton.
According to the third view, attributed to Anselm of Canterbury,
Adam received no grace after his fall. Prepositinus thinks that the
43. ALAN OF LILLE, Expositio super symbolum apostolorum et Nicenum;
Expositio prosae de angelis; Hierarchia Alani, ed. d’ ALVERNY, Teates inédits,p.
84 for the definition of angelic scientia; p. 202-209, 226-235 for the three modes
of angelic theophanic knowledge. On the latter, I would like to thank Nancy VAN
DEUSEN for bringing these references to my attention. More on this subject, tak-
ing it from ALAN OF LILLE to RoBERT GROSSETESTE, can be found in her Theo!-
ogy and Music at the Early University: The Case of Robert Grosseteste and
Anonymous IV (Leiden, 1994), ch. 6.98 RECERCHES DE THEOLOGIE ANCIENNE ET MEDIEVALE
first opinion is the likliest. In defending it, he appeals to the Lom-
bard’s angelology. Had the angels been created with grace as well
as with a natural aptitude for virtue, he argues, the fallen angels
would not have fallen. But the reverse is the case. Therefore, he
concludes, as with men, angels needed the gift of grace super-
added to their natural moral aptitudes in order to improve
morally. Omitting here a point central to the Lombard and his
contemporaries, the idea that grace is not irresistible and that it
can be rejected, Prepositinus adverts simply to the angels’ created
aptitudes and to their fall because this topic provides a parallel to
his analysis of the operative conditions of moral choice in prelap-
sarian man. Standing, like Stephen Langton, at the turn of the thir-
teenth century, Prepositinus thus serves as a good index of the nar-
rowness of the interests of most scholastic theologians on
angelology since 1160 and the reduction of the scope of their
inquiry into this field to ethics alone.
Ina way, this fact is surprising, given the increasing number of
Aristotelian works that had become available in Latin by 1200. By
then, in addition to the logica nova, Aristotle's Physica, Meteors
logica, De anima, De generatione et corruptione, and De sensu,
had been fully translated. All but Book 11 of the Metaphysica was
also available in Latin as well as Books 2 and 3 of the Nico-
machean Ethics. A considerable chunk of the Aristotelian corpus
had thus been placed in circulation during the second half of the
twelfth century; and, in some cases, the texts had been available
for decades.** Yet, it is remarkable how little of this substantive
Aristotelian material was put to use by the scholastics in our sec-
ond sub-period, however eagerly they may have embraced the /og-
ica nova with the aim of using it to hone their theological lan-
guage and theological argumentation. Equally noteworthy is the
degree to which the substance of Aristotelian philosophy was
taken up and used positively by the two thinkers we have selected
44, PREPOSITINUS OF CREMONA, Summa theologica 2, as quoted and discussed
by Albert FRIES, Urgerechtigkeit, Fall und Erbsunde nach Prapositin von Cre-
‘mona und Withelm von Auxerre (Freiburg, 1940), p. 9-15.
45, Bemard G. Dos, Aristoteles Latinus, in The Cambridge History of Later
Medieval Philosophy, ed. Norman KRET2MANN et al. (Cambridge, 1982), p. 46-
48, 69-16,EARLY SCHOLASTIC ANGELOLOGY 99
to represent the third sub-period of early scholasticism, whose
works date to the first quarter of the thirteenth century. Our exam-
ples, Alexander of Hales and William of Auxerre, have been cho-
sen because they are mainstream thinkers, representatives of a
generation at the University of Paris typically seen as conserva-
tive, or as less than enthusiastic about the reception of Aristotle.
Accounts in standard reference works describe Alexander as “not
influenced by it [i. e. Aristotelianism]” and portray William as a
“pre-Aristotelian” thinker.*® But, in comparison with their imme-
diate predecessors, both Alexander and William reveal a serious
interest in philosophy and a positive willingness to apply it to their
angelologies. Indeed, it is often the philosophical traditions of
Neoplatonism and Aristotelianism that set the agendas and pro-
vide the lexicons used by these early thirteenth-century theolo-
gians in their treatises on angels.
William of Auxerre’s angelology is found in the second book of
his Summa aurea, composed between 1215 and 1229.7 While it
follows the Lombardian scheme of organization, William's
summa gives the reader the immediate sense that he has stepped
into a different intellectual environment, not only because of the
freedom with which William disagrees with the Lombard but also
because of the amplitude of his discussion of angels, quite striking
in comparison with the lean treatment given to this topic by his
immediate predecessors. William is not particularly interested in
the angels’ metaphysical constitution. What does interest him is
their nature as intelligent beings, moral agents, and ministers to
mankind, While metaphysics is secondary to this concern,
William none the less brings exemplary causes back into play in
his account of the creation, following Augustine by identifying
46, Conrad Harkins, Alexander of Hales, in Dictionary of the Middle Ages,
ed. Joseph R. STRAYER (New York, 1982), 1: 148; Gideon GaL, William of Aux-
erre, in New Catholic Encyclopedia (New York, 1967), 14: 922. As recently as
1993, Gillian R. EVANS, Philosophy and Theology in the Middle Ages (London,
1993), p. 45-46, could treat WILLIAM OF AUXERRE as dismissive of Aristotelian:
ism, On the other hand, Alain de LiBERA, La philosophie médiévale (Paris, 1993),
p. 377-379, 382, sees both WILLIAM and ALEXANDER as being more receptive to
philosophy in general and to Aristotelianism in particular. None of the scholars
cited in this note discusses the angelology of either figure.
47, WILLIAM OF AUXERRE, Summa aurea, ed, Jean RIBAILLER (Paris/Grotta-
ferrrata, 1980-87). Evidence for the date is given by the editor, 1: 7.100 RECERCHES DE THEOLOGIE ANCIENNE ET MEDIEVALE
exemplars with ideas in the mind of God. In his treatment of this
doctrine his principal concern is to refute the Platonic view of the
exemplars as standing above God or as existing independently of
Him, and also the view that God had, perforce, to create the uni-
verse in virtue of having the rationes of all things in His mind.
William also wants to refute the doctrine of the eternity of the
world, and does so by drawing a clear distinction beween the
exemplars of all things in God’s mind, eternally, and the reifica-
tion of the creatures whose forms they become in time when God
wills that these creatures should come into being. While William
agrees that Christ is the supreme /ogos of creation, the supreme
exemplar, he expressly rejects a chain of being or emanationist
model of creation, Still, he begins his account of creation with the
exemplars because a hierarchical treatment of creation, starting
with them and continuing with angels as spiritual beings, human
beings, and then the material world, appeals to him.* We can thus
see in William’s account of creation a selective use of the Platonic
tradition, some of whose features he plainly rejects while others he
finds attractive.
With the Lombard, William treats the angels as the “heaven”
that God created at the beginning of the Genesis account. On the
other hand, dispensing with the creation simul theory in any of
its forms, he presents angels simply as the first beings created
and moves directly to their psychological and moral characteris
tics and their fall or confirmation in goodness. William revie
the debate summarized by Prepositinus on whether the angels
had virtues by means of grace as well as nature in their original
state, and joins him in supporting the Lombardian position that
the gratuita, when added to the naturalia, enabled the angels to
acquire merit-bearing virtues. This teaching, he says, is the com-
mon one; if he is correct in making that observation, a consen-
sus had emerged on the point quite soon after Prepositinu
day.”
48, Ibid. 2. tract. 1. c. 1-3, 2: 12-30. William is here drawing on an argument
against the etemity of the world derived from PSéUDO-DionysiUS, On the Divine
Names, as is noted by Richard C. Dates, Medieval Discussions of the Eternity of
the World (Leiden, 1990), p. 78 n. 68.
49, WILLIAM OF AUXERRE, Stunna aurea 2. tract. 3. ¢. 1, 2: 3:
5,EARLY SCHOLASTIC ANGELOLOGY 101
In describing what the angelic naturalia actually were, William
expands the catalogue of their natural virtues and displays his
philosophical proclivities in so doing. These givens of the angelic
nature, he states, included free will, the ability to love God, and
also self-love. With self-love, he strikes a new note. For William,
self-love is a natural moral aptitude and a natural moral inclina-
tion. It includes the desire to live, the desire to know oneself, and
the desire for self-preservation. In an aside he notes that this type
of love is also natural to human beings and that it is not sinful.
Here, William distinguishes natural self-love, on the one hand,
from self-love that is sinful in that it is proud or disordered, and,
on the other hand, from charity as a theological virtue. In addition
to having self-love as a natural virtue, he holds, the angels also
had a natural love of God, and for His own sake, not merely for
their own. To be sure, he adds, this natural love of God was also
useful to the angels, and supremely so. Thus, while this natural
virtue can also be distinguished from charity, he sees the natural
love of God and charity as quite compatible.” Altogether, while
he accepts the consensus position that grace is needed for merito-
rious virtue, in this analysis William makes a significant contribu-
tion to the doctrine of natural virtue and narrows the gap between
natural and supernatural virtue.
As for the angels’ fall, William agrees with the substance of the
common teaching of the day while adding a few elements of his
‘own, some theological and others philosophical. In speaking of the
pride that led to Lucifer’s fall, he frames the point in Aristotelian
causal language. Free will, he says, was the efficient cause, the vol-
untary consent to temptation that constitutes sin. At the same time,
he brings into his account a Neoplatonic understanding of evil as a
privation of the good, in this case, the privation of good will. Either
way, he situates Lucifer’s fall within the context of a eudaimonis-
tic view of ethics that is compatible with both philosophi
schools. Moral agents, he notes, are motivated by what they judge
to be good, even if their assessment of it may be erroncous.’!
50. Ibid. 2. tract. 2. c. 2-5, 2: 36-46. The definition of self-love is at c. 2, p.
38: “Amor naturalis sui est amor quo aliquis vult naturaliter sibi bonum, scilicet
esse, vivere, intelligere, et talis amor non tendit nisi ad conservationem sui, ad
utilitatem sui.”102 — RECERCHES DE THEOLOGIE ANCIENNE ET MEDIEVALE,
William aligns himself with the Lombardian idea that, in the state
of innocence, the angels could stare on their own but that they
needed grace in order to proficere, and that God granted that grace
to the good angels. But, he departs sharply from both the Lombar-
dian and Augustinian traditions alike by rejecting the theory that
the fallen angels fell because, for some mysterious reason, God
withdrew His grace from them. In William’s view, on the contrary,
God granted the grace of perseverance to all the angels. Those who
fell did so because they rejected God’s grace.*? Here, although
William departs from one aspect of the Lombard’s teaching, he
does so to buttress another feature of that same teaching, the idea
that grace is not irresistible. In William’s eyes, the angels’ fall was
spiritual and local. The fallen angels lost spiritual and intellectual
gifts which they had enjoyed in the creation and they were also
physically ejected from heaven and sent to a fiery hell. Here it must
be noted that, while William agrees with the position that the fallen
angels cannot be redeemed because they sinned in spirit only, hav-
ing no bodies, as well as because they had no external tempter, his
lack of any real discussion of the metaphysical constitution of
angels makes it difficult to see how beings regarded as purely spir-
itual could have a local habitation at all, whether before of after
their fall. William revives an early twelfth-century concern with
refuting Origen on this topic; his strategy, however, is to attack
Origen with Pseudo-Dionysius on angels as a counter-authority.°?
William devotes a great deal of attention to the states of both
sets of angels after their fall or confirmation in goodness, intro-
ducing some new topics in this context and attaching to it themes
sounded already by earlier scholastics but not under this heading.
An excellent case in point is the doctrine of synderesis or con-
science, which the Lonbard had reintroduced into ethics and
which had received extended consideration in the second half of
the twelfth century.** William is the first scholastic to apply this
31. Ibid. 2. tract. 3. ¢. 1, 2: 46-50, 58
52. Ibid. 2. tract. 3. c. 4, 2: 60-61.
53. Ibid. 2. tract. 3. €. 5, ¢. 7, 2:64, 66-67.
54. PETER LOMBARD, Sent. 2. d. 39. c. 3.3, 1: 556; for the discussions about
conscience in the following decades, see Odon Lorri, Les premiers linéaments
du traité de la syndérése au moyen age, in Revue néo-scolastique de philosophie
28, 1926, p. 422-459,EARLY SCHOLASTIC ANGELOLOGY 103
idea to the fallen angels. As with human sinners, he argues, con-
science in angels can be defined as the spark of reason and desire
for the good that is not extinguished by the fall. He holds that,
while it is present in the psychology of fallen angels, conscience
has been reduced to the point where it cannot inspire them to seek
the good and to reject their disobedience to God. Still, he
observes, Lucifer himself suffers the remorse of conscience (con-
scientiam remordentem), a situation that makes his punishment
still worse, since he recognizes that he has cut himself off from.
God forever and that, in some sense, he has made his own hell. If
they are like fallen men in the possession of conscience, the fallen
angels are unlike fallen men, for William, in their lack of the
‘fomes peccati, or inclination to sin that is a consequence of the fall
in mankind.55 The reason William gives for this asymmetry is the
idea that the inclination to sin resides in the body, in human
beings. Lacking bodies, angels cannot have this affliction. But,
this conclusion, while it would appear to reflect the appeal of a
Platonizing anthropology to William, is inconsistent with his loca-
tion of sin in the voluntary choice of the will, a mental faculty, and
his recognition that temptations can be spiritual, as they were in
the case of the fallen angels.
Turning his attention, finally, to the good angels, William
describes their hierarchy in exhaustive detail. It is not sufficient,
for him, merely to specify that seraphim constitute the highest
rank of angels, and why this is the case. Rather, the characteristics
and functions of all the angels in all the ranks are deemed to
require an extremely thorough treatment. And, it is no longer sat-
isfactory to adduce both Gregory and Pseudo-Dionysius as author-
ities of equal weight. William quite pointedly rejects the Grego-
rian hierarchy and regards the Dionysian position as the only
acceptable one, revealing, in so doing, a careful and attentive read-
ing of his Celestial Hierarchy.5 In addressing the ministry of the
good angels to man, he expands on the Lombard, and in a Lom-
bardian spirit. We recall that Peter had argued that demons, in
tempting men, enter their minds and bodies through their effects,
55. WILLIAM OF AUXERRE, Summa aurea 2. tract. 3. ¢. 7. q. 4, 2: 76-77. The
quotation is on p. 77.
56, Ibid. 2. tract. 4. c. 1, 2: 85-103,104 RECERCHES DE THEOLOGIE ANCIENNE ET MEDIEVALE,
but not substantialiter. William extends the same analysis to the
ministry of the guardian angels and sharpens the point. As he sees
it, neither personal angels nor personal demons enter into the
human beings to whom they are assigned. Further, neither angels
nor demons are the causes of human moral actions. William thinks
that this point is especially important to make with respect to the
guardian angels, lest they be seen as taking God’s place in the
conversion of human hearts from sin.’ William adds two other
points here. In working for the salvation of the people they guard,
the guardian angels do not and cannot act in contravention of
God’s eternal decree concerning which people He will save.
And, another new topic that William takes up under this heading
is the question of whether the human Christ had a personal
guardian angel. No, he responds, with respect to Christ’s knowl-
edge, which was greater than any angel's knowledge; but yes,
with respect to the comfort and solace which His angel gave the
human Christ in the midst of His fears and sorrows. Like the
Lombard, William is interested in the continuing condition of the
good angels after their confirmation, But, like Alan of Lille, he
confines himself to their knowledge, omitting their virtue. He
agrees that the angels lack foresight. Adding more authorities than
were brought to bear on this point by the Lombard, William con-
cerns himself with some new issues relative to the angelic episte-
mology that develop this subject farther than Alan of Lille had
taken it. Agreeing with Alan, although without using his theo-
phanic terminology or his trifold subdivision of angelic knowl-
edge, William thinks that angels know what they know by an
instantaneous act of direct intellectual perception, without having
to undergo any process of ratiocination. At the same time, he adds.
the condition that the angels need divine illumination in order to
know in this way.’ This interest in angelic knowledge, which
concludes William’s treatise on angels, accounts for an apparent
57. Ibid. 2. tract. 5. ¢. 1-5, ¢. 8, c. 10, 2: 103-116, 118-119, 122-123.
58. Ibid. 2. tract. 5. c. 8, ¢. 10, 2: 118-119, 122-123.
59. Ibid. 2. tract. 5. c. 1-4, 2: 103-111, For the passage in the LOMBARD in its
original context of man's ethical activity, see PETER LOMBARD, Sent. 2. d. 27. c.
1-2,3, 1: 480-482,
‘60. WILLIAM OF AUXERRE, Summa aurea 2. tract. 3. ¢. 1, tract. 6, 2: 46-50,
124-141.EARLY SCHOLASTIC ANGELOLOGY 105
anomaly in Book 2 of his summa, a discussion of prophesy
inserted between angels and the rest of the creation. His rationale
for this unusual schematic decision is the felt need to contrast
angelic knowledge with the knowledge possessed by prophets.
While prophets, unlike angels, are permitted to see the future, their
knowledge he judges to be otherwise far less extensive than that of
the angels.°!
In sum, William shares with the scholastics of the late twelfth.
century an interest in angels that is primarily ethical, although he
joins Alan of Lille in his concern with the angelic epistemology
and agrees with the substance of his teaching. At the same time,
he reprises some major topics that had been treated by the Lom-
bard and that his more immediate successors had scanted or
ignored, sometimes agreeing with the master of the Sentences and
sometimes not. William draws philosophy into the analysis of the
points he covers in some cases, appealing to Aristotelianism, to
Neoplatonism, and, indirectly, to the Stoicism from which the idea
of synderesis derives. He knows exactly what he agrees and dis-
agrees with in the Platonic tradition. Its position on hierarchy,
human nature, and the privative theory of evil attracts him; but he
dissociates himself pointedly from cosmological doctrines
advanced by the Platonists that would undercut the freedom and
power of the deity in the creation. In treating the moral state of
angels before the fall, he widens appreciably the scope of natural
virtue. His treatment of this topic shows an affinity for Aris-
totelian ethics, as does his use of Aristotelian causal language in
describing the role of angelic free will in the making of moral
choices. When it comes to the angelic hierarchy, he reflects a clear
and preclusive preference for the Dionysian account, as well as for
the idea that the rankings of angels were instituted after the good
angels’ confirmation. William’s most notable innovation as an
angelologist is his attribution of conscience to Lucifer and the
fallen angels. His most serious weakness is his lack of an overt
consideration of the metaphysical status of angels, although he
assumes, without discussing the point, that they are spiritual
beings. This notion makes highly problematic his localization of
61. Ibid. 2. tract. 7, 2: 142-166106 RECERCHES DE THEOLOGIE ANCIENNE ET MEDIEVALE
them before and after the fall as well as his exempting of fallen
angels from the inclination to sin as a consequence of their fall
What we have seen as the most salient weakness of William of
Auxerre’s angelology emerges as the most noteworthy strength of
the angelology of Alexander of Hales. His focus on the metaphys-
ical status of angels is what gives his teaching its special charac-
ter. In addition, that teaching makes it clear that, by the time
Alexander had written his Glossa on the Sentences of Peter Lom-
bard (1220-25), Aristotelian metaphysics has settled in for the
duration and was informing the thought of scholastic theologians
not hitherto regarded as hospitable to this new philosophy. It is
true that Alexander lacks an interest in some of the cosmological
questions that had agitated scholastics in the first half of the
twelfth century and that continued to be of interest to William of
Auxerre, such as when the angels were created and the issue of
creation simul, or, for that matter, exemplary causes and the cre-
ation of primordial matter, all of which he omits. He begins his
creation account with the angels; following them he presents the
standard hexaemeral version from the Book of Genesis. Having
ushered angels onto the scene, what he emphasizes is their meta-
physical constitution. This is the single most important subject
that Alexander’s angelology seeks to address. Given their nature
as simple and as purely spiritual beings, he asks, how can angels
be undertood as created substances? How can such beings be dis-
tinguished from the deity? And how can they have location? In
answering these questions, Alexander shows his awareness of the
fact that the term substantia is defined differently by different
schools of philosophy. At the same time, the definition that clearly
sets the terms of the debate, for him, is the Aristotelian one, He
acknowledges the fact that angels, understood as simple and spiri-
tual beings, simply do not square with the Aristotelian notion of
creatures as substances made up of matter and form. He sees, and
poses, this problem quite clearly. Given the philosophy of Aristo-
tle, which he refuses to fudge, angels are a metaphysical anomaly:
from an Aristotelian perspective, simplicity and pure spirituality
62. ALEXANDER OF HALES, Glossa in quatuor libros Sententiarum Petri Lom-
bardi, ed. Collegii S. Bonaventurae (Quaracchi, 1951-57). The date is given by
the editors in 1:65*, 110*-114*.EARLY SCHOLASTIC ANGELOLOGY 107
would appear to be attributable to the deity alone. Alexander's
solution to this dilemma — and it is a solution that forecasts the
essence-existence distinction applied to angels later in the century
by Thomas Aquinas — is to invoke the distinction made by
Boethius between the quo est, or essential character of a being,
and its quod est, or current manifestation of its being, which can
differ in actuality from its quo est. This possibility extends to
angels, and to all other creatures, while it does not apply to God,
Whose quo est and quod est are identical. We may recall that,
taking a cue from the Summa sententiarum, the Lombard had also
offered a metaphysical explanation of the differences between
angels and the deity, based on the distinction between angelic
mutabilty and divine immutability. Alexander’s argument is
equally metaphysical. But it an argument addressed specifically to
the Aristotelian doctrine of the structure of being, within whose
parameters he finds it necessary to make his case.
Another index of Alexander’s wish to come to grips with the
metaphysical questions surrounding angels is his reversion to a
topic that had been in abeyance in the angelologies of scholastics
since the time of Peter Lombard, and which Alexander sees as nei-
ther irrelevant nor frivolous, the status of the bodies used by
angels on their missions; whether, as embodied, they can beget
offspring upon human women; and, if so, what the metaphysical
status of those children would be. Alexander concedes that he
cannot answer the first of these questions. He admits the possibil-
ity of angelic incubi and thinks that their offspring are hybrid in
nature, doubting that they are really human beings.“ This discus-
sion harks back to the larger metaphysical question of how spiri-
tual beings can be given location, or bodily habitations, even on an
ad hoc basis. What is striking about Alexander's handling of these
questions is his refusal to fall back on the Bible or religious
authority in order to answer them. In his view, they have to be
63. Ibid. In 2 Sent, d. 3. c. 7, 2: 27. CF. THOMAS AQuinas, In 2 Sent. d. 3. q
1.4.1 solutio, in Opera omnia (New York, 1948 (repr. of Parma, 1866 ed.]). 6:
411-412. THoMAS yokes this point, in d. 3. q. 1. a. 2 solutio and d. 11. q. 2. a. 1
solutio, 6: 429, 482, with the doctrine of angelic mutability taught by the author
of the Summa sent, and the LOMBARD.
64, ALEXANDER OF HALES, In 2 Sent, d. 8. c. 6, 2: 75-76.108 — RECERCHES DE THEOLOGIE ANCIENNE ET MEDIEVALE,
addressed philosophically; and it is better to leave them open than
to compromise that principle.
The other topics that Alexander takes up in his treatise on
angels show him as less original than he turns out to be in his
treatment of the angelic nature. With William of Auxerre, he finds
it important to discuss the angelic hierarchy in painstaking detail,
to comment on the functions of angels in all its ranks, and to rely
exclusively on Pseudo-Dionysius as his source. His similarities
with William here suggest that this amplitude on the angelic hier-
archy is an authentic note of early thirteenth-century angelology
On the angels as moral agents, Alexander is far briefer than
William, and less innovative. He agrees with the Lombardian dis-
tinction between the naturalia and the gratuita and the angels’
need for the latter in order to develop virtue, merit, and glory. He
is interested in the angels’ fall, their exercise of free will both
before and after it, and the permanence of the condemnation of the
fallen angels, although the anti-Origenist brief has dropped com-
pletely from his agenda on that last point.” Alexander agrees with
the Lombard’s analysis of the good angels’ quantitative growth in
knowledge after their confirmation, although he omits their
growth in virtue; he adds nothing fresh to that topic.
What is most remarkable about Alexander's angelology, on the
whole, is the contribution he makes to framing the metaphysical
issues and problems that angels present for him in terms of Aris-
totelianism, and the solution he provides to their anomalous status
as creatures although they are not composite beings made up of
matter and form. He remains true to his philosophical colors and
does not try to bend Aristotelianism to make it fit a type of being
which that school did not envision and for which it did not provide
an explanation. Even in the case of the embodiment of angels, and
the problems it brings in its train, which he admits he cannot
resolve conclusively, what is noteworthy is the fact that Alexander
prefers to acknowledge defeat in the effort to find a philosophi-
cally satisfactory answer rather than to resort to theological mys-
65. Ibid. d. 9, d, 10. ¢, 6, 2: 83-97, 120.
66. Ibid. d. 3. c. 19, 2: 35.
67. Ibid. d. 5. c. 2, d. 7. c. 6-10, 2: 42, 60-62.
68. Ibid. d. U1. ¢. 8, 2: 113.EARLY SCHOLASTIC ANGELOLOGY 109
tery or miracle. If soluble at all, these questions, for Alexander,
have to be settled in the light of the Aristotelian doctrine of being.
This finding shows Alexander of Hales to have been much
more open to Aristotelianism in the field of metaphysics than he is
typically credited with being, just as our consideration of William
of Auxerre has shown him to be knowledgeable and deliberate as
he picks and chooses from among available philosophical options,
Aristotelian and Neoplatonic alike, in developing the moral and
epistemological approach that he takes to angels, We have like-
wise seen how the schematic concerns of the systematic theolo-
gians in the first half of the twelfth century play a critical role in
making the place of angels in the creation account the major issue
they feel a need to address, just as their interest in angels as intel-
ligent and moral beings is controlled by their desire to attack Ori-
genism. As for the theologians of the second half of the twelfth
century, whose angelologies have been ignored even more than
those of their immediate predecessors and successors, they show,
even in their abbreviated consideration of this subject, and even in
their occasional misreadings of, departures from, or expansions on
the angelology of Peter Lombard, how swiftly his treatment of this
topic became a standard one, influencing masters whether they
were disciples of his or not. Their angelologies are thus part of the
larger history of the emergence of Lombardian theology as main-
stream Paris theology during their period.
While confined to angels and to the figures and works here sur-
veyed, this study thus points to the need for a fuller investigation of
the writings of the scholastic theologians who wrote between the
Lombard’s day and the generation following William of Auxerre
and Alexander of Hales, as well as for an appreciation of the shift-
ing generational concerns that informed them, no less than their
particular solutions to the problems they addressed. It is our hope
that this brief and limited investigation of angelology, as a litmus
paper test of the interests of the early scholastics, will encourage
other scholars to map what still remain some of the terrae incogni-
tae in our knowledge of the first century of scholasticism.
Oberlin College Marcia L. CoLisH