John Dewey's Concept of The Student: Douglas J. Simpson
John Dewey's Concept of The Student: Douglas J. Simpson
John Dewey's Concept of The Student: Douglas J. Simpson
Douglas J. Simpson
In this article, I have examined Dewey’s concept of the student through the lens of his
poetry and prose to show that his poetry clarifies his prose. I have devoted special attention
to a study of Dewey’s poetry to reveal his belief that students are more fragile than his
prose suggests and that they need guidance in their desire for freedom to learn. His
poetry also suggests that students need help to navigate society’s contradictory educational
currents. Without such help, they will likely suffer damaging, permanent outcomes.
L’article analyse, à travers les poèmes et la prose de Dewey, son concept de l’élève. Les
poèmes de Dewey présentent l’élève comme étant plus fragile que ce que pouvait laisser
supposer sa prose et comment il doit être guidé dans son désir de liberté dans
l’apprentissage. La poésie de Dewey laisse entendre aussi que les élèves ont besoin d’aide
pour trouver leur voie dans les courants éducatifs contradictoires de la société. Sans
cette aide, ils risquent d’être affectés de manière permanente.
––––––––––––––––
John Dewey’s thoughts about students and learning have long interested
educators, although many have failed to study his writings and have
misinterpreted and misapplied his ideas (Archambault, 1964/1974, p. ix).
This lack of attention to his writings extends to his poetry which has been
studied even less than his prose. In this article, I address this neglect by
examining in more detail some of his philosophical and pedagogical beliefs
about students through attention to his poetry.
Dewey thought that the major responsibility for education fell initially
upon adults, teachers, and others. He did not intend that students be held
primarily responsible for their achievements or shortcomings. Instead, he
considered adults responsible for creating learning conditions to promote
educative experiences for children. Even so, he encouraged teachers to
ensure that learners come to understand their limitations and potentialities
through their critiques of student performance and other feedback
(Boydston, 1976/1980, p. 28). This is not to say that Dewey did not place
emphasis on the learner’s initiative and involvement. He clearly stated
that the teacher’s guiding, directing, and navigating were impossible if
the energy for learning does not come from the student: “Since learning is
something that the pupil has to do himself [or herself] and for himself [or
herself], the initiative lies with the learner” (Dewey, 1933/1960, p. 36). So,
too, Dewey expected the student to adapt to the curriculum as much as he
expected the teacher to adapt material to the student (Dewey, 1938/1963,
pp. 46–47).
When Dewey was writing his poems (1910 to1918), he was in his fifties
and sixties and had completed most of his major works on education
(Boydston, 1977, p. xvii). Interestingly, he did not want his poetry
published. Given the aesthetic interest the poems have generated, one
might conclude that his judgment of the pieces was superior to that
displayed by those who had the works published. Yet, the poetry does
illuminate Dewey as a person and a philosopher. In particular, the poetry
partially informs the reader of Dewey’s opinions of students, teaching,
and education. Of Dewey the person, his poetry provides glimpses of a
“loving, sensuous, playful, perceptive, and at times emotionally torn,
weary, self-doubting, depressed” individual (Boydston, 1977, p. xxii). His
poetry also suggests that his affection for Anzia Yezierska may not have
been completely platonic. Yet in his poetry Dewey echoes, expands, and
clarifies his thinking about several subjects, including philosophical
anthropology and pedagogical theory.
PHILOSOPHICAL ANTHROPOLOGY
Rather than pursue the full scope of Dewey’s thought about the child, I
have limited my comments to his opinions of the student’s nature, soul,
and significance. To begin with, it is worthwhile to comment on a feature
of Dewey’s educational theory that stems from his philosophical
anthropology. Although Dewey is frequently considered a child-centred
educator (Archambault, 1964/1974), this description is somewhat
inaccurate because he explicitly denied this label and stated that he was
better described as community-centred because he thought learning was
a social activity, not an individual one (Boydston, 1981–1991, vol. 11, p.
206; vol. 17, p. 53). Community should be understood to include children,
youth, and adults. On the other hand, Dewey believed “the centre of
gravity” needed to shift from the curriculum and teacher to the child and
her or his impulses as a member of a social group (Dewey, 1956/1990, p.
34). The following three subtopics — the student’s nature, soul, and
significance — are treated separately for the sake of discussion, although
they overlap in Dewey’s philosophy.
DEWEY’S CONCEPT OF THE STUDENT 185
Dewey’s ideas regarding the child evolved throughout his life, but there
is a remarkable continuity in his thought on the subject. For example, he
had an abiding confidence in the child’s nature and ability and believed
that, when educators guide a student’s growth, his or her natural tendencies
lead to educative experiences and to a better functioning society. The School
and Society, published in 1899 and revised in 1915, offers Dewey’s clear
early statement on the child’s nature (Burnett, 1976/1980, p. vii). He
explained why he believed that understanding the child’s nature is a
starting point for education and identified four major instincts that
educators should “get hold of” and “direct” toward “something better”
to educate a child (Boydston, 1976/1980, p. 31). Noteworthy is his belief
that the investigative and artistic instincts grow out of the communicative
and constructive tendencies. His ideas are outlined as follows:
Instincts Manifestations
communicative saying, communicating
constructive making, playing, shaping
investigative finding out, inquiring
artistic creating, fashioning
In addition to attributing these four impulses to all children — a term
Dewey used as a synonym for instincts, his affirmation about how to
understand students differed from many of his contemporaries. Dewey
claimed, first, the importance of understanding the “individual mind as a
function of social life — as not capable of operating or developing by itself,
but as requiring continual stimulus from social agencies, and finding its
nutrition in social supplies” (Boydston, 1976/1980, p. 69). This emphasis
ran counter to beliefs that the mind is innate or individually created.
Second, he argued that the child should be understood from the perspective
of emotion and endeavour as well as knowledge and intellect (p. 69). The
student is a feeling, purposive, and intellectual being who needs to be
approached as a whole person. Third, he insisted that mind is not a static
entity that comes fully developed but instead is “a process” and “a growing
affair” characterized by “distinctive phases of capacity and interest” (p.
71). Dewey argued that education is neither a “drawing out” nor a “pouring
in” but a “taking hold” of the activities that stem from instincts. These
activities need to be directed toward valuable outcomes (Dewey, 1956/
1990, p. 36).
186 DOUGLAS J. SIMPSON
(1) observation of surrounding conditions; (2) knowledge of what has happened in similar
situations in the past, a knowledge obtained partly by recollection and partly from the
information, advice, and warning of those who have had a wider experience; and (3)
judgment which puts together what is observed and what is recalled to see what they
signify. A purpose differs from an original impulse and desire through its translation into
a plan and method of action based upon foresight of the consequences of acting under
given observed conditions in a certain way. (Dewey, 1963, p. 69)
civilized group will relapse into barbarism and then into savagery” if
society neglects its educative responsibilities (Dewey, 1916/1944, pp. 3–
4). To successfully pursue desirable outcomes, Dewey thought that society
needed to understand that the purpose of education was not just to transmit
customs, beliefs, and occupations to the young but also to help create souls,
selves, or people. Schools, therefore, are institutions of creation, not just
places of transmission.
In poem #77, Dewey asserted that an active body created the self and one
became her or himself through living and making decisions: “Learning
hate and love and poise in his strife” (p. 56). In the end, it is “the body’s
movement to and fro,/As loving, hating; it everywhere doth go/That
creates a soul from soulless things” (p. 56). Dewey, therefore, argued for
educational environments founded upon a belief in the guided movement
and involvement of the child. The child’s nature demanded such an
environment for her or him to learn and to become a self. He added that
education is an endeavour that was designed to see a community of
inquiring selves creating themselves and one another. Children create
themselves and help create others. Educators contribute to the creation of
DEWEY’S CONCEPT OF THE STUDENT 189
other selves because they are an important part of the environment. Or, as
others say, “each of us becomes those people with whom we work, talk,
share, and grow” (Tharp, Estrada, Dalton, & Yamauchi, 2000, p. 60). The
self as a human creation, then, is a lifetime undertaking, and educators
guide in part this creation as they direct impulses, assist in the conversion
of impulses into desires, and are co-partners with students in the
transformation of desires into reflective purposes.
If a child is not created in the image of God and not a self in an historic
sense, one may wonder how there can be any value attached to the person.
And if there is no significance to children beyond that given to other socially
created objects, why should society value and educate children? Why spend
time in meaningless activities with valueless creatures? Dewey answered
that all nature was of one kind and in the process of time became significant.
The significance rests in the historical development of the universe and
the human race. Humans evolved and acquired the potentiality and
resources to be more than mere matter because “in experiment of Time’s
changes wise,/Recovered, conscious now, eternal peace/And Eternity
knew Death and Care her own” (Boydston, 1977, p. 36). To clarify the
significance of the self, Dewey explained that nature is “the whole complex
of the results of the interaction of man, with his memories and hopes,
understanding and desire, with that world to which one-sided philosophy
confines ‘nature’” (Dewey, 1934/1962, p. 152). Boydston’s observation
about Dewey’s poem “Creation” amplifies his viewpoint:
Creation moves from a picture of pre-creation, when nothing existed but “sterile Time,”
through the beginning of life activity and of physical ordering, into human history that is
at first indiscriminate, “careless of offspring come and gone,” and, finally, to the emergence
of morality and of human sensitivity to value priorities, when “Time was won to love of
feeble things that die,/And turned to tender care of all that grows.” (Boydston, 1977, p.
liv)
growth of human understanding and the meaning that humans gave the
universe when they first appeared on earth. He claimed,
We insisted at the last hour upon the unique character of every intrinsic good. But the
counterpart of this proposition is that the situation in which a good is consciously realized
is not one of transient sensations or private appetites but one of sharing and
communication — public, social. Even the hermit communes with gods and spirits; even
misery loves company; and the most extreme selfishness includes a band of followers or
some partner to share in the attained good. Universalization means socialization, the
extension of the area and range of those who share in a good. (Dewey, 1920/1957, p. 206)
PEDAGOGICAL THEORY
While this idea of schooling may be simple, it is not easy. Many factors
may combine to create an unfriendly environment for the natural
tendencies of the student. Certainly, many traditional schools of Dewey’s
period did not welcome the natural propensities of children. Nor did they
192 DOUGLAS J. SIMPSON
seek to guide and transform them. In poem #66, Dewey stressed the critical
nature of the school environment. He envisioned, as he wrote this poem,
an old man asking a boy if he understood what an imaginary educator
had just said to him. The boy responded by exclaiming that he had not
understood a single word. The lad added that a telling approach to teaching
was inappropriate for him and resulted in no learning. If, however, people
genuinely wanted him to learn, the way was clear: “put me with the little
kiddies and I shall learn” (Boydston, 1977, p. 48). Educators must create
an environment that connects children’s common means of learning or is
consistent with natural learning theory. Only then did Dewey envision
the fullness of the spirit of learning being present in classrooms: “the holy
spirit’s dove once more descend/As it hath from the beginning and shall
to th’end” (p. 48).
The student’s desire to converse with Education, the god from above,
was thwarted at nearly every turn by an adult-constructed wall. The child
was “captured in illusion” by “outward things said clear;/And about was
the confusion/Of all the grown up persons said” (Boydston, 1977, p. 52).
These adults warned the child against listening to Education before the
appropriate time:
It is forbid
That you should hear till lid
Lifts from the things immured
I’ the past; nor is it to be endured
That you should hear direct
Before the hull of your mind be o’erdecked
With stiff well seasoned boards
Brought from dry scholastic hoards. (Boydston, 1977, p. 52)
The proper time for the student to listen was only after he or she had been
thoroughly socialized and his or her mind had been endlessly prepared
(Boydston 1977, pp. 52–53). By the time these social boards had been nailed
in place, adults had built “a thick wall” between the child and educative
experiences, a wall that blocked and distorted Education’s call. Indeed,
Education’s call “Arrives suppressed, altered in sense/Through medium,
sound-proof, dense” (p. 53). Sadly, then, the forces of school and society
often combine to erect “learning’s fence” to hide the student from rich
educative experiences and transform him or her into an alien in a distorted
world: “In lands where we are foreign born/Living protected, safe, —
and forlorn” (p. 53). The student’s natural curiosity and adventuresome
spirit were misshaped and, thereby, he or she was turned into an alien.
over, with activities” (Boydston, 1976/1980, pp. 24–25) and that educators
should direct these activities. But the battle to interpret children as Dewey
did was not easy to win because many adults believed that children had
limited intellectual abilities. Rather than seeing them as active, thinking
beings, these adults saw them as passive vessels waiting to be filled or
creatures that needed their interests extracted. Dewey countered by saying
“the native and unspoiled attitude of childhood, marked by ardent
curiosity, fertile imagination, and love of experimental inquiry, is near,
very near, to the attitude of the scientific mind” (Dewey, 1933/1960, p. v).
He manifested a similar attitude in his poems, revealing his admiration
for nature and nature’s gift: mind. In “Thy Mind,” he delighted in the
person who continued to grow in understanding:
He revealed both his admiration for the mind and his naturalistic ontology
in poem #34 where he compared his view of human thought to an example
of holy ground found in Hebrew scripture:
But Dewey knew that thinking is not easy and that certain environments
made it more difficult. In “Pulse in an Earthen Jar,” he went even further
and expressed doubt about a student’s ability to recover from the
detrimental consequences of being fully immersed in an unreflective,
oppressive culture:
I think he is dead;
They have smothered him.
Does he dream when the soft wind sighs
At four in the summer’s morn?
I think he is dead.
They have choked and stifled him. (p. 25)
The smothered, the choked, and the dead are those who have had their
impulses and inquiries squelched by others. They do not dream of
DEWEY’S CONCEPT OF THE STUDENT 195
possibilities nor think of solutions, much less think clearly, cogently, and
coherently. In short, they never learn to think. And for Dewey the only
kind of thinking is thinking for oneself. Educators, therefore, must not
smother students but create learning environments to provide authentic
problems that cultivate thinking (Dewey, 1916/1944, p. 303). Paradoxically,
he also thought thinking could be stimulated in negative kinds of settings.
Life need not be good or enjoyable for a child to learn to think. The injustices
and oppressions of the child may awaken powers that a life of ease does
not: “[only] when thinking is the imperative or urgent way out, only when
it is the indicated road to a solution” does it occur (Dewey, 1920/1957, p.
139). When writing about children’s mistreatment, he stated (poem # 86)
that only those who rebel learn to think. And they are happier than those
who never “felt the lash/’Cross their defenceless backs” (Boydston 1977,
p. 64). Dewey (1920/1957) later amplified his thinking:
Men [and women] do not, in their natural estate, think when they have no troubles to
cope with, no difficulties to overcome. A life of ease, of success without effort, would be
a thoughtless life, and so also would a life of ready omnipotence. Beings who think are
beings whose life is so hemmed in and constricted that they cannot directly carry through
a course of action to victorious consummation. Men [and women and children] also do
not tend to think when their action, when they are amid difficulties, is dictated to them by
authority. (pp. 138–139)
How many students . . . were rendered callous to ideas, and how many lost the impetus
to learn because of the way in which learning was experienced by them? How many
acquired special skills by means of automatic drill so that their power of judgment and
capacity to act intelligently in new situations was limited? How many came to associate
the learning process with ennui and boredom? How many found what they did learn so
foreign to the situation of life outside the school as to give them no power or control over
the latter? How many came to associate books with dull drudgery, so that they were
“conditioned” to all but flashy reading matter? (Dewey, 1923/1963, pp. 26–27)
Dewey clarified his view of the desirable teacher, not only by his explicit
and positive comments but also by his criticisms of the weaknesses of the
traditional teacher and the excesses of the progressive teacher. His poetry
moved beyond his other writings to reveal a loathing for a certain kind of
teacher: the pedantic teacher who destroyed the natural learning
inclinations of students. The mind of the teacher, in “To a Pedant,” has
storerooms stocked with ostentatious ornaments, a covered pool in a
marble hall with no sign of life, cabinets with numerous pigeon-holes and
other indicators of debt to “stale antiquity’s refurbished store,” a dining
hall with four-hundred-year-old “cold banquets,” a library with second-
hand “substitutes for thought,” and a “pompous sentinel” to ensure the
present did not invade the past. The sentinel stood
Dewey wanted a different model for students. He did not want teachers
who displayed knowledge for others to see, who shielded themselves from
ideas that might breathe new life into their thinking, who interpreted fresh
DEWEY’S CONCEPT OF THE STUDENT 197
What avail is it to win prescribed amounts of information about geography and history,
to win ability to read and write, if in the process the individual loses his [or her] own
soul: loses his appreciation of things worth while, of the values to which these things are
relative; if he loses desires to apply what he has learned and, above all, loses the ability to
extract meaning from his future experiences as they occur? (Dewey, 1938/1963, p. 49)
CONCLUSION
A study of Dewey’s poetry and its illumination of his concept of the student
is not likely to change what many think about his controversial opinions.
Indeed, the new insights, fresh meanings, and powerful expressions found
in his poems may simply confirm the prior judgments of many critics. To
claim, therefore, that the relevance of his ideas for the future depends in
part upon how much his readers agree with his philosophy is almost not
worth saying. Yet, this point cannot be ignored. Those who think Dewey’s
philosophical beliefs about students and pedagogy are seriously flawed
can hardly be expected to welcome his poetic assertions. On the other
hand, some may agree with much that he thought and still object to his
views of human impulses, self, and significance. Moreover, his theory of
198 DOUGLAS J. SIMPSON
self may leave critics wondering how a balanced approach to the creation
of the self by both the child and the school can be ethically and operationally
accomplished. How can so many creators of a child’s self leave room for
her or his personal identity and integrity? So, too, those who argue that
Dewey had an “ultrasocial conception of individuality” will not be
comforted by his poetry (Ryan, 1995, p. 319). Similarly, those who are
immersed in contemporary psychological theory and research may doubt
the validity of Dewey’s classifications and descriptions of original impulses
and their relevance for schooling. Further, those who have learned from
postmodernism may question his tendency to universalize student
impulses. For a variety of reasons, both his critics and proponents may
challenge his assumption that all students need to be physically as well as
intellectually active. Does this belief imply too much, i.e., does it question
the learning abilities of the physically challenged? Likewise, contemporary
thinkers may believe that Dewey placed too much emphasis on a student’s
natural learning propensities and too little on how a school and a student
develop an adult mind. Acquiring an adult mind, critics may insist, is too
complex an undertaking to be guided by natural theory of learning alone.
Of course, one may agree with aspects of Dewey’s concept of students
and pedagogical thought while objecting strenuously to some of his basic
assumptions and beliefs. Rightly understood, for example, it may appear
that his attention to students, teachers, knowledge, and society is a healthy
counterbalance to fashionable trends that sweep certain quarters. These
fashions sometimes take the form of emphasizing teachers or students,
knowledge or students, or some other dichotomy. These components were
important to Dewey because he viewed each as a critical part of the
educational enterprise. Growth is an interactive process that involves
educators, students, knowledge, and the broader environment.
Dewey’s attention to means and ends may also be important in
environments that tend to overemphasize either methodology or outcomes.
He was interested in the means of education as well as the outcomes. The
ethical justification of the means — the lack thereof being a primary source
of smothering, choking, and destroying students — was as important as
the rationale to pursue a set of ends. He may also raise our sights in the
area of ends in a way that too few politicians and bureaucrats appreciate.
For instance, he was interested in moving beyond narrowly defined student
performance standards to nurturing reflective children and youth who
are contributors to the development of healthy societies. Stressing the ends
of personal and community growth may be a healthy counter force to the
overemphasis of some on the relationship of schooling to economic
outcomes. Arguably, Dewey’s treatment of non-, mis-, anti-, and educative
DEWEY’S CONCEPT OF THE STUDENT 199
REFERENCES
Archambault, R. D. (Ed.). (1974). John Dewey on education: Selected writings.
Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. (Original work published 1964)
Boydston, J. A. (Ed.). (1967–1972). The early works of John Dewey, 1882–1898
(Vols. 1–15). Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press.
Boydston, J. A. (Ed.). (1977). The poems of John Dewey. Carbondale, IL: Southern
Illinois University Press.
Boydston, J. A. (Ed.). (1981–1991). The later works of John Dewey,1925–1953 (Vols.
1–17). Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press.
Boydston, J. A. (Ed.). (1980). The school and society. Carbondale, IL: Southern
Illinois University Press. (Original work published 1976)
200 DOUGLAS J. SIMPSON
Burnett, J. R. (1980). Preface. In J. A. Boydston, (Ed.), The school and society (pp.
v-vii). Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press. (Original work
published 1976)
Dewey, J. (1944). Democracy and education: An introduction to the philosophy of
education. New York: The Free Press. (Original work published 1916)
Dewey, J. (1957). Reconstruction in philosophy (Enlarged edition). Boston, MA:
Beacon Press. (Original work published 1920)
Dewey, J. (1960). How we think: A restatement of the relation of reflective thinking
to the educative process (New edition). Lexington, MA: D. C. Heath and
Company. (Original work published 1933).
Dewey, J. (1962). A common faith. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. (Original
work published 1934).
Dewey, J. (1963). Experience and education. New York: Collier Books. (Original
work published 1938)
Dewey, J. (1975). Moral principles in education. Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois
University Press. (Original work published 1909)
Dewey, J. (1990). The school and society and The child and the curriculum. Chicago,
IL: The University of Chicago Press.
Ryan, A. (1995). John Dewey and the high tide of American liberalism. New York:
W. W. Norton & Company.
Simpson, D. J., & Jackson, M. J. B. (1997). Educational reform: A Deweyan
perspective. New York: Garland Publishing.
Tharp, R. G., Estrada, P., Dalton, S. S., & Yamauchi, L. A. (2000). Teaching
transformed: Achieving excellence, fairness, inclusion, and harmony. Boulder,
CO: Westview Press.