The Self and Its History: AHR Roundtable
The Self and Its History: AHR Roundtable
The Self and Its History: AHR Roundtable
LYNN HUNT
media/SfN/Documents/Annual%20Reports/2011_annual_report.ashx, 22.
2 Nikos K. Logothetis, “What We Can Do and What We Cannot Do with fMRI,” Nature 453 (June
434 – 472; and the critical remarks about the use of neuroscience, especially by Jan Plamper, in Nicole
1576
The Self and Its History 1577
huge and difficult subject on its own. Attention to recent developments in neuro-
science can stimulate new ways of thinking about historical interpretations of self-
hood. It may do this just by shaking out new metaphors that help us make sense of
human identity and action.
Eustace, Eugenia Lean, Julie Livingston, Jan Plamper, William M. Reddy, and Barbara H. Rosenwein,
AHR Conversation, “The Historical Study of Emotions,” American Historical Review 117, no. 5 (De-
cember 2012): 1487–1531; and William M. Reddy, “Neuroscience and the Fallacies of Functionalism,”
History and Theory 49, no. 3 (October 2010): 412– 425.
4 A preliminary discussion of some of these issues can be found in Lynn Hunt, “Psychology, Psy-
choanalysis, and Historical Thought,” in Lloyd Kramer and Sarah Maza, eds., A Companion to Western
Historical Thought (Malden, Mass., 2002), 337–356. Some of the material here has been adapted from
Lynn Hunt, Writing History in the Global Era (New York, 2014), 101–118.
5 Gustave Le Bon, The Crowd: A Study of the Popular Mind (New York, 1896), quotes from 13, 17,
and 109. See also Susanna Barrows, Distorting Mirrors: Visions of the Crowd in Late Nineteenth-Century
France (New Haven, Conn., 1981), especially 169.
6 Alfred Stein, “Adolf Hitler et Gustave Le Bon: Der Meister der Massenbewegung und sein Leh-
many working people willing to submit themselves to this form of “psychic exploi-
tation”? Thompson regarded the “evidence of hysteria” in Methodist revivalism as
an unfortunate psychological response to the defeat of revolutionary impulses in
England.8 Good crowds were never subject to psychologizing, it seems, only bad (in
this case, politically passive) ones.
1957. William L. Langer, “The Next Assignment,” American Historical Review 63, no. 2 (January 1958):
283–304.
12 On the contemporary view of psychoanalysis, see, for example, Peter Brooks and Alex Woloch,
eds., Whose Freud? The Place of Psychoanalysis in Contemporary Culture (New Haven, Conn., 2000).
13 I discuss the demise of psychohistory at greater length in “Psychology, Psychoanalysis, and His-
sense of self and agency (Freud’s ego), and that the mind also serves to connect an
individual to social communities (Freud’s superego).14
The prospects for dialogue between history and psychology are even bleaker
when it comes to academic psychology. Psychoanalysis, in its clinical practice, relies
on historical narratives (the stories the patient tells the analyst), whereas research
The Handbook of Social Psychology, 4th ed., 2 vols. (Boston, 1998), 1: 680–740, quote from 680. A more
positive tone, emphasizing the recovery of interest in the self, can be heard in the recent version of the
handbook: William B. Swann, Jr., and Jennifer K. Bosson, “Self and Identity,” in Fiske, Gilbert, and
Lindzey, eds., Handbook of Social Psychology, 5th ed., 2 vols. (Hoboken, N.J., 2010), 1: 589–628.
16 Michael S. Gazzaniga, The Mind’s Past (Berkeley, Calif., 1998), xi.
17 Michael S. Gazzaniga, “Forty-Five Years of Split-Brain Research and Still Going Strong,” Nature
Reviews Neuroscience 6 (August 1, 2005): 653–659, quotes from 657 and 658.
18 William M. Reddy, The Navigation of Feeling: A Framework for the History of Emotions (Cambridge,
2001). See also Barbara H. Rosenwein, Emotional Communities in the Early Middle Ages (Ithaca, N.Y.,
2006).
in historical documents more readily than any other expression of selves.19 Anger,
disgust, fear, joy, surprise, and sadness can be traced in many different kinds of
documents, ranging from court cases to paintings. Paul Ekman famously argued that
these were basic human emotions found in all cultures and that they give rise to
universally recognizable facial expressions.20 Even if this is true, and there is still
of the Emotions in Man and Animals, Introduction, Afterword, and Commentaries by Paul Ekman (Ox-
ford, 2002).
21 A review of some of the disputes can be found in Paul E. Griffiths, “Basic Emotions, Complex
Emotions, Machiavellian Emotions,” Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 52 (2003): 39–67. The
issue of cross-cultural differences is important and vexed. Many psychological studies of such differences
rely on Western approaches (e.g., comparing responses of college students in the U.S. to their coun-
terparts in Japan using the same questionnaire). Yet anthropological studies of differences in the self
have their own issues, as Douglas Hollan pointed out many years ago; the use of simplified and idealized
notions of cultural difference can obscure similarities in subjective experience. Hollan, “Cross-Cultural
Differences in the Self,” Journal of Anthropological Research 48, no. 4 (December 1992): 283–300. The
main lesson to be derived is that much more historically informed study is needed.
22 Antonio R. Damasio, Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain (New York, 1994).
See also his The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness (New York,
1999). On affective sciences, see John Protevi, Political Affect: Connecting the Social and the Somatic
(Minneapolis, 2009), 23. For the implications for historical analysis, see William M. Reddy, “Saying
Something New: Practice Theory and Cognitive Neuroscience,” Arcadia—International Journal for Lit-
erary Studies 44, no. 1 (2009): 8–23.
23 Here I differ from Ruth Leys, who considers Damasio an arch anti-intentionalist (“The Turn to
pulsive and prone to violence, and more naı̈ve and simplistic than the periods that
followed), the work of historians such as Barbara Rosenwein and Ute Frevert dem-
onstrates that they need not be.24
From his work on emotions, Antonio Damasio has developed a model of the
neural basis of the self that is at once biological and historical. The self depends, he
1978; original German ed., 1939); Rosenwein, Emotional Communities in the Early Middle Ages. See also
Jan Plamper, “The History of Emotions: An Interview with William Reddy, Barbara Rosenwein, and
Peter Stearns,” History and Theory 49, no. 2 (2010): 237–265; and Ute Frevert, Emotions in History—Lost
and Found (Budapest, 2011). For the best overview, see Monique Scheer, “Are Emotions a Kind of
Practice (and Is That What Makes Them Have a History?): A Bourdieuian Approach to Understanding
Emotion,” History and Theory 51, no. 2 (2012): 193–220.
25 Antonio Damasio, Self Comes to Mind: Constructing the Conscious Brain (New York, 2010), 193.
26 Damasio, Descartes’ Error, 238–239.
27 Damasio, Self Comes to Mind, 196–197, emphasis in the original.
other way around, and no one yet has been able to explain the advent of conscious-
ness.28 It is worth noting that Mikkel Borch-Jacobsen similarly criticized Freud for
assuming the consciousness of the ego in order to explain its emergence: “How is
it that I may have a relation to my body as my body, my own body, if it is not by saying
‘I,’ ‘me,’ ‘ego,’ Ich? . . . Are we not dealing, much more probably, with the ego-
2011, http://www.nybooks.com/articles/archives/2011/jun/09/mystery-consciousness-continues/.
29 Mikkel Borch-Jacobsen, The Freudian Subject (Stanford, Calif., 1989), 70–71, emphasis in the
original.
30 Searle, “The Mystery of Consciousness Continues.”
31 Francisco J. Varela, Evan Thompson, and Eleanor Rosch, The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science
and Human Experience (Cambridge, Mass., 1991), 14, as quoted in Zoe Drayson, “Embodied Cognitive
Science and Its Implications for Psychopathology,” Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology 16, no. 4 (2009):
329–340, quote from 331.
32 See, for example, George Lakoff and Mark Johnson, Philosophy in the Flesh: The Embodied Mind
develops its own contribution; it is not just a product of external sensations (or social
construction). It has to act in its own right to even begin to make sense of the world.
To hold to a concept of an embodied self is to give priority to the body’s inter-
actions with the world. It follows, then, that mind and body are not separate. This
lack of separation might seem obvious, since the brain is located in the body and the
to the importance of a sense of ownership of one’s body and of agency in action and
cognition. Mental illnesses such as schizophrenia reveal how vital these are to func-
tioning in the world. Auditory hallucinations, delusions of control, and “thought
insertion” (“the FBI put a chip in my brain that told me to kill him . . .”) are usually
disorders of the sense of agency. Patients suffering from them do not, as it were,
WHAT DIFFERENCE MIGHT THE EMBODIED SELF make to historians? Historians hardly
need to be convinced that important things are happening outside of brains. The
question is rather whether what is happening inside an embodied self makes any
difference to history. Even as historians have turned to investigating the forms of
embodiment (where Elias and after him Foucault, feminists, and gender theorists
have led the way), the self has virtually disappeared, and with it, I argue, the sense
of agency and convincing explanations for historical change. The emphasis on the
plasticity, trainability, and social construction of bodies has been most successful at
explaining how systems such as prisons, factories, or gender and race differences
work; it has been much less able to explain how new understandings, practices, or
institutions can emerge.41
Many if not most major historical events occurred only because many individuals
experienced emotions that were strong enough to impel action. Agency and historical
change both depend on an interactive relationship between individual selves and the
social or collective dimensions of life (which includes intersubjectivity, the relation
of self to self). Individual consciousness, because it is embodied, can change the
outcome of action, not through the expression of “free will,” pure subjectivity, or a
38 For more discussion, see ibid., 173–178.
39 Hanne De Jaegher, Ezequiel Di Paolo, and Shaun Gallagher, “Can Social Interaction Constitute
Social Cognition?,” Trends in Cognitive Sciences 14 (October 1, 2010): 441– 447.
40 “Social neuroscience” uses neuroscientific techniques to get at the brain functions that underlie
behavior rather than studying how social interactions shape neurological development itself. See, for
example, Tiffany A. Ito, “Implicit Social Cognition: Insights from Social Neuroscience,” in Bertram
Gawronski and B. Keith Payne, eds., Handbook of Implicit Social Cognition: Measurement, Theory, and
Applications (New York, 2011), 80–92.
41 Although I disagree with her analysis on some points, I still find extremely useful the analysis of
disembodied mind, but rather through chains of interaction and interpretation that
include but are not limited to conscious thought.42
An example might make these assertions less abstract. The English printer Sam-
uel Richardson published his novel Pamela in 1740. All kinds of models for this work
might be cited, yet in many ways this story about a virtuous servant girl was un-
Approach to Embodiment and Agentic Capacities,” Political Studies 53, no. 1 (2005): 124 –142.
43 Lynn Hunt, Inventing Human Rights: A History (New York, 2007).
the linguistic turn, with its emphasis on language, text, and representation as fun-
damental components in the construction of reality, the vocabulary of embodiment
calls attention to gesture, action, movement, and unconscious or tacit forms of
knowledge. Experience is not just a linguistic event. Many kinds of knowing precede
the acquisition of language and accompany it thereafter. Learning a language and