Abstract: Several Kinds of Non-Argumentative Discourse Are Characterized, Illustrated, and Distinguished From Argumentative Discourse
Abstract: Several Kinds of Non-Argumentative Discourse Are Characterized, Illustrated, and Distinguished From Argumentative Discourse
Abstract: Several Kinds of Non-Argumentative Discourse Are Characterized, Illustrated, and Distinguished From Argumentative Discourse
Recognizing Arguments
Two conditions must be fulfilled for a passage to purport to prove something: At least
one of the statements must claim to present evidence or reasons; and there must be a claim
that the alleged evidence supports or implies something—that is, a claim that something
follows from the alleged evidence or reasons.
To be an argument, then, a passage must contain both a factual claim and an inferential
claim. The factual claim is expressed in the premises, and the inferential claim is the claim that
these sentences support or imply something further. The implication may be implicit or
explicit. In deciding whether there is a claim that evidence presented supports or implies
something; look for 1) premise and conclusion indicator words and 2) the presence of an
inferential relationship between the statements. Note, though, that the mere presence of an
indicator word is not a guarantee that it’s an argument. (Hurley, Section 1.2, taken from
http://faculty.bsc.edu/bmyers/Section1.2.htm on January 26, 2019)
Given these characterizations, then, how do we sort out arguments from the rest of the
kinds of linguistic behavior? In effect, what we are doing is separating the territory of logic
from the rest of the world. In order to know to what we can apply our powerful methods of
analysis, we need to learn how to separate argumentative discourse from non-argumentative
discourse. (taken from https://philosophy.lander.edu/logic/nonarg.html on January 27 2019).
Most factual claims fall outside the domain of logic. So in this class, we’ll be focusing in
inferential claims. Inferential claims are either explicit or implicit. (taken from
https://prezi.com/sqqxhgtdpywe/recognizing-arguments/ on January 28, 2019)
No premise indicators or conclusion indicators are used here, yet the argument
is clear. Indicators are absent in the following argument in Sam Harris’s Letter to a
Christian Nation, whose premises and conclusions are unmistakable:
Often, however, the force of an argument can be appreciated only when one
understands the context in which that argument is presented. For example, the
undergraduate admission system of the University of Michigan that gave a fixed number
of extra points to all members of certain minority groups was held unconstitutional by
the U.S. Supreme Court in Gratz v. Bollinger in 2003. Justice Ruth Bader Ginsburg
dissented, defending the Michigan system with the following argument:
D. Unstated Propositions
1. By carefully reading the text, you can discern several important differences
between an argument and an explanation.
(1) The Roman Empire collapsed because (2) it lacked the spirit of liberalism and
free enterprise.
a. Which statement is better known (1) or (2)? Since the first statement is better
known, we would normally conclude that this is an explanation which shows a causal
connection rather than an argument with a logical implication. However, Copi has taken
this passage out of context as we will see below.
b. If the author were advancing the general thesis "All countries that lack these
attributes crumble to dust," therefore the Roman Empire did, then a Deductive
Nomological Explanation is being given. In point of fact, this is precisely the argument
which von Mises gives in the original passage from which this passage was excerpted:
"The Roman Empire crumbled to dust because it lacked the spirit of liberalism and free
enterprise. The policy of interventionism and its political corollary, the Fuhrer principle,
decomposed the mighty empire as they will by necessity always disintegrate and destroy
any social entity."
[All countries that lack the spirit of liberalism and free enterprise crumble to dust.] I.e.,
contraposition of the last sentence of the passage above.
The Roman Empire lacked the spirit of liberalism and free enterprise.
4. Some passages are a mixture of argument and explanation. Consider this example:
"There was therefore a sound reason why, despite theological differences, the political
theories of Calvinists in France or Scotland should have had certain similarities with those
of the Jesuits. Both were in a situation where it was necessary to urge that political
obligation is not absolute and that a right of rebellion exits against an heretical ruler. Both
depended upon a common heritage of medieval thought and argued that the community
itself creates is own officials and can regulate them for its own purposes. Both held,
therefore, that political power inheres in the people, is derived from him by contract, and
may be revoked if the king becomes a tyrant."
(George H. Sabine, A History of Political Theory, 3rd. ed. (London: Haarp, 1963), 388.)
The second and third statements are reasons for the conclusion expressed in the third
statement. The third statement is the explanans (that which is the explanation) for the first
statement which is the explanandum (that which is to be explained)..
Note: Explanations often are given for well-known states of affairs. In science, the
explanation is almost always less well known than that which is to be explained.
Hence, unlike arguments, the statements in an explanation generally "move" from well-
known to less well known statements.
Every argument makes the claim that its premises provide grounds for the truth of its
conclusion; that claim is the mark of an argument. However, there are two very different
ways in which a conclusion may be supported by its premises, and thus there are two great
classes of arguments: the deductive and the inductive. Understanding this distinction is
essential in the study of logic. A deductive argument makes the claim that its conclusion is
supported by its premises conclusively. An inductive argument, in contrast, does not make
such a claim. Therefore, if we judge that in some passage a claim for conclusiveness is being
made, we treat the argument as deductive; if we judge that such a claim is not being made,
we treat it as inductive. Because every argument either makes this claim of conclusiveness
(explicitly or implicitly) or does not make it, every argument is either deductive or
inductive.
In contrast, the central task of inductive arguments is to ascertain the facts by which
conduct may be guided directly, or on which other arguments may be built. Empirical
investigations are undertaken—as in medicine, or social science, or astronomy—leading,
when inductive techniques are applied appropriately, to factual conclusions, most often
concerning cause-and-effect relationships of some importance
In sum, the distinction between induction and deduction rests on the nature of the
claims made by the two types of arguments about the relations between their premises and
their conclusions. Thus we characterize the two types of arguments as follows: A deductive
argument is one whose conclusion is claimed to follow from its premises with absolute
necessity, this necessity not being a matter of degree and not depending in any way on
whatever else may be the case. In sharp contrast, an inductive argument is one whose
conclusion is claimed to follow from its premises only with probability, this probability
being a matter of degree and dependent on what else may be the case.