The Art of The Stage Set As A Paradigm For An Aesthetics of Atmospheres

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 10

Ambiances

Environnement sensible, architecture et espace urbain 


Redécouvertes | 2013

The art of the stage set as a paradigm for an


aesthetics of atmospheres
La scénographie comme paradigme d’une esthétique des ambiances

Gernot Böhme

Electronic version
URL: http://journals.openedition.org/ambiances/315
DOI: 10.4000/ambiances.315
ISSN: 2266-839X

Publisher:
Direction Générale des Patrimoines - DAPA - MCC, UMR 1563 - Ambiances Architectures Urbanités
(AAU)
 

Electronic reference
Gernot Böhme, « The art of the stage set as a paradigm for an aesthetics of atmospheres »,
Ambiances [Online], Rediscovering, Online since 10 February 2013, connection on 22 September 2020.
URL : http://journals.openedition.org/ambiances/315  ; DOI : https://doi.org/10.4000/ambiances.315

This text was automatically generated on 22 September 2020.

Ambiances is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0


International License.
The art of the stage set as a paradigm for an aesthetics of atmospheres 1

The art of the stage set as a


paradigm for an aesthetics of
atmospheres
La scénographie comme paradigme d’une esthétique des ambiances

Gernot Böhme

Making atmospheres
1 Our general theme, Making atmospheres1, has a provocative character. It sounds slightly
perverse, even paradoxical. Making - does that not have to do with something tangible?
With the world of concrete things and apparatuses? And atmosphere - is that not
something airy, indefinite, something which is simply there and comes over us? How is
one supposed to make atmospheres? Well, there is one sphere in which that has
actually been going on for a long time: the art of the stage set. In it we have a paradigm
which not only encourages us in our enterprise but endows the idea of making
atmospheres with objective reality2.

Atmosphere - a familiar yet extremely vague


phenomenon
2 The term atmosphere has its origin in the meteorological field and refers to the earth’s
envelope of air which carries the weather. It is only since the 18th century that it has
been used metaphorically, for moods which are “in the air”, for the emotional tinge of a
space. Today this expression is commonly used in all European languages; no longer it
seems artificial and is hardly even regarded as a metaphor. One speaks of the
atmosphere of a conversation, a landscape, a house, the atmosphere of a festival, an
evening, a season. The way in which we speak of atmospheres in these cases is highly
differentiated - even in everyday speech. An atmosphere is tense, light-hearted or

Ambiances , Redécouvertes
The art of the stage set as a paradigm for an aesthetics of atmospheres 2

serious, oppressive or uplifting, cold or warm. We also speak of the atmosphere of the
“petite bourgeoisie”, the atmosphere of the Twenties, the atmosphere of poverty. To
introduce some order into these examples, atmospheres can be divided into moods,
phenomena of synaesthesia, suggestions for motions, communicative and social-
conventional atmospheres. What matters is that, in speaking of atmospheres, we refer
to their character. With this term character we already bring our understanding of
atmospheres close to the sphere of physiognomy and theatre. The character of an
atmosphere is the way in which it communicates a feeling to us as participating
subjects. A solemn atmosphere has the tendency to make my mood serious, a cold
atmosphere causes me to shudder.
3 The scholarly use of the term atmosphere is relatively new. It began in the field of
psychiatry, specifically in Hubert Tellenbach’s book Geschmack und Atmosphäre [Taste
and atmosphere] (Tellenbach, 1968). Here, atmosphere refers to something bordering
on the olfactory - such as the climate of the homeland or the smell of the nest, that is, a
sphere of familiarity which is perceptible in a bodily-sensuous way. Since then,
atmospheres have been researched in detail by phenomenology. Talk about
atmospheres plays a part today in interior design, town planning, advertising and all
fields related to the art of the stage set - that is, the creation of backgrounds in radio,
film and television. In general, it can be said that atmospheres are involved wherever
something is being staged, wherever design is a factor - and that now means: almost
everywhere.
4 Now, this matter-of-fact way in which atmospheres are talked about and manipulated
is extremely surprising, since the phenomenon of atmosphere is itself something
extremely vague, indeterminate, intangible. The reason is primarily that atmospheres
are totalities: atmospheres imbue everything, they tinge the whole of the world or a
view, they bathe everything in a certain light, unify a diversity of impressions in a
single emotive state. And yet one cannot actually speak of “the whole”, still less of the
whole of the world; speech is analytical and must confine itself to particulars.
Moreover, atmospheres are something like the aesthetic quality of a scene or a view,
the “something more” that Adorno refers to in somewhat oracular terms in order to
distinguish a work of art from a mere “piece of work”; or they are “the Open” which,
since Heidegger, has given us access to the space in which something appears. Seen in
this way, atmospheres have something irrational about them, in a literal sense:
something inexpressible. Finally, atmospheres are something entirely subjective: in
order to say what they are or, better, to define their character, one must expose oneself
to them, one must experience them in terms of one’s own emotional state. Without the
sentient subject, they are nothing.
5 And yet: the subject experiences them as something “out there”, something which can
come over us, into which we are drawn, which takes possession of us like an alien
power. So, are atmospheres something objective after all? The truth is that
atmospheres are a typical intermediate phenomenon, something between subject and
object. That makes them, as such, intangible, and means that - at least in the European
cultural area - they have no secure ontological status. But for that very reason it is
rewarding to approach them from two sides, from the side of subjects and from the side
of objects, from the side of reception aesthetics and from the side of production
aesthetics.

Ambiances , Redécouvertes
The art of the stage set as a paradigm for an aesthetics of atmospheres 3

Reception aesthetics and production aesthetics


6 The conception of atmospheres as a phenomenon has its origin in reception aesthetics.
Atmospheres are apprehended as powers which affect the subject; they have the
tendency to induce in the subject a characteristic mood. They come upon us from we
know not where, as something nebulous, which in the 18th century might have been
called a je ne sais quoi, they are experienced as something numinous - and therefore
irrational.
7 The matter looks different if approached from the side of production aesthetics, which
makes it possible to gain rational access to this “intangible” entity. It is the art of the
stage set which rids atmospheres of the odour of the irrational: here, it is a question of
producing atmospheres. This whole undertaking would be meaningless if atmospheres
were something purely subjective. For the stage set artist must relate them to a wider
audience, which can experience the atmosphere generated on the stage in, by and
large, the same way. It is, after all, the purpose of the stage set to provide the
atmospheric background to the action, to attune the spectators to the theatrical
performance and to provide the actors with a sounding board for what they present.
The art of the stage set therefore demonstrates from the side of praxis that
atmospheres are something quasi-objective. What does that mean?
8 Atmospheres, to be sure, are not things. They do not exist as entities which remain
identical over time; nevertheless, even after a temporal interruption they can be
recognised as the same, through their character. Moreover, although they are always
perceived only in subjective experience - as a taste or a smell, for example, to return to
Tellenbach - it is possible to communicate about them intersubjectively. We can discuss
with one another what kind of atmosphere prevails in a room. This teaches us that
there is an intersubjectivity which is not grounded in an identical object. We are
accustomed, through the predominant scientific mode of thinking, to assume that
intersubjectivity is grounded in objectivity, that detection of the presence and
determinateness of something is independent of subjective perception and can be
delegated to an apparatus. Contrary to this, however, the quasi-objectivity of
atmospheres is demonstrated by the fact that we can communicate about them in
language. Of course, this communication has its preconditions : an audience which is to
experience a stage set in roughly the same way must have a certain homogeneity, that
is to say, a certain mode of perception must have been instilled in it through cultural
socialisation.
9 Nevertheless, independently of the culture-relative character of atmospheres, their
quasi-objective status is preserved. It manifests itself in the fact that atmospheres can
be experienced as surprising, and, on occasions, in contrast to one’s own mood. An
example is when, in a cheerful mood, I enter a community in mourning : its atmosphere
can transform my mood to the point of tears. For this, too, the stage set is a practical
proof.

Phantastike techne
10 All the same, can one really make atmospheres? The term making refers to the
manipulating of material conditions, of things, apparatus, sound and light. But

Ambiances , Redécouvertes
The art of the stage set as a paradigm for an aesthetics of atmospheres 4

atmosphere itself is not a thing; it is rather a floating in-between, something between


things and the perceiving subjects. The making of atmospheres is therefore confined to
setting the conditions in which the atmosphere appears. We refer to these conditions
as generators.
11 The true character of a making, which does not really consist in producing a thing, but
in making possible the appearance of a phenomenon by establishing conditions, can be
clarified by going back to Plato’s theory of mimesis.3
12 In the dialogue Sophist, Plato draws a distinction between two kinds of performing art,
in order to unmask the mendacious art of the Sophists (Sophist, 235e3-236c7). There is a
difference, he argues, between eikastike techne and phantastike techne. It is the latter
which interests us here. In eikastike techne, mimesis consists in the strict imitation of a
model. Phantastike techne, by contrast, allows itself to deviate from the model. It takes
account of the viewpoint of the observer, and seeks to make manifest what it
represents in such a way that the observer perceives it “correctly”. Plato bases this
distinction on the practice of the sculptors and architects of his time. For example, the
head of a very tall statue was made relatively too large, so that it did not appear too
small to the observer, or the horizontal edges of a temple were curved slightly
upwards, so that they did not seem to droop to the observer (Lamb et Curtius, 1944,
p. 17). This art of phantastike is perhaps not yet quite what we mean by the art of
making atmospheres, but it already contains the decisive feature: that the artist does
not see his actual goal in the production of an object or work of art, but in the
imaginative idea the observer receives through the object. That is why this art is called
phantastike techne. It relates to the subject’s power of representation, to the imagination
or imaginatio. We come close to what concerns us through the skenographia developed
by the Greeks as early as the fourth century BC. In his Poetics 1449a18 Aristotle ascribes
this to the tragedian Sophocles. The classical philologists believed that skenographia
already implied perspective painting, an invention frequently attributed to the
Renaissance (Frank, 1962, p. 20). They claimed that the geometrical doctrine of
proportion, in particular the theorem of radiation we find developed in the Elements of
Euclid, was derived from skenographia. For in order to create spatial depth through
painting, perspectival foreshortening of the objects represented - buildings, trees,
people - is needed. In scenography, therefore, we have an art form which is now
directed explicitly, in its concrete activity, towards the generation of imaginative
representations in the subjects, here the audience. It does not want to shape objects,
but rather to create phenomena. The manipulation of objects serves only to establish
conditions in which these phenomena can emerge. But that is not achieved without the
active contribution of the subject, the onlooker. It is interesting when Umberto Eco
claims precisely this for all pictorial representation (Eco, 1976, p. 32, footnote 7): It does
not copy the object, he asserts, but only creates the conditions of perception under
which the idea of the object appears for the viewer of the image. That may be
overstated, yet it is true for Impressionist painting, for example. That painting does not
aim to copy an object or a landscape, but rather to awaken a particular impression, an
experience in the onlooker. The most convincing proof of this is the technique of
pointillism. The colours the painter wishes the onlooker to see are not located on the
painted surface but “in space”, or in the imagination of the onlooker.
13 Of course, the art of the stage set has by now advanced beyond pure scenography.
Wagner’s operas seem to have given particular impetus to this development, firstly

Ambiances , Redécouvertes
The art of the stage set as a paradigm for an aesthetics of atmospheres 5

because they demanded a fantastic ambiance in any case and, secondly, because they
were intended to act especially on the feelings, not just the imagination (Schuberth,
1955, p. 86, p. 95). But the breakthrough came only in the 20th century, with the
mastery of light and sound through electrical technology4. Here, a stage art has now
been developed which is no longer confined to the design and furnishing of the stage
space but, on the one hand, causes the action on the stage to appear in a particular
light and, on the other, creates an acoustic space which tunes the whole performance.
At the same time, this has made it possible for the art of the stage set to leave the stage
itself and spill over into the auditorium, or even into space itself. The spaces generated
by light and sound are no longer something perceived at a distance, but something
within which one is enclosed. This has also enabled the art of the stage set to expand
into the general art of staging, which has applications, for example, in the decor of
discotheques and the design of large-scale events such as open-air festivals, opening
ceremonies of sports events, etc. (Larmann, 2007).
14 The present dominance of light and sound design also enables us to discern in
retrospect what the making of atmospheres consists of in the more object-related field.
It becomes clear that what is at issue is not really visual spectacles - as was perhaps
believed by practitioners of the old scenography - but the creation of “tuned” spaces,
that is to say, atmospheres. The making, as long as it concerns a shaping and
establishing of the geometrical space and its contents, cannot therefore relate to the
concrete qualities possessed by the space and the things within it. Or, more precisely: it
does not relate to the determinations of things, but to the way in which they radiate
outwards into space, to their output as generators of atmospheres. Instead of
properties, therefore, I speak of ekstases5 - that is, ways of stepping-outside-oneself. The
difference between properties and ekstases can be clarified by the antithesis between
convex and concave: a surface which, in relation to the body it encloses, is convex, is
concave in relation to the surrounding space.
15 We are concerned, therefore, with ekstases, with the expressive forms of things. We are
not accustomed to characterising things in terms of their ekstases, although they are
crucial to design, for example. In keeping with our ontological tradition, we
characterise things in terms of their material and their form. For our present purpose,
however, the thing-model of Jacob Böhme is far more appropriate. He conceives of
things on the model of a musical instrument (Böhme, 1922). In these terms, the body is
something like the sounding board of a musical instrument, while its outward
properties, which Böhme calls “signatures”, are moods which articulate its expressive
forms. And finally, what is characteristic of things is their tone, their “odour” or
emanation - that is to say, the way in which they express their essence.
16 Tone and emanation - in my terminology, ekstases - determine the atmosphere radiated
by things. They are therefore the way in which things are felt present in space. This
gives us a further definition of atmosphere: it is the felt presence of something or
someone in space. For this the ancients had the beautiful expression parousia. Thus, for
Aristotle, light is the parousia of fire (De anima, 22b17.).

Conclusion
17 What I, harking back to Plato, called phantastike techne, would no doubt today be called
design. We have oriented ourselves here by a prototypical area of design: stage design.

Ambiances , Redécouvertes
The art of the stage set as a paradigm for an aesthetics of atmospheres 6

But for our purpose it is important to modify the traditional understanding of design,
according to which design amounted merely to shaping or configuring. That
understanding is already prohibited by the extraordinary importance of light and
sound, not only in the field of the stage set but also in advertising, marketing, town
planning, interior design. One might speak of a practical, or better: a poetic
phenomenology, because we are dealing here with the art of bringing something to
appearance. A term used by the phenomenologist Hermann Schmitz is very apt here: he
speaks of a “technology of impression” [Eindruckstechnik] (Schmitz, 1999). Admittedly,
this term is used polemically, being applied to the generation of impressions for
propaganda purposes in the Nazi period, or what Walter Benjamin called the
“aestheticizing of political life” (Benjamin, 2003, p. 269). Let us therefore speak more
generally of the art of staging. On the one hand, then, we have preserved the connection
to our paradigm of the art of the stage set and, on the other, we have included in this
expression the purpose for which atmospheres are predominantly generated today: the
stage set is itself a part of the staging of a drama or opera. The art of atmospheres, as
far as it is used in the production of open-air festivals or in the build-up to large
sporting events such as the Football World Cup or the Olympic Games, is their staging.
The role of the generation of atmospheres in marketing is that of staging commodities.
The commodities themselves are valued, in the aesthetic economy where they now
serve only relatively little to satisfy basic needs, for their staging-value, that is, they are
valued to the extent that they help individuals or groups to stage their own lifestyles.
And finally, in democracies, or more precisely media-democracies, in which politics is
performed as if in a theatre, the generation of atmospheres has the function of staging
personalities or political events.
18 If we review these examples, it emerges that the attention which is now paid to
atmospheres in aesthetic theory has its material background in the fact that staging
has become a basic feature of our society: the staging of politics, of sporting events, of
cities, of commodities, of personalities, of ourselves. The choice of the paradigm of the
stage set for the art of generating atmospheres therefore mirrors the real
theatricalisation of our life. This is why the paradigm stage set can teach us so much, in
theoretical terms, about the general question of the generation of atmospheres, and
therefore about the art of staging. But in practical terms, too, there ought to be much
to be learned from the great tradition of stage set design. That will happen indeed, but
one should not expect that it will be possible to say very much about it. For the art of
the stage set has been transmitted up to now, like traditional crafts, in master-pupil
relationships, by collaboration and imitation. The guiding practical knowledge is tacit
knowledge. It is all the more pleasing to find now and then, in the many books which
exist on the subject of the stage set, something explicit about the craft. In conclusion, I
will give an example of such knowledge from the praxis of the stage set. It is found in, of
all places, a philosophical dissertation, Robert Kümmerlen’s book Zur Aesthetik
bühnenräumlicher Prinzipien (Kümmerlen, 1929).
19 Kümmerlen writes about the use of light on the stage. He argues, we should note, that
an atmosphere is created on the stage with light. He then defines the effect of the light-
atmosphere more precisely by saying that a characteristic mood is imparted by it to the
performance. As examples, he mentions somber and charming moods - that is, moods
with a synaesthetic and a communicative character. Finally, he also recognises the
status of the “in-between existence” typical of atmospheres: “The lighting on its own

Ambiances , Redécouvertes
The art of the stage set as a paradigm for an aesthetics of atmospheres 7

generates a fluid between the individual structures of the performance”. But now, let
me give the quotation in full:
The space to be contemplated is given its brightness by the lighting; stage
performances are only made visible by light. The first function of lighting, the
simple provision of light, creates, with the brightness, what might be called the
atmosphere in which the space exists. The light-atmosphere, achieved in the most
diverse ways, varies the space; through the lighting the performances take on a
characteristic mood. The space creates an effect in its totality; the lights of the
special representation produce a self-contained impression; the space stands in a
unifying light. With the illumination of the whole scene a “unified character” is
produced. A uniform mood emanates from the space; for example, the
representation of space is subjected to a “muted” light. We find that three-
dimensional objects “gleam” in a regular light; the space appears, for example, as
“charming” or “somber”. The lighting on its own generates a fluid between the
individual structures of the performance. A specific mood is contained in the space
represented through the ethereal effect of brightness (Kümmerlen, 1929, p. 36).

BIBLIOGRAPHY
Benjamin, Walter. 2003. The Work of Art in the Age of its Technical Reproducibility [translated by
Edmund Jephcott]. In: Walter. Benjamin. Selected Writings, vol. 4, Cambridge Mass. and London:
Harvard University Press. p. 19-55

Böhme, Gernot. 2011. Un paradigme pour une esthétique des ambiances : l’art de la scénographie.
In : Augoyard, Jean-François (ed.). Faire une ambiance = creating an atmosphere : actes du colloque
international Grenoble 10-12 septembre 2008. Grenoble : A la croisée. p. 221-228

Böhme, Gernot. 2001/2005. Aisthetik. Vorlesungen über Ästhetik als allgemeine Wahrnehmungslehre.
München: Wilhelm Fink. Japanese translation by Akira Imura, Masato Ogawa, Miyuki Abe, Yuichi
Masuda. Tokyo: Keisoshobo.

Böhme, Gernot. 2006a. Architektur und Atmosphäre. München:Wilhelm Fink.

Böhme, Gernot. 2006b. The Aesthetics of Atmospheres - A challenge from New Phenomenology. Kyoto:
Koyo Shobo. In Japanese

Böhme, Gernot. 1995. Atmosphäre. Essays zur Neuen Ästhetik. 6. th ed. Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp

Böhme, Jacob. 1922. De signature rerum oder von der Geburt und Bezeichnung aller Wesen. In:
Jacob Böhmes sämtliche Werke vol. 1. K.W., Schiebler (ed.). Leipzig: Johann Umbrosius Barth

Eckert, Nora. 1998. Das Bühnenbild im 20. Jahrhundert. Berlin: Henschel

Eco, Umberto. A Theory of Semiotics. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1976

Frank, Erich. 1962. Platon und die sogenannten Pythagoreer. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche
Buchgesellschaft

Kümmerlen, Robert. 1929. Zur Aesthetik bühnenräumlicher Prinzipien. Ludwigsburg: Schmoll

Lamb, Carl; Curtius, Ludwig. 1944. Die Tempel von Paestum. Leipzig: Insel-Verlag

Ambiances , Redécouvertes
The art of the stage set as a paradigm for an aesthetics of atmospheres 8

Larmann, Ralph. 2007. Stage Design, Köln: Daab

Schmitz, Hermann. 1999. Adolf Hitler in der Geschichte. Bonn: Bouvier.

Schuberth, Ottmar 1955. Das Bühnenbild. Geschichte, Gestalt, Technik. Munchen: Callwey

Tellenbach, Hubert. 1968. Geschmack und Atmosphäre. Salzburg: O. Müller

NOTES
1. For the Aesthetics of Atmospheres see my German and Japanese Books: Böhme 2001, 2005, 2006
a,b, 2009.
2. This article has been published in French in the proceedings of the 1st international congress
on ambiances "Faire une ambiance, Grenoble, 2012". See Böhme 2011.
3. Cf. Böhme, 2004, Chapter III.2, "Theorie des Bildes".
4. See Eckert, 1998, esp. the chapter: "Mehr Licht! – Die Lichtbühne", p. 106-113.
5. Böhme, 2001, chapter IX.

ABSTRACTS
This article delineates the aesthetics of atmopheres in general but has an emphasis on making
atmospheres. From this point of view the art of the stage set turns out to be a paradigm for what
are the main concepts of the theory of atmosphere: types of atmospheres (characters), their
quasi-objectivity, means to produce atmospheres, emotional content. The ubiquitous meaning of
atmospheres is demonstrated from the background of staging everything in our present
civilization: public events, politics, commodities, and even personal life.

Cet article dessine le contour d’une esthétique générale des ambiances (atmospheres) en mettant
l’accent sur leur fabrication. De ce point de vue, l’art de la scénographie se révèle être un
paradigme pour ce qui concerne les concepts principaux de la théorie des ambiances : les types
d’ambiances (caractères), leur quasi-objectivité, les moyens pour produire une ambiance, le
contenu émotionnel. La teneur ubiquitaire des ambiances est démontrée par la propension à tout
scénographier dans notre civilisation présente : événements publics, politique, marchandises et
même vie privée.

INDEX
Keywords: atmosphere, staging, commodity aesthetics, emotions, space
Mots-clés: ambiances, scénographie, esthétique, émotions, espace

Ambiances , Redécouvertes
The art of the stage set as a paradigm for an aesthetics of atmospheres 9

AUTHOR
GERNOT BÖHME
Prof. of Philosophy Technical Univ. of Darmstadt
Director of the Institut für Praxis der Philosophie
Institut für Praxis der Philosophie e.V., IPPh. Rosenhöhweg 25, D-64287 Darmstadt, FRG
re.boehme@t-online.de
www.ipph-darmstadt.de

Ambiances , Redécouvertes

You might also like