0% found this document useful (0 votes)
112 views2 pages

GSD1x 1 Kant 1 1 Aesthetic Perception Rc1-En

The speaker discusses the architectural imagination and its role in shaping how we perceive and understand architecture. The architectural imagination allows us to abstract common characteristics between structures and form templates to compare them. It bridges the gap between perception and understanding by enabling us to visualize and materialize concepts. The speaker demonstrates this by having the listener compare two images of buildings without any context, and through the comparison the listener's architectural imagination abstracts their shared characteristics, like being enclosed volumes defined by modulated columned wrappers that relate to the ground and landscape. This shows the architectural imagination at work in forming aesthetic judgments and templates that seem to preexist our perceptions.

Uploaded by

Natnael Bahru
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as TXT, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
112 views2 pages

GSD1x 1 Kant 1 1 Aesthetic Perception Rc1-En

The speaker discusses the architectural imagination and its role in shaping how we perceive and understand architecture. The architectural imagination allows us to abstract common characteristics between structures and form templates to compare them. It bridges the gap between perception and understanding by enabling us to visualize and materialize concepts. The speaker demonstrates this by having the listener compare two images of buildings without any context, and through the comparison the listener's architectural imagination abstracts their shared characteristics, like being enclosed volumes defined by modulated columned wrappers that relate to the ground and landscape. This shows the architectural imagination at work in forming aesthetic judgments and templates that seem to preexist our perceptions.

Uploaded by

Natnael Bahru
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as TXT, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 2

[MUSIC PLAYING]

K. MICHAEL HAYS: I'm in Gund Hall, which is the home of the Graduate
School of Design.
And I'm in the studio space, which is where the most intense activity takes
place of design, of analysis and research, of imagination.
We'll speak about the architectural imagination.
And I'm going to suggest that some concept like the imagination
is necessary if we want to treat architecture as a mode of knowledge.
The classical philosophers said, the soul
never thinks without phantasm, which is to say that thought needs a material
image, something to carry the thought.
So we begin to think of the imagination as bridging the gap between perception
and understanding.
What's implied is that there is actually a space in the mind
where the work of picturing takes place.
The imagination is different from other mental processes
like perceiving or remembering insofar as to perceive something requires
that something has to be there.
And that's not required of the imagination.
And even to remember something-- the event or the object or the person--
it had to have already been there in order to remember.
But the imagination creates its image.
The image isn't there until the imagination produces it.
The imagination is also different from a concept
because the imagination requires the materialization of thought.
For example, I can conceptualize freedom.
I can even explain to you what freedom is as a concept.
But it's very difficult to show you freedom.
In order to show you freedom, I would have to construct a picture.
I would have to construct a scene.
Then I could help you imagine freedom in that materialization, in that scene,
in that picturing.
So we should think of the imagination as the capacity
for producing images, the mental capacity to picture things.
And what we want to show is that there is a specific kind of imagination,
which is the architectural imagination.
Look at these two images.
Let's say you know nothing about them.
You don't know what their function is.
You don't know who their patron was.
You don't know where they are.
But you can already start to compare them nevertheless.
One is made of stone.
The other one is made of white stuff and glass, probably wood or steel.
Look at how they meet the ground.
One is nestled into the ground.
It almost seems to be emerging from the earth.
Indeed, some scholars would say that it even compares itself to the landscape
and to the mountains around it.
It almost wants to become like a mountain.
Now, the other one is also very conscious of the landscape,
but it's lifted off the earth.
It doesn't emerge from the earth, but it kind of perches on the earth.
But both of them are conscious of the ground.
Already, the architectural imagination is starting to emerge.
And then we could also say they have something else in common.
They both have a kind of wrapper, which encloses a single volume.
But the wrapper is very special.
It's a modulated wrapper.
It's made of columns.
Even though one has stone columns, one has steel columns,
even though the columns have different spacings,
the space in between the columns is important.
The proportion of space in between the columns and the rhythm of the columns
is important.
And then look at how the columns meet the horizontal beam,
or what we call the entablature.
In one case, there's a very articulated picture
of the joinery, the way the vertical column meets the entablature.
And there are several pieces in between that
make that transition from horizontal to vertical articulate.
Now, the other one doesn't have all those pieces.
But it almost seems like there's still great thought about the pieces.
But it's a kind of negation of all the articulation.
And yet, in the very negation, the intensity of that joint is still made.
So what do we have?
They're both empty, rectangular volumes defined by a wrapper.
And the wrapper is articulated by columns
and space that have a geometry, a kind of geometrical, proportional system.
They both pay a lot of attention of how they meet the ground.
And they both pay a lot of attention about how they're in a landscape.
So what has happened is that we have constructed.
And what has started to emerge is a very particular kind of imagination
that is purely architectural.
It's independent of the materials.
It's independent of the function.
It's independent of who paid for it.
And we have adapted a set of assumptions about one building
to a set of perceptions about another building.
We've worked across those two buildings.
Now, what's implied here is that template of things, in some sense,
had to preexist our understanding of those buildings.
That set of architectural characteristics
that they share in common had to, in some sense, already be there when
we start to perceive those buildings.
This is nothing less than the architectural imagination at work.
And what we have arrived at is a fundamental instance
of aesthetic judgment.
In the comparison, that set of assumptions emerged.
And it is as if it preexisted in order that you could
make the comparison in the first place.
So what's happening is that, let's say, a very old building
is shaping our perception of a very new building,
but also that that more modern building is shaping
our perception of the old building.
And it seems as if that template of items and assumptions
that we made about the wrapper, about the ground, about the landscape--
it seems as if those assumptions preexisted our perception.

You might also like