Janaway, C. Images of Excellence
Janaway, C. Images of Excellence
Janaway, C. Images of Excellence
EXCELLENCE .
Plato's Critique of the Arts
OXFORD
UNIVERSITY PRESS
Great Clarendon Street, Oxford OX2 6DP
Oxford University Press is a department of She University of Oxford.
It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship,
and education by publishing worldwide in
Oxford New York
Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi
Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi
New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto
With offices in
Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece
Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan South Korea Poland Portugal
Singapore Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam .
ISBN 978-0-19-824007-5
Of all philosophers he is the most poetical. Yet if he will
defile the fountain out of which his flowing streams have
proceeded, let us boldly examine with what reasons he did
it,
SIR PHJLIP SIDNEY
PLATO is the greatest writer ever to theorize about the arts, yet—to
over-simplify again—everyone thinks he was wrong. My aim is to
offer evidence pertinent to the first of these statements, and to argue
that 'whether Plato was wrong' about the arts is a question as intricate
and profound as any in philosophy.'
More than ten years ago, as a newly appointed lecturer, I was simul-
taneously developing courses in Greek Philosophy and in Aesthetics,
Encouraged by the example of my predecessor, Ruby Meager, I de-
cided that Aesthetics need not begin with eighteenth-century authors,
and tried to include Plato and Aristotle, I was struck by the power and
lucidity of Plato's writings on poetry, inspiration, and artistic represen-
tation, and wished for a philosophically informed guide to them, some-
thing which I now hope to have written. I did not set out to write
principally for specialist scholars of Greek philosophy, though the end-
product has the ambition of interesting them as well. The more I have
worked to clarify my own interpretation, the more I have been drawn
into the vast field of scholarship on this topic. References in the foot-
notes give the reader the opportunity to retrace some of my paths, but
I do not claim to offer anything like a comprehensive survey of the
field. My governing aim remains to make clear Plato's philosophical
position and what is interesting or important about it,
People occasionally describe aesthetics as the 'Cinderella' of philo-
sophy, perhaps feeling that it doesn't make it to the ball with its sister-
subjects such as logic or ethics, or even that it ought not to (in a
whisper: it's not much of a subject). It is a shame if people think that,
Art, greatly more pervasive in history than science (for example), is one
of the most characteristic things human beings do. Fine forms and
sounds, depictions, and invented stories occupy most of us to some
extent, and for some lives they provide the very backbone. But how
important are they really? Aesthetics is not much of a subject if it takes
for granted that we all know that the arts are valuable,, and why. But
if we assume that neither point is obvious, addressing these questions
becomes a philosophical challenge of the deepest complexity and the
widest import.
It is surprising that Plato should be able to toach us how central the
philosophy of art is. For he stubbornly refuses to set the arts apart as
viii Preface
having a value of their own, and always asks how they help us to be
better people, what elements in our psychological make-up they engage
and promote, how they make a community better to live in, or how they
contribute to the search for truth; and he bids us wrench ourselves away
from art which we love, if it fails to satisfy these stringent tests. But it
is precisely this refusal to privilege or bracket off the arts which chal-
lenges us to say what importance they have. For Plato, the enquiry into
the nature and value of the arts is simply philosophy, and in this I think
he was right.
Parts of Chapters 1, 2, and 6 have appeared in earlier versions in the
following places:
'Plato's Analogy between Painter and Poet*, British Journal of Aesthetics, 31
(1991), 1-12,
'Arts and Crafts in Plato and Collingwood', Journal of Aesthetics and Art
Criticism, 50 (1992), 45-54,
'Craft and Fineness in Plato's Ion', Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 10
(1992), 1-23.
I am grateful to audiences in Sydney, Melbourne, and Canberra,
where some early material towards Chapters 5 and 6 was presented. Let
me finally thank all those who have shown their interest by listening,
reading, and offering support, and especially the following for giving
me their views on later versions: Anthony Price, Stephen Halliwell,
Roger Scruton, Adam Mills, Malcolm Budd, and. Sebastian Gardner.
C.J.
London
September 1994
Contents
Preface vii
Introduction 1
1. Rhapsody 14
5. Mimesis 106
Bibliography 204
THE arts are seen to play a positive role in the lives of many people.
Across cultures, times, places, and class-divisions, people sing, dance,
decorate, enact, represent, narrate, and express, in conventionalized ways,
to audiences who enjoy and participate in these activities, and often
care about them deeply. It seems natural, if not highly informative, to
call such practices 'artistic'. Many of them may also be religious, com-
mercial, therapeutic, political, or educational in their motivation—but
there is usually a fairly clear distinction between pursuing such ends
umethat the arts,
artistically, and doing so in other ways. We tend to a toume
however in the end they may be defined, are in general a good thing.
Some artistic productions are better than others, some are good for one
reason, others for another—but artistic productions as a whole are some-
thing it is better to have than not to have. More inflatedly, we think that
the ability to engage in them is valuable' because it is deeply entrenched
in, or essential to, our being human. Such thoughts are often extremely
vague. So what can philosophy do? Socrates tells us that 'the uaexamined
life is not worth living for a human being* (Apol. 38a5—6). Many of us
live with the arts with few qualms-—philosophy tempts us to step back
out of that security and ask what account can be given, in a general
way, of the nature and value of the arts.
The first attempt at such an examination in western philosophy is that
of its great ancestral figure, Plato. Although Plato's thinking about the
arts of his culture cannot really be described as a systematic theory, he
has consistent preoccupations from Ms earliest to his latest writings,
which reach a peak in the best-known work of his middle period, the
Republic. We find a body of arguments addressing central questions
about the arts, and engaging with themes that are centrally Platonic. If
Plato initiates western philosophy's ethics and theory of knowledge,
then—as part of the same project—he initiates its examination of the
arts in an equally powerful way. Following Socrates' example, he asks
naive questions: Is poetry good for us? Why do we enjoy tragedies?
What does Homer really know about, and what does he teach us about?
The combination of his blunt, unflattering answers and the brilliance of
2 Introduction
the literary medium in which he conveys them gives Plato's critique of
the arts its unique flavour,
Today's writers on the philosophy of art often discuss Plato's views,
or allude to them while in pursuit of their own ends. Such mentions are
not always unfavourable or dismissive;1 nevertheless, Plato has been
dubbed a philistine, Ms arguments have been pronounced bad, Ms crit-
ical attitude to art one-sided and prejudiced, I believe that this is too
harsh a picture. Plato's arguments are by no means flawless, but they
are not stupid. The claim of philosophy's pre-eminence over the arts,
though perhaps too rigid, is there for good reasons. Most of all, as 1
hope to show, Plato was far from being a philistine—he did not lack
appreciation of the arts, nor of their claims to importance. In Ms roost
extreme moment he wished to eliminate the chief forms of poetry from
the city-state and from the republic of the soul, but not for philistine
reasons; rather because, as his examination convinced him, they were
incompatible with a life devoted to truth and the good, and hence, in
his view, incompatible with what it was to be a human being in the
noblest and healthiest of ways. This was an argued position whose
premisses were central to his whole pMlosophy. If we consider that
philosophy worth studying and think it worthwhile to have a view
about the value of poetry, music, and the like, we cannot lightly bypass
Plato's critique of the arts.
Arthur Danto has recently suggested that Plato set the agenda for the
whole history of that philosophical subject which was to become known
as 'aesthetics*. That Plato openly devalued art in comparison with its
rival, pMlosophy, Danto believes is to his credit. At least the nature of
the enterprise is honestly acknowledged, whereas Plato's successors
have played the same game in more underhand fashion: Danto discerns
a 'somewhat shabby history of the philosophy of art as a massive
political effort either to emasculate or to supersede art*, and thinks that
"from the perspective of art aesthetics is a danger, since from the per-
spective of pMlosophy art is a danger and aesthetics the agency for
dealing with it'.2 In that case, the pMlosophy of art has always been
'footnotes to Plato'. An equally broad-brush picture—perhaps equally
plausible—might show us a long line of thinkers sensitive to the position
1
IB recent philosophical aesthetics Plato is taken seriously and maintains a substantial
presence in e.g. Motbersill, and Danto (1981) and (1986). Schaper, and Halliwell (1991)
argue clearly for his importance to contemporary aesthetics.
2
Danto (1986), 16, 13. This piece has influenced me more than I suspected h would
when I first tried to sum it up (Janaway (1989), 198),
Introduction 3
the arts hold in our lives, and developing glowing philosophical ac-
counts in order to atone for the blasphemy of their ancestor. (Perhaps
both pictures are compatible. It is after all Hegel's philosophical eleva-
tion of art which, for Danto, serves as a way of neutralizing it as an
independent force, by presenting it as a kind of philosophy in imperfect
form.)
If the first western philosophy of the arts turns out to have this kind
of enduring foundational role, then an elucidation of its arguments will
have even greater import. The prime task, however, is to understand
Plato's thought and the extent to which it holds credence. I shall seek
to show how Plato's account of the nature, production, and experience
of the arts (as distinct from the question of value) is often on the right
lines: sometimes it is true, or the beginnings of something true. At other
times it is probably false, but the beginnings of something arguable or
worth entertaining. Either way, Plato provokes us into a more thorough
re-examination (such as he himself envisaged3) of the questions we
need to consider about the nature of the arts, if we are to assign them
a positive value. To find that he occupies such a position in the dialectic
of the philosophy of art will be good enough vindication of Plato against
his less favourable critics, and against those who ignore him.
If this book regards the value of the arts, and especially poetry and
drama, as open to question, it is because prior to an engagement with
Plato we cannot afford to assume that we know what that value is, or,
therefore, that they do have a value. Is art per se, and without extensive
regulation, compatible with a rational and ethical life? We hope so.
Was Plato then wrong about the nature of the arts, or only about the
best way to live? Or was he wrong about both? Does art convey truth
and enable knowledge? Does it harmonize essentially with the ration-
ally chosen good? Or can it be guaranteed to do neither? Are these
perhaps the wrong questions to ask about it? Should we be looking to
a unique kind of pleasure with its own value, and leave truth and
morality aside until that is accounted for? Can 'truth' and 'morality*
even be ranked as some kind of construct on a par with what artists pro-
duce? These are the questions I shall regard as open at the start.
J
Rep, 607c4-el: "If poetic mimesis designed for pleasure has any argument to bring
forward io prove that it must have a place to a well-governed city, [we] should be glad
to welcome i t . . . We should also give its champions who are not poets the opportunity to
speak on its behalf in prose to the effect that it not only gives pleasure but is useful to
cities and to human life. We shall Bstett to them in a friendly spirit* (slightly adapted
from Grebe's translation with help from HalliwelTs), This is neither a philistine nor a
totalitarian voice.
4 Introduction
In any philosophical examination of the arts we must ask sooner or
later bow poetry, drama, or representational painting achieve what they
do. Is some special understanding or other state of mind required for
the production of these things? And what kind of entity does an artist
really produce—something in the same class as a carpenter's table, or
(as many have thought) something quite different? How is it that drama
or painting acquires a content, presents an appearance that we recog-
nize as something from the real world? How do these arts engage our
minds—thoughts, emotions, appetites—as we take.them in? Which parts
of the psyche do they appeal to, and nourish? Plato initiates all these
debates, which are still with us, unresolved in one degree- or another,
Not until we establish one or two answers here will, we be able to'
explain art's relation to the world of real things or to the human rnind,
and not until these relations are understood will we have the basis for
a proper answer to the question of value raised above.
When it comes to art and the community Plato's stance is notoriously
uncompromising. He wants political control over the arts, from nursery
tales onwards. He advocates explicit censorship and, for the most dis-
tinguished and impressive poetry, prohibition and deportation. All such
measures are to be undertaken for the general good of the state—but so,
we should remember, is every measure envisaged in the ideal polis
Plata constructs. With this end in view, he advocates, for example, that
deformed newborns should be abandoned to die because they will be of
no use, and that the state should control human reproduction to ensure
the breeding of the right kind of 'stock' (or 'herd'). In this context,
anyone who is particularly enraged by Plato's willingness to censor
Homer selectively for use in schools, or even by Ms ban on perform-
ances of tragedy, may have things a little out of proportion. It is not,
at any rate, some peculiar blind spot about the arts that prompts Plato's
harshness. So it is a worthwhile exercise, not to deny or to excuse the
abhorrent political measures, but to push them a little into the back-
ground, to see whether there is any sense in what Plato says about the
nature of the arts as such,
Plato insists on raising questions about the educational, political, and
moral value of art, and about what outside itself it enables us to know
or to do better. Such questioning can seem misguided if one is prone
to a blanket-response of 'art for art's sake*. Plato prompts us to recog-
nize an often disguised prejudice which bestows on the arts a self-
contained, self-guaranteeing status. He reveals in us an adherence to
aestheticism, the view that some form of pure pleasure or beauty which
Introduction 5
can be isolated from other states and values is the dominant or sole
scale of evaluation for the arts, Aestheticism and 'art for sot's sake*
form an easy way of thinking which partly explains the lack of atten-
tion paid to Plato's views. We are the inheritors of a rather vague
orthodoxy, built to an extent on diverse materials laid down in the
eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, much questioned more recently,
which nevertheless persists in people's minds and practices. What we
may find it hard to forgive in Plato is the apparent arrogance with
which he ignores our orthodoxy. However, if we avoid such an ana-
chronistic attitude and suspend our prejudices, we can allow Plato's case
to be heard. Art may have a self-contained value, but we should not get
away with this as a lazy, unargued, or even unstated assumption.
A point of terminology: is it 'art' we are talking about, or 'the arts'?
Plato discusses poetry (his main interest), drama, story-telling, dance,
painting, and music on various instruments and in various contexts. In
other words, he discusses the arts, or some of what we call the arts
today, and it is these discussions that define my topic. We should hesi-
tate a moment before placing any of Plato's writings in the modem
genre 'philosophy of art'.4 He certainly has no single word that trans-
lates as 'art'. But on the other hand, he makes explicit links between
poetry and painting, especially when elucidating the notion of mim&sis,
the making of appearances or representations. Further, he brackets music'
and poetry together under the wider. Greek conception of mousike. Of
great importance too is the fact that poetry for Plato is usually publicly
performed and, as tragedy and comedy, includes dramatic characteriza-
tion and the music and dance of the chorus. We should remind our-
selves that near to our time the model for the Gesamtkunstwerk, the
total or complete work of art, has been found in Greek drama. Such
works were fiction (or something dose to it), they employed repres-
entation both of character and of scene, they used music, human
movement, lyric poetry, and dialogue, and spoke directly to a whole
community, moving them, to intense emotion, and, they supposed, in-
forming them about themselves, their common past, and their destinies.
This was art, if anything was, whatever Plato and Ms contemporaries
called it. The same can be said of the Iliad and the. Odyssey, which
were also publicly performed in Plato's day and revered for their
as poetry.
4
HalliweB (1991) suggests that we should not hesitate too much; 'The often repeated
claim that the Oreeks had no conception of art "in our sense" is unjustifiably drastic, not
least because of the thinness of the modem concept of "fine att(s)" itself* (325 n. 8).
6 Introduction
Plato's continuing relevance to the philosophy of art lies here. What
he lacks is, as it were, the concept of art with a capital 'A*, the concept
which prejudges questions of the value of artistic activities. Lacking
this attitude to the arts, he raises the question of value with a vigour that
proves hard for many modern readers to stand. Faced directly with
what for us remain paradigmatic works of art, comprehending them,
and indeed admiring them in some ways, he was prepared to reject
them. It is because the rejection strikes deep at what we cherish that we
are so uneasy with Plato, but that is precisely why he is important. If
his case were to hold in the face of Homer and the great tragedians,
there is nothing else we could show Plato—bringing him forward in
time, educating him in the history of all the arts put together-—that
would weigh one iota.
Is there any single point to poetry, fiction, and drama which is also
the point of music, painting, and dance? Should we pin our hopes on
Art with a capital *A*? Some may think the common factor in all
activities is 'aesthetic value*: perhaps if we could explain what that
means, we would have our "answer to Plato'. Aesthetic value is usually
conceived as a value which may obtain independently of all other
values. Take a poem which we regard as a good poem. While it is
legitimate to ask whether the poem is cognitively accurate, ethically
commendable, or useful towards some external end, to ask only these
questions is to miss the further, independent possibility of its being a
good poem in an aesthetic way. And a particular poem might easily be
a good moral judgement, a good description of a state of affairs, and
a good means of inculcating attitudes in the young, without being a
good poem in this further way which we incline to think is in some way
privileged. The inclination is to say that to be good as a poem it must
(whatever else is the case) be good aesthetically,
The second-basic feature of aesthetic value is its relation to certain
ways of experiencing things. A poem or building will not be said to
have positive aesthetic value unless it has a propensity to bring about
some kind of feeling in those who encounter it. This feeling, which
aesthetic theory has found especially elusive, may be pleasure, satisfac-
tion, elevation, or devotion, but is at any rate a feeing which is itself
of positive value to the subject. We respond positively to things that
have aesthetic value, and our doing so is intimately connected with
experiential encounter. Aesthetic value is discerned by looking, listen-
ing, or reading, and opening ourselves to feelings about the objects, of
our own, experience. This sketchiest of outlines is already enough to
Introduction 7
confront Plato with. For he seems to find no place for aesthetic value
even thus outlined—is that not his chief weakness?
It is tree that anyone expecting a theory of aesthetic valoe or aes-
thetic experience must look to more recent thinkers, for Plato has none
to give. And perhaps one reason for this is that he does not regard
aesthetic value as sufficient to justify the arts or our involvement with
them. However, there are two different views which this summary state-
ment might embody. One is the view of the crude, destructive Plato
whose over-insistence in pressing questions of function and morality
and truth blinds him to the whole glorious realm of the aesthetic. The
more sophisticated Plato, however, is the one who has inhabited this
realm, knows how sweet, wondrous, and divine the arts can be, knows
the argument that pleasure should be the criterion of value, and knows
that the human psyche will always be drawn to fine words, sounds, and
pictures. This second picture is the right one. Only once we acknow-
ledge the aesthetically sensitive side of Plato, the poet, speechmaker,
and musician in him, can we understand the voice he adopts to resist
the aesthetic spell. His resistance is to a part of himself, as he makes
clear in the Republic when he declares his arguments a 'charm' to ward
off the fine works of poetty which his education has taught him to
approach as one approaches a loved one.
Why did Plato need such a defensive spell? M the Platonic dialogues
we meet Socrates, who despite variations in style, mood, and apparent
doctrine, is the steady paradigm of philosophy in its search for ttuth and
the good. But let us consider who else we encounter. There is the
reciter and poetry-critic, Ion, who claims that Homer is omniscient and
that Ms submersion in the peat poet's works makes him an expert on
every subject. There is the teacher of rhetoric Gorgias, who cannot
untangle fine talk from genuine expertise and insight, the sophist
Protagoras, who extols the traditional, method of educating the young
by setting the works of the poets before them, and Ms proud and learned
colleague Hippias, who cannot understand the distinction between beauty
and this or that beautiful thing. There are Agathon and Aristophanes,
fine poets in tragic and comic vein, who delight their audiences but may
not speak the truth and cannot follow Socrates' arguments very well.
Then Phaedrus, whose life is given up to the love of beautiful speeches,
even if they are designed to praise people who cynically manipulate
their sexual partners. We hear too of virtuoso musicians whose only
expertise is in breath-taking displays wMch gratify all and sundry, lovers
of sights and sounds who never miss any production staged at the
8 Introduction
festivals, devotees of Homer who argue that he must know everything
to be able to write so inely, and clever, versatile people whose life is
governed by the pleasures of dramatic artifice and empathizing with the
violent emotions of fictional characters,
Again and again Plato confronts Ms dogged philosopher with the
cultured class of his day. The philosopher overcomes them in argu-
ment, but they remain largely unruffled. Plato is showing us that unless
we hold the arts off at some distance, we become disabled—powerless
to distinguish the pleasing from the good, plausibility from truth, or
cleverness from genuine expertise and wisdom. Unless we question the
poetic, rhetorical, pleasure-loving culture in radical terms, it remains
impervious to the very conceptual distinctions it needs in order to raise
questions of value about itself. Unless philosophy is founded as a mode
of enquiry that resists the arts, they will engulf everything. So I shall
argue that Plato understands the basic premisses of one kind of 'aes-
thetic* defence of She arts. He is aware that some people assign the
t arts
autonomous value on the basis of the pleasure they provide to those
who experience them, and that some who attribute great moral and
educational significance to the arts have not properly disentangled such
achievements from that of giving pleasure. Plato's counter-campaign is
not gratuitous, but is intimately linked with his concern to establish
philosophy as an independent method of enquiry.3
My interpretation of Plato differs from a number of others. There are
those who have argued that really, deep down, Plato is not opposed to
the arts—he is opposed to pseudo-art, to misuse of art, to bad art, to bad
as opposed to good mimesis, or whatever, but really means as to see
that art could (at least) be a good tiling. I think that this way of inter-
preting Plato, sometimes born of wishful thinking and anachronism,
is largely wrong. Plato is sensitive to the arts, and often respectful
towards them; he is willing to grant some art-forms instrumental value
in society, and to regard harmony, form, and proportion as profoundly
educative of the human psyche. But there is no Platomc theory which
proclaims "good art* per se, as the modem world thinks of it, to be
intrinsically important and good. Another camp consists of those who
have thought Plato's views so absurd, or just so badly argued, that they
do not even constitute a case against the arts that is worthy of the name.
I offer to displace this view by presenting a set of tolerable philosoph-
ical arguments that serves at least as an initial case.
5
Cf. HaUiweH (1991) again; "If ... Plato lacked anything narrowly (or currently)
describable as an aesthetic theory, this was not because he failed to see the need for one,
but because he held reasons for actually denying such a need* (328).
Introduction 9
Plato's fullest and most damning discussion of the arts comes in the
Republic, to which Chapters 4-6 of this study are devoted. But there
is some business to attend to before we reach the Republic, First (Chap-
ter 1) an examination of the witty and puzzling early dialogue, Jon,
which asks how poetry relates to knowledge. Poets themselves are
praised—perhaps with irony—as 'divinely inspired', but in the same
breath Plato makes a negative claim which he never relinquishes. It is
that fine poetry requires neither poet, nor performer, nor audience, to
possess or acquire any knowledge. Plato's greatest ridicule is directed
at people who make extravagant claims to knowledge because they do
not realize that this is true.
It is of course unclear what kind of knowledge we are looking for.
What kind of knowledge might we want to attribute to a poet or a
performing artist? To answer this we must confront the ubiquitous
concept of recline—craft, expertise, expert knowledge, or, in a mislead-
ing'sense, art. We can still speak of the politician's art, or the wrestler's
or the carpenter's art. But clearly we do not mean thereby to embrace
these activities among 'the arts', which, I take it, include music, litera-
ture, drama, painting, sculpture, dance ... (The tinge of vagueness is
harmless: when we turn to the 'arts page' of a newspaper, or discuss the
funding of the arts, we are sure enough what we are talking about.) In
speaking of the art of the politician, wrestler, or carpenter, we mine
a more archaic layer of meaning, more closely akin to the techne of
Plato's Greek. In the Ion, Plato makes the point that poetry does not
succeed by the same kind of rational processes as these ordinary "arts*
or "crafts'; nor does familiarity with poetry teach us any genuine exper-
tise. It is in this sense that it neither proceeds from nor engenders
knowledge.
In Chapter 2, looking especially at the Gorgias (a dialogue usually
placed at the end of Plato's early period and regarded as transitional to
the period of the Republic), I examine Plato's charge that, arts such as
music and drama aim solely at producing pleasure- or gratification, and
(because there are no generalizable principles of pleasure) can give no
rational account of their mode of success. Once again the concept of
techne is used, this time as the ideal of a rational understanding con-
trolled by knowledge of the good. In Plato's early ethical thinking
activities which do not measure up to the ideal of techne cannot be
a route to knowledge of good and evil. How could a thing without a
rational account ever be knowledge?
We are bound to wonder whether beauty is a relevant issue. Is not
beauty what the arts primarily, and distinctively, have to offer? In
10 Introduction
Chapter 3 I consider Plato's view of beauty. In Ms Hippias Major, for
instance, some of the examples of beautiful things are works of art, but
many are not. The Greek word kalos which we translate as 'beautiful*
often means something which is fine or admirable, and is much wider
in its connotations than our 'beautiful* tends to be. People, actions,
political constitutions, and humble artefacts such as a soup-ladle, cart
without any strain be described, and thereby praised, as kalos. If we
think that works of art are pie-eminent in possessing an aesthetic prop-
erty we call 'beauty', kalos is the wrong word for fliis—and again Plato
has no ready alternative. He sometimes calls poetry hedus—sweet, pleas-
ant, or pleasure-giving—but that could apply just as well to a wine or
a summer breeze, and so gives no aid to the arts in their search for a
value of their own,
And yet, although Plato has no word for 'aesthetic', he recognizes
that there is aesthetic fineness or beauty. As he puts it, some things are
fine because, through our sight and hearing, they give us a pleasure
without any particular benefit. He acknowledges that people place value
on the arts because they are fine things in which we take great pleasure.
But he is not swayed by this. Even with an explicit concept of the
aesthetic it would not be easy to convince Plato that the arts roust have
anything particularly valuable about them. Not all aesthetic things are
art-products; and besides, the analysis of the aesthetic may not reveal,
it to have any peculiar value that overrides Plato's other concerns. He
is alive to the charms of beauty, but will not rate them highly compared
with the values of discovering truth and being an excellent human
being. Furthermore, in Ms 'middle period' philosophy Plato has an
account of beauty which reduces any mere beautiful thing to only sec-
ondary importance. 'Beauty itself', a beauty absolute, undimmed, and
unchanging, becomes for him the ultimate value and the ultimate object
of love, as we see in. the famous speech of Socrates in the Symposium,
with which I conclude my Chapter 3. Here we confront the theory of
Forms, This absolute Beauty is a Form, shared in imperfectly by many
perceptible things, but itself imperceptible and accessible only to pure
thought. It is for Plato a supreme object of knowledge and a standard
of all genuine value, akin to the Form of the Good which is the philo-
sopher's highest goal in the Republic. Yet there is little reason to think,
this 'beauty itself has much to do with the arts as such.
In Books 2 and 3 of the Republic Plato discusses the role of poetty
and music in the education of the young citizens of his ideal city-state.
All aspects of content and form, he argues, should be rigorously censored
Introduction 11
to control their effects on the characters of the young during their
formation. As I hope to show in Chapter 4, Plato has interesting argu-
ments for his view, and starts from premisses that are sensitive to the
importance of the arts. An example is the discussion of the nature and
effects of dramatic characterization (mimesis) on its participants: mimesis
alters people's characters because they tend to become assimilated to
what they habitually enact. Pursuit of dramatic enactment as an end in
itself distorts the personality, making a person 'double' or 'multiple'.
Plato insists throughout that the arts be subservient to moral aims. It is
not immediately obvious whether he is wrong to do this. We should not
be blinded by the levels of political control which he thinks legitimate
in furtherance of his aims. Looking more carefully, we find that the arts
are accorded a strong positive role in early education, that of moulding
the human soul, making it well-proportioned and harmonious, and hence
receptive to right ways of thinking and acting later on.
Chapter 5 is devoted to an analysis of the concept of mimesis, which
emerges in Republic Book 10 as a wider conception of the way the arts
present an appearance of reality. I shall argue that here mimesis is best
understood as what we today call 'representation', and that Plato has,
in outline, a unitary account of how representation is achieved in the
visual, arts and in dramatic and epic poetry. Mimetic artists make no
real thing, only an appearance of a thing of some kind. There is no need
to believe that Plato limits the arts to a crude or mechanical copying or
to the making of literal illusions. He has much subtler concerns, still
linked closely with Ms discussions of ethics and knowledge. This is
revealed in Chapter 6, where I consider the arguments Plato presents in
Book 10 against mimetic poetry. He is highly critical of poetry and
drama, on the grounds that they engage an unstable emotional part of
us and subvert reason, while yet seeming to proceed from, and to trans-
mit, knowledge, He is especially concerned that poets are regarded
as possessing and conveying knowledge in the ethical sphere, when in
fact they have only an ability to produce pleasurable and convincing
'images of excellence*. These arguments, both epistemologicat and
psychological, form Plato's strongest critique of the arts. They are the
arguments which must act as the charm to ward off mimetic poetry,
whose banishment from Socrates' model city founded in words sym-
bolizes its exclusion from the individual psyche.
Plato's thought about the arts and related matters did not cease with
the end of the Republic. In later works he developed bis thinking on
inspiration and madness, pleasure, image-making, techne, and the place
12 Introduction
of the arts in the social order. In Chapter 7 I look at passages which
may seem to evidence a change in Plato's outlook, chief among them
the passages on poetic inspiration in the Phaedrus. But although we
sometimes fiad Plato less vehemently antagonistic to the arts than he
was in the Republic, there is no reason—or so I shall argue—to at-
tribute to him any fundamental reversal of his position. The continuity
of the later with the earlier Plato is shown in the discussions of techne
and mimesis in the Sophist, Statesman, and Philebus* and the well-
considered view of the role of the arts which he constructs in the long
late dialogue, the Laws, Many themes recur from the Republic, but in
the Laws Plato no longer yearns for an ideal community. In the real
world the arts will always be there, and Plato tells us in detail how they
should be organized to contribute to a well-ordered and moral life,
Arguing that pleasure should not be the criterion of evaluation in the
arts, he nevertheless organizes the life of Ms citizens so that they will
learn through play—music, dance, and poetry—how to feel pleasures
correctly. He keeps the arts under strict regulation lest the horrors of
experimentation break out, and he still will not tolerate tragic drama.
Allowing that Plato has made a case, what is its place within the
philosophy of art? In the final chapter, I consider the challenge of
providing a 'defence of art'. Is it possible, by stating what we know
about the arts in the late twentieth century, to lay the Platonic critique
to rest? Though the issue is vast, 1 consider a number of approaches.
One line of thinking says that a proper account of aesthetic judgement
will give us a defence of the arts. Another holds that the mimetic arts
in particular have a direct input into our learning to be better human
beings. Plato need not be left with the last word—yet our thoughts are
liable to be more confused here than Plato's. It is not clear whether the
concepts of art and the aesthetic can. be relied upon to answer Plato's
more radical questions. Is art a serious endeavour? Is its value aesthetic
value? How does aesthetic value relate to other values? Do we not, on
the one hand, sometimes expect to enjoy artworks -'for their own sake*,
locating them in an area where questions about ethical value and literal
truth may be allowed to go fuzzy—or rather, where we may choose
either to invoke such considerations or to ignore them? For Plato that
is no truly serious endeavour: if truth and goodness matter, they matter
absolutely, and if they do not matter absolutely in the arts, then the arts
reduce to harmless play or amusement. On the other hand, do we not
also find ourselves taking art with enormous seriousness as if it em-
braced every conceivable value and improved us in every way Plato
Introduction 13
could demand? One part of the problem is that modern views of art are
so diverse: Plato poses his questions with a greater suigle-mindedness
than we can muster in response. One part of the answer—perhaps the
least tolerable part to Plato—is that art's values are in principle plural
and elusive, and even to be. cherished because they are so.
1
Rhapsody
1 2
See Shelley, 233-48. Ibid, 135.
3
See. Schaper, 35-8, 120-34, for a wider discussion of Romanticism in relation to
this aspect of Plato,
Rhapsody 15
4
Your art [techni } makes it right and proper for you to dress up and look as
grand as you can, And how enviable also to have to immerse yourself in a great
many good poets, especially Homer, the best and most inspired of them, and
to have to learn his thought thoroughly aad not just his lines! For if one didn't
understand what the poet says, one would never become a good rhapsode,
because a rhapsode has to be an interpreter of the poet's thought to the audi-
ence, and that's impossible to do properly if OIK does not understand what he
is saying, (Ion 530b6-c5.)
14
A succinct gloss is provided by Sauwfcrs (1987), 55 n.: 'Corybants were mythical
quasi-divine attendants on Cybele, a Phrygian goddess of nature and fertility; like them,
her human worshippers engaged in frenzied dancing.'
15
Saunders again (ibid.): 'Plato treats the ecstasy and dancing of Corybantie and
Bacchic ritual as essentially similar, Bacchus (Dionysus) was the god of raw natural
vitality.'
20 Rhapsody
rivers—exactly what the souls of the- lyric poets do, as they say themselves.
You see, I understand the poets Inform us that they bring, their lyric poetry to
us from certain gardens and glades of the Muses, by gathering it from honey-
springs, like bees, and flying through the ak like they do. And they are right.
A poet, you see, is a Eght thing, and winged and holy, and cannot compose
before he gets inspiration and loses control of his senses and his reason has
deserted him. No man, so long as he keeps that, can prophesy or compose.
(533e3-S34b7.)
16
Apparently not a genuine fact, though. Tigerstedt (1969,28} gives a salutary reminder;
'Everybody knew, for instance, that Pindar had composed both dithyrambs, encomia and
dance-songs. Yet, it suited Plato to disregard this.*
17
Kant, §49, 175-6. The central thought that crystallizes in this Ion passage is, inci-
dentally, one Kant agrees with: 'No Homer or Wieland can show how bis ideas, so rich
at once in fancy and in thought, enter and assemble themselves in his braia, for the good
reason that he does not himself know, and so cannot leach others* (ibid. §47, 170: almost
an allusion to the lanl),
18
Shelley, 114. " Ibid. 124.
Rhapsody 21
(and act just in flights such as that quoted) is something we must
'acknowledge straight away.
Let us return to the argument. If this account of inspiration should
prove to have some element of troth in it, how does it relate to what
has gone before? How is Ion's ability to judge Homer without exercis-
ing a craft explained by Homer's composing his splendid poetry in a
state of irrational possession? The answer is provided by spelling oat
the image of magnetic attraction with which Socrates* long speech
begins. As the poet is an interpreter of the divine message, so the
performer is in turn an interpreter of the poet for the audience (cf.
535a4-7). The performer's relation to the poet is the same as the poet's
to his divine source. There is a single origin of magnetic power external
to all the metal rings in the chain, which causes each to attract the next.
And, just so, the single divine source of inspiration attracts the per-
former and the audience in turn to the poet's work. Because the poet
is inspired, his work inspires its performer, and the performer's work
inspires us.
It must then be shown that performer and audience are similarly
affected by their attraction to the Mase through the poet. We switch
attention from Ion's ability to discourse about his favourite poet, to Ms
activities. as a public performer. White performing one of the famous
Homeric scenes involving Achilles and Hector, or Odysseus confront-
ing the suitors, what is Ms state of mind? "When you give a good
performance of epic and stun your audience . . , are you, at that mo-
ment, in control of your senses? Or are you taken out of yourself, and
does your soul, inspired as it is, imagine itself present at the events you
describe?*20 Socrates* question suggests a state in' which the performer
is 'out of his senses* or "out of himself*, being so wrapped up in the
fictional course of events, and imagining them so vividly, that he no
longer thinks of his actual situation as a person on a stage performing
a fictional narrative, and so on. Ion picks up a related feature of this
state; 'When I say something piteous, my eyes fill with tears. When it's
something frightening or terrible, my hair stands on end with fear, and
my heart thumps* (535c5—8). He experiences something like genuine
emotions, with appropriate bodily manifestations, but directed towards
events within the fictional scene. Plato senses that there is something
odd about this, and the present passage is perhaps the very first in
20
Ion 535b2--c2, Saunders has "when you give a performance of epic*, but the Greek
is hotan eu eipeis epe, so I have amended to " . . . a good performance ,,.' which reflects
'eu'.
22 Rhapsody
which the problem of 'fearing fictions' gets an airing, at least en
passant.21 If these emotions are anything like genuine, then must not
the person who feels them be in a particular sort of cognitive state
directed towards the fictional events—perhaps something approaching
but falling short of a belief which is literally true? Conversely, if there
is nothing approaching belief here, then how can there can be genuine
emotion? Plato highlights two peculiarities of Ion's state of mind in
performance which contribute to the puzzlement:
SOCRATES. Well then, Ion, take a man dressed up at a feast or festival in
elaborate clothing and golden crowns. If he has lost none of these things, but
nevertheless breaks out in tears, or if he gets into a panic in spite of standing
among more than twenty thousand friends, when no one is denuding him or
doing him any harm, are we to say he's in his senses at that moment?
ION. No, by Zeas, not at all, Socrates, if the truth be told,
SOCRATES. And do you realize that you people have exactly these effects on
most of your spectators?
ION. Yes, Fin very well aware of it. At each performance, I look down on them
from up there on the platform as they weep and look at me with dire emotion
in their eyes, in amazement at my story. Yon see, I have to pay a lot of
attention to them—since if I make them cry I shall laugh all the way to the
bank, whereas if I provoke their laughter, it's I who'll do the crying, for loss
of my money. (535dl-e6.)
The dramatic performer must be disjointed from his ordinary beliefs
if he is to react with such emotional intensity to the unreal action he
relates—he must be at least to this extent 'out of his mind*. Yet at the
same time he must observe the audience and monitor their reaction,
The joke at the end has its serious point. Only if his performance is a
good one will he be paid: he needs to be cool-headed enough to know
that his performance is a good one. (The curious split in the performer's
state of mind is reflected in some remarks by a present-day actor, who
writes mat "unless it's your own lust, longing, or craving, the audience
will only be intellectually aroused: the thing will have been referred to,
21
Gorgias had already noted fear and pity as characteristic effects of tragedy (Enco-
mium of Helen, f 9, in Sprmgue (ed.), 52—and see the discussion of Gorgias in Ch. 2
below), Aristotle remarks that in a tragedy 'the plot ought to be so constructed that, even
without the aid of the eye, someone hearing the story told will shudder with fear and feel
pity at the events in it* (Poetics 1453b3—6). But is genuine emotion here compatible with
understanding the context as fictional? Plato comes closer than Gorgias or Aristotle to
regarding this as a problem, A well-known recent discussion of the issue (to which I
allude) is by Walton. For a comparison of passages on pity and fear in Plato and Gorgias,
see Flasfaar, 68-72.
Rhapsody 23
but not experienced*, and. yet at the same time; *No matter how intense
or painful the emotions of a part, the more you enter into them in a
good performance, the less you are affected by them. , , . The emotion
passes through you.'22) It has been suggested that Ion's conscious
attention to the public's reaction is incompatible with 'a real state of
possession',23 He cannot be literally in a trance-like'Bacchic transport,
and his implicit willingness to accept that he is is ironic. But Ms not
being folly in rational control of what he is doing in performance, and
Ms being genuinely moved to emotions disjointed from the reality he
believes to obtain, need not conflict with Ms calculating attitude to-
wards the audience. Plato merely grazes the surface of these problems,
and his view concerning the • mental state of the audience is even less
developed. They simply 'weep' and have 'dire emotion in their eyes'—
no hint of the special problem of emotional distancing that attends
dramatic representation. Still, it is probably part of the truth that the
performer and audience may be 'out of their senses' in being forgetful
of their real-life situation and feeling temporary emotions out of tone
with it
So in the central section of the Ion Plato offers a single explanation
for the ability of poets to write good poetry, of performers to perform
it well, and of an audience to receive it in a way that they value. A good
performance is one in which an audience becomes emotionally en-
gaged, to the exclusion of their more self-possessed ordinary beliefs.
The ability to produce a good performance requires the ability to be-
come emotionally involved in the act of presenting the scene, so as to
bring about the audience's emotional response, and again to the exclu-
sion of some of one's more self-possessed beliefs. The basis of a good
performance is a good poem to interpret, one that attracts the performer
into the right emotional involvement. And a good poem is one written
by someone possessed from outside by a force which they cannot under-
stand, but which enables them to animate the emotions of performer
and audience alike.
K this is how things stand, we can expect poets themselves to
run into problems when posed certain kinds of question—something
n
Callow, 167, 200. An anecdote reveals how actors learn to observe their own genu-
inely emotioaa! behaviour in a detached way. The actor Michefl MacLiammout heard, in
real life, that B friend was dead: 'He burst into tears and ran downstairs to the reception
desk. OB the way down, he passed a mirror and caught sight of himself in it "Oh,H he
thought to himself, "that's what one looks like when the dearest person to one in the
whole world has just died" * (ibid. 174).
B
Tigerstedt (1969), 21.
24 Rhapsody
confirmed elsewhere by Plato. In the Apology of Socrates poets are
among those Socrates says he has examined by cross-questioning and
found to claim knowledge which they do not have. "I decided*, Socrates
says, 'that it was not wisdom that enabled them to write their poetry,
but a kind of instinct or inspiration, such as you find in seers and
prophets who deliver all thek many fine messages without knowing
anything of what they say'.24 A further remark intimates why this dis-
covery should be so important: 'I also observed that the very fact that
they were poets made them think that they had a perfect understanding
of all other subjects, of which they were totally ignorant' (Apol, 22c4-
6). While Ion's extravagant professions to knowledge are—as we shall
see—ridiculous, Plato is also concerned that poets themselves claim
wide-ranging knowledge which they do not have. But why do they
have no-knowledge?
I turned to the poets, dramatic, lyric,25 and all the rest... I used to pick up what
I thought were some of their most perfect works and ask them closely what they
were saying ... It is hardly an exaggeration to say that any of the bystanders
could have spoken better about the poetry they had made,26
24
Apol, 22b8—c3. The word rendered 'instinct' is ptatsis, 'nature'—compare the idea
of a 'natural gift*.
25
Literally, 'the poets [makers] of tragedies, of dithyrambs, and, the rest'. Dithyrambs
are discussed briefly in Ch. 2 below.
26
Apol. 22a8-b8. Emphases mine, marking divergences from Tredennick's less literal
translation,
77
Woodruff (1982), 144, Cf, Ferrari's view: 'a poem is not meant to be a set of
opinions ...; it is meant for performanc** (1989, 103).
Rhapsody 25
means or thinks, which would neatly explain the phenomena Plato
remarks upon.
Here we may recall Socrates' opening remarks: the rhapsode must
interpret not only the poet's words, but his thought (dianoia); one can-
not be a rhapsode properly if one does not understand what the poet is
saying. Ion presumably expounds Homer's pronouncements on many
topics In a highly convincing manner, not just repeating the verse, but
offering helpful elucidations. However, what worries Plato is that while
poetry's words convey thoughts, the process by which these thoughts
come to lodge in the mind of the audience is suspect. Homer, to start
with, was far from being an authority on the truth of the thoughts in his
poetry. He did not arrive at Ms words by rational means, and is no
infallible authority even on which thoughts they convey. Then the in-
spired expositor se to to work, and may discern a great many thoughts
conveyed by the poem, but another enthusiast may disagree—no one
has over-riding authority or responsibility for truth anywhere in the
chain. It can happen that a thought is picked up which announces some-
thing true and important, as Plato says elsewhere.28 But this is only
"hitting on* the truth by an unreliable method, and is not sufficient for
anyone to claim knowledge,
The chief negative point of the Ion is that Ion's ability to speak finely
about Homer arises 'not from techne or knowledge'. Instead it is 'by
divine dispensation (theia moira)' that our rhapsode is enabled to speak
so finely of Homer. That he discerns value in Homer and has the ability
to convey Ms apergus to others stems from Ms being caught up, as a
performer, in the power of a chain of inspiration. One argument was
given earlier for the dialogue's negative claim; following the glimpse
of Ion as performer of Homer, we revert (536d4) to considering him as
the critic or 'eulogist' of Homer, and after one final reinforcing argu-
ment, Socrates offers Ion the choice of being considered the possessor
of a genuine techne—but "unfair* for not revealing it under question-
ing—or 'divine' because his ability stems from a state of possession,
'It's a much finer thing to be thought divine*, says Ion (542bl—2),
though in accepting ignorance and lack of a techne along with 'divine*
status, he receives at best a double-edged compliment. It is in this final
18
Cf. in the late dialogue Laws; Homer wrote some marvellous lines about the found-
ing of Troy 'under some sort of inspiration from God .., And how. true to life they are!
This is because poets as a class are divinely gifted and are inspired when they sing so
that with the help of Graces and Muses they frequently hit on how things really happen*
(Laws 682a2-5).
26 Rhapsody
section that it is hardest to sympathize with Plato's direction of pro-
ceedings; Socrates appears to ask grossly irrelevant questions, to which
Ion responds with sheer stupidity, I shall suggest that the argument
nevertheless establishes something which is true, even if its point is
obscure until more philosophical work is done.
Socrates has 'spoken well' of the divine power that produces good
poetry and rhapsodic performance, but Ion is still sure that he is not
'out of his senses' when he eloquently praises Homer. To convince
him, Socrates fastens attention on the question of subject-matter. Ion's
subject-matter is what Homer says about various things. But which
subject-matter in Homer is it that gives Ion the opportunity to 'speak
well'? 'Every single one of them*, is his claim—there is nothing in
what Homer covers that Ion 'does not know about' (536el-7). What
are we to make of this? In a sense the claim is harmless. As a frequent
reciter of extracts from the poems, Ion is familiar with the entire
Homeric corpus and well aware of its dramatic successes, whatever is
taking place within the narrative. Accordingly, we find that when Soc-
rates mentions a random topic, chariot-racing, Ion replies with Nestor's
speech before the chariot-race in Iliad Book 23. Whatever Homer speaks
about, Ion could find a passage and discourse eloquently on it.
Socrates is concerned with Homer's portrayal of chariot-racing,
medicine, fishing, prophecy, generalship—i.e. the exercise of some techne
by a fictional character, whom the poet either describes as exercising
expertise, or makes speak in a manner betokening it. But Ms key ques-
tion is this: Does speaking well about a poet's depiction of a character
with some techne require possession of that techne by the speaker? The
question is ambiguous. Ion 'speaks well' in the sense that he is eloquent
and convincing in his praise of Homer as a poet Socrates, on the other
hand, allows 'speaking well* to encompass only saying whether a craft
is depicted correctly or not (e.g. "Are we to assert that it is more the
business of a isberman's techne, or that of a rhapsode, to assess what
[Homer] says [about fishing], and whether he says it well or not?'
(538d4-5)). Obviously one does this best if one possesses the craft
oneself. Once things are set up this way, each real-life exponent of a
craft has certain portions of Homer's work on which they are especially
competent to pronounce, and so it makes sense for Socrates to demand:
'Pick oat for me the sort of thing which concerns the rhapsode and the
rhapsode's techne, and which Ae rhapsode properly examines and judges
better than the rest of us.* Ion dare not say 'Nothing*. But on the reason-
able assumption that each craft must have its own circumscribed subject-
matter, he cannot claim to know everything in Homer.
Rhapsody 27
He must make a positive, but limited claim to knowledge; and his
next suggestion is by no means foolish, A rhapsode in particular would
know:
What may suitably be said by a man . . , and the sort of thing suitably said by
a woman; the sort suitable for a slave to say, and the sort suitable for a freeman;
and the sort of fting suitable 'm the mouth of a ruler, and the sort suitable in
that of a subject. (540b3-5.)
Socrates insists, however, that it is only when such persons are exercis-
ing a specialized role that the question of what is appropriate for them
to say arises (when a slave is a cowherd, a woman a wool-spinner, and
so on). At this, Ion's last refuge is to select some specific craft depicted
by Hornets and claim that it is in this sphere that he is knowledgeable.
There is a peat deal of generalship in the Iliad—so a rhapsode would
certainly know "what is appropriate in the mouth of someone who's a
general, when he is exhorting Ms troops'. But to make Ion sustain this
line, Plato reduces him to the ridiculous expedient of claiming to see
'no difference' between the craft of generalship and that which makes
Mm a good rhapsode, and even to be himself the best general among
the Greeks, (Iris Murdoch finds 'unspeakable charm' here,29 but is the
irony overdone when Ion adds, 'that too I learnt from the works of
Homer*?) It is easy to show that the crafts of general and rhapsode are
distinct, and to point out that Ion's life has shown no evidence of
generalship. He is being 'unfair' if he has genuine military 'techneand
knowledge', and has carefully concealed it (541el-3). Otherwise he
must lack such knowledge; and, if he lacks it, the only explanation is
that his.ability to speak about Homer stems from the inspiration dis-
cussed earlier. He acquiesces in the final statement that, as eulogist of
Homer, he should be accorded the status of being 'divine* rather than
skilled (technikos).
The truth which this final passage establishes is that to speak well,
in the sense that Ion can lay claim to, about Homer's depiction of any
techne, does not require possession, of that techm oneself. Plato does
not make the false claim that a successful eulogist of Homer cannot
have the knowledge of a general or a charioteer. Rather, he makes the
point that such knowledge is not necessary, and would therefore be
incidental to one's success, in the role of eulogist In the Republic he
makes the same point concerning the poets,30 and there is clearly a
s
Murdoch, 8.
* Sep. 598b-60tb, See toe discussion'in Ch. 6 below, and also Janaway (1991),
Urmson (1982, 129—35) expounds the point and related issues with vigour.
28 Rhapsody
connection between the two cases. How could Ion, whose ability is the
derivative one of discoursing about Homer's writing, be required to
have knowledge of generalship, when Homer himself can lack such
knowledge and still write good poetry about its exercise?
A useful picture is that of different levels of techne.31 A general or
a charioteer has a techne which is basic, in that its subject-matter is
simply directing men in warfare or driving a chariot By contrast, the
techne of the poet is at second level: its subject-matter includes the
basic technai, along with their subject-matter. The rhapsode's critical or
eulogistic art is at a third level: when he "speaks well* of Homer, Ms
subject-matter is the poetic fee/we Now note two important points. In
one sense, there is a transparency between these levels: in discoursing
on Homer's exercise of the art of poetry, one obtains generalship and
charioteering as part of one's subject-matter. But knowledge of the
basic subject-matter is not transmitted op the hierarchy of levels. Al-
ready at the poet's level, including a tecknein one's subject-matter, and
having the ability to make fine poetry about it, does not require that one
have knowledge of its subject-matter. How much less then, on the
strength of his abilities, should a mere eulogist of poetry claim know-
ledge of any basic techne. As we shall see, these two theses, the trans-
parency of poetry's subject-matter, and its non-transmission of
knowledge, remain fundamental to Plato's thinking about the arts: the
discussion of mimesis in Republic Book 10 has equivalents of the same
theses at its core.
Earlier we raised the question whether there are rhapsodic and poetic
crafts at all for Plato, The rather rambling final argument tells us noth-
ing more about whether there is a poetic techne. But it makes eight
mentions of 'the rhapsodic techne", all put into the mouth of Socrates,32
as if he affirms its existence. Of course, on one view33 this should again
be read as a temporary assumption of precisely what is to be refuted.
But if we look carefully at the argument's conclusion, we do not find
any statement that there exists no rhapsodic techne. The conclusion is
31
Here I am indebted to Spragne (1976), 6-7.
32
538M, c5, d5, 539e3, 540a2, aS, d.4, 541al-2. Three of these use the expression he
rhapsattiki, omitting the word techne. In these passages Ion admits that the rhapsodic
techne is distinct from those of the charioteer, doctor, and fisherman, is asked whether
be sticks by his doomed claim that the rhapsodic uchni is identical with that of the
general, asked what the special subject-matter of the rhapsodic techne is, and forced to
conclude that tie rhapsodic techne does not know everything,
33
That of Flashar.
Rhapsody 29
34
that as a eulogist of Homer Ion is not master of any techne, Moreover,
the dialectical context requires only that Ion's own professions of know-
ledge are refuted, and what is contested is not his claim to be an expert
rhapsode, or Ms claim that there is such a thing as expertise in rhap-
sody. The dubious assertions he has made are that he is an expert on
everything that Homer writes about, and that he is an expert in the
techne of generalship. The argument refutes these claims easily, using
as premisses the general proposition:
If technai T, and T2 are distinct, then the practitioner of T, does not
as such have the knowledge enjoyed by the practitioner of T2.35
and the specific assumption about the rhapsodic techne;
The rhapsodic techne is distinct from those of charioteering, medi-
cine, generalship , . . (all the technai Homer portrays).36
Thus if the rhapsode's techne is distinct from any one of the technai
Homer depicts, the rhapsode will not have knowledge of all such forms
of expertise, as Ion initially claims. If it is distinct from every one of
them, then the rhapsodic expert can claim knowledge of none of the
technai portrayed in the Homeric poems. Conclusion: no techne ex-
plains the success of the rhapsode when he acts as judge or eulogist of
his poet's handling of particular subject-matters. But this is not to say
'there is no rhapsodic techne'. It is compatible with the dialogue's
ending that there should be a rhapsodic craft. The point is that, if there
is such a craft, its practitioner speaks finely rather than knowledgeably
when discoursing on Ms favourite poet, and that such fine speaking is
precisely what cannot be explained by mastery of a techne.
This is all well and good, but we may feel that important issues have
been evaded. As Ms Murdoch puts it: "Ion, looking for something to be
expert on, might more fruitfully have answered: a general knowledge
of human life, together of course with a technical knowledge of poetry.
34
In the final sentence he is said to be me tectmikan peri Hameratt epainetem; not a
eulogist about Homer by techne (542b3-4). The conditional choice offered hita prepara-
tory to this conclusion is in precisely the same tarns: either he is able to eulogize Homer
by tecbne. and episteme (541el—2), or he is not technikos, but speaks many fine things
about the poet through, being possessed by diviae power and knowing nothing (542a2-
5). Cf. 532c6~7, 53642-3, 536cl~2.
55
Cf. bila pasan, ion technan, ha lei heterai technei gignaskomen, on gnosometha tei
heterai, 53741-2.
36
538M-5 states this, step explicitly for charioteering. The ensuing argument brings
in parallel technai without stating this step ag for for each—a tactical suppression, which
enables the final skirmish in which Ion denies the distinction between rhapsody and
generalship.
30 Rhapsody
... The humane judgement of the experienced literary man is excluded
from consideration, by Socrates* sharp distinction between technical
knowledge and "divine intuition",'"There are two points here: firstly,
if we are talking about technical knowledge at all, then it is false that
poet and critic lack it, since they have specialized technical knowledge
concerning poetry itself. Secondly, the discussion should not be re-
stricted to technical knowledge, since there is also a 'general know-
ledge of human life'—dare we say "wisdom'?—that informs the best
poetry, and gives authority to criticism. Let us take the two points
separately.
First consider 'general knowledge of human life*. Ion comes closest
to this when he talks of 'what may suitably be said by a man ... and
the sort of thing suitably said by a woman; the sort suitable for a slave
to say*, and so on. It has been suggested that 'with this objection Plato
shows that he is aware of the narrowness of his own handling of the
problem*'.38 However, the issues become anything but clear once this is
mooted. Are we considering the 'general knowledge of human life'
which any ordinary person above a certain age would have acquired?
If so, we still lack any specialist knowledge for the rhapsodic critic per
se. Are we looking for an uncommon range of experience and depth
of insight into human Me? If so, why should that be the prerogative of
the poetry critic? Why, indeed, should such wisdom be Ms at all? Ion
manages to be a great eulogist of Homer without showing exceptional,
wisdom. The only "knowledge of what is suitable for people to say* that
is a plausible candidate as the rhapsodic critic's specialism is know-
ledge of what it is suitable for people to say in an epic poem—in other
words, how characters are appropriately represented by a poet such as
Homer. And why should that require any more than an ordinary know-
ledge of life itself? Julius Moravcsik suggests that 'poets and their
appreciators* are likely to have more sensitivity than the average person
to 'the cruelty and senselessness of war*, for example; this is something
which Homer "knew as much about, if not more, than any general*.39
But again would our best description be that Homer had a special
sensitivity to the cruelty of war, or that he had the sensitivity to imagine
and represent it? If the latter, we are in the province not of knowing
about war, but of the ability to compose fine poetry, which Plato has
already dealt with in this dialogue: it comes not from knowledge, but
from inspiration.
37 s
Murdoch, 9. * Schaper, 33. Moravcsik (1982), 36.
Rhapsody 31
Murdoch's other point is that Plato ignores the importance of that
technical knowledge of poetry which Ion may have. I take it we mean
such things as rales for writing or reciting in a set metre, what marks
the difference in the epic genre between narration and a speech in
character, perhaps even which modes of diction (vocabulary, syntax)
are appropriate for poetry as opposed to prose. All of this can be learned,
and is appropriately called the craft of poetry. The rhapsode's expertise
in performance may be fed by such knowledge, and may -in addition
have rules of its own that can be learned. If Ion has such technical
knowledge, it is strange that we hear nothing' of its informing Ms dis-
course on Homer's good qualities, especially since the possibility was
canvassed earlier of judging poetry by a genuine form of expertise.
That possibility has receded by the end.* But in the final argument
Plato shows not (hat Ion lacks any technical knowledge—only that the
critic need possess none of the crafts portrayed in the poetry he judges.
He neither affirms nor closes off the possibility of a proper craft of
poetry-criticism. Thus on my reading Plato need not be denying
specialist expertise to the poet and rhapsode. Their having it will
not be very important, though: knowing in detail how to construct and
enunciate hexameters is not evidence- of knowing anything else.
So a poet's ability to compose fine poetry does not stem from 'techne
and knowledge*—-while yet Plato appears to assume that there is a
poietikS techni But this position is intelligible. What is at stake is the
fineness of poetry and performance—and this may not stem from the
correct exercise of the crafts of poetry and rhapsody, even if they exist.
Plato makes clear in the middle section of the Ion that he is concerned
to account for the fineness or beauty of what good poets say:
All good epic poets recite all that splendid [kala] poetry not by virtue of a
techne, bat in a state of inspiration and possession. The same is true of good
lyric poets as well:... it's when they are not in control of their senses that the
lyric poets compose those fine [kala] lyric poems.41
"These fine [kala] poems are not on the- human level nor the work of
humankind, but divine, and the 1 work of gods', says Socrates at the
* LaDriere (31) suggests this is because tfw latter part of the dialogue is 'devoted to
establishing that no such criticism can be found, or is in the nature of things possible'.
41
Ion 533e5~534a2. kalos and cognate terms oecw a fcrther six tinws in Socrates'
long speech up to 535a2. (This is well brought out by Dorter, 75.) Plato's phrasing
emphasizes that it is good poets he is talking about: hoi ton epon paietm hoi agathoi...
kui hoi melopoioi hoi agathoi might be teanslated 'the epic poets — The -good ones , . .
and the makers of lyrics — the good ones'.
32 Rhapsody
culmination of Ms long speech. There are bad poets, of whom Tynnichus
is said to be one, but the gods proved themselves the true origin of ine
poetry, when Tynnichus of all people produced the finest [kaUiston]
lyric (534e2-535al). The rest of Tynniehus' output demands no ex-
planation in terms of divine inspiration. It is the fineness or beauty of
poetry that is inexplicable even to the poet and requires the theory that
he is a mouthpiece for an external agency. Bad or indifferent poets,
who may yet be bona fide poets composing according to the poetic
techne, are bad or indifferent because they are not visited by the right
divine power. This appears to be Plato's view in the later Phaedrus: 'if
a man comes to the door of poetry untouched by the madness of the
Muses, believing that techne alone will make him a good poet, he and
Ms sane compositions never reach perfection, but are utterly eclipsed
by the performances of the inspired madman,'42 The point is: techne is
not sufficient But it is not necessary to tack it in order to be a good
poet or, for that matter, a good eulogist of a good poet
Some have doubted the extent to which Ion is supposed to be genu-
inely inspired.43 But this is not very troubling. His acquisition of the
epithet 'divine' at the end of the dialogue is ironic in tone, but need not
be insincere in substance. Ion is touched, relatively remotely, by the
divine chain of inspiration—he is 'divine* by proxy. What he produces
is genuinely fine and admirable, and it is these qualities in particular
which Plato wishes to explain as having a divine source. But just for
this reason Ion cannot take the credit by attributing the fineness of Ms
performances to Ms own agency. If the gods may choose Tynnichus
as their direct mouthpiece, their power may light—at further remove
—upon a pretentious fool. We do not have to find him particularly
admirable, for the 'divine dispensation' thesis to be literally believed
by Plato.
What then of the inspiration of poets? Although Plato says that his
doctrine of inspiration corresponds with what 'the poets inform us',
scholars have recently suggested that the view of inspiration as an
irrational state in which one is 'out of one's senses' is simply Plato's
own,44 Poets traditionally called on the Muses (the invocations at the
beginning of the Iliad and Odyssey are probably the best known, exam-
ples) for assistance in exercising their craft, in getting their story right,
in having sufficient powers of memory, and in conveying the truth
42
PUr, 245a5—8. slightly adapted from the translation by Hamilton. For more discus-
sion, see below, Cfi. 7.
43
See Piashw, 72-3, 88. * Sec Tigeretedt (1.970); Murray.
Rhapsody 33
aboat their subject-matter. Skill, craft, knowledge, and moral wisdom
are all assigned to poets with no suggestion that inspiration would rob
them of such qualities. Plato's notion, however, is a new one at odds
with this. For him craft-knowledge and poetic inspiration exclude one
another: the inspired are in a state of mind in which they do not under-
stand what they are doing and are even not full agents, merely mouth-
pieces for higher beings who speak through them. According to W. J.
Verdenias, inspiration takes on a problematic character once this change
to the traditional notion has been made, 'The old collaboration of the
poet and Ms Muse breaks down", he writes,45 'because the poet, in Ms
ecstasy, is no longer himself, . . . The same inspiration which estab-
lishes his contact with the Muse mars his understanding of her inten-
tions.* In Verdenius* view the poet is like an over-excited messenger
who can pass on only a garbled version of an important piece of news.
What rings untrue in Verdenius' reading is the implication that in-
spiration for Plato consists of two separable components: («) receiving
some message from a higher authority, and (b) being in an irrational
frenzy. If only—we are supposed to think—one could receive the
message whilst in a fit fitate of mind to make rational use of it.
But there is no clue from the Ion that this is possible, because Plato
is not looking to the divine source of poetry as an explanation of its
truth or wisdom—rather as an explanation of its fineness as poetry,
which he identifies as a distinct question. There is a tension throughout
the dialogue between two senses of 'speaking finely'.46 Only the fisher-
man can judge if Homer speaks finely—-correctly—of the fisherman's
craft, or whether Ion in his eulogizing lectures 'speaks finely*—
correctly—of these same matters. But in these very lectures Ion is said
to 'speak many fine things* about the poet, and what the poet himself
says in his art is of a dazding beauty. Plato thinks that the ability to
speak correctly, truly, or wisely stems from knowledge or techne, to
possess wMch is to apply rational, principles of which one is folly
conscious. By contrast, to speak finely or beautifully, as poet, per-
former, or eulogist, so as to bring aboat pleasure and emotional in-
volvement in an audience, is not a matter of knowledge or techne, but
of inspiration. The older notion of inspiration has the poet fully in
control of his mind, yet aided by the Muse in delivering truth and
wisdom. In Verdenius* view inspiration is both the Muse's delivery of
truth and wisdom, and the poet's being in a state of unknowing passivity.
43
Verdenius (1983), 44. * As pointed out by Dorter, 75,
34 Rhapsody
But Plato is further away from the older notion than that. There is in
his account no divine 'truth,* to be interpreted rightly or wrongly—only
a power which enables the production of beauty. Through the media-
tion of a human mouthpiece the gods speak beaatifully, as Socrates
says at 534e. The "interpreter of the poet's thought* moves us simply
because he is a channel for the transmission of inspiration.47
So is this twist of the inspiration doctrine designed to belittle poets?
The difficulty of taking the 'passive possession* .view literally may
force us to construe it as remaining at the level of metaphor. Then we
are pushed in one of two directions: either the account is meant not
seriously, but as an ironic demolition of the poets' own pretensions; or
Plato's metaphorical flights offer serious praise of poetry by essentially
poetic means,48 The dialogue as a whole cannot be read as praising
poetry unequivocally; but its obvious irony belittles not so much poetry
as one character's ill-thought-out claim to a kind of knowledge and
expertise he does not have. Good poets produce a species of beauty or
fineness, and it is quite in order to say that we should admire them for
this, while insisting that they do not do so from the rational application
of readily explicable principles, as in a standard techne.49 Read in this
way, the Ion does not devalue poetry itself, but puts forward a theory
of what makes good poetry good. And it makes fun of those who do
not accept that theory and take themselves to have gained an enormous
amount of knowledge from poetry. These are the same epaineteis of
Homer who in the Republic (606el ff.) claim that their poet is the chief
educator of Greece. They rely on the premiss that to make poetry finely
(kalos), the good poet must do so with knowledge, and from this they
conclude that Homer, who makes poetry finely about a panoramic range
of subjects, has knowledge of all the crafts, and of all matters concern-
ing the human and the divine.50 But the premiss is false, and so is the
47
Moravesik states the cancel view succinctly: 'At no point ... is inspiration con-
strued as a special kind of insight; the inspired poet , . . lacks what Plato would regard
as genuine knowledge or understanding' (1982, 35). Ferrari (1989, 99) also sees that
Plato contrasts 'inspiration with understanding and verbal performance with genuine
communication*.
48
Tigerstedt (1969), 26, who cites Goethe and Marsiio Ficino as exemplary authori-
ties for the "ironic* and "praising* readings respectively.
* Thus 'Plato's attitude toward inspiration mixes sweet with sour' (Woodruff (19826),
138), though this need not betoken the incptness implied by Else: 'He sets out to hold
[poetry] up to mockery , . , But somehow in the doing be is carried away and paints so
glowing a picture of the poetic afflatus that we almost believe it is divine' (1986, 8).
x
Rep. S98d8-e5. See below, Ch. 6, and Jaaaway (1991).
Rhapsody 35
conclusion—as Plato shows (or comes near to showing) when he
approaches the topic in serious mood.
Shelley approaches Plato's view in saying that poetry 'acts in a
divine and unapprehended manner, beyond and above consciousness',51
though really, as we saw in the passage quoted at the outset, he thinks
that the 'power* of the mind in creation 'arises from within', from,
presumably, a portion of our own nature of which we are not conscious.
This too is a mere gesture, as undeveloped, if also as evocative, as
Plato's: it is unclear what such a 'power' is going to be. But there is
a core position common to Shelley and Plato: that when poetry is good,
it does not owe its goodness to any exercise of rational principles by
its author, and that its author can offer no explanation, from within the
conscious apprehension of his or her own psychology, for the fineness
of the product. I have not said that this view of the nature of good
poetry is true. Deciding the extent of its truth is, however, a task which
Plato sets for the philosophy of art, and one which will remain with us
in this book.
51
Shelley, 116.
2
PLATO alleges that the performing arts of music and tragic drama aim
solely to produce pleasure in their audiences, and that to do so they
employ a sophisticated kind of guesswork. They do not—as he would
prefer—•aim at what is good for the audience, nor do they pursue their
eeds by adhering to general, rational principles. Their practitioners
cannot, then, claim knowledge, aor any genuinely beneficial effect on
the community. In these ways they are unlike medicine and should
instead be classed with public rhetoric, of which Plato cannot approYe,
Rhetoric is massively persuasive, and dangerous because its speaker
(rhetor) seeks merely to gratify the audience, who then cannot distin-
guish gratification from learning and improvement. Knowledge and
genuine excellence are lost, but their loss is masked by the presence of
a beguiling counterfeit which more than satisfies its recipients. We
shall see these allegations made in the Gorgias, where Plato again uses
the concept of techne, though this time in a more strongly theoretical
manner. By the criteria Plato uses here neither rhetoric nor the pleasure-
giving performing arts which he discusses qualify as technai at all.
There is a misapprehension which some historians of aesthetics have
fallen into—that it is safe to treat techne as the cental positive concept in
Plato's philosophy of the arts. The picture is this: first an all-embracing
theory of what techne is, then a division of 'the arts* (technai) into
various classes and subclasses (such as the productive and the 'imita-
tive'), where what appEes to techne as a whole applies to each species,
including poetry and the other 'fine arts* of modem times.11 think this
picture is misguided, IB. bis later works Plato is interested in a system-
atic account of techne by the method of division, and for the purposes
' Examples: Bosanquet, 38: Grey, 303-10; Lodge, 52-63; Hofctadter and Kuhns, 3;
Beardsley, 32-3. Sometimes teclme is rendered 'art', with the acknowledgement that
'an' includes both fine arts and crafts. However, Lodge (62) repeats Collingwood's claim
(discussed below), saying that "poetry is an outstanding example of human craftsman-
ship* for Plato.
Arts, Crafts, and Pleasure 37
of such classifications various art activities will belong under the head-
ing of techne? But in earlier writings the story is quite different. We
have looked at the Ion, where poetry's artistic success (as we would
call it) steins from inspiration, and mentioned the Apology, where
Socrates complains that poets cannot explain what they have written
about. In the Gorgias, as we shall see, tragedy aad some kinds of music
are explicitly denied the status of a techne. The trend culminates in
Republic Book 10, where it is argued that poets lack knowledge, and
where they are contrasted unfavourably with ordinary craftsmen. It would
be fanciful to treat all these passages as aberrations from some precon-
ceived system of classification in which poetry is neatly subordinated
to the concept of techne,
R. G. Collingwood provides an interesting example of the
aesthetieian's mistake about techne. While in his own theory 'art.' and
'craft' are mutually exclusive categories,3 he attributes to Plato the
view that poetry is simply a craft. Craft, he claims, is what in Latin was
called ars, and in Greek techne. He glosses it as 'the power to produce
a preconceived result by means of consciously controlled and directed
action'.4 Collingwood sees that techne cannot properly be translated as
'art* and is somewhat closer to his own conception of 'craft'. Yet he
announces boldly that his own conception was 'expounded once for all'
in the writings of the Greek philosophers, and that Plato and Aristotle
'took it for granted that poetry, the only art which they discussed in
detail, was a kind of craft, and spoke of this craft as poietike techne,
poet-craft'.5 In the Greek conception, he continues, the poet 'is a kind
of skilled producer; he produces for consumers; and the effect of his
skill is to bring about in them certain states of mind, which are con-
ceived in advance as desirable states. The poet, like any other kind of
craftsman, must know what effect he is aiming at, and must learn by
experience and precept... how to produce it.*
We may note two of the characteristics ColMngwood himself assigns to
craft, and which he claims are lacking in the case of art (or 'art proper*).
Firstly, the distinction, between means and end-—a craft always has an
end-product, to which certain actions are means. Characteristic of such
2
See Soph. 219a-d, 233d-236c, 264c-267d; Pol. 284e, 2S8c; Phil. 55d-56c. These
passages are discussed in Ch. ? below,
3
Collingwood recognizes the importance of hard-won technique for artists (1938,26—
9), and allows that a work of art can also be a work of craft. But, for him, something's
being an exercise of craft-technique is never part of what makes it art.
4 5
Ibid. 15. Ibid. 17, 18.
38 Arts, Crafts, and Pleasure
actions is that they 'are passed through or traversed in order to reach
the end, and are left behind when the end is reached'. Secondly, the
distinction between planning and execution—
Collingwood argues that what is 'properly' called art shares none of the
features of craft. According to Shelley, 'A man cannot say "I will
compose poetry*". Collingwood agrees. In Ms view, all art including
poetry is an act in which the artist expresses Ms or her emotion in a
moment of authentic self-realization. Prior to the completion of a poem,
there can be no accurate specification of the finished product There
may be planning and execution of a kind, but there is no foreknowledge
such as the practitioner of a craft must have. The idea is that if I could
tell you what I wanted to express in a poem prior to its completion, it
would be redundant to complete the poem—or, contrary to hypothesis,
it would already be complete, because I would already have expressed
my emotion in telling you. For the same reason, the means-end distinc-
tion is lacking. The *end' is not specifiable until it is reached, and the
'means' are not discarded as mere instruments once an 'end' is reached—
for, according to Collingwood, the process of expressing one's emotion
really is the work of art itself,
Now Coltiftgwood thinks Plato had the correct conception of craft,
but confusedly made poetry into a species of craft which worked as a
means to the end of arousing emotions. What Plato objects to, on this
story, is poetry's craft-like manipulation of its audience into the frivo-
lous emotional states of "mere entertainment*. It is true that Plato criti-
cizes some of the arts, including some poetry, for aiming at the
production of pleasure. But, contrary to what Collingwood says, this is
part of the argument that such arts are in the strict sense not instances
of techne at all. In fact, Plato's views are closer to Collingwood's own
than he appreciates. It is precisely poetry's unprincipled, un-craft-like
' Ibid. 15-16,
Arts, Crafts, and Pleasure 39
nature which makes it so suspicious to him. In the sense of 'skill' that
matters to Plato, poets are not skilled producers,
We should be wary of making too many assumptions about 'craft* and
'techne'. Although it is common to talk of a Socratic *eraft-analogy*,
it has.been doubted, recently whether "craft* is an appropriate transla-
tion of techne at all. Some technai, such as medicine, are too theoretical
to be called crafts; others, such as arithmetic, lack any separable end-
product.7 'Expert knowledge' or 'expertise* are probably the terms which
best match the range of techne. On the other hand, activities which we
do call crafts are usually included under techne. Thus if poetry turned
out to be a kind of skilled making analogous to building or weaving,
then it would be a techne too,
To what extent should we agree with Collingwood in divorcing art
from crafts such as these? His view that true art must occur wholly
without preconception or the deliberate application of means to an end
is undoubtedly a myth. But there is a less hard-line view which per-
meates a great deal of modem thinking about art. This is the view that
art involves an exercise of craft as a necessary condition, but is not
exhausted by it. Kant provides a clear instance. The production of
works of ine art, Kant claims, requires 'a talent for producing that for
which no definite rule can be given: and not an aptitude in the way of
cleverness for what can be learned according to some rule';8 but
nevertheless 'there is ... no fine art in which something mechanical,
capable of being at once comprehended and followed in obedience to
rules, and consequently something academic does not constitute the
essential condition of the art'.9 Even though without craftsmanship there
would be no art at all, the criterion of 'fineness* in fine art always
exceeds the requirement that a craft has been exercised properly. We
shall see that in some respects Plato's denial of the status of techne to
musical performance and tragedy is parallel, except that, as with the
case of inspiration, his evaluation is reversed; if a performer is not
technikos; that is a pound for disapproval.
Plato deploys the concept of techne in the early dialogues for
7
The translation "craft* may wrongly suggest an activity whose end-product is iden-
tifiable independently of the activity itself, (As Critias asks in the Charmides, "What is
the product [ergon] of the art of arithmetic or geometry, in the way that a house is the
product of building, a cloak of the art of weaving, or many other such products of many
arts which one could point to?' {Char, 165e6-166al, trans. Watt). See Roochnik, who
argues1 against the view of Irwin (1977a); and Nussbaum (1986), 97, 445.
8 f
Kant, §46, 168. Ibid. §47, 171.
40 Arts, Crafts, and Pleasure
different purposes to suit different dialectical contexts,10 He often uses
the ordinary, familiar technai as examples when refuting claims to
knowledge, or illustrating the difference between knowledge and mere
opinion. Each such techne must embrace some body of knowledge that
is teachable, it roust have a clearly identifiable subject-matter of its
own, and it must be sufficiently based on generalizable principles that
it can claim knowledge of the whole of its subject-matter,11 The other,
narrower conception is that of the single, higher-level techne, the
'ruling' or 'adequate' techne. None of the ordinary specialized technai
amounts to a totally self-sufficient expertise; each lacks an account of
what, overall, counts as its good exercise. The adequate or ruling techne,
by contrast, would always aim at the good, guided by principles which
enabled it to give an account of what the good is.12
In the early dialogues Plato shows us a Socrates for whom goodness
and knowledge are closely linked. 'Goodness* or 'being good* is the
condition called arete in Greek, the excellence or virtue of something
or somebody. Socrates seeks the arete of a human being as such—what
it is for someone to be excellent, or possess virtue as a human being.
That being good is equivalent to knowing what is good and evil is one
of the main planks of Socratic ethics. It is a strong and paradoxical
claim, embracing both the thought that knowledge of good and evil is
necessary for being good, and the thought that in order for someone to
be good, it is sufficient that they know what is good and what is evil.13
Now possessors of techne are experts in a specified field of knowledge,
whose judgements are superior to the run-of-the-mill judgements of the
many, and who are in a position to transmit knowledge through teach-
ing to others. Success is predictable and objectively ascertainable: "there
is- a right method, and answers do not depend on the prejudices of
particular people.'14 Whether something is a good table or chariot is not
10
I am indebted here to Woodruff (1990), and to Roochnik.
11
Nwsbautn (1986, 94-6, with 442 ff.) gives a succinct account of the features of
techfie in Greek thinking from the fifth century down to Aristotle, drawing particularly
on medical literature. The chief features of techne in her account are: (1) having universal
principles that apply to a group of similar cases and yield predictions about future cases;
(2) being teachable to an individual prior to that individual's direct experience; (3) having
precision—a notion frequently linked with that of a measure or standard; (4) being able
to give an explanation-of why procedures adopted are successful.
12
In spelling out this contrast, Woodruff has written that Socrates 'allows the term
[tecknel for crafts that are plainly subordinate, and withholds it from those that might
masquerade as a Ruling Techne', the latter being the supposedly authoritative activities
of 'poets, politicians and the like* (1990, 69-70).
13
This account is influenced by frwin (1977a), chs. HI and iv.
14
Ibid, 75.
Arts, Crafts, and Pleasure 41
just a matter of opinion, but requires reference to principles stating that
if a chariot has certain specific features it will be a good chariot. In
many of Plato's prime cases the presence of these features will be
objectively measurable.
The production of excellence by a technl is not haphazard, then. It
is regular, reliable, predictable, transmissible, and explicable in terms
of general and impersonal principles possessed by its practitioners. If
one believes that knowledge of good and evil is necessary and suffi-
cient for human excellence, and observes that excellence in many
special fields is brought by techne, then it is tempting to suppose that
possession of a kind of supreme techne will be equivalent to human
excellence. In a much-discussed part of the Protagoras Socrates goes
to the extreme of advocating a moral techne which would accurately
measure all goods and evils on a single scale of value, determining
them as 'more or less, greater or smaller, nearer or more distant' (3S?a5-
b4). This would be achieved if there were a single desirable standard
of measurement, which Socrates here (but nowhere else) suggests is
pleasure. In the Gorgias he holds that any true techne aims always at
the good, which is distinct from pleasure. What persists is the drive to
show that having or transmitting moral excellence consists in possess-
ing genuine expertise of a certain kind,
The dramatic context of the Gorgias h Socrates' conversation with
the great practitioner and teacher of rhetoric, Gorgias, and with Polus,
his younger colleague. Gorgias of Leontini is usually treated as one of
the sophists.IS He travelled widely and displayed his talents for rhetoric,
though it appears that, unlike other sophists, he did not profess to teach
excellence via the medium of persuasive speaking.16 His rhetorical style,
which Plato sometimes parodies, is calculated for impressive effect,
using repetition of sound-patterns and deliberately piling up redundant
parallels or opposites for almost any word or idea It comes across as
ponderous and artificial-—but bears out the fact that Gorgias was also
a theorist about language and its effects. The best, source for Gorgias'
views about the nature of speech is his Encomium of Helen, in which
he exercises his- rhetorical powers in arguing that Helen, who ran off
adulteroBsly with, Paris, should be absolved of blame, \vhatever caused
13
Dodds dissents (1959, ?), but is criticized for taking the term 'sophist* too narrowly
by Kerferf, 45. Kerferd gives a clear account of Gorgias' doctrines (78—82), including
a paraphrase of the most important passages in the Encomium of Helen. See also Gufhrie
(1971), 20, 25, 44-5, 50-1, 168, 180-1, 269-74.
'* Cf. Menu 95b9-c4i Gorgias laughs at the other sophists who claim to teach arete—
his task is to make clever speakers.
42 Arts, Crofts, and Pleasure
her to act as she did. Particularly interesting is the section in which he
argues that if speech (logos) influenced her actions, she is not to be
blamed. Speech is a 'powerful lord' with an overwhelming ability to
persuade." Speech "constrains*,18 and leaves the persuaded one without
responsibility for what she does. In so doing, it operates on the human
capacity for belief or opinion, rather than knowledge of the troth. In-
deed knowledge is impossible.19 All we can have at our disposal are
opinions, together with speech, which is an irresistible tool for persuad-
ing people to adopt opinions, provided we capture our hearers by giv-
ing them pleasure. A speech for Gorgias 'delights and persuades a vast
audience by the skilfatoess of its composition, not by the accuracy of
its statements* (technii grapheis, ouk aletheiai lechtheis)', at work is a
power 'which by its witchery enchants, persuades and changes the souls
of men*,20 Because truth is not its aim, and knowledge supposedly
could not be its outcome, all persuasion by speech is a deception of
opinion, a deception of the soul,21 which Gorgias classes as a form of
witchery (goeteia). Speech works in the same way as a drug works on
the body, except that rather than curing or killing, it affects the soul
with a whole panoply of emotions,
Pot just as different drugs dispel different secretioas from the body, and some
bring an end to disease and others to life, so also in the case of speeches, some
distress, others delight, some cause fear, others make the hearers bold, and
some drag and bewitch the soul with a kind of evil persuasion.**
30
'Hattery*: la>lakeiat a highly disparaging term, as Dodds's memorable gloss tells us:
'The Max is what the eighteenth century called a toad-eater or lickspittle and schoolboy*
call a bum-sucker* (1959, 225),
31
Cf. the famous passages at Memo 97e6-98a8, 99ci-100b4. An inexplicable 'divine
dispensation* (theio. moira, the same expression as was applied to Ion) may enable some-
people, including statesmen, priests, prophets, and poets, to have the right beliefs; but this
is not the same as genuine knowledge, Knowledge is having a belief which is 'tied down*
by a 'working out of the reason*. This working out (logismos) marks the crucial differ-
ence between merely getting things right, and knowing,
32
At Prot. 354a5-7, 'doctors* treatment involving cautery or tie knife [amputation]
or drugs or starvation diet' is an example of something 'good but painful* (though the
argument as a whole pronounces such things 'good' only in that they bring greater long-
term pleasure). At Rep, 357c6 ff,, being treated when ill is something good not for its
own sake, but for its consequences.
46 Arts, Crafts, and Pleasure
what they do. In the process medicine introduces order (kosmos) and
structure (taxis) into the body, which makes for its excellence (arete)
(504a2-c9).
The close connection Plato makes between good, knowledge, and an
account can perhaps be elucidated thus. In order to aim at the achieve-
ment of the best state of something of some" kind (K), one must have
a conception of what a good thing of that kind (a good K thing) is. In
a techne this conception must reliably guide action to a successful
outcome. One's conception of a K thing must be correct and one must
not attain the outcome by chance whilst happening to have the right
conception. One must, then, have knowledge or understanding of what
a good K thing is—hence knowledge of the true nature of a K thing—
and be able to give a rational account of the procedures undertaken to
reach one's goal. 'I don't call anything a techne which'is without an
account (alogon)', says Socrates (465a5-6). The person with a true
techne is in possession of the principles which he or she has followed
in order to produce the desired outcome in any particular case. He or
she is able to give a logos—aa account, explanation, reason. Any alogon
pragma (thing without an account) is not a techne.
The activities which Socrates calls 'flattery* aim at pleasure, treating
their direct product—say, a meal, or a speech—as purely instrumental
towards the bringing about of pleasure in a recipient. Provided that the
thing I produce caases pleasure, my end is attained. Any conception of
*the best' product is therefore irrelevant—I need only observe carefully
what has caused pleasure in the past, and repeat that. Success depends
on whether what I produce is to the recipient's liking. Thus, though I
may be able to recognize a good meal or speech when I see it, I lack
any generalizable explanation of how to succeed, or any criteria for the
assessment of meals or speeches in general, which can predict, accord-
ing to the features they possess, whether they will be good or bad,
Plato makes each instance of 'flattery' the false image (eidolon) of an
instance of craft. Cookery is the image of medicine, cosmetics that .of
gymnastics. In each case an apparent good condition mimics a genuine
one: medicine produces the genuine good condition of the body, cook-
ery a merely apparently good condition which mimics it. Likewise
rhetoric, in, producing gratification by the persuasion of public speak-
ing, merely mimics justice; and sophistry is the false image of genuine
law making. Hence activities which are not genuine exercises of techne
can seem to be genuine to those who are not on their guard. 'If a doctor
and a cook had to compete among children, or among men as foolish
Arts, Crafts, and Pleasure 47
as children, to decide which of them understands more about worthy
and base food , . . then the doctor would die of starvation' (464d5—e2).
The rtteta"'& position is the same
about the just and the onjust, the fine and the shameful, and the good and the
bad . , , —be doesn't know the things themselves, what is good or bad, what
is fine or shameful or just or unjust, but has devised persuasion about them so
that though he doesn't know, among those who don't know he appears to
know, rather than the man who knows. (459dl-eL)M
So Plato sets out to show that rhetoric is not an adequate techne. In
ordinary usage it will continue to be classed as a techne, as it is at the
start of the Gorgias. But in Plato's stricter philosophical sense a truly,
adequate techne both aims at the good and is a form of knowledge.
Because good and pleasure can diverge, as is argued later (495e-500a),
a techne is not concerned to produce what pleases. Pleasure may be a
consequence of its application, but it will eschew what pleases if that
is incompatible with the good. It. will not, however, eschew the good
if that is incompatible with what pleases. The practitioners of activities
which aim solely at pleasure, meanwhile, are unable to discriminate
good from bad pleasures—it needs a craftsman (technikos) to do that
(500a4-6).
Now what is the position of the arts going to be? In the opening part
of the dialogue the -arts figure- prominently as examples of eraft or
expertise,34 But this tells us little of substance. At this stage in the
dialectic the argument is governed by the assumption that rhetoric too
is a craft. Painting, sculpture, and music are brought forward.as at least
having a clear subject-matter, in contrast to rhetoric, which has no
clearly definable subject that it is 'about'. This is the first move in the
campaign to oust rhetoric from the strict category of techne. But paint-
ing and sculpture might also fail to qualify once 'aiming at the good
by applying known principles* is made constitutive of techne, Plato
produces no argument to this effect in the Gorgias, But some of the
performing arts decidedly do not qualify.-
In conversation with Callicles Socrates discusses a number of musi-
cal practices which he puts under the heading of 'gratifying souls al in
a crowd at the sane time*:
M
Thl& and the previously cited passage are closely echoed at Rep. 598b8-c4 and
6QOe4~601W, in the discussion of poetry. Poets make eidSla—false images—of excel-
lence, which take in children and fools.
34
See 448W 1-cl, 453c6,449d3-4,450e!0 for mentions of painting, music, sculpture.
48 Arts, Crafts, and Pleasure
First of all, let's consider flute-playing. Don't you think it is the kind of practice,
we mentioned, Callicles, pursuing only our pleasure, and concerned with noth-
ing else? .,. And aren't all of this kind similar—such as lyre-playing before
large audiences? , , , And what about the teaching of choruses, and the making
of dithyrambs? Isn't it apparently something of the same kind? Or do you think
Cinesias the son of Meles cares at all about saying the kind of thing to make
the audience better? Or does he care about what win gratify the mob of spec-
tators? , , . But consider: don't you think that all singing to the lyre and com-
position of dithyrambs has been discovered for the sake of pleasure?
(5Qlel~5G2a8,)
The discussion concerns those arts designed, like rhetoric, for public
performance which gives pleasure to a large mass of people. A dithy-
ramb was a poem written to be sung by a chorus at one of the regular
Athenian festivals. As this practice developed, the works apparently
became highly elaborate, the musical element predominating over the
text,35 Cinesias was a dithyrambic poet active during Plato's early life,
a somewhat controversial figure who has been called a leading repre-
sentative of the 'new music* of the day.3* The lyre (in fact, its larger
relative the kithard) figures twice here: in straightforward lyre-playing,
and in singing accompanied by the lyre. Both were practised in public
competitions at Athens. Aristotle agrees that such perfonnances aimed
only at the pleasure of the audience and resulted in a tendency towards
impressive technical 'fireworks'.'7 In 'flute-playing*, the instrument is
the aulos, which was a reed-instrument rather than a flute. By reputa-
tion it was not wholly respectable. It was used as an accompaniment in
the theatre, but was also associated with 'the wilder sort of evening
parties',m and with ecstatic dancing at Dionysiac and other cults. We
may infer that the aulos was also used as a solo instrument in public
performances involving a high degree of exciting virtuoso display. Its
reedy timbre was in itself no doubt a thrilling sound. In some respects,
the nearest twentieth-century equivalent is the saxophone.39
35
"The making (poiesis) of dithyrambs' refers to the composition, of the poem of
which the dithyrarabic performance was a setting, 'the teaching of choruses' obviously
to the element of musical preparation and performance itself—see Dodd& (1959), 323.
K
Ibid. Cf, Aristophanes' caricature of Cinesias in Birds 1373-1404, which ridicules
his 'multiplication of meaningless epithets' (Packard-Cambridge, 60).
37
Politics 134la9, blO, as discussed by Dodds (1959), 323.
38
Dodds (1959), 322, on whose account I rely. Dodds notes that Aristotle calls the
instrument 'not ethikon, but rattier orgiastikon', and that the Pythagoreans condemned it
as vulgar,
39
Urmson writes: "Much about the aulos is uncertain; one of the few certainties is thai
it is not a flute. English musical writers refer always to the aulos; even "shawm" is better
than "flute", and "tenor saxophone", while appalling, is not as bad* (1984, 210).
Arts, Crafts, and Pleasure 49
So Plato is discussing specific practices, not music as a whole. Else-
where he has room for the thought that music does more than aim at
pleasure, as witness the view he gives to Protagoras (Prot. 326a4—b6):
music in education can 'instil self-control and deter the young from
evil-doing*. The young are taught the lyre, and then progress to singing
poetry accompanied by the lyre. By the process of familiarization, with
different forms of rhythm and harmonia, they 'become more civilized,
more balanced, and belter adjusted [euarmostoteroi-—more well-in-tune]
in themselves and so more capable in whatever they say or do*. 'This
is a view of the educational role of music which Plato will himself
endorse in the Republic and later in the Laws.40 But it is not incompat-
ible with what is said in the Gorgias. Some musical performances are
aimed solely at gratification rather than at what is good. But singing
and the playing of instruments are not necessarily to be used in this
way, and can also constitute a valuable part of one's moral education.
Plato does not here give us a theory of music as such, nor does he say
that all music is a bad or a worthless thing—merely that the music of
pleasure-giving public display should be classed as a form of 'flattery',
not as techne.*1 Pandering to their tastes in an ingratiating way, music
thus performed does not do the audience any good, Plato thinks, but
masquerades as something which does.
Now the discussion moves on to another art: 'Then what about this
august and wonderful pursuit, the composition of tragedy, and its con-
cern?' (Garg, 502bl—2). The epithets are clearly ironic,42 but reflect the
importance Plato attaches to classifying tragedy correctly. Socrates argues
that tragedy's concern too is to gratify the mass of spectators at its
performance, and that therefore it is a species of flattery. It is even a
species of rhetoric:
S O C R A T E S . Is its undertaking and concern, in your opinion, just to gratify the
spectators? Or does It struggle, if anything is pleasant and gratifying to them,
tat base, to avoid saying it, and if something is without pleasure tat benefi-
cial, to say and sing this, whether they enjoy it or not? Which way do you
think; the composition-of tragedies is equipped?
C A L L I C L E S . This much is clear, Socrates, that it concentrates oo pleasure and
on gratifying spectators.
SOCRATES. And didn't we say just now that this sort of thing is flattery,
Catiicles?
C A L L I C L E S . Quite.
SOCRATES. Well now, if someone took away from all poetic composition the
These few highly disparaging remarks are not Plato's final word on
tragedy, nor do they really say anything about poetry more generally.
(The conclusion that poi&iki is a kind of public oratory need not be
taken to apply across the board.) The discussion is limited by its sub-
ordination to the themes of rhetoric, pleasure, and good. In Gorgias'
own writings tragedy (and indeed all poetry in his case) is made con-
ceptually subordinate to speech in general, the great power to persuade
and deceive human opinion. With Gorgias present, Socrates is thus
bringing out a further consequence of his account of rhetoric for some-
one who thinks as Gorgias does. But is Plato's subsumption of tragedy
under rhetoric at all plausible? Tragedians portray persuasive dialogue
and sometimes "set debates, with formal speeches argning for and against
a thesis'.43 But it would be short-sighted to call tins the essence of
tragedy, forgetting the great lyric choruses, the reflective monologues,
the messengers* speeches reporting the worst, or the lament of the hero
or heroine after the inevitable reversal of fortune. Tragedy as a whole
can count as 'rhetoric' only on the grounds that it employs speech to
gratify a mass of spectators. (Playing the aulos is, it seems, not be
classified as rhetoric. Is this just because tragedy gratifies with speeches,
aal0s-playing with melodies?) That would make the claim 'tragedy is a
species of rhetoric* relatively uninformative—tautologous with 'tragedy
gratifies in the medium of speech*.
However, the core of Plato's claim is that tragedy aims at gratifying
a mass of spectators, not at what is good. The circumstances of the
performance of tragedy in Athens, at the festivals of the Great Dionysia
and others, are well known, and we need have no quarrel with Plato's
description of the audience. We should also remember that tragedies
were written for a single occasion of performance, which was a com-
petition. In the Theaetetus Plato celebrates with relief the contrasting
43
DtxMs (1959), 325.
Arts, Crafts, and Pleasure 51
circumstances of philosophical discussion: 'We have no jury, and
no audience (as the dramatic poets -have), sitting in control over us,
ready to criticize and give orders.* (Tht. 173c4-5,} Tragedians were
perforce concerned to aim at pleasing both masters—nor were the ver-
dicts of the two always independent.44 la this light, the notion of the
tragedian trying to 'persuade' or 'win over' a mass audience—in a way
analogous to the rhetor—is fully intelligible,
In classing tragedy as a form of flattery, aiming at pleasure not the
good, Plato comes down firmly against the tragedian's exercising a
techne in the strict sense. Tragedy will lack any rational principle by
which to explain its activity, and will succeed by something akin to
guesswork. If any artistic practice m aimed at pleasure or gratification
as an end, precisely this distances it from the strict philosophical cate-
gory of techne. Poets, composers, actors, singers, instrumentalists may
produce fine works, but it is not from knowledge that they do so. They
can give no account which explains why the product of their activities
turned out to be a fine one. They can say what they did, and have
enough experience to have picked up the 'knack' of getting things right
nearly all the time (since practice makes perfect). But they cannot point
to general principles which link their actions with the right outcome.
Performance and composition in these arts is an alogon pragma, a thing
without an account, a business without a rational principle. With this
goes the claim that the 'lightness* aimed for in poetry and music, and
the criterion of success, is that of pleasing an audience, whereas with
a true techne the criterion of success is irrespective of pleasurable re-
action (sometimes at odds with it) and consists in the production of an
object or outcome which is measurable against an objective standard of
goodness.
Is not this view a travesty of the arts? That depends on what is true
concerning the arts. There are two main questions: (1) Is poetry, or
music indeed an alogon pragma, or is either after all the domain of a
techmkasl (2) Is the aim of poetic and musical performance, and the
criterion by which they are judged to have succeeded, the giving of
pleasure? It is difficult to answer these questions in isolation from one
another, and without importing many other notions. They eventually
lead deeper into the philosophy of art than present space will accom-
modate. Nevertheless, an argument can be constructed to support answers
** As we may infer from Plato's later insistence that judges really should not take their
lead from the crowd {Laws 659a—b).
52 Arts, Crafts, and Pleasure
compatible with Plato's account. In outline it is as follows. For tragedy
not to be an alogon pragma, its author must work according to
generalizable principles which explain a successful dramatic outcome.
But it is arguable that the aim of tragedy, and its criterion of success,
is pleasure—of some sort. And there are no generalizable principles
which reliably specify that pleasure will be felt in an object of a certain
kind. So tragedy, given its characteristic aim and mode of evaluation,
cannot work according to generalizable principles of the right kind. It
is therefore not a techne, but an alogon pragma. To make this argument,
plausible, we need some backing for two claims, namely the claim that
tragedy aims at and is judged by pleasure, and the claim that there are
no generalizable 'principles of pleasure.
Does tragedy aim at pleasure? Is the criterion of its success that of
producing (or being such as to produce) pleasure? At a very broad
level, we must surely answer: Yes. The idea of an excellent drama
which fails to give pleasure at all is an odd one—assuming that it has
not met the fate of being wrongly understood or not properly staged.
Imagine a dramatist, like Collingwood's carpenter, successfully fash-
ioning a piece which corresponds with an intricate set of preconcep-
tions and rules: still, he or she has scarcely 'succeeded* in producing
a good drama, unless it is the case that pleasure would result from a
performance of the piece in appropriate circumstances to people who
understand it. The idea that the bringing about of pleasure might be a
purely incidental aim of the tragedian is one we should also reject.
Even if, contrary to what Plato thinks, tragedians do aim to educate us,
make us wiser or more pious, their way of pursuing these aims is, unlike
the way of many another educator, essentially via a kind of pleasure.
However, before acquiescing in the claim that tragedians aim at pleas-
ure, we should be circumspect. Plato imposes on the performing arts a
dubious polarity, between, on the one hand, an activity's aiming at the
good (or the best) outcome and, on the other, its aiming at pleasure via
a product which is merely instrumental towards producing that pleas-
ure—as if the artist's product is not aimed at on its own account and
is not itself 'good* in any sense. We could read into this the dubious
implication that the tragedian is simply out to please the audience, and
does not care at all what he or she produces, provided it brings about
pleasure. Calling tragedy 'flattering' already carries this implication,
Against this, we may first note an important sense in which embrac-
ing pleasure as an aim does not exclude aiming at the best, or at the
good, in the object that is to bring about pleasure. We may want to say
Arts, Crafts, and Pleasure 53
that the tragedian aims indeed at pleasing the audience, but that he or
she wants to please them by putting before them a good tragedy, and
having them be pleased by apprehending just those features in virtue of
which it is a good tragedy. Pleasures are distinguished by their inten-
tional objects—the objects they are directed towards. So there is such
a thing as pleasure in a good play, which can be distinguished from
other pleasures experienced while present at the performance of a play,
caused by that performance, but not really having the play itself as
intentional object. An example of Aristotle's makes the point. A tragedy,
on his account, should make us feel a pleasure associated with our
response of pity and fear, but
those who employ spectacular means to create a sense not of the terrible bat
only of the monstrous, are strangers to the purpose of tragedy; for we must not
demand of tragedy any and every kind of pleasure, but only that which is
proper to it. And since the pleasure which the poet should afford is that which
comes from pity and fear through mimesis, it is evident that this quality must
be impressed upon the incidents.45
Spectacular stage-machinery and breath-taking turns of events can give
pleasure. So, no doubt, can the sheer diction of a superb actor or the
beauty of a sequence of gestures. It would be possible to enjoy a
tragedy in the way transient Western tourists today might enjoy an
Indonesian epic drama.46 But there is also a pleasure 'proper to tragedy*,
to have which one must apprehend as fearful and pitiful the connected
series of depicted incidents, the plot. Plato's polarity of good and pleas-
ure falsifies, because it disguises the fact that aiming at pleasure does
not exclude aiming at a good product And to experience pleasure in
something does not exclude either its being good or the apprehension
of it as good.
The notion of something's being a good tragedy or a good musical
performance—which Plato appears to ignore in the Gorgias—-remains
totally unexplained here. So does Plato recognize that there are such
things as good poems, good musical compositions, or good perform-
ances? Recalling the Apology and Ion, we can say that he does. In the
former, poets 'say many ine [kola] things' but cannot explain 'their
most perfect works*,47 In the Ion Socrates talks of good epic poets,
45
Poetics 1453bS-14.
* See Scruton (1974), 163-4, for essentially the same example.
47
Apol. 22c2-3, 22b3-4. In the latter passage Socrates talks of the poems ha moi
edokei malista pepragmateusthai autois—perhaps 'which seemed to me their most
accomplished efforts*.
54 Arts, Crafts, and Pleasure
good lyric poets, and a bad poet who nevertheless produced the finest
lyric; he talks of works which are kalos—fine, splendid, beautiful—and
questions the rhapsode abort what it is like when he is performing well
in public. Plato omits the notion of a good tragedy or musical perform-
ance in the Gorgias because he is concerned with the good of the souls
that consume them. Cinesias and the tragedians do not intend to make
their audiences better people, but to please them. Yet they may never-
theless care whether their performances are good performances, or their
works good works. A base action may be depicted because, in the
context of the plot, it gives pleasure; but a dramatically inept depiction
will be avoided, even if it would give pleasure of some kind. Take a
modern parallel: a film-maker might debate whether to include an
explicitly sexual scene in a film. Let us take it for granted that this
particular scene would give the majority of viewers pleasure. Despite
this pleasure, the scene might be excluded, either because it was judged
base and corrupting or because the film would be a better film without
it. Plato laments that artists fail to make the former, ethical, type of
decision. But Ms description allows for—without mentioning—'artis-
tic' decisions of the latter type. So we can agree to the broad claim that
tragedy aims at pleasure without having to accept the implication that
tragedians are bent on causing pleasure irrespective of the fineness of
their dramatic productions.
Now we turn to the other claim which needed some support: that
there are no principles of pleasure. For Plato the tragedian's or musi-
cian's aiming at pleasure and being judged on the basis of bringing it
about is linked with the idea that they can give no explanation. They
have the knack of producing pleasure, but can give no explanation 'of
the pleasure', or of 'what they do* (501ai-bl). This may look straight-
forwardly false. We can easily imagine the director of a dithyrambic
chorus explaining to the ensemble why one performance worked better
than another: 'In this performance the lines of the poem were articu-
lated properly because your breathing was better co-ordinated*, or "hav-
ing slowed down the tempo, there is now room for all the ornamentation'.
These are straightforward reasons for the success- of a performance
(even if 'success* equates with giving pleasure to a mass audience).
Aristotle's detailed remarks about what makes a good tragedy good are
still exemplary pieces of the same kind of reason-giving. So this looks
like a clear sense in which these artistic practices are not 'without a
logos'. However, there is a big difference between critical reasons and
principles of taste or composition. What we have described is the reason-
Arts, Crafts, and Pleasure 55
giving of criticism: reasons for artistic success or failure given after
the event. When it is clear whether the performance worked or not, the
experienced critic can often explain why by citing observed features.
Plato, by contrast, emphasizes knowledge which produces, desired out-
comes with a reliability not simply gained by approximation or repeti-
tion of what has worked in the past: he is thinking of the situation of
the composer or performer vis-d-vis the work not yet executed. For
Plato to be wrong, there must be principles of composition or perform-
ance which the tragedian or performer can rationally follow in order to
ensure success. Still agreeing that the relevant 'success' is some suit-
ably qualified pleasure, are there such principles?
To support the claim that there are EO "principles of pleasure*, let us
return somewhat abruptly to Kant A central plank of Kant's argument
concerning judgements of beauty (what he calls 'judgements of taste')
is that they can never be arrived at by use of a rule or principle. 'There
can*, he writes, 'be no rule according to which anyone is to be com-
pelled to recognize anything as beautiful. Whether a dress, a house, or
a flower is beautiful is a matter upon which one declines to allow one's
judgement to be swayed by any ... principles.'48 The compulsion or
swaying he refers to is that of deductive inference. An object's possess-
ing certain features, combined with a general rale or principle that any
object possessing those features is F, allows one to deduce the conclu-
sion that the particular object is F*9 (An example might be the judge-
meet 'This poem is a sonnet'. This could be supported by the observation
that the poem has fourteen lines of a certain metre and a certain rhyme
scheme, together with the principle that anything with those features is
a sonnet.) But, according to Kant, such a model does not apply when
we judge something beautiful, or aesthetically good. No list of an ob-
ject's features can ever be sufficient for us to deduce its beauty by
means' of a principle. A judgement that something is beautiful has as its
basis a feeling of pleasure of a particular kind: a disinterested pleasure
in the object's perceptual form.
• Now Plato never gives an analysis of the kind of judgement which
is at the heart of Kant's problematic.50 However, when Kant comes to
2
Orube (1927), 287.
3
See the survey of uses by Dover (1974), 69-73. Whether a thing has or lacks fine
appearance is commonly a central question in whether it is kalos. Sexual intercourse and
superficial personal appearance provide different examples in the Hipputs Major, the one
of something that cannot be fine because it is not fine to see, the ofcer of something
which possibly is fine just because it looks fine {HiMa. 299a3~bl and 293e7 ff,). Mothers!!
(263) is perceptive about a pazzle the second passage raises: in effect, What is the
difference between being beautiful and looking beautifal? The ridiculous man may look
beautiful in sufficient garb, though he is not beautiful. Alcibiades is beautiful—but what
is that? He too is beautiful in that he looks, appears, is seen to be beautiful. All beauty
depends on appearance, ('True beauty is what matters, but the appearance of beauty is
not flatly a fraud,1)
4
Paul Woodruff writes: 'Like beauty, to kalon is something splendid and exciting; and
in women or boys it is the loveliness that excites carnal desire. Bat the use of kalos for
that quality is embraced by its use as a quite general term of commendation in Greek.
"Noble," "admirable," and "fine" are better translations, and of these "fine" is best of all
in virtue of its great range' (I982a, 110). See also Moravcsik (1982), 30-2 and 43, for
a helpful discussion of the fine and its relation to beauty.
5
Cf. frwin (1979), 154: 'There is no reason to believe that the use of "kalon" for what
we call moral properties indicates that the Greeks have a particularly "aesthetic" attitude
to morality, as the translation "beautiful" might suggest.'
6
Collingwood (1938), 39.
60 The Fine and the Beautiful
we adopt CoIIingwood's view, then to kalon is very like beauty, and it
makes sense to maintain that 'Plato has a lot to say about beauty, in
which he is only systematizing what we find implied in the ordinary
Greek use of the word':
To call a thing beautiful in Greek . . . is simply to call it admirable or excellent
or desirable. A poem or painting may certainly receive the epithet, but only by
the same kind of right as a boot or any other simple artifact The sandals of
Hermes, for example, are regularly called beautiful by Homer, not because they
are conceived as elegantly designed or decorated, but because they are con-
ceived as jolly good sandals which enable Mm to fly as well as walk,7
This captures some of the truth about calling a thing kalos. But why
follow Collingwood and say that the English 'beautiful* is substautiaEy
the same? We cannot just stipulate out of existence the understanding
of 'beautiful* which gives it a peculiarly aesthetic significance,
It is Kant who has here provided the clearest paradigm for recent
aesthetics. Kantian beauty (das Schone) is something we may predicate
of any kind of object (it is pointedly not restricted to the arts), but in
doing so we always make an evaluation which is expressly neither
moral nor utilitarian. The attribution of Kantian beauty depends on the
occurrence of a distinct kind of pleasure, which for present purposes we
may simply call 'aesthetic pleasure*. In her recent discussion of beauty,
written within this Kantian tradition, Mary Mothersill8 has argued that
the term 'beauty* picks out a concept of aesthetic value of the most
general nature, which is a 'standing concept', or one which we could
not do without. Beauty, according to her, is a kind of good, which may
be found in objects of any sort, and 'is causally linked with pleasure
and inspires love*,9 Plato pervades Mothersill's discussion, for she thinks
that this standing concept of beauty is also Ms; "if Plato characterizes
as kalos such disparate items as youths and maidens, goddesses, horses,
lyres, codes of law, this- suggests that kalos is a good match for the
English "beautiful" which has an analogously wide range.'10 This is not
to agree with Collingwood, whose view is that 'beautiful* has this same
wide range and does not pick out an aesthetic concept, MothersilFs
view is that beauty is rite'aesthetic concept and has a range analogous
to that of kalos.
The view I develop will be at odds with both Collingwood and
Mothersill. I do not accept the bald riding that 'beautiful* has no aesthetic
1 8
Collingwood (1938), 38. Mothetsiii, 247 ff.
* Ibid. 271. '" Ibid. 251.
The Fine and the Beautiful 61
connotation, and will, for now, retain it as the term picking out a
generic, standing concept of aesthetic value," But if this is what our
'beautiful' means, 1 do not believe that Plato's kalos is its straight
equivalent. Kalos is a ranch wider term. There are things which are
kalos because they give aesthetic pleasure—but that is only one species
of kalos, Mothersill says that poems and sculptures are 'cited as clear
... instances of beauty* by Plato.12 Yes, but poems and sculptures may
only belong to the sub-species of what is feifes-by-giving-aesthetie-
pleasure, Kalos as such, cannot be equated with 'beautiful' in its aes-
thetic sense,13 When in the Symposium Plato talks of to kalon as the
supreme object of love, to which we make a transition from first loving
a particular human body that is kalos, it is then, I adroit, hard to resist
Bsing the word 'beauty*. To say that we first love a particular person's
physical fineness and ascend to loving fineness itself loses the reso-
nance of Plato's language in that extraordinary passage, and also its
sense for us. Yet this does not overturn the view that kalos in general
is a much wider term than 'beautiful* when the latter is taken as the
generic aesthetic predicate.
Returning briefly to the Gorgias, we find that Socrates addresses part
of our first question—is there aesthetic fineness?—-by offering the
following account of what is fine:
All fine things, such as bodies, colours, shapes, sounds, practices—do you not
call them each fine with reference to something? First of all, for instance, don't
you say that fine bodies are fine either because of use, for whatever each of
them is useful for, or because of some pleasure, if they give onlookers enjoy-
ment when they look on? ... And don't you call all the other things fine too
in this way—shapes and colours—either because of. some pleasure or because
of some benefit or because of both? ... And don't you call sounds and every-
thing to do with music fine in the same way? (474d3-e5.)
There is a case for saying that Plato here acknowledges the existence
of aesthetic pleasure in a limited way. The point may be elucidated
thus. Colours, shapes, and sounds seein to have been selected as the
simplest' objects of straightforward sensation or perception, and Plato
appears happy to say that there is pleasure in the mere seeing or hearing
of them. He recognizes that fineness may be a matter of benefit, or a
" I argue elsewhere that Mothersill's account of beauty will not stretch to cover
natural and artistic beauty univocally (see Janaway (1993)).
12
Mothersill, 251.
13
Here I follow Moravcstk (1982), 31: 'what we call beautiful is for the Greeks "fine
in appearance"', a species of what is fine.
62 The Fine and- the Beautiful
matter of both benefit and enjoyment. It may please us to see an object
which also is of some yse or benefit to us—a well-wrought urn could
be fine because of its pleasing contour and also because we usefully
store things in it; or (elaborating Plato's example) think of a man with
a strong physique who is a fine man because he can help us in adver-
sity, and fine because we enjoy seeing him when he is throwing the
discus. (The linkage of 'bodies' with "giving onlookers enjoyment'
suggests an athletic context.) But there is also a pleasure in seeing or
hearing things where we may discount benefit altogether. Such things
have the kind of fineness which Aquinas (defining beauty) calls *id
cujas apprehensio ipsa placet' ('that of which the apprehension in itself
pleases').14 Such things do not just please us when we-apprehend them;
rather it is the very apprehension of them which pleases. It is this
pleasure in seeing or hearing that, in the most minimal sense, we could
call an 'aesthetic* pleasure.
This brief passage arguably shows that Plato recognizes aesthetic
pleasure in. a limited but informative sense. It also suggests answers
to the other questions we have raised,. Firstly, some of the arts are
included among the providers of this kind of pleasure-—explicitly
'everything to do with music' (though note that music's fineness may
also reside in its being beneficial or of use to us). Secondly, Plato is.
prepared to include things which give such pleasure among things that
are ine. The two points combined allow us to construct the thought
that artistic products which give aesthetic pleasure are a species of fine
things. We have discovered that Plato comprehends the idea of a posi-
tive value in some pleasing works of art, independently of any further
use or benefit they may have.
The dialogue of Plato's which takes the fine as its central topic is the
Hippias Major.K5 Socrates is here in conversation with the sophist Hippias
of Elis, who is satirized as superficial, unthinking and self-satisfied.
The description of his multi-talented achievements is peppered with
14
Summa Theologiae la. 2ae, 27,1 (76—7). The- definition is of the beautiful ipulchrum).
Motber&ul (323 ff.) argues that Aquinas' formulation encapsulates a truth which stands up
to philosophical scrutiny.
15
If it is by Plato: the dialogue's authenticity, though broadly accepted, remains a
subject for argument. See Waterfield's discussion in Saunders (ed.). 217-28, for a start
on the debate. Woodruff (1982a) provides an extensive case for authenticity; Kahn a
forthright argument against, but note his comment (269) that 'no serious philosophical
harm will be done to scholars and students who take the work for Platonic, so cleverly
has the author done his job'. I treat the Hippias Major as a work by Plato, written before
the Republic and the Symposium, making no other assumptions.
The Fine and the Beautiful 63
references to Ms being 'fine*, his doing things 'finely' (kalas), and so
on ('You're putting fine thoughts in fine words, Hippias*, says Socrates
at 282bl). Thus Ms inability to say what fineness is seems all the more
calamitous, though he shares with Ion (who also cuts a fine figure in
public) an unawareness of the direction the Socratic manoeuvres are
taking. Hippias and Ion each make a claim to 'speak finely' about a
compendious list of subject-matters, and both claims are coupled with
astounding ignorance. There is also an underlying continuity with
Gorgias, who is mentioned in Hippias Major as "the well-known soph-
ist' (282b4-5), and seems to have provided Hippias with the model for
Ms pompous rhetorical style.1* With Plato's Gorgias in mind, we can
see that Hippias* early claim to 'know most finely of men how to pass
virtue [aretel on to other people' (284a2-3) is an obvious target for
demolition,17
When aesthetic pleasure emerges at the end of the dialogue, it is only
after many different angles on fineness have been tried, Socrates makes
it crystal-clear to us (if not to Hippias) that he seeks an answer to the
question 'what the fine is itself*,18 and that this is to.be distinguished
from the question 'What is a fine thing?* What Socrates wants is that
which makes all fine things fine, understood in a constitutive rather than
a causal sense: What constitutes the fineness which all fine things have?"
The dialogue puts the same point by asking for 'that because of which
fine things are fine' or 'that by which fine things are fine*. The answers
Hippias first gives confirm the range of the terra kalos: *A fine girl is
a fine thing' (287e4); 'the fine is just gold' (289e3); and 'it is always
finest... to be rich, healthy, and honoured by the Greeks, to arrive at
old age, to make a fine memorial to his parents when they die, and to
have a fine, grand burial from his own children' (291d9-e2), The last
of these is clearly not an aesthetic fineness. The first is probably not,
if *a fine girl' is fine because she is desired (or is human, beauty always
aesthetic?), to the example of gold the claim that 'wherever that is
added, even if it was seen to be fool before, it will be seen to be fine
when it has been adorned with gold' (289e4-6) may more readily
16
See Woodruff (l9S2a), 116-17, 123-35.
" I make no assumptions about the chronological ordering of Gorg. and HiMa, Wood-
ruff regards the issue an 'too close to call* (19820, 102). Dodcfc argues that Gorg, 4?4ti—
475a is probably later than the parallel passage HiMa, 298a~~b (1959, 250),
18
auto to kaJon hoti eai, HiMa. 286d8-el.
" Woodruff refers to the fine as the 'logical cause' of fineness in things (see 1982a,
ISlfi), borrowing the term from Vlastos (1969), 9Iff, The fine is referred to as 'what
makes things fine* at 29M2, 294aL 2§4d6-7, 300a9-10, 302dl-2,
64 The Fine and the Beautiful
suggest that Hippias has an aesthetic value in mind—-though even here
nothing necessitates an. exclusively aesthetic reading.
The, example Socrates throws back at Mm is Pheidias' monumental
statue of Athena inside the Parthenon. If gold is truly that which, by
being 'added', makes all fine things fine, the peat Pheidias must-have
been ignorant of fineness, and hence a 'bad craftsman [d&niourgos]'.
Why? 'The point is ... that Pheidias didn't make Athena's eyes out of
gold, nor the rest of her face, nor her feet, nor her hands—as he would
have done if gold would really have made them be seen to be finest—-
but he made them out of ivory* (290b2-5). Hippias, unruffled, replies
that ivory is- fine too. But if it is gold and ivory that are fine and make
things fine, why did the sculptor construct the middles of Athena's eyes
out of stone? The truth is that properties which make something fine
can equally make something else foul. (The same properties could make
something else simply lack fineness —a distinct way of failing. An
Athena with golden eyes and ivory robes might have been an abomi-
nation, but it might simply have been a flop.) Any of the properties
mentioned makes things fine, then, only when it is appropriate. Another
example of the same kind is the stirring spoon for a bean soup: should
it be made of gold or of igwood? If the figwood spoon is finer, then
once again gold is not what makes all fine things fine. Hippias' surprise
at the demeaning turn the conversation suddenly takes here is a well-
worked piece of.comedy (290d7—el). But the- same transition, may have
its point for us too: splendid aesthetic fineness is not the exclusive topic
of discussion. Fine pots and spoons are fine things, even though among
fine, things they are not especiaDy fine, as Hippias recognizes in an
earlier remark,20
This discussion has come nowhere near defining auto to kalon, Hippias
has merely given examples of things which are fine, and has chosen
things each of which can in some way be seen to lack fineness: a fine
girl is not fine in comparison with a goddess, not an applications of
gold produce fine objects, and the supposedly fine life Hippias de-
scribes, .including burying one's parents, would not be fine for someone
like Achilles whose father was immortal,21 We shall not discover what
20
288e-6—9, A .girl and a horse are finer, than a fine pot. The only other fine thing in
the immediate context is a lyre. None of these need be taken as exhibiting a particularly
'aesthetic* fineness.
21
"The first fails because it is not fine in every comparison; the second because it is
not fine in every use, and the third because it is not fine in every instance* (Woodruff
(1982(1), 48).
The Fine and the Beautiful 65
the fine itself is until we can locate something strictly or completely
fine, something for which there is no comparison, use, instance—in
short, no way at all—in which it can be seen not to be fine.22 In pursuit
of this, Socrates and Hippias try out other evaluative notions: the ap-
propriate, the useful, and the beneficial—but each fails in turn to pro-
vide a definition of the fine itself, whereupon Socrates proclaims himself
'stuck*, in a state of aporia.
It is now that aesthetic ineaess seems to provide a way out: is the
fine after all 'what is pleasant through sight and hearing*?
If whatever makes us be glao, not with all the pleasures, but just those through
hearing and sight—if we call that fine, how do you suppose we'd do in the
contest?
Men [i.e. people: anthropoid when they're fine anyway—and everything deco-
rative, pictures and sculptures—these all delight us when we see them, if they're
fine. Fine sounds and music altogether, and speeches and storytelling have the
same effect. (297e5-298a5.)
Eating and smelling involve lowly pleasures which are just not admir-
able or interesting enough to be judged 'fine'. Things to do with ta aphro-
disia are refused the title because they are foul to be seen, confirming
again that a thing's having an admirable outward appearance will always
be relevant to whether it is kalos.
Not everything pleasant is fine. So, if it is not being pleasant per se
that provides the single definition of the fine, what is it? Here is the
difficulty, What is it that is common between, say, a painting the seeing
of which pleases us, and a melody the hearing of which pleases us? It
is not that both please through sight, nor that both please through hear-
ing (299e2-300a3). Nor is it true of each that it is pleasant through
sight and hearing. Yet what is true of both of two things, Socrates
insists, really must be true of each; if both the painting and the melody
The Fine and the Beautiful 67
please by being F, then the painting is F and the melody is F. On these
grounds the definition fails, Socrates seems to become more interested
in a tortuous piece of logical theorizing then in pursuing fineness, even
though something akin to Aquinas' definition beckons; the fine is what
pleases in the very apprehension of it—with some suitable qualification
on what counts as 'apprehension', if one can be found.
Stuck with 'pleasure through sight' and 'pleasure through hearing**
Socrates at least asks whether there is any overarching common feature,
and he answers that 'they are the most harmless pleasures and the best'
(303el-5). He then strangely interprets Ms own remark as saying that
'beneficial pleasure' is the fine (303e9), 'Beneficial pleasure* excludes
(contra Gorgias 474d) both the merely pleasing and the merely useful,
leaving only the category of things which are called fine because of
pleasure and benefit. It would rule out the fineness of 'purely aesthetic
pleasure'. However, this interesting final development is curtailed
because of the problems encountered earlier over defining the fine in
terms of the beneficial. The dialogue ends with Hippias re-asserting his
Gorgianic claim that one should stick to 'presenting a speech well and
finely, in court or council or any other authority* (304a7-bl) and walk
off with the rewards. Socrates counters with the traditional Socratic
worry, addressed first and foremost to himself: 'How will you know
whose speech—or any other action—is finely presented or not, when
you are ignorant of the fine? And when you're in a state like that, do
you think it's any better for you to live than die?' (3Q4dS-e3.)
Having acknowledged the existence of aesthetic pleasure, and having
located it substantially within the group of activities which we call 'the
arts', Socrates has at last confronted the question: What is it about just
these pleasures that is peculiarly fine? It is disappointing that he rejects
the only answer he thinks of—but Ms formulation of that answer itself
is perplexing. For it would 'be stretching things to- the point of incredu-
lity if we were expected to equate 'most harmless' (or 'least harmful*)
with 'most beneficial'. My examples of smelling a rose or playing
backgammon show this: they may well provide pleasures which are
among the most harmless, but it is still an. open question whether these
pleasures are among the most beneficial, or are beneficial at all. In the
Gorgias Plato presented the line that public performance of instrumen-
tal music, dithyrambs, and tragedy does the audience no good what-
ever, but merely serves to give them pleasure. Which is. the more
plausible defence against this line: that the pleasure provided by
68 The Fine and the Beautiful
the arts is fine because it is harmless, or that it-is fine because it is
beneficial?25
We have so far met no evidence that Plato considers aesthetic pleas-
ure—to ttie extent that he recognizes it—a harmful thing. Reflect, how-
ever, that a sweet-smelling plant can be poisonous. Its smell would not
be a bad thing, but its being poisonous and sweet-smelling would make
it all the more dangerous. This, I think, is how Plato comes to view
some, of the arts. Good poetry which pleases us when we hear it is eo
ipso a fine thing—no need to deny that. But until we have asked how
it stands with relation to knowledge, learning, and human excellence,
we have not said anything particularly important. In the same vein, it
is doubtful whether a Mend of the arts would wish to take a stand on
the 'pleasure through sight and hearing' which Plato acknowledges, for
it is a pretty flimsy affair. Is the value of attending a recital of Homer
or a Sophocles drama to be found in the pleasure of sight and hearing?
It is still unclear what the question means, but what is good about these
occasions—if anything is—cannot be just that they look and sound
pleasant How could we ignore the thoughts with which the poet en-
gages our imaginations and our emotions, seeming to teach us some-
thing about life and about ourselves? These are surely where a friend
of the arts would begin.26 Thus it becomes plausible that the kind of
'aesthetic pleasure* Plato recognizes is indeed only a small portion of
fineness, which in itself is insufficient to make the arts worthy of our
highest aspirations.
In the much later dialogue Philebus Plato comes close to a positive
notion of aesthetic pleasure, but very little that is 'artistic' appears to
be covered by it. The great distinction which divides the pleasures here
is that of the pure and the mixed. Mixed pleasures contain, or depend
on, soform ofrmpain or distress, while pure pleasures do not. The
pleasures to be taken in some kinds of beauty are * quite unlike those
of scratching*, for instance (Phil. 51dl). Pleasure in scratching depends
25
The claim in Rep. 10 (595b5-6) that mimetic poetry is ruinous to the intellect could
be countered by according it the fineness of harmless pleasure. But this would be playing
into Plato's hands, for by the end of Rep, 10 (607dS-9), he demands a defence of poetry
'as not only pleasant [hedeia}, but also beneictal [aphdime^ to cities and to human life*
(my translation).
26
"The traditional defence of poetry has been founded on the consideration that the
finest works of poetry can help u& to better OBT lives. They provide us with a particularly
important means of enriching our awareness of human experience, and they enable us to
give to our feelings greater precision, purity, strength and depth. Poetry is a means of
increasing our intelligence and strengthening our moral temper' (Budd (1983), 155).
The Fine and the Beautiful l 69
on the distress of the itch that is relieved. Bat some pleasures in colour,
shape, and sound are not at all of this nature:
By 'beauty of shape* I don't mean what most people would understand by it—
I am not thinking of animals or certain pictures, but, so the thesis goes, a
straight line or a circle and resultant planes and solids produced on a lathe or
with ruler and square.... On my view these things are not, as other things are,
beautiful (kala) in a relatiYe way, but are always beautiful in themselves, and
yield their own special pleasures quite unlike those of scratching. I include
colours, too, that have the same characteristic.... With sounds, it is the smooth
clear ones I am thinking of, ones that produce a single pure tune (melos), and
are beautiful not just in a certain context but in themselves—these and their
attendant pleasures. (5Icl-d9.)
29
Schopenhauer, i, 208.
30
The alternate explanation is that Plato is criticizing mimesis as an 'inferior redu-
plication' of 'commonplace reality' (Hackforth (1958), 99), But that gives no ctoe as to
why the non-representational, non-artistic beauty of living things should also be excluded
from the 'pure* category,
31
Cf. the explanation by Gosling (1975), 122.
The Fine and the Beautiful 71
we feel distress and pleasure, "The audience at a tragedy actually enjoy
their tears' (48a5-6). Plato continues to assume that distress in the
audience is genuine. Given that premiss, no one would enjoy tragedy
in the same way if the events were depicted so as to avoid distress! The
whole point of a tragedy—and of why we enjoy it—would be lost. Our
liking for portrayals of the painful is puzzling.32 Plato offers a hint of
a general explanation when he says that many emotions which are
forms of distress—anger, fear, yearning, sorrow, love, envy, malice—
turn out to be 'imbued with an unexpected degree of enjoyment* (47e5).
If sorrow and fear in real life can be tinged with pleasure, perhaps
pleasure in a depiction of the fearful and sorrowful is only what psy-
chology would predict, after all. But there is clearly no likelihood of
tragedy's proving an object of 'pure' pleasure in the sense which Plato
goes on to delineate. Pleasure in comedy, too, depends on our having
certain emotions. Plato argues that we must feel malice towards a char-
acter whom we laugh at as an object of ridicule, and (less convincingly)
that malice is in itself a distressing emotion. Therefore, our pleasare in
laughing at a comedy is also mixed with distress (48aS—50a9). Indeed,
wherever emotions are involved, pure pleasure is not to be found, 'In
dirges, tragedies, and comedies, not only on the stage, but in the whole
tragi-comedy of life, distress and pleasure are blended with each an-
other* (50bl—4). We might observe that this idea of a 'pure* pleasure
embodies something of a flight from life itself.
Well, as Socrates might say, all that is fine ... but aren't we forget-
ting something else that someone once said about to katonl At the
climax of his literary masterpiece, me Symposium, Plato has Socrates
relate the wise words which Diotima, a woman of Mantinea, suppos-
edly addressed to biro, revealing an absolute beauty as the supreme
object of love. The whole dialogue is devoted to. love, evoking and
portraying it as well as attempting to define it. What is loved is what
is kolos, and in this context, as I have conceded, we can scarcely help
thinking of beauty. Because love is the topic, we meet no soup-ladles,
pots, or sandals, however fine, Perhaps more surprising is that in
Diotima's account of the lover's ascent to beauty itself, the fine objects
of love encountered, on the way include no paintings, sculptures, music,
story-telling—nothing artistic. Despite Plato's poetic writing in this
work, and the inclusion in the cast-list of a comic and -a tragic poet—
Aristophanes and Agathon, each of whom speaks with eloquence—we
32
The discussion of this familiar point by Sehier (1989) is stimulatiag.
72 The Fine and the Beautiful
learn little concerning the arts from the explicit content of the Sympo-
sium. Rhetoric is given full rein but then put in its place: when Socrates
is called upon to take his turn at speaking about love, he first subjects
the previous speaker, Agathon, to a cross-examination. It is agreed that
Agathon spoke finely, in a spectacular rhetorical style which reminded
Socrates of Gorgias,33' But Socrates draws a sharp contrast between two
activities, namely speakiag finely (katos) and speaking the truth (the
former possible on Gorgias* theory, the latter not). He purportedly re-
futes one of Agathon's statements—so what Agathon said was not the
truth, and he did not know what he was talking about—-'still, you did
speak finely, Agathon' (201 cl). Fineness masks falsity: rhetoric is, once
again, a mere image 'in words,
Once launched into his retelling of Diotima's teachings, Socrates
brings forward the new definition of love as 'desire for the perpetual
possession of the good* (206all—12). The argument requires the re-
placement of 'beautiful' by 'good*, which is simply achieved by
Diotima's saying we may 'change terms and substitute agathos for
fetes* (204el—3). This makes the class of things that are agathos and
the class of things that are katos coincident, the terms being *inter-
changeable ... but not synonymous'.34 Being fine is one tiling, being
good another, but still all and only good things are fine things. So if a
poem or a painting is fine (perhaps by being pleasing to see or hear),
then it cannot help being in the class of good things. But we should not
assume that this settles very much about the value of the arts. Agathon's
speech was fine.-It was beautiful. But for whom and in what way would
Plato regard it as good? It appealed to (persuaded? deceived?) the
gathering, but was based on a falsehood. Agathon's or anyone's trag-
edies, similarly, according to the Gorgias, may be as fine as they like,
but in fact benefit no one in the respects that matter to Plato. Both
3J
Symp. 198cl-5. Dover (1980, 123-4) explains some features of Plato's extended
parody of Gorgias, and shows by metrical analysis bow 'Plato has taken considerable
trouble to gi¥e Agathon's peroration [197dl—e5] a poetic character in addition to cari-
caturing its. "Gorgianic" structure',
M
Price, 16, following Dover (1980), 136: 'Anything which is kalon, I.e. which looks
or sounds good (or is good to contemplate), is also agatkon, i.e. it serves a desirable
purpose or performs a desirable function, and vice versa.' 'Contemplation* has to be
taken pretty widely to make this explanation stick, and we also have to be careful about
desirable functions and purposes. Someone's life could be fine and good without bating
particularly interesting, and without subserving any function or purpose outside itself,
Price's more cautious gloss brings out both points: 'The kalon is what presents itself
appcalingly (though not only to tie senses); the agaliutn is good for someone In some
way (though not only in&truBientally).*
The Fine and the Beautiful l 73
35
before and after the Symposium Plato thinks that what presents itself
appeattngly may,fail to be good in important ways and may even be
harmful to those whom it charms,
Have we-in Diotima's speech at last, struck an account which will
place artistic products firmly among the good things towards which
human beings should aspire? Diotima assigns a role to poets and poetry
when she talks of the offspring of the sonl rather than the body. The
motivation of all eras is procreative, it desires to generate something
new. This is. woven in with the notion that all humans desire immor-
tality, and the original strand which says that love is love of the beau-
tiful. ('From fairest creatures we desire increase,! That thereby beauty's
Rose might never die.*) The aim of love is 'to procreate and bring forth
in beauty*. Thus the happiness we seek in possessing beauty is the kind
of immortality we think may be provided by producing offspring—'the
nearest thing to perpetuity and immortality that a mortal being can
attain'. It is only 'in* beauty that we wish to procreate.36 While physical
intercourse and procreation provide the context for the ordinary under-
standing of ems, Diotima's account uses the physical as a metaphor for
something more general. The same impulse to generate can show itself
in spiritual form, and is in Plato's eyes clearly superior when it does so.
Without having to have "recourse to women* one can seek out a beau-
tiful companion with a beautiful soul and with him generate "children
of the soul* which really can last forever. What is the offspring of the
soul?
It is wisdom and virtue [arete} in general; of this poets and such craftsmen
[demiourgoi] as have found out some new thing may be said to be begetters;
but far the greatest and fairest branch of wisdom is that which is concerned
with the due ordering of states and families, whose name is moderation and
justice. (209a3-8.)
Poets rank only with inventive producers in general, and can claim to
do nothing so ine as lawgivers—that said, Diotima is prepared to give
35
Tragic poetry is again called katos bat harmful overall in Rep. 10 (595b3—c2, where
the context—conceding admiration to Homer-—makes kales (cl) unlikely to be merely
ironic).
36
206e5—8. The imagery is thoroughly sexual, based on a particular assumption about
why males desire sexual intercourse with beautiful females, and also on the common
ancient assumption that it is the male who 'generates*, with the- female serving as the
place or receptacle where generation occurs. Plato also offers no argument for the ideas
that heterosexual intercourse is essentially motivated by reproductive ends, or that repro-
duction manifests the desire for immortality.
74 The Fine and the Beautiful
poets credit as begetters of wisdom and virtue (or excellence). Homer
and Hesiod feature prominently, alongside the lawgivers of Sparta and
Athens, Lycurgus and Solon, in a resounding defence of the superiority
of non-physical generation, whose children
surpass human children by being immortal as well as more beautiful. Everyone
would prefer children such as these to children after the flesh. Take Homer, for
example, and Hesiod, and the other good poets; who would not envy them the
children that they left behind them, children whose qualities have won immor-
tal fame and glory for (heir parents? ... and so it is in many other places with
other men , . , who by their many fine actions have brought forth good fruit of
all kinds; not a few of them have even won men's worship on account of their
spiritual children, a thing which has never yet happened to anyone by reason
of Ms human progeny. (209c6—e4.)
J7
Dover (1980, 151-2) speculates that 'it can only be the virtuous character of the
[society] for which Homer sang", which seems somewhat lame. Plato's text give* no hint
of an answer. Price (27) brings out the unsatisfactory nature of this passage.
The Fine and the Beautiful 75
persuade Ms poetic co-symposiasts of some point about tragedy, com-
edy, and techne. ('They were giving way to his arguments, which they
didn't follow very well, and nodding. Aristophanes fell asleep first, and
when it was tally light Agathoo followed him' (223d6-8).) Here is
what was going on in the small hours:
The main point was that Socrates was compelling them to admit that the man
who knew how to write a comedy could also write a tragedy, and that someone
who by techne was a tragic writer was capable of being also a comic writer.
(223d2-6.)
40
Dodds (1959), 250.
41
Bearefsley, 41. Lucas (260) also sees Plato taking *a step along the path* to exalta-
tion of the artist.
The Fine and the Beautiful 77
will see it as absolute, existing alone with itself, unique, eternal, and all other
beautiful things as partaking of it, yet in. such a manner that, while they come
into being and pass away, it neither undergoes any increase or diminution nor
suffers any change, (210e2-2llb5.)
The lover attains to the Form, auto to kalon: the beautiful, or the fine,
itself, which is set in contrast with the multiplicity of mere beautiful
things. They participate in it, and, as we learn elsewhere, it is this
relation of participation in the. Form of the beautiful that makes any-
thing beautiful,42 Socrates tried to cajole Hippias into seeking that o0e
single characteristic, the presence of which constituted something's being
kalos. Plato now tells us how fineness itself must be conceived. It is
single, eternal and unchanging, dependent on nothing for its existence,
and distinct from any particular thing (or class of things) that is kalos,
This passage has commonly been read as saying that the beautiful itself
simply and strictly is beautiful, in the sense that it itself is a beautiful
thing.43 Plato lists many ways in which an ordinary beautiful thing
could also be the opposite of beautiful, in order to show that, in con-
trast, the beautiful itself suffers none of these admixtures of the ugly or
the foul; this invites the interpretation that the Form itself is kalos.
Furthermore, unless the Form is itself beautiful or fine, Plato's extrava-
gant claims for its effect on the lover's life make no sense. The Form,
once known, must strike the human mind in such an overwhelming way
that it diminishes all other objects of love. It must be completely-and
overwhelmingly beautiful. Then we can explain why Plato eaa speak
with such moment of 'the region where, if anywhere ... a human life
is liveable, contemplating absolute beauty*.44 To fulfil this exalted role,
the beautiful itself (arguably) has to be measured on the same scale as
familiar beautiful things, and be superior to them in value on that scale.
42
43
Phda. I00b3-e3.
The classic statement of this interpretation is in Vlastos (1965). In a recent challenge
to it, Peiiner has argued that 'the aim ia the upward path is not to ascend from less tolly
beautiful to most fully beautiful objects. Rather it's to ascend from interior (nominalist}
candidates for being what beauty is to the best of all candidates' (1987, 139). Penner
argues (see 127ff.) (i) that Plato is not committed to the claim that the Form is itself a.
beautiful thing by his talk of 'the beautiful itself, (si) that he is not so committed by the
contrasts between the Form and other things which ate and are not beautiful, (lii) thai he
is not so committed by the talk of the beautiful itself as a supreme object of erds. One
might agree with (i) and (ti) while finding (iii) unconvincing. Price (43 n. 49) writes; 'if
[Beauty itself} is to gratify the lover in a manner analogous to beautiful sights ... it must
itself, supremely, be beautiful to contemplate. Nowhere else does "self-predication" (or
better,
44
self-participation) have such clear point.'
Symp. 21W1-3: my translation, influenced partly by Nn&sbaum (1986), 467 n. 34.
78 The Fine and the Beautiful
The beauty of former treasures such as boys, clothing, and. gold
becomes, from this vantage point, something to disdain. It is 'beauty
tainted by human flesh and colour and a mass of perishable [mortal]
rubbish'—while the eternal, untainted fineness itself is 'divine*, and the
lover who has intercourse with it will be the most nearly immortal of
humans (21 Ie2-212a7), Plato has not given up Ms sexual imagery, and
he does not forget to mention the offspring generated by the lover who
lays hold of the Form: *he will beget not images of excellence [eidota
aretes}, in that he will not grasp an image, but true excellence, in that
he grasps the truth* (212a3-5). To be capable of bringing genuine
excellence into the world is to know and love the eternal, divine, logi-
cal cause of things' being fine, and nothing short of that. Could the
supreme lover of auto to kalon be a poet? Poets were earlier said to be
among the 'begetters of wisdom and excellence*. But a Homer, in order
to have engendered true excellence, must have grasped the eternal. Form
of the beautiful, not a mere image of if. Could a Homer do that? Per-
haps Diotima's teachings are mysteries too mysterious to contain, a
definite answer. On the other hand, in a more sober passage in the
Republic Plato chooses the sames words to give a resounding No: all
poets, starting with Homer, make only images of excellence; they never
rise to, or know, the real thing, they never grasp the truth.45
It is only when the lover is at the earliest level of loving the beauty
of bodies that poetry is seriously in consideration. The 'beautiful dis-
course' generated at this early stage possibly includes poetry,* though
Plato does not say so explicitly. Perhaps it would have been misleading
to say so. Since tragedy, comedy, and epic are not likely to spring from
such a context, the poetry engendered by the love of a beautiful body
is hardly representative of what Plato usually discusses under that head-
ing. More importantly, such discourse is only a beginning. At higher
levels non-poetic discourse takes over: a moral discourse 'that improves
the youths', and then 'much fine and noble discourse and thoughts
contained in abundant philosophy'. In Diotima's finalvision poets quietly-
slip out of view. Beautiful poems last a long time, but could never be
an exchange for beauty itself.
Surely, however, the aesthetic is lauded as a- self-standing value in
this whole passage? And, since the aesthetic will have something to do
with the arts, surely Plato cannot be seen as excluding them from the
45
Rep, 600e4—6- The same phrase, eidola aretes—"images of excellence'—is used
here and at Symp, 212a,4, Ton alethous ephaptomenoi at 212a5 is also echoed by let de
aletheias ouch haptesthai. in the Sep. passage.
* For this vwj¥ of 210a7-8, see Moravcsik (1971), 292-3, and Price, 41, 47.
The Fine and the Beautiful l 79
highest human life? Care is respired. It is unclear how much of Diotima's
teachings are really concerned' with an aesthetic fineness, or even an,
aesthetic beauty. At the first stage, again, where the lover loves the
beauty of bodies, Plato talks of to ep' eidei kalon, the fine in appear-
ance or outward form. Do we then have, as has been suggested, 'love
of bodies for the sake of bodily beauty that can be abstracted and
contemplated on a general level*, followed by a 'move from mere sexual
interest to some sort of aspiration, presumably aesthetic*?47 A sharp
distinction cannot always be made between 'erotic* and 'aesthetic* con-
templation of human beauty, and it would be wrong to try to force such
a distinction upon Diotima. However, it is fairly clear that for her the
contemplation of-human bodies is never purely aesthetic. The lover is
not one to whom pleasure occurs merely in the looking (unlike the
'onlookers* of Gorg. 474d8-9), and Ms aspiration, whatever it ends up
generating, is always erotic. And is there a move in the direction of the
aesthetic? Higher up the ladder towards the ideal we find the contem-
plation of laws, sciences, and excellences, and it is not clear that we
should describe these as the objects of an aesthetic aspiration.
Although Plato is talking about value, about fineness, and about beauty,
there is little indication that artistic practices or an exclusively aesthetic
form of value have any special place in the Symposium's, vision of the
best of lives. And yet one reason remains why it is strange to say this.
For Symposium 210a—212a is among the most elevated and beautiful
stretches of writing ever composed. To be moved by it to any degree
is to allow ourselves the thought -of a standpoint from which the fair
products of the arts count for little and the complexion of all human
institutions is dimmed by contrast with the Forms. But what has been
capable of making the aspiration to this 'higher' region live in our
minds is the offspring of Plato the literary artist, who has brought us to
this point scarcely by argument—rather by extended, subtly modulated
rhetoric, layers of fictional narrators, and beguiling persuasion,481 have
argued so far that Plato is not blind to the beauty which poetry has to
offer, but that he does not place any very great value upon it. His own
poetic achievements, I shall eventually suggest, do not conflict with his
opposition to the poetry which he actively rejects. But it is to the
Republic that we must first tarn, to see what the reasons for that rejec-
tion are. -
41
Mtaavcsik (1971), 291, For criticism, see Price, 37-8.
48
Socrates tries to persuade others of what Diotima said to him, having been
persuaded himself (212bl—3). At one point she convinces him "like a perfect sophist*
(208b7-ci). See Nussbaum (1986), 176-7.
4
1 2
Jaeger, 214. Ct HaUiweU (1991), 335, for this verdict
The Formation af Character 81
they now be released for general viewing? Most of the films were poor
as films, but one in particular (entitled Jud Suss, and 'highly recom-
mended* by Goebbels) was thought probably worthy of suppression
because of its artistic superiority. This judgement parallels the many
which Plato makes about Homer and bis colleagues. It is essential to
see past our likely disagreement with Plato about what is morally
dubious: we understand in principle an argument that the 'artistic' can
be more worthy of suppression than the crude and inept.3
Having mentioned film, let us note another point which a number of
commentators have made. Plato's censorship of poetry is an attempt to
influence a medium of mass communication, in which, as he sees it,
ethical judgement about what is portrayed has been subordinated to the
end of gratifying the audience. He engages with poetry in the way
recent critics have engaged with television, cinema, and video: 'the
endless proliferation of senseless images', 'ubiquitous and intrusive
purveyors of bad taste, deformed paradigms, and questionable values",
from which children and others nevertheless learn.4 If we think that
such products of our culture should be answerable to obligations of a
moral or political nature, especially when children are at the forefront
of the debate, as they are for Plato, then we should not find Plato's
approach alien.
The Republic begins with scrutiny of the question 'What is justice?*
In a way that is • sometimes overlooked.,5 poetry and myth enter the
discussion near the start of Book 2. Socrates proposes that justice is
something good in itself, irrespective of consequences (though he thinks
it also has beneficial consequences), and that it is better than being
unjust. But Plato is at pains to emphasize how popular thinking is at
odds with the Socratic line, and he has Glaucon and Adeimantus present
a rhetorical defence of the view that people should be just only to the
extent that it brings, greater reward and reputation—being just is as such
a mere chore, and if one could escape detection and punishment, the
unjust life would be much better. In support of this line, Glaucon uses
the traditional tale of Gyges, whose ring made him invisible and so able
to commit injustice on a grand scale. Adeimantus cites Hesiod and
3
Latfy Chatterley's Lover was defended on the grounds that it had literary merit, and
that it was not liable to corrupt. The first defence, would cut no ice with Plato if the
second failed,•
4
Quotes from Murdoch, 65; Nehamas (1982), 51. In more recent articles {1988),
(1991), Nehamas makes an extended parallel between Pbto aad recent critics of television.'
5
Exceptions are Gadamer, 51; Ferrari (1989), tit; Else (1986), 17-18.
82 The Formation of Character
Homer who present lines of thought congenial to the anti-Socratic view
of justice, such as
you can choose to have evil, and heaps of if, too,
for its house lies near and the path to it is smooth.
But the immortab decreed that man must sweat
to attain virtue; the road to it is steep and long
and rough at first,*
* Discussion of the arts in Books 2, 3, and 10 together takes up roughly one seventh
of Plato's space.
86 The Formation of Character
gods and heroes. No one is to show gods committing crimes, as do
Cronos and Zeus against their fathers in the traditional myths. Other
prohibited themes are battles and quarrels between gods, gods trans-
forming themselves into other shapes, deceiving or lying, the terrors for
human heroes of death and the underworld, lamentation over some-
one's death by a god or a hero, indulgence in violent laughter, undis-
ciplined abuse, gluttony, over-powering sexual desire, greed for money
and possessions, resentment or disobedience towards a god, atrocities
of war. Heroes must be shown as better than ordinary human beings,
and gods must never be shown to be anything but perfect, unchanging,
and the cause of good. Many of the most powerful scenes in Homer
will be proscribed. Plato shrinks from having to say so "out of respect
for Homer* (391a3), but nevertheless spells out the kind of lines which
he will have cut by law from the Iliad and Odyssey. Tragedy too will
be curtailed: god-induced sufferings (such as those of Niobe or the
house of Pelops) contravene the principle that the diviae is cause only
of good, unless it can be shown that the sufferings are deserved as a
punishment which after all 'benefits' its recipient (380a5—b6).n-
We should not lightly assume that all censorship is bad; furthermore,
many different reasons may be urged for it. Plato is concerned initially
with the education of the young, and works under the assumption that
when anything is young and tender 'it takes shape, and any mould one
may want can be impressed upon it' (377bl—3). He thinks that beliefs
may be 'taken into the soul' (377b7-8) at this impressionable stage (as
we still say). So it matters, right from the nursery on, what stories
(nuithot) are told to the young guardians. All tellers of stories, including
nurses and mothers, play an important role in 'fashioning their souls'.
It is in this context that we must consider the worst of the crimes of the
mythical gods, such as Cronos' treatment of his father Ouranos, in
Hesiod's Theogony. Plato is too sensitive to name the crime or quote
the passage, which (as his audience would know) contains these lines;
Great Ouranos came, bringing on night, and upon Gaia
he lay, wanting love and fully extended;
his son, from ambush, reached out with Ms left hand
and with his right hand took the huge sickle,
long with jagged teeth, and quickly severed
" The banned 'sufferings* here are paths. Gould links this term with a traditional
(especially tragic) conception of undeserved catastrophes caused by the gods (see Gould,
pp. xvii—xviii, 21, and passim).
The Formation of Character 87
his own father's genitals, and threw them to fall
behind."
Later in the story Cronos swallows Ms own children, except Zeus who
defeats him by force. Plato says: 'I do not think this should be told to
foolish and young people ... If there were some necessity to tell it,
only a very few people should hear it, and in secret.*19 Many will surely
sympathize (however significant they may find the poet's imagery).
Plato sees a continuity, however, not only between childhood story-
tellers and all poets who 'put together fictitious stories* (377d4-6), but
also in the audience, for he is prepared to regulate consumption of
poetry by the middle-aged and the old as well.20 This makes for an
obvious difficulty in Ms argument. From the point of view of the child's
acquisition of beliefs, it is plausible to say that the distinction between
a nursery tale and an epic poem is immaterial. (At one point, Plato
considers the objection that the stories of the gods in Homer are
allegorical, but he remarks that the young cannot distinguish what is
allegorical from what is not, and may still acquire deep-seated beliefs
from a literal interpretation of a story (378d6—el}.} But if the argument
for censorship turns on the malleability and lack of sophistication of the
young, we should expect there to be, at least in principle, some point
at which a person's character and beliefs become fixed enough not to
require such care. The idea that no one in a community should witness
what a child should not witness does not immediately recommend it-
self.21 If Plato gives no reason for extending his prohibition to mature
adults, that is a serious weakness in Ms case. Plato has an answer to this
challenge, but it comes later in the Republic after he has argued for the
division of the soul and (in Book 10) explained how there is in all
of us a childish 'part' which is engaged by dramatic representation.
Although we may calmly recognize dramatic action as fictional and
'* Hesiod, Theogony, 176-82, trans. Caldwell.
'* Rep. 378a2-S. to the Euthyphro w« meet a character who prosecutes his own father
for murder, citing as a justification the behaviour of Ecus and Cronos in punishing their
fathers {Euth. 5eS—6a5). This shows us the kind of impression Plato is worried about
making on young souls, (See Adam, t, 112.)
20
Rep. 37§cS~d2, Cf. 387M-5: 'the .less they should be heard by children and by men
. ..' (also 380ci). HalliweU (1991) suggests that the intention throughout is to describe
*a kind of mode! of sn aesthetic environment*. *a complete culture', not limited by a
purely educational context (329-30). S«e Irwia (I977a), 330-1, for a list of passages in
which Plato seems to direct education more widely to everyone in the city—-though, by
twin's own lights, the guardians are singled out in eighteen passages,
21
Annas comments: 'This is ... paternalism, treating adults as though they were
children' (1981, 85).
88 The Formation of Character
explain its significance as allegorical, this is not the whole story, A
'lower' part of everyone's soul craves emotional expression and likes
to indulge its craving in a welter of powerful images without the inter-
vention of thoughts about the worthiness or rationality of doing so. If
we acknowledge such a 'child within' we shall be less likely to find
Plato's extension of censorship to adults lacking in support.22
The guardians are required by the Principle of Specialization to fulfil
one and only one role in the city. If their moral character is faulty, then
the whole city will be endangered. So, if this moral .character is moulded
by beliefs acquired in early education, and if such beliefs can be ac-
quired from fiction, Plato has good reason to hold that the young guard-
ians should not be exposed to everything that fiction is able to offer.
The guardians must be brave, self-controlled, disciplined, not prone to
deception, crime, or sacrilege. Beliefs acquired early about modes of
behaviour among the superhuman gods and heroes could interfere with
their attaining these qualities. More specifically, they must 'fear slavery
more than death* (38?b4-6) if they are to be free, and must believe
'that no citizen has ever hated another and that this is impious" (378c7-
8). Hence the ban. on depicting misery and terror in the afterlife or
conflict among the gods. Plato's attack on the traditional Olympian
theology is noteworthy. He seeks to replace it with a view of 'the god*
or "the gods* as unchanging, in no way deficient in fineness or virtue,
and as the cause only of good (379a-381e). Only conceived thus will
the divine, as an absolute standard, be worthy of belief. If title guardians
are going to have anything like a religion, it had better be one which
sets before them an appropriate moral paradigm?3
1 have used the term 'fiction'. Plato classifies the myths and epic
scenes .he discusses as pseudeis logoi, or fake discourses. The precise
role which this conception plays in the argument is not always easy to
discern. Plato says that the young guardians should be educated first in
the pseudeis logoi, and later in the species of discourse which is true
(376ell-377a2), So 'falsehood' must be merely a way of classifying
discourses, not in itself a reason for objecting to them,24 otherwise all
2
Ferrari (1989, 114) is excellent here. The Book 10 argument is dealt with in ch. 6
below.
23
Commentators often locate Plato in a tradition of philosophical criticism of early
poetic theology goiag back to Xenophanes (Diels-Kranz, 21 Al, Bll, B12). Later poets
such as Pindar and the tragedians shared these criticisms of Homer. (Gadaroer, 43—4;
Jaeger, 213-14; Ferrari (1989), 110.)
24
Outline (1975, 457) agrees that this is a 'neutral' use of pseudos, and suggests that
'fiction*, 'fictitious*, and 'invented' convey the sense.
The Formation of Character 89
such stories would be banned without the long exercise in selecting
specific themes and passages. Plato does not, however, think of stories
as 'fiction' in any sense which would assign them an autonomous value.25
It soon becomes clear that within the class of stories defined by their
being false some approximate more to truth, and this is the issue that
most concerns Plato. His statement of the point occurs at 377d7—s3:
Which stories do you mean .., and why do you object to them?
— Because of what one should object to first and most, especially if the fictitious
is not well told.
— As for instance?
— Whenever any story gives a bad likeness of the nature of the gods and
heroes, like a painter drawing a bad picture, ualike what he is wanting to
portray.
Whether a likeness has been made badly (kakos) or finely (kalos) is thus
a discriminating factor within the class of pseudeis logoi, or what I
shall call fictions. A discourse which is literally false, in being a fiction,
can nevertheless be a more or less accurate portrayal of something. If
a fiction does not make a good likeness it is a falsification: 'the greatest
pseudos about the most important matters was that of the man who told
a pseudos badly (OK kalos epseusato) when he said that Owanos did
what Hesiod tells us he did.*26 What Plato means here is that a fiction
was not finely told, in that it was a falsification, a bad likeness of the
truth.
Obviously there is a distinction between the question whether a poetic
discourse is fitting or beneficial and the question whether it is true.27
Plato sometimes makes use of the distinction—for example, the tales of
Cronos and Ouranos should not be told to the young, even if they were
true, he says.28 On the other hand later, when discussing falsehoods
which can be useful or beneficial, he says: 'because of our ignorance
of what truly happened of old, we then make the fiction [pseudos] as
like the truth as we cm, and so make it useful' (382dl-3). Here moral
benefit seems to depend on correctness of representation. So bow do
25
On this see Penan (1989), 113.
36
Cf. Halliweli (1992). 58, for a similar explanation of pseudos here.
2!
'A distinction is drawn between mere lies and the lie which is in itself am baton,
unbeautifut and immoral in tendency, e.g. tie story of Uranus and Cronos • . - Such
legends not merely misrepresent the gods, but also corrupt mankind' (Adam, i. 112).
m
Rep. 378al-3. The issues of veracity and moral effect are separated at 381e4-6
(stories slander the gods and at the same time make children more cowardly) and 386btO-
cl (stories are neither true nor beneficial).
90 The Formation of Character
faithful representation and moral appropriateness relate to one another?
The issue is one of substance, for if we understand misrepresentation
and impressing a bad character on the young as two distinct faults, then
we must face Plato with the possibility of a fiction's failing on one
count while succeeding on the other. Would Plato be content with any
fiction—misrepresentation or not—provided it had a beneficial effect
on the character of Ms young guardians? Would he ban the most
accurate fictional representation if it was morally corrupting? Or, for
the sake of the truth, would he allow the guardians to hear1 things that
would jeopardize their character? The dilemma does not become expli-
cit for Plato because he is confident that the most accurate representa-
tion of the gods and heroes will also be the one that is conducive to
moulding souls of the right kind. But consider, for example, the rival
tragic view that the supernatural plays the leading role in ensuring
human suffering: if this could somehow be shown to be nearer the
truth, where would it leave Plato? If the tragic view were less condu-
cive to the production of courageous and obedient citizens, Plato roust
either modify his picture of the character-traits required by his guard-
ians, or accept that a fiction which misrepresents these fundamental
matters m after all a beneficial educational instrument.
If there are no strictly true stories about the divine and the supposed
distant past, what standard of correctness of representation can there
be? Aristotle remarks that poetry tends to express the universal—'how
a person of a certain type will on occasion speak or act, according to
probability or necessity*,29 and for Plato too this is what is required.
The heroes ought to function as true paradigms of human behaviour,
and the gods as a universal supernatural expression of general, truths
about the world and the place of human beings within it Plato thinks
that poets are trying to represent these basic features of humanity, and
that one way they can be criticized, like a painter who tries to paint a
particular subject, is for failure to produce a good likeness. (Internal
plausibility of the story might be another standard of correctness—but
is it more or less plausible in the story that Achilles behaves insultingly
towards his dead opponent rather than honourably, or that he weeps out
of all measure at the death of Ms beloved comrade, rather than bearing
Ms loss moderately?)
A similar interpretation has recently been put forward by Julius
Moravcsik: 'if a poet represents humans or gods, he will have to have
38
Moravcsik (1986), 40-1. See also HaUiwelTs discussion of the paradigmatic force
of mimetic works (1992, 56ff.).
31
Moravcsik (1986), 43.
32
Though implicitly he allows something like this later in discussing "gracefulness*
(4O3e-4G3c).
33
Nussbauin (1986), 157-8.
92 The Formation of Character
Although Plato seems confident that his 'good man* will not mourn in
the circumstances he describes, the passage asserts only a comparative
self-sufficiency, not the absolute 'perfection* Nussbaum discerns.34
Nevertheless, there is a problem: given that we are human, with all our
vulnerabilities, how can a higher standpoint—even one of comparative
self-sufficiency—illuminate what is of value for us? Plato's reply would
surely be thai, as a model to aspire towards in early education, the self-
sufficient, non-lamenting agent is preferable. But the integrity of this
reply depends on his having located the correct moral paradigm. We
may wish to argue for a rival paradigm such as the tragic view of
humanity, or we may wish to argue that there is no single true account
of the Meal human agent. If either line were successful, Plato's position
would be seriously compromised: he is certain that only his choice of
subject-matter will produce expert guardians, but if the truth about
humanity is different, a very different curriculum would be demanded.
And if the model city can achieve its caste of specialized, morally pure
guardians only by feeding them a tailor-made falsification of human
nature, then the model is bankrupt
In Book 3 of the Republic we are not yet in a position to establish
what is and what is not a falsification of human nature. At 392a
Socrates leaves behind the realms of gods, heroes, spirits, and things in
the underworld, and proposes to move on to tales about human beings.35
The suspicion is that the poets and other writers go wrong in saying that
injustice can bring happiness, that justice is a burden, and so on—but
clearly this brings us back to the point at issue in the Republic as a
whole. We started with a collection of such sayings from the poets, and
were promised an account of justice in the individual by analogy with
the model city. We have not completed that account, so the discussion
is here postponed: 'we shall agree what tales must be told about
humans when we have discovered the nature of justice, that it is by
nature beneficial to its possessor* (392cl-3). Plato is right: if poetry is
answerable to moral philosophy, then we need to have done our moral
philosophy properly first.
Plato's discussion now moves on to matters other than poetry's sub-
ject-matter. But let us pause to take stock. There are many points where
we may disagree with Plato about politics, education, or moral psychol-
ogy. To what extent should a state have responsibility for educating its
M
See Irwin (1988), 376 n. 1.
35
Adam's view is that these are the 'tree logo? that were distinguished from the false
at 376e (see Adam, j, 110; Belfiore (1985), 49).
The Formation of Character 93
citizens? Plato assigns the state total responsibility, but clearly argu-
ments might be advanced in favour of no control by the state, or only
some. To what extent should poetry and story-felling play a role in
education? It is less likely that we shall disagree with Plato here. Like
him we neither countenance an education wholly taken up with poetry
and myth, nor one from which they are wholly absent. Is there a single
correct account of human nature? If so, is Plato's version of it correct?
Here, as I have said, we may reserve the right to disagree. But what has
Plato said about poetry to which we may object? Perhaps it is what he
has not said that will strike the reader. He has not said that the young
should be exposed to 'good poetry*. Nor has he said that hearing all
these tales of the gods and heroes brings us a pleasure or fulfilment of
its own, and is therefore a valuable activity to include in the life of the
young. Rather, he says this:
We shall ask Homer and the other poets not to be angiy if we delete these and
all similar passages [concealing the pitiful souls of the dead]: not because- they
are not poetic [poietikos] and pleasing to the majority of hearers, but the more
poetic they are the less they should be heard by children and by men who must
be free and fear slavery more than death. (387M-6.)
Plato claims that people acquire from poetry beliefs, desires, and emo-
tions which can have a significant effect on the development of their
ethical, character. He thinks that the greater the poetry's pleasure-giving
potential, the more pronounced the effect on one's character is likely to
be. He assumes that poetry is answerable to the question whether what
it portrays gives a true likeness of human life, and that this question
may take precedence over the question whether it gives pleasure. These
four claims offend against the view that art's value in education is its
giving pleasure, irrespective of its relation to life'—but that is merely
a form of the questionable view I have called aestheticisnn. Artists and
critics have frequently sided with Plato. For Ms Murdoch, 'Bad art is
a lie about the world*,3* For Ruskin, good novels well.read (as they
rarely are, he thinks) are ''nothing less than treatises on moral anatomy
and chemistry; studies of human nature in the elements of it'.37 And
Ezra Pound, who also compares artist to scientist, manages to sound
more severe than Plato himself:
If an artist falsifies his report as to the nature of man, as to his own nature, as
to the nature of Ms ideal of the perfect... of god, if god exist, of the life force,
34
Murdoch, 83. " Rnskin, 65-6.
94 The Formation of Character
of the nature or good and evil, if good and evil exist . . . If he lies out of
deliberate will to lie, if he lies out of carelessness, out of laziness, oat of
cowardice, out of any sort of negligence whatsoever, he nevertheless lies
and he should be punished or despised in proportion to the seriousness of Ms
offence.3*
The rest of Plato's discussion of mousike fafls into three parts; the
first deals with poetry's mode of diction or lexis (dealing in particular
with the conception of mimesis) (392e~398b), and the second with lyric
odes and songs (398c—4QOc), while the third is an eloquent description
of the way all the arts impart gracefulness to the soul (400c-403c). The
question of lexis or 'mode of diction* receives an explanation so long-
winded that we may suspect Plato regards the point as a new one,39 But
what is at issue is a straightforward distinction between two forms of
narration: narration which uses dramatic characterization, and narration
which does not, Plato's word for dramatic characterization is mimesis.
His word for narration is diegesis. It has sometimes been thought that
Plato makes a clean dichotomy between narration and characterization,
but in fact he states clearly that the choice is between simple narration
and narration brought about by way of characterization.* In the Iliad
it is narration both when Agamemnon or some other character speaks
and 'between the speeches' (393b7-8). What happens between the
speeches in Homer is that 'the poet himself is speaking and does not
attempt to turn our attention elsewhere as if the speaker were someone
other than himself* (393a6—7). But when the poet has written a speak-
ing character such as Chryses "he speaks as if he were Chryses and tries
as far as possible to make us think that the speaker is not Homer, but
the priest, an old man', in, which case 'he makes Ms language as like
as possible to that of whatever person he has told us is about to speak'
(393a8-b2, cl-3). Later this is described as the poet 'hiding himself*
(393cl 1). Plato makes Ms distinction clear by translating a chunk of the
Iliad into (dull) non-dramatic narration, and by spelling out the genres
in which the different forms of narration are used: narration in the
poet's voice, without mimesis, is found mostly in dithyratnbic poetry;
tragedy and comedy are narration entirely through mimesisi and epic
poetry is an example of narration partly with and partly without mimesis,
38
Poand, 43-4,
39
Ferrari (1989, 1.14-15) thinks the terms may not be 'Platonic neologisms', just ones
with 'a technical air' which the dialogue's characters, especially Adeimantus, would not
be used to,
* Rep. 392(15—6: hapledieifsu, as against diigesu which is dia mimeseos gignomene.
The Formation of Character 95
Plato also feels the need for a brief argument that 'mim&sis' is the
natural term to apply to those passages where- the poet "makes Ms
speech like that of another'. To 'imitate* (mimeisthai) someone is to
"make oneself like somebody else in voice or form* (393c5-6), Outside
poetry or the arts mimesis often means simply "acting like* someone
else, in the sense of doing as they do—which would include emulating
as well as mimicking someone.4' Plato seems to be arguing that the
activity of writing words spoken by a dramatic character should be
called mimesis because it is an instance of the more general phenom-
enon of 'making oneself like* someone. Within the poetic sphere mimesis
is here applied not just to the activity of the poet. For clearly it is an
actor or rhapsode, rather than Homer, who makes himself like
Agamemnon in voice. Homer writes words which the audience is to
take, within the story, to be the words of the character, Agamemnon;
these words must resemble those the character would use, which, loosely
perhaps, is for Homer to make himself like the character in voice. But
there is not even a loose sense in which Homer makes himself like
Agamemnon inform. Plato rolls into one the poet's writing a dramatic
character and the actor's or rhapsode's acting it out. So three different
things are elided in this discussion of mimesis: the poet's use of
dramatic characterization (narration through mimesis), poetic mimesis
which embraces the activity of both poet and performer, and the still
wider category of "doing as someone does', in or out, of drama. The
gap between merely behaving as someone else does and acting out a
dramatic character might seem small if one thinks of the latter in terms
of resemblance to a kind of person or action, as Plato does.42
After this, the discussion of mimesis becomes harder to follow, at
least on a superficial level. In quick succession, Socrates asks two
questions about the role of mimesis in the model city:
We need to agree whether we will aflow the poets to make narrations to us
using mimesis, or to make some using mimesis and others not, and what kind
of things in each case, or whether they are not to use mimesis.
41
This is suggested by Nehamas (1982, 56—7) as the key sense of mimesis in passages
before Plato—though note that a number of different views have been pot forward (e.g.
Koler; Else (1958); Keuls, ch. 1; Sftrbora). The account by Halliweli (1986), ch. 4, is
illuminating here. On Plato's usage, 1 agree with Halliweli (1992, 60) that Plato wants
features of toe ordinary 'imitation* or 'emulation* to carry over into the sphere of poetic
enactment, in particular its 'character-forming power'.
42
At Rep, 395b6, e.g., mimanata are said to be aphomoiomata (likenesses) of actions.
96 . The Formation of Character
I presame, he said, that you are examining whether we shall accept tragedy
and comedy into ow city, or whether we shall not
Perhaps so, I said, or perhaps even more than that, but we must foEow the
argument wherever, like a wind, it may lead us. ...
Consider this point, Adeimantus, whether our guardians should be mimetic
or not. (394dl~e2.)
43
See Havefock, esp. chs, 3, 9; Annas (1981), 94-6.
The Formation of Character 97
(394e8—395b6), There is empirical evidence of this, too. Poets are
either tragedians or comedians, professional performers are either
rhapsodes or actors, actors are either tragic or comic actors, and human
nature is 'fragmented by even smaller differences than this' as regards
mimetic abilities just as much as abilities in 'real life* (recall again how
Ion specializes in Homeric poetry). If this is true, it tells us that, just
as the guardians must not undertake a plurality of real-life activities, so
they must not engage in mimesis of a multiplicity of character-types. At
most they most play one kind of role. According to the Principle of
Assimilation, engaging in mimesis of any character-type that differs
from the ideal guardian will tend to make them less like the Meal
guardian and more like something else. The conclusion Plato reaches
by applying Ms two principles is that the objects of mimesis for the
guardians should be only the kind of people they themselves are or are
being trained to be, namely "brave, self-controlled, pious, and free men
and all their actions' (395c4—5). He says that this is the mimesis they
should indulge in, if they imitate at all.44 Nowhere does he say that they
should wholly abstain from mimesis.45 Thus he does not take the option
left open at 394d of forbidding the poets in the model city to practise
any mimesis.
In the final part of the discussion of mimesis Socrates asks Adeimantus
to choose between three styles of 'poetry for inclusion in the education
of the guardians. Commentators have sometimes expected that this
threefold division will be the same as that made at 394c—i,e. narration
through mimesis, narration without mimesis, and narration through both—
or that the latter division is the former 'modified*.46 But this is not the
case: Plato has substituted another threefold division. He accepts that
the guardians will use some mimesis; therefore, in terms of the earlier
distinction, they will narrate through both mimesis and simple narration,
a point which Plato goes out of his way to emphasize.47 Yet their style
will involve imitation oaly of one kind of person, avoiding other
models, and hence will have to use a large measure of simple narration,
44
eon de mimontai, 395c3.
43
Cross pud Woozley (272) state Plato's position thus; 'they should play no other
role nor should they imitate' (my emphasis)—presumably based on 395c2—3, oudeti di
cleat an atttous atto prattein crude mimeisthai. However, this surely means; 'they should
neither do nor imitate anything else', particularly since the next sentence begins 'And if
they do imitate . , .*
* The view of Tate (1928), 18.
47
At 396c5-7: 'estai, . . he lexis metechousa , , . amphoteron, mimeseds te leal Sis alles
difgeseos'—a lexis sharing in both mimesis and the other kind of narration.
98 The Formation of Character
not adopting any other voice which departs from the one noble manner
of diction that is the guardians' own. Plato is interested in defining
the narrative style of someone kalos kagathos—'fine and good*, the
standard designation for a superior person of noble class. (Grebe's
translation 'the true gentleman' hits the right note in this respect,48)
Such a person is also called *a moderate man'.49 In narrating, this
person will fall quite naturally into mimesis of the actions and language
of a good man, but will draw the line at enacting scenes in which a
good man is less than perfect (when overcome by disease, sexual pas-
sion, or drunkenness, for example). Nor will he wish to 'make himself
like* someone inferior to himself, except if that person happens to be
performing a good deed, or, Plato adds, perhaps for the sake of play
(paidias char in, 396d5-e2). Just for a joke, one might portray a mem-
ber of the lower orders doing something disreputable, presumably out
of a desire to ridicule that person. Then one would not be departing
from one's 'noble* character but in a way reinforcing it.50
Plato's list of 'inferior' subjects which Ms guardians must be ashamed
to enact is class-specific—many lowly occupations are expressly ex-
cluded from their mimetic training, along with the role of slaves, and
what Plato thinks of as slavish behaviour, such as cowardice and other
moral error, ridicule, or bad language. It is also gender-specific. Despite
Plato's later idea (454b—457a) that women should be included in ruling
and military tasks according to their ability, he appears to assume here
that the guardians will be male, and as such will not be allowed 'to
imitate a young or older woman who is railing at a man, or quarrelling
with the gods, or bragging while thinking herself happy, or one in
misfortune and sorrows and lamentations, even less one in illness or in
love or in labour' (395d5~e3). It seems obsessively anti-female to
think of including this last example. It is, however, reminiscent of the
charge made by Aristophanes that Euripides showed the public, among
other things, 'women giving birth in temples'.51 Euripidean heroines
may be a particular target for Plato,52 though clearly they will not be the
only casualties in tragedy and comedy to fall before Plato's restriction
of mimesis to the model of the 'good man'.
All these exclusions fix the first style in the list from which
48
Dover (1974), 41-5, catalogues some uses of the term, which he asserts to be often
descriptive of a social class,
49
Or 'measured*, metrias* Rep. 396c5.
58
For this view ef. Ferrari (1989), 119; Nehamas (1988), 215; Halliwell (1992), 64n. 24.
3i n
Frogs, 1080. As suggested by Adam, i. 150,
The Formation of Character 99
Adeimantos must choose. It narrates using both simple narration and
mimesis, but keeps mimesis to the minimum because *the good man* is
the only character it enacts dramatically. The second style is said to be
its antithesis, that of someone who thinks nothing unworthy of himself
and will enact or imitate anything 'in earnest [not to make fun of it] and
before a large audience" (397al—4). To show the comprehensive range
of this style Plato mentions a panoply of sound-effects and animal
noises, whose relevance to the argument is puzzling,53 But the essential
point is that all the kinds of person and action prohibited in the first
style will be open to this kind of speaker. With so much to imitate, this
style 'will consist entirely of mimesis in voice and gesture, or at least
have very little straight narration* (397bl-2). It will also need to em-
ploy a great variety of musical modes and rhythms, while the style that
enacts only the words and deeds of the good man will be homogeneous
in these respects as well (397b6-c6), Which do we choose for the
guardians: the first style, which has mimesis at a minimum because only
one kind of character is enacted, the second with its maximum mimesis
of diverse subjects, or a third style resulting from the 'mixture' of these
two? Adeimantus, of course, opts for the 'unmixed imitator [mimetes]
of the good man'. Commentators have found the idea of a third, mixed
style here difficult.54 But Plato is not confused. A mixture between the
53
Adam (i. 151) finds a reference to the use of stage-machinery and musical effects
in drama, although the style is supposed to be totally dim mimeseas phimais te kai schemasin,
which is probably 'by voice and gesture (or posture)*, Adam also mentions the degen-
erate form of dithyramb—but this is not mimetic in the right sense. Else (1986, 36}
suggests that this imitator of dogs, birds, and thunder is a thaumatopoios or magic-show
man, a 'seedy music hat! character' who 'has little or nothing in common with any
serious Greek poet'.
54
Julia Annas writes of this passage; 'there is uncertainty over whether Plato does in
the ead alow there to be any good, imitative poetry in the ideally just state. His muddle
here is irritating, but understandable ... he is very sure what is bad, but less sure about
what is good. He is canght between the idea that imitation is all right as long as only
morally certified models are imitated, and the idea that there is something morally fishy
abosit imitation as such' (1981, 99), Annas says that all is well (without 'muddle'), if one
keeps the twofold division, between the good man's style and its opposite apart from the
earlier threefold division between pure mimisis, simple narration, and narration using
both modes of diction. But the only reason she gives for thinking that Plato fails to keep
the two divisions apart is that 'at 397d, Socrates asks which style we shall have in the
city—one of the pure ones or the mixed one?' It is a common assumption that the
threefold division of 394b—c must play a role in the choice of Adeimantus at 397d, Else
for some reason thinks that a threefold distinction between diegesis, mimesis, and 'their
mixture* would be "more consistent* or "logical* than what Is in the text (1986, 29). That
Plato is not confused is brought out well by Ferrari (1989), 118; Gaudreault, 80-83; and
Grube (1981), 75-6, n. 23,
100 The Formation of Character
good man's and the versatile style is not identical with the lexis which
uses both mimesis and simple narration. It does use both, but, as we saw
earlier, this may be true of the good man's style and the versatile
mimetic style, although the proportions of mimesis to simple narration
are not equal in those two eases.
What differentiates the good man's style from that of someone who
'thinks nothing unworthy of himself* is its governing aim or motiva-
tion. The good, man's style is governed by a normative conception of
how one should behave and speak. The extent to which it uses mimesis
is merely secondary to this consideration. Perhaps someone with this
motivation will use no dramatic enactment and narrate everything in Ms
own voice, but not because mimesis as such is bad: he will use mimesis
if it conforms to his overall aim of assimilating himself to the preferred
way of acting and speaking. On the other hand, the versatile mimetic
style is governed by the aim of indulging in mimesis, and the more of
it the better. Any considerations about how one should look and sound
will be subordinated to the goal of producing dramatic effect.55 Now we
can see what the 'mixture* of these two approaches is: it is a style
governed by both these motivations, in which one seeks to accommo-
date one's poetic narration to a conception of the good person, but also
values dramatic impersonation of many characters simply for the sake
of doing it, Socrates emphasizes that the 'mixed' style brings pleasure,
while 'the opposite to the one you have chosen is by far the most
pleasing to children and their tutors and to the majority of the mob'.56
Children are not yet in a position to be guided by the normative con-
ception of the good man, and "the mob', Plato presumably thinks, never
will be. They seek only the maximum of pleasure. But the mixed style
might be thought a good compromise: why not allow the guardians to
indulge in mimesis for the sake of its own peculiar pleasures, provided
that we also train them, towards the good character demanded by their
role in the city?
In rejecting anything but the style of the good man as 'not fitting in*
55
'Plato forbids not imitation . . , but imitativeaess, the desire and ability to imitate
anything independently of its moral quality and without the proper attitude of paise or
blame toward it* (Nebamas (1988), 215). Belfiore (1984) coins the term 'versatile imi-
tation' for what Plato objects to. Cf. also Ferrari (1989), 117.
56
Rep. 397d6—8, my translation of hedm ge kai ho kekramenos, polu de hidistos ,. ,
ho enantios hou su hairS, which makes a distinction between the mixed style which is
hed f, and the style of the inferior man which is polu hidistos.
The Formation of Character 101
37
to the model city, Plato shows that the root of his position is a fear
of diversity or plurality within the individual: "with us a man is not
double or multiple*. By the Principle of Assimilation, anyone who
imitates many things becomes like each of them, hence becoming, in a
sense, a multiple person. Someone who sought to emulate the good
man, bat who also enjoyed mimesis for its own sake, would be 'mul-
tiple' to a lesser extent, but would at least be 'double* in being ruled
by two motivations which may conflict. The more models he permitted
himself to imitate, the less single he would be in Ms commitment to
developing the ooe character he regarded as Ms ideal.
We may suggest another sense in which fostering mimesis for its
own sake might breed diversity. In tragedy, or in the Iliad, a number
of different characters are presented to us. In dramatic interchanges
between protagonists, conflicting points of view are given voice, with-
out necessarily any single assessment which we can call the poet's
own; the characters each have an equal claim on our attention and
emotional engagement38 Mimesis as such brings with it a pleasure and
an exciting stirring of the emotions. But to pursue mimesis as an end in
itself, for the sake of this emotional involvement, even 'mixed' with the
pursuit of the good man's style, is to risk assimilating oneself to diverse •
characters with diverse points of view. Plato concludes his discussion
of mim&sis with his first image of banishment, amid ironic praise (re-
calling the Ion) of the virtuoso dramatic artist as 'sweet' and 'holy*:
If a man who in Ms cleverness can become many persons and imitate all
things should arrive in our city and want to give a performance of Ms poems,
we should bow down before him as being holy, wondrous and pleasing, but we
should tell him that there is no such man in our city and that it is not lawful
that there should be. We would pour myrrh on Ms head and crown Mm with
wreaths, and send him away to another city. We ourselves would employ a
more austere and less pleasure-giving poet and storyteller for our own good,
oae who would imitate the speech of a good man.5'
57
Rep. 397d!0-e2, In 'you would say that it does not fit in to our city* (dlO-cl), the
"if seems to refer only to the extreme style of the inferior man, the opposite of the style
chosen by Adeintaotns. But the reason given for rejecting this is surely also a reason for
rejecting the 'mixed* style.
's Ci Annas (1981), 98. Plato makes the point explicitly at Laws 719c5-dl.
59
Rep. 398al—b2. The crowning and anointing may allude to flic practice of adorning
statues of the gods. Another evocative view, reported by Adam (i. 154} sees an allusion
to the anointing of swallows by Greek women.
102 The Formation of Character
If his argument so far is persuasive, Plato is entitled to send away the
mimetic poet who tries to infiteate the education system. Given the
Principle of Specialization, the Principle of Assimilation, the assumed
educational value of poetry, and the interventionist role he conceives
for the state, he has no choice. The pleasure of mimesis weighs little
against the cumulative power of these considerations. And if the soul
remains liable to radical 'moulding* throughout life, or always retains
a childish part, then there are grounds for the complete dismissal of the
poet who is dedicated to mimesis as an end.
The next section of Plato's discussion of mousike concerns music
proper, though still in connection with lyric poetry. We need not specu-
late about the details of the musical modes, which Socrates claims not
to know properly. Let us instead look at the philosophical principles
that underlie his prescriptions. Song has three elements: words, mode,
and rhythm.* As far as the words go, what was said above about the
content of speech without music is sufficient. And mode and rhythm
ought to be appropriate- to the words. Lamenting modes or scales
(harmoniai) and soft, relaxed ones will not be required in the city
because there will be no narrations of events to which they are appro-
priate. Socrates wants to have just two musical modes, one robust and
warlike, the other peaceful but self-controlled and 'willing*—they turn
out to be the established Dorian and Phrygian modes. Note that the
rationale behind this invokes mimesis in a very broad sense; 'Leave me
those two modes,' says Socrates, 'which will best imitate [mimesontai]
the accents of brave and moderate men both in misfortune and in pros-
perity* (399cl—4), dearly mimesis here is not dramatic impersonation.
We might talk of music 'expressing' a mood or character, of its 'being
expressive of courage*, or even 'being courageous*—terms for a pheno-
menon which philosophers to this day have been unable to unravel
with any great conviction.61 Plato calls the phenomenon mimesis, pre-
sumably because he thinks of the music as resembling a character or
mood. If the music I perform is warlike or self-controlled, Plato thinks
that in performing it I 'make myself like' the typical warlike or self-
controlled individual. From the same idea come prescriptions about
which instruments the model city should make and use, the aulos once
again falling foul of Plato's preferences, along with complicated stringed
instruments designed to be versatile in playing an exotic range of modes.
60
. logos, harmonia, rhythmos. Rep. 398dl—2.
61
A point admirably shown by Budet (1985).
The Formation of Character 103
The 'luxurious* city is gradually being purged of many of its accoutre-
ments. A discussion of rhythm and metre follows (399e8-400c6), in
which the same basic principle applies. Different rhythms are appropri-
ate to, or are 'imitations* (mimemata) of, different ways of living—
though Socrates leaves us to consult Ms contemporary Damon on the
details.
The inal passage of Plato's discussion of mausike broadens into a
positive account of the value of all the arts, briefly achieving an elo-
quence comparable with the Diotima-speech in the Symposium: and
indeed, Plato rounds off by saying that a discussion of mousike ought
to end in the love of the beautiful. Here it seems appropriate to translate
mousike as 'the arts', and the present passage thus differs from the
Diotima-speech in the prominent role it gives to the arts in making the
soul akin to, and a lover of, the beautiful.62 The truly educated person
must be able to recognize self-control and courage occurring in persons
and actions, and see this as of a piece with63 recognizing likenesses
(eikones) of self-control and courage—that is, the likenesses of these
human qualities as they occur in dramatic characters, styles of speech,
musical modes, and an orderly manner of production in all the arts. It
is thus that being a devotee of momike in its widest sense embraces an
acquaintance with the human virtues.64
Why is 'nurture in the arts' (en mousikei trophe) so important for
Plato?—- 'because their rhythm, and harmony permeate the inner part of
the soul, bring gracefulness to it, and make the strongest impression*
(40Id5—8). 'Gracefulness* is euschemosuni, an unusual word meaning
literally 'weU-formedness', which Plato here us to to denote a virtue
that can be shared by the soul and art-products alike. An early educa-
tion in the arts forms the soul, then, in such a way that it spontaneously
welcomes what is fine and good. Before attaining full use of reason, the
young can be prepared by contact with beautiful sights and sounds—
but only if their nourishment is carefully controlled. Not only the poets,
c
It is another question whether it encompasses Plato's full-blown doctrine of foam,
as we-said the Symposium does. Plato says that no oae cm become tally educated in the
arts,' or truly mousikos, until they team to recognize the forms (eidl) of self-control,
courage, and other virtues, and to pereewe them in things they occur in, both the things
themselves and likenesses of them (to' auta kai eikonas auton). Although eide is Plato's
wort for separate Fonns when he is discussing them, the cautious reader should not
import that doctrine into this passage. Cf. Adam, i. 168; CSuthrie (1975), 459-60; Orabe
(1981), 82 n. 29; Annas (1981), 100.
63
Tart of the same craft and training' (402e?-8).
w
There is no doctrine here of art's being able to 'imitate* Forms directly, despite the
views of Grey, 299; Tate (1928), 21-3.
104 The Formation of Character
but all other producers—painters and the like, weavers, embroiderers,
builders—-must be 'forbidden to put the bad character that is unre-
strained, unfree and graceless into their likenesses of Jiving things or
their buildings or any other of their works' (401b4-7). There is a
relation between the character (&hos) of the soul and the speech, rhythm,
harmony, and form which occur in the arts, Plato calls this relation
variously one of likeness, kinship, foEowing or consequence, or mimesis,
Good form or gracefulness issues spontaneously from a well-formed
soul. But stylistic good form in poetry aad the visual arts, which is a
likeness of the soul's good character, can also impress itself on a soul
by- habituation. By exercising gracefulness in the arts, and consuming
well-formed products, one's soul becomes assimilated to them, and
since they are a mimema of the good character, one's soul becomes
more like a good soul.
So Plato has a role for artists which is both positive and profound:
We must seek out such craftsmen [demiourgof\ as ha¥e the talent to pursue the
beautiful and the graceful in their work, in order that our young men shall be
benefited from all sides like those who live in » healthy place, whence some-
thing from these beautiful works will strike their eyes and ears like a breeze
that brings health from salubrious places, and lead them unawares from child-
hood to love of, resemblance to, and harmony with, the beauty of reason.
(401c4-d3.)
The pursuit of beauty through the arts is thus seen as necessary in the
education of the truly excellent human being, though it is not sufficient,
but merely a preparatory stage prior to the Ml acquisition of reason.65
I wonder if we do not believe something approximating to this? We
give the arts a fairly prominent place in the education of the young. It
has at least been part of our tradition to teach them, long before they
reach intellectual and ethical maturity, to dance, to sing in tune, to
follow a rhythm accurately, to paint, to notice form, to build; we select
their fiction and drama, their musical instruments even, believing that
omitting such steps risks impoverishing their overall development. Plato
can be seen as giving elevated expression to a similar way of thinking,
As far as Books 2—3 of the Republic are concerned, therefore, Plato's
critique of the arts is a thorough overhaul, not an outright rejection. But
is that the end of the story? Plato retains the arts and charges them with
the precious task of benefiting the souls of Ms young guardians, but it
is easy to feel that the arts have really been undermined and replaced,
45
As is spell out by 4Giel-402a4. See also Irwin (1977a), 202-3.
The Formation of Character 105
because Plato's aims are so antithetical to those that we normally
recognize as 'artistic*. Thinking of Plato, E, M. Forster wrote that from
the State's point of view the artist never quite 'fits in*:
The State believes in education. But does art educate? 'Sometimes, but not
always* is the answer; an unsatisfactory one. The State believes in recreation.
But does art amuse? 'Sometimes, but not always* is the answer again. The State
does not believe in experiments, in the development of human sensitiveness in
directions away from the average citizen. The artist does, and consequently he
and the State ... must disagree,*
Plato opposes what we would call 'Art* as a motivating force in the life
of an individual or a community. For he opposes the pursuit of diversity
or novelty for their own sake, the seeking out of pleasurable experi-
ences, the imaginative exploration of the morally reprehensible and
ambiguous sides of human existence, the cultivation of the viewpoints
of women and slaves which challenge the secure habits of the aristo-
cratic kalos kagathos. The arts may be a preferred means of fulfilling
Plato's educational and political ends, but we are bound to feel that he
subordinates them rather violently to those ends, at the expense of their
other potential values,67
To complain that Plato has omitted such characteristically 'artistic'
values is not to revert to the view which I earlier called aestheticism.
We can agree with Plato that form and content in the arts influence
people's characters hi ways that are morally and politically important,
that the arts can be criticized for the inaccuracy of their portrayal of
human life, and that if pursued for the sake of novelty and pleasure
without being answerable to any values outside themselves they may
be corrupting. We may even share Ms demand that some moral and
political benefit from the arts is a condition of acknowledging their
worth. But all this is compatible with valuing as beneficial precisely the
'experiments' and 'development of human sensitiveness* that Forster
speaks of. This suggests that it is not so much what Plato says about the
nature of the arts themselves that is objectionable, but rather his rigid
authoritarianism and the narrowing vision expressed in his Principle of
Specialization.
* Forsttr, 97,
6J
This is no doubt a particularly modern thought. IB Aristophanes* Frogs Aeschylus
and Euripides contend in a comic debate for the titie of best poet, but despite great
differences in style and social attitude they agree that what they ought to be doing is
"making people better in the cities* (Frogs 1009—10).
5
Mimesis
1
Among namerous discussions of mimesis, two which bring out its wide-ranging
character in Plato are McKeon, and HaUiwell (1986, 116-21). The attempt by Verfenius
(1949, 16-18} to find Plato giving 'art* a worthy place in a 'hierarchical: structure of
reality' relies on uses of mimesis in which cue thing strives to emulate something higher
(e.g. truth or divine harmony), or in which something is a sensible instance of a Form,
Neither relates directly to Plato's conception of mimesis fa the arts,
2
The disparity issue is raised e.g. by Gwene, 50 ff,; Tate (1928), 16; Cross and Woozley,
277-9; Collingwood (1938), 47-8; Mehamas (1982), 48-54,
Mimesis 107
contradicts Book 3, or Plato is now using 'mimetic* In a radically
different sense.
However, if we concentrate on the kinds of artistic practice rejected
in Book 3, we find that Plato does not go back on what he said there.
The key question (394e) was whether the guardians should be
mimetic—whether mimesis should be an end in itself for them. By giving
a negative answer to that question, Plato in a certain sense did reject
'such poetry as is .mimetic' (mimetike): he rejected poetry whose domi-
nant motivation was the production of pleasurable dramatic impersona-
tion at the expense of any discrimination among role-models. Book 10
does not alter this situation. The fact that some sort of dramatic imper-
sonation was retained as beneficial when it subserved educational and
moral ends is less important.3 Secondly, the focus of the critique of
poetry remains, as we shall see, on tragedy and Homeric poetry. I shall
argue that the two discussions use different senses of mimesis, but that
the reference of the term has a certain stability: instances of poetic
mimesis in the Book 3 sense are also the central topic of Book 10.*
What, then, is mimesis in Book 10? Socrates asks: *Could you tell me
what mimesis as a whole is?'s By 598b8 the answer has been given:
'Mimetic art [he mimetike] is far removed from the truth, and that is
why ... it can make everything, because it touches only a small part
of each thing, and that an image [eidolon].* As a means of reaching this
answer, Plato discusses a painting of an object, such as a bed. So
'mimesis as a whole" embraces painting as well as some forms of
3
Nehamas (1988, 215) and Ferrari (1989, 125} argue for continuity between Books 3
and 10 on similar grounds. Neharnas: 'Plato forbids not imitation, which he considers
essential to education, but imitativeness, the desire and ability 'to imitate anything inde-
pendently of its moral quality and without the proper attitude of praise or blame toward
i t , . . . When Socrates says in Book x that "all mimetic poetry" (paie.ieas hose mimetike)
has been excluded from the city, he does not refer to imitation but o n l y . . . to poetry
which involves and encourages imitativeness: the conflict disappears.' Belflore, in a
detailed study (1984), makes a similar point: Plato opposes in both Books 3 and 10 what
she calls 'versatile imitation' (rnitnitikl).
4
Cf. Halliwell (1988, 5), who speaks of a 'shift in the use of the mimesis word-group
from denoting dramatic enactment through direct speech (3. 39245 ff.) to tneaniEg artistic
representation or depiction in a much broader sense*, ft is fairly traditional to see a shift
in the sense of mimesis—though harder to find agreement on what the different senses
we. (See Havelock, 20-6; Grebe (1935), 185,188; Comfort (1941), 324 n. i; Cross and.
Wooztey, 271-2; Annas (1981), 336; Else (1986), 44.) BeWore's attempt to see the sense
of mimesis as constant between Books 3 and 10 lacks plausibility: the Book 3 definition
is surely not 'making something sirniiar to something else in. sound or shape* (1984,124—
6) but is restricted 10 dramatic enactment or composition.
5
Uimesin holds echais an mat eipein hoti pot' estinl (595c7).
108 Mimesis
poetry. It seems a fair approximation to say that in modern terms Plato
is talking about representation in the arts, or at least one kind of rep-
resentation, in which an artist represents something by making an ap-
pearance of it. Mimesis, in Book 10, is making an appearance which by
intention resembles things of some kind, but is not really one of them,
Plato's account of the human soul will enable him to argue that in
poetry this sort of activity is potentially dangerous (595a5-b7), But the
initial explanation of 'mimesis as a whole' is given, in metaphysical and
epistemological terms: Plato tries to establish what entities are made by
mimesis, and what knowledge its practitioner requires. In all this he
relies on doctrines developed earlier in the Republic, so a brief sketch
of some of these will help us here. Plato's model city, which we left
with its specialized class of military guardians, soon, acquires another
specialized class selected from among their ranks: a class of rulers.
Socrates' account of justice has it that if the city consists of three
classes, rulers (to which he now transfers the name 'guardians'), milit-
ary (now called auxiliaries), and the economic class of producers and
traders, it will be a just city provided that, each of these classes per-
forms its own function properly without usurping the function of the
others. Plato's attention shifts to the role of governing the whole city,
and a new phase of the Republic begins when he suggests (in Book 5}
that 'philosophers {should] rule as kings in the cities, or those whom we
now call kings and rulers [should] genuinely and adequately study
philosophy' (473cl l-d2).
Philosophers are defined by their relation to the Forms, Fine and
Ugly, Just and Unjust, Good and Bad, each of which is itself one, but
which appear in multiple instantiations.6 Contrasted with the philo-
sophers, who look towards the single Form in each ease, are people
whom Plato calls philotheomones and philekooi, lovers of sights and
lovers of sounds. These people 'run around to all'the Dionysian festi-
vals omitting none ... as if their ears were under contract to listen to
every chorus' (4?5d5—8), But they are unable to "look* towards Fine-
ness itself or to enjoy it. They believe only in 'fine things', not in
Fineness itself, and, thinking that the only fineness there is lies in a
multiplicity of colours, shapes, and sounds (476M-c7), they mistake a
mere likeness for the real thing. In a long and difficult argument, Plato
puts forward the view that it is the philosophers who have .knowledge,
while the lovers of sights and sounds have only belief. Knowledge,
6
See Rep. 475e9-476a7, and 476WO-11, for auto to kaion.
Mimesis 109
then, is tied to Forms: someone who denies the existence of Forms, or
is incapable of apprehending them, can have no knowledge.7
Since the sight-lovers' lack of knowledge is linked to their attitude
towards enjoying the arts, we ought to consider where the deficiency of
these unphilosophlcaJ aesthetes is supposed to Me. They believe, as
surely everybody does, in many things or actions that are fine or beau-
tiful. They seek out such things, to gain from them the pleasures of
sight and hearing. What Plato particularly criticizes them for, however,
is their failing to believe in what is distinct from the many things or
actions: Fineness or Beauty itself. He complains that because they view
reality as not containing Beauty itself, 'the many conventional opinions
of the many, about beautiful and the others [kalou te peri kai ton all on],
are rolling around, as it were, between what is not and what purely is'.8
This strange wording seems to indicate that the sight-lovers go wrong
primarily in the negative view they hold about beauty. Their opinions
are many because they hold that beauty is no one thing at all. They
judge on each occasion 'this is beautiful', 'that is beautiful', but when
asked what makes all of these things beautiful (when asked, if you like,
for their opinion about what 'beautiful* itself is), they do not believe
that there is a single answer. Thus they are in, the position of Hippias,9
when he said that beauty was 'being made of gold' and on other occa-
sions 'being made of ivory': they wiE have as many different opinions
as there are different properties which make particular things beautiful.
This is in line with a recent interpretation, according to which Plato's
'many beautiMs* here are the many sensible properties10 which some-
one might believe beauty to consist in. The things which have one of
these properties are and are not beautiful—meaning that some gold
things are beautiful, some are not, some brightly coloured things are
beautiful, some are not, and so on. We cannot say that any of the many
'beautifuls' *is any more than it is not what anyone might call it*
1
The traditional reading is that knowledge can be only of Forms, beliefs only of their
many sensible instances. This has recently been questioned by Fine (1978 and 1990).
8
479d3—5, translation adapted from Reeve.
* HiMu. 289e2~290d6, discussed above (Ch. 3). Another relevant comparison is Phtlo.
IQOeiO-dS, where Socrates rejecis the 'blooming colour' or 'shape' of a thing as the
reason for its being beautiful, preferring instead the explanation of its participating in the
beautiful itself.
18
See Gosling (I960); Irwin (\977b), 7-9; Fine (1990), 91. Hippias answers that
fineness is a beautiful girl, and that It is -being made of gold*. If he is a prototype of the
sight-lovers, it is probably a mistake to think that they care to distinguish between the
many beautiful things and the many properties that can make things beautiful. Cf. Gos-
ling (1960), 116 n. I.
110 Mimesis
(479b9-40). On this interpretation, to say that opinions about beauty
'roll about between being and not being* means that, among the things
exhibiting those sensible properties which are wrongly held to consti-
tute beauty, some are beautiful and some are not—which in turn means
that the conventional opinions about beauty are and are not true.
In Books 6 and 7 Plato portrays the philosophers' knowledge and
•their more advanced education. At the pinnacle of their achievement is
to be knowledge of the Forms, crowned by knowledge of the Form of
the Good, which, like the sun in the sensible realm, illuminates and
sustains the existence of everything in the realm of Forms. A mefliod
of reasoning, which Plato calls dialectic, will take them to knowledge
of the highest of principles, from which they will be able to deduce
further knowledge. Throughout this part of the book Plato operates in
pictures or likenesses, which are a second-best to genuine knowledge
and possibly deceitful, as Socrates himself warns.1-1 Plato's set of simi-
les relies on permutations of the relation between a thing and its mere
likeness. X and F are related as likeness and original when X resembles
F, but is not as real a thing as F, Shadows and reflections are contrasted
with the solid things of which they are mere likenesses; yet these things
relate to the higher realm of Forms just as their own likenesses relate
to them,12 Forms, in particular the Form of the Good, are the only
elements of reality which cannot be viewed as a likeness of something
else. This is another way of marking them out as 'most real* and as the
proper objects of knowledge,13
In Ms approach to artistic image-making in Book 10 Plato exploits
this background, and sets out to locate the products of mimesis within
a hierarchy of likenesses and originate which still has Forms at its head.
But rather than reproducing the metaphysics of Books 6 and 7 exactly,
he adapts it to a new argumentative task.14 Two features are worth
noting: firstly, in the whole of Book 10 he does not use the usual term
1
' In the Sun simile Socrates disclaims knowledge of the Good, and says only 'what
appears as the offspring of the Good an4 is most like it* {Rep. 506e3—4); he adds: 'be
on your guard, lest I unwittingly deceive you and give you a counterfeit account* (507a4-
5). The account of the Cave is also just a "likeness" (eikon: 5I5a4, 51?a8).
12
See the simile of the Divided Line (Rep. 509el-510b5 and 5tOd5-5ila8). The
ascent in the Cave simile (514a2-5l6b7) uses repeated likeness : original contrasts to
illustrate the transition from ignorance to full knowledge,
13
At Rep. 476c2-7 those who recognize, beautiful things but not the Form are said to
"think that a likeness is not a likeness but the thing itself which it resembles*.
14
A point made by HalHwel (1988), 118.
Mimesis 111
eikon for an image or likeness, preferring instead terminology to do
with appearance (phainomenon, phantasma) with shades of apparition
and magic attached to it, and the word eidolon which tends to mean a
false image, or a counterfeit,15 (Recall the claim IB the Gorgias that
rhetoric is the mere eidolon of true justice.) And secondly, Plato here
has some curious ideas about Forms which he does not entertain any-
where else.
In some respects, then, we have to regard Socrates* opening invita-
tion, as disingenuous:
Do yon want us to start looking in our usual way? We are accustomed to
assuming one Form in each case for the many particulars to which we give the
same name .., Let us then take any set of particulars you like. For example,
there are many beds and tables . , , But there are only two Forms for these two
articles, one of the bed and one of the table ... We also usually say that the
makers of these articles look to the Form when they make, one the beds, the
other the tables, which we use. And so with other things. The Form itself is not
the work of any craftsman, for how could it be? (596a5-blG.)
Plato thinks of the relation between the ordinary bed which we use and
the Form of 'what a bed really is* as a relation between likeness and
original. The Form is 'what is*, hence the maker of the bed makes "not
what is, but something which is like what is, but is not that* (597a4-
5). It is into this context of likenesses and originals that he introduces
the painter who paints a picture of a bed. What does this painter make?
The answer is now a natural one; the painter makes something which
is not a bed, but which is a likeness of it. The practitioner of mimesis
is thus the maker 'whose product is at two removes from nature*, or
from what truly is. While the bed is not 'what is' (the Form) but merely
something like it, the painting is in turn not a bed but merely something
like it."
As has often been said, the present passage is dubious when
15
See HalliweB (1988), 118-19, on Plato's avoidance of eikon, and {he connotations
of phantasma and eidolon,
" Nehamas writes that Plato never 'accuses art of being an imitation of an imitation
. . . not once in Republic 10 is mimesis used to refer to the relationship between sensible
objects and Forms , . , nothing in the text implies that the relationship between a work
of art and its subject is the same as that between a physical object and its farm or Forms'
(1982, 60), The two relationships are of course not the same: the bed. is not a picture of
the Form, and the painting is not an instance of the ted. Yet Plato does say that the
object: Form relationship is one of being fife—the carpenter makes ti toiouton hoion
to an (597a4-5). (Cf. Belfiore (1984), 125.)
112 Mimesis
considered for the eoatribution it makes to the Theory of Forms.17
Socrates" hesitant speculation about the Form, *we would say, as I
think, [it] is the work of a god* (597b6~7), has him toying with an idea
that Plato never entertains elsewhere: usually, since there never was a
time when Forms were not, Plato does not need to consider who or
what brought them into existence. Secondly, we may doubt whether it
is proceeding in the 'usual way* to assume that any set of many par-
ticulars which we call by the same name has an associated Form. Thirdly,
should we not be surprised that a humble craftsman is now granted a
glimpse of the Form as the guiding principle in the production of beds,
when earlier in the Republic much was made of the fact that only
philosophers have access to Forms? We may even doubt whether
Plato's view of Forms elsewhere would really allow him to think there
are Forms of artefacts. (What do these have in common with the Fine
itself or the Good?) On these issues Book 10 seems to some extent
adrift from the main body of the Republic.
However, these anomalies do not detract from the clarity of Plato's
explanation of mimesis. His dominating concern is with the question
what 'kind of maker' the practitioner of mimesis is (596bl2). This,
together with the desire to place the product of the mimetic artist within
the hierarchy of likenesses and originals, leads him to seek also a
hierarchy of makers or producers. Once started along this path, he is
forced to use an artefact as his example of an object depicted by the
painter, simply because the painter has to be contrasted with a maker
of a 'more real' product18 (Plato does not believe the absurd proposi-
tion that painters paint pictures only of artefacts.) His talk of a god
making the Form can be explained as the completion of a hierarchy of
three producers to match that of the picture, the bed, and the Form.
Finally, an analogy has to be drawn between the intentions of the painter
and the intentions of the carpenter. The painter intends to make some-
thing which is a likeness of a bed without being one, in the same way
as the craftsman intends to make something which is a likeness of
'what a bed truly is' but without being that. This analogy could not
work unless the carpenter's activity was allowed to be guided by some
kind of cognitive access to the Form itself. Plato needs to specify the
kind of artefact made by the practitioner of mimesis', he sets himself the
" Sec e.g. Nehamas (1982), 54-5; Chemiss; Annas (1981), 227-32; Cross and Woozley,
284-6; Griswold (1981), 135-6.
18
'Had he selected e.g. mountains, it would be difficult to specify the middle term'
(Adam, ii. 387).
Mimesis 113
additional imaginative task of contrasting three kinds of artificer. This
goes some way towards explaining the oddities we have mentioned.'*
What, then, does the practitioner of mimesis make? A telling ex-
change occurs at 596elO—11: *in a way the painter too makes a bed,
does he not?—Yes, he does, but only the appearance of a bed [or "only
an appearing one", phainomenln ge].' The painter does not make noth-
ing, but what he or she does make is only an appearing something. It
is a case of 'making in a way, but in a way not*, as Plato also puts it
(596d3—4). The second peculiarity is that mimesis can make an appear-
ing thing of any kind. There is an easy way in which everyone could
do this;
Carry a mirror with you everywhere; you will then quickly make the sun and
things in the heavens, the earth as quickly, yourself and the other living crea-
tures, manufactured articles, plants, and all that was mentioned just now,20
Yes, he said, I could make them appear, tat I could not make them as they
truly are. [Or: 'I could make appearing ones (phainomena), but not ones that
really are in troth.'] (596d9-e4.)
That a painting can be a copy of Forms is, it may be felt, too large
a point for us to be 'left to understand' by Book 10. Tate, however,
draws additional evidence from a passage in Book 6 where Socrates
imagines an outline of the ideal city sketched by 'painters who would
use the divine model' (50€te3—4). These painters would 'keep looking
back and forth, to Justice, Beauty, Moderation, and all such things as
28
Criticism of Plato for overlooking artistic mimesis of Foims conies from Grube
(1935), 202, 206; Adam, ii. 393; Daiches, 20. Credit to PJato for believing in artistic
mimesis of Forms is given by e.g. Tate (1928); Verdenius (1949), 18; Golden, 123-4,
130. The discussion and bibliography of Nebamas (1982), 58-60 and 75-7, is invaluable
here,
29 30
Tate (1928), 21, Ibid. 19-20.
Mimesis 117
by nature exist, and they would compose human life with reference to
these* (SOlbl—4). It is true that these imagined painters could be guided
by knowledge of Forms. But how are we to imagine their picture of
'human life*? Any such picture must (to reiterate the point) present to
us an appearance of some aspect of human life—how could it be 'a
direct copy of reality', if that means a direet copy of Forms? Another
problem is that Socrates' painters here are purely imaginary: we cannot
take this as evidence for Plato's believing in any real artistic activity
guided by knowledge of the Forms. The passage is an elaborate meta-
phor and is not really about painting at all. It is about philosophers,31
To make more vivid the role he is assigning to philosophers, Plato asks
us temporarily to think of them as if they were designers of some
visible product, who have the philosopher's privilege of knowing the
Forms. A careful look at the passage reveals that the 'fine picture* these
"painters* make is 'human life* itself. Philosophers, knowing Forms,
make human life into a likeness of Justice, Beauty, and Moderation,
that is, make life so that it is just, beautiful, and moderate. When the
metaphor is explained we see that painting is not the issue, A similar
passage is 484c8-dl, where Plato says that the guardians must 'as
painters can, look to that which is most true, always refer to it, contem-
plate it as exactly as possible*. It has been said that 'not too much must
be made of this passage*32—wisely, since again we are dealing with a
simile, which gains its point because painters can make exact copies of
the ordinary things (not Forms) which they observe carefully with their
eyes. (It would/anyway be very lame to say that the guardians must
carefully attend to the Forms, like painters carefully attending to the
Forms!)33
31
As Rep, 500c9, el make clear. See Nehatnas (1982), 59; Keuls, 41, 50,
32
Grube (1935), 188. Also see Keuls, 50-1, for a sensible discussion.
3J
Other passages may appear to support Tate's idea that there can be artistic mimesis
of Forms. One is where Plato says that no one can become truly educated in the arts until
they team to recognize the forms of self-oonttol, courage and other virtues, and to per-
ceive them in things and in likenesses of things (402b9-c8), But, as we said in Ch. 4,
it is not very likely that the "forms* mentioned here are the Forms to be put forward later
in the central part of the Republic. Plato is talking about reeogaizing instances of the
virtues in people and things and in artistic images of people and things. Another passage
is at. 472d4-7, where Plato uses fte simile of the painter who paints the model of the
perfect human being. This shows that Plato could regard a painting as something admir-
able, if it depicted something admirable, and that he' could imagine a painting which was
not merely a slavish copy of what already exists. But what is painted here is not a Form,
but 'an appearing matt', an image of the way an ideal man might look. Tate's remaining
point, that there is 'good* and 'bad' mimesis In Book 3, does not help his position cither,
From the fact that modelling one's dramatic behaviour on one type of person is "good*
118 Mimesis
So what philosophical position, if any, can we attribute to Plato in
Book 10? His view is quite simple; to paint is to make only an appear-
ance, not something real—a painting of an X is an intentionally made
image, something which is a likeness of an X's appearance without
being an X. Tn taking as Ms example a painting of an object, he is
singling out the kind of thing we would call & representation and the
activity we would call representing. But pictorial representation is not
an easy phenomenon to analyse, and our use of expressions such
as 'image*, 'appearance*, 'likeness', 'painting of ..." has left many
issues unclarified. To begin with, Plato assumes that representation is
a matter of resemblance. Recent philosophical writing has put such an
assumption under strong attack.34 If we are tempted to say that the
painter makes something like* a bed, we are most likely to mean that
what is represented in the painting is like a bed: that the bed we see in
the picture is like real beds.35 However, once we make this distinction
between a painting's resembling a bed and the-bed~in-the-painting*s
resembling a bed, we bring into focus a striking feature of Plato's
account: he never says that the painter's product, is a painting, a marked
surface, or a 'real* thing of any kind at all. What resembles a bed for
him is the 'bed' that the painter 'makes'. The painter makes only an
appearance, *an object whose identity is constituted by the thing that it
seems to be, not by any properties that it might have in its own right',36
It is in this sense that the traditional translation of mimesis as 'imita-
tion' is appropriate. The painter makes a bed, a person, or a bowl of
flowers, which is not a real one. What the painter makes is not a real
anything: it is always an imitation something. As Arthur Danto has put
it, a feature of the imitation theory is *the logical invisibility of the
medium'.37 We might naively consider the painting to be an intention-
ally produced set of physical marks in a physical medium on a physical
there is BO jnference to the claim that painting can represent Forms, In Book ID'S sense
the mimesis of any type of person would be the 'making' of an 'appearing person'—and
neither an appearing good person nor an appearing bad person would differ ontologieaUy
from an appearing bed,
34
See e.g. Goodman, cfa. 1, and Schier (1986), 2-9, and for further discussion, Budd
(1991),
35
See Wollheim, 18.
36
Nehamas (1982), 63. Nehamas (ibid. 62} rightly notes a 'vacillation* in Plato's
description of artists, between 'imitator of an appearance' and 'maker of an appearance*
(cf. 598b3-5, 596elO-l 1 on the painter) or between 'imitator of images* and 'maker of
an image* (600e5, 59943 on the poet). What is represented is the appearance of things
in the world, but what is made is also only an appearance.
"fl Danto (1981), 151.
Mimesis 119
38
surface —-but Plato does not consider that this is anything important,
interesting, or pleasing in its own right. So he cannot think of evaluat-
ing the painter's choice of substances to paint with, or the painting's
success in handling colour or line. The product of the painter's activity,
for Mm, is just something secondary to other objects, a non-real bed or
a non-real person.
It is relevant here to remark on a fact about the phrase 'a painting of
...': it can be, but does not have to be, completed by an expression
referring to some particular subject When it is, we have, for example,
a painting of Socrates, or of the particular bed on which Socrates died.
It is plausible to say that the painting manages to be of these subjects
by standing to them (or standing for them) in some relation parallel
with linguistic reference. On the other hand, there can be a painting
which is 'of a bed* not by being related in any way to any particular
bed, but only in the sense that a bed figures as the 'representational
content' internal to the picture, to understand which is to understand the
picture at the most basic level. Plato is aware of Hie second kind of
representation,39 but he makes no theoretical distinction between these
two ways of understanding 'painting of ...' And this could be seen as
» difficulty, in view of his comparison, between painting and holding up
a mirror to things. For something to be 'a mirror image o f . . .* always
does require some particular original of which it is the image, Plato
concentrates on the fact that in both eases what is made is an appearing
thing, not a real thing, overlooking the difference between the two
cases: that the mirror image is essentially dependent on its more real
original, both for its existence and for what it appears to be, whereas
a painting of a bed, if that phrase is understood in the 'non-referential'
way, does not have to have such a dependence on any other particular
object.40
While Plato makes nothing of this difference, it is nevertheless un-
justified to claim that Plato equates mimesis with 'photographic real-
ism', or even that this is a manner of representation that particularly
concerns him. Commentators sometimes assume that Plato thinks of the
painter as 'a mere mechanical copyist' indulging in 'uncritical copying
** I note in passing that this too has been disputed. For an initial discussion, see
Woflhehn, 11 ff. and 177-84.
3S>
Two examples in the Republic: (A) The painting of the ideally beautiful human
being (472d4-7) is not any kind of copy of a particular person. It is a 'non-relational*
painting. (B) The patater 'of a cobbler, of a carpenter, of other craftsmen' (598b8-cl)
need not copy some actual person. And the painting of the bed is the same.
48
The same point is made by Panto (1981), 69.
120 Mimesis
of an object*, 'exact copying of the way things in the world look*, a
'mindless' or 'slavish reproduction of reality*, and that he "degrades
[painting] to the level of photography'.41 This relies on taking the anal-
ogy with the minor-carrier as a very tight one indeed. la a mirror, the
appearance of some existing particular thing really is reproduced both
exactly and mindlessly. But Plato does act say painting is holding a
mirror to the world (for that matter, he does- not even say that the
mirror-carrier performs mimesis, only that two are the 'same kind of
maker*). Nothing in the discussion requires there to be some particular
bed which is 'copied' by a painting which succeeds in being *of a bed'.
And even a depiction of some actual bed does not have to be 'photo-
graphic* or 'exact* in its style in order to make 'an appearing bed*. It
merely has to bring a bed to mind in some natural way.42 It is thereby
rendered derivative from a kind of real things—no one could recognize
images of beds if they did not recognize beds—but does not have to be
a 'slavish copy' of any particular thing.
What about the idea that Plato positively believes mimesis to be the
production of an illusion? In the clearest and crudest sense, producing
an illusion is bringing about a false belief in the existence of a thing,
where that belief is engendered by the apprehension of what is only an
appearance, image, or imitation.43 If this were.Plato's view, it would be
open to two broad objections; (1) even in the case of painting, with
which Plato chooses to exemplify 'mimesis in general', it is an implau-
sible view of the nature of representation (of a painting's managing to
be 'of a bed'), and (2) it gives a poor account of poetry, which will be
Plato's main concern in the remainder of the discussion. To take the
first objection first, paintings plainly do not very often work, or succeed
in being *of' something, by engendering an illusion. There is a weaker
view which says that, when we see a painting which we understand to
represent (say) grapes, we are under an illusion of seeing grapes at least
some of the time (perhaps momentarily). But that view is no better. We
should bear in mind those many ordinary viewers who are never under
any illusion while looking at a particular painting of grapes, and who
are aware throughout that they see a flat, painted surface. The price
41
Adam, ii. 393; Grebe (1935), 203; Annas (1981), 336; Osborne, 65. Ferrari (1989,
12?) parallels my criticism of these views.
42
Two notions that have had much currency recently are 'seeiag-as* and 'seeing-in'.
See WoHteta, esp. 205-26; and Scruton (1974), eh, 13.
* The well-known theory of Gombrich (I960) does not take illusion to involve false
belief (see Gombrich (1973) for elucidation). But I shall discuss the attribution to Plato
only of the cruder 'illusion' view.
Mimesis 121
they pay is not that they cannot access the content of what is repres-
ented. So representation, does not entail illusion. If Plato held blankly
that in all paintings mimesis is a matter of inculcating illusions, then he
held a crude and implausible theory.
A second illusionistic interpretation would have it that Plato deliber-
ately limits the discussion to that sub-category of painting manifested
in the tale of the painters, Zeuxis and Parrhasius—one of whom painted
grapes so realistic that the birds pecked at them, only to be trumped by
his rival, who fooled him by painting a curtain seemingly in front of
one of his pictures, but actually part of the picture. Some have main-
tained that Plato is criticizing a change towards illusionistic styles Oc-
curring during his lifetime, in contrast with more conservative modes
of painting of which he approves.*14 But there is no-good evidence for
this view.45 The only relevant technique that Plato shows any interest
in is that of sMagrapMa, literally 'shadow-painting', which used small
areas of contrasting colour, distinctly visible when viewed from close-
up but not when viewed at a distance. Impressionism or PointilMsrn
seem to be £he nearest modern approximations, and by analogy with
these the point of interest for Plato must be that what were 'really*
diverse blobs or strokes could come to 'appear as* a homogeneous
surface or a depicted object if viewed from far enough away.46 He is,
accordingly, suspicious of skiagraphia and prone to use it as a vivid
example—sometimes purely in metaphor—of something which puts up
an appearance that closer consideration reveals to be false.47 It is fair to
say that Plato treats skiagraphia as a genuinely illusionistic or trompe
44
A view put forward by SchuM, and Steven,
45
See Demand, esp. 17 ft; and Keuls. There is no clear indication of what style Plato
would be contrasting 'illusionism' with. Some of the identifiable 'illusionist' techniques
may have been well established by his day, rater than being innovations that could be
contrasted with 'more consecutive* art. And Plato generally seams more interested in
illusionistic painting as an example of illusion rather than as a style of painting. Zeuxis
is one of the few painters Plato refers to by tame—but these references (Gorg, 453c—
d, Prat. 318h—c, the latter calling him Zeuxippos (see Keuls, 90)) merely treat Win as
the standard example of a well-known painter, and criticize neither him nor any style of
painting,
* Two references to skiagraphia outside the Republic indicate this: farm. 165c—d,
and Tht. 2§&: Tin for all the world like a man looking at a shadow-painting; when I'm
close up to it 1 can't take it in in the least, though when J stood well back from it, it
appeared to me to have some meaning.* Later in Book 10 skiagraphia is said to exercise
a kind of 'wizardry* that exploits the mind's propensity to succumb to optical illusions
(602dl-3).
47
Cf. Rep. 523a10-b6 (skiagraphia comes to Glaucoo's mind as an example where
'perception does not achieve a sensible result*); and 365c4, 583b5, 586JJ8, where
skiagraphia is a metaphor for something deceptive. Laws 663c2 is another example.
122 Mimesis
foe/I style of painting. But does he limit mimlsis to this narrow genre?
If so, then the second broad objection to Book 10 comes into play: as
Mia Annas puts it, 'Plato , , . has done nothing to show that (the poetj
imitates in the way that a trompe-l'oeil painter does',48 rendering his
case 'forced and unconvincing', because it is vastly implausible that a
Homer or Aeschylus does something analogous to inducing a false
belief in the existence of concave surfaces or real grapes.
There is no firm evidence for either of these illusionistic interpreta-
tions in the discussion of 'mimesis as a whole\45> Plato does not use the
term skiagrapkia here, only the more general word for a painter,
zographos. When he writes 'carry a mirror with you everywhere; you
will then quickly make the SUE and things in the heavens, [etc.]* (596d9-
e3), the reference to 'making' is ironic: the 'sun* in the mirror is not -
the sun, it merely has the appearance of the sun. Bat something which
has the appearance of the sun does not have to be an illusion of the sun,
The emphasis is not on whether anyone has believed that something is
there which is not, but rather on the question: What kind of thing would
you have 'made', if you held up a mirror to reality? The same point,
I argue, can be extended to the painter. The carpenter makes a bed and
'in a way the painter too makes a bed, does he not?—Yes, he does, but
only an appearing one' (596elO—11). There is simply no reason'to find
a preoccupation with illusion here. Plato might have said: 'the painter
produces not a bed, but something resembling a bed in appearance', or
'... not a bed, but a bed~seen-in~a-picture% and his point would have
been unchanged. If something is a mere appearance and not a reality,
it does not follow that it is an appearance taken for a reality. The
possibility of being deceived will be something to guard against; but,
I suggest, deceit is not built into the examples which explain 'mimesis
as a whole'.
As we saw, Plato sums up with these words: "So mimetic art is far
removed from the truth, and that is why, it seems, it can make every-
thing, because it touches only a small part of each thing, and that an
image' (598b6-8). He emphasized earlier, when discussing the mirror,
that mimesis is a capacity for making everything, in appearance at any
rate. This is an important point, which provides another argument against
48
Annas (1981), 338, 340.
* I.e., on my reading, up to 598b8. Belfiore seems right in saying "There is no ques-
tion of deception in Republic 10 until 598c, where the painter, "if he is a good painter",
is said to be able to deceive "children and fools" by showing his works "from a dis-
tance"'(1984, 128 n. 23).
Mimesis 123
the illttsionistic reading of these passages. Has anyone ever remarked
on the extreme oddity of thinking that the artist can make an illusion
of everything? Grapes and curtains hanging in front of the picture are
part of a reasonably small repertoire of trompe-l'oeil subjects. No one
seriously thinks there can be successful illusionistic renderings in paint-
ing of the entire range of animals, or of "the earth and the heavens and
the gods, all things in heaven and all things in Hades below the earth'
which Plato says the mirror-carrier 'makes', adding that the painter
belongs in the same class of makers (596e5-6). You can paint pictures
of all these things, but not in an iHusionistie manner. The all-embracing
nature of mimesis is of vital importance to Plato, as we see from his
critique of poetry. There are some people who claim that Homer and
the tragedians 'know all the crafts, all human affairs concerned with
virtue and vice, and all about the gods as well'.* Plato wants to show
that these people are wrong. Mimesis can masquerade as comprehen-
sive knowledge and can lead us to erroneous judgements about what is
good. In that way, in the case of poetry, it can give rise to false be-
liefs—and indeed, for illustrative purposes, Plato will liken such false
beliefs to visual illusions,51 He uses the loaded terminology of phan-
tasms and false images because he wants us to see the potential for
illusion and error lurking in mimesis. But that is a far cry from saying
that a painting's being a mimesis of a bed must consist in its perpetrat-
ing an illusion to which the spectator falls prey.
Plato has yet to convince us that any kind of poetry fits into the
account given of mimesis and has yet to show that, if it does, it will tfuis
be revealed as dangerous. It has been suggested that Plato is inconsist-
ent: the inclusion of poetry in mimesis would support the view that
poetry is a trivial and unimportant thing, yet Plato takes it very seri-
ously as something harmful.52 But even if it is Plato's intention to show
that poetry is 'trivial', there is no real inconsistency here. If people
devote large portions of tiheir lives to the pursuit of something trivial,
in ignorance of its triviality, that they do so is surely an important and
potentially dangerous fact
Is any poetry mimetic in the sense established? From the single
30
598d8-e2. Halliwetl suggests (1988, 111) that Socrates' irony about mimesis as a
making of everything is 4ta part directed against claims for the general wisdom and
knowledge of poets'. 'In part' strikes me as an understatement We readily think of Ion's
claim that reading Homer makes him an expert OB every subject (see Plashar, 42 a, 1).
Plato never writes of such claims in relation to painting.
51
See Rep, 598cl-4, 600e4-6Qlb4, «2c?-605c5, and Ob. 6 below.
52
Annas (1982), 11-12, and (1981), 342.
124 Mimesis
mention of any poet in the discussion of 'mimesis as a whole' (595c7-
598b8) it can look as though Plato'merely assumes without argument
that tragedy is mimetic in the right sense. Here it is:
You would call the maker of a product at two removes from nature a mimStSsI
— Absolutely.
— Hie maker of tragedies will be this too, then, given that he is a mimetes,
someone naturally third from the king and the truth, and so will all the other
mimetai.
— Probably.
— We are agreed on the mimetes. (597e3~10, ray translation.)
However, this may be read in two ways. The clause "given that he is
a mimetes [eiper mimetes erfi]' may mean either 'since the tragic poet
is a practitioner of mimesis' or *if indeed the tragic poet is a practitioner
of mimesis'. On the first reading Plato assumes without further argu-
ment that the tragic poet fits into the same mould as the painter of a
bed. This would be unfortunate, for nothing has been said to establish
that he practises mimesis in the Book 10'sense.53 However, the other
reading-—with *if54—leaves it to be established separately whether the
tragic poet does practise mimesis. This reading not only clears Plato of
an illegitimate move, it also makes much better sense of Socrates*
saying later "Next we have to examine tragedy and its leader, Homer*
(598d7—8), as if up to this point in the discussion the status of tragedy
was an open question.55 So 1 think we should not read Plato as assum-
ing without argument that tragic poetry is an instance of mimesis in the
sense he is seeking to establish in Book 10.
The next question is whether, as some have claimed,5* Plato now
53
The tragic poet is obviously a mimetic poet in the Book 3 sense of using dramatic
characterization, but that is not a matter for argument in Book 10. Plato at times finds
it natural, as at the beginning of Republic Book, 2 (373b5 ff.), to apply the classificatory
term mimetes to poets along with other performers and painters—cf. Haiti well (1988),
116. But again this does not address the issue of mimesis in the Book 10 sense.
54
LMdetl and Scott give the tost meaning of eiper as 'if really, if indeed', the second
as 'if as is the fact* or 'since*. For 'if indeed' see Reeve, in his revision of Grube's
translation. Storey and Jowett also have 'if'. Other translators go for versions of the
'since* reading (e.g. Lee (1955), Grebe (1981), Comfort (1941)). Hatliwett (1988, 116)
has "given that1, but in the commentary assumes the 'since* reading, remarking: "This
direct inference from painting to poetry is ... a weak link in the argument.* On my
reading there is no inference here, only the assertion of a conditional.
55
Also—for what it is worth—the 'if reading gives force to Socrates* sayiHg that the
maker of tragedies will be third from the truth (rather than 'is'), and to the non-committal
answer "probably* (kinduneuei). (Bnt perhaps Socrates and Glaucon are just being hesi-
tant about the 'third from She King' metaphor.)
56
See Annas (1981), 336; Cross and Wooztey, 277-8; itoelock, 24-6; Colliogwood
(1925), 166 (but repudiated by him in (1938), 46 ft),
Mimesis 125
treats all poetry as a form of mimesis. Since the opening remarks of
Book 10 mention 'such poetry as is mimetic', our answer here should
help us decide whether Plato is going to attack all poefry. If all poetry
is mimetic, all poetry will be objectionable. Before examining that
question, however, let us note that Plato's overwhelming emphasis in
Book 10 is on one specific kind of poetty: that which is dramatic, and
hence mimetic in the restricted sense established in Book 3. Later I
shall split the Book 10 discussion into four main arguments against
mimetic poetry, all of which have as their explicit targets Homer, who
is called 'the teacher and leader of all those fine tragedians' (595cl-2),
and the tragedians themselves.57 Thus in the first argument Plato states
that the maker of tragedies will be removed from truth, and calls for an
examination not of 'all poets', but simply of 'tragedy and its leader,
Homer* (597e6, 598d7-8),S8 In the second he concludes that 'the tragic
poets, whether they write in iambics or in epic verse [the metres of
tragic dialogue and Homer respectively] are mimetic to the greatest
possible extent" (602b8-10); then a third argument is launched with the
statement that mimetic poetry 'imitates people acting voluntarily or
under compulsion . . .* (603c4-5), which suggests that mimetic poetry
is essentially dramatic. And the final 'chief accusation' (605c6ff.)
concerns what happens when we 'hear Homer or some other tragedian
imitating one of the heroes sorrowing ., .*. Each of the four main
arguments, then, is aimed fairly sharply at Homer and tragedy,59
Calling these kinds of poetry mimesis can be seen to have its point,
Drama and the kind of character-writing found in Homer clearly have
something in common with painting a picture, in that the dramatist and
the epic story-teller make things we see and hear "in a way*—namely
persons and actions which are only 'appearing persons* and 'appearing
actions', not real ones. The characters of epic and tragedy exist only in
the medium of words, but their image (voice and shape) literally ap-
pears before us in the person of an actor or rhapsode. So epic and
tragedy, which qualified as poetic mimesis in Book 3, are also instances
of the wider artistic mimesis of Book 10. They are in the intersection
between 'making oneself like another in voice or form* (Book 3 mimesis)
and'artistie 'appearance-making* (Book 10 mimesis) (see Figure 1), In
51
Socrates' comment about his being denounced 'to the tragic poets and all the other
mimetic ones* (595b3—5) is vague: there is no licence to read it as referring to all poets.
58
The oofy other poets eamed in this argument are Bested, who provides a subsidiary
illustration to the points made about Homer's achievements, and Homer's obscure com-
panion Creophylus, who does him no credit as a teacher (600d6, 600b6).
5S
Cf. Grube (1935), 188, 190,
126 Mimesis
Book 3 Plato's topic was how our actions can be modeled on the
behaviour of different types of person. The guardians' emulation of the
good type of person in real life was one example, dramatic enactment
of a character was another. But we realize in Book 10 that some enact-
ment is also representation, and so- can be classified in a different way,
along with painting a picture. The sense of the term mimesis changes
between Book 3 and Book 10 without losing its reference to the same
kinds of poetry, and it is still these which Plato is most concerned to
criticize, though now predominantly from the point of view of the
audience who apprehend the representation rather than that of the per-
son who performs the enactment.
However, Plato now also speaks as if all poetry can be included in
Book 10's circle of artistic mimesis. He concludes prominently that 'all
of the poets, beginning with Homer, are imitators of images of excel-
lence [mimetas eidolon aretes] and of everything else they write about*
(6Q0e4-6), and he describes 'Homer or any other poet' as merely a
mimetes of doctors* words (599b9-c2). Other passages which seem to
treat all poetry as mimetic are 60la4-6, where 'the poet* does not
understand anything but how to perform mimesis and 603b4—7, where
'poetry* is the name given to the mimetic art (mimetike) which is
Mimesis 127
60
concerned with hearing rather than sight, Does Plato really mean that
all poets are mimetic? Given the chief target of his arguments, one
coulcl suggest that "all poets* is merely elliptical for 'all tragic and epic
poets* (mimetic poets in the Book 3 sense), and so on with the other
passages mentioned. However, this is not a very convincing suggestion,
given that the final few pages of Book 10*s discussion of poetry are
decidedly more comprehensive in scope. The "ancient quarrel' (607b5)
is between philosophy and poetry— not just something narrower called
mimetic poetry. Plato says now that poetry is to be banished (6Q7bl-
3); and he explicitly objects to 'the Muse of sweet pleasure whether in
lyrics or epic* (607a§-6), So it is hard to discount the view that in the
earlier passages, even, though focusing on. Homer and tragedy, he means
to label as mimetic 'all poets' and "poetry' without exception.
This leaves us with a problem: in virtue of what does all poetry now
qualify as mimesis! Is there something common to all poetry which
makes it analogous to the painting of a bed? Plato is not explicit about
this: his references to any poetry beyond Homer and tragedy are vague,
he does not debate the possibility of some poetry's falling outside the
Book 10 heading of mimesis,61 nor does he tackle questions about the
differences between pictorial and poetic representation. But if the dis-
cussion is to have any cohesion, he must have an. implicit reason for
regarding all poetry as a kind of mimesis: he must believe that poetry,
like painting, can 'make* everything—not really, but in image—and
that its images lay hold only of the way things appear.
Think back to Book 3 and Plato's illustration of the difference
between straight narration and narration using dramatic characters: the
same story can be told either- as a description of what Chryses did or
as a scene in which we imagine Chryses himself speaking (393cll ff.).
Plato's own descriptive re-casting of the tale from the Iliad is unpoetie
(393d8), but we can conceive of it told again using Homer's poetic
resources, though still in purely descriptive narration. Is there not a
sense in which the poet in either case will have 'made' something?
Chryses is still there in both versions, be is the same man, he has the
same daughter, he goes on the same mission with the same outcome.
Characters, things, and events are (as it were) conjured up by the poet,
m
Also 603cl, U tis poilseds mimitild—if it means 'that kind of mimlsis which is
poetiy* rather than 'the kind of poetry which is mimetic*.
61
I have previously suggested that Plato could recognize and approve poetry that was
not mimesis in the Book 10 sense (see Janaway (1991), 4). Anthony Price has convinced
me that thig claim cannot be supported.
128 Mimesis
and the difference between the two forms of narration brought to promi-
nence in Book 3 is now irrelevant So presumably what Plato thinks the
generic poet 'makes'—and here the irony that poietes means 'maker*
cannot but surface—is an imaginary scene containing characters, ac-
tions, and so forth. Poetry makes its own world, presenting before the
receptive imagination Chryses, Agamemnon, the city of Troy, the Greek
ships, the gods, battles, conversations, moral conflicts—ttius the poet
may 'make' any kind of thing without limit, but only in the way in
which a painter makes a bed.
Does the similarity rest there? Plato concludes that 'all of the poets
... are imitators of images of excellence and of everything else they
write about' (6QOe4-6). The argument for this conclusion will be dis-
cussed in Chapter 6 below, but what does the conclusion mean? To be
an 'imitator of ..." embraces being a maker of something and being a
partrayer of something.*2 So the phrase 'imitator of images* may, for
Pkto, mean someone whose product is an image, but it also implies
that the models which the imitator attempts to portray are themselves
only images. Earlier the painter not only made a 'non-real bed', but
took as model the appearance of a bed from a particular angle. If the
poet is analogously to be an 'imitator of images of excellence1, then his
or her product must be modelled, not on excellence itself (the Form),
but on excellence as it can appear in the behaviour or the traits of some
particular person or kind of person. Plato mentions that, for instance,
a poet may be 'an imitator only of doctors* words' (599c2). The poet
cannot be a doctor or do what doctors do, but can make a character who
speaks and acts in the manner of some possible doctor. Such 'convinc-
ing portrayal of character' consists, for Plato, in the poet's approximat-
ing the world within the poem to one of the many ways in which things
might appear to the audience.
So with ethical qualities the poet will know how to assimilate the
content of the poem to possible episodes of observable behaviour which
will seem to the audience those of a courageous or pious or wise person
in particular circumstances. But that, for Plato, is not knowing such
virtues themselves. Like the rhetorical manipulator of the Gorgias, the
poet will not know what excellence is, but will contrive to present
before the many a gratifying appearance of human behaviour, from
which they may falsely take themselves to be learning of excellence (or
62
See above, n. 36; also Adam, ii. 402.
Mimesis 129
6 5
the lack of it). * He will... make his imitation, without knowledge of
where good, and bad lies in each case. Instead, so it seems, it's what
appears to be good [kalon] to the ignorant masses that he will imi-
tate,*6* The audience's perspective on arete may well agree with that
of Meno, who tells Socrates:
If it is manly virtue [arett] you are after, it is easy to see that the virtue of a
man consists in managing the city's affairs capably, ... Or if you want a
woman's virtue, that is easily described. She must be a good housewife, careful
with her stores and obedient to her husband. Then there is another virtue for a
child, male or female, and another for an old man, free or slave as you like; and
a great many more kinds of virtue, so that no one need be at a loss to say what
it is. For every act and every time' of life, with' reference to each separate
function, there is a virtue for each one of us, and similarly, I should say"; a vice.
(Meno 71e2-72a5.)
Plato has in miod an audience who, like the 'lovers of sights and
sounds', will, not acknowledge even that there is a single Form of
arete—in their view, repeated acquaintance with particular episodes
which manifest this or that courage or lack of it, this or that wisdom or
lack of it, will suffice for 'knowing excellence*. There will be many
excellences and deficiencies (virtues and vices) for this audience, and
the poet will succeed if he or she gives pleasure by making recogniz-
able images of some of them,
It is in this way, I think, that we must construe Plato's implicit reason
for claiming that all poetry is a form of mimesis. Poetry will lead us to
apprehend imaginary versions of every kind of thing including people
and their actions—images whose production is merely the successful
attempt to 'convince' by simulating the myriad appearances of human
life as the mass audience understands it. Knowing excellence, by con-
trast, is a philosophical enterprise which neither turns the gratifying
image into an end in. itself, nor looks for insight from the' way virtues
variously appear in different human circumstances. Arete itself is 'an
eternal and unvarying object of intellection, which poetry and poetry's
audience neither comprehend.nor even try to comprehend. Again Plato
suffers less from a radical misconception about poetry than, from his
severe and outlandish conception of what qualifies as knowledge. One
powerful reply to Plato—outlined in Chapter 8 below—begins with the
63
Compare" Gorg, 464dS-e2, 459dl-el and Rep. S98b8-e4 , 6QOe4-601bl.
64
602b, HaUiwell's translation.
130 Mimesis
thought that there is a knowledge that is best acquired from imaginative
engagement with images of human beings in the particularity of their
actions and feelings.65
Another difficulty in the Book 10 discussion is that despite the ap-
parentty comprehensive critique of poetry, Plato nevertheless keeps some
poetry in the city: 'Homer is most poetic and , . . stands first among the
tragedians, but you must know for sure that hymns to the gods and
eulogies of good men are the only poetry which we can admit' (607a2-
•5). For Plato to be consistent, the hymns and eulogies in his ideal city
must escape his criticisms. Are they mimetic? Are they poetry? If they '
count as poetry and as mimetic, and if all mimetic poetry is to be
banished, Plato's retention of them leaves the whole discussion in a
hopelelsly ragged state. The suggestion has been made that the hymns
and eulogies do not count as poetry for Plato.6* That is one way to make
him consistent. However, the idea that what remains in the model city
could not seriously be termed poetry betrays a highly questionable
assumption that Plato approves only of what is dull. The sacred works
of Palestrina probably contain nothing to which Plato would object, and
the motet Nuper rosarum fiores by Guillaume Dufay—which marked
the consecration of Florence cathedral by the Pope, setting to music
of great beauty and perfect proportions a text that refers to the act of
consecration and its eminent executor—would not be out of place'on a
similar occasion in the model city. There is no correlation between our
regarding something as high art and Plato's not liking it. Nor should we
disregard the simple point that he calls his hymns and eulogies the only
sort of poetry that he will accept in the city (607a4-5). As Collingwood
remarks, when Socrates says this, 'no character is made to protest: "But
was not all poetry to be excluded?"'67—which makes it look as if
banishment for all poetry never was proposed. If this is an anomaly, it
would be tedious to make too much of it: the essential point is to
exclude any poetry subservient to 'the Muse of sweet pleasure' (607a5).
65
I am echoing Nussbaurn's comments: 'Certain truths about human experience can
best be teamed by living them in their particularity,... But we cannot all live ... through
all that we ought to know in order to live well. Here literature, with its stories and images,
enters in as an extension of our experience, encouraging us to develop and understand our
cognitive/emotional responses* (1986, 186).
* Annas remarks 'Plato is enough of a creative artist himself to know that such pro-
ductions are not real poetry* (1981, 344)—(hough it is surely unclear what 'real poetry'
is, especially to Plato.
67
Collingwood (1938), 48.
Mimesis 131
The hymns and eulogies will not necessarily be judged 'most poetic' by
standards that have prevailed hitherto, because they aim to benefit the
citizens, not simply to please them. But they will still be poetry,
However, difficulties remain. If all mimetic poetry is banished, the
hymns and eulogies cannot be mimetic. Yet if they are not mimetic,
how can all poetry be mimetic? Again, I doubt whether we should press
these questions too hard. The truth is that Plato wanders in Ms descrip-
tions of the poetry he criticizes. Sometimes it is 'all poetry*, sometimes
Homer and the tragedians, sometimes something called 'mimetic poetry*,
sometimes the kind of poetry whose aim, is pleasure. Late in the discus-
sion he rejects 'mimesis' and "poetry that aims at pleasure' all in one
breath: he pros Mdonen poietike kai M mimesis,6® a phrase which may
be read as the single idea 'poetic mimesis designed for pleasure' or as
'all poetry which aims at pleasure, including mimetic poetry*. The lat-
ter reading is possible because poetry's aiming at pleasure (rather than
the good) would be sufficient objection regardless of whether or not it
was a kind of mimesis. But the single idea of 'poetic mimesis designed
for pleasure* takes us closer to the heart of Plato's worries.
For once again Ms greatest concern is with the governing aims of
different kinds of poetry. We saw that the beneficial style of'poetry in
Book 3 could use mimesis, but was not allowed to be 'mimetic* in its
motivation. Now again there is one sense in which Plato's favoured
hymns and eulogies will not be 'mimetic': they will not privilege the
aim of appearance-making, of conjuring up a world of persons and
things for the imagination. If appearance-making in itself is one's aim,
one may endlessly delight the human soul. But this, as ever, cuts across
the Platonic project of improving the soul and attuning it more closely
to the truth. Plato might easily think (though he does not say) that even
his hymns and eulogies, being poefry, would use imaginative appearance-
making. What better way to honour a great, departed citizen in words
and song man to make Ms bearing, Ms speech, and Ms actions as
vividly present as possible? But what matters most is that the poetry
of the city shall never regard imaginative appearance-making and its
pleasures as autonomous ends.
Finally, before we turn to Plato's arguments against mimetic poetry,
let us note that he does not seek to banish painting from the model
68
607c4-5. Halliwell (1988, 69, 155) treats the Greek phrase as a hcndiadys: "poetic
mimesis designed for pleasure*. I agree with Halliwell that the mimesis meant here is not
mimesis in general: 'Plato's earlier interest in visual mimesis has now- been put aside.'
132 Mimesis
9
city.* He has been disparaging about painting, but his aim in discussing
it is to reach an. understanding of 'mimesis as a whole*, as part of the
attempt to show the true nature of mimetic poetry. While he announces
clearly at the beginning that mimetic poetry is Ms target, and ends by
banishing poets—except for the beneficial eulogizers—he says neither
that painting is dangerous nor that he will exclude it from the model
city. And the reason is plain: in Plato's experience of it, painting' nei-
ther masquerades falsely as knowledge, nor corrupts our moral judge-
ments by the appeal it makes to the emotions.70 Poetry does both—or
so the arguments of the sequel will attempt to show,
* This view is supported by e.g. Mehamas (1982), 47-8; Keuls, eh. 2; Urmson (1982),
136; Belftbre (1983), 49, Even so, Plato's hostility to painting may be variously assessed.
We need not treat everything said of Sic painter as merely illustrative of points about
poetry, as implied by e.g. Havelock. 32, Demand finds an 'attack against the painter in
full swing' (8). And, ob¥iou,sly, if there is a critique of 'representational (mimetic) art as
a whole* (HaUiwell (1988), 6), it will be a critique of painting too.
'° Ferrari seems in line with Plato's view: 'A poetic performance ... engages its
participants ... in the whole "feel" of the human action it portrays ... a caavas on a wall
tends to invite sustained and relatively detached meditation rather than sympathetic par-
ticipation in the portrayed scene* (1989, 109).
6
1
Rep. 598b8-c4. My translation, partly based on that of Shorey.
134 Against Mimetic Poetry
images of? The earlier 'painter of a bed* did not (or need not) under-
stand the craft of carpentry, because he was making an image of a bed
and not a real bed. That is fully intelligible. But the 'painter of crafts-
men' is making an image of a craftsman—why then is Ms lack of
ability to make beds, or shoes, at all to the point?
1 believe there is a satisfactory answer to these questions, Plato is not
now explaining the nature of mimesis in general. We do not have to
regard all the features of this 'example' as intended to .be typical, of
painterly activity, or as defining features of mimesis. At this point Plato
enters the second stage of his argument, in which poetry specifically is
to be scrutinized. That may seem to stretch incredulity even further,
since Plato does not mention poetry or poets at all in the passage
quoted. But the same example returns later, with a reference back to its
first occurrence, and this time Plato leaves us in no doubt as to its point:
Shall we then lay it down that all of the poets, beginning with Homer, are
mimetai of images of excellence and of the other things about which they make
poetry, and that they do not lay hold on truth, but as we were just now saying,
the painter will make what looks like a cobbler, even though he understands
nothing of the cobbler's craft and nor does his audience, whose perception
depends only on the shapes and colours? ... In this way, I think, we will say
that the poet, understanding nothing but how to mimeisthai, lays on with words
and phrases the colours of the several crafts so that other such people whose
perception depends, on his words think—whether someone speaks in rhythm,
metre, or harmony about cobbling or generalship or anything whatever—that
he speaks extremely well.2
2
600e4—601bl. This translation is also partly based on Shorey, but owes a lot to
Haffiwelt (1988).
3
HalliwelTs view (1988, 120) seems just right: 'Plato is using the extreme case of
visual illusion as a blatantly rhetorical means of preparing the ground for his main
argument—-that poetry is falsely credited with a standing {that of ethical wisdom etc.)
which it has no claim to,*
Against Mimetic Poetry 135
prophets, charioteers, doctors—exponents of a techne. So when Plato
talks of the poet 'laying on with words and phrases the colours of the
several technai' this is part of what he means: using language, the poet
can create a character which me audience accepts as possessing any of
the many brands of human expertise. But, as Plato suggests, in addition
the poet's characters may have, acquire, or be seeking understanding of
the goods and evils of human life and of the ways of the gods: they are
locatable somewhere on the spectrum of ethical knowledge. Enmeshed
with the analogy between the poet and the "painter of craftsmen*, a
more familiar analogy is also at work: having ethical knowledge is
analogous with possessing a techne, and so making poetic characters
who appear to possess ethical knowledge is analogous with making
characters who appear to be exponents of a techne. The painted images
of cobbler, carpenter 'and the other craftsmen* are included, I suggest,
wholly for the sake of analogy and correspond in this way to the char-
acters who appear in poetry, displaying to us what we take for virtues
(or the lack of them).
What then of the other questions we posed about the "painter of
craftsmen' analogy? What is the interest of the mistakes of fools and
children? And of what import is the painter's ignorance of the crafts of
those 'he portrays? The point is that poets who write of generals and
rulers and charioteers do so in ignorance of any of these areas of human'
expertise; and in like manner (as Plato sees it) poets who write of
human goods and evils do so while lacking ethical knowledge. To
make a successful poetic character, Plato is saying, it no more takes
knowledge of the truths about value in human life, than it takes exper-
tise in shoemaking to make
make a convincing visual image of a cobbler.
This is Ms fundamental point. The fools and children are analogous to
those people who do not realize this—those who believe, falsely, that
poets themselves have knowledge of every conceivable kind.4 The
analogy is thus slightly off-centre. Fools and children mistake a painted
image at a distance for a real thing. Those who ascribe knowledge to
poets do not mistake Homer's characters for real persons; what they do
is mistake the poet for a really knowledgeable person. Plato's rhetorical
point is that this mistake puts those who perpetrate it on a par with the
children and fools of the analogy.
Eead this way, the analogy embodies a mismatch between (in the
case of the 'painter of craftsmen') mistaking an image of a person for
s
An alternative reading of the analogy has been offered by Elizabeth Belflore (1983).
Belflore agrees that the mistake Plato alleges about poetic mimesis is not that of falling
under the illusion of taking mere images for real things. But she also argues that in the
illustrative half of the analogy, the 'painter of craftsmen* image, the mistake of the fools
and children *is not about ontology, but about a craft, carpentry* (44-5), and that the
mistake made is, ia both halves, 'veridical'—wrongly taking the content of painting
(carpenfty) and poetry (arete) for true. This reading makes the analogy sttucturally more
perfect than the one I propose. However, for some critical comments see Janaway (1991),
6-7.
Against Mimetic Poetry 137
person knows, only more accurately, then it is likely that $ is
simple-minded, and has been deceived by a magician and mimetes,
because of an inability to distinguish knowledge, ignorance, and
mimesis (598c7—d5).
Plato continues with the remark, 'Next we roust examine tragedy and
its leader, Homer'.6 The point is that there are people who stand in just
this relation to these poets:
2, We hear from some people that Homer and the tragedians know
all the technai, and all things, human and diYine, pertaining to
excellence and evil (598dS~e2),
Plato would expect us to infer:
3, It is likely that the people making the claim of knowledge for
these poets are simple-minded, and have been deceived by a
magician and mimetes, because of their own inability to distin-
guish knowledge, ignorance, and mimesis,
The final conclusion Plato is aiming for is that Homer and -the tra-
gedians are nothing but mimetai, that they make only an image of the
appearance of certain things, and hence are 'removed from truth*. But
first he has to deal with the, argument used by the friends of the poets,
which is as follows:
4, (i) Homer and the tragedians are good poets (make poetry finely).
(ii) A necessary condition for the ability to make (good) poetry
about a subject-matter X is knowledge of X.
(iii) Therefore, for any subject which Homer and the tragedians
make poetry about, they must have knowledge of that subject
(598e3-5).
Sometimes the views expressed in this little argument 4 (i)-(iii) are
attributed to Plato himself,7 despite the fact that he attacked an almost
identical position in the Ion, and despite the fact that the overall argu-
ment works only if this is the reasoning of Plato's opponents. (He asks
6
S98d?~S: This is the first explicit proposal, since the topic of "mimesis as a whole'
was broached (595c7), to examine poetry specifically; and note that not all poetry is
included at this point,
7
e.g. Nussbauai (1982), 84; Collingwood (1938), 49, Attain (it 396-7) is clear, on the
other hand, that this is a view Plato is attacking, as are Hall well (1988), 45, 121, and
Osborne, 59-60. For Grebe (1935, 190 a. 3), Plato agrees with 'the ordinary Greek view*
that good poets have full knowledge, but 'does not agree that the so-called "good poets"
like Homer have any such knowledge". But Plato does not regard Homer as merely a 'so-
called' good poet, nor does he share the 'ordinary* view he goes on to argue against!
138 Against Mimetic Poetry
shortly 'whether there is something in what they say, and in truth good
poets do have knowledge*—only to deny that there is anything in what
they say.) Furthermore, if 4 (i)-(iii) constituted Plato's own view, he
would have to say that Homer is not a good poet. But he nowhere
disputes Homer's claim to be a good poet, recognizes him as 'most
poetic' {poietikotatos, 607a2), and expresses reluctance to criticize him
(S9Sb9~c3). (This also parallels a feature of the 'painter of craftsmen'
analogy: it is if the painter 'is a good painter* that some people may be
misled on seeing Ms work.)
So far, then, we have two views about the status of the poets, and
Plato now offers to decide between them. He states the issue with
complete precision. It is: whether the friends of the poets
have met with mimetai and been deceived, and on seeing their works do not
perceive them to be twice removed from what is and easy to make for someone
who does not know the truth—-for it is appearances not real things that Aey
make—or whether there is something in what they say, and in truth good poets
do have knowledge of the things about which they seem to speak weB to the
many. (598e5-599a4.)
Plato does not deny 4 (i). Instead, he attacks 4 (ii) and (iii) with two
counter-arguments. The first is as follows:
5. (i) If anyone was able to produce both some real product X and
images of X, then they would prefer to produce X.
(ii) If Homer and the tragedians had knowledge enabling them to
produce what they make images about, then they would not
have chosen to make images about it,
(iii) But Homer and the tragedians chose to make images or
appearances, not real things.
(iv) Therefore, Homer and the tragedians have no knowledge of
the kind of real things they make poetry about (599a6—b8).
5 (iii) is Plato's own premiss.8 It can safely be taken for granted that,
qua poet, Homer makes appearances or images of things. The question
is: what kind of ability does making them require? The argument 5 (i)—
(iv) is valid. But, if 5 (iii) is uncontentious, 5 (i)—also Plato's own
premiss—is not. Plato has no right to the assumption that poetry is an
activity of such obviously low value. The upshot of his whole argument
might be that poetry is worthless, but he should not assume that en
8
Cf. the parenthetical remark "for it is appearances not real things that they make' at
599a2-3.
Against Mimetic Poetry 139
route. So the first counter-argument against, the friends of the poets is
not convincing.
The second counter-argument to show that good poets do not require
knowledge is a brief survey of the empirical evidence concerning the
achievements of poets, mainly those of Homer,
6. (i) There is no evidence of Homer (or any poet) exercising abil-
ities in medicine, generalship, government or education.
(ii) Anyone who had such abilities to offer would not have been
allowed by their communities to "go about rhapsodizing* like
Homer and Hesiod. (In other words, there would have been
evidence of their exercising these abilities, if they had had
them.)
(iii) Therefore, the poets all lack knowledge and are mere mimetai
(599b9-600e3).
This argument is no stronger. The supposed survey of evidence is based
on (to put it mildly) too small a sample, and one could no doubt easily
supply counter-instances where a poet has had some of the abilities
mentioned. The second premiss is again dubious because it begs the
question, attributing Plato's own low evaluation of poetry to the com-
munities in which poets have lived.
However (especially for readers of the Ion and the Gorgias), it is act
difficult to see that good poetry does not require knowledge, and all
Plato needs, to show this, is one clear example where a good poet's
work springs from no first-order knowledge of his subject-matter. If
Homer is a good poet and lacked the knowledge in question, then such
knowledge cannot be a necessary condition of successful poetic image-
making. Plato appears at times to think he has shown that poets cannot
have knowledge of what they make poetry about. What is more con-
vincing is that they do not need such knowledge as a condition of
making good poetry, that any knowledge a good poet were to have
about X would be coincidental, and would not account for the goodness
of Ms or her poetry about X—the reason being that good poetry is
a form of good image-making, in Plato's sense, and nothing more,
The poet's words conjure up an image of a sorrowing or jealous or
cowardly person, of a person deciding what it is right, to do or bowing
before what honour dictates, and so on. Success ia this enterprise can
be no more—Plato alleges—than satisfying the audience, who lack
knowledge of good and evil (vouchsafed, remember, only to philoso-
phers who can grasp Forms), with a sfretch of fictional behaviour they
140 Against Mimetic Poetry
can accept as a credible portrayal. Success in the poet's enterprise does
not, then, require the poet to have knowledge of good and evil either.
Plato brings home Ms conclusion in the way we discussed earlier:
the good poet is analogous to the ignorant 'painter of craftsmen*, who
is nevertheless a good painter. Even if poets are not necessarily igno-
rant, the analogy holds. The convincing appearances of persons know-
ledgeable in various ways—the characters poets make—are liable to
give rise to false beliefs about the poets' own capabilities. The beliefs
that the poets* knowledge is compendioas, and. that knowledge of X is
a necessary condition for making good "poetry about X, can be shown
to be false. Given the fact that these false beliefs are held, together with
Plato's premiss I concerning the likely cause of such beliefs, there is
a coherent case for concluding that Homer and the tragedians are
mimetai. Their ability, in other words, is just an ability to make images
of the way things of certain kinds appear, and is not essentially fed by
knowledge. Homer and the tragedians (and all poets, Plato says) are in
this sense 'removed from truth*.
Plato rubs salt in the wound by saying that because the poets know
nothing except how to make appearances, but are thought to speak well
about many topics, their activity must be one of 'enchantment* (kelisis,
601bl). It is the metre, rhythm, and harmony, or what Plato now refers
to as poetry's 'musical colours' (601b2), which spellbind the audience,
blinding them to the ignorance from which the poetry really steins.
Strip these colours away from poems, and 'you know what they look
like*, says Socrates. (I think of Tolstoy's hilarious 'stripped-down'
narration of Wagner's Ring; "Three Noms plait a golden rope and talk
about the future. They go away. Siegfried and Brlinahilda appear.
Siegfried takes leave of her, gives her the ring, and goes away [etc.].*)*
What is. left of poetry without its superficial means of 'enchantment* is
bald and banal, like the plain faces, of those who have lost their youth
and with it their only attraction (601b6-7).
The second epistemological argument against mimetic poetry (601b9—
602bll) is what we may call the 'user/maker* argument. This is distinct
from what went before, and alleges that the mimetes of any thing has
neither knowledge nor true belief about it. Plato returns to a general
point about mimesis, illustrated by reference to another painter, who
this time paints a horse's reins and bit. In contrast with the saddler and
bronzesmith who would make the real reins and bit, the painter—of
9
Tolstoy, 2J2,
Against Mimetic Poetry 141
course—does not understand how the reins and bit should be. But then
Socrates suggests that "not even the maker of them, the broBzesmith
and saddler, understand that, but only the person who knows how to
use these things, the rider.'10 It is like this with everything, he contin-
ues: there are three technai, one which uses the thing, one which makes
it, and one which imitates it. And only the user of something has
knowledge of how it should be, that is, of the thing's 'excellence and
fineness and Tightness', also of its 'deficiency*,11 The maker is com-
pelled to consult the user, and thereby acquires a correct belief about
the excellences and deficiencies of reins and bits, or flutes, or anything.
The point is supposed to stretch to 'every artefact, creature, and activ-
ity*: for everything, the criterion of its being fine, excellent, or right is
what use it has (6Gld4-6), aad only the thing's user will know what
it takes to have an excellent thing of a particular kind. As a general
principle this seems unlikely. Even allowing that everything has a 'use',
many things do not have the kind of expert users who have superior
understanding of excellences and deficiencies. The beds and tables from
the earlier discussion are a case in'point.12 One even suspects that the
majority of things we use have excellences and deficiencies which it
takes a designer or producer to point out I may understand why a thing
is excellent for my purposes without knowing much about it at all.
(Think of computers.) Another possible worry is that in the previous
argument the maker of a bed could 'look to* the Form. If that entails
knowing what makes some particular bed a good one (which is not
clear), then it is odd that now the maker has only true belief.
However, the passage at least asserts a more refined charge against
mimetic poetry. We might have swallowed the previous argument that
Homer lacks knowledge of the various technai and of human excel-
lence, but still think him and Ms colleagues useful for getting tihings
right in a way which fell, short of knowledge—mimetic poets may have
and communicate true beliefs, for all that Plato has said. His real inter-
est now is in the claim that mimetic artists have neither knowledge
nor true belief about the excellences and deficiencies of what they
represent." Painting reveals that making the appearance of musical
instruments, riding tackle, and so on, demands neither knowledge nor
16
60lcll-13, translation by Halliwell (1988),'
11
arete, katlos, orthotis (601d4), poneria (6Q2a9).
" Halliwelt's point (1988, 129). For other difficulties, see ibid. 129-31, and Annas
(1981), 337.
13
See 602a§-9 for exactly this claim.
142 Against Mimetic Poetry
true belief about the excellences and deficiencies of such objects. That
is surely true. So will it not also be true that the mimetic poet, who
makes only images of persons and actions, requires neither knowledge
nor tree belief about the genuine nature of excellence and deficiency?
If so, Plato continues, the mimetic poet will be altogether lacking in
wisdom (sophia, 602all—13) concerning the things he writes about, but
will not let that prevent him composing, for what he represents will be
guided instead—reiterating a point from the previous- argument—by
'what appears fine to the multitude who themselves know nothing'
(602bl-4—cf. 601a4-9).
At the end of the 'user/maker' argument Plato's epistemological
charges against mimetic poetry are complete:
We have a reasonable agreement that the mimetic practitioner knows nothing
significant on the subjects of Ms imitation, but that mimesis is a game and not
a serious matter; and that those who put their hand to tragic poetry, whether in
iambics or in hexameters, are all mimetic practitioners par excellence.u
The claim that Plato has made, then, is that the tragedians and Homer
are practitioners of mimesis, making only images of the way things
appear, and that as such they lack both knowledge and true belief
concerning anything they write about. They are good poets only be-
cause their use of metre, rhythm, and harmony succeeds,in enchanting
their audience. If their poetry has any value, it is only that of a pleasing
game. Poetry itself does not have any serious ethical or educational,
weight. A prevailing theory that would counter this says that the ability
to make good poetry must stem from knowledge of its chosen subject-
matter. But this theory is false, and to accept it is to have been duped
by a kind of 'magic*—the pleasure which Ine poetry is capable of
inducing. Plato's position is not substantially different here from what
it was in the Ion and the Gorgias. The difference is that he can now
claim to have developed, in the main body of the Republic, a positive
account of what it is to achieve knowledge, and of the pursuits which
do have ethical and educational weight.
The theme of 'enchantment' runs throughout the Book 10 discussion
of poetry. Scholars have pointed out a number of allusions here to
Gorgias* doctrine of the power of language.15 For example, when Plato
writes that the defenders of Homer have probably 'been deceived by
I4
.602b6-10 (HalliwelTs translation).
15
See Pohlenz, 463 ff,; Flashar, 68-72, H I ; Be-More (1983), 59 n. 32; Verdenius
(1983), 30; HaliiweU (1938),-128.
Against Mimetic Poetry 143
some magician and imitator they have met, into the opinion that he
is all-wise','* the sentence is packed with Gorgianie words: goites,
exapatan, doxa—magician, deceive, opinion. It may not be too fanciful
to see a link with Gorgias in Socrates' opening announcement that he
will provide an antidote to mimetic poetry. The antidote is apharmakon,
the word Gorgias uses when he compares the action of a speech to that
of a drug.17 Socrates' pharmakon is then a drug against a drug. Later
he says in the same vein that we should repeat the troth about poetry
to,ourselves as a constant charm to ward off its spell (608a3-5). Plato
apparently agrees with Gorgias that speech, when used by mimetic
poetry, drags and bewitches the soul. But whereas for Gorgias this was
the only option—charming the soul and bending opinion was all that
any speech could do—Plato contrasts this effect of speech with differ-
ent practices (reasoning and discovering truth) that involve another part
of the soul. Hence the other opening remark that the dangerous nature
of mimetic poetry can be more clearly revealed 'now that the parts of
the soul have each been separately described*.
There follow two psychological arguments against mimetic poetry,
which I shall call the "conflicting attitudes' argument (602cl-605c5)
and the 'greatest charge* argument (605e6~606d7). They capitalize on
earlier passages in the Republic, where Plato argued that each human
soul has an internal structure and is not a unity. Conflicting attitudes
such as desires can be explained, he claimed, as originating in distinct
"parts' or aspects of the self.18 There is the reasoning part, with which
we desire to think rationally and gain knowledge, there is the part
which has appetites for things such as food and drink and sex, and there
is the 'spirited' or emotional part 'with which we become angry', and
which seeks honour and victory. The Republic's most important single
idea is that justice comes about, in the individual as much as in the city,
when each of the parts which constitute the whole performs its own
function, not seeking to usurp the functions of the others. In a healthy
soul, the reasoning part rules, taking thought for the overall good of the
individual and setting criteria for which of the appetitive desires is
followed; the spirited, irascible part allies itself with the reasoning part.
19
571M—d4 (Book. 9). The allusion to Oedipus seems to prepare the way for the
critique of tragedy in Book 10. Gould makes much of this connection, and thinks that
Plato's remark about 'not refraining from any kind of food' may allude to the tragic
figure Thyesfcs, who eats his own children at a banquet (see p. xviii, 30).
20
Moline, esp. 6-14, brings out this point. See also Annas (1981), 131, 142-6.
21
Bumyeat's succinct remark is helpful: *it is as mistaken to suppose the lower two
parts of the soul incapable of thought or judgement as it is to deny desires and pleasures
to the top part' (1976, 35 n. 22). See 580d3-581c6. (each part has its kind of pleasure and
desire; each is predominantly a lover of something); 5?lc3-d4 (in sleep the 'animal' part
of us autonomously exercises desires and experiences pleasure); 574d5-5?5a6 (ethical
beliefs are overwhelmed in the individual by the beliefs of his lustful part); 442clO-dl
(an individual has sopkrosune (self-control) when "all the parts hold a common opinion
that reason should rote*). See also Irwin (1977a), 191-2, 195; Lovibond, 36 ff.; Penaer
(1971), 100-3; Moline, 10-12.
Against Mimetic Poetry 145
esteem which having it would bring. If I seek out and take pleasure in
something and at the same time wish to avoid it, then I am not, for
explanatory purposes, merely one thing,22
So the question is: What in a human being does mimesis relate to
when it exercises its power? (6G2e4-5). Mimesis is 'at third remove
from the trath*,23 so it can hardly be the wisdom-loving logistikon, the
part "by which we learn', that mimesis engages. To illustrate a split in
the soul here, Plato reverts'to painting, and explicitly discusses visual
illusions:
The same magnitude does not appear to our sight to be the same size when we
look at it from nearby or from a distance.,. And the same things seem crooked
when we sec them in water and straight when we see them out of it; the same
things appear concave or convex because our eyes are confused by colours, and
every confusion of this kind clearly exists in our soul. Skiagmphia relies upon
this weakness in our nature and is nothing short of bewitchment {gaeteia}; so
does conjuring and other such trickery, (602c7-d4.)
That we succumb to optical illusions does not itself illustrate that the
soul is split into parts. But now follows the crucial point: at the same
time we are able to use measuring, counting, and weighing, which work
against the tendency to believe that we see a genuinely bent stick, 01
a genuinely concave surface among the painted scenery, and so on.
These activities are the function of the logistikon, the calculating or
rational part of the soul (6Q2d6-e2). The basic argument here is as
follows:
1, It is impossible for the same thing to hold opposed beliefs about
the same object at the same time.
2, We believe at the same time (e.g.) that we see a. flat surface and
that we see objects with depth.
3, Therefore, two distinct parts of us must hold these two beliefs,
Brushing aside the most obvious philosophical worry—whether this
type of illusion, involves false belief24—we can understand how Plato,
arriving at the view that there is complexity within the soul, must
22
Plato's example of Leontius being angry with himself for wanting to look at dead
bodies (Rep. 439e7—440a6) raises an interesting question; are we considering conflicting
attitudes directed towards a single object, or a conflict between, say, a desire and an
aversion to that desire? (See Irwin (1977a), 191—2.) This distinction lurks under the
surface of Book 10's discussion of attitudes to grief.
23
The point reiterated at 602cl-2, just before the question of parts of the soul is
addressed.
24
Raised by Haffiweil (1988), 134,
146 Against Mimetic Poetry
locate the propensity to error ia 'one of the inferior elements, in us'
(603a7-8). Being duped could hardly be. the function of a better part of
us. The most obvious way to take the division in the soul here is. as a
split between the logistikon and part of the soul distinct from the
logistikon,15 Then the argument continues more or less as follows:
4. It is the function of the logistikon to correct our beliefs by apply-
ing the standards of measurement and calculation.
5. Therefore, it is the function of something other than the logistikon
to believe that depth is perceived, even when the conrect belief
(that we see a. flat surface) has been arrived at by measurement
and calculation.
Having reached the idea tiiat some "inferior part of us' is in play,
Socrates makes one of his rudest pronouncements about the arts,
saying:
Painting, and mimetic art [he mimitike] as a whole, produces a work that is far
from, the truth; it consorts with a part of ourselves that is far from intelligence
and is its companion and friend for no healthy or (rue purpose.... Mimetic art,
being an inferior thing and having intercourse with something inferior, pro-
duces inferior offspring.1*
25
The view of e.g. Adam, ii. 408, 466-7; Crombie, i. 146, and probably the majority
view (although among those who hold it there is no consensus about whether it makes
for coherence or not—foe contrasting assessments, see Annas (1981), 338—9, and Belflore
(1983), 50-6). A minority view is that the logistikon itself has two contrary attitudes and
is split into two parts (sec Nehamas (1982), 64-4, and Murphy, 239-41, criticized by
HaUiwdl (1988), 134).
m
603al0~b4. My translation, adapted from Grebe's.
Against Mimetic Poetry 147
right to Ms conclusion that all mimesis appeals to an inferior part of
us, or his overall theory of mimesis is the implausible illusion view.
It may be that Plato makes no distinction between 'appearance of X*
and 'illusion of X*. This would not be surprising since Ms terminology
for both is the same. (What we earlier translated as 'the appearance of
a bed' was phainomene Mine, literally *an appearing bed'. When he
talks of illusions it is to phainomenon meizon e elatton, literally 'the
appearing larger or smaller*, or 'what appears larger and smaller*.) If
mimesis always makes only 'appearances', and if there is an inferior
part of the soul which is prone to believe in 'appearances' that are at
variance with measurement, it may look as if we need no farther argu-
ment for the conclusion that mimesis always appeals to the inferior part
of the soul. But take images of people in mimetic drama or in an
ordinary non-illusionistic painting: if we are able to gaze on these without
the kind of conflict of beliefs that Plato explains by invoking the soul's
different parts, then there is no direct argument yet for the conclusion
that these works as such—mainstream examples of mimesis—appeal to
an inferior part of the soul,
We discover, however, that the attack on mimetic poetory is not really
furthered by Socrates* general disparagement of mimesis. For he says
immediately that we must not trust the comparison with painting, but
must give a separate account of mimetic poetry. The ensuing argument
against mimetic poetry does not rely on the analogy with visual illu-
sions:27 It has nothing to do with illusions as such, and everything to do
with conflicts of attitudes of a different kind. The vicissitudes of life
give plenty of opportunity for 'internal dissension* within the soul
(603d2—3). One's child dies-—Plato's example. One feels intense grief
and has the desire to lament endlessly, to abandon oneself to sorrow.
But one also has the desire to act rationally, to do what is for the best.
This can be-used to show another split in the soul. Simple, unreflective
expression of grief is one attitude towards a death. But one may take
a different attitude to it, reflecting that the value of such events is never
clear-cut, and mat the importance of anything human is not very great
(604blO-cl). Moreover, one may challenge one's own desire to in-
dulge in ^ieving, and, while still having that deske, seek also, at least
in public, to moderate one's grieving, subordinating it to other concerns
rather than submitting to it One has two conflicting attitudes, then,
27
As emphasized by Adam, ii. 408-9, and Hailiwell (1988), 136—the latter against
Annas' claim (1981, 339} that toe present analogy with painting is by itself supposed to
'prove" something about poetry.
148 Against Mimetic Poetry
towards one's own propensity for violent and prolonged expression of
grief, pulled one way by rational desires for the good, another way by
the grief itself.2* By analogous reasoning to that used before, there must
here be two parts of the soul, there is a part of us which calculates,
deliberates,2* and (metaphorically now) measures our behaviour.30 An-
other part, which Plato calls 'irritable' and 'variegated*,31 behaves like
a child crying and hugging its own wound (6Q4e8-9) and gives in
uncritically to emotion. The part which seeks to moderate grief and act
always in a consistent manner, calmly seeking the best according to
'reason,* and "custom*, is the familiar Iffgistikxm, the superior rational
part which governs in. a healthy soul. However we read the analogy
with visual illusions, the two cases of conflict have a common feature:
the desito to indulge the disorderly, childish part of IK persists despite
rational judgement to the contrary, just as we continue to fall prey to
optical illusions however well-established our correcting beliefs may
be.32 It is this pertinent observation about two cases of conflicting
attitudes which gives a solid core to the otherwise rather troubled
analogy,
But now the most important question is: How can the conflict of
attitudes towards grief and its manifestations be used against mimetic
poetry? Plato first lights upon grief and other emotions within the rep-
resented story. The objects of poetic mimesis are 'people acting volun-
tarily or under compulsion, and believing that as a result of these actions
they have fared well or ill, also suffering and rejoicing in all this*,33 and
21
Cf. auto to pathos, 604bl. Pathos 'covers ... both the objective suffering and the
corresponding emotion* (Halliwell (1988), 138); Gould, 32 n» 3, takes the pathos to be
'the pitiable event', in this following Adam, ii 410.
s
The best part of us engages in calculation (logismos, 6Q4d5) about how to beha¥e
so as to secure Ihe best long-term outcome. One sfaoald deliberate (bouleuesthai, 604c5)
about how to arrange one's affairs as reason (logos) chooses.
* Plato's way of speakiag of "moderation* keeps the link with 'measuring* alive:
meeriasei .,. pros lupen, 'he will be measared with regard to his sorrow* (603e8).
^•aganaklitikos, poikilos (604eI-2, 605a5), The former epithet reminds us of the
'spirited* part of the soul from Book 4, the latter of the appetitive part (Nehamas (1982),
67), (See also Adam, ii. 406.)
32
See Penner (1971), 100-2; Nehatnas (1982), 65-6; White, 253,
33
603c4-7. There is probably another reference to Gorgias here—he said of poetry 'at
the actions and physical sufferings of others in good fortunes and in evil fortunes, through
the agency of words, the soul is wont to experience a suffering of its own* (Helen, §9).
Plato later echoes this when he says: 'Only a few will reflect that the enjoyment will be
transferred from the spectacle of another's sufferings to one's own*. 604e5—6, allotriou
... pathoiis he mimesis autois gignetai also puns on the same passage of Gorgias. See
Bellore (1983), 59 n. 32.
Against Mimetic Poetry 149
this kind of subject-matter- tends to be full of people indulging their
emotions, governed by a part of themselves other than the logistikon,
The calm, rational, good-seeking reaction to events does not lend itself
to depiction and would not mate for & drama pleasing to the mass
audience (604e3—605a6). Guided by the aim of producing pleasure
rather than that of making Ihe spectators better, poets depict multifari-
ous behaviour which lacks the measure and composure associated with
the best part of the soul. This, Plato then suggests, strengthens and
nourishes that inferior part of the soul in the spectator, setting up a civil
war within us, whose end result is the destruction of the logistikon
(605M-5), So mimetic poetry encourages us to acquire attitudes to-
wards our emotions, and propensities to behave in certain ways,- all
learned through the gratification of a pleasing image, rather than by
applying thought to which way of feeling and acting is best.
Though its conclusions, are broadly parallel to what we have seen
elsewhere, this argument is -ambitious and full, of slippery assumptions.
Plato assumes that dramatic portrayals of characters guided by emotion
and/or appetite will be enjoyed only by a corresponding 'inferior' part
of the spectator—presumably because he thinks that what we enjoy
about these portrayals is feeling (or imagining that we feel) what the
characters feel, and hence engaging the same part of the psyche as we
see expressed by them. He also assumes that this enjoyment will change
us by progressively strengthening the part that does the enjoying, and
that someone who enjoys seeing a dramatic representation of some way
of behaving will come to behave in that way in life outside the drama.
Perhaps Plato's position is not altogether unfamiliar: many people today
believe that the depiction of violence feeds an aggressive part of us that
may vent itself in real actions or in a more tolerant attitude towards real
violence which • we witness. But Plato's assumptions may still be ques-
tioned. He regards drama as a whoEy. permeable medium, as if oar
response could not be to the dramatic representation as such and did not
essentially discriminate between a real course of events and a fictional
one.34 This assumption seems naive. However, the issue is addressed
more subtly in the second psychological argument against mimetic
poetry.
This second. psychological argument presents Socrates' 'greatest
34
See Nehamas (1988) on this (esp. 258-19), and on the modern parallel; 'the greatest
part of contemporary criticisms of television depends on a mora! disapproval which is
identical to Plato's attack on epic and tragic poetry* (222).
150 Against Mimetic Poetry
35
charge* against it —that it is powerful enough to 'corrupt' or 'impair*
even good men, with very few exceptions, and so is dangerous. As
basis for this charge, we must confront another psychological fact:
When even the best of us hear Homer or some other tragedian making a mimesis
of one. of the heroes sorrowing and stretching out a long speech of lamentation
or a chorus beating their breasts you know that we enjoy it, surrender ourselves,
share their feelings and earnestly praise as a good poet the one who affects us
most in this way, (605cI0~d5.)
However reflective we are, however governed by reason, however
desirous of the good, we still cannot resist feeling a pleasure in tragic
drama, which arises out of an identification with the characters' emo-
tional situation. Danger lurks in the poet's uncanny ability to draw us
into the feelings of the drama and provide a pleasure which will over-
ride whatever reflective capacities we may have. In these circumstances,
regarding ourselves as safe because of the remoteness of the fictional
sufferings, we are prone to indulge the very part of ourselves which, in
the previous argument, we saw to be at variance with the logistikon;
The part which is forcibly controEed in our private misfortunes and has been
pining to weep and adequately lament, as it is by'nature desirous of this, is the
very part which receives satisfaction from the poets in the theatre and enjoys
it. That part, of ourselves which is the best by nature [the logistikon}.., relaxes
its watch over the wailing part because it is watching another's suffering and
there is no shame involved for itself in praising and pitying another man who,
in spite of Ms claim to goodness, grieves excessively. Moreover, there is, he
thinks, a definite gain, namely pleasure, and he would not welcome being
deprived of it by despising the whole drama. Only a few will reflect that the
enjoyment will be transferred from the spectacle of another's sufferings to
one's own, and that one who has nurtured and strengthened the part of him that
feels pity at those spectacles will not find it easy to hold it in check at the time
of Ms own misfortunes, (606a3—b8.)3<*
In feeling pity, we indulge the 'lower', 'wailing' part of ourselves
because of the sheer fact that it brings pleasure to do so,- and this
35
Socrates says *we have not yet made the greatest charge against it* {ou ... to ge
megiston kategorekamen autes, 605c6). What is the 'it'?—poetry, mimesis, or mimetic
poetry? The pronoun cmtex seems to refer back, but there is no clear noun (such as
poiem, mimesis, mimetike) for it to refer to. However, 'the mimetic poet* (605b7) was
the subject of the previous paragraph, and Homer and the tragic poets are the principal
target of the "greatest charge*.
36
The translation 'the wailing part* (for tau thrlnodous toittou) I owe to Belfiore
(1983), 57.
Against Mimetic Poetry 151
indulgence spills over into our real-life attitudes. However, the most
serious charge has several further sophistications. Firstly, we do not
merely experience pleasure in 'sharing* the character's emotions, but
we consciously assign a positive value to the having of this pleasure.
And secondly, the circumstances in which we can gain this pleasure,
sunk in concentration on a theatrical performance, rob us of the ability
to consider whether what we are experiencing will smuggle itself into
our attitudes towards our own lives, and remove our capacity to take' a
view about whether this' is beneficial. The pleasure of mimetic poetry
is so strong that it takes away the power to decide rationally whether
submitting oneself to this pleasure is beneficial or not. But thirdly, Plato
charges, what we grow accustomed to feeling and approving in a drama
will shape our responses in ordinary life, whether we realize it or not.
The same point, covers comedy as well: we take a pleasure in seeing the
ridiculous enacted, but run the risk, while off our guard, of becoming
"comedians in our own life*, of taking indulgent pleasure in things
which our better judgement would bid us take seriously as objects to be
hated.37 Along with the dispositions to pity, grief, and ridicule, mimetic
poetry also 'nourishes and waters' many others which 'ought to wither'
and should not gain the upper hand in the polity of the soul: many
"appetites, pleasures, and pains', including those concerned with sex
and anger/8
Thus the greatest charge against mimetic poetry is that, willy-nilly,
we receive from it a training in many real-life feelings and ethical
attitudes, which works by by-passing rationality, giving pleasure to a
'lower*, indulgent part of the soul, and thereby disabling the power to
reflect on the question of its own influence and value.39 The charge that
Plato is naive about mimesis may be softened to some extent by this
argument. He does not overlook enjoyment of the dramatic representa-
tion per se, nor the rational defences which can in principle prevent
reactions to fiction from spilling over into real life. Instead he makes
the positive claim that drama, with its apparent 'zone of pleasure
divorced . , . from ethical consequences*,40 encourages an emotional
involvement that disarms those defences even when they are strong and
confuses us as to whether we' approve of the representation per se or
41
Ferrari (1989, 138). *2 'Poetry', without qualification: 607bl-3.
Against Mimetic Poetry 153
is at pains to spell out Ms motivation. It is not from 'harshness and
boorishness' that he attacks poetry (though poetry has often descended
to mere abuse of philosophy*"), but, on the contrary, as a lover who has
been convinced that his attachment must cease because it will bring
Mm no good, and forces himself to stay away (607e4—608a5). He even
wishes that poetry could put forward an argument for its own value,
because it is hard to cast off something one has been brought up to
cherish, and because if poetry really does have a positive value, we
shall benefit greatly. We should listen, to a defence of poetry, from any
source, in a friendly spirit. But the task of any defender will be a stiff
one: to show that poetry is 'not merely pleasure-giving, but beneficial
to cities and to human life* (6Q7d8-9),
Plato banishes mimetic and pleasure-giving poetry from the 'city of
words', but envisages that in the real world it will continue to be there.
'We shall listen to it', he says44—but the important question is; With
what attitude? Plato's answer is that we should sacrifice an almost
irresistible pleasure for the sake of a higher principle: the truth about
what is good or bad.
As long as it is not able to put ap such a defence, we shall listen to it but repeat
to ourselves like an incantation the argument'we now put forward and be
careful not to fall again into that childish and popular love. We shall go on
repeating that such poetry must not be taken, seriously as if it had any contact
with truth and were a serious matter, but that the man who is anxious about the
government of his soul must be careful when he hears it, and that what we have
said about poetry must be believed....
The struggle to become good or bad is important, my dear Glaucon, I said,
much more important than people think, so that it is not worth being led on by
honours, wealth or any office, nor indeed by poetry, to neglect justice and the
rest of virtue.45
We must certainly consider how we might make the defence of poetry
which Plato invites—a task of some difficulty which I reserve until ray
final chapter. But how good is the prosecution case in the first place?
43
607b6-c2 quote a few instances of such abuse, whose sources ate, unfortunately,
unknown,
"** Gould (221) takes the view that this "probably means, not "as we enjoy poetry", but
"as we listen to poetry's defence of itself"'—but (whether or not the text supports
Gould's idea) would aot poetry's defence of itself also be poetry? Plato pointedly con-
trasts poetry's self-defence with a defence in prose by non-poets (607d6-9).
43
608a2-b8 (Grebe's translation, slightly adapted).
154 Against Mimetic Poetry
46
Many writers have been convinced that there is no case to answer—
on the grounds that Plato's arguments are bad, unclear, or insincere—-
or else that Plato can be brought to drop the charges: we secure an
admission that in other places he explicitly or implicitly defends poetry
(or some restricted class of 'real' or 'good' poetry). Either way, Repub-
lic Book 10 can be made to emerge as something that a philosopher of
art does not have to worry too much about. Whether Plato's views
elsewhere mitigate the attack on poetry can be answered only when all
the evidence is in, and we still have,to examine a number of works
written later than the Republic. But what of the idea that Book 10 itself
does not present a case worth worrying about?
One problem here is the temptation to detach the discussion of
mimetic poetry from the central themes of the Republic. Few would
wish to concede to Plato outright Ms views of knowledge and truth,
pleasure, desire, and the best constitution for the human soul, let alone
Ms doctrine about the manner in which philosophy can lead us to knowl-
edge in the ethical sphere. But for all that, and for all its own doctrinal
quirks, Book 10 is the final chapter of a systematic ethics and episte-
mology, and if we treat it as a self-contained treatise on the arts, many
of its assumptions will seem gratuitous and baffling. We ought to be
asking whether the account given of the arts would be persuasive to
someone who accepted the Republic's account of the soul and, how it
acquires justice. If you believe that the logistikon should govern in a
healthy individual, and that nothing should be allowed to hamper it in
its quest for the eternal truth about what Good is, and that fostering
pleasures associated with the appetites and emotions will set up the rule
of something other than the logistikon—then when you find intelligent
people sitting in enjoyment of a representation of Medea planning the
murder of her children, should it be beyond contention that this is a
perfectly fine thing for them to do? Should it be obvious to Plato why
this kind of activity has a positive value? The first prerequisite for
* They protest too much: Plato is assailed with 'gross illogicality and unfairness*,
'passionate, hopelessly bad arguments", 'trivial or sophistic arguments which he can not
himself have regarded as conclusive', and a position which is 'quite unacceptable* (how
dare he!)—bat then again it is said that he is only 'enjoying himself by over-stating his
case', that a 'comparison with other dialogues makes it quite clew that [these sections of
the Republic} do not contain his considered opinion', and that we should 'construct a
nobler and more generous theory of Aesthetic Art* on his behalf. Perhaps there is a
hidden 'commendation of good art* even within Book 10 itself, or is Plato 'struggling
after a theory of aesthetics which does not find full expression before Hegel'? (Sources:
Warty, 55, 65; Annas (1981), 344; Greene, 54-5; Cross and Wooztey, 281; Crotnbie, i,
147; Adam, II 393; Grube (1935), 192; Grey, 298.)
Against Mimetic Poetry 155
allowing the case against mimetic poetry to come to court is to realize
that its issues are ones which Plato cannot avoid raising if Ms work is
to have integrity.
The second prerequisite is to examine our own prejudices. In particu-
lar, that anachronistic and loaded concept, 'Art*, should not be de-
ployed until we have understood what Plato achieves without using it.
We may be tempted to imagine teaching Plato this concept of ours, and
patiently leading him out of error: 'You see, these things that you are
attacking are Art. If something is Art it invariably has the foEowing
value ... and does not really need any further justification,' ("Thank
you for clearing that up', he might reply—though this strategy would
rebound on the champion of Art, if the concept is, as I argue later, an
almost vacuous one for the purpose.) Bot we should'first establish what,
if anything, is wrong with his position as it stands. Otherwise there is
little chance of a fair hearing, since 'attacking Art' appears to count as
either blasphemy or blatant stupidity.
Plato's epistemological arguments, as I have interpreted them, fail to
convince in points of detail: recall the implausibility of the user/maker
dichotomy, the sweeping empirical claims about poets' lack of practical
expertise, and the question-begging assumption that no one would want
to Make a mimesis of something if they could make a real filing of the
same kind. The psychological arguments, for their part, rely heavily on
the principle that conflicting attitudes cannot stem from a unitary entity,
and on a puritanical prescription4' about which psychological reactions
and modes of behaviour one should approve in oneself. Overall Plato
proceeds on a nai've notion of artistic representation, as the production
of 'appearing things' whose status is wholly derivative from the kind
of thing they appear to be. He is sometimes under suspicion of making
no distinction between appearance and illusion. He uses illustrative
analogies—the painter of craftsmen and the 'bent-stick' visual, illusion
cases—which are over-stretched and potentially misleading, and he is,
perhaps, vague as to whether his points apply to all poetry and which
poetry really counts as mimetic.
Yet, despite these flaws, there is a coherent and interesting case to be
heard Firstly, what do mimetic poets characteristically do? They rep-
resent persons acting, suffering, and exhibiting varied psychological
reactions to events in their lives. Their best subject-matter is provided
47
'Extreme emotional puritanism* (Halliwell (1988), 151). But if 'puritaaism' means
a blanket hostility to all pleasure, Plato is not guilty of it (Ferrari (1987), 99).
156 Against Mimetic Poetry
by characters in situations which call for a wide range of elaborately
expressed emotions. If mimesis is understood as the intentional produc-
tion of an appearance of a thing of some kind, then clearly these poets
perform mimesis, and may be classed with the most usual kind of visual
artist. However, in dramatic poetry, mimesis has an especially potent.
effect on the human mind. It produces images of persons and their
actions so successfully that the spectator is drawn to feel emotionally
involved in the drama. Poetry uses a number of 'musical' means—
rhythm, metre, and harmony—without which the narration would not
be captivating to the same degree. To feel emotions along with char-
acters who are portrayed by such poetic means affords an intense pleas-
ure. When poetry enchants us so much that we identify with the
characters and feel its powerful effect on us, we praise its producer as
'a good poet*.
It would surely be hard to deny any of this. The next part of the case
asks: What value do these activities of producing and hearing mimetic
poetry have? Essentially, two prevailing views are canvassed and re-
jected. The first says that the mimetic poet is an educator, whose ability
to write finely stems from knowledge, or at least from true beliefs about
human affairs in all their many aspects-—the value of mimetic poetry is
that we learn from it, often about weighty matters. Plato dismisses this
view, and- in. so doing makes a good point: the theory of poetry which
explains its success in terms of a compendious knowledge on the part
of the poet is a foolish mistake. We must realize the difference between
the ability to make a fine, pleasurable, enchanting, and (as we say)
convincing artistic representation, and the ability to know or even be
right about the highest truths of human existence. It is implausible to
say that the two could not even coincide. But where Plato is surely right
is in saying that they are distinct and may float free of each other, and
that those who think otherwise are sunk in a deep error which not only
renders their philosophy of poetry childish but makes any proper
ethical thinking impossible.
The second view which Plato opposes locates the value of mimetic
poetry in the pleasure it gives. We count this pleasure itself as a benefit
But pleasure ought not to be self-guaranteeing: we must ask why, if at
all, the pleasure characteristic of mimetic poetry is good for us to have,
and in order to do so we must analyse its nature. Plato suggests, with
great plausibility, that we are not beings in full rational control of our
reactions, and that mimetic poetry appeals to the psyche by engaging
a more primitive 'wailing' part of us. While our rational defences are
Against Mimetic Poetry 157
relaxed, because we are aware that the situation is remote, poetry, with
its ability to create a convincing world in appearance sad its splendid,
involving 'musical colours', makes us feel emotions which in other
circumstances we might choose to check as unworthy or dangerous.
Once one has surrendered oneself, the emotions are hard to resist and
the pleasure in feeling them is intense. To keep oneself away from such
experiences is akin to separating from someone with whom one is in
love. Who would maintain, after this analysis, that Plato lacks insight
into the nature of mimetic poetry or understanding of why people think
it is a good thing? He understands these matters well, but thinks we
must tear ourselves away from pleasures if by rational argument we can
recognize them as undesirable.
In broad terms what Plato has said about the nature of mimetic
poetry—what it is aod does—is persuasive. That, together with its roots
in his ethics and epistemology, makes his prosecution worth hearing.
There are some obvious points for the defence to fasten upon. Some-
thing is still missing from Plato's account of what it is to take pleasure
in a representation, and we are likely to wonder whether our reactions
to tragedy really spill over into our lives in such a wholesale and
pernicious way. We may claim that even repeated exposure to drama
does not change the whole balance of the soul, or that it does, but in
a beneficial way. Or we might 'suppose its effect harmless enough that
the value of mimetic poetry is found, after all, in, a perfectly innocent
pleasure. But Plato's monolithic standards for what constitutes a healthy
individual and what it is to understand good and evil also stand out as
targets, Plato may have some misconceptions about the arts, but let us
not forget that he also pits them against a vision of attaining excellence
and truth to which nothing human could ever be equal.
7
Why deny that toe interest here is partly 'aesthetic*? But the chief
ideas—tfaat orderliness must win out over pleasure, that pace should be
1
These traits are apparent in Theaetetus and Parmenides, though I do not discuss
these dialogues here. The only assumption about chronology required by this chapter is
that Phaednts, Timaeus, Sophist, Politicus, Philebus, and Laws are all later than the
Republic. la practice 1 treat the Laws as Plato's last work.
2
Murdoch, 56.
:i
Verdenius (1949), 13. Else (1986, 60-1) has essentially the same thought,
"" Cf. Bosanquet, 29, for the idea that beauty and not art is at stake here.
Myth, Madness, Pleasure, and Play 159
impressed on the soul—conie straight out of the Republic; there is no
evidence that Plato's position has changed.
Some may find a softening towards the 'artistic* in the fact that the
Timaeus presents itself as a mythical image—a 'likely story (muthosY
(29d2). But again, it is unclear how much can be made of this. Firstly,
it is nothing new: the Gorgias, the Phaeda, and the Republic all end
with myths composed by Plato. Secondly, how much of Plato's moti-
vation in asing a myth is what we would call 'artistic' and how much,
for example, does he regard it as a probable 'scientific*- hypothesis?5
The general question of the status of Plato's myths has been much
debated. What we should ask here is whether Ms writing them conflicts
with the treatments of poetry and the other arts we have examined so
far. The strongest possible affirmative is that the myths constitute
Plato's own 'defence of poetry',6 or at least are of value to Plato and
his reader in just the way that poetry would be.7 However, even if there
are consciously poetic elements in the myths, Plato has not necessarily,
in writing them, undermined or modified his own critique of poetry.
That would be true only if he had previously condemned all poetic
writing absolutely. But we should remember that he positively wanted
poets to produce myths for Ms young guardians, • the complaint being
simply that existing poets told unsuitable myths which were a bad
likeness of the truth,8 The myths he himself invents might be regarded
as the kind of composition that would be allowed in the model city.
In the Phaedo Socrates expresses a decided attitude to Ms myth
about the soul in the afterlife: it would be a mistake to insist on its
truth, but 'that either this or something like it is true ... is fitting and
worth risking, for one who believes that it is so—for a noble risk it is—
so one should repeat such things to oneself as a spell'.* Socrates has
just produced a series of muscular arguments for immortality, and
searches for a noble enough myth to match his belief. Notice that the
myth's role is presented in the same terms as that of the argument
(logos) against mimetic poetry in the Republic—a charm which pre-
serves us against corruption or error.1* Myth may serve as 'a prolongation
5
'A mythos is a tale. Not al tale* are fictions' (Vlastos (1939), 382).
6
The claim made by Elias, 36: 'The myths are Plato's poetry, designed ... in the
manner of their telling to supply the defence he has called for.*
1
The essential charm of these Myths is that of Poetry generally' (Stewart, 46). (This
chann is said to lie in 'its power of inducing, satisfying, and regulating what may be
called Transcendental Feeling*.)
s
See Belfiore (1985). ' Phdo. U4d2-7, translation by Gallop.
10
Here the dangers are- of lacking confidence in the soul and neglecting it in favour
of the pleasures of the body (fhdo, I I4d8-e3).
160 Myth, Madness, Pleasure, and Play
.into the unknown of the lines established by philosophical argument*,11
but it is also a tool interchangeable with argument in that it shares the
same goal: to attach us more securely to what we ought to believe in.
Why myth as well as argument? One answer lies in the Republic's
division of the soul.12 Because each of us is a plurality, to address the
logistikan alone would fail to persuade us. If each element within us
has its own pleasures, desires, and modes of understanding, more than
one treatment (charm, spell, pharmakon) will be required to draw the
soul towards justice or make it embrace a doctrine such as that of
immortality. Myth can present an attractive and worthy picture which
satisfies us in ways that argument cannot If we think of it as working
on the soul in parallel with the poetry, music, story-telling, and
encomium-singing which Plato wanted to retain in his ideal city, we see
that Platonic myth is not at odds with his critical views about poetry.
It may use poetic means, but does so in order to counteract or replace
mimetic, emotion-stirring art-forms. It does not proceed in total igno-
rance or disregard of truth, but seeks an image complementary to the
truth which has been, or might be established by argument. It does not
masquerade as all-embracing expertise, or feed the childish part of us
at the expense of order in the soul, or disable our moral thinking, or
luxuriate in spurious paradigms of behaviour. It does not challenge
philosophy, but is a part of philosophy, which will assist in guiding the
whole person towards a love of truth and goodness.
Nevertheless it could be maintained that Plato is a poet, and that his
doctrinal opposition to poetry is undermined by his own practice as a
writer. Apart from his use of poetic images and diction, there is the fact
that he constructs his works using dramatic mimesis. Socrates is a
character, painted in words. Plato 'hides himself' much more thoroughly
than Homer,13 and even plays self-consciously with the character who
is usually Ms mouthpiece, making Mm hide among parodies, rhetorical
exercises, and layers of fictional narrators. While the words of Plato's
texts may proclaim that mimetic art is to be kept at bay, Ms methods,
it might be argued, show him doing just what he attacks. This way of
thinking can be challenged, however, in two principal ways. Firstly,
although Plato is a poetic writer, and although he enjoys himself in
a thoroughly 'literary' fashion, this need not undermine Ms serious
a
" Dodds (1959), 376, Here I follow the insight of Moline (esp, 16-19).
13
This fact, at once, obvious and neglected, is brought into relief by Kostnan, esp.
73-8.
Myth, Madness, Pleasure, and Play 161
statements of philosophical doctrine. Secondly, it is a mistake to think
that what he practises is the same as what he preaches against. His
whole manner of writing is, possibly, calculated to woo away the 'friends
of the arts' to philosophy,14 But his ends are the discovery of troth and
an insight into how to live a good life. He does not object to pursuing
these goals using mimesis and poetic diction, but rather to those who
either neglect these goals in favour of 'artistic' aims, or mistakenly
think that to produce fine poetry is already to have reached them,'3
One dialogue which is peculiarly ali¥e to poetry's possibilities and
engages most self-consciously with issues surrounding myth, argument,
and rhetoric, is the Phaedrus, Socrates (inspired, as he suggests, by
whatever deities inhabit the banks of the Hissus, and by the cicadas who
sing overhead) composes a 'mythic hymn* to love, beauty, and the
philosophical life, juxtaposing it with a more careful philosophical argu-
ment about the nature of rhetoric. The dialogue, artistic throughout in
its portrayal of scene and characters, and offering great potential for
self-reflexive comment on its own methods of discourse, seems to be
telling us that if rhetoric needs philosophical dialectic, the reverse is
also true.16 How differently this all strikes us from the stern voice of
Republic Book 10—no wonder that writers are prone to announce the
Phaedrus in particular as Plato's recantation, his true defence of what
he had previously attacked.17 Yet nothing here is simple.
Let us begin with the much-quoted passage where Socrates praises
the 'greatest of goods* (244a6-7) that stern from different forms of
'madness*, among which a
14
The idea that Plato Is consciously trying to supplant an old art-form with a new is
present in Nietzsche: see The Birth of Tragedy, sect. 14 (90). And see Nussbauni (1986),
122-35, for the idea of Plato's works as 'a theater constructed to supplant tragedy as the
paradigm of ethical teaching* (129).
15
Ferrari (1989, 145} is sensible on the differences between Piatonic dialogue and
conventional drama. See also Gould, 12.
16
See Ferrari (1987), esp. '34, 38. •
17
Martha Nussbauni writes as follows (with ray interpolated lettering): *[«] 'poetry
inspired by "madness" is defended as a gift of the gods, and an invaluable educational
resource. [t>] Socrates presents his deepest philosophical insights in poetic language, in
the form of a "likeness" , . . [c] philosophy itself is said to be a form of mania.—of
"possessed", not purely rational activity , . , [d] the Phaedrus is . , , more hospitable to
poetry and the poet than the Republic, and less certain about the distinction between
poetry and philosophy' (1982, 80-1). I agree with \b] and partially with (<fl, but argue
against [a], which is clearly a separate point. I have not space to discuss properly [c]=s
claim that philosophy is held to be 'not purely rational', or the wider implications of the
Phaedrus* moral psychology. But I find Prfce's comment apt "Plato, the arch-rationalist,
is at last doing justice to unreason; but we shall not find him changing sides* (67).
162 Myth, Madness, Pleasure, and Play
kind of possession and madness [mania] comes from the Muses: taking a ten-
der, virgin soul, and arousing it to a Bacchic frenzy of expression in lyric and
other forms of poetry it educates succeeding generations by glonfymg myriad
deeds of those of the past; while the man who arrives at the doors of poetry
without madness from the Muses, persuaded that expertise [techne] alone will
make him a good poet, both he and his poetry, the poetry of tbe sane, are
eclipsed by that of the mad, imperfect and unfulfilled,18
What conflicts with the Republic! Not the familiar idea that techne is
insufficient for good poetry and that good poets require divine interven-
tion: although the Republic does not mention, inspiration, this idea is
consonant with that dialogue's chief complaint that poetry is far re-
moved from knowledge. Certainly nothing in the Republic requires
Plato to believe that those traditionally recognized as good poets are not
inspired. So we may assume that the belief in poetic inspiration found
in the earlier dialogues has persisted, and surfaces again in the Phaedrus,
However, two ideas do appear to clash with the Republic: the idea that
good poetry is straightforwardly a fine thing for humanity, and the idea
that it educates us through its glorification of ancient times. In the
Republic Homer's being 'most poetic' was no indication of his true
worth-—virtually the opposite was the case (Rep. 607al—5; cf. 387bl-
6). And the elaborate set of arguments in Republic Book 10 is precisely
aimed to repudiate those who say that Homer educated Greece. The
conflict cannot be explained away by saying that Plato here means to
confine admiration to the less pleasure-giving portion of poetry which
is admitted in the Republic}9 For how could the reader be expected to
guess that poetry 'inspired by the Muses* was now meant to exclude
not only Homer (about whose divine inspiration so much is made in the
Ion) but all the pleasure-giving works traditionally considered 'most
poetic* and rejected in the Republicl"20
In the Phaedrus it is now said that good, inspired poetry is a fine
thing and that Homer (no mere technician) really educates us. But is it
credible that Plato should thus assert, in a rather showy rhetorical manner,
the negation of a conclusion for which he had laboured through so
many pages of the Republic! As it is the character Socrates who is
made to utter both that argument and this simple statement, do we not
need some hint of a reason why he has changed his mind? Perhaps we
18
Phdr, 245al~§. Rowe's translation, with my addition of 'alone' (the Greek is ek
technes hikanos poietes esomenos).
" The suggestion of Haclforth (1952), 62, with reference to Rep. 607a.
20
See Tigerstedt (1969), 55.
Myth, Madness, Pleasure, and Play 163
may begin to reconcile the two passages by reflecting on their different
contexts of utterance, A serious argument was called for to complete
the picture of the model city. By contrast, Socrates has here arrived at
a crux in a game with the speech-loving Phaedrus: having tried to beat
the speech-maker Lysias in praising the cynical non-lover, he is ashamed
of Ms dishonesty, and wishes now to praise love, but still in mythical,
poetic manner. His speech praising love precisely as a form of madness
can, be made more palatable by a rhetorical preamble cataloguing dif-
ferent forms of beneficial madness. It is in place to say something
celebratory, and indeed quite conventional, invoking the Muses and the
'myriad deeds* of the ancient past.21 If its rhetorical function can be
understood in this way, the passage by itself will not require Plato to
have recanted anything from the argument of the Republic}0 He is not
necessarily using this passage to enunciate any serious doctrine of Ms
own, or of Socrates', about the nature or value of poetry.
Elsewhere in Ihs "Phaedrus poetry is not especially praised. In the
main body of the mythical speech on love, when Socrates places his
reincarnated souls in order of importance, he assigns the soul of a poet
sixth place out of nine, below gymnasts and seers, and above only
craftsmen, farmers, sophists, demagogues, and tyrants. Those inclined
to think that 'Plato's true voice* must be showing through in the open-
ing praise of poetry. find this low ranking rather a shock. But is it not
just as likely, given what we heard in the Republic, the Ion, the Gorgias,
even the Symposium, that we are nearer to the true voice here in the list
of souls? What Socrates actually says is 'for the sixth place, the fitting
life will be that of a poet or some other life from among those con-
cerned with mimesis' (248el—2). Haekforth writes with supreme assur-
ance that 'Plato must be thinking of that sort of poetical mimesis which
is condemned in the Republic', it need not, and indeed cannot, imply
that every sort of poietikos bios [poetic life] is so low in the scale of
values', and that 'Plato cannot have in mind the inspired poetry of
245a*.23 But why not? The mimesis attacked in the Republic includes
that of the greatest poets, and they are precisely the ones whose success
" Plato includes the opposition between mania and techni which is his own doctrine
elsewhere; but it is possible to use, for rhetorical ends, expressions of what one genuinely
believes. Ferrari (1987, 113—19) treats the opening praise of poetic inspiration as aimed
non-ironically at the historical past, but in pointed contrast to contemporary poets.
22
The wholly 'ironic' reading is supported by WoodtufF(1982fc), 150 rt. 17; 'Plato never
has Socrates speak sincerely of poette inspiration*. See also Tigerstedt (1969). 50—3.
23
Haekforth (1952), 84. (Haekforth accepts Tate's account of good versos bad mimesis
(Tate (1928)), which I criticized to Ch. 5 above.)
164 Myth, Madness, Pleasure, and Play
Plato elsewhere puts down to inspiration. Besides, if Plato had wanted
to assign his sixth-ranking life to a "bad" or 'uninspired' poet (or any
other specific kind), he could easily have added a few words to accom-
plish that.24
We have to accept that this passage ranks the poetic life without
qualification, and implicitly that of other artists, comparatively low in
the scale of things. If we can regard the praise of poetry in the intro-
duction to the speech as something of a preparatory rhetorical flourish,
not a statement of doctrine, there is no serious inconsistency. If, on the
other hand, Plato means us to take both passages in earnest, there is a
jar in tone,25 and possibly a direct contradiction—it would at least
be odd to maintain that five other kinds of life surpass a life devoted
to one of the "greatest goods* (244a6—7). However, we have seen Plato
elsewhere recognize the fineness of a poet's output while refusing any
great value to the poet's own capacities.26 In the Ion Homer's fine
works are among the blessings of madness, but presumably Homer's
life, being low on the scale of knowledge, was less of a life than some
others. If we seek "Plato's voice' (a perilous exercise in this dialogue
especially), it is easiest to hear it in the low ranking of the poet, and
in the distancing of fine poetry from techne.21 We have much less
reason to ascribe to him a serious belief that inspired poetry is truly
educational,
The highest form of life put forward fa Socrates' myth provides
another opportunity for those who hope that Plato is embarked on a
rehabilitation of the arts. The highest life belongs to *a man who will
become a lover of wisdom or of beauty, or devoted to the Muses
[mousikos] and to love' (248d2-4). What to make of the contrast be-
tween this life and that of the sixth-ranking poet or mimetic practi-
tioner? Some abandon caution at this point: 'No other meaning than
24
Nussbauiu (1982, 89} points out that the sixth-ranking poet 'is not said to be Muse-
inspired*. True, but nor is he said to be the 'ordinary* poet who trusts in techne alone.
See Verdenius (1962), 133; Ferrari (1987), 118 and 25? n, II; Tigerstedt (1969), 55;
Price, 65 n. 9; Burnyeat (unpublished).
25
Ferrari (1987, 119} sees this as a calculated effect.
26
Burnyeat (unpublished): 'He thinks, as he always thought, that the marvellous and
useful pronouncements tiey make are no credit to them, but to the god who speaks
through them," (Cf. Rowe, 169.)
J<
Collingwood seems right that even in the fhaedrus 'poetry is enthusiasm or inspi-
ration , , , but ...on this account the poet comes low in the scale of souls* (1925, 167,
my emphasis).
Myth, Madness, Pleasure, and Play 165
28
creative artist* can be given to these words, But there is no good
reason for this anachronistic suggestion, and Neharoas* deflating com-
ments seem especially apt;
Taking 'mnsical* to refer to some sort of artist, commentators have seen Plato
here distinguishing between a true artist and a mere imitator. But the Phaedrus
tas been discussing the soul and the proper relations between its parts. The best
lives are lived by the most harmonious souls.... The 'musical*, in this as well
as in other contexts, is not the artist but the gentleman who patronizes the
artists and knows what to take from them.29
In other words, the so-called "creative artist* is, for Socrates, if any-
where, in the sixth-ranking position, and distinguished from the cul-
tured philosopher/lover at the top. Poetry and mimetic art are distanced
from the best life of the philosopher. The distancing is carried out in a
very different mood from the banishment in the Republic, using a dif-
ferent image, but there is no fundamental reversal in Plato's position.
This may seem an insensitive way of reading the Phaedrus. Firstly,
it may be thought, the power of Socrates' mythic hymn on the value of
love is so great that Plato must have meant to embrace poetic madness
implicitly in the same account. This is not a very convincing thought
on its own. Bat there are signs scattered around that Socrates regards
himself, in speaking the myth, as rising to poetic heights in a state of
inspiration. Assuming that Plato is firmly behind what the myth says
about the lover and Ms soul, how could he not regard with reverence
the very poetic inspiration which he says produces the myth? Here, I
believe, the Phaedrus is far from offering any simple answer. The
purpose of Socrates' bouts of 'inspiration' in the dialogue has been
much debated. In rather over-larded fashion he professes that his first
speech is inspired by something 'divine* outside of himself (235c5—dl,
237a7-lQ, 238c5-d3, 241el-5). But this is the very speech where he
speaks falsely and is shamefully dishonest. If we take seriously the idea
that Socrates is inspired, Plato is reinforcing the old message that in-
spiration is no guide to truth. On the other hand, there are reasons to
regard the talk of inspiration as on the playful side—a way for Socrates
M
Gates, 59, Similarly incautious claims about the Phaednts are found in Bearrfsley,
44: "the artist may have his own insight into the nature of ideal beauty"; and Partee
(1971), 87, for whom the poet is 'only slightly inferior to the philosopher in Ms access
to absolute knowledge*. It is hard to see bow these claims could be supported,
2
* Nehamas (1982), 60, (Tate (1929, 22) is once again the opponent cited.)
166 Myth, Madness, Pleasure, and Play
to expose the poetic diction30 which Phaedras is compelling him to use,
and to excuse Socrates' words as not really his own. The second speech,
the one which presents the wonderfiil myth of the philosophical lover's
soul, is also expressed in 'somewhat poetic language', ostensibly again
to please Phaedras (257a3—6). But Socrates at one point describes it as
the best paliaode which lies within his power, suggesting that he is
either not inspired, or inspired in some way 'from within*. It is unsafe
simply to put Socrates on a par with a poet inspired to madness by the
Muses.31
Looking back on his mythic speech in a more sombre mood,
Socrates cites its poetic qualities as grounds for its being only an 'amuse-
ment* or 'play*. But these remarks are especially hard for the interpreter
to treat straightforwardly. What degree of evasion should we read into
this description of the mythic speech: 'by expressing the experience of
love through some kind of simile, which allowed us perhaps to grasp
some truth, though maybe also it took us in a wrong direction, and
mixing together a not wholly implausible speech, we sang a playful
hymn in the form of a story* (265b6-el)? ("And it gave me great
pleasure to hear if responds Phaedras, as if that were all that mattered.)
What do we make of Socrates' view that, although some rather dry
principles of philosophical method came to light,12 *to me it seems that
the rest really was playfully done, by way of amusement (paidiai
pepaisthai)' (265c8—9)? Is the mythic speech being dismissed as not
serious at all?33 The only trouble is that we do not know how playful
Socrates is being when he says that the earlier speech was merely
playful. The philosophical headway made in the myth suggests that
its playful invention cannot be dismissed with total seriousness.34 So is
the mytih itself "seriously meant', and, if it is, can the idea of its being
composed in mad, spontaneous inspiration be anything other than
a 'playful* touch? Such questions are left hanging because the very
30
'Almost dithyrambic* and even epic diction (238d2~3, 241el-2.}.
31
My reading here is strongly influenced by Burnyeat (unpublished) and Woodruff
(l9S2h), 150 n. 17. However, Price (66-7) argues that 257a3-4, 'the best palinode of
which I am capable', is compatible with Socrates* being inspired, and points out that
Socrates appears to invoke external inspiration later in a more general way (262d3-6,
263d5-6).
32
265c9 ff. The reference is to the method of collection and division, which we shall
shortly
B
see exemplified in Soph-, Pol., and PhiL
34
Implied by Woodruff (19826), 150 a. 17,
For other passages where Socrates calls his own discourse playful, see 262d2,2?8b7.
Myth, Madness, Pleasure, and Play 167
distinction between 'serious* and 'playful' is one which the dialogue
keeps undermining,35
In the last part of the Phaedrus Plato reasserts the primacy of philo-
sophical knowledge over both ifaetoric and any form of writing that can
be called poetic. Rhetoric could be scientific-—it could be the genuine
tec fine which it was not in the Gorgias36—if only it were preceded by
dialectic, the philosophical method which establishes the truth about
the just aad the good, and about the nature of the human soul on which
persuasion is exercised,37 The truly knowledgeable rhetorician, who did
not just tack together any old methods picked op empirically, would be
a philosopher. (On the other hand, of course, dialectic would be incom-
plete without rhetoric: the mythic speech gave the only account of the
soul which was humanly possible, in terms of a simile (246a4—6},}
Plato's complaint that anything set down in writing is mute and
powerless has had peat influence on recent deconstractionist writings.38
But we must remember that he uses the point to discriminate the philo-
sopher from the mere writer, or me poet. His point is that unless one
already has knowledge prior to encountering the written marks, they
will remain a mere amusement, a play of signs. A person who writes
without knowledge will be rightly called a poet or author of speeches,
and is comparable to a rhapsode- (278d8-e2, 277e5-9). These people
are nothing but writers: in a wonderfully telling phrase, Plato speaks of
someone who 'does not possess things of more value than the things
he composed or wrote* (27§d8^9). In stark contrast stands the philo-
sopher, who
has composed these things knowing how the troth is, able to help his compo-
sition when he is challenged on its subjects, and with the capacity, when speak-
ing in Ms own person, to show that what he has written is of little worth.
(278c4-7.)
•" Plato does not, in this sense, depart from Ms 'rationalism*. See Price, 67; Irwin
(1988), 380; Dodds (1951), 64, 218-19.
* As recent commentators have put it, philosophers are allowed to use 'poetic images
as structures that point away from themselves* (Moravcsik (1982,44)) towards things of
true value, and to make *a poetic and philosophic call to the philosophic life* (Ferrari
(1989, 148)}.
41
Woodruff (19826. 149 n. II) believes the remark about the insufficiency of techne
'consistent with the idea that poets have no skills*. But surely Plato is less likely to say
that poets believe techne sufficient, if he thinks there is no such teehni.
Myth, Madness, Pleasure, and Play 169
exercises his new method of division (or definition by progressive clas-
sification), mimetic art is classified as a form, of techne, as are painting,
sculpture, and music. Some earlier commentators were drawn to these
systematic passages in the hope of finding Plato's 'definition of art',42
But as I said in Chapter 2, I think that this idea should be resisted.
Firstly, these passages were written late in Plato's career, using a method
which he did not possess in the early and middle dialogues, so it would
be dangerous to assume that his way of systematizing here will provide
any definite structure for passages up to and including the Republic,
Secondly, we must keep alive a sense of the strident oppositions be-
tween poetry and genuine techne in the Ion, Gorgias, and Republic 10.
Thirdly, as we shall see, no single systematic account emerges in any
case: the late passages classify the arts by dividing techne in a number
of different ways, and rather than constituting a single theory of art,
they are continuations of a number of earlier ideas, particularly from
the Republic and Gorgias.
None of the arts emerges with much greater credit than it enjoyed
in those dialogues. This pass from rom the Politicus (or Statesman) is
especially trenchant:
Might we agree to name a fifth class [of techne} including all things concerned
in decoration and painting, and everything which produces representations
whether using these or using music and poetry? They are produced simply to
give us pleasures, and all may justly be included under one description . . . We
use the expression 'diversion* [paignion] ,., this is the name we can apply to
all of these things. For none of them has a serious purpose; all are performed
for pure amusement [paidia].4*
Plato could scarcely ha¥e grouped 'the arts' together more succinctly
or dashed more decisively any hope that his earlier views would be
recanted. 'Amusement' is here a pejorative term—even with the playful
Phaedrus fresh in our minds, it is hard to find this classification ironic.
The same notion of mimetic art as paidia, amusement or play, appears
in the Sophist: 'Could you think of a more expert or delightful form of
amusement than the mimetic [to rnimetikonjT (Soph, 234bl—2). In this
passage the sophist is being nailed as a mere producer of images, and
to this end Plato rehearses some key thoughts of Republic 10.—
What would you think if you met someone who understood how to
produce everything from a single tecknel That would be a fine kind of
42
See above, Ch. 2, n. 1,
43
Pol 288cl-10. Translation by Sketnp, slightly adapted.
170 Myth, Madness, Pleasure, and Play
amusement. The sophist, if he does this, would be in the mimetic cate-
gory, which means he would be a kind of wizard or wonder-worker.
The art of painting, after all, if it displays its products at a distance, can
deceive the foolish among children into thinking that the artist has
wide-ranging capacities, and the sophist seems to pull off a comparable
trick with words,44—Plato holds fixed his earlier view of mimesis and
repeats parts of it (sometimes word for word) to create a vivid compari-
son with Ms present quarry, the sophist.45
The Sophist does offer something new, however. The method of
division leads Plato to seek greater precision about the class of 'image-
raaking* crafts. Having divided off the productive from the acquisitive
crafts, he makes a distinction between the making of images
(eidolopoiike) and the making of originals or real things, and then sets
to work making further divisions. The making of images is itself of two
kinds: the making of likenesses (eikastike) and the making of phan-
tasms or semblances (phantastike), A genuine likeness is one which
conforms to the original in all three dimensions and whose every part
has the same colour as the original (Soph. 235d?~e2). To make a like-
ness (eikon) on this definition is to make a perfect replica. 'Is not that
what all mimetic artists try to do?' asks Theaetetus naively (235e3—4),
It is not Very often artists depart from the true proportions of the
object they are depicting. Colossal sculptures and paintings, which, must
be seen from a limited viewpoint, are not made in true proportion, since
otherwise their upper parts would look too small and their lower parts
too large. So artists 'leave the truth to take care of itself and concen-
trate instead on what will appear fine. They do not really make like-
nesses then, but something that only seems like the original—a seeming
or phantasma. This phantasm-making variety 'is a very extensive class,
in painting and in imitative art (mimetike) as a whole* (236b9-cl).
Having made a distinction which allows mimesis to be genuine likeness-
making, and which would provide an opportunity to show greater
leniency towards mimetic painting or poetry, Plato shows no inclination
to place any of the arts he previously attacked into this new class.*
44
See-ths passage 233d9-235b6. On the rehearsal of ideas from Rep, here, cf. Cornford
(1935), 198.
45
The mirror-carrying wonder-worker in the Republic was already referred to as 'an
amazing sophist* (Rep. 596dl).
* Hhe point is more letting if we look more closely. Ostensibly the wider class to be
divided into two is called eidelopoiike—-ihe making of images. But Plato uses mimetike
as a direct synonym for this (235c2, dl, 236W; see also 235e2, mimema, and 235e3,
mimoumenoi). Thus, while all of mimetike is still the making of images, as it was i«
Myth, Madness, Pleasure, and Play 111
Later in the Sapkist Plato makes further subordinate divisions within
image-making. The results of the whole discussion are best conveyed
in diagrammatic form—see Figure 2.47 The final set of divisions which
eventually pens the sophist in Ms correct box is notable for its complex-
ity. The term mimesis is now reserved especially (malista, 267a8) for
the making of visual or auditory semblances with,-one's own body
or voice, moving back closer to the sense of mimesis developed in
Republic Book 3. (A painter, using implements and materials, could not
in this sense be practising mimesis.) On the other hand the wider notion
of mimetiM is treated as synonymous with image-making in general,48
and retains more or less the sense established in Republic Book 10. The
divisions lower down appear to offer some hope that Plato will be more
discriminating in, Ms view of the arts. The sophist falls into the category
of doxomanetike: he produces his semblances only on the basis of
opinion (doxa) and has no knowledge. On the other hand, an artist
might produce a semblance of someone which was born out of genuine
knowledge of them. Plato hints that a successful mimesis of Theaetetus
must spring from knowledge of Mm (267bll-12). Just after this he
switches to the obvious point that some people, without having know-
ledge of justice or excellence, can make themselves seem to embody
it. We are left wondering whether a category of artists has not. been
glossed over. We know that Homer and his tribe make only .images of
excellence—even 'semblances' rather than fully faithful replicas. But,
Republic 10, not all of It is the making of mere phantasms, or something far from the
truth (as at Rep. 598b3-8>. Yet Plato does not note any consequences for the mimetic arts
which he discussed before, Tate (1932, 163-4) adduces the discussions of image-making
in Soph, as support for his reading of the Rep. as involving 'good* and 'bad' artistic
mimesis. But if the evidence for that distinction in Rep. is wanting (see Ch. 5 above), it
is better to say that Plato has moved oil to a new distinction, Tate also seems to make
an error whea he says that the eikastike/phantastikie distinction is 'virtually the same* as
the distinction lower down (see Fig, 2) between mimesis with knowledge and mimesis
without (= doxomim&iK). This can scarcely have been Plato's view of the matter.
47
A further complication, omitted from Figure 2, is Plato's division of both auiopoietikl
aad eidOIopoiiki into human and divine making, Sophist 265b-266d, which can be seen
as another modification of the analysis in the Republic. Here the idea of divine production
of » Form is replaced by divine production of ordinary things in nature such as ourselves,
animals, and plants, This is divine original-making (autopoietiki)—-a doctrine which
Plato remarks as somewhat, controversial (see 265c5—c6). Since images also occur natu-
rally in the form of dreams, shadows, and so on, the category of divine image-soaking
{eidolopffiiU) e needs to be added. But these changes do not affect Plato's account of
human making, where the division between e.g. an original house made by the craft of
building (autopoietike) and a corresponding house-picture made by painting (eiddlopoSK)
—'like a human dream for those awake* (266c9)—is standard and familiar.
41
See above, n. 46.
craft (technS)
acquiring making (poi&ikH)
(ktetike)
original- image-making (eidolopoiike)
making
(auto- likeness- semblance-making (phantaslike)
poietike) making
(eikastikS) , , , with . . . with own voice and person (mimesis)
instruments
(di'organdri) scientific opinion-based (doxomimetike)
(historike)
simple ironic (eironikos)
(haplous)
mimetes public: private:
the dem- the
agogue sophist
" The reference to mimesis here is unmotivated by the discussion "m Phil, itself
(cf. Gosling (19-75), 133-4).
52
empeiriai kai tini tribei—-the same terminology as at Gorg. 462c4—7.463b4,501 a7.
a
The translation departs from the Oxford Classical Text here, adding the reference
to lyre-playing on the excellent grounds that 'few flutes have strings* (Gosling (1975),
126), and reading phthengomenes for pheromenis in 56a6.
54
Already in the Republic Plato had stated that every true form of techne or know-
ledge necessarily partakes of number and calculation {iagismos) (Rep, 522ci-8). See also
Pol. 283e3-284d8.
Myth, Madness, Pleasure, and Play 175
Socrates nevertheless sees no place at all for any pleasures except those
that are pure. The rest, he argues, are not true pleasures, and are not
even truly pleasures at all. The tiniest patch of pure white is more truly
white than oceans of off-white. By analogy, the pure enjoyment got
from a fleeting glimpse of a perfect geometrical figure would more
truly be pleasure than the most intense delights of a protracted love-
affair, or of years spent unravelling Sophocles' character-portrayals.
Never mind which feels mom pleasing—Plato does not flinch: *any
pleasure however slight and inconsiderable it may be, so long as it is
purified of aE distress, is pleasanter, truer and finer than any other
whatever its size or quantity' (53blO-c2). The best of lives will not be
devoted to pleasure, bat nor will it be devoid of it. Pleasures there will
be, but only those that are conducive to intelligent thought and the
pursuit of the truth. In a speech put into the mouths of Intelligence and
Thought, who welcome the true, purified pleasures along with those
that accompany virtue, health and self-control (63d2-64a3), we hear a
tone reminiscent of the Republic's concern to protect the intellect from
destruction. Intense and violent pleasures are rejected as a form of
disruptive mania (63d6}, wreaking havoc in the psyche. Eveo if we
tried to 'square* the Philebus with the Phaedrus—probably we should
not55—much of what passes for 'madness* is still, to Plato, dross to be
left behind. His prime concern is that life should he ordered, controlled,
not exceeding the due measure (66a6-7), and have its parts in a
state of overall harmony; 'proportioned and beautiful ... perfect and
satisfying*.56
We can "construct a limited aesthetic* out of the materials in the
Philebus.57 It is not sought among the wondrous high-art products of
Plato's culture, but derived from still higher considerations concerning
the orderliness and excellence of life as a whole.-Existing art forms
such as tragedy, comedy, and the representational visual arts would be
excluded from the best life in the Philebus, as would the emotional kind
of pleasure Plato thinks people generally take in music. The shapes,
colours and sounds that are conducive to pare pleasure are austere- in
the extreme. "The paintings of (for instance) -Mondrian and Ben.
55
As Hacfcforth sensibly urges {1958, 99).
56
66bl-2, in HacMorth's translation (1.958). His comment on the distinction between
metron {measure) and summetron (proportion): 'in the formula of the first we are looking
at each part or factor of the good life by itself... In the formula of the second we look.
at the good life as a whole, or (which is the same thing) we apprehend the relations of
its parts' (138).
17
Murdoch, 9.
176 Myth, Madness, Pleasure, and Play
Nicholson", writes Iris Murdoch 'might be thought of as meeting his
requirements, [but] would I think be regarded by Plato as histrionic and
dangerously sophisticated*.58 There remains modest ornamentation of
buildings and utensils, and the direct simplicity of folk art.
Plato is much concerned with pleasure also in the Laws. We have
asked whether Plato shows any fundamentally changed attitude towards
the arts in works after the Republic. So far the answer weighs towards
the negative, bat our clues have been picked up as Plato addresses the
topics of love, rhetoric, sophistry, pleasure, and craft. In the Laws we
hit on a substantial body of evidence: an extended- re-examination of
the arts and their role in a human community, in which Plato no longer
aspires to delineate a model 'laid up in heaven*, bat turns to the formu-
lation of a social structure which he thinks will actually work. Conse-
quently, we hear far more detail than we did in the Republic about the
cultural practices of which he approves.'9 The city of the Laws will
make careful provision for recreation or play for all its citizens, of
whatever age. There will be religious festivals at which poetic compo-
sitions are performed, choruses in which song and dance are enjoyed,
competitions for solo rhapsodes, lyre-players, and awlos-players, train-
ing for all in lyre-playing and the reading of poetry and prose.60
Paidia, amusement or play, assumes an important social role. The
whole of life should be spent 'at play—sacrificing, singing, dancing*
(803el~2). Play is defined as an activity giving harmless pleasure
(667e5-8), but Plato is adamant that such pleasure cannot be left to
develop of its own accord. Play must be regulated. Children must
always play the same games, under the same rules, otherwise the city
becomes unsettled. For if the young are allowed to innovate, they will
become different from their parents and seek a different life (797a9-M,
798b6—dl). In general, Plato asserts, 'change, except in something evil,
is extremely dangerous' (797d9—10)—-a statement which puts at its
bluntest the deep cultural conservatism that repeats itself throughout
this long work. Plato admires the Egyptians whose laws decree that the
samerules as the paintings of ten
paintings of the present follow the same
thousand years ago (656dl—657a2), If there are decidedly better and
worse ways of painting, composing, and dancing, and these can be
discovered, then it is legitimate, Plato believes, to ensure by persuasion,
si
Murdoch, 16.
59
This, I think, is the main reason why Plato appears to 'take poetry more seriously'
in the Laws. Cf, Ferrari (1989), 107.
60
See 653c7ff,, 764d5-e3, 809a6-8l3a3, 814d8-817e3, 828b7ff.
Myth, Madness, Pleasure, and Play 111
compulsion, and the penally of law, that the better are adhered to.
Compulsion reigns everywhere in the interstices of the system; per-
formers, critics, and teachers of the arts are under the eye of cultural
directors who themselves are compelled by the state to implement fixed
standards,61 The gloom descends as we learn that the legislator must
'think up every possible device to ensure that as far as possible the
entire community preserves in its songs and stories and doctrines an
absolute and lifelong unanimity' (664a4-7). The arts must not be- per-
sonal to any one: they axe decidedly 'of the state*.
Plato insists that the right standards of evaluation for the arts are
those of morality. This is partly because he sees the arts as more per-
vasive in life and learning than we do. No one will count as educated
unless he or she is continually an active participant in a chorus, know-
ing how to sing and move with a sense of the order and disorder present
in rhythm and harmonia. The educated person must be able to sing and
dance well or finely (kalas). But what does it mean to perform these
activities well? (654b6—9), Instead of developing any aesthetic crite-
rion, Plato sticks to the idea that 'all movements and tunes associated
with spiritual or bodily excellence ... are good (kalaY (655b3—5). So
to sing well is to sing a song that is good (654bl 1—cl), and a good song
is one which has the effect of making you good, or (which in the end
will amount to the same thing) presents you with an accurate likeness
of goodness,62 Pleasurable recreation is thus required as a part of edu-
cation which tunes the individual's sense of pleasure and displeasure
(653bl—c4, 659dl—e2). It is not enough to know what good and evil
are; the truly educated, those truly possessed of arete, will also feel
attachment or affection for the good, and distress towards its opposite.
The more specific prescriptions in the Laws implement these general
principles about moral standards, correct models, and enforced uni-
formity. Thus poets must be constrained to portray brave and self-
controlled men, dances must be a mimesis of selected warlike and
peaceful character-traits, hymns must honour gods, heroes, and departed
citizens who have served the community, the rhythms and modes
employed in song must match up with the words so that'll is crystal-
clear what they imitate, purely instrumental music should, not exist,
orderliness should be impressed on artistic products even at the-expense
61
A catalogue of compulsions and penalties Is easily built up: e.g., 656c3-657b3,
660a3-8, 660e2-5, 661c5-8, 670c9-dl, 799b4-8, 800a4-bl, 801cS-d6, 804d3-6
80Ste7 ff.
62
See e.g. 655d5-656b7.
178 Myth, Madness, Pleasure, and Play
of pleasure, new styles which people happen to enjoy should be sup-
pressed, showmanship, buffoonery, and malicious ridicule should be
curtailed, each separate genre should stick to its own without any mix-
ture, performances which arouse strong emotions should be frowned
upon, tragedy 'should not be allowed to propose its view of life as an
alternative to that enshrined in the state's practices, no poet should say
that the just and good are anything but fortunate and blessed, and so on
through many autumnal variations on themes first heard in the Republic.63
Plato argues that the standard for judging mimesis in particular should
not be pleasure.64 When we attach value to anything, it can be because
of three factors: attractiveness, correctness, or benefit,65 If either benefit
or correctness can legitimately be invoked, then pleasure cannot be the
proper criterion of value. In the case of the arts of image-making, they
have an attractiveness, because we take pleasure in representation; but
the function of these arts is to produce likenesses, and here correctness
comes into play (Laws 667c9-d7). 'What is equal is equal and what is
proportional is proportional, and this does not depend on anyone's
opinion that it is so, nor does it cease to be true if someone is dis-
pleased at the fact. Accuracy, and nothing else whatever, is the only
permissible criterion' (668al—4). To judge the fineness of visual
images requires knowledge of what is being represented and how a thing
of that Mad ought to be (668dS~669a4), The same applies to mousike,
the whole of which he now declares to be mimetic and eikastic (668a6-
7). His conclusion could fairly be said to apply across all the arts:
Anyone who is going to be a sensible judge of any likeness (eikori)—in paint-
ing aid music and every other field—should be able to assess three points: he
must know first of what this or that likeness has been effected, second how
correctly, and third how well.66
67
See 700el-4. 'Theatrocracy' is in the same passage, 701a3.
** 802t>6-c2, heavily adapted from Saundets's translation.
69
S02bl-3, Plato stipulates a minimum age for the controllers or authors of artistic
prodycts also at 7<S5al-2, 829c7. The interlocutors of the Laws keep emphasizing that
they are advanced in age. and that they are trying to construct tjje state from an old man's
point of view.
180 Myth, Madness, Pleasure, and Play
which is not only aesthetically correct, bat imitative of, and productive
of, the good,
Plato imagines the poets of Ms state looking for guidance from its
legislators. They can claim to be inspired, but are aware that this is not
enough:
There is an ancient story, legislator, which we poets never tire of telling and
which all laymen confinn, to the effect that when a poet takes his seat on the
tripod of the Muse, he cannot control his thoughts. He's like a fountain where
the water is allowed to gush forth unchecked. His technem that of mimesis, and
so he is obliged, when he represents people with contrasting characters, to
contradict himself, and he doesn't know which of the opposing speeches con-
tains the truth. But for the legislator, this is impossible: he must not let Ms laws
say two different things on the same subject; his rale has to be 'one topic, one
doctrine'. (719cl-d3.)
Plato steals the epithets 'tragedian* and "poet' and the language of
dramatic production, but this should not lead us to think that a kind of
poetry or a kind of art is here given approval. What is proposed is a
displacement of tragedy. Plato truly 'sets up the philosophical life . . ,
as an alternative to the life of the tragic hero, and ... makes the writing
of philosophy an alternative to the writing of tragic drama'.11 Since the
city of the Laws is, like its predecessor in the Republic, a city of words,
there is little difference between recommending the city's way of living
as an image of the best and finest life, and recommending in the same
terms the discourse which describes it, a fact on which Plato plays
when he recommends the Laws, the very text that he is writing, as the
best model to give to educators in the state. Plato's Athenian, stranger
says that all the words he has uttered in the dialogue 'as it seems to me,
not without a certain inspiration from the gods' (811c8—9) are the best
possible model of what is suitable in the curriculum, and show a sim-
ilarity with 'a sort of poetry' (811c9—10). This is Plato's provocative
way of saying that his own most sober thoughts must replace poetry as
an educational means. Philosophy is the greatest mousike12 only in the
sense that everything cultural or artistic must be shaped by, and subor-
dinated to, the disciplined life of rational enquiry into truth and the
good.
11
Halliwell (1984), 58, '* Phdo. 6la3-4.
8
1
Frog* 1491-5. Translation by Levi, 179.
Plato and the Philosophy of Art 185
The arts are there, as independent cultural traditions; some may think
the wisest option is simply to embrace them for what they are, and not
impose an alien critique upon them. Philosophy of art can seem at best
irrelevant, at worst destructive of something precious. Since in practice
even aesfbeticians tend to to ep quiet and enjoy the performance, the
sarne stance may seem attractive as a lifelong policy. To open oneself
to the power of even a few significant artworks—^probably a different
set in each person's case—may be more effective than any general
theory of art a philosopher can devise,
It seems excessively evasive, however, to resort so soon to this re-
treat from philosophy—Plato shows-us, if nothing else, that what we
hold dear must not be exempt from all questioning. What we may
usefully point out, none the less, is that Plato demands an evaluation of
the arts from outside; instead of adopting the perspective of someone
who lives and breathes in an artistic culture, he aspires to stand some-
where else and ask 'What is the point of that?* No doubt many aspects
of human life can be made to appear strange if we pretend to abandon
all participation in them. Almost anything we habitually do and which
imbues our lives with sijpuficance can seem to- have that significance
removed if it is interrogated in a harsh enough light This will espe-
cially be the case with something so subtly ingrained in the psyche and
so definitive of culture as the arts appear to be. Bat we can refuse such
an inquisition; the over-examined life does not reveal why it is worth
living for a human being.
Is that sufficient, though? Surely there is a more positive account of
the arts to be given? Some thinkable strategies are unattractive here
because they are forms of capitulation to Plato. Firstly, there is the
thought that art is a gratuitous but harmless enjoyment of leisure time,
like breeding tropical fish: people like doing it and find it thoroughly
absorbing and it gives them plenty to talk about We. can imagine
someone urging that the value of art is of this kind. But to adopt this
line would not be- a 'reply to Plato', but an acquiescence, taking a single
Platonic notion—the arts as paidia, a pleasing pastime, not to be taken
seriously—and exaggerating it further. Secondly, in a similar category,
there is art as sheer instrumentality. Art, we might say, has its place
because it is socially useful, politically powerful, it trains us as-' good
citizens or as correctly class-conscious opponents of the society we
inhabit. Of course art has always had such uses, but if its very value is
going to be of this order, then we flow once again into a Platonic
stream. Nobody much likes Plato's political ends, but if we say that
186 Plato and the Philosophy of Art
art's value is as a political or social means, we shall not be disagreeing
with him fundamentally about art.
My third unattractive strategy is one which has often seemed the
most promising: the view of art as the supreme route to a knowledge
Plato thought reserved for philosophy—art as uncoveier of eternal Ideas,
or some similar 'higher* reality. This view has a long history, starting
with Plotinus and moving through Renaissance and Romantic guises,
among others. At the beginning of this century a historian of literary
criticism could write that 'some form of the Ideal Theory is indeed
necessary to the critic; the beauty of literature is hardly accessible,
except to one who is more or less a Platonist',2 while a Plato scholar
was firmly convinced that 'the famous lines of Wordsworth on King's
College Chapel "They dreamt not of a perishable home,! Who thus
could build," are more truly and characteristically Platonic than Plato's
attack upon poetry and painting*,3 Thinking in this way, commentators
tried to save Plato from disgrace by discerning their own view of art in
the Platonic writings themselves. I have argued repeatedly that such a
reading is erroneous. I suspect that anyone who is not already "more or
less a Platonist' about literature will find no hints that Plato is one
either. However, even-if Plato did not think so, it is still at the back of
our minds that the artist is concerned with uncovering truth and may
have special cognitive access to something eternal and universal. So
why is the Platonist reply not the most effective reply te Plato?
There are two reasons. Firstly, it requires us to believe that a realm
of Forms or some 'higher reality' exists, and that the mind has some
peculiar cognitive access to it. Accepting a metaphysics as extravagant
as Plato's, and an epistemology as mysterious, is too high a price to pay
for the benefit of correcting his view of art. Indeed, our account will be
all the worse if it is required to postulate knowledge of eternal Forms
solely in order to give a value to art, when so many other areas of
human endeavour, from science to public administration, give us little
or no call to. believe in such entities. That is making art too special for
its own good. Secondly, as a positive strategy it would be unappealing,
since it would in effect collude in a Platonic subordination of the arts
to philosophy, making them worthy only by borrowing the latter's quest
for knowledge of the absolute.4 The two reasons combine: since not
even philosophy understands itself any longer as a quest for eternal
2
Saintstary, 18, * Adam, ii. 393.
4
Cf. Danto's view (1986,16) that Hegel's defence of art has the'effect of patronizing
it as 'philosophy in one of its. self-alienated forms'.
Plato and the Philosophy of Art 187
Forms, we should not force the same implausible task on the arts in-
stead. This leaves it open that art is in some way concerned with truth.,
but there is no call to construe truth on the Platonic model.
Can we defend what Plato attacks by relying on the concept of art?
The modem reader may look at Homer, tragedy, mimetic painting,
florid dithyramhic performances, and the more adventurous musical
modes, and think 'If only Plato had conceived of all these practices as
art, he would not have objected to them!' Unfortunately, this line of
thinking leads us in no clear direction, Plato lacks (as I pot it) the
concept of Art with a capital A, but he knows quite well what he is
talking about; we, with the concept, do not. We do not know what art
is, or at any rate what value we are attributing to something by calling
it art. Consider first what a farrago the concept is. Even from the outset,
when eighteenth-century Europeans began to place the diverse activ-
ities of poetry, painting, music, sculpture, and architecture firmly to-
gether under the common heading 'the fine arts', distinguishing them
thereby both from crafts and sciences, the principle of unity was al-
ready in doubt: either they all 'imitated beautiful nature', or they aimed
at pleasurable entertainment and could be dubbed the 'polite* or 'ele-
gant arts*,5 The latter idea was surely the more fruitful: it led to the
modern elaboration of 'the aesthetic' as an identifiable area of value.
Art could then be understood in terms of the aesthetic. But there have
been numerous subsequent attempts to provide a definition of what
makes such things art and other things not. To use the concept 'art'
nowadays is to inherit salient chunks of this history, but not necessarily
to possess a concept with a philosophical edge clear enough for a
response to Plato.
For example, do we concentrate on the eighteenth-century ideas that
art has pleasure as its object and requires a cultivated taste to appreci-
ate? Or do we, in a more Romantic vein, locate the key element in the
mental powers of the artist from which the work of art issues, dignified
perhaps by the title "genius'? Some have seen art as essentially a type
of activity, in which a person crystallizes Ms or her emotions,6 whereas
others have seen it more as a privileged set of objects whose form
moves the receptive perceiver to a certain kind of response.7 Both of
s
See Kristeller (1952). Kristelier (1951) is also required for the full narrative,
6
I think here especially of ColBngwood (1938).
1
Merely two examples: "There must be some one quality without which a work of art
cannot exist . , , Only one answer seems possible—significant form, ... I mean a com-
bination of lines and colours ... that moves me aesthetically' (Bell, 87—9). "Art is most
simply and most usually defined as an attempt to e*eate pleasing forms" (Read, 16).
188 Plato and the Philosophy of Art
these views set themselves in opposition to the "imitation of nature*
view (traditionally regarded as the oldest definition of art, and of course
claiming Plato himself as ancestor), so that in the earlier part of this
century it was customary to decry representation as inessential, in
favour of expression or form.8 Another familiar variable in theories of
art is whether art is or should be morally significant. That pair of
extremist contemporaries, Tolstoy and Oscar Wilde, tend to be invoked
to point up this debate, saying on the one hand that true art must
transmit sound moral feelings from person to person or be worthless,
and on the other that art is 'immoral' and aims at 'emotion for the sake
of emotion*, having nothing to do with anything else in life.9 Probably
few agree with either extreme—but they illustrate the great diversity
with which the essential point of art has been conceived. Revisionists,
in the hope of making the concept begin to be clear, have been over-
rathless in ruling certain generally accepted forms •as not art 'proper*.
If art is 'significant form*, many representational paintings need not
count among the definienda. If art is 'expression of emotion*, works
which are calculated merely to arouse emotions such as amusement or
patriotic feeling or religious awe, need not be art 'properly speaking'.
If art is 'transmission of moral and religious feeling", the opposite
applies. Fundamental antagonists seem curiously agreed about the gen-
eral kinds of thing which fall within the range of the term 'art', which
are more or less the beaux arts of the eighteenth century. But their
stories are unhelpfully diverse.
Recognizing at last that the various things called art in modem times
share no single obvious set of properties, philosophical aesthetics has
moved into a new era. Writers in aesthetics fight shy of the question
what gives art its value, because they no longer seriously believe that
there is an elusive essence—the 'one common quality', the nature of
'art proper*-—to dispute about With such a view, no unanimous decla-
ration about the value of art can be expected. A still stronger line,
impressed by successive waves of me avant-garde in this century, says
that the whole point about the concept of art is that it is thoroughly
revisable, open-ended, allowing for radical change in practice. The
activities of Duchamp and Ms successors down to today's conceptual,
performance, and installation artists have widened the understanding of
what can be art, and posed fundamental questions about how it comes
8
See. Cotlingwtwd (1938), 42-6; Bell, 91 ff.
9
Tolstoy, esp. 49-54; Wilde, 380.
Plato and the Philosophy of Art 189
to be so. Some writers have resorted to institutional and historical
definitions10 where art is simply a classificatory term; that which bears
a certain relation to the actual institutions of making, performing, con-
suming, and learning about paintings, plays, musical pieces, literature,
is art; or art is simply that which intentionally bears some specifiable
relation to what in the past was accepted as art. Such theories claim that
the only fact about art as such is that it has been classified as art—and
they do not pretend to tel us what is of value in having things so
classified. Nothing prevents as asking what is important aboat the in-
stitutions we have, but again we may expect only a shifting answer, an
answer responsive to historical change and unable to deal in essences,
What institutional theories do not tell us is whether institutions which
are called 'art' arise or persist because things of genuine value are
produced or discovered within them,"
We can proceed, then, only if we resist- our own Socratic inclination
to demand a single, common characteristic in answer to the question
'What is .. ,?* The concept 'art* will yield us no straightforward reply
of the form "Art is .,.' or "The value of art is ., .*, It is a concept which
can seem to stand for the perpetual possibility of change—the last
thing to fit into the cities of the Republic or the Laws—or merely a
permissive empty space travelling through history, to be filled variously
according to circumstance: now ethical, now beautiful, now soothing,
now harrowing, now truthful, now superficial, now deliberately
ambivalent. Art is what Plato would call pantodapos: it is manifold,
capable of being anything' and everything. He would regard this as an
admission of .defeat, an acknowledgement of the very disunity he puts
his finger on: people say that the arts are fine because they give pleas-
ure, but they also say that Horner gives a profound and comprehensive
education. (They also, remember, have the quite unfounded thought
that to make fine poems which give pleasure qualifies you as an ethical
teacher.) Now art itself proves to be fickle. Question it on its 'moral
seriousness and it becomes, full of superficial beauty; praise its charms
and it pretends to be deep. Is its point to be a likeness of reality, or a
study in balance and form, harmony, line, and colour? Should it please,
challenge, or change us? Art begins to look worse than the person in
Republic 3 who becomes 'double' through following two masters. Never-
theless, whatever defence we give must acknowledge the abundant
10
Two much-discussed attempts are Dickie, and Levinson,
11
Cf. Wollheim, 160 ff.
190 Plato and the Philosophy of Art
diversity of the arts, and so must reject any insistence on a monolithic
answer,
Thus far our strategy is one of resistance; evasion of over-intense
inquiry from outside our own way of life, and refusal of the assumption
that a plurality of answers is a defeat. Resistance can be undertaken in
a more radical spirit, however, resulting in what may be called an 'anti-
philosophy* strategy. There is truth in the idea that Plato had to attack
mimetic poetry in order to found his philosophy at all: he had to make
room for the distinctions between truth and appearance, goodness and
pleasure, or goodness and mere opinions of goodness. The dialectical
method and what it valued could not be assimilated into a theatroeraey,
so a radical break was required. Once philosophy has established an
absolute dominance, it is easy for it to regard the arts as alien or
puzzling. Plato is too early in the process to be. other than hostile; later
(the narrative is that of Danto12) philosophy becomes confident enough
to welcome the arts as something of a domestic pet. A defender of
the arts might seek to exploit this story and reverse the direction of
dominance. Philosophy—at least in Plato's conception of it—may itself
seem the questionable act of violence against which one roust rebel in
order to restore art to its proper value.
This is one aspect of the influential, diagnosis given by Nietzsche in
The Birth of Tragedy, Socrates, the archetypal, philosopher, whose 'logi-
cal urge* was 'absolutely prevented from turning against itself',13 looks
at tragedy with his 'one peat Cyclops eye', and of course finds 'Some-
thing rather unreasonable ... so motley and manifold that it could not
but be repugnant to a sober mind, and a daDgerous tinder for sensitive
and susceptible souls.'14 The-Platonic dialogue, Nietzsche writes, 'was, as
it were, the barge on which the shipwrecked ancient poetry saved herself
with all her children: crowded into a narrow space and timidly submit-
ting to the single pilot, Socrates, they now sailed into a new world.*15
If the archetypal philosopher, as he stands scrutinizing tragedy for its
rational justification, is the very rock on which it is wrecked, we may
conclude that the antagonism between tragedy and philosophy is genu-
ine, and that attempts to neutralize the "ancient quarrel* are misguided.16
12
Danto (1986), 1-21, '3 Nietzsche, The Birth of Tragedy, sect. 13 (88).
14 I5
Ibid., sect. 14 (89), Ibid 90-1.
16
Cf.: 'art, in which precisely the lie is sanctified, and the wilt to deception has a good
conscience, is much more fundamentally opposed to the ascetic ideal than is science: this
was instinctively sensed by Plato, the greatest enemy of art Europe has yet produced.
Plato versus Homer; that is the ccanplete, the genuine antagonism* (Genealogy afMarah,
iii, sect. 25 (589-90)).
Plato and the Philosophy of Art 191
In Nietzsche's story, the Socratic'cultural force measures tragedy against
the standard of intelligibility17 and thereby kills it, because tragedy's
excellence lies not in its appealing to the rational mind, but in a fusion
of the Apollonian and the Dionysian, the radiant image and the terri-
fying enactment of the individual's destruction. The Apollonian image
of the hero is a dream, an appearance, whose function is to amaze, and
to transmute into something bearable the Dionysian glimpse into the
abyss which the drama as a whole presents. Plato's suspicions are
accurate, on this view; tragedy is wizardry, it trades in Traum and
Rausch—dream and intoxication. The later Nietzsche builds on this
opposition between philosophy and art. Art, for him, is a set of fabri-
cations—'we possess art lest we perish of the truth'1*—and Plato must
be hostile to it because of his all-governing aspiration towards troth.
Now Nietzsche urges us to to ist that aspiration, which for him manifests
the 'ascetic ideal5, a longing 'to get away from all appearance, change,
becoming, death';** if we become suspicious of that allegedly life-
denying ideal, then we must be suspicious about oar own "will to truth*:
'the value of truth most ... be experimentally catted into question',20
It is salutary to reflect mat the status and origin of the Platonic
philosophical enterprise is not above suspicion. Plato's own use of
mimesis, myth, and poetic language suggests an awareness of the dif-
ficulty of self-justification:21 the life devoted to rational enquiry into the
truth is not defended simply by engaging in rational enquiry, but has to
be pictured, acted out, and metaphorically conveyed. However, to adopt
a radically anti-philosophical stance—trying to undermine Plato by
posing the question "Why is truth so important to you?*-—generates at
best an uneasy pluralism: we dare not regard either philosophy or the
arts as a secure enough platform from which to assess the value of the
other. Our questions about the arts themselves are, meanwhile, left
hanging. So instead of merely refusing complicity with the Platonic
mode of inquiry, we must attempt a more positive account of the arts.
The emissaries charged with defending mimetic and pleasure-giving
poetry arrive in the model city-—what do they say? "Philosophy as Plato
conceives it is naturally antithetical to the arts, their nature and value
is diverse and difficult to capture, and one should look at them only
17 l?
Birth of Tragedy, sect. 12 (82-4). The Will to Power, aphorism 822.
M
" Genealogy, iii, sect. 28 (598-9). Ibid, sect 24 (589).
21
Cf. Gri&wold (1988), who understands the 'ancient quarrel' as concerning the
fundamental viability of philosophy itself, and fads that some of Plato's modern
critics, including Nietzsche, lead us to an 'irreducible pluralism' (see esp. 152 ff.).
192 Plato and the Philosophy of Art
from within the-cultural life in which they play a significant role.'—A
preamble, but surely there is more? I shall propose two lines of thought,
which I call the aesthetic defence and the cognitive/ethical defence.
First let us try to develop the aesthetic defence in outline. Plato's
very complaints that the arts are concerned with pleasure, appearance,
and play rather than fostering moral goodness or extending our know-
ledge, allow room for the thought that their point is, as we would say,
aesthetic, and so not reducible to anything whose point is moral or
cognitive. Although Plato talks of fine things which give pleasure with-
out any other benefit, he does not envisage a proper defence of the arts
emerging from this notion. To move to a convincing theory of the
aesthetic, we must try to specify a .kind of response, be it pleasure or
satisfaction or liking, which is sui generis, irreducible to other forms
of response, and possessing a unique value for the person who has it.
Following Kant, we might suggest that this is a response to the ex-
perienced perceptual form of an object, and one which is not grounded
on any desires we may have towards the object. The Kantian notion is
disinterested pleasure, and although both 'disinterested' and 'pleasure'
are terms liable to be disputed, we can take this as a model for the kind
of response on which the aesthetic defence is to build. This aesthetic
way of responding enables us to make a distinctive kind of judgement,
which cannot be reduced to any other kind. Aesthetic judgements do
not assert that an object is morally good, or that it fulfils a purpose, nor
do they state a knowledge-claim about it. They are not based on the
kind of expert-principle which Plato sought in the ideal techne. Never-
theless they have standards of correctness of their own. They do not
merely assert a subjective like or dislike, but are judgements which
claim validity for the whole community. The reasons 1 have for my
judgement are also reasons for others. There can thus be standards of
aesthetic value to which a whole community in principle assents.
This framework will allow us to reply to Plato on two specific points.
He alleges that artists, if allowed their freedom, will attempt to instil
pleasure in an audience in a wholly indiscriminate manner, pandering
to whatever preferences they may have. And, secondly, he claims that
the arts lack any proper autonomous measure of success or failure; they
can be measured by external standards for truth or moral value, but to
rely on the pleasure they give is to have no real standard of judge-
ment—the poet must look for this to the lawgiver or philosopher. With
some conception of a specifically aesthetic response we can reply to the
first point by saying that the artist need not be out to cause pleasure in
Plato and the Philosophy of Art 193
an. unqualified manner. Not all pleasures are aesthetic pleasures. Enjoy-
ing something which one finds aesthetically good can (in principle)
be distinguished from enjoying something for sentimental reasons, or
because it arouses acquisiti¥eness or sexual feeling or plays on one's
prejudices. Because of this differentiation of the aesthetic response, it
becomes possible to distinguish propagandistie, pornographic, or merely
entertaining works from those whose point is aesthetic. On the second
point we can say this: It is true that success and failure in the arts
cannot be measured by the kind of objective standard required by a
techne. An aesthetic judgement is based not on generalizable principles
of correctness, but on the particular response which an observer has,
But there are, nevertheless, genuine aesthetic standards. AH aesthetic
judgement claims that the work is a good or bad one, going beyond a
mere report that some subjective response has occurred. The judgement
is shareable. A community can come to agree that a work is aesthetic-
ally fine or aesthetically poor, by agreeing in their aesthetic response to
it, and by discourse which fixes the reasons for that response. So al-
though the aesthetic domain is in a senseunprincipled (alogon pragma),-
it is not without standards. Ait can have genuine standards which need
not be moral or cognitive.
There is no doubt that the aesthetic defence fills a lacuna in the
Platonic picture. Not to acknowledge that there are aesthetic responses
(however they are to be theoretically described), that some things are
valued because we can respond aesthetically to them, and that some
judgements about the arts are judgements of aesthetic value which purport
to be communal rather than merely subjective, is to miss a great deal.
To give but one example, the elaborate world of musical performance,
reception, criticism, and education would be unintelligible to someone
who did not believe in the existence of aesthetic responses, judgements,
and values.
Any renewed Platonic challenge must now be cast thus: if aesthetic
value is irreducible to moral or cognitive value, and if the point of the
arts is their providing aesthetic value—what 'is then so good about
having the arts in our lives? Or, to pot it bluntly, what is the value of
having works with aesthetic value? This is a strange question, But it is
important to see why. For the proponent of the aesthetic defence may
be tempted by the following analysis: 'Plato, in demanding that the arts
always contribute towards making his citizens healthier and wiser and
Ms community more cohesive, was guilty of instrunnentalism—of seek-
ing a value for works of art only in some further end to which they
194 Plato and the Philosophy of Art
could serve as a means. Adopting the aesthetic defence against Plato
means demarcating a unique and irreducible species of value. If we
then go on to ask for the value of haviag works with aesthetic value,
we lapse back into instromentalism and fail to give an account in which
aesthetic value is autonomous,*
However, the opposition between autonomous and instrumental
value here is too simple. A distinction can be drawn between evaluations
of works of art and apologies for them,22 The former are answers to the
question 'What makes this, a good painting or tragedy?* and the latter
to the question 'What makes art a good thing to have in one's life?* If
we assume that answers to the first kind of question will be evaluations
in aesthetic terms, then since presumably nobody wants an apology for
bad art, the second question will indeed amount to the following: 'What
makes art which is aesthetically good a good thing to have in one's
life?' The question is strange not because it misconceives aesthetic
value as a form of instrumental good, but because it strays again into
scrutinizing aesthetic practices from an external, alienated standpoint.
By contest, fully to imagine the absence of the aesthetic from some-
one's life would give sufficient insight into that life's impoverishment,
and render the question practically unaskable. A total non-aesthete,
who never listens with pleasure to any music, never reads a poem or
novel, never visits an art gallery, never produces anything 'artistic*, and
takes no interest whatever in the pleasing appearance, order, or struc-
ture of any part of the world he or she experiences, would arguably be
deficient in one of the characteristic aspects of human life. It only
remains to point out that the most frequent and fruitful exposure to the
aesthetic is gained by participating in the many traditions of poetry,
drama, music, and painting which already exist. They are one obvious
way to remain in touch with one of the characteristic aspects of one's
own humanity.
The proponent of the aesthetic defence is thus drawn into the vertigi-
nous feat of arguing that art, as the prime arena of communally aesthetic
value, is an absolute good in itself. Kant's thinking here is suggestive
but difficult: making judgements of beauty supposedly exemplifies a
supersensible harmony between our fundamental cognitive abilities and
nature, and, by manifesting our freedom in the phenomenal realm enables
us to reconcile our own place in nature with our status as rational
n
The point and the terminology are taken from Diffey, 165 ff.
Plato and the Philosophy of Art 195
23
moral agents. This has first to be shown to apply to art in particular,
and thea to be rendered intelligible. The same applies to Hegel's view
that the value of art is explained by a fundamental human need for self-
realization ('man's rational impulse to exalt the inner and outer world
into a spiritual consciousness for himself, as an object in which he,
recognizes his own self*24). Is this difficult notion a tree reflection of
reality, and to what extent is the general need for self-realization one
whose fulfilment requires art as such? We may look to the idea that art
presents in sensuous terms the reconciled opposition of particular and
universal,25 or to Schiller's notion of the aesthetic as the site of freedom
or play which unifies the sensuous and the intellectual and realizes the
human potential to the fullest.2* On the way to making such thoughts
perspicuous, we shall have discovered that the task before us is not dial
of clearing up some quirky blind spot of Plato's, local to what we call
aesthetics. Only by confronting Plato's notion of human excellence on
the pandest scale can the aesthetic defence hope to succeed.
The aesthetic defence, again calling on Kant and Schiller,27 also has
on its side the argument that a culture depends on the aesthetic, and that
our being fully human depends, on our belonging to a culture: only if
we can aim to converge in judgements that' are made in a realm of
freedom are we fully human. If this is true, then even though particular
individuals.may turn their backs on the aesthetic to a greater or lesser
extent, their other ethical, social or cognitive ends depend on their
Eving in a culture in which artworks are produced and evaluated aes-
thetically. It will, again, be quite difficult to determine whether this
elevated claim is one we should believe. If it is, the aspirations embod-
ied in Plato's own thinking may be owed to his belonging to the culture
of tragedians, rhapsodes, and the lovers of sights and sounds—and that
would be an impressive point to be able to make in the debate we are
imagining,
Suppose that we have a convincing story about the fundamental
importance of the aesthetic value of art, what would it have achieved
against Plato? He might (let us imagine) concede that aesthetic evaluation
is autonomous, and agree that engaging in some activities of aesthetic
value is a species of absolute good for any human being, and that only
in an aesthetically enriched culture can other human endeavours be
23 n
Cf. -Savile, 103. Hegel, 36.
25
Ibid 59-61. * Schiller, esp. 94-109.
27
Here I am assisted espeeialy by Hampshire (1960) and (1989).
196 Plato and the Philosophy of Art
realized. He would not need to change his views radically: recall the
love of beauty, order, and harmony which he would inculcate into Ms
citizens in Republic 3 and Lows.28 But his critique is not necessarily
silenced. His line will still be that the aesthetic cannot be allowed to
dominate in a healthy life, whether individual or communal. The aes-
thetic, he will say, cannot be that around which our lives are structured,
and it cannot alone set the standard for art. Troth and the good, once
our culture can grasp them as distinct ends, are more important. So
although we will now have reason to recognize the aesthetic as a self-
contained value, and reason not to expunge it from our ideal commun-
ity (as Plato never really wished to do anyway), we will still have reason
to regulate its particular instances in the light of our other values. And
particular instances were always the point: if tragic poetry or some
other form of mimesis-—irrespective of its being a fine instance of
aesthetic value—is, by its nature and by its characteristic psychological
effects, detrimental to the search for truth and the good, then we should
still be concerned not to let it rule in our souls, but ward off its
powerful spell with argumentative remedies. Plato's arguments for
this appraisal of tragedy still stand awaiting a reply.
'The total non-aesthete might be ethically and cognitively impover-
shed. Lacking all propensity to respond disinterestedly to pattern or
order, he or she would arguably have a diminished capacity to under-
stand his or her fellow humans, or indeed the world: he or she might
be less able to reason, to do science, history, mathematics, or philoso-
phy, Plato could concur: he never advocated or even conceived of a
total non-aesthete. But how clear is it that these other endeavours would
be hampered by one's failing to confront beautiful works of artl The
claim that someone involved with aesthetically valuable art would be
morally better than someone not so involved is questionable. It could
turn out to be an empirical truth that those with their aesthetic sensibili-
ties directed specifically towards the arts tend to have a better ail-round
responsiveness in human or ethical terms. (It could turn out not to be
the case.) But if so, we should not know how to explain the correlation,
since it is possible that having some generalized human responsiveness
disposes one well towards the arts, and not the other way round.29
Concern with the aesthetic in art might be a symptom of being morally
sensitive; Kant thought something parallel when he wrote that an interest
a
Halliwei (1991, 330} suggests that in Rep, 3 (400c-402a, 403c) Plato has in effect
accepted something congenial to Schiller's notion of an aesthetic culture.
29
Also a point rnatte by Diffcy, 1,14,
Plato and the Philosophy of Art 197
in contemplating natural beauty 'is at least indicative of a temper of
mind favourable to the moral feeling* and. requires that someone• 'has
previously set his interest deep in the foundations of the morally good*.30
(Note, incidentally, that here interest in art is excluded from such a
connection with moral goodness.) We might suggest that the art-free
life must lack something in understanding of human psychology, and
that art is of value in helping us to know the nature of courage and
justice, or in understanding the intricacies of the ways people think and
feel. But would art make this contribution in virtue of having aesthetic
value? We have explained the aesthetic in a more or less Kantian way,
in terms of non-moral, non-cognitive judgements that are founded on
disinterested responses to objects perceived. Aesthetic value is -some-
thing like beauty, on this account. But, although the two may often be
found together, it is not clear that a concern for beauty in art improves
one's understanding of human behaviour.
Thus we are led to the second- line of defence, which I have called
the cognitive/ethical defence. It will not be concerned to dispute whether
the value of tragedy and its kindred arts is aesthetic. It need make no
use of that concept at all, as (on a plausible reading31) Aristotle does not
in his reply to Plato. Instead, it undertakes to show by a direct route that
tragedy and other fictional representations of human behaviour make a
fundamental contribution to our ethical life and to our knowledge. What
kind of knowledge, though? It seems unlikely that there is class of true
propositions which only artworks can put us in touch with—artworks
could be at best the most effective means of coming to know them. But
there is a further difficulty here: if we ask which prepositional truths a
particular drama or novel teaches us, answers tend to be either banal or
implausible.32 Even supposing that we manage to cull some useful piece
of wisdom (such as, perhaps: "When retiring as head of a family or
government, it is unwise to yield your authority too early to whoever
puts up the best show of affection*)—we ought to woader whether the
dramatist could not have conveyed that proposition in less labour-
intensive fashion. The conclusion should be, not that there is nothing
30
Kant, §42, 157, 160 (my emphasis}..
" Well presented by Halliwell (1991), 339-42.
12
As Stolnitz illustrates, by considering Pride and Prejudice, (with its 'psychological
troth": "Stubborn pride and ignorant prejudice keep attractive people apart*) and Crime
and Punishment {'Punishment for a crime frightens a criminal less lhan we think because
the criminal himself demands it'). These are probably truths, in that what they describe
happens, but the value of the respective works does not He in their putting us in mind
of these propositions.
198 Plato and the Philosophy of Art
to learn from drama, but that not all learning is the mastery of true
propositions.
The 'knowledge' that we may more plausibly claim for tragedy is an
understanding of human behaviour through imagining possible human
behaviour.and being impressed by its emotional significance. This is a
kind of understanding whose attainment is an ethical gain, and part of
what being a good person is. So the point is not that tragedy has two
valoes, one cognitive and one ethical: rather that it enables us to attain
a kind of .knowledge in a way which is ethically valuable,33 We are
required to disagree with Plato over the nature of ethical understanding,
affirming that we learn best when allowed to explore ideas of jealousy,
lust, stupidity, confusion, and despair as they affect passages of
people's lives, not when kept on a restricted diet of artificially rational
paradigms. Secondly, we must disagree with Plato over the nature of
mimesis. In a nutshell, the claim will be that fictional representation
involves the creative use of the imagination, that the imagination, by
showing us how it would feel to be a person in multifarious circum-
stances which we will never in fact occupy, helps us eventually learn
how to feel,34 and that learning to feel in just this way is an irreplace-
ably valuable part of ethical development.
For all Ms imaginative writing, Plato does not do justice to imagina-
tion's role in the human make-up,35 Yet how basic it is to entertain a
thought about how the world is not but could be—to compose an in-
telligible picture or story about intelligible people who do not exist. Not
to imagine would be exceedingly strange for a member of the human,
species. Aristotle corrects Plato in devastating manner with the simple
utterance that 'man differs from the other animals in being most
mimetic*; imaginative production is something kataphusin—in accord-
ance with our nature.56 That we are all natural and skilful imaginers is,
however, something Plato appears, or affects, to overlook. Again and
again we have seen him not grasping the point of representation in the
arts; a painter makes a bed which strangely happens not to be a real one,
33
I have found Nussbaum (1990) suggestive here (see esp. 23-9).
34
I am tntoeneed here by Scroton (unpublished): 'We learn by example what to feel,
and what not to feel. Involved in this process incidentally, is another kind of knowledge:
knowing what it's like. Shakespeare's King Lear teaches us what it's like to undergo the
extremes of ingratitude, by enabling us to imagine what it's like. What we acquire is not
propositions! knowledge of some "subjective" fact, but familiarity with a state of mind."
55
His critique of drama seems indeed to be 'rooted ultimately in a fear of imagiaa-
tion"— Halliwell (1992), 69.
y
> Poetics 1448b4-20.
Plato and the Philosophy of Art 199
Homer mysteriously tries to 'persuade us* that he is someone else,
audiences and actors weep and shudder at distressing events which they
perversely enjoy. Why not say that they are using their imaginations
and making or enjoying a representation? As Aristotle's other well-
known dictum has it, 'objects which in themselves we view with pain,
we delight to contemplate when reproduced in a likeness with minute
fidelity*.37 Plato recognizes that people tend to think pleasure in mimesis
is a good thing for its own sake. But he denies the possibility that we
both benefit from experiencing the contents of our imaginings and at
the same time happily recognize them as only imaginings.
Plato thinks that taking pleasure in representations of actions is never
clearly distinguished front approving actions of the same kind in real
life. So poets who aim to benefit their audience ought not to write about
baseness, excessive grief, or unpunished injustice, because these will
simply escape beyond the conines of the image. What we enact and see
enacted we will become ourselves; whether the enactment is in or out
of a story makes, for him, no difference. It is as if drama has no
containing skin around it, so that despicable things leak out and are
soaked up by the defenceless psyche,38 The traih, however, is that
imaginings interact in a much more subtle way with other thoughts and
emotions. We exercise our full understanding on Thebes, Oedipus, and
Jocasta. Although they are only an image, our (funking about them is
no less systematic or fruitful than our thought about the real world. In
this way imagination is not a wholly separate capacity from those of
ordinary belief-formation and reasoning, which is why there is no bar-
rier to our learning about real actions, motivations, and conflicts through
watching a drama. But on the other hand, we are not always at the mercy
of whatever appears before us. We can—effortlessly, kata phusin—-
approve the representation without simply approving or copying what
is represented. That is the first massive achievement of Aristotle's theory
as a reply to Plato.
The second is the hint that tragedy's engagement with our emotions
is both an essential and a beneficial feature of it. It is difficult to know
exactly what to say here. Somehow our feelings for the situation of
37
Ibid. 1448blO-ll,
31
Dante (1987, 4) uses the same metaphor for the opposite view from Plato's: "The
concept of art interposes between life and literature a very tough membrane, which
insures the incapacity of the artist to inflict moral harm so long as it is recognized that
what he is doing is art.* I owe this quote to Nehaaias (1991), 350. See also Nehamas
(1988) on the 'transparency' of representation in Plato.
200 Plato and the Philosophy of Art
Oedipus are not cordoned off from the rest of OUT feelings; they are
not-mere pretence, for 'fearing* and 'pitying* here really can—as Plato
over-insists—affect our attitudes in ordinary life. And yet these are not
straightforwardly real emotions, since they cannot' initiate action towards
Oedipus, and are not unbearably painful to experience. We are on the
edge between safety and vulnerability here: safe because we handle
mimesis with ease, vulnerable because an understanding of the scene's
bearing on our own emotional life is forced upon us. Plato would see
this doubleness as bearing out his worst fears about tragedy, but the
cognitive/ethical defence seeks to transform this very feature into a
positive one.
On this account artistic mimesis is continuous both with the life in
which we act and suffer, and with the educative aims of other forms
of discourse—the sermon, the philosophical treatise. It presents us with
an opportunity to learn how to live, what to seek, what comforts not
to expect. It differs, however, both from ordinary life and from these
other forms of discourse. As against life, it.offers both objectivity, and
intimacy without predicament, Flint Schier is helpful here;
In real life close knowledge entails intimacy, but intimacy entails predicament;
to be inward with someone's feelings usually entails that we begin to care
about those feelings ... but then when we care about them, we naturally want
to do- something. ... In the theatre, we can achieve an intimate knowledge of
characters without really finding ourselves sharing their predicament, ... But
there is a second advantage for art over reality which I think is even more
important than the disinterest of the spectator: that is the disinterest or objec-
tivity of the artist. Obviously, if someone is in the throes of agony they will not
so conduct themselves that we will be provided with a maximally acute sense
of their distress. Real distress is often much less powerfully expressed than
theatrical distress—partly because people rarely want to stare (heir own situ-
ation in the face. ... The great artist can escape this restriction; and therefore
his characters will speak and act in a much more revealing way than would an
actual victim of disaster.3*
We may add that actual victims tend either to perish or to carry away
with them some kind of impairment. To survive as an enriched spec-
tator in a real version of Lear's Britain would be inhuman.
As against life, then, tragic mimesis offers us clear vision and free-
dom to think. As against the sermon or philosophical treatise, it offers
us not generalities but the image of humanity in the particularity of
K
Schier (1989), 24.
Plato and the Philosophy of Art 201
action. And Plato was right: part of us must submit to the image with
a trusting, uncritical sensitivity to the feelings it portrays—this submis-
sion helps us begin to learn what it feels like to suffer at the very limits
of endurance, to inflict suffering, or to allow it to happen. In that worn-
out metaphor, drama 'brings home* the truth. It feeds into our under-
standing of our own lives at a level which mere argument and exhortation
cannot penetrate. This, in outline, is the cognitive/ethical defence. Its
strength is that it combines an end—learning how to live a better life—<-
that Plato could not fault, with an account of why mimesis is a uniquely
valuable means to it Neither philosophy nor the events of life itself
could replace the satisfying and natural combination of emotional in-
volvement and dispassionate contemplation that mimesis of human action
has to offer.
We have now prepared two different replies for our defenders of the
arts. Art has aesthetic value, which is an important human achievement
irreducible to other values. Art presents to us images from which we
learn in a unique way about ethical matters. Both seem true. Aesthetic
value and cognitive/ethical value are compatible—many artworks ob-
viously score on both counts. Nor can these two kinds of value always
be isolated from one another: we know that relations between form
and content, for example, are various and complicated. But can either
defence be collapsed whoEy within the other? I would argue not. One
reason for pressing the two accounts together would be the thought that
the pleasure in representations and the pleasure in beauty are of a kind,
or, as Roger Scrtton puts it, 'interest in representation is a special case
of aesthetic interest*.40 The ease with which Aristotle has so often been
co-opted into- the aesthetic defence suggests that such a view is wide-
spread. But although the cognitive/ethical defence claims that fictional
representation has the advantage of 'distancing* us from real-life pre-
dicament (Schier talks of the 'disinterestedness* of artist and spectator
as a cognitive/ethical benefit), it makes DO mention of aesthetic judge-
ment or beauty. We attend for the sake of learning and expanding our
ethical awareness, and 'to learn, gives the greatest pleasure*.41 Attending
for the sake of learning may marry 'happily with taking: an aesthetic
interest in the drama, even to the extent that in experience we cannot
clearly discriminate the two as separate attitudes. Nevertheless they are
separate, and in practice we retain ttie right to shift from one to the
other. Opera is full of examples. Someone may find the mental lives of
48 4I
Scroton (1974), 167, Poetics 144SM3.
202 Plato and the Philosophy of Art
Tristan and Isolde incoherent and unedifying or the moral sentiments of
The Magic Flute reprehensibly paternalistic, and yet see this as detract-
ing hardly at all from the greatness of the respective works, fa the face
of supreme aesthetic exceEence, it is boring and over-earnest to press
the eognitiYe/ethical line too hard. Yet if we decide that the point of
some artwork has been to justify racial hatred, say, we may suddenly
change tack and regard with great suspicion the person who claims to
embrace it wholeheartedly on its 'purely aesthetic* merits.
This chapter has been a series of sketches, and no doubt there-are
other strategies for arguing against Plato in the philosophy of art. But
we already have enough to be able to conclude. We may claim to have
shown that countering Plato's critique of the arts is an ambitious philo-
sophical undertaking. We must pay attention to questions about the
nature of philosophical enquiry itself and its relations to artistic prac-
tices from which it claims to distinguish itself. We must question
Plato's notion of human excellence and Ms conception of knowledge,
build up our own conception of the aesthetic, decide how it relates to
other values he recognizes, and fashion some alternative to his account
of the healthy working of the psyche, showing the importance of im-
agination and the capacity for aesthetic response, and facing up to the
idea that what is not rationally explicable to us can have a proper place
in our psychological well-being. This is vindication enough of the idea
that Plato's philosophy of art is a monumental contribution to the sub-
ject. For if he is wrong, it is scarcely about anything small or easy.
The most satisfying reply will have a number of components. We
must explain that no single defence can be demanded of the arts, and
insist that our natural involvement with them from within be allowed
to inform our account. Let us then assert that there is aesthetic value,
that artistic products often provide it, and that the best of (hem, in so
doing, address something of irreducible importance to us. Let us agree
that the imaginative portrayal of human action, thought, and feeling is
a unique contribution to our natural moral growth and self-understand-
ing. Let us also admit that die arts have a separate origin from philo-
sophy, and that they do not have to harmonize with any given set of
philosophical preconditions on pain of being valueless. But finally, let
us wonder whether the whole point of the arts is not deeply anti-
Platonic in another way. We have asserted that a plurality of values
may be found in the arts. It is not just that some works have one kind
of value, others another—though that is true. Rather, even the single
works that seem most to merit the title of art have a fullness and
Plata and the Philosophy of Art 203
richness which resists our puny attempts to compartmentalize them.
When we embark on artistic ventures, we take the risk of being seduced
by pleasing images, and the opposite risk of confronting a horribly
truthful likeness. It would be a security to know that what happened in
art did not matter to anything outside it, and equally a security to know
that it mattered a great, deal. Bat, it seems, we mast always engage with
art in insecurity over these questions, Plato's face would be a mask of
incomprehension, but let us put it to him that the final secret of art's
value lies in our being able to embrace it whole witfiout knowing ex-
actly what its value is, its contribution to the good life residing in a
unique openness to possibilities and a freedom from having to be merely
one definite thing.
Bibliography
Items marked * contain those translations of Plato which I have used unless
otherwise stated.
ADAM, J., The Republic of Plato (2 vols.; Cambridge, 1902).
A N N A S , J., An Introduction to Plato's Republic (Oxford, 1981).
—— Tlato on the Triviality of Literature', in Moravcsik and Tcmko (eds.)»
Plato on Beauty, Wisdom, and the Arts (1982), 1-28.
AQUINAS, STTHOMAS,SummaTheologiae(Blackfiiarsedn.;London, 1967),
vol. xix, la. 2ae, 22-30.
AR ISTOTLB, Poetics, in S. H. Butcher, Aristotle's Theory of Poetry and Fine
Art (1911; rcpr. New York, 1951).
B A R N E S , J., The Presocratic Philosophers (London, 1982).
B E A R D S L E Y . M . C., Aesthetics from Classical Greece to the Present: A Short
History {University of Alabama, 1966).
BELFIORE, E., 'Plato's Greatest Accusation against Poetry', in New Essays
on Plato, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Vol. DC (1983),
39-62.
*A Theory of Imitation in Plato's Republic'. Transactions of the American
Philological Association, 114 (1984), 121-46.
- * "Lies Unlike the Truth"; Plato on Hesiod, Theogony 27*, Transactions
of the American Philological Association, 115 (1985), 47-57.
BELL, C., "Significant Form*, in J. Hospers (ed.), Introductory Readings in
Aesthetics (New York, 1969), 87-99.
BOSANQUET, B., A History of Aesthetic (London, 1892).
ButJD, ML, "Belief and Sincerity in Poetry', in E. Schaper (ed.), Pleasure,
Preference and Value (Cambridge, 1983), 137-57.
—-— Music and the Emotions: The Philosophical Theories (London, 1985).
'How Pictures Look' (Inaugural Lecture at University CoDege London,
1991).
B O R N Y E A T , ML, 'Plato on the Grammar of Perceiving*, Classical Quarterly,
26 (1976), 29-51.
——The Theaetetus of Plato (Indianapolis, 1990).
"The Passion of Reason in Plato's Phaedrus' (unpublished).
CALLOW, S., Being an Actor (Hannondsworth, 1985).
C H E R N i s s, H., *Qn Plato's Republic X 597B1, American Journal of Philology,
53 (1932), 233-42.
C L A Y, D., 'The Tragic and Comic Poet of the Symposium', in J. P. Anton and
A. Prens (eds,), Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy, vol. 2 (Albany, NY,
1983), 186-202.
C O L L I N G W O O D , R. G., 'Plato's Philosophy of Art*, Mind, 34 (1925), 154-72.
Bibliography 205
— The Principles of Art (Oxford, 1938).
CORNFORD, F. M., Plato's Theory of Knowledge: The Theaetettts and the
Sophist of Plato translated with a running commentary (London,, 1935).
* Sophist, in Hamilton and Cairns (eds.}, Plato: Collected Dialogues, 957—
1017.
The Republic of Plato (Oxford, 1941).
C R o M B i E» JL M., An Examination of Plato's Doctrines (2 vols.; London, 1962-
3).
C R o s s, R, C,, arid WOOZLEY, A. D., Plato's Republic: A Philosophical Com-
mentary (London, 1964).
DAICHES, D., Critical Approaches to Literature (London, 1956).
DANTO, A. C., The Transfiguration of the Commonplace (Cambridge, Mass.,
1981).
The Philosophical Disenfranchisement of Art (New York, 1986).
—— The State of the Art (New York, 1987).
D E M A N D , R, 'Plato and the Painters', Phoenix, 29 (1975), 1-20.
D E R R I D A , J., 'Plato's Phamaey', in Dissemination, trans. B. Johnson (Lon-
don, 1981), 61-171.
DICKIE, G., Art and the Aesthetic: An Institutional Analysis (Ithaca, NY, and
London, 1974).
DIELS> BL and KR AN z, W., Die Fragments der Vorsokratiker, 3 vols. (Ber-
lin, 1951-4),
DIFFBY, T. J., The Republic of Art and Other Essays (New York, 1991).
DOODS, E. R., The Greeks and the Irrational (Berkeley, Calif., 1951).
—•—Plato: Gorgias (Oxford, 1959).
The Ancient Concept of Progress and Other Essays on Greek Literature
and Belief (Oxford, 1973),
DORTER, K., "The Ion: Plato's Characterization of Art', Journal of Aesthetics
and Art Criticism, 32 (1973-5), 65-78.
DOVER, K. J., Greek Popular Morality in the time of Plato and Aristotle
(Oxford, 1974).
—•—Plato; Symposium (Cambridge, 1980).
ELI.AS, J. A., Plato's Defence of Poetry (London, 1.984).
ELSE, G. F,,'"Imitation" ia the Fifth Century', Classical Philology, 53 (1958),
73-90.
Plato and Aristotle on Poetry (Chapel Hill, NC, 1986),
E V E R SON, S. (ed.)> Epistemology (Companions to Ancient Thought, 1; Cam-
bridge, 1990).
F E R R A R I , G. R. F., Listening to the Cicadas: A Study of Plato's Phaedrus
(Cambridge, 1987),
—— 'Plato and Poetry', in G. A. Kennedy (ed.), The Cambridge History of
Literary Criticism, i. Classical Criticism (Cambridge, 1989), 92-148.
FINE, G., 'Knowledge and Belief in Republic v", Archiv fur Geschichte der
Philosophic, 60 (1978), 121-39.
206 Bibliography
FINE, G., 'Knowledge and Belief in Republic v-vii", in S, Everson (ed,), Epis-
temology (1990), 85-115,
F L A S H A R , H., Der Dialog Ion als Zeugnis platonischer Philosophic. (Berlin,
1958),
FOR STB R, E, M,s "The Duty of Society to the Artist", in Two Cheers for
Democracy (London, 1972), 94-8.
GAOAM BR, H.-G., 'Plato and the Poets1, in Dialogue and Dialectic: Eight
Hermeneutkal Studies on Plato, trans, P. C. Smith (New Haven, Conn.,
1980), 39-72.
GALLOP, D,, Plato: Phaedo (Oxford, 1975).
G A u D K E A u L T, A., 'Mimesis etDiegesis cibezPlaton*,RevuedeMetaphysique
et de Morale, 94 (1989), 79-92.
GOLDEN, L., 'Plato's Concept of Mimesis', British Journal of Aesthetics, 15
(1975), 118-31. '
GOMBRICH, E, H., Art and Illusion (London, 1960).
'Illusion and Ait', in R. L. Gregory and E, H. Gombrich (eds.), Illusion
in Nature and Art (London, 1973).
GOODMAN, N., Languages of Art (New York, 1968).
GOSLING, J. C. B., 'Republic v; TaPollaKala etc.*,Phronesis, 5 (1960), 116-
28.
* Plato: philebus (Oxford, 1975).
GOULD, T,, The Ancient Quarrel between Poetry and Philosophy (Princeton,
NJ, 1990).
GREENE, W. C., 'Plate's View of Poetry', Harvard Studies in Classical Philo-
logy, 29 (1918), 1-75.
GREY, D. R., 'Art in the Republic', Philosophy, 27 (1952),'291-310.
G R i s w o L 0, C. L., "The Ideas and the Criticism of Poetry in Plato's Republic,
Book 10', Journal of the History of Philosophy, 19 (1981), 135-50,
'Plato's MetapMtesophy: Why Plato Wrote Dialogues', in C, L. Griswold
(ed.), Platonic Writings, Platonic Readings (New York and London, 1988),
143-67,
GEUBE, G. M. A., 'Plato's Theory of Beauty', The Monist, 37 (1927), 269-88.
—Plato's Thought (1935; rcpr, London, 1980),
* Plato: The Republic (London, 1981).
*GUTHRIE, W. K. C., Plato: Protagoras and Meno (Haimondsworth, 1956).
The Sophists (Cambridge, 1971),
A History of Greek Philosophy, TV. Plato the Man and His Dialogues:
Earlier Period (Cambridge, 1975).
HACKFORTH, R., Plato's Phaedrm (1952; rcpr. Cambridge, 1972).
Plato's Philebus (1958; repr, Cambridge, 1972).
HALHWELL, S., 'Plato and Aristotle on the Denial of Tragedy*, Proceedings
of the Cambridge Philological Society, 30 (1984), 49-71.
-—-Aristotle's Poetics (London, 1986),
— Plato: Republic 10 (Warminster, 1988).
Bibliography 207
— "The Importance of Plato and Aristotle for Aesthetics", Proceedings of the
Boston Ana Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy, 5 (1991), 321-57.
• 'Plato and the Psychology of Drama', in B. Zimmermano (ed.), Antike
Dramentheorien und ihre Rezeption (Stattgart, 1992), 55-73.
H A M i L T o N, E,, and C A i R N s, H. (eds.), Plato: Collected Dialogues (Princeton,
NJ, 1963).
*HAMILTON, W., Plato: Symposium (Hannondsworth, 1951).
HAMPSHIRE, S., 'The Conflict between Art and Politics*, The Listener, Oct.
13, 1960, 629-36.
'The Social Spirit of Mankind*, in E. POrster (ed.), Kant's Transcendental
Deductions {Stanford, Call, 1989), 145-56.
HAVELOCK, E. A., Preface to Plato (Cambridge, Mass., 1963).
H E o E L, O. W. P., Introductory Lectures on Aesthetics, trans. B. Bosanquet, ed
M. Inwood (Harmondsworth, 1993).
HESIGD, Theogony, in Hesiod's Theogony, fcrans. with introduction, etc.; by
E. S. Caldwell (Cambridge, Mass., 1987).
Works and Days, trans. A. N. Athanassakis, in Hesiod: Theogony, Works
and Days, Shield (Baltimore and London, 1983).
HOFSTADTER, A. and KB HNS, R., Philosophies of Art and Beauty (Chicago,
1964).
IRWIN, T. H., Plato's Moral Theory (Oxford, 1977u).
-— 'Plato's Heracleiteanism', Philosophical Quarterly, 27 (1977ft). 1-13.
*—-Plato: Gorgias (Oxford, 1979).'
Review of M. Nussbaian, The Fragility of Goodness, Journal of Philo-
sophy, 85 (1988), 376-83.
JAEGER, W., Paideia: The Ideals of Greek Culture, vol. ii, trans. G. KHghet
((Word, 1944).
J A N A WAY, C, 'Recent Woric in Aesthetics', Philosophical Books, 30 (1989),
193-201.
'Plato's Analogy between Paiater and Poet', British Journal of Aesthetics,
31 (1991), 1-12.
— 'Arts and Crafts in Plato and Colltngwood', Journal of Aesthetics and Art
Criticism, 50 (1992«), 45-54.
• 'Craft and Fineness in Plato's Ion', Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy,
10 (1992*), 1-23.
—— 'Beauty in Nature, Beauty in Ait', British Journal of Aesthetics, 33 (1993),
321-32.
JOWETT, B., Republic, in The Dialogues of Plato: translated into English with
analyses and introductions, vol. ii (Oxford, 1953), 1—499.
KAHN, C., 'The Beautiful and'the Genuine: A Discussion of Paul Woodruff,
Plato, Hippias Major', Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 3 (1985), 261-
87.
KANT, L, Critique of Judgement, trans. J. C, Meredith (Oxford, 1928).
K E R F E R D , O. B., The Sophistic Movement (Cambridge, 1981).
208 Bibliography
KEULS, E. C., Plato and Greek Painting (Leiden, 1978),
KOLLER, H., Die Mimesis in der Antike (Berne, 1954),
KOSMAN, L. A., 'Silence and Imitation in the Platonic Dialogues', in J, C.
Klagge and N. D. Smith (eds.), Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, suppL
vol. 1992: Methods of Interpreting Plato and his Dialogues (Oxford, 1992),
73-92.
KRISTBLLER, P. O., "The Modern System of the Arts: A Study in the History
of Aesthetics (I)*, Journal of the History of Ideas, 12 (1951), 496-527.
'The Modem System of the Arts: A Study in the History of Aesthetics
(II)', Journal of the History of Ideas, 13 (1952), 17-46.
LADRIERE, C., "The Problem of Plato's Ion', Journal of Aesthetics and Art
Criticism, 10 (1951), 26-34.
LBE, H. D. P., Plato: The Republic (Harmomdsworth, 1955).
* Plato: Timaeus (Harmondsworth, 1965),
*LEVETT, M. J. (rev. M. Burnyeat), 'Plato's Theaetetus', in M. Bumyeat, The
Theaetetus of Plato.
LEVi, P., 'Greek Drama' in J. Boardman, J. Griffin, and O. Murray (eds.)> The
Oxford History of the Classical World (Oxford, 1986), 156-85.
L E V I N S O N , G., 'Defining Art Historically', British Journal of Aesthetics, 19
(1979), 232-50.
LIDDELL, H. G., and SCOTT, JR., A Greek-English Lexicon, rev. H. S. Jones
(Oxford, 1968).
LODGE, R. C., Plato's Philosophy of Art (1953; repr. New York, 1975).
L O V I B O N O , S., 'Plato's Theory of Mind', in S. Everson (ed,). Psychology
(Companions to Ancient Thought, 2; Cambridge, 1991), 35-55.
LUCAS, D. W., Aristotle: Poetics (Oxford, 1968).
LYONS, J,, Structural Semantics: An Analysis of Part of the Vocabulary of
Plato, Publications of the Philological Society, 20 (Oxford, 1963).
McKsoN, R., "Literary Criticism and the Concept of Imitation in Antiquity',
in R. S. Crane (ed.), Critics and Criticism (Chicago, 1957), 117-45.
MOLINE, J., 'Plato on the Complexity of the Psyche*, Archivfur Geschichte
der Philosophic, 60 (1978), 1-26.
M O K A V C S I K , J. M. E., 'Reason and Eros in the "Ascenf'-passage of the
Symposium', in J. P. Anton and G. L. Kustas (eds.), Essays in Ancient Greek
Philosophy (Albany, NY, 1971), 285-302.
-—— 'Noetic Aspiration and Artistic Inspiration', in Moravcsik and Ternko
(eds.), Plato on Beauty, Wisdom, and the Arts (1982), 29-46.
'On Correcting the Poets', Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 4 (1986),
35-47.
and TEMKO, P. (eds.), Plato on Beauty, Wiscfam, and the Arts (Totowa,
NJ, 1982).
MOT HERS ILL, M., Beauty Restored (Oxford, 1984),
MURDOCH, I, The Fire and the Sun (Oxford, 1977).
MURPHY, N. R., The Interpretation of Plato's Republic (Oxford, 1951).
Bibliography 209
M U R R A Y , P., 'Poetic Inspiration in Early Greece", Journal of Hellenic Studies,
101 (1981), 87-100,
N E H A M A S , A,, 'Plato on Imitation and Poetry in Republic 10*, ia
Moravcsik and Temko (eds,), Plato on Beauty, Wisdom, and the Arts (1982),
47-78.
'Plato and the Mass Media', The Monist, 71 (1988), 214-34.
'Commentary on HaHiwelT, Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium
in Ancient Philosophy, 5 (1991), 349-57.
N I E T Z S C H E , E, On the Genealogy of Morals, trans, W, Kaufinann, in Basic
Writings of Nietzsche (New York, 1968), 449-599.
The Birth of Tragedy, ibid. 15-144.
- The Will to Power, ed, W. Kaulmann, trans. W. Kaufinann and R, J.
Hollingdale (New York, 1968),
N U S S B A U M , M, C., "'This Story Isn't True": Poetry, Goodness, and Under-
standing in Plato's Phaedrus', in Moravcsik and Temko (eds.), Plato on
Beauty, Wisdom, and the Arts (1982), 79-124,
-—- The Fragility of Goodness (Cambridge, 1986).
-—•—Love's Knowledge: Essays on Philosophy and Literature (New York and
Oxford, 1990).
GATES, W. J., Plato's View of Art (New York, 1972).
OSBORNE, C., 'The Repudiation of Representation in Plato's Republic and its
Repercussions', Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society, 33 (1987),
53-73.
PARTEE, M. H., 'Inspiration in the Aesthetics of Plato', Journal of Aesthetics
and Art Criticism, 30 (1971), 87-95.
P E N N E R , T., 'Thought and Desire in Plato', in G. Vlastos (ed.), Plato: A
Collection of Critical Essays (New York, 1971), ii. 96-118.
The Ascent from Nominalism (Dordrecht, 1987).
P I C K A R D - C A M B R I D G E , A. W., Dithyramb Tragedy and Comedy (Oxford,
1927).
P L O T I N U S , The Enneads, trans. S, MacKenna (London, 1962),
POHLENZ, M., 'Die Anfange der griechischen Poetik* (1920; repr. in Kleine
Schriften, ii (Hildesheim, 1965), 436-72.
POUND, E,, 'The Serious Artist', in Literary Essays of Ezra Pound (London,
1954), 4)_57.
PRICE, A. W,, Love and Friendship in Plato and Aristotle (Oxford, 1989).
READ, H,, The Meaning of Art (1931; repr. Hartnondsworth, 1949).
R E E V E , C. D. C., Plato: Republic, trans. G. M. A. Gnibe, rev. C. D. C. Reeve
(Indianapolis, 1992).
R O O C H N I K , D. L., 'Socrates's Use of the Techne-Analogy*, Journal of the
History of Philosophy, 24 (1986), 295-310.
*ROWE, C. J., Plato: Phaedrus (Warminster, 1986).
R u s K i N, J.,' Sesame and Lilies *, in Sesame and Lilies, The Two Paths and The
King of the Golden River (London, 1907), 1-79.
210 Bibliography
S A I N T S BURY, G., A History of-Criticism and Literary Taste in Europe, i.
Classical and Mediaeval Criticism (Edinburgh and London, 1908),
S A U N D E R S , T. J. (cd.), Plato: Early Socratic Dialogues (Barmonds worth,
1987),
* Plato: Ion, in Saunders (ed.), Plato: Early Socratic Dialogues (1987),
39-65,
* piat0: The Laws (Harmondswortb, 1975).
S A VILE, A,, The Test of Time; An Essay in Philosophical Aesthetics (Oxford,
1982),
SCHAPEE, E., Prelude to Aesthetics (London, 1968).
SCHIBR, F., Deeper into Pictures (Cambridge, 1986).
'The Claims of Tragedy: An Essay in Moral Psychology and Aesthetic
Theory', Philosophical Papers, 18 (1989), 7-26,
SCHILLER, F, On the Aesthetic Education of Mankind: In a Series of Letters,
ed, and trans. E. M. Wilkinson and L. A, Wilfoiighby (Oxford, 1967).
S C H O P E N H A U E R , A,, The World as Witt and Representation, trans. E, F, J.
Payne (2 vols.; New York, 1969).
SCHUHL, P.-M,, Platan et I'art de son Temps (Paris, 1933).
SCRUTON, R., Art and Imagination (London, 1974).
'On "knowing what"' (unpublished),
SHBLLEY, P. B,, The Complete Works of Percy Bysshe Shelley, vii (London,
1965).
SHORBY, P., Republic, in Hamilton and Cairns (eds.), Plato: Collected Dia-
logues, 575-844.
S I D N E Y , SIR PHILIP, *A Defence of Poetry', in K. Duncan-Jones and J, van
Dorsteo (eds.), Miscellaneous Prose of Sir Philip Sidney (Oxford, 1973), 73—
121.
*SKEMP, J. B., Statesman, in Hamilton and Cairns (eds.), Plato: Collected
Dialogues, 1018-85.
SORBOM, G., Mimesis and Art (Uppsala, 1966).
S P K A G U E , R.K. (ed.), The Older Sophists (Columbia, SC, 1972).
——Plato's Philosopher-King (Colombia, SC, 1976).
STEVEN, R. G., 'Plato and the Art of His Time', Classical Quarterly, 27
(1933), 149-55.
STEWART, J. A., The Myths of Plato (1905; repr, Fontwel, Sussex, 1960).
S T o L N i T z, J., 'On the Cognitive Triviality of Art', British Journal of Aesthet-
ics, 32 (1992), 191-200.
TATE, J., '"Imitation" in Plato's Republic', Classical Quarterly, 22 (1928),
16-23,'
—— 'Plato and "Imitation*", Classical Quarterly, 26 (1932), 161-9.
TAYLOR, A. E., Plato: The Man and his Work (London, 1926).
TIGERSTEDT, E. N., Plato's Idea of Poetical Inspiration (Helsinki, 1969).
''Furor poeticus: Poetic Inspiration in Greek Literature before Democritus
and Plato*, Journal of the History of ideas, 31 (1970), 163-78.
Bibliography 211
TOLSTOY, L,, What is Arfl, trans, A. Maude (Indianapolis, 1960).
*TR EDEN NICK, H., Apology, in The Last Days of Socrates (Hannondsworth,
1969).
URMSON, J. O,, 'Plato and the Poets', in Moravcsik aad Temko (eds.), Plato
on Beauty, Wisdom, and the Arts (1982), 125-36.
—— 'Pleasure and Distress: A Discussion of J, C. B. Gosling and C, C. W.
Taylor, The Greeks on Pleasure*, in Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy,
2 (1984), 209-21.
V E R D E N I U S , W. J., Mimesis: Plato's Doctrine of Artistic Imitation and its
Meaning to us (Leiden, 1949).
'Der Begriff der Mania in Platora Phaidros', Archiv fur Geschichte der
Philosophic, 44 (1962), 132-50.
- "The Principles of Greek Literary Criticism', Mnemosyne, 36 (1983), 14—
59.
VLASTOS, G,, 'The Disorderly Motion in the "Timaeus"' (1939), rep. in
R. E. Allen (ed.), Studies in Plato's Metaphysics (London, 1965), 379-99.
'Degrees of Reality in Plato* (1965), repr. in Vlastos, Platonic Studies,
58-75.
• 'Reasons and Causes in the Phaedo' (1969), repr. in Vlastos, Platonic
Studies, 76-11,0.
Platonic Studies (Princeton, NJ, 1981).
WALTON, K., 'Fearing Fictions', Journal of Philosophy, 75 (1978), 5-27.
W A R R Y , J. G., Greek Aesthetic Theory (London, 1962).
WATT, D., Charmides, in Saanders (ed.), Plato; Early Socratic Dialogues,
163-209.
WHITE, N. P., A Companion to Plato's Republic (Oxford, 1979).
WILDE, O., "The Critic as Artist', in R. Ellman (ed.), The Artist as Critic;
Critical Writings of Oscar Wilde (New York, 1968), 371-408.
WOLLHEIM, R., Art and its Objects (2nd edn.; Cambridge, 1980).
*WOODRUFF, P., Plato: Hippias Major (Oxford, 1982a).
"What Could Go Wrong with Inspiration? Why Plato's Poets Fail*, in
Moravcsik and Temko (eds.), Plato on Beauty, Wisdom, and the Arts (1982ft),
137-50.
• 'Plato's Early Epistemology', in S. Everson (ed.), Bpistemotogy (1990),
60-84.
X E N O P H O N , Memorabilia (Memoirs of Socrates), trans, H. Tredennick and
R. Waterfleld, in Conversations of Socrates (Hatmondswarth, 1990),
Glossary of Greek Terms
The main text of the book does not assume that the reader knows Greek: when
Greek words are introduced they are always explained. However,' some Greek
terete are used without a translation on every occurrence. The following is a list
of such terms, with preferred English equivalents.
agttthos good
alogon without a rational account (logos)
alogon pragma a thing without a rational account
aporia perplexity
areti excellence, virtue
aulos 'flute*—in fact a reed instrument
demiourgos, (pi, demiourgoi) craftsman, maker
diegesis narration
eidolon (pi. eidala) image
eikon (pi. eikones) likeness
epainetes (pi epaineteis) eulogist
episteme (pi. epistemai) knowledge, branch of knowledge
ems love
euschemasune grace, well-formedness
harmonia (pi. harmaniaf) musical mode, tuning, harmony
kalos line, beautiful (masculine)
kalon (pi, kala) fine, beautiful (neuter)
to kalon; auto to kalon fineness, beauty; fineness itself, beauty itself
kattistos finest, most beautiful (masculine)
kattiston finest, most beautiful (neuter)
kalos finely
kalos kagathos "fine and good', noble
lexis mode of discourse
logismos reasoning, calculation
logistikon the rational part (of the soul)
logos (pi. logoi) word, account, argument
mania madness
mimesis (pi. mim&seis) representation, artistic image-making,
dramatic enactment, imitation
mimeisthai to represent, imitate
mimetike, to mimetikon the mimetic arts
mimema (pi. mimemata) representation, copy, imitation
mimetes (pi. mimetai) mimetic artist, practitioner of mimesis
rnousike music, the arts, culture
mousikos cultured, educated
Glossary of Greek Terms 213
muthos (pi. muthoi) story, myth
paidia amusement, play
phantasma (pi. phantasmata) semblance
pharmakon drag, spell, remedy
poietes poet, maker
poietibos poetic
poietikotatos most poetic
poietike techne poetic craft or expertise
polls city, state
pseudeis logoi false stories, accounts
pseudos falsehood
rhetor public speaker, rhetorician
skiagraphia 'shadow-painting', illusionistic painting
technique
techne (pi. technaf) craft, expertise, expert knowledge
technikos possessing craft, expertise
theios divine
theia moira divine dispensation
This page intentionally left blank
General Index