Webber - Rethinking Existentialsim Chapter 1
Webber - Rethinking Existentialsim Chapter 1
Webber - Rethinking Existentialsim Chapter 1
Rethinking Existentialism
Jonathan Webber
What Is Existentialism?
Jonathan Webber
DOI:10.1093/oso/9780198735908.003.0001
When the term ‘existentialism’ became popular across the arts and culture of the
Western world in the aftermath of the Second World War, it was defined by its
most prominent exponents as a substantive philosophical position. But articles
and books on existentialism written in English ever since have eschewed precise
philosophical definition, instead identifying it loosely as a movement of thinkers
concerned with certain questions and to some extent providing similar answers.
These works disagree over which questions and which thinkers to include, which
makes it difficult to see why there is thought to be any genuine movement here
at all. Categorizing diverse thinkers together in this way, moreover, has distorted
the reception of their ideas by foregrounding superficial similarities at the
expense of deeper disagreements and features that do not easily fit this
Page 1 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (oxford.universitypressscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press,
2021. All Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: Newcastle University; date: 24 January 2021
What Is Existentialism?
Although there are good historical reasons for this divergence of writings about
existentialism from the substantive philosophical definition set out at its
inception, these reasons do not provide any theoretical justification for
preserving this divergence. In this book, we will recover and delineate a sharper
and more fruitful understanding of existentialism by returning to that original
definition and using it to analyse the works it describes. This allows us to
identify a range of new contributions that classical existentialism can make to
the theoretical models currently being developed and deployed in social
psychology, philosophy of mind, moral philosophy, cultural theory, and
psychotherapy, and conversely to release the potential for each of these areas of
inquiry to enrich one another by refining this existentialist perspective.
Page 2 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (oxford.universitypressscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press,
2021. All Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: Newcastle University; date: 24 January 2021
What Is Existentialism?
existentialists whether God exists (EH: 20, 27–30, 53–4). Beauvoir’s article is
more (p.3) carefully considered and composed. But it was overshadowed by
Sartre’s lecture, partly because Sartre was already a major literary and
philosophical figure by the time it was delivered whereas Beauvoir was not yet.
Sartre’s use of a series of memorable images and phrases is perhaps also why
his lecture had the greater impact. His slogan ‘existence precedes essence’ is
intended to convey the idea that a human being has no inbuilt essence, no innate
or fixed personality, but instead creates their essence, or their character and
outlook, through the values and projects they choose to adopt (EH: 22).
Beauvoir, by contrast, presents the same claim without any handy soundbite to
summarize it (EPW: 211–13). Sartre’s slogan, however, can seem paradoxical.
For if this is indeed the defining feature of human being, then it might seem to
be an essence that already defines any person prior to their adopting any values
or projects. It seems contradictory, moreover, to claim that any qualities of a
person resulting from their own undertakings could be essential to that person,
given that the person is thereby claimed to have existed without those qualities.
Page 3 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (oxford.universitypressscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press,
2021. All Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: Newcastle University; date: 24 January 2021
What Is Existentialism?
aspects of that person, so could have been adopted by that individual and could
later change.
Sartre makes it clear that his view that people do not have inbuilt essences, in
this sense of the term, entails that there is no such thing as human nature, no
inbuilt essence common among people. Humans are neither inherently selfish
nor inherently altruistic, for example. This contrasts sharply with the view of
human existence that Albert Camus develops in his philosophical and literary
writings. Camus is often classified as an existentialist despite explicitly refusing
the label in a newspaper interview during the existentialist offensive, declaring
that ‘Sartre and I hold nothing in common and refuse to be held responsible for
one another’s debts’ (IJD: 345). ‘The whole effort of German thought has been to
substitute for the notion of human nature that of human situation’, he wrote in
his notebooks soon afterwards, and ‘existentialism carries that effort even
further’, whereas ‘like the Greeks I believe in nature’ (CN: 136). Indeed, as we
will see in Chapter 2, he was already developing a theory of human nature and
its grounding of ethical value profoundly opposed to existentialism before he
even met Sartre and Beauvoir and well before the existentialist offensive.
Page 4 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (oxford.universitypressscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press,
2021. All Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: Newcastle University; date: 24 January 2021
What Is Existentialism?
central characters to their shared life project. Beauvoir holds that freedom
consists in the ability to commit to projects that shape one’s outlook and that
sedimentation is essential to such commitment. She recognizes that projects can
become so embedded that they can be difficult to overcome, but her position
does entail the ongoing freedom to alter or reject any project through the
sedimentation of new values.
Since existentialism is defined by the idea that existence precedes essence, the
idea that we have freedom over the values that organize our experience and so
shape our behaviour, Merleau-Ponty’s rejection of this theory of freedom means
that he is not an existentialist, despite his commitment to the philosophical
methodology of phenomenology that drives both Beauvoir’s and Sartre’s forms
Page 5 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (oxford.universitypressscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press,
2021. All Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: Newcastle University; date: 24 January 2021
What Is Existentialism?
However, once we have understood what Sartre means by the claim that
‘existence precedes essence’ it becomes clear that his analysis of the structures
of human being requires some theory of the essential structures of the mind.
Sartre does tend to avoid using the term ‘mind’, which carries connotations of
an inner realm distinct from the world (see e.g. IPPI: 5–7). But the structures of
consciousness, perception, imagination, affectivity, deliberation, and rational
motivation are central to his analysis of human being. Beauvoir’s publications of
the 1940s are likewise replete with theories of desire, emotion, perception, and
motivation. Since a person’s ‘essence’, in Sartre’s famous slogan, is the overall
structural property that explains their behaviour, it must organize the
experience of the world that motivates that behaviour. Moreover, since this (p.
8) essence consists in the person’s projects, which have values at their core, the
claimed freedom over this essence must consist in their ability to alter the values
that structure their experience of the world. The central ontological claim of
existentialism therefore requires a model of psychological functioning, with the
Page 6 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (oxford.universitypressscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press,
2021. All Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: Newcastle University; date: 24 January 2021
What Is Existentialism?
The reason Heidegger gave for rejecting the label ‘existentialist’ was that the
terms ‘existentia’ and ‘essentia’ carry metaphysical connotations that derail any
serious attempt to think clearly about the ontology of human being or about
being in general, so the slogan ‘existence precedes essence’ must be rejected
(LH: 157–8). This does not reflect the outlook of Being and Time, however, which
was written two decades earlier. In that book, Heidegger does proclaim ‘the
priority of “existentia” over “essentia”’ (B&T: § 9). The resemblance between
this phrase and Sartre’s slogan is part of the reason why Heidegger is often
classified as an existentialist. But this resemblance is merely superficial.
Heidegger is not using ‘essentia’ here in the Aristotelian sense that Sartre uses
‘essence’. Rather, he means the properties necessary for something to be a
member of a specific kind: to be the kind of thing that we are is to have a
specific kind of existence, which he then describes as structured by concern
about one’s own existence. Heidegger’s phrase, therefore, is not a claim about
the motivations behind an individual’s behaviour and so does not commit him to
a model of psychological functioning.
(p.9) But this relation between existentialism and Freudian psychoanalysis has
also been obscured by the tendency of French philosophers from the 1950s
onwards to endorse the broad Freudian tradition while exaggerating the
distance between their own positions and existentialism (Crowell 2012: 11–13).
Together with the absence of Freud from lists of existentialist thinkers, this has
led to existentialism being understood as an entirely separate intellectual
tradition that provides an alternative to psychoanalysis. Beauvoir and Sartre in
fact both preserve much that they find valuable in Freud’s work. Their objection
is only to his theories of the structure of the mind, which they argue are
incoherent and fail to explain the phenomena they are designed to explain. Their
Page 7 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (oxford.universitypressscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press,
2021. All Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: Newcastle University; date: 24 January 2021
What Is Existentialism?
Page 8 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (oxford.universitypressscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press,
2021. All Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: Newcastle University; date: 24 January 2021
What Is Existentialism?
and Jew, written at the time of the existentialist offensive. The central values of
Jewish culture, he argues in that book, are a response to a climate of anti-
Semitic hostility. This hostility takes the form of a thoroughly negative image of a
fixed Jewish personality. The authentic response of affirming one’s own freedom
is rare, argues Sartre, though he does not say why. The usual response, he
thinks, is to affirm fixed personality traits that are contrary to the anti-Semite’s
image of Jewishness. This is a form of bad faith, since it asserts a fixed
personality. The values common among Jewish people, argues Sartre, are those
endorsed as though they were a fixed Jewish nature, the values that are directly
contrary to the anti-Semite’s image of Jewish people.
Much has been written about the shortcomings of this as a theory of the origins
of Jewish culture, or indeed of any culture. One central failure of the theory is
indicative of a deep problem with Sartre’s initial form of existentialism. This is
the failure to explain why authenticity is rare and bad faith is widespread. After
all, if this is true then it too is a cultural phenomenon that stands in need of
explanation and Sartre’s theory has (p.11) no resources to explain it. Sartre’s
initial form of existentialism can ground a cultural theory, therefore, only on the
basis of this unexplainable coincidence. It seems to be for this reason, as we will
see in Chapter 7, that Sartre soon abandoned his initial form of existentialism
and adopted Beauvoir’s theory of the sedimentation of projects. By the time he
wrote Saint Genet, first published in 1952, he had accepted her view that
projects increase in inertia and influence as they continue to be endorsed. This
is the theory he employs to explain the formation of Genet’s character and
aesthetic taste.
In the same year, Frantz Fanon published his Black Skin, White Masks, which
argues that racial identity is formed through the sedimentation of projects, that
there are no genuinely fixed personality traits of individuals, and that the
problems of racism can be overcome only by gradually overcoming those
sedimented projects and removing the social structures conducive to them. This
is, as we will see in Chapter 8, a profoundly existentialist work. Fanon’s theory of
racialization has much in common with Beauvoir’s theory of gender. Fanon does
not seem to have read Beauvoir, but does develop his theory through critical
analysis of Sartre’s initial form of existentialism, alongside many other
influences. We should accept, therefore, that this theory common to Beauvoir,
Sartre, and Fanon in 1952, according to which an individual’s Aristotelian
essence is formed through the sedimentation of their projects chosen in their
specific social environment, is the canonical form of the theory that existence
precedes essence.
Page 9 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (oxford.universitypressscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press,
2021. All Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: Newcastle University; date: 24 January 2021
What Is Existentialism?
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (oxford.universitypressscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press,
2021. All Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: Newcastle University; date: 24 January 2021
What Is Existentialism?
Beauvoir does argue for the strictly moral imperative to recognize and respect
the structure of human existence irrespective of our prior commitments across
her short book Pyrrhus and Cineas, published in 1944. Her argument aims to
derive this imperative from the structure of human existence itself. In this
regard, it resembles Immanuel Kant’s argument across his Groundwork for the
Metaphysics of Morals that the structure of human agency entails the imperative
to treat human agency itself as objectively valuable. Beauvoir’s argument,
however, does not rely on the conception of rationality or the related
metaphysical system that Kant’s argument relies on. Instead, her argument aims
to derive the imperative of authenticity from an opening premise which,
according to the theory that existence precedes essence, everyone must accept.
This is the premise that some ends are valuable. Beauvoir’s sophisticated
argument cannot be summarized easily. But, as we will see in Chapter 10, it
deserves serious consideration in contemporary moral philosophy. That it has
not been identified before is perhaps partly due to the (p.14) tendency to read
thinkers classified as ‘existentialist’ focusing on their perceived shared interests
and ideas while Kant is not included in that classification.
Page 11 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (oxford.universitypressscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press,
2021. All Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: Newcastle University; date: 24 January 2021
What Is Existentialism?
As we have already seen, this requires excluding Heidegger and Camus from the
category of existentialist thinkers. Since these two are almost always included in
that category despite their protestations, this might seem unacceptably
revisionary. We should first consider, however, exactly why they were included in
the loosely identified category of existentialism in the first place. It seems that
there were two pressures that led to existentialism being defined in that way.
One is that Beauvoir and Sartre began the trend of classifying other thinkers as
existentialists despite those other thinkers never having identified themselves as
such. Beauvoir and Sartre did this, moreover, in the very works in which they
defined existentialism during the existentialist offensive. Beauvoir cites Camus
approvingly, for example, though stops short of explicitly calling him an
existentialist (EPW: 209; see also P&C: 92–3). Sartre does explicitly classify
Heidegger as an existentialist (EH: 20).
(p.15) The other pressure was the general hostility to European thought in
post-war anglophone philosophy (Barrett 1958: ch. 1). At the same time,
existentialism enjoyed huge cultural popularity (McBride 2012). In this climate,
categorizing diverse European thinkers together in courses entitled
‘existentialism’ was an important strategy for getting their works analysed and
applied at all. Two anthologies set the curriculum for such courses. Walter
Kaufman’s introduction to his anthology described existentialism as ‘not a
philosophy but a label for a set of widely differing revolts against philosophy’
and ‘not a school of thought nor reducible to any set of tenets’ (1956: 11).
Robert Solomon ended the introduction to his anthology by claiming that
‘nothing could be further from the existential attitude than attempts to define
existentialism, except perhaps a discussion about the attempts to define
existentialism’ (1974: xix). These comments might appear to disavow any unity
to each anthology, but they only strictly deny any shared substantive claims or
theoretical methods.3
What these anthologies gather together are works with a certain set of
philosophical interests, ones that were being sidelined by anglophone philosophy
in those decades. The same set of philosophical interests justifies Beauvoir and
Page 12 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (oxford.universitypressscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press,
2021. All Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: Newcastle University; date: 24 January 2021
What Is Existentialism?
Page 13 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (oxford.universitypressscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press,
2021. All Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: Newcastle University; date: 24 January 2021
What Is Existentialism?
This rethinking also brings into clearer view the status of existentialism as an
ethical theory. For ethics is not an essential aspect of existential philosophy
itself. Iris Murdoch’s comment that Sartre’s biography of Genet is a work of
ethics in ‘paradoxical guise’ is instructive (1957: 676). For this is paradoxical
only if we expect ethics to provide moral constraints and prescriptions. We
would then be at least surprised to find a work on ethics detailing the life of a
professional thief. But as the broader concern with how best to live, ethics
necessarily involves clarification of how people develop the commitments,
preferences, tastes, and other characteristics that shape their lives. The
development of existentialist psychoanalysis is therefore integral to the ethical
programme of existentialism. But this does not mean that existentialism eschews
the idea of morality. Focusing on the works of Beauvoir and Sartre of this era as
equally expressive of existentialism allows us to see that Sartre’s comments in
Existentialism Is A Humanism endorsing an imperative of authenticity that does
not reflect any of his own works are best understood as referring to the Kantian
moral argument of Beauvoir’s Pyrrhus and Cineas, published the previous year.
Page 14 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (oxford.universitypressscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press,
2021. All Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: Newcastle University; date: 24 January 2021
What Is Existentialism?
For this reason, the analysis of existentialism across this book is resolutely
philosophical rather than historical or biographical. It is concerned with
identifying and assessing the philosophical arguments published across a ten-
year period, 1942–52. These analyses will show why Camus and Merleau-Ponty
are not existentialists, though they are both existential thinkers, and will thereby
clarify existentialism itself and identify the deep reasons for the bitter political
disputes that famously ended each of their friendships with Beauvoir and Sartre.
These chapters will clarify the Freudian influence on existentialism, the reasons
why Sartre abandoned his initial version of existentialism in favour of
Beauvoir’s, and the underlying existentialist unity of Fanon’s analysis of
racialization. They will identify existentialism’s central eudaimonist arguments
for the virtue of authenticity and their limitations before detailing Beauvoir’s
argument for a categorical moral imperative of authenticity. These analyses have
all already been sketched in this chapter. But their details are essential if they
are to make significant contributions to current debates about ethics and the
mind. So they are articulated more precisely across the next nine chapters,
before a final chapter indicates some potential contributions they could make to
current thought.
Notes:
(1) Works by Beauvoir, Camus, Fanon, Freud, Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, and
Sartre are indicated by title abbreviations rather than dates, to avoid confusion
between first publication and edition used. Full details are given in the
Bibliography by surname and abbreviation, listed for each author in order of first
publication. All other works are cited in the usual way, by publication date of
edition used.
(2) Throughout this book, I use the term ‘metaphysical’ interchangeably with
‘ontological’ to describe anything pertaining to the structures of being. Thus,
metaphysical freedom is the freedom that existentialists consider human agents
to have over their own being, their ability to shape their own essence. This is
despite the distinction that Sartre draws towards the end of Being and
Nothingness between ‘ontology’ as the analysis of the structures of being and
‘metaphysics’ as the study of the aetiology of those ontological structures, a
Page 15 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (oxford.universitypressscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press,
2021. All Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: Newcastle University; date: 24 January 2021
What Is Existentialism?
study which he declares that he has not undertaken (B&N: 639). So far as I
know, Sartre’s definition of ‘metaphysics’ here is entirely idiosyncratic. My use
in this book is normal in contemporary anglophone philosophy.
(3) The anthologies cement an already existing tendency, which had been begun
by Beauvoir and Sartre in referring to other thinkers in their descriptions of
existentialism (see e.g. Blackham 1952). Their editors’ comments are then
echoed in the ideas that existentialism is defined by ‘opposition to the
philosophical tradition’ (Dreyfus 2006: 137), cannot be clearly and objectively
defined because it is opposed to the traditional philosophical aim of providing
such definitions (Macquarrie 1972: 13; Earnshaw 2006: 1–2), comprises no
substantive tenets but only a set of interactions between thinkers addressing
certain concerns (Grimsley 1960: 1–11; Reynolds 2006: 2–3), and can be
understood only as a ‘family resemblance’ category (Warnock 1967: 1–2;
Macquarrie 1972: 14–18; Flynn 2006: 8; Joseph et al. 2011: 3–4). David E.
Cooper offers a rare substantive definition of existentialism as those
philosophical views of Heidegger and Sartre found regularly among the
existentialist family (1990: 6–10; 2012: 28–30). All these characterizations result
in some way from attempting to discern common ideas of thinkers already
identified as existentialists. If the arguments of this book are right, there is now
much to be gained by distinguishing the broad existential inquiry in which these
thinkers are all engaged from the substantive theory that provided the original
definition of existentialism.
(4) Heidegger did not invent this restricted concept of existence. Søren
Kierkegaard had used the Danish word ‘existenz’ in this way almost a century
earlier. Karl Jaspers had used the term in a related way, to label the kind of
being that he recommends that we adopt, a few years before Heidegger
published Being and Time. But neither Kierkegaard nor Jaspers was particularly
influential on European thought until after Heidegger had established the idea
of existential philosophy.
(5) Jeff Malpas (2012: 293) also argues that we should distinguish between
‘existential’ and ‘existentialist’. But he assumes that ‘existential’ should be used
in its ordinary English sense, which pertains to anything at all that there is,
instead of identifying the specific meaning with which it is used by Kierkegaard
and Heidegger. As a result, he uses ‘existentialist’ to refer to the concern with
the structures of human existence, leaving him with no term for the substantive
ethical theory that Beauvoir and Sartre articulated as the original definition of
‘existentialism’.
(6) Two further influences on this aspect of existentialism that have been
occluded by the focus on the loose category of existential thought are ancient
Stoicism and seventeenth-century French philosophy. Beauvoir and Sartre both
cite Stoic philosophers regularly. In a magazine portrait of Sartre published as
Page 16 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (oxford.universitypressscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press,
2021. All Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: Newcastle University; date: 24 January 2021
What Is Existentialism?
Page 17 of 17
PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (oxford.universitypressscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press,
2021. All Rights Reserved. An individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of a monograph in OSO for personal use.
Subscriber: Newcastle University; date: 24 January 2021