India'S Participatory Model: The Right To Information in Election Law
India'S Participatory Model: The Right To Information in Election Law
India'S Participatory Model: The Right To Information in Election Law
MANOJ MATE*
INTRODUCTION
* Associate Professor of Law, Whittier Law School, Professor (by courtesy) of Politi-
cal Science, Whittier College; Director, Center for International and Comparative Law;
Member, California Bar; Chair-elect (2015–present), Section on Law and South Asian
Studies, American Association of Law Schools (AALS); Ph.D. 2010, Political Science, Uni-
versity of California, Berkeley; M.A. 2010, Political Science, University of California, Berke-
ley; J.D. 2000, Harvard Law School; B.A. 1997, Political Science, University of California
Berkeley. This Article was recently selected for presentation at the 2015 Annual Meeting
of the AALS Section on Comparative Law. Special thanks to Teemu Ruskola for serving as
a discussant and for his valuable comments and feedback, and to Seval Yildirim for her
insights on the project. I also thank Robert Post, Bruce Cain, Jonathan Glater, David Men-
efee-Libey, Thad Kousser, Stewart Chang, and Erez Aloni for comments. All errors are my
own.
1. See generally Robert Post, Meiklejohn’s Mistake: Individual Autonomy and the Reform of
Public Discourse, 64 U. COLO. L. REV. 1109 (1993) [hereinafter Post, Meiklejohn’s Mistake]
(critiquing the failure of the collectivist model of free speech to protect the autonomy of
speech and public discourse and articulating a “participatory model” of speech); ROBERT
POST, CITIZENS DIVIDED: CAMPAIGN FINANCE REFORM AND THE CONSTITUTION (2014) [here-
inafter POST, CITIZENS DIVIDED] (analyzing the relationship between discursive democracy
and representative democracy in U.S. politics and suggesting that campaign finance
reform regulations on corporate speech could be justified by the interest in electoral
integrity).
2. See infra Parts I and II (discussing pluralist, deliberative, and participatory theories
of democracy). See ROBERT DAHL, PREFACE TO DEMOCRATIC THEORY 125 (1956) (advancing
a pluralist theory of representative democracy); JÜRGEN HABERMAS, BETWEEN FACTS AND
NORMS: CONTRIBUTIONS TO A DISCOURSE THEORY OF LAW AND DEMOCRACY 165 (1992)
(advancing a proceduralist model of deliberative democracy theory); CAROLE PATEMAN,
PARTICIPATION AND DEMOCRATIC THEORY 2, 17–21 (1970) (analyzing the historical geneal-
ogy of participatory democracy theory).
377
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 2 11-JAN-16 16:01
3. See Nancy Fraser, Rethinking the Public Sphere: A Contribution to the Critique of Actually
Existing Democracy, 25/26 SOCIAL TEXT 56, 56–57, 60–63, 65–67, 71–76 (1990) (analyzing
the shortcomings of Habermas’ theory of the public sphere).
4. See LAWRENCE LESSIG, REPUBLIC LOST: HOW MONEY CORRUPTS CONGRESS AND A
PLAN TO STOP IT 17–20 (2011) (describing the problem of “dependence corruption” in
U.S. politics); see also Joseph Fishkin & William Forbath, The Anti-Oligarchy Constitution, 94
B.U. L. REV. 669, 669–71 (2014) (arguing that extreme levels of economic inequality and
oligarchic concentrations of power pose threats to republican democracy); TIMOTHY
KUHNER, CAPITALISM V. DEMOCRACY: MONEY IN POLITICS AND THE FREE MARKET CONSTITU-
TION 9–11 (2014) (tracing how the U.S. Supreme Court’s campaign finance reform juris-
prudence has allowed corporate power to dominate democracy).
5. Citizens United v. FEC, 558 U.S. 310, 311 (2010); KUHNER, supra note 4, at 12–14; R
Zephyr Teachout, Neoliberal Political Law, 77 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 215, 219 (2015) (dis-
cussing the First Amendment rationale for the majority’s opinion in Citizens United); see
McCutcheon v. FEC, 134 S. Ct. 1434, 1438 (2014).
6. POST, CITIZENS DIVIDED, supra note 1, at 36–37. R
7. Id.
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 3 11-JAN-16 16:01
8. Union of India v. Association for Democratic Reforms, (2002) 5 SCC 294 (India)
(holding that Article 19(1) of the Indian Constitution guarantees a voters’ constitutional
right to know the financial, criminal, and educational antecedents of candidates in elec-
tions); People’s Union for Civil Liberties v. Union of India, (2003) 4 SCC 399, 403–04
(India) (reaffirming voters’ right to information in elections and invalidating a legislative
provision enacted to override and limit the Supreme Court’s earlier decision in Union of
India v. Association v. Democratic Reforms, (2002) 5 SCC 294 (India)).
9. Union of India, 5 SCC at 294. For scholarship on election law and reform in
India, see David Gilmartin & Robert Moog, Introduction to Election Law in India, 11 ELECTION
L.J. 136 (2012); see also Ujjwal Kumar Singh, Between Moral Force and Supplementary Legality:
A Model Code of Conduct and the Election Commission of India, 11 ELECTION L.J. 149 (2012);
M.V. Rajeev Gowda & E. Sridharan, Reforming India’s Party Financing and Election Expenditure
Laws, 11 ELECTION L.J. 226 (2012).
10. People’s Union for Civil Liberties, 4 SCC at 403–04.
11. S. Subramaniam Balaji v. Union of India, (2013) 9 SCC 659 (India) (holding that
political parties’ promises of “freebies” to voters in election manifestos do not constitute
corrupt practices under Representation of People Act of 1951, but recommending that
Election Commission of India issue directives regulating how party manifestos include
freebies).
12. People’s Union for Civil Liberties v. Union of India, (2013) 10 SCC 1 (India)
(holding that the right to vote for “none of the above” is protected as part of the freedom
of speech and expression under Article 19(1) of the Indian Constitution).
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 4 11-JAN-16 16:01
13. This Article advances a conception of the participatory model that is analytically
distinct from Robert Post’s participatory model. See Manoj Mate, High Courts and Election
Law Reform in the United States and India, 32 B.U. INT’L L.J. 104–05, 131–32 (2014) (compar-
ing the jurisprudential approaches of the U.S. and Indian Supreme Courts in electoral
reform and detailing differing free speech and First Amendment approaches).
14. Sunila Kale, The State of the States, in THE STATE OF INDIA’S DEMOCRACY 209–218
(Sumit Ganguly et. al. eds., 2007) (analyzing the impact of spatial inequality at the state
level on Indian democracy); see JEAN DRÈZE & AMARTYA SEN, INDIA: DEVELOPMENT AND PAR-
TICIPATION 347–63 (2002) (analyzing the gap between functional democratic institutions
and democratic practices and the impact of social and economic equality on democratic
participation); see infra Part V.A. See generally FRANCINE FRANKEL, INDIA’S POLITICAL ECON-
OMY 1947-2004: THE GRADUAL REVOLUTION (Oxford Univ. Press, 2d ed. 2005) (1978) (pro-
viding a political history of the evolution of economic policy from early statist socialism
through the post-liberalization era); see generally Pranab Bardhan, Inequality, Inefficiency, and
the Challenges for Social Democracy in India’s Economic Transition, in AN INDIAN SOCIAL DEMOC-
RACY, ACADEMIC FOUNDATION 18–39 (S. Khilnani & M. Malhoutra eds., 2013) (explaining
the detrimental effect of India’s pervasive social, political, economic, and educational ine-
quality on its ability develop a “social democracy” and the need to develop and agree on
social protection ideology and programs to combat the inequality).
15. See generally DRÈZE & SEN, supra note 14 (analyzing the gap between functional R
democratic institutions and democratic practices and the impact of social and economic
equality on democratic participation).
16. See infra Part III.
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 5 11-JAN-16 16:01
17. Cf. JEAN DRÈZE & AMARTYA SEN, AN UNCERTAIN GLORY: INDIA AND ITS CONTRADIC-
TIONS 265–69 (2013) (discussing how the dominance of upper class and intellectual elites
distorts news media coverage and political discourse in India).
18. See SUDIPTA KAVIRAJ, THE IMAGINARY INSTITUTION OF INDIA: POLITICS AND IDEAS
20–22 (2010) (discussing the significant gap between elite and mass discourse in Indian
politics and governance).
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 6 11-JAN-16 16:01
omy, and of civil society and the public sphere, with the domain of
government.23 Elements of pluralist-representative democracy and
deliberative democracy dominate modern democratic systems.
Both conceptions create opportunities for distortion in governance
and discourse by dominant economic elites, and both heavily con-
strict the possibility of active participation in discourse and govern-
ance. A positive rights participatory model based on the right to
information can address these weaknesses.
B. Deliberative Democracy
A second conception of democracy in western liberal scholarship
is deliberative democracy.33 In recent years, scholars have shown
renewed interest in deliberative or discursive democracy and have
framed it as an alternative to the pluralist model.
2. Civic Republicanism
A variant of deliberative democracy is the theory of civic republi-
canism.51 Theories of civic republicanism build on aspects of delib-
43. Id. at 308–10.
44. See Flynn, supra note 35, at 438; see also HABERMAS, BETWEEN FACTS AND NORMS, R
supra note 2, at 298–301. R
45. HABERMAS, BETWEEN FACTS AND NORMS, supra note 2, at 298–301. Cf. ROBERT C. R
POST, DEMOCRACY, EXPERTISE, AND ACADEMIC FREEDOM (2012) (arguing that a primary goal
of the First Amendment is democratic legitimation).
46. HABERMAS, BETWEEN FACTS AND NORMS, supra note 2, at 486. R
47. Id. at 307–08.
48. See id. at 308.
49. See id. at 299, 358.
50. See id. at 368, 370–74.
51. See Frank Michelman, Law’s Republic, 97 YALE L.J. 1493, 1494–95 (1988) (advanc-
ing a diaological approach to republican theory); see also Cass Sunstein, Beyond the Republi-
can Revival, 97 YALE. L.J. 1539, 1541 (1988) [hereinafter Sunstein, Beyond the Republican
Revival] (analyzing the key components of civic republican theory).
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 11 11-JAN-16 16:01
C. Participatory Democracy
A third conception of democracy is participatory democracy,
which emphasizes direct and equal participation by individuals in
the political process.57 Rousseau envisioned a political system in
which citizens would participate directly in political decision-mak-
ing processes as equal and independent individuals who are also
interdependent on each other and equally dependent on all the
others who are collectively viewed as sovereign.58 The core princi-
ple of Rousseau’s theory of participatory democracy—the general
will—is centered on the idea that men should be governed by laws,
and not by men.59 The general will requires political equality of all
individuals participating in the decision-making process such that
52. See HANNAH ARENDT, THE HUMAN CONDITION (1958); see also ARISTOTLE, POLITICS
(Ernest Barker ed. & trans., Oxford Univ. Press 1972).
53. See Sunstein, Beyond the Republican Revival, supra note 51, at 1541 (arguing that R
most conceptions of civic republicanism consists of four key attributes: deliberation, politi-
cal equality, universalism and citizenship).
54. See id. at 1541, 1550–51; see Michelman, supra note 51, at 1503–04; see also R
HABERMAS, Three Normative Models, supra note 24, at 239–42, 245 (comparing the liberal and R
civic republican models of democracy to the proceduralist model of deliberative
democracy).
55. Sunstein, Beyond the Republican Revival, supra note 51, at 1556; see Michelman, supra R
note 51, at 1503 (arguing that “political engagement is considered a positive human good R
because the self is understood as partially constituted by, or as coming to itself through,
such engagement.”).
56. See Michelman, supra note 51, at 1503–04. R
57. This Section draws heavily from PATEMAN, supra note 2 (analyzing the history of R
participatory democracy theory).
58. See id. at 24.
59. See id. at 24–25.
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 12 11-JAN-16 16:01
they can only vote for policies acceptable to all individuals voting,
and requires a process in which the benefits and burdens of
enacted policies are shared equally.60
Modern participatory theorists, including Carole Pateman and
Jane Mansbridge, revived interest in the value of participation in
democratic systems. Drawing on earlier insights from classical the-
orists, Pateman critiqued representative democracy institutions as
insufficient to provide for full democracy.61 Instead, Pateman sug-
gested the need for a model of democracy based on equal partici-
pation in the actual making of decisions, and political equality.62
Moreover, Pateman’s ideal form of democracy would provide for
participatory democracy in all aspects of the polity and in society,
including industry and the workplace.63
60. Id. at 24 (citing JEAN JACQUES-ROUSSEAU, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT, bk. II, ch. 3 (Pen-
guin Classics ed. 1968). A corollary of Rousseau’s ideal general will model is that organ-
ized groups should not be present in the decision-making process because it would allow
for the triumph of particular wills over the general will.
61. PATEMAN, supra note 2, at 42. R
62. Id. at 43.
63. Id. at 43, 45–84, 102–11.
64. See Fraser, supra note 3, at 60–67, 72–77. R
65. See id. Owen Fiss arguably anticipated some of Fraser’s critiques of the public
sphere in his scholarship. See Fiss, supra note 22, at 1412–13. R
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 13 11-JAN-16 16:01
66. See HABERMAS, BETWEEN FACTS AND NORMS, supra note 2, at 298–300; see also POST, R
CITIZENS DIVIDED, supra note 1, at 36–37, 48–49, 53–54. R
67. See HABERMAS, BETWEEN FACTS AND NORMS, supra note 2, at 298–99. R
68. Id. at 299.
69. Id.
70. See id. at 300–01.
71. Fraser, supra note 3, at 72. R
72. HABERMAS, THE STRUCTURAL TRANSFORMATION, supra note 32, at 131–32, 161, R
175–79.
73. Id. at 161–63, 175–79.
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 14 11-JAN-16 16:01
96. See ADORNO, supra note 95; see also HABERMAS, THE STRUCTURAL TRANSFORMATION, R
supra note 32, at 162–63, 172–73. R
97. See DRÈZE & SEN, supra note 14, at 355. See generally AKHIL GUPTA, RED TAPE: R
BUREAUCRACY, STRUCTURAL VIOLENCE, AND POVERTY IN INDIA (2012). See infra Part V (dis-
cussing the elite skew and distortion of media and political discourse in India, and failure
of media elites to discuss poverty as a crisis).
98. See id.; see also infra discussion in II.B. See generally Patrick Heller, Democracy, Par-
ticipatory Politics and Development: Some Comparative Lessons from Brazil, India and South Africa,
44 POLITY 643 (2012) (discussing the relationship between, civil society, state institutions,
and the concept of effective citizenship and associational autonomy).
99. DRÈZE & SEN, supra note 14, at 266. R
100. See Patrick Heller, Toward a Sociological Perspective on Democratization in the Global
South: Lessons from Brazil, India, and South Africa 10, 12 (Comparative Research Workshop,
Yale Univ., Feb. 8, 2011).
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 18 11-JAN-16 16:01
C. Accountability
The positive rights participatory model would also address the
third shortcoming of deliberative democracy theory—the lack of
accountability between deliberative and decision-making bodies,
and the public sphere. The relationship between the state, the
public sphere, and civil society is crucial for understanding the
108. Fraser, supra note 3, at 66–67.
109. Id. at 59. Fraser here suggests a broader conception of public spheres in observ-
ing that these spheres may consist of “various journals and various social geographies of
urban space.” This suggests that various forms of news media, publications, as well as the
spatial design of communities each can play a role in controlling and shaping public dis-
course in the public sphere.
110. See generally Joshua Cohen, Reflections on Habermas on Democracy, 12 RATIO JURIS 385
(1999).
111. Id. at 409.
112. Id.
113. Id.
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 20 11-JAN-16 16:01
114. See generally HABERMAS THE STRUCTURAL TRANSFORMATION, supra note 32 (discuss- R
ing the relationship between the state, market, civil society, and the public sphere).
115. Id.
116. Fraser, supra note 3, at 75 (emphasis added). R
117. Id. at 75–76.
118. Id. at 76.
119. Id. at 75.
120. Id. at 76.
121. Id.
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 21 11-JAN-16 16:01
CTO, A.I.R. 1963 S.C. 1811 (India); Barium Chemicals v. Co. Law Bd., A.I.R. 1967 S.C. 295
(India)).
128. See Mukhariya v. Ram, (1955) S.C.R. 608 (India) (holding that candidate speech
in elections is based in statutory, not constitutional rights, and therefore is not absolutely
protected under Article 19 of the Indian Constitution).
129. Ministry of Law and Justice (Right to Information Act) No. 22, 2005, The Gazetter
of India Extraordinary, sec. I (2) (June 15, 2005), http://www.righttoinformation.gov.in/
rti-act.pdf.
130. See Rob Jenkins & Anne Marie Goetz, Accounts and Accountability: Theoretical Impli-
cations of the Right-to-Information Movement in India, 20 THIRD WORLD Q. 603 (1999) (analyz-
ing the development and impact of the MKSS farmers’ movement on India’s political
system); see also Trilochan Sastry, Toward Decriminalization of Elections and Politics, 49 ECON. &
POL. WKLY 34 (2014).
131. CORE-COMMITTEE ON ELECTION REFORMS, MINISTRY OF LAW & JUSTICE, GOVERN-
MENT OF INDIA, BACKGROUND PAPER ON ELECTORAL REFORMS (Dec. 2010).
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 23 11-JAN-16 16:01
132. K. Subramanian, Towards Free and Fair Elections in India, HINDU (July 2, 2008),
http://www.thehindu.com/todays-paper/tp-opinion/towards-free-and-fair-elections-in-
india/article1288143.ece (last visited Aug. 24, 2014).
133. Trivedi v. Union of India (1997) 4 SCC 306 (India).
134. EC Focus on Crime-Politics Ties, INDIAN EXP. (Aug. 21, 1997), http://
archive.indianexpress.com/Storyold/10279/.
135. Subramanian, supra note 132. R
136. The Unholy Nexus, INDIAN EXP. (Aug. 22, 1997), http://archive.indianexpress.com/
Storyold/10370/. The Election Commission also issued an order in August 1997 that clari-
fied the scope of Section 8 of the Representation of People Act of 1951 as requiring that
disqualification of candidates under this Section would begin from the date of conviction.
See generally V. Venkatesan, Crime and Politics, FRONTLINE, Vol. 18, Issue 26, Dec. 22,
2001–Jan. 04, 2002.
137. Subramanian, supra note 132. R
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 24 11-JAN-16 16:01
138. See Ass’n for Democratic Reforms v. Union of India, 2001 AIR 126 (Del.) 128–32
(India), citing to 170TH REPORT OF THE LAW COMMISSION OF INDIA: REFORM OF THE ELECTO-
RAL LAWS, http://www.lawcommissionofindia.nic.in/lc170.htm (last visited Nov. 22, 2015).
139. Id. at 131.
140. Id. at 131–32.
141. Id. at 128–29.
142. Id. at 126, 130.
143. Id. at 128–29. Notably, the High Court also provided an in-depth review of the
history of government commissions, reports, books, and articles that documented the rise
of criminalization in Indian politics.
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 25 11-JAN-16 16:01
tions.150 Gill, a state legislator, stated that “[u]nless you have hun-
dred men with guns you cannot contest elections in Bihar,” and
another minister admitted, “I am honest enough to declare that I
keep goondas. For, without them, it is virtually impossible to win
elections.”151
In expanding the right to information, the Court drew on its
earlier free speech decisions interpreting Article 19(1)(a), which
provides that citizens have a right to freedom of speech and expres-
sion. These decisions recognized that Article 19(1)(a) also encom-
passed a citizen’s right to receive information and right to know.152
In Indian Express Newspapers v. Union of India (1985), the Court held
that Article 19(1)(a) must be broadly interpreted to include the
right to circulate view through speech, writing, and audio and vis-
ual media, including the print media, radio, and television.153 The
Delhi High Court concluded that the right to freedom of speech
and expression encompasses several inter-related rights, including
the right to voice one’s opinion, the right to seek information and
ideas, the right to receive information, and the right to impart
information.154
In the Airwaves case, the Supreme Court held that the freedom
of speech and expression included the right to acquire and receive
information and the right to disseminate it. The Court held that
“[f]reedom to speech and expression is necessary, for self-expres-
sion which is an important means of free conscience and self-fulfill-
ment. It enables people to contribute to debates . . . [i]t is the only
vehicle of political discourse so essential to democracy.”155 Signifi-
cantly, the Court also recognized that the right to information also
was based in protections of liberty and equality, in citing to the
Preamble, Article 14 (“the state shall not deny to any person equal-
ity before the law”) and Article 38(2) of the Directive Principles
(“[t]he State, shall, in particular-endeavor to eliminate inequalities
in status, facilities and opportunities, not only amongst individuals
but also amongst groups of people.”)156
150. Id.
151. Id. at 134.
152. See id. at 135 (citing State of Uttar Pradesh v. Raj Narain, (1975) 4 SCC 428
(India)).
153. Id. at 136 (citing Indian Express Newspapers v. Union of India, (1985) 1 SCC 641
(India)).
154. Id. at 136–37.
155. Id. at 135 (citing Sec’y, Ministry of Info. & Broad. v. Cricket Ass’n of Bengal,
(1995) 2 SCC 161 (India)).
156. Id.
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 27 11-JAN-16 16:01
157. Id.
158. Id. at 136 (citing Sec’y, Ministry of Info. & Broad. v. Cricket Ass’n of Bengal,
(1995) 2 SCC 161 (India)).
159. Id.
160. Id. at 136 (citing S.P. Gupta v. Union of India, AIR 1982 SC 149 (India)).
161. Id. at 138.
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 28 11-JAN-16 16:01
162. Id.
163. Union of India v. Ass’n for Democratic Reforms, (2002) 5 SCC 294, 303 (India).
164. Id. at 306.
165. Id.
166. Id. at 312–14, 319–21.
167. Id. at 316–17.
168. Id. at 317.
169. Id. at 321.
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 29 11-JAN-16 16:01
177. Section 33-B of the amended Representation of People Act only required disclo-
sure of assets and liabilities of a candidate and a candidates’ spouse and dependent chil-
dren to the Speaker of the Lok Sabha after a candidate was successfully elected to office.
Representation of People Act, No. 43 of 1951, INDIA CODE [hereinafter Representation of
People Act].
178. Id. at 80.
179. People’s Union for Civil Liberties, (2003) 4 SCC 399, 402–03 (India).
180. Id. at 438.
181. Id. at 434.
182. Id. at 438 (citing INDIA CONST. art. 19(1)(a), 19(2)).
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 31 11-JAN-16 16:01
183. Id.
184. Id. at 423.
185. See id. at 425–30.
186. Id. at 430.
187. Id. at 450, 453.
188. Id. at 459–60.
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 32 11-JAN-16 16:01
which decided the case in 2013.193 One of the main issues referred
to the larger bench was the issue of the maintainability of the writ
petition under Article 32. During the hearings before the original
two-judge bench, respondent Union of India argued that the writ
petition was not maintainable under Article 32 on the grounds that
the right claimed by petitioners (the right to vote) was not a funda-
mental right under Part III of the Constitution, but rather a statu-
tory right recognized under the Representation of People Act.194
The division bench referred the matter to a larger bench because
of some confusion and ambiguity about the status and nature of
the right to vote as expressed in the Court’s decisions in the earlier
ADR and PUCL decisions in 2002 and 2003, and a later decision,
Kuldip Nayar v. Union of India (2006).
In adjudicating the threshold issue of maintainability, the three-
judge bench held that the writ was maintainable because while the
right to vote was a statutory right (and not a fundamental or consti-
tutional right) under Section 79(d) of the Representation of Peo-
ple Act, the actual casting of a ballot during an election is part of
the fundamental right to expression guaranteed and protected
under Article 19(1)(a) of the Constitution.195 Writing for the
bench, Chief Justice Sathasivam further clarified that the actual
casting of a vote is “a facet of the right of expression” under Article
19(1)(a) as held by the Court in the earlier ADR (2002) and PUCL
(2003) decisions.196
The Supreme Court invalidated Rules 41(2) and (3) and Rule
49(O) of the rules as ultra vires Section 128 of the RPA and Article
19(1)(a) of the Constitution “to the extent they violate secrecy of
voting.”197 Section 49(O) required that voters seeking to cast a
NOTA vote must first inform the presiding officer of their inten-
tion of casting a ‘none of the above’ vote, and required that the
presiding officer must then record an entry in a rulebook after
recording the signature of the voter.198 According to the PUCL,
Section 49(O) was violative of the constitutional provisions guaran-
teed under Article 19(1)(a) (Freedom of Speech and Expression)
and Article 21 (Right to Liberty) and violated the concept of secret
ballot.
193. People’s Union for Civil Liberties v. Union of India, (2013) 12 SCR 283, 294
(India).
194. Id. at 295.
195. Id. at 307–08.
196. Id. at 307.
197. Id. at 322.
198. Id. at 315.
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 34 11-JAN-16 16:01
Income Tax Act, and not through direct disclosure through the
Election Commission or other agencies.210
210. See Common Cause v. Union of India, (1996) 2 SCC 752, 754 (India).
211. Id. at 755.
212. Id.
213. Id. at 756.
214. Id.
215. Id. at 756–57.
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 37 11-JAN-16 16:01
information under the Right to Information Act has been less suc-
cessful. This is illustrated by ongoing non-compliance of political
parties with disclosure regulations and orders of the Supreme
Court.228
However, in Subash Chandra Agrawal v. Indian National Congress
and Other Parties (2013), the Central Information Commission
ruled that political parties constituted “public authorities” under
the Right to Information Act and therefore were required to dis-
close information regarding all aspects of parties’ campaign
finance under the Act.229 The CIC’s decision highlights the extent
to which the Indian government itself provides free office space,
rent, television time, and tax exemptions to political parties.230
Like earlier judicial decisions, none of the major political parties in
India have complied with the CIC’s decision.231
233. Robert Post, Reconciling Theory and Doctrine in First Amendment Jurisprudence, 88
CALIF. L. REV. 2353, 2367 (2000).
234. Id.
235. POST, DEMOCRACY, EXPERTISE, AND ACADEMIC FREEDOM, supra note 45, at 33–34 R
(2012).
236. Post, Meiklejohn’s Mistake, supra note 1, at 1113; Robert C. Post, Between Governance R
and Management: The History and Theory of the Public Forum, 34 UCLA L. REV. 1713, 1775
(1987).
237. See Post, Reconciling Theory and Doctrine, supra note 233, at 2367–68. R
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 41 11-JAN-16 16:01
238. See Robert Post, Regulating Election Speech Under the First Amendment, 77 TEX. L. REV.
1837, 1841 (1998–1999).
239. Id.
240. See POST, DEMOCRACY, EXPERTISE, AND ACADEMIC FREEDOM, supra note 45, at 37–41 R
(recognizing that in certain areas of First Amendment jurisprudence, the Court has held
that certain areas of speech are protected because they advance the value of democratic
competence).
241. AUSTIN, supra note 19, at 26–46. R
242. JACOBSOHN, supra note 19, at 91; GARY JACOBSOHN, THE DISHARMONIC CONSTITU- R
TION 12 n.27, http://uchv.princeton.edu/constitutionalism/Jacobsohn.pdf.
243. See AUSTIN, supra note 19, at 41–44, 75–83. R
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 42 11-JAN-16 16:01
244. See supra Part III for discussion accompanying note 178.
245. Article 14 provides that “the State shall not deny to any person equality before the
law.” INDIA CONST. art. 14.
246. Article 38 (1) of the Indian Constitution provides: “The State shall strive to pro-
mote the welfare of the people by securing and protecting as effectively as it may a social
order in which justice, social, economic and political, shall inform all the institutions of the
national life.” Article 38(2) states that: “(2) The State shall, in particular, strive to mini-
mise the inequalities in income, and endeavor to eliminate inequalities in status, facilities
and opportunities, not only amongst individuals but also amongst groups of people resid-
ing in different areas or engaged in different vocations.”
247. Ass’n for Democratic Reforms v. Union of India, 2001 AIR 126 (Del.) 136 (India).
248. See Mate, supra note 13. R
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 43 11-JAN-16 16:01
254. See People’s Union for Civil Liberties v. Union of India, (2013) 12 SCR 283, 294
(India) (holding that “the doctrine of parliamentary sovereignty as it obtains in England
does not prevail here except to the extent and in the fields provided by the Constitution.
The entire scheme of the Constitution is such that it ensures the sovereignty and integrity
of the country as a republic and the democratic way of life by parliamentary institutions
based on free and fair elections.”).
255. Id. at 320 (upholding the right to vote for none of the above via secret ballot).
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 45 11-JAN-16 16:01
259. Here, in contrast from existing conceptions of autonomy in the literature on First
Amendment free speech, and deliberative democracy, this Section relies on literature from
state-society and democratization in delineating a more robust conception of autonomy.
260. Theorists and scholars have offered competing conceptions and dichotomies for
understanding different facets of autonomy. See HABERMAS, BETWEEN FACTS AND NORMS,
supra note 2, at 84–94 (1996); see also Heller, Democracy, Participatory Politics and Development, R
supra note 98, at 646–47. R
261. See Heller, Democracy, Participatory Politics and Development, supra note 98, at 6. R
262. Id. at 647.
263. See Patrick Heller, Degrees of Democracy: Some Comparative Lessons from India, 52
WORLD POLITICS 484, 517–19 (2000) (tracing interactions between democratic institutions
and social processes in order to understand obstacles to democratic deepening in India).
264. Among the leading state-in-society pieces of scholarship are JAMES SCOTT, SEEING
LIKE A STATE 2–5 (1998) and JOEL MIGDAL, STRONG SOCIETIES AND WEAK STATES: STATE-
SOCIETY RELATIONS AND STATE CAPABILITIES IN THE THIRD WORLD 260–77 (1988).
265. Patrick Heller, Democratic Deepening in India and South Africa, 44 J. ASIAN & AFR.
STUD. 123, 125–26 (2009) (analyzing trajectories of democratization in India and South
Africa and arguing that subordinate groups have limited opportunities for meaningful
engagement with state institutions).
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 47 11-JAN-16 16:01
271. Id.
272. Id. at 647.
273. Id. at 647–48.
274. Id. at 646–48.
275. See CHARLES EPP, THE RIGHTS REVOLUTION (1994); see Manoj Mate, The Rise of Judi-
cial Governance in the Supreme Court of India, 33 B.U. INT’L L.J. 169, 191–98 (2015).
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 49 11-JAN-16 16:01
276. See Sanjay Ruparelia, A Progressive Juristocracy: The Unexpected Social Activism of
India’s Supreme Court (Kellogg Inst., Working Paper No. 391, Feb. 2013). Yet another exam-
ple of coordination between social movements, civil society, and oppositional state institu-
tions can be seen in the right to food movement in India. It began as a social movement in
which subaltern and subordinate groups, including peasant farmers groups, worked with
civil society and legal groups to address famine prevention. See Jean Drèze, Democracy and
The Right to Food, 39 ECON. & POL. WKLY. 1723, 1726–28 (2004) (describing right to food
social movement and right to food litigation in the Supreme Court of India).
277. See generally Rob Jenkins & Anne Marie Goetz, Accounts and Accountability: Theoreti-
cal Implications of the Right-to-information Movement in India, 20 THIRD WORLD Q. 603 (1999)
(tracing the development of the MKSS movement, and its broader impact on the national
right to information movement).
278. Sudha Venu Menon, Right to Information Act and NREGA: Reflections on Rajasthan,
MUNICH PERSONAL REPEC ARCHIEVE, http://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/id/eprint/7351
(last visited July 24, 2015).
279. A recent example of the inter-related nature of social movements within the pub-
lic sphere, and political movements can be seen in the emergence of the Aam Aadmi Party,
which had its roots in the national RTI movement. See generally Andrew Wyatts, Arvind
Kejriwal’s Leadership of the Aam Aadmi Party, 23 CONTEMP. S. ASIA 167 (2015).
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 50 11-JAN-16 16:01
2. External Autonomy
280. See INDIA CONST., 73rd Amendment and 74th Amendments; see also Heller, Toward
a Sociological Perspective, supra note 100, at 14–15 (discussing the impact of the 73rd and R
74th amendments on Indian democracy).
281. DRÈZE & SEN, supra note 14, at 358–64. R
282. See Heller, Democracy, Participatory Politics and Development, supra note 98, at 644 R
(citing DIETRICH RUESCHMEYER ET. AL., CAPITALIST DEVELOPMENT AND DEMOCRACY (1992)).
283. Id.
284. Heller, Degrees of Democracy, supra note 263, at 504. R
285. Id.
286. Id.
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 51 11-JAN-16 16:01
302. See generally KANCHAN CHANDRA, WHY ETHNIC PARTIES SUCCEED (2004).
303. See Arjun Appadurai, Success and Failure in the Deliberative Economy, in DELIBERATION
AND DEVELOPMENT: RETHINKING THE ROLE OF VOICE AND COLLECTIVE ACTION IN UNEQUAL
SOCIETIES 67, 69 (Patrick Heller & Vijayendra Rao eds., 2015).
304. See DRÈZE & SEN, supra note 14, at 364–65. R
305. Id. at 365–66.
306. See Manoj Mate & Adnan Naseemullah, State Security and Elite Capture: The Imple-
mentation of Antiterrorist Legislation in India, 9 J. HUM. RTS. 262, 275–76 (2010).
307. Heller, Degrees of Democracy, supra note 263, at 510–14. R
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 54 11-JAN-16 16:01
308. Id.
309. Fraser, supra note 3, at 66. R
310. Id.
311. Id.
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 55 11-JAN-16 16:01
319. Id.
320. See DRÈZE & SEN, supra note 17, at 266 (noting that “there is very little coverage of R
rural issues in the mainstream media: a recent study found that rural issues get only 2 per
cent of the total news coverage in national dailies (in spite of national dailies being widely
read in rural areas). The interests of what is described as the Indian ‘middle class’ (even
though most members of this class are way above the middle of the spectrum of affluence
of Indians as a whole) receive enormously more attention than the concerns of the under-
privileged, with a bias that slants the papers and broadcast channels towards such subjects
as fashion, gastronomy, Bollywood and cricket.”).
321. DRÈZE & SEN, supra note 17, at 268 (citing Ashok Rudra, Emergence of the Intelligent- R
sia as a Ruling Class in India, 24 ECON. & POL. WKLY. 142, 147–49 (1989)).
322. See Milan Vaishnav, The Market for Criminality: Money, Muscle, and Elections in India
(Univ. of Penn. Working Paper, Aug. 31, 2011).
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 57 11-JAN-16 16:01
323. A.T., Campaign Finance in India: Black Money Power, ECONOMIST (May 4, 2014),
http://www.economist.com/blogs/banyan/2014/05/campaign-finance-india.
324. ELECTORAL REFORMS REPORT, supra note 250. R
325. See Vaishnav, supra note 322. R
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 58 11-JAN-16 16:01
C. Accountability
Jean Dreze and Amartya Sen distinguish between democratic
ideals, democratic institutions, and democratic practice, highlight-
ing the gap between democratic institutions and democratic prac-
tice in India, specifically focusing on barriers to effective
democratic practice.329 In particular, Dreze and Sen highlight key
obstacles or challenges to the three key foundations of democratic
practice: facility or functional democratic institutions, involvement
(informed public engagement with these institutions), and equity
(the level of fairness in the distribution of power within a particular
system). Dreze and Sen, and other scholars, have highlighted
some of the main problems with the state of representative democ-
racy in India.330 These include political corruption in government
and criminality in elections and government. In this Section, I ana-
326. See Fraser, supra note 3; see NANCY FRASER, TRANSNATIONALIZING THE PUBLIC SPHERE R
ON THE LEGITIMACY AND EFFICACY OF PUBLIC OPINION IN A POST-WESTPHALIAN WORLD
(2007).
327. Fraser, supra note 3. R
328. Id. at 68.
329. DRÈZE & SEN, supra note 17, at 246–48, 250–57, 259–61. R
330. See id. at 81–82, 86, 88–91, 94–99, 246–48, 250–51.
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 59 11-JAN-16 16:01
1. Electoral Accountability
Representative democracy provides limited opportunities for
meaningful individual participation in political processes and gov-
ernance beyond retrospective voting. India’s party system has con-
tinued to largely be a top-down system, with party leaders at the
national level controlling selection of parliamentary candidates in
elections. In conceptualizing the ideal approach to enhancing
participation in democratic processes, it is crucial to identify and
understand the nature of obstacles to making participation
meaningful.
India’s embrace of a right to information regime has largely
been driven by a desire to rein in the twin evils of criminalization
and corruption in politics by promoting informed voting and par-
ticipation. Enhancing the quality of public discourse and political
participation through the adoption of the positive rights par-
ticipatory model can help counter corruption and criminality in
politics in India. The role and influence of money has increased
dramatically in politics and elections in India, and in the 2014 elec-
tion, over 300 billion rupees (the equivalent of $5 billion dollars)
was spent in the national Lok Sabha elections in which Narendra
Modi’s BJP won a landslide victory at the polls.332 India’s political
system has also struggled with the challenges of the criminalization
of politics at levels that interfere with core notions of the rule of
law, responsiveness, and accountability.
In order to address the “influence gap” inherent in representa-
tive democracy, the participatory model can improve both the
331. The Indian model suggests that the right to information can be conceptualized
both in terms of speech (Article 19), as well as other core rights, including equality in
Article 14, and due process in Article 21. As S.P. Sathe has argued, this suggests two
dimensions of the right to information in India—a speech-based instrumental right to
facilitate expression and voting and an accountability-based conception that is actually
based on equality and due process that seeks to facilitate citizens’ ability to interact with
and ensure accountability from the state in its performance of its duties vis-à-vis citizens.
See DRÈZE & SEN, supra note 17, at 81–82, 86, 88–91, 94–99, 250–51. R
332. Sruthi Gottipati & Rajesh Kumar Singh, India Set to Challenge U.S. for Election-Spend-
ing Record, REUTERS (Mar. 9, 2014), http://in.reuters.com/article/2014/03/09/india-
election-spending-idINDEEA2804B20140309.
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 60 11-JAN-16 16:01
informed voting, and expand the scope and power of civil society
institutions and social movements by leveling the playing field
through equalized informational access. Furthermore, opposi-
tional state actors can help bolster social movements and civil soci-
ety groups with the resources necessary to promote accountability
in elections and governance.346
Effectuating a positive-rights participatory model in developing
democracies like India can help the state achieve what this Article
refers to as “participatory equilibrium”—the proper balance
between the role of the state, and the role of civil society in effectu-
ating democratic participation.347 The positive-rights participatory
model can help enhance participation by reforming discursive
democracy by increasing autonomy and access to the public
sphere, “scaling up” grassroots participation to magnify the impact
of social movements and mass participation, and “pushing down”
national governance to the local level through participatory
democracy reforms.348
Challenges still remain to the full effectuation of participatory
parity, and deeply embedded social and economic inequality con-
strains the possibility of democratization in India. Implementation
of the right to information and transparency regimes must be
accompanied by efforts by the state and civil society to ameliorate
social and economic inequality to allow for meaningful participa-
tion in governance. In addition, the Supreme Court, political par-
ties, government agencies, and other institutions continue to resist
compliance with the right to information regime, and structural
problems like corruption, criminality, and patronage politics have
arguably narrowed the scope of actual differences in the agendas
of parties. These prevailing issues suggest the need for bolstering
“internal accountability” institutions that enforce anti-corruption
and anti-criminality norms within the political structure such as the
Lokpal, as well as bolstering civil society groups and social move-
346. See JEAN COHEN & ANDREW ARATO, CIVIL SOCIETY AND POLITICAL THEORY 19
(Thomas McCarthy ed., 1992); see also Mark Tushnet, The Constitution of Civil Society, 75
CHI.-KENT L. REV. 379 (2000). Cf. JONATHAN ISHAM, THOMAS KELLY, SUNDER RAMASWAMY
SOCIAL CAPITAL AND ECONOMIC DEVELOPMENT: WELL-BEING IN DEVELOPING COUNTRIES
(2002).
347. Participatory equilibrium is a concept distinct from the concept of “democratic
equilibrium” developed by Adam Przeworski. See generally Adam Przeworski, Democracy as
an Equilibrium, 123 PUBLIC CHOICE 253 (2005).
348. See Heather Gerken, Federalism as the New Nationalism: An Overview, 123 YALE L.J.
1626 (2013) (proposing reforms that push governance and decision-making process to the
state and local level); Archon Fung & Erik Olin Wright, Deepening Democracy: Innovations in
Empowered Participatory Governance, 29 POL. & SOC’Y 5 (2001).
\\jciprod01\productn\J\JLE\48-2\JLE203.txt unknown Seq: 64 11-JAN-16 16:01
349. See generally Mitu Sengupta, Anna Hazare’s Anti-Corruption Movement and the Limits of
Mass Mobilization in India, 13 SOCIAL MOVEMENT STUD. 406, 406–08 (2014) (discussing
Hazare’s social movement to establish a Lokpal in India).