The Brain's Sense of Movement - Alan Berthoz
The Brain's Sense of Movement - Alan Berthoz
The Brain's Sense of Movement - Alan Berthoz
Stephen M. Kosslyn
general editor
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
Alain Berthoz
Translated by Giselle Weiss
Berthoz, A.
[Sens du Mouvement. English]
The brain’s sense of movement / Alain Berthoz ; translated by Giselle Weiss.
p. cm. — (Perspectives in cognitive neuroscience)
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 0-674-80109-1 (cloth)
ISBN 0-674-00980-0 (paper)
1. Motion perception (Vision) 2. Orientation (Physiology)
3. Proprioception. 4. Brain. 5. Neuropsychology.
I. Title. II. Series.
QP493 .B47 2000
612.8⬘2—dc21 00-023758
FOREWORD TO THE AMERICAN EDITION
This book was published in 1997. Science moves fast, and many new ideas and
observations have emerged in the intervening time. Yet the ideas proposed in
this book have, if anything, been reinforced by recent knowledge about the
brain. I did not think it useful to revise all the references, but I have included a
number of papers published by our laboratory or close collaborators since
1997. I have also included a number of reviews from 1998 and 1999 in which
the reader will find more general recent references.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
I would like to thank Odile Jacob, who agreed to publish the French edition of
this book at the suggestion of Jean-Pierre Changeux and who saw it through
production with the combination of keen intuition and professionalism that is
her trademark.
Mountain climbers need a guide. Writing a book is a little like climbing a
mountain. The guide knows the way to the top, avoiding loose rocks and haz-
ardous trails. He knows the moods of the mountain and its traditions. He
keeps everyone on course, makes detours when needed, sets the pace, and
transforms the climb step by step into a rewarding human adventure. My edi-
torial guide for this book was Gérard Jorland. The breadth of his knowledge as
a philosopher and historian, his generosity, his trust, and his critical comments
helped me, encouraged me, and touched me.
Maya, you accompanied this book. In form as well as in substance, you
helped me to make it not only readable but understandable.
The work of our laboratory would not have been possible without the
support of the Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique (CNRS), the Cen-
tre National d’Etudes Spatiales (CNES), and the Collège de France, which
managed simultaneously to have faith in us, to rigorously evaluate our work,
and to tolerate the gambles that are necessary for new ideas to emerge.
I would also like to thank the people who willingly read parts of the
manuscript, my friends and colleagues Pierre Buisseret, Valérie Cornilleau-
Pérès, Jacques Droulez, Jean-René Duhamel, Werner Graf, Alexej Grantyn,
Isabelle Israël, Joseph McIntyre, Edmund Rolls, Jean-Michel Roy, Jean-Jacques
Slotine, Yves Trotter, Pierre-Paul Vidal, Paolo Viviani, Sidney Wiener, as well
as our entire laboratory team, who carried out the experiments described
here.
I am grateful to the journal La Recherche for permission to reproduce a
portion of the text and illustrations that appeared in a special issue on the
brain in 1996.
I am also grateful to Solange Fanjat de Saint Font for editorial help and for
assembling the bibliography. Her expertise was critical in bringing this difficult
project to completion. And last but not least, I thank Frédéric Lacloche, whose
computer graphics skill I admire. He adapted the illustrations.
Finally, I am most grateful to Giselle Weiss who translated this book in
English with remarkable speed, exceptional insight into what I wanted to say,
and a wide and deep culture, which has earned my admiration. My gratitude
also extends to the team at Harvard University Press for the thorough profes-
sionalism with which they handled this project.
The translator is deeply indebted to Greer Ilene Gilman and Barbara Breasted
Whitesides for editorial and research assistance.
viii •
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
CONTENTS
introduction
Building Coherence
How Vision Detects Movement
Visual Movement and Vestibular Receptors
Am I in my Bed or Hanging from the Ceiling?
The Coherence between Seeing and Hearing
The Problem of the Coherence and Unity of Perception
Autism: The Disintegration of Coherence?
Frames of Reference
Personal Space and Extrapersonal Space
Egocentric and Allocentric Frames of Reference
Natural Frames of Reference
Selecting Frames of Reference
Capture
The Toad’s Decision
The Art of Braking
What If Newton Had Wanted to Catch the Apple?
x •
CONTENTS
Imagined Movement and Actual Movement
Dynamic Memory and Predictive Control of Movements
Was Piaget Right?
Balance
A Physiology of Reaction
How to Make the University of Edinburgh Oscillate
Toward a Projective Physiology
Adaptation
Adaptation and Substitution
The Rheumatologist and the Ophthalmologist
The Role of Activity in Compensating for and Preventing Disorientation
Notes 269
Works Cited
Credits
Index
CONTENTS •
xi
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
INTRODUCTION
Irish storytellers always begin this way: “It was not in my time, not in your
time, not in anybody’s time.” The story I am about to tell also belongs to no
time because it relates to the greatest mystery of all time: the brain.
This book is a reflection on how the brain works, based on the idea that
the brain is used to predict the future, to anticipate the consequences of action
(its own or that of others), and to save time. To this end, very diverse biologi-
cal mechanisms developed over the course of evolution: the architecture of
the skeleton, the subtle properties of sensory receptors, and the marvelous
complexity of the central nervous system. These mechanisms endowed the
brain with internal models of the world and of the body—not just any mod-
els, but models that reflect the laws of nature, the Umwelt of each species, to
use Uexküll’s term, and that ensure the survival of each animal.1 The brain is
not a reactive machine; it is a proactive machine that investigates the world.
To become a ski champion, it is not enough for the skier to continuously pro-
cess sensory cues and correct his trajectory; he must go over the run in his
mind, anticipate its stages and the state of his sensory receptors, foresee possi-
ble solutions to every error, take chances and make decisions before he makes
a move.
Our ability to understand the brain and cognition is of course limited, but
it is not for lack of trying. First we must consider the question of how the
brain relates to the mind. At a recent meeting on the subject of cognition and
geometry that brought together mathematicians, physicists, physiologists, and
philosophers, one participant, a philosopher, suddenly lost his temper, ex-
claiming angrily: “I don’t even want to hear what physiologists have to say, be-
cause brains are just bloody things that I see at the local butcher shop!” This
outburst would be a suitable epigraph for an anthology on militant dualism. It
shows that we still have a long way to go to persuade even the most eminent
thinkers that cognition is a property arising from the amazing complexity of
the brain.
I think that we are partially responsible for prejudices like those the philos-
opher and mathematician Châtelet exposes when he writes:
Typically it seems as though the work of science is limited to maintain-
ing knowledge, ignoring the contributions of those who further that
knowledge and disseminate it. But these are the very people who rescue
science from the burden of endless accumulation and stratification, the
fatuity of established ideas, the convenience of expediency, and, finally,
the temptation to seek refuge in rules. They demonstrate how urgently
we need to construct a genuine theory of the way information is pro-
cessed and to learn about learning. Such reasoning is of course the an-
tithesis of a neural barbarism that is stubbornly dedicated to hunting
down the neuronal basis of thought and that confuses the activity of
learning with the fruits of learning, that is, knowledge. Schelling saw
this more clearly: he knew that, in any event, thought was not encapsu-
lated in a brain, that it could be anywhere . . . outside . . . in the morn-
ing dew.2
Despite Faust’s warning that “in the beginning was the Deed,” many read only
the first line of Goethe’s poem and still believe that “in the beginning was the
word.” Through an understandable fascination, it was actually believed for
twenty years that understanding language, an attribute specific to humans,
would enable us to understand cognitive function. This belief, reinforced by
the influence of several groups in the eastern United States who have pro-
moted the idea that the brain is a computer, led to a symbolic and computa-
tional conceptualization of the nervous system.
The American functionalist school and some of its European adherents
defend a cognitive psychology that maintains in principle that the higher func-
tions of the brain must be studied without any reference whatsoever to their
neural underpinnings. These functions may be emergent or dissociated, but in
4 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
the end they are viewed merely as superstructure. We have probably not heard
the last of the dualist tendencies.
This risk was brilliantly exposed by Kant:
Misled . . . by such a proof of the power of reason, the demand for the
extension of knowledge recognises no limits. The light dove, cleaving
the air in her free flight, and feeling its resistance, might imagine that its
flight would be still easier in empty space. It was thus that Plato left the
world of the senses, as setting too narrow limits to . . . the understand-
ing, and ventured out beyond it on the wings of the ideas, in the empty
space of the pure understanding. He did not observe that with all his ef-
forts he made no advance—meeting no resistance that might, as it
were, serve as a support upon which he could take a stand, to which
he could apply his powers, and so set his understanding in motion. It
is, indeed, the common fate of human reason to complete its specula-
tive structures as speedily as may be, and only afterwards to enquire
whether the foundations are reliable.4
Plato forgot the body. This book is an apology for the body.
I will proceed in the following way. First I will lead you on a walk through
the land of the senses. In addition to the receptors that make up the usual five
senses—vision, smell, hearing, touch, and taste—we must identify several oth-
ers, those of the muscles, joints, and inner ear. In fact, we do not have only
five senses, but eight or nine. Is there any point in listing them?
Not at all, because the brain does not process sensory cues independently.
Each time it commits to an action, it makes assumptions about the state of
certain receptors as the action unfolds. The ski champion cannot constantly be
checking the state of all his sensory receptors; he mentally simulates the
course of his run down the slope, and it is only from time to time, intermit-
tently, that his brain checks to see whether the state of certain sensory recep-
tors is in accordance with its prediction of the angle of the knees, the distance
from the ski poles, and so on. These groupings of receptors are called configu-
rations, and it appears that the brain checks configurations of specific recep-
tors as it plans movement.
With that in mind, I will define all the sensory receptors that enable us to
analyze movement in space. These receptors are collectively responsible for
what is called the sense of movement, or kinesthesia. Kinesthesia is the result
of cooperation among several sensors, and it requires the brain to coherently
reconstruct movement in the body and in the environment. When this coher-
ence cannot be achieved, perceptual and motor disturbances result, as well as
INTRODUCTION •
5
illusions, which are actually solutions the brain devises to deal with discrepan-
cies between sensory information and its internal preperceptions.
Next I will examine how the brain uses memory to predict the conse-
quences of action. An especially interesting example is that of episodic mem-
ory and working memory. Various mechanisms enable the brain to preserve
the traces of recent events, to combine motor and sensory signals, and to rep-
resent the required process for accomplishing a move or attaining a goal.
Having completed this ramble through the land of the senses and the
mechanisms of perception, I will ask the reader to make a special effort to
consider a fundamental aspect of the relationships between perception and ac-
tion: the mechanical properties of bodily masses. Indeed, it is impossible to
understand anything about how the brain works without conceding that its
main problem is to put mass into motion. Instead of saying “mass,” one might
say “inertial moment,” or the considerable, complex forces that arise as soon
as a mass is in motion, like the Coriolis forces created by three-dimensional
movements of the head, the resultant of angular accelerations in several
planes. The Russian physiologist Bernstein drew attention to the fact that in
animals and in man, the limbs have enormous “degrees of freedom,” and con-
sequently nature has had to find tricks to simplify the work of the brain. Study
of the geometry of movements helps to grasp the natural solutions devised by
the nervous system to solve this problem. Skeletal anatomy can be explained
in this context; moreover, prewiring motor synergies is another way of simpli-
fying neurocomputation, and simple kinematic relationships connect the ge-
ometry of movement and dynamics.
After examining these aspects of perception and movement, I will offer a
few concrete examples of motor organization in connection with locomotion,
gaze orientation, and control of balance. I will consider how neural mecha-
nisms and internal models enable prediction, how preselection of sensory
messages is carried out, and especially what the fundamental role of synaptic
inhibition and simultaneous parallel and hierarchical processing is. I will exam-
ine how the same structures can be activated in both executed and imagined
movement and, in the case of damage or of sensory conflict, how the brain in-
vents new solutions to restore functional plasticity.
In short, I present a theory one step ahead of those that consider the brain
to be a simple proactive or representational organ. I suggest that the brain is a
biological simulator that predicts by drawing on memory and making assump-
tions. Flight simulators neither predict nor invent. The brain has a need to cre-
ate; it is an inventive simulator that forecasts future events. It also acts to emu-
late reality.
6 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
I finish with a tirade against architects who have abandoned the brain’s in-
stincts and preferences in favor of their new idols: uniformity, profitability, and
the tyranny of the right angle. They have forsaken all sense of finesse for a
geometric approach of unparalleled mediocrity.
My scientific tool will be physiology. It is necessarily multidisciplinary, be-
cause it involves both structure and function. In the compelling words of
Bergson, whose seductive dualism will be challenged several times in these
pages,
A final word: I will not talk much about emotion in this book, except in
the chapter where I briefly examine the problem of decision making in the
context of a theory of Damasio. And yet, there is no perception of space or
movement, no vertigo or loss of balance, no caress given or received, no
sound heard or uttered, no gesture of capture or grasping that is not accompa-
nied by emotion or induced by it. But it is necessary to construct a physiology
of relationships between movement and emotion, as Ribot suggested:
What are called agreeable or painful states only constitute the super-
ficial part of the life of feeling, of which the deep element consists in
tendencies, appetites, needs, desires, translated into movements. Most
classical treatises (and even some others) say that sensibility is the fac-
ulty of experiencing pleasure and pain. I should say, using the same ter-
INTRODUCTION •
7
minology, that sensibility is the faculty of tending or desiring, and conse-
quently of experiencing pleasure and pain. There is nothing mysterious
in the tendency; it is a movement or an arrest of movement in the na-
scent stage. I employ this word “tendency” as synonymous with needs,
appetites, instincts, inclinations, desires; it is the generic term of which
the others are varieties; it has the advantage over them of embracing at
the same time both the psychological and physiological aspects of the
phenomenon.6
8 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
1
P E R C E P T I O N I S S I M U L AT E D A C T I O N
Our sensations are purely passive, while all our perceptions or ideas are born
out of an active principle which judges.
—J.-J. Rousseau
A major theme of this book is that perception is more than just the interpreta-
tion of sensory messages. Perception is constrained by action; it is an internal
simulation of action. It is judgment and decision making, and it is anticipation
of the consequences of action. This is not an entirely new concept, as a
glimpse at some of the ideas that prefigured it will show. There are so many
theories of perception that I will not try to cover them all here. I wish simply
to provide a taste of what is in store.
A history of the motor theory of perception was recently published by
Viviani, who recalls that it was very fashionable before 1940.1 One of the first
modern works to signal the importance of movement in perception was that
of Lotze in 1852.2 His theory affirmed that spatial organization of visual sensa-
tions results from their integration with a muscular sense. The idea that the
information that triggers a motor command is used by the brain to recognize
movement was proposed by Helmholtz.3 For him, motor control operates by
comparing sensations with predictions based on the motor command. In 1890,
William James also described a neural circuit that anticipates the sensory con-
sequences of movement (Figure 1.1).4 A simple way of conceptualizing the
perception of movement, he proposed, would be to assume that a sensory cell
Motor neuron
M
S
K
“idea of movement”
10 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
us the action we associate with the armchair, which we call a perceptual
schema—here, the action of sitting in a particular way in the armchair.”9
Merleau-Ponty put it very well: “Vision is the brain’s way of touching.”10
Research on the physiological bases of the relationship between percep-
tion and action nevertheless remained limited until just recently. Viviani at-
tributes the post-1940 eclipse of the motor theory of perception to the ap-
pearance of the analytical neurophysiology of Sherrington, the influence of
Gestalt, and even to the constructivism of Piaget. The compartmentalization
of disciplines whose efforts should converge, such as biomechanics, experi-
mental and cognitive psychology, psychophysics, functional neurobiology, and
so on, were for a long time another obstacle that today the cognitive sciences
are attempting to overcome. After 1950, the motor theory of perception
was revived. For example, consider the work of Lashley, Gibson, the Teuber
school, and more particularly the work of Held and Hein on the role of action
(not just activity) in the development of the visual system. Or consider the
work of the psychologist Johansson in Scandinavia and that of Fessard and
Piéron in France—Piéron maintaining that perception is awareness of external
objects and events that give rise to sensations. In the 1970s the research groups
of Imbert and Jeannerod made major discoveries concerning the development
and functioning of the visual system and its relationship to the vestibular sys-
tem, the control of ocular movements and posture.
Though underrated in the West, the Russian Anokhin’s seminal ideas made
him a trailblazer.11 In his day, Pavlov’s theories and experiments on condi-
tioned reflexes, which profoundly influenced our century, were predominant.
But Anokhin found Pavlov’s definition of reflexes too limiting. He also criti-
cized Descartes for having sidestepped the question of the relevance of the
reflex response to the higher brain and thereby influenced future studies of
the complex adaptive actions of animals and man for years to come. Anokhin
introduced a key idea to the theory; that at the end of the reflex arc there is a
reflex action. Although Pavlov’s idea was already old, Western physiologists
ignored subsequent contributions of Russian physiologists for fifty years, ex-
cept to plagiarize their ideas without citing them—intellectual petty thievery
that the isolation of the Russians helped to disguise. Western physiologists
used the word “response” to refer to the effect of a stimulus in a reflex arc,
whereas the Soviet literature emphasized and still emphasizes the concept of
12 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
animal. Noting that he could as well have called his apparatus “the acceptor of
the afferent results of a completed reflex action,” Anokhin explained that he
had chosen the word “acceptor,” from the Latin acceptare, because it combined
two ideas: accept and approve. Consequently, he incorporated a clear role for
the acceptor of the result of action in decision processes. For example, if a
person sitting in the living room decides for one reason or another to go into
the dining room, at the precise moment of the decision, the set of afferents
from all the stimulatory cues he has received in the dining room in the past
(acceptor of action) is reproduced in his cerebral cortex. If, after the person
has entered the dining room, the cues coincide perfectly with what the accep-
tor of the result of action predicts, the person then moves on to the next ele-
ment of intended behavior. But if the acceptor of the result of action detects
an error, an incongruity with what is predicted, the brain produces an orienta-
tion reaction, as described in the Soviet literature—that is, it reacts by analyz-
ing new events.
Bernstein’s Comparator
Another master of modern physiology who had an even more profound influ-
ence on our generation was the Russian physiologist Bernstein. Persecuted for
his overly original ideas in the time of Pavlovian hegemony, he studied natural
movement and inferred general rules of cerebral functioning from it.12 To
avoid a naïve linear description of the regulation of the coordination of move-
ment as a succession of phases—prediction, preparation, execution, and con-
trol—Bernstein proposed a circular schema (Figure 1.2) that introduced the
concept of the action-perception cycle. The basic element is a “comparator”
that establishes the “required value.”
This required value fulfils at least three different functions, all equally im-
portant. The first is detecting an error between accomplished movement and
predicted movement that triggers a correction (from a cybernetic vantage).
The second is recognizing that an action has been accomplished, which allows
progression to the next action in sequence. “This aspect of function,” says
Bernstein, “is mainly reminiscent of what Anokhin has termed ‘sanctional
afferentation.’” The third function is the adaptation itself. Indeed, when action
encounters surprises, it is impossible, or irrelevant, for corrective impulses to
reestablish the initial plan of action. In this case, the receptor of information
acts as an initiator (and not as a regulator) of adaptive changes in the program
being executed. It does this by introducing either small technical changes into
CORRECTIONS ∆w
PROGRAM
6 4
REGULATOR Sw COMPARATOR
Iw
ENERGY
Iw
1
3
EFFECTOR
RECEPTOR
(muscle)
Sensory
receptor
INFORMATION
Locus of
activity
Figure 1.2. Schematic diagram showing the cerebral organization for control of
movement proposed by Bernstein.
14 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
the movement or taking an adjacent trajectory. And it does it until the pro-
gram has been completely reorganized, even down to the repertoire of con-
secutive elements and the staging of motor action—in other words, it adopts a
new tactical approach to the task.
I think that the highest cognitive functions are the result of an evolution-
ary thrust toward developing this ability to reorganize action according to un-
foreseen events. This ability requires developing a memory of the past, the
faculty for predicting and simulating the future, and the metafaculty, in a way,
to mobilize all these capabilities rapidly, because they must integrate with a
perception-action cycle that sometimes lasts only a tenth or twentieth of a
second.
For Bernstein, these corrective processes depend heavily on what he calls
the comparator. This neural device occupies a strategic position between the
information supplied by the receptors and the elements that will effect the
necessary corrections or reorganization. It does not function between two
successive or simultaneous receptors to compare two distinct events, but be-
tween flowing, continuous reception and an internal guide.
An important property of the comparator is its capacity to detect varia-
tions in sensory information owing to the central nervous system’s use of
fresh traces. Our bodies, says Bernstein, have no receptive apparatus capable
of perceiving velocity directly. This task is resolved in the central nervous sys-
tem by the comparator. It instantaneously compares the cues about the posi-
tion of the moving organ with the fresh trace of its position approximately 0.1
second before. The brain thus recognizes two positions with a certain interval
of time between them. So it can easily reconstruct the velocity, which is dis-
placement (the difference from one position to the other) divided by time.
Bernstein saw that the control of movement is not continuous but dis-
crete, under the control of the comparator. He arrived at this conclusion from
contemporary work that linked motor action with brain waves having a fre-
quency of 8 to 14 cycles per second—that is, α waves measured by electro-
encephalogram.13 This is, at least in part, the frequency of rhythmic oscilla-
tions of excitability for the principal elements of the reflex circuitry of our
motor apparatus. Bernstein regarded the intervals between each cycle at the α
rhythm as units of an internal physiological clock, or pacemaker.
Bernstein’s vision was prophetic, since it was not until 1990 that Llinás
suggested that movement is subtended by neural activity oscillating at 10 Hz
(ten oscillations per second).14 This suggestion remains viable, as it is possible
to observe synchronizations of 10 Hz in the neck muscles of an alert cat.
Movement may therefore be subtended by coupled oscillators that function at
PERCEPTION IS SIMULATED ACTION •
15
this frequency, as Bernstein foresaw. The work of Sokolov and his school in
Russia on the hippocampus,15 that of Rougeul-Buser in Paris, and of olfaction
and sleep specialists has also demonstrated the importance of these central
rhythms during various tasks that require alertness or organized movements.16
It seems clear now that several oscillatory processes with frequencies whose
values are 8 to 12 Hz, 16 Hz, 40 Hz, 70 to 90 Hz, and so on subtend the inter-
nal workings of perception and movement. Llinás summed up his ideas by
saying that “we think at 40 Hz and move at 10 Hz,” asserting laconically that
the minimum time to process mental data is of the order of 25 milliseconds,
and the minimum time for a motor control operation around 100 millisec-
onds. He proposed a theory that explains how the brain uses internal circuits
that oscillate forty times per second (40 Hz) to develop multisensory percep-
tion and guarantee its coherence (Figure 1.3).
Bernstein completes his analysis of the microfunction of the perception-
action cycle with more general considerations of the role of anticipation. He
observes that in fact a wide range of movements anticipate or extrapolate by
analyzing fresh traces of the past. I will offer many examples of these neural
memories, within the cell itself or in complex networks, which maintain sen-
sory elements for a certain time, the new idea being that they allow prediction
of the future. If I am not mistaken, Husserl’s concept of simultaneity of
“protention” and “retention” is quite close to this idea.
A final basic conceptual contribution by Bernstein concerns the very prin-
ciple of motor control. Suppose that I wish to move my arm from one posi-
tion to another: the motor command an engineer might use would employ a
potentiometer to measure the angle, then construct a movement command
that controls the motors, which in this case are the muscles. A force com-
mand, or rather a coupling command (force multiplied by the lever arm),
would be the controlling variable, and the resulting displacement the variable de-
tected by the muscle receptors that are the biological equivalent of the potenti-
ometer.
Bernstein reasoned that the brain controls another variable, the point of
equilibrium between the two muscles that are in opposition around a joint—
the biceps and triceps in the arm, for example. He started from the idea that
when the forces exerted by these two muscles—which depend on the activa-
tion of motor neurons and their mechanical properties—are equal, the arm
will be in a given position. To define a position in space or to maintain a cer-
tain relationship among muscular forces is equivalent. Thus, space is perhaps
not coded explicitly, but the trajectory of movement results from this dynamic
equilibrium. Movement is simply a progressive shifting of postures.
16 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
A B
Layer I
+ Bursting
+ 40Hz
+
CORTEX IV
+
−
Layer V −
+
Interneuron
VI 40Hz +
P
Reticular + +
nucleus + +
THALAMUS − −
+ +
Specific nuclei Intralaminar
nonspecific nuclei
A concept proposed a long time ago to link perception, action, and memory is
that of the motor schema. According to Schmidt, movement structures, which
he calls “schemas,” are stored in the brain.17 These schemas are not sensory or
motor elements, but memorized relationships—topological links, mathemati-
cians would say—between several sensory or motor components of action
(like the position of limbs, the state of a target in space, and so on). Schmidt
PERCEPTION IS SIMULATED ACTION •
17
Initial conditions
Desired outcome
Recognition
Past
schema
schema
Recall
(Controls (Estimates
rapid consequences)
movements)
Expected
Response
sensory
specifications
consequences
Figure 1.4. The brain anticipates the consequences of movement from past ac-
tion to prepare and initiate a movement. Reading from top to bottom, antici-
pated movements begin with a set of initial conditions and a plan of action that
will lead to the desired outputs. These are compared with the results of past ac-
tions recalled by two types of memory: left, memory of motor commands, and
right, memory of sensory data associated with past movements and their ef-
fects on the environment. It is therefore possible to recall the expected sensory
consequences, or the messages detected by the receptors during and after ac-
tion over the course of movement. Control of movement involves estimating
discrepancies between anticipated and actual sensory data.
Mental Nodes
The idea that the brain does not simply detect the physical parameters that ex-
cite the senses is a very old idea. One interesting (unfortunately not very well
known) expression of it was offered by MacKay in several theoretical essays
dating from 1970 to 1980. His theory, called “mental nodes,” aimed at integrat-
ing interactions between perception and action. Others before him had tried
this approach: “Not all theoretical thinking in psychology has adopted the as-
sumption that components for perception and action are completely separate
or unshared. In particular, Lashley proposed that speech comprehension and
production make use of common components and mechanisms because ‘the
processes of comprehension and production of speech have too much in com-
mon to depend on wholly different mechanisms.’ . . . I conclude that percep-
tion and production share some components but not others.”19 But, as he ob-
served at the time, the dominance of research on perception isolated from
action derived as well from the philosophical view of researchers that “ac-
tion [was] functionally, temporally, and evaluatively subordinate to perception;
functionally subordinate because they considered perception the sole means
by which knowledge is acquired (empiricism); temporally subordinate because
they considered perception a necessary precursor to action (paleobehavior-
ism); and evaluatively subordinate because they viewed the contemplative life
as superior to a life of action (see Plato).”20
According to MacKay, two major mechanisms underlie most mental oper-
ations in sensorimotor systems. The first processes information from the sen-
sory receptors that the system forwards to a comparator where it is subjected
to criteria, such as a desired position. Error signals for checking corrections
are sent from the comparator—Bernstein’s classical loop—but MacKay adds a
second circuit based on sensory information. Sensory data in this second cir-
cuit are not processed by the nervous system to extract velocity, force, vol-
ume, dilation, and so on; they are interpreted as attributes, that is, configura-
tions of pertinent information that have a category-specific meaning. These
PERCEPTION IS SIMULATED ACTION •
19
data are directed to an operator that organizes or decides or chooses or finally
executes a projective feedforward under the control of the supervisor. This op-
erator recognizes pertinent cues for the task and evaluates the sensory context
to anticipate the movement; it controls motor activity.
What is missing in this model is direct action by the organizer on the re-
ceptors; that is, an influence of active perception on sensation, although exten-
sive proof exists for such action as I have indicated here, and as I will show
again later. In particular, what is missing is a conception of the brain as a rep-
ertoire of sensorimotor schemas that are just so many possible actions and
that organize perception even before sensory stimuli are processed. I will de-
velop this idea further, but it is worth examining a clear example at the outset.
Mirror Neurons
Support for the idea that the brain contains schemas in its neuronal organiza-
tion that constitute veritable behavioral actions was recently provided by
Rizzolatti.21 He discovered neurons in area F5 of monkeys, later termed “mir-
ror neurons,” which fire each time the animal makes a particular gesture, for
example, lifting a peanut to its mouth, turning a handle, and so on. But the
same neurons also fire when the monkey sees the experimenter make that
same gesture. In other words, these neurons are activated both when the ani-
mal makes the gesture and when it sees the gesture being made. From that it
can readily be deduced that the network of neurons, which includes this par-
ticular neuron, codes for a schema of the behavioral repertoire of the monkey.
Do we make that deduction? I will discuss it; but whatever the outcome of the
debate, this discovery argues for the existence of a repertoire of preperceptions
linked to a repertoire of actions. Consequently, the brain can simulate actions
to predict their consequences and to choose the most appropriate among
them.
A word in passing about the term “encoding.” I will use this term to desig-
nate the message contained in the firing of neurons whose properties I will de-
scribe. This usage is defensible even though it makes a major assumption,
which is that the temporal or frequency characteristics of the discharge contain
signals relevant to the functioning of the nervous system. The frequency of
neural discharge is not the only code possible. The coincidence between the
firing of several neurons or the temporal organization of their firing, the aver-
age activity of a population of neurons, synaptic modifications at the molecu-
lar level, are just so many different codes that we still do not understand. Sub-
stantial research efforts are ongoing to understand the respective contributions
20 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
of temporal encoding and frequency encoding. I can only touch on this ques-
tion, though it is fundamental.
A final word about the philosophical framework of this book. I will rarely use
the word “representation,” and when I do, I will use it reluctantly. Indeed, I
think that it is very trendy and very convenient—for hiding our ignorance. Un-
der the guise of seemingly centralist theories, it very often conceals subtle
forms of dualism that I reject. In a recent review of theories of perception, in
particular that of Helmholtz, Bouveresse articulated the dangers inherent in
the concept of representation:
Projective
process
Motor
command Sensory
input
Figure 1.5. The brain activates two parallel modes over the course of an action.
The first, which is the oldest, is conservative. It tends to maintain certain vari-
ables within limits defined by the intended action. It functions in closed circuits
that couple the sensory receptors to motor commands either via reflexes or
through central structures that specify preconfigured motor programs in a rep-
ertoire of interconnected synergies. It also uses motor primitives—gestures
with recognizably distinctive features organized in specialized groups of neu-
rons in the brain (the basal ganglia, the motor and premotor cortex, the cere-
bellum, and so on). In this mode, the brain functions like a controller to correct
for mechanical variables such as velocity and force. The second mode of con-
trol evolved more recently. It is projective, using internal maps to simulate
movement without carrying it out. These maps are not the same as geographic
maps. Although some (like those of the colliculus) are genuine environmental
maps, the concept of map here means that the groups of neurons in a particu-
lar region of the brain have a structured set of properties analogous to the ex-
ternal world. If the input and output switches (that is, the sensory information
and motor activity) cease to operate, this mode can still function as a simulator,
as in a dream.
late a velocity. This property allows the cat to survive without having to do
calculations. Roboticists also began by making robots that simulated by calcu-
lating, but these robots are slow. The new generation of robots is endowed
with properties of adaptation and prediction. These robots use synthetic work
parameters that simplify calculations and that permit internal simulation of
processes for finding new solutions. I will come back to these ideas in Chap-
ter 8.
PERCEPTION IS SIMULATED ACTION •
23
The fact that perception and simulation of action are embedded in each
other has been demonstrated recently in an experiment concerning mental ro-
tation. Imagine that you wish to compare two identical or different but similar
objects that are tilted with respect to each other by a certain angle. If you are
asked to decide whether they are different or identical, it will take you a cer-
tain time to answer (which can extend to seconds). The value of this mental
processing time is proportional to the angle between the two objects. This fact
has led psychologists to suggest that the brain performs a mental rotation of
the objects to compare them more easily. We have shown that if, during the
mental time of comparison, the subject is asked to perform a movement with
his hand in either the same or a different direction than the mental rotation, a
change in the time to respond occurs.27
Now that I have provided a general idea of the field, why not tackle the
first problem that arises: How do we get from a physiology of sensation to a
physiology of perception that acts, judges, and decides on the basis of action
and of the future consequences of action?
24 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
2
T H E S E N S E O F M O V E M E N T: A S I X T H S E N S E ?
Praised be our senses. Magically, they make manifest for us various vibrations
as light, color, and heat—not just sound; they capture the forces of chemical at-
traction as flavors or odors. In short, for our experience of all the enchanting
splendor and invigorating freshness of the physical world, we are indebted to
the senses and the symbols that serve as their intermediaries, through which
we gain news of these things . . . Think of the months, perhaps the years of
work that it would cost a physicist to define the color tones of a landscape seen
only one time, which our eye apprehends with a single look and is immediately
ready to exchange for another image.
—H. von Helmholtz
In the first chapter, I claimed that the senses are not passive receptors. Now I
will show that anticipation really is an essential characteristic of their func-
tioning, and that even at this level certain mechanisms allow internal simula-
tion of movement. I will pay particular attention to senses that are not very
well known: muscular proprioception and the vestibular system.
Indeed, to the five traditional senses—touch, sight, hearing, taste, smell—
we must add the sense of movement, or kinesthesia. Its characteristic feature
is that it makes use of many receptors, but remarkably it has been forgotten in
the count of the senses. We seem to be stuck at Aristotle’s assertion: “In the
Psychology we have given a general account of the objects corresponding to
the particular sense-organs, to wit colour, sound, smell, flavour, and touch.”1
By what twist did language suppress the sense most important to survival? A
plausible explanation is that it is not identified by consciousness, and its recep-
tors are concealed. It seems normal to us to recognize the movement of our
Vestibular receptors
Visual receptors Semicircular
canals
Otoliths
Cochlea
Muscle receptors
Cutaneous receptors
Joint receptors
Figure 2.1. Sensory receptors contribute to the sense of movement. The recep-
tors located in the muscles (neuromuscular spindles, Golgi tendon organs) and
the joints (joint receptors) all detect movements of the limbs. This is
proprioception. Cutaneous receptors detect skin pressure and friction from
contact of the limbs with each other and the external world. Vision detects
shifting images of the visual world on the retina, the position of objects in
space, shape, color, and so on. Movement of the head in space is detected from
a combination of visual and proprioceptive cues, but it is also detected indepen-
dently by the vestibular receptors. These receptors are situated in the inner ear
near the cochlea and comprise three semi-circular canals (horizontal, anterior
vertical, and posterior vertical) in three perpendicular planes and the otoliths
(the utricle, in the plane of the horizontal canal, and the saccule, in the plane of
the anterior vertical canal).
arm or vertical direction, but nothing indicates that we have receptors for
stretch and force in our muscles, for rotation in our joints, for pressure and
friction in our skin, and that in each inner ear we have five receptors (the
utricle, the saccule, and the three semicircular canals) that specifically detect
movements of the head (Figure 2.1).
Proprioception
34 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
control systems, introduced in neurophysiology by Hartline, Terzuolo, and
others in the 1960s, provided a quantitative method for evaluating receptor dy-
namics: a nerve fiber was recorded while the animal was rotated on a turnta-
ble that was subjected to sinusoidal movement. Varying the frequency of oscil-
lation (the number of oscillations per second) made it possible to obtain the
response of the receptor to movements of differing rapidity. It just required
measuring the amplitude of the modulation of neural discharge and the tem-
poral relation between discharge and movement (phase).
Consider the case of rotations in the horizontal plane, a movement you
make hundreds of times each day in turning your head. When an animal is
subjected to sinusoidal horizontal rotations alternating clockwise and counter-
clockwise and whose frequency of repetition goes from one cycle every 100
seconds (0.01 Hz) to five per second (5 Hz), the neurons of the vestibular re-
ceptors fire with a frequency that also varies in a sinusoidal manner. The am-
plitude of their modulation is weak for the slowest movements (0.01 Hz), then
increases with frequency, remains stable between 0.1 and 1 Hz (the frequency
of everyday movements), then increases again beyond that. The delay with
which the neurons fire in relation to the displacement of the head varies with
the frequency of oscillation. They are in phase with acceleration for slow
movements, which is normal since the semicircular canals are receptors for an-
gular acceleration; then they are in phase with the velocity of the head for the
frequency of natural movements (between 0.1 and 1 Hz) and with very rapid
movements, like those made when falling down; and they come back into
phase with acceleration, which makes possible the rapid reactions needed for
getting back up.
Generally, the signals from these receptors enable anticipation of the fu-
ture position of the head owing to their sensitivity to derivatives (jerk, acceler-
ation, and velocity) of movements of the head. These receptors not only
transmit signals to the brain, they are also subjected to centrifugal control
from the central nervous system that modulates their properties. As a matter
of fact, efferent neurons project from the brainstem to the receptors of the
sensory cell. The exact mechanism of centrifugal control is not yet completely
understood. Nor is it the only one: interactions between receptor cells enable
retrocontrol of sensory messages; that is, rapid and subtle adjustment of the
sensitivity of the cell to the origin of the sensory signal.19 The sensory mes-
sage is thus processed by the brain at its source. The same two major princi-
ples already described for the muscle receptors also apply to the canals: detec-
tion of derivatives of movement that enable anticipation, and modulation of
A SIXTH SENSE? •
35
the message at the source by the central nervous system. One of the basic
functions of the vestibular system is thus to detect movements of the head in
a Euclidean reference system.
Very early in evolution the canals appeared in certain animals: the lamprey,
one of the oldest among the fishes, has two sets. Mammals have three of them
on each side of their heads. The canals are situated in three approximately
perpendicular planes, though not the ones you might guess merely by observ-
ing animals from outside. One of the planes corresponds to the horizontal
plane of the head. To locate it in humans, just look at a person from the side
and plot a line from the meatus of the ear to the external edge of the eye. The
horizontal canal is in a plane that overhangs this line by 20 degrees (see Fig-
ure 2.4).
The two remaining planes of the canals are at 45 degrees with respect to
the frontal and saggital planes of the body.20 Why is this anatomical detail im-
portant? Because the three planes so constituted form a basic egocentric frame
of reference with respect to which, as I will discuss later, our entire perception
of movement in space is organized. The geometry of the canals dictates the
organization of the cerebral analysis of visual movement and perhaps also
other movements. It might yet prove to be the basis of Euclidean geometry.
Poincaré was interested in this question. In his book La valeur de la science
(The Value of Science), he commented on the theories that pitted Cyon, on
the one hand, against Mach and Delage, on the other. According to Cyon,
“The three pairs of canals would have as sole function to tell us that space has
three dimensions. Japanese mice have only two pairs of canals; they believe, it
would seem, that space has only two dimensions . . . The lampreys, having
only one pair of canals, believe that space has only one dimension, but their
manifestations are less turbulent.”21 Poincaré objected to this view and main-
tained, along with Mach and Delage, that the semicircular canals “contribute,
therefore, to inform us of the movements that we have executed, and that on
the same ground as the muscular sensations.”22 For Poincaré, “the sense-or-
gans are designed to tell us of changes which happen in the exterior world. We
could not understand why the Creator should have given us organs destined
to cry without cease: ‘Remember that space has three dimensions,’ since the
number of these three dimensions is not subject to change.”23
Elsewhere Poincaré asks an important question: Why are Euclidean move-
ments perceived as actual movements? He says, “Our mind adapted itself to
the conditions of the external world through natural selection; it adopted the
geometry most advantageous or, to put it another way, most convenient to the
species. Geometry is not true; it is advantageous.”24 “One geometry cannot be
36 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
more true than another; it can only be more convenient. Now, Euclidean geom-
etry is, and will remain, the most convenient: 1st, because it is the simplest,
and it is not so only because of our mental habits or because of the kind of di-
rect intuition that we have of Euclidean space; . . . 2nd, because it sufficiently
agrees with the properties of natural solids.”25
What are the relationships between geometric space and representative
space? Are their properties similar? “It is often said,” Poincaré writes, “that the
images we form of external objects are localised in space, and even that they
can only be formed on this condition. It is also said that this space, which thus
serves as a kind of framework ready prepared for our sensations and represen-
tations, is identical with the space of the geometers, having all the properties
of that space.”26 However, he argues, geometric space is continuous, infinite,
three-dimensional, homogeneous (all its points are identical), isotropic (all the
straight lines that pass through the same point are identical). In contrast, rep-
resentative space (which is primarily visual space) is two-dimensional (retinal
space); it becomes three-dimensional owing to convergence and accommoda-
tion; it is not homogeneous, because the part of the retina that is most sensi-
tive to shape, the fovea, is nonhomogeneous with the periphery. It is thus not
isotropic.
Poincaré concludes from this that representative space is only an image of
geometrical space distorted by the rules that govern how our perceptive appa-
ratus works. “Thus we do not represent to ourselves external bodies in geomet-
rical space, but we reason about these bodies as if they were situated in geo-
metrical space.”27 Modern psychophysics confirms this intuition.
Poincaré introduces a fundamental notion that is essential to my own the-
ory: “To localize an object simply means to represent to oneself the move-
ments that would be necessary to reach it. I will explain myself. It is not a
question of representing the movements themselves in space, but solely of
representing to oneself the muscular sensations which accompany these
movements and which do not presuppose the preexistence of the notion of
space.”28 But then, if we cannot represent geometrical space for ourselves, and
if our representation of space is in fact only what I call a simulation, that is,
the movements that we need to make to travel it, the question becomes one
of knowing how the idea of geometric space could even have come about. We
must, says Poincaré, look at the way we evaluate how change affects an object.
An object can undergo a change of state or of position. In either case, the
change is signaled “by a modification in an aggregate of impressions.”29 By this
Poincaré means something very close to what I call a configuration of states
of sensory receptors. Inasmuch as position can be corrected, the brain distin-
A SIXTH SENSE? •
37
guishes change of state and change of position: “We could restore the primi-
tive aggregate of impressions by making movements which would confront us
with the movable object in the same relative situation . . . [A] motionless be-
ing,” he adds, “could never have acquired [the idea of space], because, not be-
ing able to correct by his movements the effects of the change of position of
external objects, he would have had no reason to distinguish them from
changes of state.”30 Sight and touch would not be able to give us a sense of
space without the “muscular sense.”
These processes require that objects be rigid. If there were no solid bodies
in nature, there would be no geometry. For Poincaré, geometry is thus the de-
scription of phenomena called displacements, that is, external changes that
can be compensated for by changes in our own bodies detectable by the ves-
tibular receptors.
Hair
cells
Vestibular nerve
Gravity
Gravity
Figure 2.2. The otolithic receptors. The upper part of the figure shows schemat-
ically the mass of crystals floating in the endolymph, which together constitute
the otoliths. The endolymph is not shown. The hairs of the sensory neurons
are situated beneath the crystal mass. The lower part of each drawing depicts
the base of the receptor (called the macula). Ionic changes triggered by move-
ment of the hairs result in discharge of the sensory cells that travels along the
vestibular nerve to the brain, which is thereby informed about the magnitude
of acceleration of the head. In this case, gravity has no effect on the receptor,
because it is perpendicular to it. If the receptor is tilted, the gravitational com-
ponent is in the plane of the macula. This receptor indicates both acceleration
and tilt of the head. The receptor shown here is the utricle, which detects hori-
zontal accelerations of the head; another receptor, called the saccule, is located
perpendicular to it and detects accelerations and gravitational force in the verti-
cal plane.
A SIXTH SENSE? •
39
A
Acceleration
Acceleration
Inertial force
Re
su
lta
nt
Gravity
Gravitational
component in
the plane of
the otoliths
Gravity
Figure 2.3. Ambiguity results when the head is simultaneously accelerated and
tilted. (A): If the head accelerates forward, a backward inertial force is exerted
on the crystals of the utricle. The combination of this force and the downward
gravitational force produces a resultant tilting force. The brain has the illusion
that this resultant is gravity. And because it uses gravity as a fixed reference
with respect to the earth, the brain deduces that the head is tilted. (B): When
the head is motionless but tilted backward, a gravitational component in the
plane of the receptor gives the impression of a forward acceleration. (The size
of the receptor has been considerably enlarged.)
40 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
displacement of the crystals, which leads to activation of the vestibular nerves.
The same activation is produced by tilting the head. In this last case, tilting in-
duces a modification of the magnitude of the component of gravity acting on
the crystals. They are thus both accelerometers and “tiltometers.” One could
simply say that the saccule (the sensor of vibrations in insects and batrachia),
whose plane is close to that of the vertical anterior semicircular canal, detects
vertical linear accelerations of the head (when you jump up and down with
your feet together, for example), and that the utricle, whose plane is close to
that of the horizontal semicircular canal, detects horizontal linear accelera-
tions of the head (when your car brakes or accelerates, for example).
These two kinds of vestibular receptors, the canals and the otoliths, detect
movement of the head in space without needing a reference point. They con-
stitute a genuine inertial system like those mounted on board airplanes. More-
over, they use gravity as a reference to supply the brain with information
about the static tilt of the head. In microgravity—in space stations—these re-
ceptors can thus always detect angular or linear accelerations of the head, but
can no longer rely on gravity for detecting angle of tilt. The brain has to rein-
terpret the information transmitted by these receptors to be able to compare
them with sensations from other proprioceptive and visual receptors.
Finally, let me reiterate a point that is often poorly understood: vestibular
receptors are not only sensors of movement. They also signal immobility. In-
deed, these sensors have a basic discharge whose lack of variation is inter-
preted by the brain as immobility. They are essential for assessing what is
called the subjective vertical (see Chapter 4).
Although they make it possible to recognize head movements, vestibular
receptors alone are not enough, because of the ambiguous information they
provide. For example, they cannot distinguish between acceleration of the
head in one direction and braking in the other direction. Tactile or visual in-
formation helps to resolve this ambiguity. This clearly shows how perception
requires cooperation among the senses.
Another ambiguity that has already been mentioned is the distinction be-
tween the angle of tilt of the head and linear acceleration. This is known as
the problem of gravito-inertial differentiation, and I will refer to it again in Chap-
ter 13. To this problem nature found a solution, called frequential filtering. It
consists in separating the two components of movement at the level of the
first sensory relays, in the so-called vestibular nuclei and perhaps even at the
level of the fibers that connect the receptors to these first relays. In fact, in the
vestibular nuclei there are two kinds of neurons. Some respond especially to
slow variations in acceleration, but are indifferent to rapid movements. The
A SIXTH SENSE? •
41
solution is an elegant one, because detecting the angle of tilt of the head in-
volves slow neurons, and detecting acceleration involves rapid neurons. Oth-
ers are highly activated by very rapid movements of the head and only slightly
by slow movements. Differentiation of gravito-inertial forces is resolved by
segregation at the very level of capture of sensory information.
This very early capacity for segregation is a basic feature of sensory ana-
lyzers. I will discuss it further in Chapter 3.
42 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
mation about visual movement borrows yet another pathway called the acces-
sory optic pathway, where geometric segregation happens early on.
It is as if the senses were specialized organs for detecting variables perti-
nent to the survival of each species, nature having put in place very periph-
eral mechanisms for selecting these variables and dissociating them. Once
the brain has these bits of information, it reconstructs them into more com-
plex messages and encodes them for adaptation to various central operations
needed for perception and action. Gibson stressed the idea that the senses are
analyzers that do not merely detect the physical variables likely to stimulate
their endings, but that in a way they have integrated into their functioning the
elements of nature important for the animal’s repertoire of actions. The early
segregation of sensory information by the senses and their first analytical neu-
ral networks supports this idea and does seem to suggest that the transduction
of physical variables (light, sound, pressure, etc.) responds to preexisting ques-
tions that the nervous system asks the world.
Postural Stabilization
The vestibular system ensures postural stability. If we trip over a root, our
head accelerates, and the canals and the otoliths are activated, exciting the so-
called vestibulospinal reflex pathways that initiate the reactions needed to re-
adjust posture: lifting the head and the rest of the body by means of proprio-
ceptive reflexes whose receptors are located in the neck. I will not describe this
function, known since the work of Magnus31 and Rademaker32 at the begin-
ning of the century and studied by the Italian school of neurophysiology dur-
ing the 1950s, the Japanese school of Fukuda, and by Roberts at Edinburgh.
What I will stress is the anticipatory properties of these reflexes. The anticipa-
tory power of the vestibular receptors comes from the fact that they detect ac-
celeration. Now, acceleration is maximal from the beginning of a fall or loss
of balance. The reflexes for getting back up are thus very rapid since they are
initiated as soon as the perturbation begins. The conjunction of the discharge
of the tactile receptors of the spindles sensitive to the velocity of stretching—
for they are sensitive to variations in pressure—and the vestibular receptors
sensitive to acceleration supplies the nervous system with preliminary infor-
mation about the nature of loss of balance. The muscle contractions that lift
the body are the result of this anticipation, and the swiftness of the postural
A SIXTH SENSE? •
43
adjustment is further facilitated by virtue of the brain’s repertoire of ready-
made postural reactions. These stereotypical reactions are triggered by spe-
cially configured sensory signals that set in motion what are called synergies
(see Chapter 7). The vestibular receptors are initiators, not just detectors. The
information they convey is a sign, not just a signal.
Gaze Stabilization
Perceptual stabilization is the second major vestibular function. Indeed, if the
world appears stable when we move, it is first and foremost owing to reflexes
of vestibular origin that stabilize the image of the world on the retina. These
reflexes connect the vestibular receptors to the muscles of the eye. The anat-
omy of neural connections is such that moving the head in one direction leads
to moving the eye in the other, which has the effect of suppressing, or dimin-
ishing, the shifting of images on the retina (retinal slip).
You can very easily see for yourself. Just look at a point on the wall in front
of you. Close your eyes, turn your head while imagining the point on the
wall, and open your eyes. You will notice that your gaze has remained on the
point that you memorized. Your eye made a movement in a direction contrary
to that of your head, and of the same amplitude. Its origin is vestibular: it is
produced, in the horizontal plane, by the semicircular canals. But how do I
know, you say, that the muscle receptors in the neck have not detected the
movement of my head? To answer your question, you have only to sit in a
rolling chair and ask someone to repeat the experiment by turning you to one
side or the other. This time, as your eyes are closed during rotation, only the
semicircular canals detect the rotation (the tactile receptors alone are not suf-
ficient to detect a rotation angle). You will see that your gaze has remained
fixed on the same point on the wall. Thus the semicircular canals are able to
do the job by themselves. (However, the receptors in the neck do help during
natural rotations of the head, cooperating with the vestibular receptors.)
But, you say now, how do I know that it is a reflex? Since I am introducing
the memory of a target on a wall, it is very likely that I am also involving my
cerebral cortex and the structures that are implicated in spatial memory. You
are correct. In fact, the vestibulo-ocular reflex is nothing like a simple reflex;
its amplitude is regulated by the cortex, and I will show in Chapter 3 that ves-
tibular information is transmitted to the cortex and that the zones that receive
it project in their turn to the vestibular nuclei.
Around 1930, Lorente de Nó discovered a network of neurons in the
brainstem that connects the semicircular canals and the muscles of the eyes.33
He suggested that the reflex is subtended by an arc of three neurons (Fig-
44 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
Cerebellum
(flocculus)
Vestibular nuclei
Semicircular
canals
Motoneuron
Figure 2.4. The vestibular reflex stabilizes retinal images during head move-
ments. What is called the vestibulo-ocular reflex is the product of the network
of neurons that join the vestibular receptors to the muscles of the eyes. Vestib-
ular information is relayed to the cerebellum via the Purkinje neurons, inhibi-
tory neurons that coordinate and modulate the reflex (black circle). The part of
the cerebellum involved in rotations is the flocculus.
ure 2.4): a peripheral neuron that connects the semicircular canals to the ves-
tibular nuclei of the brainstem; an intermediary neuron, called the second-or-
der vestibular neuron, whose cellular body is in the vestibular nucleus and
which projects to the motor nucleus called abducens (motor nucleus VI); and
finally a neuron that causes the muscles of the eyes to contract (motor neu-
ron). A second reflex pathway includes a mechanism for generating the rapid
A SIXTH SENSE? •
45
phase in the form of a cascade of neurons situated in the reticular formation.
Around 1965 Szentagothai established the exquisite correspondence between
each canal and each of the three pairs of eye muscles.34 The basic anatomy of
a reflex was thus pieced back together.
It was Eccles’s perfection of the methods of intracellular recording that
furthered the understanding of the synaptic organization of the reflex.35 This
organization turns out to be both very simple and very subtle. A network of
excitatory and inhibitory synapses underlies it and ensures a very rigid kind of
“push-pull” functioning. Moreover, indirect pathways alter signals of move-
ment and produce vestibular nystagmus. Finally, circuits that traverse the cere-
bellum exert feedforward control on the reflex. The discovery that I made,
with Baker, of the role of the prepositus hypoglossi nucleus as a supplementary
reticular relay for control pathways further complicates the organization of
this reflex, which is composed of a series of parallel pathways that interact
one with the other.36 But this is not the place to describe this remarkable
mechanism.
Just when the complexity of neural organization could have trapped elec-
trophysiologists in a profusion of details, systems theory emerged with several
welcome simplifying concepts.
46 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
subjected to sinusoidal stimulation, the head is briefly rotated, the fibers of the
vestibular receptors respond very quickly, and their response diminishes spon-
taneously after about 5 to 12 seconds once the head has stopped moving. The
neurons of the vestibular nuclei do not stop firing until about 20 to 25 seconds
afterward. You can feel this effect by closing your eyes and turning your head
very rapidly, and concentrating on the impression of rotation that follows: you
will continue to feel it for about 20 seconds. But a supplementary integration
intervenes between the vestibular nuclei and the movement of the eyes.
The research on this central neuronal integrator has greatly fascinated
physiologists. To avoid confusion, let me make clear that I am not talking
about the concept of integration as Sherrington used it, in the sense of a com-
plex combination of multiple signals to “integrate their messages,” but rather
in the literal mathematical sense of progression from the derivative of a vari-
able of movement to its integral; that is, of acceleration to velocity or of ve-
locity to position. The theory of servo systems, which was developed mainly
during World War II to control radar and which flourished in the 1950s,
was very useful for expressing these dynamic transformations in quantitative
terms. Engineers use concepts borrowed from the analysis of servo systems to
describe these dynamic transformations.
At least four mechanisms have been proposed to explain this integration.
Lorente de Nó was the first to suggest that simply returning discharge from a
neuron to itself in a so-called re-excitation or recurring excitation loop sufficed
to maintain activity and produce integration. The same effect could be pro-
duced by an extended long loop action involving other groups of neurons. A
third hypothesis was the intervention of inhibitory mechanisms that could
produce the same effect (lateral inhibition). Finally, a cascade of successive
partial integrations in a nucleus close to the vestibular nucleus, the prepositus
hypoglossi nucleus, could lead to this progression from velocity to a signal of
position. The question has not been resolved, although Baker and his col-
leagues have identified precise zones of the brainstem in the fish where these
networks of neurons that enable integration are probably located. It is also
possible that integration is due to so-called intrinsic properties of the same
neurons. For example, certain neurons can respond to a burst of activity with
a continuous discharge. This mechanism involves ion channels in the neuronal
membrane that depend on the concentration of calcium ions. Settling on the
right mechanism is a matter of time. It will require new methods that are only
now being developed and that will permit manipulation of the properties of
membranes in the intact brain.
A SIXTH SENSE? •
47
The Problem of Geometry: Is the Brain a Tensor?
How does the brain handle problems of geometry? Control of a reflex as sim-
ple as the vestibulo-ocular reflex does not consist merely in resolving relational
problems among acceleration, velocity, and position—in other words, prob-
lems of dynamics. The six muscles of the eye and the thirty muscles of the
head, situated in very varied orientations, also must be controlled by the three
semicircular canals and the otoliths, which are located in three planes. Re-
stating the problem will better indicate its complexity. Imagine that you are
sitting in a boat and a wave comes and rocks the boat; your head will move in
rotation with the boat. If you want to stay upright, you will have to make a
movement of straightening your body, equal to and in a contrary sense from
that of the boat. Your semicircular canals (ignoring the otoliths for now) de-
tect three projections of this rotation in three perpendicular planes. Thus you
have three values that represent the projection of the true rotation in a system
of special coordinates whose axes are at right angles. Put simply, the rotation
is encoded as covariant coordinates. The numerical values of these coordi-
nates constitute a vector that can be represented by an arrow whose magni-
tude and direction are measures of the intensity of the sensation detected by
the receptor.
A system of coordinates encodes the movement that the eyes, head, and
even the trunk must make to compensate for this rotation due to the motion
of the boat. These systems of coordinates are the directions of tension of the
muscles of these different parts of the body. The brain thus has to transform
the sensory information, encoded in covariant coordinates, into motor com-
mands expressed in the systems of coordinates of the muscles and their planes
of action.
Pellionisz and Llinás maintained that certain portions of the brain trans-
form sensory coordinates into motor coordinates.37 They observed that as
there are in general more dimensions in muscular frames of reference than in
sensory frames of reference, in principle the problem of transformation has
many solutions. One of their solutions was the idea that perhaps the brain
functions like a tensor. A tensor is a group of mathematical operators called
matrices that carry out transformations between vectors. They have proper-
ties that are irrelevant to the discussion here. P. Churchland’s book Neuro-
philosophy contains a summary of this theory.
Pellionisz and Llinás applied their theory to two examples: the vestibulo-
ocular reflex, which stabilizes gaze, and the vestibulo-nuchal reflex, which lifts
the head when the boat rocks.38 In the case of the vestibulo-ocular reflex, they
48 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
assumed that rotations of the head are encoded covariantly by the vestibular
receptors and that several successive transformations precede the motor com-
mand that turns the eye in the coordinates contravariant to the six muscles of
the eyes. In another model, they suggested that the cerebellum was the struc-
ture that carries out the most important transformations.39 I will try to explain
broadly the basic idea of these models. When the motor command is sent to
the motor neurons of the neck muscles, it is distorted by the geometrical
properties of the components of the forces (contravariant projection) and by
the mechanical properties of the head and neck. To obtain a movement of the
head that is in perfect opposition to that of the boat such that the vestibular
receptors can detect it, one solution, invented by roboticists, is that the com-
mand signal itself be already distorted in an inverse way before it is sent to the
muscles. The simplest image I have been able to come up with to represent
this process is that of a casting mold, which is in a way the inverse of the ob-
ject it is intended to shape. In fact, we use this strategy in many movements;
for example, if we need to lift an object that is hanging at the end of a rubber
band, we make a much bigger movement, because we are anticipating the
elasticity of the rubber band. The advantage of the internal model that ac-
complishes the inverse is precisely that we do not have to produce a different
motor command: it is automatically transformed. This inverse transformation
is assumed to take place in the cerebellum.40
To sum up: The movement of the boat is detected by the vestibular recep-
tors in three planes. It is thus represented by three vectors. This information is
sent to a nerve center (in this case, the cerebellum), which transforms these
signals to supply them with properties that will, in advance, compensate for
the distortions the signal will undergo in the movements coordinated by the
muscles, as a function of the mechanics of the limbs. The signal is then sent to
the muscles; it undergoes contravariant transformations of the coordinates,
and the head is stabilized.
Even if the brain is not a tensor, and if today the subscribers to this theory
are not legion, the fact remains that the theory of tensors has forced a genera-
tion of physiologists to take very seriously the question of geometry and the
solutions that nature appears to have found to simplify neurocomputation.41 In
addition, this theory contains an important idea, that of the internal model,
which can be found today in the most progressive theories. I will introduce
other examples in Chapter 8.
I would like to make a general observation, central to the premise of this
book. The examples taken from the theory of servo systems and of tensors
have in common that they consider reflexes and sensorimotor systems to be
A SIXTH SENSE? •
49
continuous chains of transformations that proceed from sensation to motor
command. Although this approach incorporates the idea of an internal model
and, thus, an important anticipatory mechanism, it gives short shrift to the in-
fluence of action on sensory processing. It is thus very far from a projective
conceptualization of the nervous system.
Seeing Movement
i m
lw
Z
X Vt
Y
Figure 2.5. A trolley for studying interactions between vestibular and visual de-
tection of translational movements. The subject is seated on a stool placed on
the trolley (t), which is driven forward or backward by translational movements
that are controlled by a computer. A projector (represented by a light bulb) dis-
plays a reel of transparent film (r) with various shapes (squares, points, and so
on). Theses images are projected by a set of mirrors (m) onto a screen (s) lo-
cated above the subject. The mirrors create virtual images of the screen on
each side of the subject, who sees them through lateral windows (lw) in such a
way that he has the illusion of moving in an optical tunnel. This visual move-
ment makes him feel that he is advancing or moving backward in a direction
contrary to the movement of the visual scene (called vection). The vestibular
system can be stimulated by movement of the trolley, so that the interaction
between visual and vestibular information in the perception of movement may
be studied.
54 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
The spatial frequency of the scene, that is, the number of elements per
unit of surface, also has an influence on the intensity of vection, which is
greater when you go through a village that has many visual elements per unit
of surface than when you cross the desert. Road accidents are probably caused
by disparities between the information supplied from both sides of the road;
night, especially, gives a driver erroneous impressions of changing directions
due to the difference in vection induced by each retina.
The final element is the distance of the scene in motion and, particularly,
its position as backdrop or forestage. The most distant part of the environ-
ment is what determines the intensity and direction of vection. It is yet further
proof of the extraordinary assessment of the perceptual context carried out
by the brain.
If a subject is exposed to visual movement for a long time, vection dimin-
ishes in intensity. In the example of the highway, driving for several hours in-
duces underestimation of vection and, thus, underestimation of the sensation
of velocity. When drivers leave the highway, they have a tendency to drive too
fast, which is why speed ramps exist. Adaptation to stimulus is a familiar phe-
nomenon in psychophysics. Disappearance of vection can be interpreted as
the suppression of a repetitive signal that has nothing more to contribute to
the ongoing action. If that were true, the question would appear to be one of
an interesting mechanism that would be fairly easy to test. But it seems to me
that, on the contrary, one must assume that an active neural mechanism
opposes the stimulus, the brain creating an internal movement that blocks
the stimulus supplied by the external movement. When the stimulus is sup-
pressed, all that is left is this active neural construction, which was counterbal-
ancing it. At issue here is not a simple mental object, but a mental movement.
An illusion that probably involves similar mechanisms is called “the waterfall.”
If you look at a waterfall for a long time and then cast your eye on the sur-
rounding landscape, you perceive apparent movement resulting from the ad-
aptation of your brain to the visual scene in motion. I will return to the mean-
ing of these illusions in Chapter 13.
Another especially clear example of this type of mechanism is provided by
what is called consecutive optokinetic nystagmus. This odd-sounding expres-
sion describes a very simple phenomenon. Suppose that you are on a bus,
looking out the window. Your eye follows the visual scene, then turns back.
That is optokinetic nystagmus. Now suppose that the journey lasts several
minutes and that you are suddenly plunged into darkness. Instead of stopping,
your eye will continue to move. This consecutive optokinetic nystagmus is the
result of a still mysterious mechanism: it is as if a neural memory of move-
A SIXTH SENSE? •
55
ment had “charged” (as you charge a capacitor in electronics) a signal con-
nected to the velocity of the eye, which runs down in the dark. It is likely that
this perceptual memory is of the same nature as that involved in a long sea
voyage. Indeed, sailors know that several days after their return, they will still
feel as though they are moving, even though they are on terra firma. Here,
again, the brain has constructed a dynamic internal response to the motion of
the sea, probably using visual and proprioceptive vestibular information. Dur-
ing the voyage, this internal neural activity—which predicts the disruptive ef-
fects of the oscillations caused by the waves—opposes the sensory stimuli in-
duced by pitching and rolling. Hence sailors are able to live at sea without
feeling that they are moving and are able to coordinate their own movements.
The decision to interpret a movement in the visual world as a movement
of the body is thus the result of multiple central neural processes, and yet it
seems so obvious. How does the brain succeed in giving perceptual unity to
all these variables and all their values? It is thanks to special mechanisms for
building coherence, like those that make it possible to perceive a single visual
object after it is analyzed in the first relays of visual pathways. I will return to
these mechanisms later on.
56 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
3
BUILDING COHERENCE
Sensory receptor function has a predictive quality. Receptors can detect the de-
rivatives (that is, velocity, acceleration, changes in force and pressure) of the
physical variables that stimulate them. Detecting changes in a variable allows
the receptors to predict the value of that variable at a future time. In addition,
modulation of receptor sensitivity preselects receptors that specify future
movement by endowing them with properties that anticipate the nature of
the movement, tonic or dynamic. Such modulation allows simulation of the
movement without having to carry it out. In fact, simple activation of γ fibers
simulates a displacement of the arm by triggering spindle activity, and this
spindle activity produces the perceptual illusion of movement, as vibration ex-
periments demonstrate. Finally, filtering of messages by mechanisms such as
presynaptic inhibition increases the efficiency of preselection even more.
In this chapter, I will show how the combination of signals from the differ-
ent senses—the essentially multisensory character of perception—and the
brain’s use of endogenous (that is, produced by the subject) signals further in-
creases the predictive power of the brain.1 Indeed, a true physiology of per-
ception must abandon the idea of splitting up sensory functions and instead
approach them by way of their multisensory character. Aristotle himself won-
dered about this question:
The significance of this message was neglected until very recently. For fifty
years, the entire field of the physiology of perception had isolated the senses.
Consequently, laboratories studying vision proliferated, even though as early
as 1876 Ferrier was writing: “Without these labyrinthine impressions, optic
and tactile impressions are of themselves unable to excite the harmonious ac-
tivity of the centres of equilibration.”3 The same is true for hearing, since vi-
sion can modify auditory perception in a decisive way.4 Ventriloquists provide
the best example of this phenomenon: they create the illusion that their words
are coming from their dummy. The mere fact of not moving their lips and
working those of the dummy displaces the perception of the source of the
sound. I will describe the neurophysiological discoveries that may explain this
effect. Similarly, the art of entertaining demonstrates that the flavor of a dish
depends no less on the way it looks than how it smells. The same agreeable
smell at the beginning of a meal may become disagreeable by the end, owing
to a property of the brain called allesthesia—taste is a source of pleasure when
a person is hungry and of repulsion when the person is sated.
The importance of combining sensations does not appear to have inter-
ested physiologists before 1960, although a hundred years ago Sechenov tied it
to how the image of one’s own body is constructed during active exploration:
“The child often sees a toy in the hands of its mother and in its own hands.
The first of these sensations is simple; the second one is complex, including
also tactile and muscular elements. This happens many thousand times. The
two sensations become separated from each other, and the child’s own hand
appears in its consciousness with a tinge of self-consciousness.”5
In work with animals, pioneers such as Held and Hein showed the impor-
tance of activity in the development of visual functions and the coordination
of sensory systems.6 In the 1960s, Gibson suggested the basis for a new experi-
mental test of perception. “We shall have to conceive the external senses in a
new way, as active rather than passive, as systems rather than channels, and as
interrelated rather than mutually exclusive. If they function to pick up infor-
mation, not simply to arouse sensations, this function should be denoted by a
different term. They will here be called perceptual systems.”7 One compelling
explanation for the multisensory nature of perception is that every animal is
58 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
only interested in certain aspects of reality. It selects configurations of features
that are useful to it as well as the relationships between the properties of ob-
jects. For example, as Turvey says, the height of the steps in a staircase ex-
pressed in centimeters is less important than the relationship between the
height of the steps and the height to which we are able to lift our feet.8 This
explains why the steps in the staircase of a French château are not very high,
since horses had to climb them. Similarly, the height of the stairs at the opera
has to be adjusted to accommodate the step of women in evening gowns.
Gibson called these relationships that define the constants useful to a par-
ticular species “affordances.”9 They are a measure of the feasibility of carrying
out actions important for the species in question, taking into account its
sensorimotor repertoire. Sometimes opposite properties are interesting to dif-
ferent animals. Thus the degree of firmness (which can be measured as the re-
lationship between pressure and displacement) of the ground allows humans
to walk, whereas its friability permits the earthworm to move about. A single
object such as a slipper can serve as a warm refuge for a person’s foot, oral
stimulation for a puppy, and a scrumptious meal for a larva. The geometrical
constants essential for humans have ceased to be essential for other species.
What are the neural mechanisms underlying the multisensorial and ac-
tion-related character of perception? When microelectrodes were invented in
the 1950s, it became possible to stimulate different sensory receptors with
electrical impulses and to record neuronal activity in anesthetized animals. It
turned out that multisensory convergences occur at all levels of the nervous
system.
They occur first of all in the medulla, where the most important inter-
neurons—that is, neurons that link sensory and motor neurons—(like inter-
neuron Ia) are the site of convergences from muscular spindle receptors, tac-
tile receptors and the Golgi tendon organs. In the cerebellum, also the center
of intense multisensory interactions, each Purkinje cell in the cerebellar ver-
mis receives visual and proprioceptive information, just as the neurons of the
flocculus receive vestibular information, and so on. The superior colliculus is
an important structure for orienting movements. It receives visual and pro-
prioceptive information and is another focus of convergence between audi-
tory and visual signals. Convergences also occur in the so-called sensory
thalamus and in many cortical areas. Multisensory convergence is thus the
rule. What is not known is what fundamental role it plays. It was not until
the 1970s that recordings of neurons in alert animals shed some light on this
question. The last five years, however, have yielded an exceptional harvest of
BUILDING COHERENCE •
59
data on this subject. An example from our own work will show how vision
and the vestibular system work together to reconstruct movements of the
head in space.
An engineer with two sensors at his disposal for detecting movements of the
head—the retina and the semicircular canals—runs into a problem of geome-
try. Indeed, the semicircular canals detect movement of the head in their three
perpendicular planes, so information is encoded in three dimensions; that is,
in a Euclidean frame of reference. The retina encodes retinal slip on a spheri-
cal, or two-dimensional, surface. It receives information of great complexity.
To better understand the geometrical problem posed by the fusion of infor-
mation about movements of visual and vestibular origin requires a brief dis-
cussion of the concept of optic flow.
When people move about in the real world, the image of the environment
on their retinas is displaced and becomes distorted in a very complex way. This
distortion of the image on the retina during displacement is called optic flow.
It can be represented by a velocity vector at any point on the retina that repre-
sents the direction and velocity from the point of the visual environment that
is projected onto the retina.
Gibson, who worked for the American army, looked into the problem of
airplane landings and described the form of these fields of vectors, which de-
pend both on the geometry of the environment and the movement of the air-
plane. He observed that optic flow is very straightforward during a rotation
because all the points are animated by an identical angular velocity. In con-
trast, during a forward translation—for example, moving forward while walk-
ing, or landing an airplane—optic flow takes the form of a complex expansion
of the field of vectors, which appear to start at a vanishing point at the edge
of this perspective: the “focus of expansion.” During lateral translations, as
when we are looking out the window of a train, optic flow takes on a more
subtle complexity: all along the track the visual world moves in a sense con-
trary to the movement of the train, whereas the distant landscape appears to
move in the same direction as the train.
How does the brain achieve this fusion of three-dimensional messages
supplied by the canals and by optic flow? The last twenty years have provided
new data on the neural mechanisms of the contribution of vision to the per-
ception of self-motion (vection), how moving objects are sensed, and the
“blindsight” of movement. I will summarize these findings here.
60 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
Movement
stereo Color
Retinal ganglion cells
MT ? V4
Color
V2
Stereo Form
Lateral geniculate nucleus
Color
Stereo Form
1
Form
Magnocellular layer Color Color 2 and 3
Color-blind
Form
Fast
High contrast Movement Movement 4A
Low resolution
α
4C
β
5
6
Primary visual cortex
V1
Figure 3.1. Segregation of inputs for identifying shape, color, motion, and depth
in the first relays of the visual system.
FEF Frontal
cortex
DL
PN
DM
PN
Figure 3.2. The main centers involved in processing information about visual
movement. (1): The accessory optic system. In this system, visual movement is
broken down into three planes (one horizontal and two vertical) that are
aligned with those of the semicircular canals. Shown here is the nucleus of the
optic tract (NOT), which encodes horizontal movement of the visual world,
that is, shifting images on the retina that are in the plane of the horizontal
semicircular canal (when the eye is centered in its socket). (2): Pathways for vi-
sual pursuit of objects in motion. In the monkey and in humans, the image of
the object in motion is transmitted to the lateral geniculate body (LGB) by reti-
nal neurons sensitive to movement, and from there to the visual cortex (cortical
areas V1, V2, and V3). Messages about movement are next transmitted to the
parietal cortical areas (7a, 7b, LIP, and so on), the areas of the mediotemporal
cortex (MT and MTS), and the frontal oculomotor field (FOF). From the cere-
bral cortex, control and pursuit signals are sent to the dorsolateral and
dorsomedial pontine nuclei (DLPN and DMPN).
BUILDING COHERENCE •
63
during pursuit of a target even if the target disappears for a brief moment.
Messages about eye movement, which are transmitted from the centers of the
brainstem and control eye muscle contractions, activate these neurons for a
brief instant after the light disappears and thus ensure that a person’s gaze will
be in the right spot when the target reappears. This convergence of external
and internal signals also enables us to make tracking movements toward tar-
gets that are actually motionless but that we perceive to be moving, as when a
row of targets is illuminated one after another and the brain creates a percept
of movement.13
Tracking signals next activate the centers of the brainstem (the pontine
nuclei) and of the cerebellum, linking the vestibular nuclei and other pre-
motor nuclei that project to the motor neurons of the eye muscles.
The second mechanism that enables us to follow the landscape from the bus is
a very old reflex action, the optokinetic reflex, present even in the fish and the
frog, who have no fovea. Actually, all sighted animals possess this mechanism,
which allows them to follow the movements of the visual environment. It also
contributes to maintenance of posture. If you tilt the aquarium in which it is
swimming, a fish will tilt its body to align it with whichever surface of the
aquarium is lit.
The nerve pathway that processes these signals thus also influences the
centers that control posture. Anatomists discovered it a long time ago and
called it the accessory optic pathway for want of understanding its function.
What is remarkable is that all along this pathway neurons respond to visual
movements in preferred directions aligned along the planes of the semicircular
canals of the vestibular system.14
This alignment is also characteristic of the neurons of the retinal gan-
glia, which fire preferentially when the visual movement is in the plane of the
semicircular canals. This geometrical segregation becomes more pronounced
in the second relay. The neurons sensitive to movement in the plane of the
horizontal canal are united in the so-called nucleus of the optic tract (NOT)
following a very precise orientation, the temporonasal direction. Another nu-
cleus, called the medial terminal nucleus (MTN), contains the neurons sen-
sitive to downward visual movement, and yet another, the dorsal terminal nu-
cleus (DTN), contains those sensitive to upward visual movement. Other
groups of cells belonging to the same accessory optic system, situated in a re-
64 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
lay portion of the ventral tegmental area, encode combinations of rotational
and linear components of optic flow.
Consequently, just as information is broken down into its main compo-
nents (color, movement, contrast, texture, and so on) in the primary cortical
visual projections (V1–V4), the geometric properties of movement repre-
sented in optic flow are also segregated. This early segregation in the sequence
of neural processing is further refined in the next relay, the dorsal motor nu-
cleus of the inferior olive, a brainstem structure that projects to the cerebel-
lum, where some of the visuovestibular convergence takes place. This dorsal
motor nucleus contains three groups of neurons that correspond exactly to
the three planes of the canals. The next relay, the cerebellum, also contains
neurons, located in the flocculus, whose preferential planes of activation are in
those of the canals.
The existence of separate components organized according to the planes
of the semicircular canals clearly facilitates the convergence, that is, the fu-
sion, of these inputs, whose origin is visual, and those from the vestibular re-
ceptors, with which the visual messages converge.
The geometrical correspondence between the visual system and the semi-
circular canals extends to the motor system. Indeed, despite the migration of
the eyes from a lateral to a frontal position, the plane of action of the three
pairs of extraocular muscles, which enable rotation of the eyeball in all spe-
cies, has remained approximately parallel to the planes of the semicircular
canals.15
The demonstration of an organization in three planes was made using ten-
sor analysis and the theories of Pellionisz and Llinás. They proposed that the
muscles be represented by their eigenvectors, that is, their own virtual vectors
that represent the direction and amplitude of the force exerted by each mus-
cle. These vectors are classical mathematical quantities, but are very easy for
nonmathematicians to grasp. They have the advantage of being accessible to
experimentation: in animals or in humans, all that is needed is to establish
points of attachment of the muscles and to reconstruct the skeletal anatomy
of this motor apparatus, and then to record the activity of these muscles dur-
ing activation by tilting the head, which initiates the so-called vestibulo-nuchal
reflex. The eigenvectors of the neck muscles of a cat are situated in the plane
of the canals. The geometry of the semicircular canals is thus basic to the per-
ception and control of movement.
When a monkey jumps from branch to branch, when a diver leaps from
his diving board, or a gymnast grabs the high bar or jumps on a trampoline
BUILDING COHERENCE •
65
H
0.1 m
(Figure 3.3), the brain has to reconstruct the movement of the head in space
very rapidly and with the most exquisite precision. How does it do it using vi-
sual and vestibular information, and proprioceptive information from the
neck?
From the first central synapse, the velocity of the head in space is, in fact,
detected by combining the information supplied by the vestibular accelerome-
ters and the visual tachometer. This discovery was made by recording the neu-
rons of the vestibular nuclei in the fish and, later, in the monkey.16 These nu-
clei are located in the brainstem and constitute the first central relay of
vestibular information; that is, the fibers of the semicircular canals project di-
66 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
rectly to them. They are called vestibular nuclei (see Figure 2.4) for purely ana-
tomical reasons.
The famous experiment of Dichgans and his co-workers is a good illustra-
tion of the way vision and the vestibular receptors cooperate in detecting
movement of the head. Dichgans and his group put their fish on a turntable
and subjected them to three separate experiments. First, a rotation in the dark,
broken down into three stages: acceleration, then constant velocity, finally de-
celeration. We can replicate this stimulus by making a few turns with our eyes
closed. The form of the stimulus is a trapezium of velocity: one or two inter-
vals of acceleration separated by constant velocity. The vestibular receptors
are activated only by the acceleration and do not fire until the animal begins
to turn or when it brakes. The neurons of the vestibular nuclei respond to
such stimulation by increasing their discharge followed by a slow diminution
after 10 to 20 seconds. Consequently, the brain receives no information about
the rotation of the head during the period of rotation at constant velocity. It is
the same for us if we twirl around for some time: when the effect of the tran-
sitory activation of the canals wears off, we can no longer perceive any move-
ment if all we have is the vestibular information.
In the second experiment, the animal was immobilized and the visual
world rotated around it, using a rotating cylinder. The researchers observed
that these neurons, called vestibular, are also activated by visual movement.
This activation is due to transmission along the pathways of the accessory op-
tic system. The activity increases very slowly at first, then holds steady during
the rotation, and finally diminishes slowly, the animal immobile the whole
time.
The third experiment involved rotating the animal in light. Combining vi-
sual and vestibular stimuli by imitating a natural rotation, the neurons of the
vestibular nuclei, like the velocity of rotation of the head, fire in a trapezoidal
pattern. In other words, the angular velocity of the head is perfectly repro-
duced from the first neural relays by means of the combination of dynamic
properties of the visual and vestibular receptors. This discovery was repeated
in several species (frog, rabbit, cat, monkey): it is thus very likely true for hu-
mans as well.
We are aware of the angular velocity of the head thanks to the sensitivity
to rotation of both the visual and vestibular systems. Vision alone is not suf-
ficient—it is too slow. The contribution of the vestibular receptors is to inform
the brain about the movement under way by virtue of their having detected
derivatives of displacement (velocity and acceleration). The term “dynamic
complementarity” is certainly apropos.
BUILDING COHERENCE •
67
Moreover, the neurons of the vestibular nuclei do not only receive visual
and vestibular information: they are also sensitive to activation of the muscle
receptors in the neck. Very short synaptic pathways connect them to the
neuromuscular spindles (numerous in the muscles of the neck), which detect
the length and velocity of muscle stretch. When the head turns, the brain is
informed of the rotation by this combination of visual, vestibular, and pro-
prioceptive information. From the very beginning—from the first synapse of
the central nervous system—the detection of movement is multisensory.
Motor
M
center
Efferent
Perception P
copy
R E
Receptor Effector
Figure 3.4. The principle of efferent copy according to von Holst and
Mittelstaedt. Sensory signals are sent to the neural centers where perception is
derived. A motor command travels in a loop from these centers to the effectors
(the muscles). But a copy of the motor command is also sent to the perceptual
centers, where it alters sensory information according to the ongoing action.
The brain is thus able to anticipate the results of movement without having to
wait for information from the sensors.
The question has not yet been answered. For some, it is a simple change of co-
ordinates; for others, it has to do with the coordination of the eyes and the
head. In all these cases, the data show that the senses are not isolated. Action
influences perception at its source.
I have described the nerve pathways that transmit the movement detected
by vision to the cerebral cortex. I have also analyzed the vestibular detection
of head movement and the mechanisms by which vision is enhanced by
the vestibulo-ocular reflex. But vestibular information does not remain at the
level of the first sensory relays. It is also transmitted to the cerebral cortex,
where it contributes to many functions: conscious perception of orientation,
gaze movements, control of posture, coordination of gestures. It also plays a
role in constructing a coherent perception of the relationships between the
body and space. This vestibular contribution to the highest cognitive functions
was neglected until recently. Yet, a few pioneers such as Penfield had consid-
ered it.
Penfield’s subjects reported that they felt vertigo or rotating sensations,
characteristic of the vestibular system, during electrical stimulation of a tem-
BUILDING COHERENCE •
69
Motor nucleus
of the eye
Eye VI
movement
Vestibular
Vision Vestibular nuclei
neuron
Vestibular
receptors
Medulla
Figure 3.5. Second-order vestibular neurons are influenced by the direction of
gaze. A second-order vestibular neuron transmits movements of the head de-
tected by the semicircular canals to the muscles of the eyes. One can see the
axonal branching to various centers of the brain that process this information.
This neuron is the first sensory relay for vestibular information, but it receives
signals from vision and receptors in the muscles and joints as well. It also re-
ceives copies of the motor commands for eye movements.
poroparietal region.21 It also has been known for a long time that illusions of
dissociation of the body are induced during the aura—that is, alteration of
consciousness—that often precedes seizures in patients suffering from tempo-
ral lobe epilepsy.22 During an epileptic fit, these patients sometimes have the
feeling that they are simultaneously lying in their bed and floating at the level
of the ceiling, as if their body were split. The area of the brain responsible for
these illusions is located deep within the lateral sulcus, around the superior
temporal gyrus, at the caudal portion of the insula and along the retroinsular
region, near the auditory area.
Messages of vestibular origin contribute to the most cognitive aspects of
the body schema and of spatial representation.23 In humans, the existence of
this vestibular cortical area was recently confirmed by brain-imaging meth-
ods.24 Patients with lesions of the parieto-insular zone present with devia-
tions of the vertical subjective: the world appears to them to be leaning to
70 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
the side opposite the lesion. The effect is so strong that they take skewed pho-
tographs.25
A Neural Compass?
Sit in a revolving chair. Look at an object in front of you, close your eyes, then
make one or two turns. Even with your eyes closed, you will find you can still
point to the object. A neural mechanism of vestibulary origin assesses the di-
rection of the head in the horizontal plane, memorizes it, and updates it dur-
ing the movement. One of the most important discoveries of recent years was
that of the existence of neurons whose discharge is connected to the orienta-
tion of the head in the horizontal plane. These neurons have been identified in
the thalamus of the rat.32 The thalamus transmits sensory information to the
cortex and the postsubiculum, the nucleus of the hippocampal formation,
which, as I will explain later in detail, plays a role in spatial memory.
These neurons signal the direction of the head no matter where an animal
is in a room, a property that is called local invariance. Thus they constitute an
internal compass. It is a sophisticated compass, because it indicates a wide
range of directions. For example, one of these neurons, silent when the rat
BUILDING COHERENCE •
73
moves its head in many directions, suddenly starts to fire when the animal
turns toward the north, no matter where the animal is in the room. These
neurons are, however, very dependent on the local visual environment. The
animal has to be familiar with the room it is in for the directions preferred by
each neuron to be well stabilized. When the animal’s location in the room is
changed, its directional neurons are reorganized. But what is really remarkable
is that when the animal is familiar with a location, the neurons do not lose
their sensitivity to a given direction in the dark. It follows that these neurons
participate in spatial memory.
Vestibular information about head orientation is transmitted from the me-
dial vestibular nucleus to the dorsolateral thalamus and from there to the
hippocampal formation. It is also known that the hippocampus contains an-
other category of neurons, the place cells. These cells, independent of the di-
rection of the head, discharge when the animal is in a given location. It is thus
possible that memory of the object, in the experiment above, is due to vestibu-
lar information, which can update representations of space in the hippocam-
pus. I will come back to this topic in Chapter 5.
Neglect
Constructing a coherent perception of the relationships between the body and
space thus depends on both hierarchical and parallel mechanisms that com-
bine sensory cues and signals connected to action. So it is not surprising that
lesions or deficits in certain circuits induce a breakup of this coherence. One
example, which I will mention very briefly, is spatial neglect.
Patients who have a lesion of the right parietal cortex often present with
impaired space perception. Although they are looking at space in its entirety,
they can only perceive the right side, and they neglect the left side. Hence the
name of this illness: hemispatial neglect. If you ask these patients to draw a
flower, they will only draw the petals on the right side; if you ask them to
draw a clock, they will only draw the hours from 12 to 6; if you ask them to
paint objects, they will only paint one half of each object; finally, they will
only eat what is on one side of a dish of strawberries, and so on. These pa-
tients do not have all these symptoms at once. In fact, it is possible to distin-
guish several kinds of neglect: for example, personal, a person who neglects
his left arm; extrapersonal, a person who neglects to draw objects on the left
side of the room; or representational, a person who cannot picture the left
side of his living room, of his apartment, or of his city. It is also possible to dis-
tinguish perceptual from motor neglect. Motor neglect consists in not using a
limb even though its motor function is intact. Several authors have made the
74 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
remarkable observation that the simple injection of cold water into the left
ear—that is, introduction of a vestibular caloric stimulus—causes some of the
symptoms of neglect to disappear temporarily.33 This effect is not due to the
deviation of the eye induced by the stimulus.
Patients with spatial neglect sometimes have associated neurological defi-
cits, such as hemianopia (loss of vision for one half of the visual field) and
hemianesthesia (anesthesia of one half of the body).34 These deficits, appar-
ently primary—affecting primary structures in the sensory areas of the cor-
tex—also sometimes disappear after injection of cold water; in other words,
following a vestibular stimulus.35 Almost complete—albeit temporary—remis-
sion of hemianesthesia following damage to the right cerebral cortex is also
obtained as well as improvement of other impairments of the perception of
the body.36 For example, certain patients no longer feel it when someone
touches their hand. Bottini and co-workers found that vestibular stimulation
restores perception of touch in a transitory manner.37 Brain activity in such a
patient was recorded with the aid of positron emission tomography. In normal
subjects, tactile and vestibular signals share projections to the neurons of the
putamen, insula, somatosensory areas of the cortex, premotor cortex, and the
supramarginal gyrus. Some of these areas that were intact in this patient were
activated by the vestibular stimulus at the same time that sensation reap-
peared. Thus, “the somatosensory primary cortex has no priority for tactile
perceptual consciousness; rather, multiple sensory representations of the body
exist in the brain and any of these can contribute to perception.”38
Vestibular stimulation has a spectacular effect on self-awareness of body
parts. In particular, it offers relief from somatoparaphrenia. Patients with this
illness deny possession of their own limbs.39 For example, one patient denied
that her left arm was her own.40 She said: “This is my mother’s arm.” We in-
jected water into her ear (caloric stimulation of the vestibular receptors), and
this woman reclaimed possession of her arm. Unfortunately, the effect was
only temporary.
These observations suggest that spatial neglect has a single cause con-
nected to the representation of the body schema, even though it has multiple
manifestations. The efficacy of the vestibular stimulation could be due to a ba-
sic imbalance induced by the lesion and compensated for by an imbalance in
the opposite direction produced by the stimulus through the ascending vestib-
ular pathways described above, as well as through those that correspond to
the “directional neurons of the head.” If this assumption is correct, the fact
that the vibrations of the neck, the transcutaneous stimulation of the tactile
receptors, optokinetic stimulus, and wearing prism goggles also produce a
BUILDING COHERENCE •
75
remission of spatial neglect is not surprising, given the multimodal conver-
gences toward all the centers of the vestibular pathways.41 I emphasized above
that several structures formerly called vestibular are in fact multimodal and
are involved in reconstructing orientation and movement of the head in space.
These considerations are important because they provide a biological basis
for so-called out-of-body parapsychic phenomena. Quacks who may profit
from such bizarre perceptions to exploit the credulity and pocketbooks of
people by selling these illusions as supernatural phenomena should be de-
nounced.
Distance Perception
The perception of distance is another example of the multisensory nature of
perception. But, here again, the combining messages originate in part from
copies of the motor commands. In fact, the perception of distance is the result
of visual messages and signals from the convergence of the two eyes. Action is
used as information about the world.
Lorenz suggested that fish evaluate the distance of objects from the bot-
tom of the sea using a combination of visual information about disparity (that
is, the difference between the two images of the object supplied by the two
eyes) and to convergence of the two eyes on the object.42 The idea that the
perception of distance is due to a multisensory interaction was also formu-
lated by Poincaré: “However, sight enables us to appreciate distance, and
therefore to perceive a third dimension. But everyone knows that this percep-
tion of the third dimension reduces to a sense of the effort of accommodation
which must be made, and to a sense of the convergence of the two eyes, that
must take place in order to perceive an object distinctly.”43
Perception of distance is actually due to a combination of visual and mo-
tor inputs.44 In the primary visual area V1, certain neurons are activated by the
disparate images of the same object on the two eyes, with some connection to
the distance of the object. By presenting the animal with two patterned planar
images called “Julesz stereograms”—duplicating the two perspectives the two
eyes will have of the object—the apparent distance of the patterns can be
made to vary by varying only the disparity (or gap). Three kinds of neurons
from area V1 are activated respectively when the image is located behind or in
front of the point on which the eye is focused.
This sensitivity to retinal disparity can be modified by a nonvisual (extra-
retinal) signal. In fact, if the subject puts on prism goggles that bring the target
closer without changing the disparity, the two eyes converge. A neuron acti-
vated by a visual target 20 centimeters from the eye is activated again when
76 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
the target is 80 centimeters from the eye because of the prisms. This experi-
ment shows that a signal connected to the convergence of the two eyes modu-
lates the response of these neurons. The distance can also be ascertained by
measuring how much the eyes cross! The exact origin of these signals of con-
vergence is unknown. Two possibilities are the ocular muscle receptors or an
efferent copy of the motor command for convergence; in other words, a mo-
tor signal or a combination of the two. Many structures of the visual cortex—
V1, V2, MST, LIP (lateral intraparietal), PO (parieto-occipital), and so on—re-
ceive information about the position of the eyes in this way.
The idea that variables such as distance are constructed by unconscious in-
ferences, as Helmholtz suggested, is not accepted by all the philosophers. Even
Merleau-Ponty, whose ideas have been validated by experimentation, was con-
fused on this point: “How is it possible,” he writes, “to assert that perception
of distance is a construct of the apparent size of objects, of the disparity be-
tween the retinal images, of the accommodation of the lens, of the conver-
gence of the eyes, and that the perception of depth is a construct of the differ-
ence between the image supplied by the right eye and that supplied by the left,
when, if we hold to phenomena, none of these ‘signs’ is clearly presented to
our consciousness? How can we reason in the absence of premises?”45
What of the cooperation between two other sensory modalities, sight and
hearing? Everyone knows that you can catch an object more easily if, at the
same time you see it, you hear it coming. This cooperation brings into play a
special structure of the brain, the superior colliculus. Essentially a biological
machine that recognizes moving objects and identifies their distinctive features
using multisensory cues, the superior colliculus holds the key to how the brain
directs multisensory fusion and extraction of pertinent signals. It controls ori-
entation and avoidance reactions, among other behaviors, and it is a splendid
example of a sensory and motor structure that directs the execution and cor-
rection of movements carried out by multiple effectors like the eyes, the head,
the trunk, and the limbs.
It is impossible to catch moving prey without focusing in front of where
the prey is and very rapidly correcting the trajectory in the event of error. The
colliculus is thus involved in anticipation and motor prediction. Its presence
also explains how the brain assembles motor commands in a manner suf-
ficiently general for the movement to be accomplished by a variety of effect-
ors (tongue, hand or paw, foot, and so on) with differing dynamic properties.
BUILDING COHERENCE •
77
The colliculus (from the Latin collis, hill), called the optic tectum in non-
mammalian vertebrates, is composed of two symmetrical parts (hence the ex-
pression “the colliculi”). There is a superior colliculus and an inferior col-
liculus. I will consider the superior colliculus here. Lesions of this organ cause
impaired reactions of orientation and of catching a target. A damaged animal
can catch a mouse, but less rapidly, which indicates its ecological importance.
The superior colliculus is composed of seven layers of nerve fibers and neu-
rons, and its complexity is formidable. There are, however, three principal lay-
ers, called, prosaically, superficial, intermediary, and deep. These neurons re-
ceive information from more than twenty cerebral structures. The afferents of
the superior colliculus are mainly visuosensory, proprioceptive (also called so-
matic), and auditory. But it receives many cortical projections as well as pro-
jections from structures such as the basal ganglia, the cerebellum, and so on.
Other afferents, whose functions are poorly understood, come from structures
such as the raphe nucleus and the locus ceruleus. As Stein and Meredith sum
up, “Some of these latter inputs may play a role in varying the likelihood of a
given movement depending on the prior experience and immediate needs of
the organism.”46
First I will address the visual responses. If you move a point of light in
front of an animal, the neurons of the colliculus, like those of the visual cor-
tex, will respond with a discharge of action potentials. The response to the vi-
sual stimulus is selective for a particular region of visual space (this is the idea
of a receptor field). The receptor fields of these neurons are expansive. They
are bordered by an inhibitory region: if a target is present simultaneously in
the center of the receptor field and at the periphery, the response from the
center is reduced. The size of the effective stimulus is, in general, less than
that of the receptor field. Some neurons are particularly sensitive to move-
ment in certain directions. Finally, repeated exposure induces a habituation
that results in extinction of the discharge. The colliculus participates in detect-
ing the unusual. If the animal turns its attention to the visual target, the sen-
sory response is increased. This amplification of the response to a stimulus
adds weight to arguments in favor of the active character of perception.
Amplification also takes place just before an ocular saccade toward the target;
further proof that intended movement modulates the sensitivity of the first
sensory relays.
In the deep layers of the colliculus are neurons that project to the brain-
stem and the medulla where they induce ocular movements toward the target
(saccades) (Figure 3.6). A crossed projection is involved in orienting move-
ments of the head, the eyes, the trunk, and perhaps the limbs. Another, un-
78 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
Tecto-reticulo-spinal
Superior
neuron (TRSN)
colliculus
Electrodes for injection
and recording
toward
the spinal
cord
5 mm Reticulospinal
neuron
Figure 3.6. The neurons of the superior colliculus project to the motor centers
of the eyes and the head. The colliculus and the motor centers of the
brainstem interact to control movements and posture during orientation of the
head toward an object. The tecto-reticulo-spinal neuron (TRSN) connects the
colliculus to the brainstem. It is active when an animal directs its gaze to a vi-
sual target. It projects to neurons of the brainstem that activate the motor cen-
ters of the eyes, head, and perhaps the arms and trunk.
But the nervous system has other mechanisms for resolving the prob-
lem of time shift. The cerebellum receives sensory information from a wide
range of sources, in particular the proprioceptors of the limbs. It is important
for this structure to be able to compare the messages from the receptors of
the feet, arms, and neck, for example, because it is involved in coordinating
movements, especially via the precise temporal organization of gestures and
relationships between posture and movement. The solution used by the ner-
vous system may be to vary the velocity of conduction of the nerve fibers so
that all the signals arrive at the same time. The signals from the receptors of
the feet, located more than a meter from the cerebellum, are transmitted
more rapidly than those of the receptors of the neck located a few dozen
centimeters away! But the problem of time shifts is so important that the
brain has probably found numerous different solutions that should interest
roboticists.
82 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
The Visible and the Tangible
Many philosophers have emphasized the cooperation between vision and the
sense of touch. Merleau-Ponty wrote:
We must get used to the idea that everything visible emerges from what
is tangible; that every tactile being is destined in some way to be seen;
and that there is encroachment and overlap not just between touched
and touching but also between the tangible and the visible embedded in
it, just as, conversely, the tangible itself is not devoid of visibility, that is,
not without visual existence. Since the same body sees and touches, vis-
ible and tangible belong to the same world. A wonder too seldom no-
ticed is that any movement of my eyes—better yet, any displacement of
my body—has its place in the same visible universe, that through these
movements I examine and explore, just as, conversely, seeing occurs
somewhere in tactile space.50
Sartre, too, stressed the reciprocal analogies between vision and touch: “1.
A series of kinaesthetic (or tactile) impressions can function as analogue for a
series of visual impressions . . . 2. A movement (given as a kinaesthetic series)
can function as analogue for the trajectory that the moving body describes or
is assumed to describe, which means that a kinaesthetic series can function as
analogical substitute of a visual form.”51
The neuropsychologist De Ajuriaguerra, known for his rigorous analysis
of the relationships between mothers and infants, focused on the complex na-
ture of perception in his published work and in his courses at the Collège de
France. “Perception can be divorced neither from ocular motor function,” he
wrote,
nor from cognition, nor from the affective life of the subject. Perception
confirms the world of objects: there can be no cognizance of things and
beings without exploration: tactile, for the blind; tactile and visual, for
the sighted. Although it has been proposed that the two domains (optic
and haptic) are controlled by different laws, studies of blind subjects
who have recovered their sight show that they do experience some kind
of transfer between the two modalities.52
But Gross’s discovery had an even more profound impact on our under-
standing of multisensory functioning and mechanisms of interaction. Take
the properties of the neurons of the arm that are sensitive to stroking. In the
putamen, bimodal neurons have a tactile receptor field that is anchored to the
visual receptor field: if a monkey’s arm is placed on a table before it, the tactile
receptor field being, for example, on the wrist, the visual receptor field will be
within a cone connecting the gaze to the wrist or in a space surrounding the
wrist. If then the monkey’s arm is moved, its visual receptor field will follow
to stay in the same spatial register as its arm. This spatial updating is probably
a response to proprioceptive signals; it can be induced by copies of motor
commands.
86 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
Husserl57 refers to an experiment of touching. When I touch my left
hand with my right hand, my touching hand grasps my touched hand
like an object. But suddenly I notice that my left hand is beginning to
feel. The relationships are reversed. We experience an overlap between
the contribution of the left hand and that of the right hand, and a rever-
sal of their function. As a physical object the hand always remains what
it is, and yet it is different according to whether it is touched or touching.
Merleau-Ponty often comes back to this example, which for him remains one
of the great mysteries of perception. I have put the final part of the last sen-
tence in italics, because it suggests very clearly how the idea of perception is
different in these two cases, one where the limb is touched passively, and the
other where it is touched by a motion the subject makes himself. This long
philosophical introduction is just to say that evidence now exists of a differ-
ence in activity of the neurons of the brain between these two cases.
Tactile perception is not only connected with vision, it is also influenced
by the active character of visual attention. In one zone of the superior tem-
poral sulcus (STS) in the monkey, neurons are activated when the hand of
the monkey is lightly stroked with a stick; but if the monkey grabs the stick
himself, the same neurons stop firing. The active movement suppresses the
transmission of tactile information. Perrett attributes this disappearance of
response to the predictive character of the contact, and observes that the neu-
rons of this area are very sensitive to unpredictable tactile stimuli.58 In con-
trast, when the movement of the animal induces the contact, a still mysterious
mechanism of inhibition suppresses the activity. This observation corresponds
very well with the subjective impression that we have of a very reduced sensa-
tion of contact when we touch ourselves.
This selectivity also holds true for vision: the cells of the STS sensitive to
the entry of visual objects into the visual field of the monkey lose their sensi-
BUILDING COHERENCE •
87
tivity when the arm of the animal comes into the field. These effects are not
due to the simple fact of attention. They are actually very selective inhibitions
of an aggregate of multisensory properties (texture, visual aspect, space) of a
part of the body of a monkey or a known object. Perception is selection and
anticipation. Time will reveal their mechanisms.
This selection by anticipation is not an isolated case: there are many ac-
counts of reduced effects of sensory stimuli due to self-activity of the animal.
For example, the Purkinje cells in the cerebellar cortex—an organ important
for the coordination of gestures—respond much less to cutaneous stimuli
when animals make endogenous movements than when experimenters touch
them. Generally, the effect of a sensory stimulus is reduced during endoge-
nous movements. However, when the task is new, or when a stimulus is unex-
pected, sensitivity is restored. In a recent review, Prochazska concluded: “We
have seen many examples of task and context-dependent sensory transmission
in widely ranging species and widely ranging motor behaviours. From all this
it seems safe to conclude that anticipatory gain control of sensory transmis-
sion is indeed a fundamental strategy of motor systems.”60
90 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
Finally, sensory inputs are often fuzzy. They produce innumerable random
fluctuations that are unrelated to the magnitude detected. This noise is due to
the chemical and mechanical properties, among others, of transduction, but
also to neural noise introduced into central relays.
So the problem of coherence is not only a problem of geometry or of
dynamics. It assumes active central mechanisms that permit resolution of am-
biguities, catching up with or anticipating differential delays between recep-
tors, unifying space via clever biological mechanisms that are more than just
changes of coordinates, and so on. A genuine theory of coherence has yet to
be constructed.
I will start from the supposition that constructing coherence is not only an
effect of convergence, but also the product of a central activity that depends
on the knowledge of a priori mechanisms that each species possesses. “I real-
ised,” wrote Marcel Proust,
that it is not only the physical world that differs from the aspect in
which we see it; that all reality is perhaps equally dissimilar from what
we believe ourselves to be directly perceiving and which we compose
with the aid of ideas that do not reveal themselves but are none the less
efficacious, just as the trees, the sun and the sky would not be the same
as what we see if they were apprehended by creatures having eyes dif-
ferently constituted from ours, or else endowed for that purpose with
organs other than eyes which would furnish equivalents of trees and
sky and sun, though not visual ones.62
BUILDING COHERENCE •
91
struct variables relevant to the behavior and action of the organism. To this
end, it uses the fact that messages about movement, supplied by the array of
sensory receptors, are in general redundant. In other words, the same move-
ment variable can be calculated or estimated by several combinations of re-
ceptors, in addition to any specialized receptors.
The angular velocity of the head in space during movement provides a
good example. It is an important variable because it is a derivative of displace-
ment. One can thus integrate (in the mathematical sense) and obtain a dis-
placement that the brain will use either to activate stabilizing reflexes or to es-
timate trajectories or even to coordinate the movements of the eyes, head,
hands, and so on.
According to the basic assumption of the model of Droulez and Darlot,
the brain estimates this velocity of the head in at least two ways. The first, di-
rect, is detection by a specialized receptor, the semicircular canals, which de-
tect angular acceleration of the head in its plane, called the horizontal plane.
But this specialized receptor transmits a velocity to the brain, because its
viscoelastic properties delay the signals. This is precisely what an integrating
filter does. The second, indirect, way that the brain estimates the head’s veloc-
ity is a multisensory convergence of other variables—for example, the velocity
of retinal slip and that of the eye in its socket. Adding these all together gives
an estimation of the angular velocity of the head.
The main measure of this model is thus the discrepancy between a specific
sensory input and a prediction of this variable from combinations of other
signals. It was first suggested in 1989 to account for the fusion of the sen-
sory messages supplied by the semicircular canals, the otoliths, and vision.
Droulez and Cornilleau-Pérès wrote:
The fact that individual sensors provide reliable information only in a
limited (and sometimes variable) working range, in both spatial and
temporal domains, and the fact that the degradation of the measure by
noise can depend on the context (see for instance the analysis of optic
flow) and the existence of multiple interpretations suggest that sensory
signals cannot be processed as a set of measures but as a series of con-
straints upon the internal estimates. We suggest that sensory signals are
not used to directly estimate the relevant variables but to estimate the mis-
match between internal estimates and measures.64
For example, it really does seem that in vision the brain employs at least
two constraints: continuity and rigidity. Indeed, the objects that surround us
are in general locally continuous (that is, they are not divided). The painters
92 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
called pointillists provided a vision of nature that only makes sense because it
is filtered by the continuity of perception. Moreover, objects are generally
rigid. A body of evidence shows that the brain makes these assumptions of
continuity and rigidity, which helps in constructing coherence. The brain also
favors symmetry and thus tends to impose symmetry on the world it per-
ceives.
But the neural basis of coherence is still not well understood. In all likeli-
hood, coherence is due, in part, to the simultaneity of neural activities in sev-
eral parts of the brain.65 Many recent theories and experimental results in fact
suggest that establishing relations among features of perception that have
been analyzed separately in several areas of the brain might also be achieved
by temporal synchronization; that is, simultaneous activation of several
groups of neurons. This temporal encoding most likely takes a variety of
forms that have yet to be discovered.
Autistic children develop what Uta Frith calls a “local coherence.” She cites
another case; that of Elly, a child who had constructed a system of telling time
based on the shadow of her body cast by the sun.
(For instance, Elly paid close attention to shadows because they were
for some reason important and meaningful to her, and very relevant
to her moods. When she travelled to a different time zone, she was
alarmed that her shadow at 6 pm was not where it would have been at
home. She could not relax until her mother had explained to her that
6 pm on her watch meant it was only 5 pm at the new place.) This exam-
ple suggests that Elly had a limited but strongly coherent scheme about
the position of the sun at a certain time and the length of her shadow. It
really mattered to her when there were unexpected discrepancies. The
scheme had to be kept coherent. This insistence on sameness is a type
of local coherence. It is not at all like central coherence.67
94 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
I think this example is very interesting because Elly had devised a method but
had great difficulty placing it in a broader context—in thinking about changes
in time zones, for example.
Interestingly, studies in cognitive psychology on the problem of decision
making show that our cognitive apparatus makes many mistakes, due in large
part to our inability to depart from stereotyped schemas characterized by Uta
Frith’s local coherence. We have trouble revising according to context. The
perseveration of autistic children, their immutability, is perhaps only an ex-
treme version of many widespread behaviors.
But the most interesting aspect of Uta Frith’s theory is that she goes even
further in the analysis of the importance of coherence: coherence, she says, is
necessary not only to construct a perception of the body or of its relationship
with the environment, but also to elaborate what is called a theory of mind.
This notion was invented by psychologists to refer to the fact that we attribute
thoughts to others, that we have an idea, a theory of what they have in their
minds, of their intentions, and so on. Premack showed that this ability to at-
tribute thoughts to others shows up in nonhuman primates, and he gives sev-
eral examples of it. And actually anybody who has a dog will have noticed this
faculty in the animal. Uta Frith says with respect to the autistic child: “We
have hypothesized that they [autistic children] do not have the basic propen-
sity to pull together vast amounts of information from events, objects, people
and behaviour. Even if they had the cognitive prerequisites that enable them
to mentalize, they would only form ‘small’ theories about mental states, but
not a comprehensive theory of mind. Autistic children are behaviourists. They
do not expect people to be kind or to be cruel. They take behaviour as it is.”68
She is right in saying that if autistic children have no coherent representa-
tion of the world, they cannot construct a theory of mind for others and thus
communicate. It is certainly not possible to make any internal assumptions
about the intentions of others if one has not succeeded in giving coherence to
one’s perception of relationships between oneself and the environment, and
with all the information it contains.
Uta Frith completed her analysis by observing in autistic children the im-
pairment of what she calls “planning functions” (working memory, control of
impulses), which are normally a function of the frontal lobe of the cerebral
cortex. There is a paradox here, for although the impairments of autistic chil-
dren imply a deficit of the frontal lobe, patients presenting with this deficit are
not autistic. It is possible that the question is one of differences connected to
stage of development.
BUILDING COHERENCE •
95
In any case, how is it possible to imagine that children can coherently eval-
uate the people they see if they cannot evaluate relationships between their
own bodies and the environment? How is it thinkable that children who per-
ceive only a fragmented universe would have any desire to talk? How can be-
ings whose brains are the center of multiple incongruities have even the slight-
est desire to communicate with a world with which they cannot identify?
Finally, I would like to suggest a reason why autistic children have dif-
ficulty in perceiving the “global” features of the world and are confined to “lo-
cal” events. My hypothesis is that they may not be able to mentally manipulate
“allocentric” relations in their perception of space and remain stuck at “ego-
centric” coding of space, as discussed in Chapter 5.
96 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
4
FRAMES OF REFERENCE
The concept of a frame of reference is tied to that of space. Our actions un-
fold in a space organized, according to Grüsser, into “personal” space, “extra-
personal” space, and “far” space.2 Each of these spaces is itself organized into
several subspaces explorable by different mechanisms that provide distinct
frames of reference.
The first experimental proof that the distinction between personal and
extrapersonal space had a neural basis was supplied by Hyvarinen3 and con-
firmed by Mountcastle and his students.4 Neurons situated in the parietal cor-
tex of the monkey fire each time a person enters its grasping space with a
grape. The sight of the grape (monkeys are fond of them) outside of this
space is not enough to trigger the activity of these neurons.
Personal space consists of self-space (egocentered). It is perceived by the
internal senses and is in principle located within the limits of a person’s own
body. But there are some important distinctions. First, the body can be per-
ceived as an external object, especially by vision. The hand that I see at the
end of my arm is not necessarily my own (in Chapter 2 we described the case
of a patient who denied possession of her arm). Thus, attributing an element
perceived by the body to itself requires a perceptual decision. The dissocia-
tions and denials of ownership of elements of the body that manifest in cer-
tain illnesses are all too familiar. Moreover, a perception of the body can occur
even in the absence of parts of the body. The case of phantom limbs, for in-
stance, reveals the existence of mental representations of the body—that is, in-
ternal models of the body independent of its presence. Patients whose arms
have been severed feel their arms perfectly and even feel the movement of
their hands. Sometimes the presence of the whole body is perceived as ambig-
uous, and the subject may experience a phenomenon called autoscopy.
Grasping space is itself divisible into intraoral and perioral space—espe-
cially important during the first six months of life—as well as into other local
spaces connected to specific activities related to grasping. It is marked out by
visual, tactile, and olfactory cues. Indeed, the perception of the body can be
extended by a tool. For example, you feel the tip of your hand as if it were at
the end of the pencil you are holding: the body extends into the tool. Contact
with the ground is felt at the end of stilts, the driver of a car feels the wheels
on the ground, and it is well known that pilots feel the wheels of the airplane
on landing as if they were their own feet. Haptic sensations play a decisive role
in these perceptions. This property of the body—integrating with the physical
elements it has grasped—is very important, for it often determines the frame
98 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
of reference. What is remarkable about this extension is that the object is per-
ceived where it is supposed to be in the extrapersonal space and not at the
point of contact of the instrument with the body. The brain is able to con-
struct a spatially correct extension.
This ability to extend the body and to localize the point of contact is prob-
ably acquired very early, during multiple movements the baby makes in carry-
ing things to its mouth. If the object is long, the baby’s brain learns to corre-
late the tactile sensations of the hand holding the object with the sensations of
the mouth. The essential element of this connection seems, to me, to be the
rigidity of the object, which introduces covariations of pressure between the
two zones (hand and mouth) costimulated by the object. The assumed rigidity
of objects is an important property that turns up again in the visual perception
of their curvature and shape. In this case, it is said that the brain formulates a
rigidity hypothesis. The brain makes assumptions about the world based on
which it constructs internal models of reality. In the case of extension through
a tool, over the course of development a simple correlation between two parts
of the body could become the simulation of a correlation between a part of
the body (the one that is holding the tool) and a point in space.
Gravity
The semicircular canals of the vestibular organ define a basic Euclidean frame
of reference that may be at the root of our geometric perception of space. By
100 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
its very structure, it provides a reference frame only for movements of the
body. It is an egocentric system.
Nature bequeathed us another frame of reference connected to external
space: gravity. From our perspective, this omnipresent force has several very
important features. First, it does not vary in magnitude or direction with re-
spect to a plane tangential to the ideal surface of the earth—it is a constant of
terrestrial space. Second, it can be detected by specialized receptors, the oto-
liths. Finally, it constitutes a reference point external to the body and conse-
quently, as Paillard says, “an external plumb line” related to bodily movements
in a frame of reference he calls “geocentric.”6
To demonstrate the importance of this second frame of reference, I will
examine the bodily motion of a person who is jumping in a complicated way,
or running, or doing moguls down a ski slope; or the way storks fly, lions run,
and so on. My examination will reveal that during what André Thomas calls
“surplus equilibrium” (l’équilibre de luxe) with regard to movements in sports
or in dance, the head is stabilized in rotation.
I discovered that this property also applies to humans during daily locomo-
tor movements such as running. I took some photographs that Muybridge had
made of people in motion,7 and I drew on the photographs the line that con-
nects the external canthus (the corner) of the eye to the meatus of the ear
(Figure 4.1). This line is approximately parallel to one of the planes of the
semicircular canals. Making a montage of the photographs superimposing the
meatus of the ear on all of them revealed the head to be remarkably stable
during rotation. Using video cameras connected to a computer, we showed
that during walking, rotation of the head is stabilized about positions deter-
mined by the direction of gaze. In other words, we are not unlike birds when
they fly or gazelles and ostriches when they run. If you look at them on film,
you will see that their heads remain perfectly stable in relation to the vertical.
Most likely, the otoliths estimate how much the head is tilted with respect to
gravity.8 The direction of gaze determines the plane of stabilization.
It is as if the brain creates a stabilized platform to coordinate movements
of the limbs. In these complex movements, the feet rarely touch the ground,
so much so that the earth’s surface cannot serve as a reference point. The
brain uses the gravity detected by the vestibular system to stabilize the head
and create a mobile platform as a frame of reference. The advantage of this
solution is that because they do not undergo rotation, the visual and vestibular
receptors are freed from the problem of gravito-inertial differentiation that I
discussed in Chapter 2. They can cooperate better to detect translations based
on the information supplied by optic flow. Engineers who must control the
FRAMES OF REFERENCE •
101
Figure 4.1. In these drawings of a man running, the head is stabilized to control
posture and coordination of movements. Photographs by Muybridge were su-
perimposed at a single point of the head, the auditory meatus. While running,
the head is stabilized in rotation at an angle that depends on the direction of
gaze. This stabilization relies on the vestibular system, which detects the angle
of the head in relation to gravity. The straight line connects the canthus of the
eye with the meatus of the ear. It indicates roughly the plane of the horizontal
semicircular canal.
movement of satellites in space adopt the same principle. They attach a small
platform to the body of the satellite and stabilize its position with reference to
the stars.
Gravity intervenes in the organization of movements at specific times in
development. When its influence on young rats is altered, locomotion is sig-
nificantly delayed.9 Thus there is a period critical to motor function, around
ten days after birth, during which the nervous system needs gravity as a refer-
ence for organizing coordination of movements. This experiment supplies
additional evidence for the existence of critical periods such as that already
demonstrated in the development of the visual system.10 In this latter case,
proprioceptive information is important for specifying the directional sensitiv-
ity of the neurons of the visual cortex.
We have thus far considered the influence of tactile, optic and labyrin-
thine impressions on the functions of equilibration and co-ordination,
and it has been shown that the influence of each is capable of experi-
mental demonstration. Though these are apparently the main factors in
the general synaesthesis, the possible participation of other afferent fac-
104 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
tors in the general result is not absolutely excluded . . . But there appear
to me grounds for attributing some influence to visceral impressions. It
is well known that cats and other members of the family Felidae, in-
cluding animals which possess in a marked degree the faculty of equili-
bration, have in their mesentery relatively large numbers of Pacinian
corpuscles, which are specially adapted for transmitting pressure stimuli
to the sensory or afferent centres . . . It would seem, therefore, not im-
probable that the viscera are in relation with the centres of equilibra-
tion, and that they mutually affect each other. This is supported by the
phenomenon of a distressing form of dyspepsia, characterised by sud-
den attacks of giddiness, described by Trousseau under the name of ver-
tigo a stomacho laeso.16
FRAMES OF REFERENCE •
105
origin (righting reflexes) automatically trigger the coordination of motor ac-
tivity required for the animal to get back up. He also discovered that simply
pressing a board held parallel to the surface of the ground to the exposed
flank of the prone animal inhibited the righting reflex.18
Interpreting this observation is straightforward. Righting reflexes are trig-
gered by asymmetric impulses of vestibular origin and by the visual detection
of body tilt in relation to the visual vertical. But when a board is pressed to the
flank of the animal, the tactile information supplied by the pressure of the
ground on one side and of the board on the other gives the brain symmetrical
information. Apparently, the brain’s confidence in this tactile information (en-
gineers would call it gain, neurophysiologists synaptic weight) is sufficient to
block the righting reflex. This old experiment argues for my hypothesis that
the brain uses configurations of receptors to work out a perception and initi-
ate action.
Experiments in space have contributed further proof.19 On the ground, a
subject was positioned before a disk rotating in a vertical plane, which caused
a circular vection.20 A very slight tactile stimulation of his shoulder, which trig-
gered a tactile asymmetry, markedly increased the discrepancy between the
true vertical and the perceived vertical. In space, aboard the American space
shuttle, floating and holding on only to a bite bar with his teeth, the astronaut
felt a considerably stronger vection and had the impression that the vertical he
perceived was turning along with him. The absence of gravity and the lack of
contradiction between visual and tactile information increased the credibility,
for the brain, of bodily rotation.
Here, now, is the rotisserie experiment. A subject lying on a bed can dis-
cern which way is up without difficulty. Lackner had the idea of placing a sub-
ject in a machine developed during the 1950s by American air force research-
ers interested in how the otolithic organs of the vestibular system detect the
vertical.21 This machine looks like a rotisserie. Subjects are laid in it horizon-
tally, as if they were brochettes or chickens, and turned at a constant velocity
around a rotational axis perpendicular to terrestrial gravity.
When they are in the light, with their eyes open, subjects have no trouble
perceiving the direction of their rotation. If the light is switched off, they have
only vestibular and tactile information to rely on for detecting the axis of their
rotation. The semicircular canals are stimulated by the initial acceleration and
the otoliths by the sweep of the components of gravity in the planes of the re-
spective maculae of the utricle and the saccule. Then, because the velocity of
the rotation is constant, and the angular acceleration therefore nil, the re-
106 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
sponse of the semicircular canals subsides after about 20 seconds. Only detec-
tion by the otoliths of the angle in relation to gravity persists. Consequently,
during rotation at constant velocity, only the otoliths and the skin contribute
to the perception of the direction of the body with respect to the vertical.
In general, the subject correctly perceives the axis of rotation in the dark.
But Lackner demonstrated that just manipulating tactile cues is sufficient to
completely alter the perception of orientation of the body. If the subject’s feet
are suddenly pressed, he has the impression of tipping up and rotating in a
vertical position. If his buttocks are pressed, he feels as though he is sitting and
spinning in a chair. If his head is pressed, he experiences conical motion about
his head at the apex. In other words, despite the sweep of pressure on the side
of the body, the brain treats the local point of pressure as a point of reference
that determines the perceived center of rotation. In this case, the tactile cues
determine the frame of reference in which the rotation occurs.
Sometimes the postural context affects how the brain interprets tactile
cues. An experiment of Gurfinkel’s is a nice illustration of this property. Lay
your hand flat, palm up, on a table and ask someone to draw a “p” on your
palm with a pencil. Now put your hand behind your back and ask the person
to repeat the drawing. You will note that in the second case you perceive the
letter as a “b” and not as a “p.” In other words, the same sensation yields a dif-
ferent perception according to the orientation of the hand in relation to the
body.
The extremely discontinuous character of these alterations in perception
shows that the brain carries out genuine perceptual decisions based on the state
of several receptors, which we call a configuration of receptors.
FRAMES OF REFERENCE •
107
Principal sulcus
PROPRIOCEPTION
Memory
space
VESTIBULAR
RECEPTORS
Frontal eye
field
Posterior
parietal cortex VISION
(7a, 7b, LIP, VIP,...)
Oculomotor
space
Ventral
premotor Superior
cortex colliculus
Parahippocampal
Body-part-centered Putamen
cortex Oculomotor
visuomotor space
space
Entorhinal
Body-part-centered cortex
visuomotor
space
Hippocampus
Environmental space
Figure 4.2. The brain uses multiple frames of reference. The information sup-
plied by the sensory receptors (proprioception, vestibular receptors, vision)
converges in the parietal cortex, where it is integrated with many other signals
about movements and planned actions. Actions are subsequently encoded in
varied frames of reference that correspond to multiple spaces relative to the
body or the environment, even to internal memory space.
108 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
But during hand-pointing tasks the brain also uses a point of rotation lo-
cated on the shoulder. In this way it constructs a local reference point to sim-
plify neurocomputation. The brain chooses a frame of reference connected to
the limb that is executing the movement. Yet again, the advantage is that it re-
duces the number of variables that need to be monitored (engineers say de-
grees of freedom), limiting the need for neurocomputation to the single part
of the body involved in the movement.
The idea that the brain can choose multiple frames of reference depending
on the task and the context is shown by the neurons discovered by Graziano
and Gross that I described in Chapter 3. Recall that they found bimodal neu-
rons in the putamen and parietal cortex whose visual and tactile receptor
fields remain anchored in space during the course of a movement. One inter-
pretation of these findings is that the spatial encoding of movement and the
position of the limbs is not experienced with respect to a single reference
frame, as the egocentric frame of reference might suggest. Instead, there are
many frames of reference, each related to a part of the body (eyes, limbs,
trunk, and so on) (Figure 4.2). Action appears to be organized in modules
based on a repertoire of specific types of actions (gaze, reaching, locomotion),
which are themselves organized by specific basal ganglia-thalamo-cortical
loops.
The convergence of sensory information is the result of integrating data
from the senses important for each limb. For example, neurons encode the po-
sition of the head based on convergence of visual cues and other cues from
the muscles of the neck that detect movement of the head on the trunk,
as well as cues from the vestibular receptors, which also detect movement of
the head.
All of these findings suggest that the brain uses not one but multiple frames of
reference according to the task at hand together with essential or available sen-
sory cues.
Perrett and co-workers showed that in the monkey, the neurons of the
temporal cortex are involved in recognizing faces.23 The retinal image of the
face is first broken down into fragments corresponding to the principal chan-
nels of the primary visual pathways that dissociate color, shape, movement,
and so on; then other neurons reconstruct the facial features. Certain of these
neurons are activated by the eyes, others by the hair, still others by the nose,
FRAMES OF REFERENCE •
109
and so on. These features then converge on neurons that respond to faces, but
which are also sensitive to behavior, such as the direction of gaze. This ability
to detect the direction of gaze is all-important to the monkey; it probably
helps to identify the intention of another of its kind: is it friend or foe?
In this chain of processing, the meaning of a facial image is gradually re-
constructed.24 In fact, there are neurons that detect whether the face is turned
sideways or facing front, and so on. At the next level, the face is situated in the
context of the body, and neurons fire when the face is associated with a body
facing front or turned sideways, and so on. Finally, other neurons fire when
the face is familiar: a cognitive level is reached that brings memory into play.
Up to that point, even in context, the face is processed in a frame of reference
centered on the observer. The multiplicity of neurons that respond to the
same face, whether it is viewed from different sides or from a different angle,
enable the brain to configure the activity of neurons that will respond to a
given face whatever the angle from which it is seen. This flexibility implies a
level of abstraction that is independent of the frame of reference in which the
visage is perceived.
It is also possible to imagine that frames of reference are constructed in
connection with action—for example, linked to an object, a goal, and so on.
The multiplicity of possible representations enables the brain to construct ad
hoc frames of reference. This hypothesis has yet to be verified, but will be ex-
traordinarily fruitful if it turns out to be correct. It would explain in part our
ability to do geometry, which requires us to mentally change our perspective
as we view tangible objects and the environment. For Kosslyn and his collabo-
rators, categorical spatial relations (front, back, above, and so on), which main-
tain constancy of certain relationships between objects or parts of the body,
are encoded by different mechanisms of metric spatial relations that specify
distances.25
Recognition Position
criteria
Size Orientation
Activation of
visual search
Visual
Visual location location
of target
Size Orientation
Target recognition recognition
location
Orientation
Visual and Size Visual and
tactile tactile
Activation of input input
reaching
Adjustment Grasping
Figure 4.3. How to grasp an object. The brain analyzes visual inputs with re-
spect to three properties: position, size, and orientation. Similarly, neural pro-
cesses analyze movement of the hand close to an object, adjustment of the
fingers to the size of the object, and a rotation of the pincer motion depending
on the orientation of the object.
the instant the movement is begun,28 Arbib suggests that the frame of refer-
ence used by the brain is relative, particularly the relationships between the
fingers (opposition space) that are about to grasp the object: “There is no one
absolute space represented in one place in the brain, only a coupling of sen-
sory and motor spaces in such a way as to yield movement to achieve some
goal.”29
A point of reference can thus be constructed on the basis of relationships
between parts of the body. It can also be constructed actively. For example, I
said earlier that the head is used as an inertial platform that is stabilized during
complex movements and especially when there is no reference to the ground.
In this case, the brain uses gravity to stabilize the head, which can then serve
as a point of reference for coordinating the limbs. I have emphasized that a
movement’s point of reference depends on the task.30 If I am holding a full
FRAMES OF REFERENCE •
111
glass of champagne while walking or bending over, I necessarily have to adjust
its movement to the direction of gravity so I do not spill it. But if I am reading
a book while walking, the objective of my movements is to minimize the rela-
tive movement between the page and my retina, and thus I adjust the move-
ment of my hand to that of my head.
It also must be considered that the brain constructs a series of frames of
reference for each phase of the same movement.31 This is illustrated by the
trampoline jumping shown in Figure 3.3. A new physiology is needed; one
that will investigate these rapid changes, these swings from one frame of refer-
ence to another. This flexibility is so basic that it must be programmed into
the very structure of the nervous system.
112 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
threshold is thus equivalent to a position, an angle of the arm. Feldman says
that it has a spatial dimension, and that the position is reached by regulating
the λ variables of the two antagonist muscles. According to this theory, there
is no need for space to be represented explicitly, for it is implicitly contained in
the regulation of the threshold. This fits the theories of Viviani and Flash on
the morphogenetic and creative properties of geometric trajectories and the
law of minimum jerk (Chapter 6).
Feldman shows that although his hypothesis is based on neuronal func-
tioning, it has an impact on the general problem of the frames of reference ac-
cording to which movements are organized.
These theoretical results can be understood in terms of physics. Body
movement is defined as a change in position in relation to another ob-
ject, frame of reference, or system of coordinates. But the Galilean
principle of the relativity of movement is implicit in the concept of
frame of reference: movement can also be induced by a displacement
of the frame of reference. The λ threshold can be considered as the
point of origin of a frame of reference for the mobilization of mo-
tor neurons. In displacing λ, the level of control specifies a new refer-
ence point and produces movement. In this way, displacements of the
positional frame of reference underlie the control of movement even
though activation of motor neurons and production of forces are a con-
sequence of this process.33
FRAMES OF REFERENCE •
113
explains the unity of perception of the body. An explanation of how these di-
verse local neuronal subsystems are integrated in a body schema is needed.
The situation of this science is a bit like the global political situation of the
1990s. In the wake of ideologies aimed at imposing a single model, there has
been a veritable explosion of nationalisms. There is no single frame of refer-
ence, but rather a fascination for the multiplicity of cultures. How will we
manage to put together from this a world that can account for both individual
differences and what might be termed the unity of man? This is the same
mammoth challenge facing the neurosciences.
114 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
5
A M E M O RY F O R P R E D I C T I N G
DECLARATIVE NONDECLARATIVE
(EXPLICIT) (IMPLICIT)
NONASSOCIATIVE
LEARNING
FACTS EVENTS “PRIMING”
eral moments in certain cases. The motor neurons of the medulla possess
what are called plateau potentials that maintain the depolarization of their
membranes. Other mechanisms at the cellular level, such as long-term poten-
tiation, which is most likely responsible for properties of memorization in the
hippocampus and the cortex, or long-term depression, discovered in the cere-
bellum by Ito and probably involved in plasticity, or even the slow potentials
due to calcium ions, are the elementary manifestations of memory, controlled
by molecular mechanisms among which the NMDA (N-methyl-d-aspartate)
synaptic receptor plays a major role. The phenomenon of the neural integra-
tor, which we discussed earlier with respect to the vestibulo-ocular reflex and
which transforms velocity signals into positional signals, is a specific case of
memory arising from the intrinsic properties of neurons or resulting from re-
verberating circuits in which a collateral signal is returned (positive feedback).
Other mechanisms call into play activities supported by oscillations of internal
neural circuits.
The discovery of the neural basis of these memories will in fact be one of
the major issues for neurobiology in the next century. Here I will consider just
one particular form of memory—spatial memory—which has not been exten-
sively studied by neuropsychologists but which nevertheless constitutes an im-
116 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
portant model for understanding the relation between perception and move-
ment.
Spatial memory is essential in representing space. Paillard defined its role
very clearly:2
Navigational Memory
Suppose that I ask you to recall the trip you make to get to work. You will
have to remember both the way, that is, the topographic aspects of the route,
and the movements you make walking or driving.
Topographic memory allows us to locate a place and to find our way back
to it. In a sense, it is a form of procedural memory, because it involves a suc-
cession of places or local scenes and movements (turning left, right, and so
on). But it can also be a mental survey of the places that represent the trip as
on a geographic map. It is believed that this kind of memory is responsible for
anamorphoses, or distorted images. For example, if a subject is asked to draw
With regard to the question of the means by which animals find their
way home from a long distance, a striking account, in relation to man,
will be found in the English translation of the Expedition to North Sibe-
ria, by Von Wrangell . . . He there describes the wonderful manner in
which the natives kept a true course towards a particular spot, whilst
passing for a long distance through hummocky ice, with incessant
changes of direction, and with no guide in the heavens or on the frozen
sea. He states (but I quote only from memory of many years standing)
that he, an experienced surveyor, and using a compass, failed to do that
which these savages easily effected. Yet no one will suppose that they
possessed any special sense which is quite absent in us. We must bear in
mind that neither a compass, nor the north star, nor any other such
sign, suffices to guide a man to a particular spot through an intricate
country, or through hummocky ice, when many deviations from a
straight course are inevitable, unless the deviations are allowed for, or a
sort of “dead reckoning” is kept. All men are able to do this in a greater
or lesser degree, and the natives of Siberia apparently to a wonderful
extent, though probably in an unconscious manner. This is effected
chiefly, no doubt, by eyesight, but partly, perhaps, by the sense of mus-
cular movement, in the same manner as a man with his eyes blinded
can proceed (and some men much better than others) for a short dis-
tance in a nearly straight line, or turn at right angles, or back again. The
manner in which the sense of direction is sometimes suddenly disar-
ranged in very old and feeble persons and the feeling of strong distress
which, as I know, has been experienced by persons when they have sud-
denly found out that they have been proceeding in a wholly unexpected
and wrong direction, leads to the suspicion that some part of the brain
is specialised for the function of direction.4
Inertial Navigation
Darwin’s account in 1873 aroused very interesting reactions at the time. To ex-
plain this navigational facility, some people proposed a mechanical analogy
very close to the inertial navigation systems used on modern airplanes.6 Per-
haps the vestibular apparatus of animals served as an inertial detection system
for navigating. Or perhaps the vestibular apparatus enabled the brain to di-
rectly detect the Coriolis forces and to use this information in navigating. It
was even proposed that the Coriolis effect could be estimated by detecting the
movement of blood in the vascular bed, a very controversial idea.
The assumption that the vestibular system plays an important role in navi-
gating short distances was taken up by Beritoff, an Armenian physicist who
also went by the name of Beritashvili. He elucidated these processes in dogs,
cats, infants, and adult humans. He suggested that spatial orientation is the ap-
titude of organisms to locate the position of objects and to relate this position
to themselves and to other objects.7 From these perceptions, organisms form
images of the distribution of objects in the world around them. These images
initiate and guide movement oriented toward the objects, even if the objects
are not seen or perceived by other sensory organs.
Beritoff conducted experiments with dogs. He blindfolded them before
taking them into the laboratory from one side and leading them along a spe-
cific path to a food source located on the other side. Then he led them back to
the point of departure before moving them to other parts of the room. He
discovered that even blindfolded, the dogs had no trouble finding the part of
A MEMORY FOR PREDICTING •
119
the room where the food was located, whatever their starting point. He inves-
tigated the possible role of all of the sensory cues (auditory, olfactory, tactile)
but found performance of the task to be impaired only after bilateral laby-
rinthectomy. Moreover, the animals found their way to the food just as well
when they were carried to it during training as when they walked to it. These
results seem to rule out kinesthesia (the set of cues supplied by the proprio-
ceptors of the joint muscles and locomotor commands). Though he realized
that the cerebral mechanisms called into play were extremely complex, Beri-
toff was the first to demonstrate a possible role of the vestibular system in
dead reckoning.
A precise return to a point of departure in the dark and deterioration of
performance following vestibular lesions have been observed in the rat.8 Sup-
plementary proof of this contribution from the vestibular system came from
work on batrachians and desert mice9 as well as the golden hamster.10 In this
animal, a lesion of the vestibular system causes deficits in navigational tasks
that are reversible following recovery of vestibular function.11 However, de-
tecting linear movement using vestibular cues has been the subject of a major
debate, for homing experiments with rodents suggest that these animals do
not correct linear displacements or rotations as easily. There seems to be a dis-
sociation between integration of linear and angular trajectories.12
Rotational Memory
The brain thus possesses mechanisms for memorizing displacements. Does
the vestibular system really contribute to these mechanisms, as Beritoff sug-
gested? One analytical approach separates out the components of rotational
and translational displacements and asks the question: Can the brain memo-
rize rotatory displacements and translations and reproduce them using the
eyes, head, or whole-body movements? This is the question we sought to an-
swer. I will describe these experiments in detail, because they led us to a fun-
damental concept: that vestibular memory is memory of movement, not of
position.
One elegant experiment, called vestibular memory-contingent saccades,
demonstrates the ability of the human brain to accurately detect the angle of
a rotation from the acceleration signaled by the vestibular receptors.13 The
subject is seated in a revolving chair in front of two visual targets. One target
is fixed in relation to the earth, the other in relation to his head. He is asked to
look at the first target and to memorize its location in space. Then all the
lights are switched off, except for the light on the target mounted on his head,
which turns with him and keeps his eyes from moving during the rotation.
120 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
The subject thus has only vestibular cues about the displacement of his body
to rely on, since he is in the dark and can make no movement of his eyes
(which could otherwise inform his brain about his displacement by means of
extraocular proprioception and motor discharge).
When the revolving chair is brought to a standstill, the illuminated target
mounted on the subject’s head is turned off, and he is now completely in the
dark. Several seconds are allowed to pass for the vestibular effects to diminish,
after which the subject is asked to recall the position of the earth-fixed target
and to make an ocular saccade toward that spot. In other words, he is asked to
displace his gaze from the place where the chair has stopped to the point of
departure he memorized. This task amounts to having the subject make a vi-
sual oculomotor return to his point of departure. After this memory saccade,
the light is turned back on. If the subject’s gaze is on the target, his eye does
not move; if his gaze is slightly deviated, he will execute a little correcting
saccade that makes it very easy to estimate the error.
Normal subjects can make saccades toward memorized targets after rota-
tion in the dark with extraordinary accuracy.14 The brain is thus capable of es-
timating displacement of the head solely from information supplied by the
horizontal semicircular canals. The subject is asked to wait 4 or 5 minutes
in total darkness after the chair has stopped moving before executing the
saccade. Despite this delay—which requires that the subject memorize the
spatial information about the angle of rotation of the body, that the brain re-
construct this information, and that it activate the cortical centers that pro-
duce the saccade—the result is always excellent. In other words, vestibular in-
formation about displacements of the body can be stored in spatial memory.
This is true for all orientations in space, which is only natural, since the vestib-
ular system did not develop solely to execute horizontal movements but to en-
able complex movements, such as jumping from tree to tree.
Next a subject is placed on a turntable and rotated in total darkness. We
ask him to reproduce the angular displacement in the opposite direction,
which he can do using a lever that controls the movement of the table. A
healthy subject can return to his point of departure with great precision.15
Which areas of the brain are involved in this ability to estimate rotations?
Applying this test to patients with lesions of the cerebral cortex gives a partial
answer.16 Serious impairment has been observed in patients with damage to
the supplementary oculomotor field, the prefrontal cortex, and the vestibular
cortex. These findings suggest first and foremost that the prefrontal cortex is
involved not only in visual memory but also in vestibular memory. This is no
surprise, since in my opinion memory of space is memory of movement in
A MEMORY FOR PREDICTING •
121
space: thus it is essentially multisensory. Moreover, it seems to me perfectly
natural to find deficits in patients with lesions of the vestibular cortex, given
its importance in reconstructing movements of the head in space and its im-
portance for transmitting to the rest of the cortex information about displace-
ments of vestibular and tactile origin (see Chapter 3).
Translational Memory
Man’s aptitude for using otolithic vestibular cues to estimate translations in
the course of linear movements was recently established. Recall that the oto-
liths are sensors of linear acceleration in their planes. We placed the subject on
a trolley for translational movement.17 This sort of experimental sled was con-
structed in our laboratory at the Ecole Nationale Supérieure des Arts et
Métiers during the 1970s. It used a linear motor technology initially conceived
to control the movement of high-speed trains, but eventually abandoned ow-
ing to the dissipation of heat that occurs with this mode of propulsion. The
trolley made displacements of several meters with accelerations of up to
about 1 meter per second per second. The subject was seated transversally, his
displacement thus occurring in the frontal plane (that is, the plane of the two
ears). Before beginning the move, the subject was shown a visual target fixed
with respect to the earth—in this case a clothespin hanging on a line. Then the
light was switched off, and the trolley was moved 60 centimeters to 1 meter.
The subject’s eyes did not move during the translation. Once the trolley had
stopped, the light was switched back on, the effect of the accelerations on the
otoliths was given a few seconds to dissipate, and the subject was asked—as
for the rotations—to make a saccade to where he remembered the clothespin
to be. The movements of his eyes adapted perfectly, whether his head was
fixed or free. Additional support for these findings was provided by experi-
ments made with the SLED (Figure 5.2) installed at the time in a glass shell at
the Cité des Sciences in Paris. The subject was displaced in an anteroposterior
direction, facing the movement. He was asked to signal his crossings under
targets positioned all along the linear track.
Later, we adapted a mobile robot to study perception of displacements.18
The subject was seated on the robot, in total darkness, and was subjected to
noise to obliterate any acoustical cues resulting from his displacement. The ro-
bot followed a rectilinear trajectory whose profile was either triangular (accel-
eration, then deceleration), trapezoidal (acceleration, constant velocity, then
deceleration), or square (sudden acceleration, constant velocity, then sudden
deceleration). Once the passive displacement—1 to 10 meters—was com-
122 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
Figure 5.2. The SLED in the Spacelab laboratory. This space sled was used in
the American space shuttle to study the influence of microgravity on the func-
tioning of the otolithic receptors. It consists of a runway approximately 4 me-
ters long on which a trolley moves by means of wires connected to a motor.
The subject is placed in any of three positions (front, lying on his back, or cross-
wise) during translations. A digital camera, constructed by LETI (part of the
French Atomic Energy Authority), records movement of one eye, and a minia-
ture television screen projects visual scenes to the other eye, which stimulates
the optokinetic reflex. Eye movements are also recorded with electro-
oculography. The subject uses a lever to indicate which way he thinks he is
moving. A Pelletier effect system allows injection of hot air into the subject’s
ears to study the effect of microgravity on the vestibulo-ocular reflex. This ap-
paratus was constructed by the European Space Agency. Our laboratory partici-
pated in its use with the French National Center for Space Research.
pleted, the subject was asked to reproduce the displacement, from memory,
with the aid of a lever that controlled the velocity of the robot. All normal
subjects executed this task accurately.
How does the brain go about this reproduction? Does it calculate the dis-
placement in meters and memorize numeric values, or does it perhaps store
other variables? We assume that it does not calculate displacements but in-
stead reproduces a dynamic velocity profile. It simulates the movement car-
ried out. Recall the words of Poincaré: “To localize an object simply means to
represent to oneself the movements that would be necessary to reach it.” In-
Locomotor Memory
Thus the role of the vestibular system in the memory of passively experienced
displacements becomes apparent. What happens to this memory during self-
displacement while walking? In this case, the information supplied by proprio-
ception in the legs—length of step, signals of the motor commands—is very
important for evaluating distances.
Anyone can do the following experiment, credited to Thomson. Look at a
point on the ground about a dozen meters away; close your eyes and walk to-
ward the point. You will see that you arrive at your destination pretty exactly.
Another test is to look at a target point far away on the ground and walk there
with your eyes closed but in a roundabout way. You will again observe that
you reach your goal with good accuracy. You can also return to your point of
departure with your eyes closed (what ethologists call dead reckoning). Finally,
you can repeat your same route several times, always with your eyes closed,
which means that the information has been stored in your spatial memory.
How do we explain this? There are only three possibilities: the distance
covered may be calculated from proprioceptive data supplied by the muscles
and joints of the legs; it may be derived from the memory of the motor com-
mands for each step; and finally, it may be derived from inertial cues of vestib-
ular origin. For the last of these possibilities, the brain would have to calculate
124 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
the distance covered based on vestibular information about acceleration, a
process that is called path integration. Poincaré had suspected this possibility:
“Knowing the acceleration of rotational movements of the head at each in-
stant, we can deduce through unconscious integration the final orientation of
the head with respect to its initial orientation.”19 According to this theory, the
brain calculates a distance covered. But we suggest that it dynamically updates
spatial representations.20 I have proposed the term “topokinetic memory” or
“topokinesthetic memory” to indicate this dynamic type of spatial memory.
I return to Thomson’s experiment described above. There are three ways
of interpreting his results: Perhaps the brain has a memory like a map (in the
geographical sense) of the environment and calculates its position on the map,
or perhaps the distance is encoded in “action units,” to use the expression fa-
vored among Gibson’s psychologist disciples; that is, the number of steps,
without there having to be a cartographic representation of the route in the
brain. Perhaps a memory of movement (rotations, translations, and their com-
binations) is retained and detected by the sensory receptors.
When the target is situated 3 or 4 meters away, people who no longer have
the function of their vestibular receptors still carry out the task, making only a
few mistakes in selecting a path. Recently we reproduced this experiment by
asking subjects to reach a target spot over a triangular path with their eyes
closed. Each side of the triangle had a length of several meters. In every case,
subjects who had no labyrinth, or who had unilateral labyrinthic lesions, dem-
onstrated significantly impaired performance. So it is plausible that the aggre-
gate of sensory messages contributes to this internal updating of spatial repre-
sentations. Recent work by Reiser, Loomis, and Tresky in the United States, as
well as by Thynus-Blanc in Marseille, shows that there are several possible
mental strategies for updating.
The memory of displacements is probably a genuine dynamic memory
that, when invoked, induces internal simulation of the path. The brain does
not merely compare sensory information with memorized information, it also
calls into play anticipatory mechanisms.
Recent observations confirm the anticipatory character of cerebral activity
during navigational tasks. For example, 1 or 2 seconds before every bend, the
gaze of a driver on a mountain road becomes fixed on the tangent inside the
bend.21 A calculation based on these data shows that the direction of this point
in relation to that of the car makes it possible to predict the curvature of the
road beyond the bend. In other words, the gaze of the driver is positioned on a
point such that the information supplied by the optic flow allows him to pre-
dict the curvature of the trajectory. Thus the brain does not merely know the
A MEMORY FOR PREDICTING •
125
curvature of displacement of the car at a given moment based on visual and
vestibular cues: it seeks to predict the curvature at a future time.
Similarly, when we turn a street corner, our gaze anticipates the rotation
of our body. This anticipation appears in the infant in the course of its devel-
opment, and I think it must be absent in patients with lesions of the parts of
the brain that participate in anticipation.
It thus seems reasonable to suppose that in carrying out a navigational
task, the brain in a way follows an internal representation, a model of the tra-
jectory that anticipates the path, and not the other way around. This principle
could be very useful in robotics. Instead of building machines that use so-
called sensory receptors to guide their movements, we recently suggested to a
team of roboticists that they control movements using gaze to anticipate the
trajectory. This principle of guided navigation turns out to be much more in-
teresting than that based on passive detection of displacement. Here, as in
other tasks, the brain prefers a “go where you look” strategy, in which the ob-
ject guiding a control strategy is placed close to the center of vision. I think
that these anticipatory mechanisms reflect the fact that the brain carries out
tasks of guided movement based on mental paths that it constructs and that
enable it to make predictions. Navigation is no more than the execution of an
internal plan based on past experience, and the senses are used, as in the case
of the ski champion I mentioned earlier, to ensure that the plan unfolds and to
make corrections.
DENTATE
GYRUS
GRANULAR
CELLS
CA1
GIANT
PYRAMIDAL NEURONS
CA2 C4
CA3
their effects indicated that the deficits induced might also be due to a small
neighboring region that could have been damaged at the same time as the hip-
pocampus—the entorhinal cortex. Nevertheless, several different conceptual-
izations compete with one another. They are worth summarizing briefly, be-
cause they explain why I maintain that the brain uses memory to predict the
consequences of action.
Short-term Memory
In humans and in animals, damage to the hippocampus and neighboring re-
gions of the temporal lobe impairs memory; so any plausible explanation of
this phenomenon must be compatible with the physiological properties of the
hippocampus. Marr was one of the first to propose that the hippocampus
plays a role in short-term memory.24 He was interested, among other things, in
its possible role in the genesis of dreams. He posited that during paradoxical
sleep (during the dream phase), the hippocampus fires stored memories at the
parietal cortex. Later, it was hypothesized that the hippocampus contributes
A MEMORY FOR PREDICTING •
127
to medium-term memory. Mishkin suggested that the hippocampus is in-
volved in “recognition memory.”25 He demonstrated this in a delayed recogni-
tion task used largely to test short-term and working memory: the monkey
had to match the arrangement of objects in front of it before the delay with a
new arrangement after the delay.
Proust’s Madeleine
For me, one of the most fascinating aspects of Rolls’s theory is that he identi-
fied, in the neuronal structure of the hippocampal network, properties that
enable it to recall an episode or a combination of sensations given only a por-
tion of the information initially memorized (Figure 5.4). This property is the
result of the autoassociative structure of the networks of neurons of the hip-
pocampus, owing to connections of hippocampal neurons that project to
themselves or to neighboring neurons and endow the structure with a ca-
pacity for memory and for recovering memorized information (recall). This
mechanism is used in certain machines to reconstruct an image from fragmen-
tary clues, and it enables the use of past episodes as models for what an ongo-
ing action might produce. In other words, to predict the consequences of an
ongoing action, the memorized action is recalled, even if its context is differ-
ent, to serve as a model for anticipating the consequences of action and possi-
bly to alter the action. What is still not known is whether the hippocampus is
mainly involved in storing new events or in recalling past ones. The right
prefrontal cortex as well as the medial parietal cortex are also involved in re-
calling memories.
Rolls gives the following example: One day in Oxford he is crossing High
130 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
A B
Neocortex
Parahippocampic Perirhinal
gyrus cortex
PHG S
D
PHG
Entorhinal 2 3
cortex
5,6
pp
Entorhinal
Dentate
gyrus Subiculum
DG DG
CA3 CA1
Hippocampus Subiculum
CA1
CA3
Nucleus Mammillary
accumbens body
Anterior nuclei
of the thalamus
Figure 5.4. Relations between the hippocampus and other parts of the cerebral
cortex involved in spatial memory and planning action. (A): The main centers
of the brain. (B): Axonal connections to neurons. (Lower right): A characteristic
feature of the neurons of the CA1 and CA3 layers of the hippocampus is the
projection of their axons back to the same cell or to other adjoining cells. This
arrangement gives the network so-called autoassociative properties that allow it
to memorize combinations of signals and to recall the entire combination even
if some of the information the neurons memorized at the outset is missing.
Street when a bicyclist runs over his foot. The visual cues (the street, the bicy-
cle arriving at the periphery of his visual field), proprioceptive cues (the bicy-
cle on his foot), the motor action (the aggregate of information associated
with the action of placing his foot in the street), and the auditory cues (the cry
of the cyclist) constitute the configuration of sensory cues about this episode.
One week later, he is just about to step out into another street. The situation
contains enough similar cues for him to recall the bicycle episode. He sus-
pends his gesture for an instant, fortunately, for a bus is passing by at great
A MEMORY FOR PREDICTING •
131
speed, and his hesitation saves him from being seriously injured. Memory of
the past allows him to predict the consequences of his action.
This mechanism might also explain the brain’s faculty for “filling in.” By
this we mean its ability to reconstruct episodes, shapes, words, and gestures
from a few elements among a configuration of signs. For example, perhaps
you do not always realize that a word is missing a letter, or an image some de-
tail; the brain supplies the missing information. Phenomenologists, Husserl in
particular, became interested in this capacity, which they studied in connection
with caricature: how are we able to recognize a face in a simple caricature, or
a man dancing, as Johansson showed, with only five or six points in motion?
The episode of the madeleine, which Proust describes at length in Remem-
brance of Things Past, is a nice example of filling in. He has only to smell the
madeleine dunked in a cup of tea to be able to recall the entire memory.
It is a general property of the brain, and among the most remarkable, not
to need every bit of information to identify a memory, even a very complex
one. Shepard, whose theories are discussed in detail in Chapter 8, proposes the
idea of resonance between a repertoire of internal representations (preper-
ceptions) and clues, even incomplete, from the environment, and here he parts
ways with Gibson: “Instead of saying that an organism picks up the invariant
affordances that are wholly present in the sensory arrays, I propose that as a
result of biological evolution and individual learning, the organism is, at any
given moment, tuned to resonate to the incoming patterns that correspond to
the invariants that are significant for it.”32 A resonator can react to a signal only
very slightly different from the one to which it is tuned, provided it has some
relationship—for example, a harmonic—with the tuning frequency. Shepard
uses this capacity of internal systems to resonate with stimuli that resemble
normal stimuli to explain certain properties of perceptual filling in; that is, the
capacity of the brain to continue to see the external world even if some por-
tion of the required information is absent.
134 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
The perceptual theory of Empedocles is a naive form of the idea of a pro-
jective brain that I defend in this book. The brain projects the image of the an-
imal on the wall of the cave; Lascaux man sees it there, external to him. Recall
that Michotte wrote:
The role of stimuli is not, as was believed for a long time, to give rise to
“sensations” that are then combined, linked one to the other, and even
altered by certain psychic processes under the predominant influence of
acquired experience. Their role seems, on the contrary, to boil down to
the simple initiation of endogenous constructive processes that obey
the proper laws of organization, largely autonomous and independent
of experience, and that lead directly to constructing the world of phe-
nomena.35
It was enough for the shapes on the wall to suggest a part of the form of a
buffalo; for example, to enable the brain of the painter to mentally reconstruct
the entire body. I have shown in connection to my discussion of the hippo-
campus that neural networks of the autoassociative type permit construction
of an internal representation of an episode from just a few clues.
At the same time, the person looking at the animals on the wall of the
cave was probably filled with wonder at the supernatural existence, as it were,
of the animal he normally saw in nature. Perhaps this wonder even gave rise
to quasi-religious notions of a kingdom of the beyond where these creatures
lived and where one could interact with them in sanctuaries. Be that as it may,
prehistoric man was not drawing out of any mysterious symbolic impulse; he
only fixed on the walls the shapes seen there. He must have been amazed by
what he saw, even though his brain was recreating these shapes from various
cues, just as I am present as a spectator at my own lectures, an impression pro-
duced by a brain whose expression I listen to with astonishment.
The example of cave paintings has a very general significance. Artistic cre-
ations seem to me to be projections of internal simulations of the world. I re-
cently saw a fifteen-year-old sculptor crafting a horse, or maybe it was a dog,
out of clay, without the aid of any model or scale, without even looking at
what he was doing, essentially by feeling it. You could clearly see that the form
emerging from the hands of this young prodigy was not even in his imagina-
tion; it was in the tips of his fingers, just as the pilot feels the landing strip un-
der the wheels of the airplane as if it were his own feet, or as we feel the tip of
a pencil on paper like the end of our finger. “Vision is the brain’s way of
touching,” said Merleau-Ponty. He wrote:
136 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
6
N AT U R A L M O V E M E N T
The most direct, and in a sense the most important, problem which our con-
scious knowledge of nature should enable us to solve is the anticipation of fu-
ture events, so that we may arrange our present affairs in accordance with such
anticipations.
—H. Hertz
The problems the brain has to solve are mainly problems of mechanics. Mod-
ern philosophy seems to have forgotten this, so captivated as it is by language
and so convinced that the higher functions of the brain have to do with formal
logic or can be explained by analogy to computers. But if the body is to be re-
habilitated in modern neurobiology, the rules that underlie its movements
have to be rediscovered. These rules1 are intuitively understood by sculptors,
who are able to render the movements of the body and their relationship to
emotions, as are actors in Asian theater.2 These actors demonstrate that pos-
ture is the first expression of movement. In other words, it is intended or sug-
gested movement, the dynamic form of which Bernstein called “readiness to
move.” They also demonstrate that the kinematics of movement conveys
meaning, and that the trajectory of a finger, the displacement of the head, the
swaying of the body must respond to laws that are at the crossroads of me-
chanics and neurology. Moreover, they confirm that natural movement is a
source of pleasure.
It might seem surprising that I open this chapter by speaking of pleasure.
Yet pleasure is a necessary element of perception and cognition. And the
source of this pleasure is in movement. The proof of it is the delight taken in
an elegant dance step, a nicely formed letter, a ball well thrown, or the joy got-
NATURAL MOVEMENT •
137
ten from certain movements that are possible only in particular situations. As I
reported earlier, an astronaut once confessed to me his sadness at returning to
“this sticky earth”—so happy was he to be freed from the constraints of grav-
ity. He made me think of the poet Ronsard, a great master in the art of plea-
sure: “So let this muddy hide rot out, / Whose lot both destiny and fortune
gambled over. / Be spirit only. Let the body be.”3
One of the greatest pleasures of my own brain is to fancy that I am
floating like a glider, free of gravity. I have extended dreams in which I fly over
the mountains and along rivers. I particularly like to launch myself from the
top of a hill and drift slowly, close to the meadows, teasing the goats, abandon-
ing myself to the delights of effortless forward motion, impervious to me-
chanical forces. By day I also derive extreme pleasure in feeling vection, which
is the illusion of advancing that you experience watching a river flow or
watching clouds go by when you are lying on the sand.
Over the course of evolution, we learned how to make use of mechanics.
In terms an author of the Enlightenment might have used, this book is a
paean to the mechanics of the body in complex beings and the brain’s accom-
modation to it. In this chapter, I will show how the brain managed to conquer
mechanics.
It did it first by simplifying the problems, a common device in mathemat-
ics. You reduce a complex problem to a simpler one that you know how to
solve. The work of the roboticist Slotine is a good example of this approach.
Slotine developed a set of concepts from using robots that he taught to play
tennis with remarkable dexterity.4 In this way he demonstrated that making
them work at what he called “composite variables” simplified calculations con-
siderably and increased the robots’ capacity for prediction and adaptation. The
robots responded much more quickly and even solved problems for which
they lacked sufficient data. The principle of composite variables itself is sim-
ple: instead of asking a robot to control position, or velocity, or acceleration
separately, one asks it to work on a variable s that is a combination of all these
variables and whose movement is defined by what is called a Lyapunov equa-
tion. This equation is chosen in an ad hoc manner. The remarkable advantage
of this straightforward transformation is that nonlinear problems involving
successive derivatives of the nth order (for example, velocity, acceleration,
jerk, and so on) are replaced by linear problems (problems that can be resolved
by much simpler, so-called first-order equations). Of course, actual implemen-
tation of these techniques is very sophisticated and does not concern us, but
the idea is important because it developed over the course of evolution.
In the nervous system simplification was achieved by creating internal
138 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
models of physical reality that enabled simulation of movement and that con-
strain perception. This dual effect is difficult to dissociate because its two as-
pects—perception and action—are so entangled. Neuropsychology, which
grapples with dissociations in patients who have lesions, is in this respect indis-
pensable, but it cannot explain the mechanisms. Thus new theoretical and ex-
perimental tools have to be constructed. I will provide a few examples of re-
cent efforts.
A neuroethology of natural movement also will have to be constructed. It
should be one that clarifies the relationships between movement and the emo-
tions movement arouses or expresses. Darwin showed how posture expresses
the emotions of the animal or human subject (see Chapter 11).5
Unfortunately, the neurophysiology of motor systems remained for a long
time a neurophysiology of connections between nerve centers. Structure and
function were not always associated. Theory was dominated by the stimulus-
response paradigm of Pavlov and the cybernetic paradigm of Wiener. Few al-
ternatives were entertained. The physiology of reflexes was predominant
from the beginning of the century, reinforced by the discovery of numerous
tools for analytical study of the nervous system—tools like electrical stimula-
tion of nerves. Generations of neurophysiologists (a group to which I belong)
duly measured reactions and responses resulting from the application of easily
manipulable physical stimuli such as light, force, stretch, sound, and so on;
they also constructed an analytical neurobiology. How is it possible to get
from a physiology of reaction to a physiology of action, from analytical
neurobiology to holistic neurobiology? To do so we have to study natural
movement and abandon formulaic reductionism.
Pioneers
Aristotle, in De animalium motu, then Borelli, and finally the brothers Weber
were the first to attempt to adapt the laws of bodily mechanics to the move-
ment of animals. Then, in the second half of the nineteenth century, Marey
was able to generate the first real descriptions of natural movement using
chronography. At the inauguration of the chair in the natural history of com-
plex organisms at the Collège de France, where he succeeded Flourens, Marey
declared:
When we stretch our fingers and we think about the sequence of ac-
tions that had to occur . . . , at the start we find the action of volition, a
psychic action, then the transmission of this volition, a nerve action,
NATURAL MOVEMENT •
139
then the contraction of the muscle, a muscular action, and finally the
movement of the organ, a mechanical action. In what order should we
study these events? A philosopher of the past, a Spinoziste, would not
have hesitated: follow the logical path; introduce the facts in the very
order of their appearance. This is precisely the approach that our con-
temporary school rejects. The physiologists of today rethink the order
of events by beginning with the crudest and the most visible, and work-
ing up progressively to the most refined and obscure.
Bernstein was the first to formulate the question of how many degrees of
freedom need to be controlled. “The first clear biomechanical distinction be-
tween the motor apparatus in man and the higher animals and any artificial
self-controlling devices . . . lies in the enormous number (which often reaches
three figures) of degrees of freedom which it can attain . . . Because of this there
is no direct relationship between the degree of activity of muscles, their ten-
sions, their lengths, or the speed of change in length.” Bernstein gives the ex-
ample of a ship at sea and an automobile, and continues:
I draw my second example, for comparison, from the field of normal
human motor co-ordination . . . Fasten the handle end of a ski-stick in
front of the buckle of a subject’s belt. Attach a weight of 1–2 kg to the
far end and on the right and left sides of the wheel attach a length of
rubber tubing long enough to allow the ends to be held in the subject’s
left and right hands. Instruct the subject, turning the stick point for-
wards, to stand before a vertical board on which a large circle, square or
other simple figure has been drawn, and to try, manipulating the ski-
stick only by pulling on the rubber tubing, to follow the contours of the
figure with the point of the ski-stick. The stick here represents one seg-
ment of an extremity with two degrees of freedom; the tubing is analo-
gous to two antagonistic muscles introducing a further two degrees of
freedom into the system. This experiment (which is very useful for
demonstrations in an auditorium) makes clear to all who attempt it just
how difficult and complicated it is to control systems which require the
co-ordination of four degrees of freedom.
a7 a5
a6
a4
a3
a2
a1
a0
a8
a6
a7 a5
a4
a3
a2
a1
a0
Figure 6.1. Two ways of holding a glass. These two natural postures result from
controlling the number of degrees of freedom of the joints. Defining a posture
simply requires defining the relationships between angles rather than the spatial
position of each limb. This relative method simplifies control.
of movement impossible if, over the course of evolution, methods had not
been devised for decreasing both the number of degrees of mechanical free-
dom by means of the geometric organization of the skeleton and the number
of degrees of freedom the brain has to control. Roboticists, who to this day
have still not found a way to build machines matching the complexity of the
least little insect, know the extent to which any computer is quickly saturated,
both in terms of its ability to make calculations and in speed, by the few de-
grees of freedom of the robots they construct. What are the tricks nature has
found to reduce the number of degrees of freedom?
142 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
Skeletal Geometry
If you were to take a walk through the new gallery of the Museum of Natural
History in Paris to see the display of animal skeletons patiently constructed by
the systematic mind of French zoology in the last century, what might strike
you is both the enormous diversity and a certain invariance of the collection.
Despite the considerable efforts of zoology, the laws that govern the organiza-
tion of the skeleton—its geometry—are not always related to the constraints
of movement, and yet the purpose of this geometry is to reduce the complex-
ity in controlling movement. Several recent findings have nevertheless at-
tempted to link skeletal geometry to motor functions and to predatory behav-
ior. Coppens and the paleoanthropologists thereby demonstrated that the
skeletal anatomy of certain forerunners of modern man, like the famous
Lucy, resembles both tree-dwelling quadrupeds and bipeds that walk upright.
In man, nonhuman primates, and other mammals, the anatomy of the
cervical column was dictated by the need to reduce the number of degrees of
freedom. Watch a stork flying, or a lion or gazelle or ostrich running. They
keep their head held horizontally, such that the plane of the horizontal semi-
circular canals is perpendicular to gravity (see Figure 4.1). This constancy of
position in relation to gravity makes the head a stabilized platform, which
considerably simplifies processing of vestibular and visual information, as well
as their coordination.
Indeed, suppression of the rotation of the head restricts the optic flow to
alterations of the visual field connected to translations. These cues comple-
ment those supplied by the vestibular receptors of the otoliths which signal
linear accelerations, but cannot distinguish translation or tilt of the head. Sta-
bilization of the head thus simplifies the fusion of visual and vestibular infor-
mation. Of course, it also reduces retinal slip and allows the vestibulo-ocular
reflex to ensure the stabilization of the visual world on the retina.
Maintaining the head in this posture is achieved, in part, through the ar-
rangement of particular cervical vertebrae.9 In fact, curvature of the cervical
column, of which the swan is a good example but which is a feature of all
birds and all mammals, facilitates lifting of the neck, which places the head on
a pivot that has the double advantage of positioning the semicircular canals
horizontally perpendicular to gravity and creating a preferred plane of ro-
tation.
A second property of the skeleton that simplifies biomechanics is limits on
possible movements. Once more, movement of the head provides a good ex-
NATURAL MOVEMENT •
143
ample. The anatomy of the cervical vertebrae allows only certain well-defined
movements, familiar to specialists in kinesthesiology and rheumatologists. It is
easy to make very quick orienting movements of the cervical column, which
constitutes a pivot. Horizontal rotations are facilitated by a specialized muscu-
lar system, linked to horizontal movements of the eye. This architecture is
what allows the sparrow you see on the lawn to turn its head in the horizontal
plane with dizzying speed.
Look quickly straight up toward the ceiling. You will have difficulty doing
it. Your center of rotation is located at the level of the first cervical vertebra.
All the other vertebra are anatomically locked, which consequently forces a
single center of rotation. You will note, moreover, that it is relatively easier to
make an oblique movement upward and left, or upward and right, in the plane
of the vertical semicircular canals.
Now bend your head quickly downward to look at the floor. This time,
the cervical vertebrae are locked in such a way that the center of rotation is lo-
cated at the junction of the cervical vertebrae and the thoracic vertebrae. On
the other hand, the movement appears simpler because gravity aids the fall of
your head.
In other words, nature used vertebral anatomy to reduce a very complex
system to several basic movements, which simplifies its control. This descrip-
tion of anatomical constraints could be extended to the movements of the
arms, legs, and so on. Biomechanics imposes geometric solutions that have
been optimized over the course of evolution. For that matter, it is fascinating
to note that the brain recognizes, so to speak, this organization of the possible
movements of the skeleton.
The skeletal architecture of animals limits their movements in such a way
as to considerably reduce the number of degrees of freedom. It is represented
in internal circuits that allow mental simulation of movement. A new science
is needed to understand this dynamic architecture.
144 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
a single parameter, varying only the relation of amplitude of the two angles,
which considerably simplifies control. In this way, the brain controls global
variables (elevation and azimuth of the movement from the end of the finger)
and not the local variables (the multiplicity of the angles that make up the seg-
ments of the limbs themselves).11
Muscular Geometry
Yet another trick discovered by nature to reduce the number of degrees of
freedom is to play upon the arrangement of the muscles. Muscular geometry
complements the simplifications contributed by skeletal geometry. For exam-
ple, most of the muscles are located between two joints (like the knee and the
hip), but others connect distant joints (like the foot and the hip): these are
called biarticular muscles, and people have been trying for a long time to deci-
pher their role. The following example makes it easy to understand why: Take
a mug of beer and set it on the table. Now, pick it up and bring it to your
mouth. The interplay of angles made by your arm, your forearm, and your
shoulder is such that had we only monoarticular muscles, some would do neg-
ative work, which is not very economical energetically. The fact that we have
biarticular muscles enables us to recover this negative work and to reconstruct
it in a positive form at one of the joints.12 Of course, it takes a bit more mathe-
matics to demonstrate than can be shown here. The point is that nature found
an elegant way to resolve a problem of mechanics using geometry, just as car-
penters do in solving problems of static distribution of weight.
NATURAL MOVEMENT •
145
pattern of covariation between quantities related to geometry and kinematics
is likely to provide a clue for understanding the logic of the controller.”13 Two
covariations that meet these criteria have been discovered.
Two-thirds power law. When you draw an ellipse on a sheet of paper with a
natural movement, you may have the impression that the speed with which
you draw is totally independent of the shape. Well, that is not the case. There
is an extraordinarily precise relationship between the curvature of the form
you are drawing and the tangential velocity along the curve. If you try to draw
an ellipse, you will see that the speed of your pencil increases at the parts
where the curves are greatest. The movement of the pencil along the ellipse
can be described in at least three ways: first, describing the motion in time of
the Cartesian coordinates x(t) and y(t) of the tip of the pencil; second, using
equations to describe the shape of this trajectory and the law of movement
along the trajectory; third, describing the movement by specifying two param-
eters: radius of curvature R(s) of the trajectory and tangential velocity V(s) of
a point along the trajectory (s represents the curvilinear coordinate of move-
ment). The trajectory has been shown to be completely defined by these two
parameters.
By measuring these parameters, it is possible to demonstrate the relation-
ship between curvature and the velocity of movements of the hand. In 1983
Viviani and his co-workers discovered a simple relationship between curvature
(C = 1/R) and angular velocity (A = V/R) : A = KC 2/3, which they called the
two-thirds power law.
This law held only for a certain class of movements. Subsequent investiga-
tions of the law in relation to three-dimensional movements resulted in a re-
formulation that involves a greater variety of natural movements than draw-
ing; it even holds for points of inflection.14 The two-thirds power law gradually
becomes operative in infants as motor function matures. It connects the radius
of curvature at any point of the trajectory to the tangential velocity V, as well
as angular velocity. It is expressed by the following equation:
β
R( s)
V ( s) = K( s)
1+ αR( s)
Factor K depends on the length of the trajectory and not on its shape.
When β = 1/3, α = 0, and K is constant, the new formulation is equivalent to
the original equation. Is this law connected to the mechanical properties of
the limbs, or does it reflect the general principles of motor control by the
146 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
brain? It appears to be due to neural mechanisms and not to geometric or me-
chanical constraints connected to the muscles and limbs. Natural movements
are often complicated. They can be broken down into parts, and this law then
applies to each separate part.
The principle of isochrony. This second principle establishes that the velocity
of movement from one point to the other tends to increase with the distance
between the points. If you have two objects before you on a table, the princi-
ple of isochrony predicts that you will cover the distance between one object
and the other more quickly if the distance is greater. Go ahead and do the ex-
periment. It is also true for movements of the eyes: the velocity of a saccade
(see Chapter 10) increases with its amplitude. A saccade of 10 to 15 degrees is
made at around 30 degrees per second; a saccade of 50 degrees is made at
more than 500 degrees per second. According to this principle, which holds for
all natural movements, the duration of a movement is relatively independent
of its linear extent, hence the term “isochrony” (fixed duration).
Recently, Viviani and Flash noted that modulation of the average velocity
along a trajectory depends on two factors: the length of the trajectory and the
distribution of the curvature along this trajectory.15 These relationships dis-
close a more fundamental property that involves the prediction of movement.
“In both cases, the fact that velocity is modulated by a global geometrical
quantity (the linear extent of the path), even before the trajectory is fully exe-
cuted, suggests that an estimate of this quantity is available to the motor con-
trol system as part of the internal representation of the intended move-
ment.”16 This theory assumes that the motor control system is equipped with
a spatial blueprint even before the movement begins, which fits with the as-
sumptions of motor program theory; it also assumes that the geometry of the
planned trajectory limits the kinematic and temporal aspects of action.
NATURAL MOVEMENT •
147
uine organ of anticipated simulation of movement. The fish must maneuver a
complex and heavy body in an environment that allows it only a single move.
Catching prey or escaping from a predator affords the fish no room for error.
Displacement of gaze by a simplified mechanical organ (six muscles operat-
ing in pairs produce rotations of the eye in three perpendicular planes) allows
the fish to confirm that a movement it is planning to execute is the correct
one.
What a fantastic invention this little biological machine is! With a single
movement of the eye, the brain can visually pinpoint prey and check whether
its gesture is adapted to the reality of the external world. The movement of
the eye simulates the one the predator must make to capture its prey. Thus the
eye is more than just a pivoting retina: It is a very simple physical model of the
action needed to secure a meal. If I am a predator, all I have to do to figure out
how much I need to move my body to capture my prey is to duplicate with
my body the movement specified by my eye. Nature first had to simplify the
number of degrees of freedom of the problem and then solve it with a very
simple instrument.
Next, nature invented the principle of relative control of movement. It is
actually not necessary for the fish to calculate its position in space (and it
would have a hard time doing it in the water); its brain has only to minimize
the distance from its present position to its goal. Borrowing the language of
cybernetics, all the brain has to do is to minimize motor errors.
In primates, this internal simulation of a change in direction of gaze was
refined to an even higher degree by the invention of the displacement of at-
tention. Look straight ahead and turn your gaze quickly to the right. You will
notice that just before your eye turns, you feel your gaze move forward. In
Chapter 10 I discuss briefly the anticipatory displacement of the receptor field
made by the neurons of the parietal cortex before the saccade of the eye and
the mechanisms that enable internal simulation of gaze movements.
NATURAL MOVEMENT •
149
see that the final position of the die is not the same. The rotations are not
commutative. The same is true for the eye. If no simplification had occurred,
the images of the same part of the environment would project to the retina in
different ways. The result would be perceptual confusion and major difficulty
in constructing a coherent image of the visual environment based on local im-
ages.
How did nature resolve this problem? Listing17 derived a law, initially pro-
posed by Donders,18 who formalized the biological solution: Every movement
of the eye can be represented by a vector whose axis is perpendicular to the
plane of rotation and the chosen amplitude in a particular relationship with
the angle of rotation. Is it possible to provide a straightforward illustration of
this vector? Simply imagine a top: the vector of rotation of the top is the han-
dle you use to make it turn, and that is perpendicular to its plane of rotation.
Now, suppose that we make the length of this axis proportional to the velocity
of rotation. It will be quite short when the top turns slowly and very long
when it turns very fast. This use of vector of rotation is a very elegant way to
describe the movement of the top in three-dimensional space. All that is nec-
essary is to define the direction of the vector and its amplitude. The three-di-
mensional problem is then reduced to two dimensions.
Listing’s law states a remarkable property: all the vectors of rotation of
the eye are in the same plane, the frontal plane of the head, called Listing’s
plane. All the saccades you make in reading this page have vectors of rotation
in this plane. When Listing’s law is satisfied, there is no torsion of the eye,
which constitutes experimental proof of the law. Many laboratories have now
confirmed the validity of Listing’s law for eye movements.
It was believed that command of eye movements could be expressed using
mathematical rules that govern these rotational vectors. The representation of
movement by rotational vectors presents another advantage: it is possible to
characterize a vector by its constituents in space with the aid of a mathemati-
cal construct called a quaternion. A sequence of rotations can be represented
by calculating the product of their scalar constituents. It was thus suggested
that nature had discovered this property of quaternions and that the brain
uses it to encode movements in the neurons. However, this theory has yet to
be confirmed.
150 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
into play the neuronal subsystem of ocular pursuit (see Figure 3.2). This slow
movement of the eye appeared late in the course of evolution and followed
the appearance of the fovea, which, as I mentioned, exists only in primates
and in man. You can see how it works very simply by performing the follow-
ing experiment. Hold a finger out in front of you and fully extend your arm.
Move your finger slowly from left to right and from right to left, ever more
quickly. You will notice that your gaze follows your finger for slow move-
ments, whose cyclic frequency is about once per second (1 Hz). But as you in-
crease the speed, your gaze will start to lag behind your finger, and you will
get to the point where you cannot follow it anymore. In fact, the tracking sys-
tem is a slow system (up to 100 degrees per second)—unlike the saccade,
which is extraordinarily rapid (up to 800 degrees per second)—probably be-
cause it involves complex pathways. Ocular pursuit follows the law of two-
thirds power (this is also true of manual pursuit),19 but it remains a slow move-
ment. Nature’s way around this slowness is prediction.
Oculomotor pursuit is essentially predictive. Indeed, it is not only the tar-
get itself that is tracked, but an internal simulation, an internal model, of the
trajectory predicted by the target.20 If you move your finger in front of you
like a metronome, one oscillation per second, you will observe that after
about two or three oscillations your eye is ahead of the finger it is tracking.
Your brain is anticipating the trajectory.
NATURAL MOVEMENT •
151
A
Figure 6.3. Natural movement and the minimum-jerk model. Three subjects
were asked to draw three different shapes (left: A, B, C). To the right are traces
of the trajectories predicted by the minimum-jerk model.
and the velocity based on the total duration of movement, and the position,
velocity, and acceleration at points where it starts, ends, and through which it
must pass. Experiments have shown that natural movements (drawing a figure
eight, a spiral, and so on) made by subjects could be modeled very precisely
using the law of minimum jerk (Figure 6.3). However, this model does not
take into account the global isochrony of movement. One compromise is thus
to search among the theories that take into account global isochrony and rela-
tionships between geometry and velocity. The synthesis proposed by Viviani
and Flash assumes that the brain first constructs an abstract representation of
the intended movement, encoded as a sequence of boundary conditions, or
velocities and positions of departure and arrival. These conditions are then
transformed into trajectories by the laws that constrain movement (minimum
jerk, point of equilibrium, and so on).
Current theories of motor function thus adopt two completely opposite
points of view. One starts with a geometric representation of the trajectory
152 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
and assumes that the brain organizes a sequence of basic actions to follow it;
the other suggests that the brain ignores the shape of the trajectory, which re-
sults quite simply from high-order constraints such as the stability of paired
oscillators operating in tandem or the minimum jerk of a movement. Taking
it one step further, some would say the body follows the form, whereas for
others, the form follows from the functioning of the body.
NATURAL MOVEMENT •
153
7
S Y N E R G I E S A N D S T R AT E G I E S
In olden times, children might be given a splendid Harlequin doll made from
cardboard as a present. Its back concealed a network of strings, connected in
such a way that a single string made the arms and legs flex at the same time.
This invention is a legacy of Chinese shadow puppets and of Asian puppet
theater, and it illustrates a basic form of synergy. The principle involves coor-
dinating the limbs so that a single command sets in motion a network of com-
bined actions that constitute this synergy. What remarkable simplicity! Indeed,
in puppet theater, different gestures are created by manipulating various com-
binations of strings. Musical automata relied on the same principle.
The word synergy comes from syn (together) and ergos (work). This con-
cept was proposed by Bernstein to support the idea that, since the nervous
system cannot control all degrees of freedom, evolution selected a repertoire
of simple and complex movements, which are called natural movements.
These involve groups of muscles working together. I have already mentioned
the constraints the skeleton imposes on the variety of movements possible at
each joint. Moreover, this repertoire is not very extensive. Watch a dancer, and
see just how meager the motor repertoire of the human body is. What is rec-
ognized as the genius of choreography and the expressive richness of dance is
the combination in time and space of the elements of movement and the in-
terplay of partners.
Motor synergies are the basis of movement. The remarkable flexibility of
neural networks makes it possible to manipulate these synergies to produce
what I call strategies: the selection either of a particularly well adapted syn-
ergy, or of a sequence of synergies that constitute a complex movement ori-
ented toward a goal. In fact, movements are organized in sequences of syner-
gies on which behaviors are based, as Lorenz demonstrated superbly in his
experiments with greylag geese. How synergies are chosen depends on the
goal of action.1
The challenge is to construct with ethologists what I call a neuroethol-
ogy of motor function, and to work with molecular biologists to ascertain
whether some of these synergies are genetically determined by knocking out
specific parts of the genetic code in the rat or the mouse.
I will first describe the contribution of anatomy, especially the branching
of axons, to the construction of synergies; then we will analyze data from re-
search on neurons of the motor cortex with reference to problems discussed
at the end of the preceding chapter on the laws governing movement of the
arms.2
The reader would be well advised to resist the temptation to skip this pas-
sage on anatomy. The digression is worthwhile. You do not need to under-
stand the architecture of a flower to enjoy it, nor do you need to analyze how
the branches of an oak are arranged to benefit from the shade it provides. But
anyone who seeks the principles of physiological functioning must find them
first in anatomy. My objective is not to review the wealth of anatomical facts
accumulated in the aftermath of the pioneering work of Ramón y Cajal, ow-
ing to the diversity of techniques anatomists have at their disposal. Rather, I
will discuss how the branching of axons determines motor synergies and how
it links motor function and perception, in short, how anatomy comes to the
aid of physiology.
Look straight ahead and turn your head upward while keeping your gaze fixed
on an object. Your gaze will remain stable. The vestibulo-ocular reflex, de-
scribed in Chapter 2, contributes to this stabilization; vision is not necessary.
Indeed, try the following experiment: Look straight ahead, letting your gaze
rest on an object. Close your eyes and think of the object. Lift your head while
fixating behind your closed lids on the object you memorized. Open your
eyes. You will see that your gaze has remained where it was. In the dark your
eyes moved in a direction contrary to that of your head as a result of the
vestibulo-ocular reflex. Several muscles in each eye had to be jointly activated
to make this compensatory movement. This is a very simple example of mo-
tor synergy.
But there is more. Axonal organization and the structure of connections are
alterable, at least at certain stages of development. I have emphasized that
connectivity controls the geometry of movement. For example, in the flatfish
the brain can use anatomy to change this geometry. Here is the story of the
baby flatfish that wanted to swim flat on its belly.
When it is born, the baby flatfish, like all other fish, swims vertically up-
right with its eyes on each side of its body (Figure 7.1a). A distinctive fea-
ture of this fish is that it undergoes an extraordinary metamorphosis when
it is young. It suddenly flips onto its side and starts moving around flat at
the bottom of the sea (Figure 7.1b). One of its eyes is thus on the under-
dorsal
A
horizontal
semicircular canal
eye axis
ventral
B
eye axis
ventral dorsal
horizontal
semicircular canal
Figure 7.1. Eyes change position in the flatfish. When it is born, the flatfish has
eyes on each side of its head and swims upright like all other fish (A). Soon af-
ter, the fish flips onto one side and swims around flat at the bottom of the sea.
As it develops, one of its eyes migrates to the other side of its head. (B): Be-
cause the vestibular receptors do not change position, the vestibulo-ocular
reflex no longer functions correctly; in response, the anatomy of the vestibular
neurons is reorganized.
158 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
A B
oculomotor
nuclei
vestibular
nuclei
side of its body. To compensate for this disadvantage, the lower eye migrates
to the other side of the fish’s head. The two eyes end up right next to each
other.
This daring transformation of the position of the visual sensor risks com-
pletely changing the functioning of the vestibulo-ocular reflex that stabilizes
the image of the world on the retina. But in fact, the semicircular canals and
the otoliths do not move in the skull. When the animal turns, the precise con-
nections that I have described displace the eye, which has migrated in a direc-
tion that no longer corresponds at all to the correct geometry. A remarkable
reorganization of the axons of the vestibular neurons then follows, which
can be seen by injecting these neurons with a tracer (horseradish peroxidase)
that makes it possible to reconstruct the anatomy of the neuron (Figure 7.2).6
Following the transformation, the anatomy of the neurons is completely
changed: the projections are reorganized and now ensure gaze stabilization
with the new arrangement of the eyes.
SYNERGIES AND STRATEGIES •
159
Thus axonal anatomy does not determine only the geometry of the eye. It
facilitates adaptation to changes in the body. This biological solution to the
problem is extraordinarily elegant because it spares the animal complicated
neural calculations to reorganize its perceptual and motor space.
If the neurons that underlie local reflexes are organized in a way that produces
synergies, how is the cortical control of movements organized? Do the neu-
rons of the cerebral cortex that direct our movements control the muscles one
by one, or do they use the same principle as the vestibulo-ocular reflex, that is,
does each neuron drive a specific synergy? Consider the case of a part of the
cortex up to now considered simple: the motor cortex located at the apex of
the skull in the central gyrus, also called Brodmann’s area 4. The early work
concerning neural activity in the motor cortex was done by the American
physiologist Evarts in 1968. It was first assumed that each projection neuron
of the motor cortex (large pyramidal cells that project to the medulla via the
corticospinal pathway) activates a muscle or possibly a group of antagonist
muscles at the joint.7 Further studies contradicted this approach. The axons of
the corticospinal neurons, like the vestibular and collicular neurons, actually
branch out systematically into various levels of the medulla. Activation of any
one of these neurons simultaneously activates several groups of muscles
throughout the body; this contributes to a precise movement (for example,
leaning forward); that is, to a synergy. In other words, once again, anatomy
underlies synergy.
The connection between the pyramidal neurons of the cortex and the
various muscles of a motor synergy is, moreover, specific to a function and
not to the muscles that constitute their target. This functional specificity is il-
lustrated by the fact that the neurons of the motor cortex can be active during
precision gripping, as when you are picking a strawberry, but the neuron is si-
lent if the same muscles are activated with great force, in what we call power
gripping.
How these neurons control force is still a mystery. Each pyramidal cell
maintains a variable relation with the force exerted by the finger that excludes
a simple causal relationship. Certain neurons of the motor cortex are activated
only when the frequency of the movement is increased, which suggests that
these neurons control stiffness (the connection between a force exerted and
the resulting displacement) of a given joint.
160 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
The Theory of Vectorial Encoding by a
Population of Neurons
A major surprise awaited researchers once they turned to arm movements
more complex than simple grasping. They expected that many types of dis-
charges would be associated with local variables of particular joints. Instead,
they discovered that the cortex was involved in the overall movement of each
limb, such as the complete trajectory of the finger. The activity of the popula-
tion of these neurons is associated with the direction of the finger in space
(this is also true in varying degrees for other cortical areas).8 If a monkey is
asked to point its finger toward targets located in various directions in front of
it, specific neurons are activated for a particular direction of the pointing
movement. In other words, certain neurons fire more when the movement is
made, for example, toward two o’clock on the face of a clock. But these pref-
erential directions are somewhat indistinct, and some neurons fire for move-
ment in all directions. If the activities of a population of neurons (about a
hundred) are simultaneously recorded during the same movement toward two
o’clock on the clock face, some neurons will fire frequently because the ges-
ture is made close to their preferred direction; others will fire less because
their preferred direction is farther off. Taking the average of all these dis-
charges will reveal that the resultant vector of the population is very precisely
oriented in the direction of the movement of the finger toward the target.
Coordination of Synergies
type of functional flexibility has also been described by Moulins and co-work-
ers in invertebrate animals such as the snail. A network of neurons produces
rhythmic contraction of the stomach muscles of this animal and is also impli-
cated in an additional motor activity. The change in neural configuration be-
tween these two modes of functioning is assured by specialized neurons, inde-
pendent of the network. Moulins and Clarac showed that several synergies
can share the same network of neurons.
Thus, genetically determined local synergies—different kinds of locomo-
tion, ocular motor systems (saccades, vestibulo-ocular reflexes, and so on),
sexual behaviors, postures (Figure 7.3), and so forth—make up the sensori-
motor repertoire of each species. These synergies are organized as behavioral
strategies guided by global mechanisms. In higher animals and in man, these
strategies can be anticipated, selected, and internally simulated before being
executed, using the same neural structures as those of the action itself. I will
show examples of these processes in gaze orientation and postural control.
SYNERGIES AND STRATEGIES •
163
The cerebellum probably plays a fundamental role in organizing synergies.
The scope of this book prevents me from examining the role of this structure
in the coordination of gestures, for I would also have to compare its function
with that of the basal ganglia, and so on. I will merely take note of the follow-
ing: It is well known that stimulation of muscular, tactile, and joint receptors
activates the Purkinje cells of the cerebellar cortex. These sensory projections
are distributed over microzones, each receiving projections from sensors lo-
cated on the tongue, neck, arms, hands, feet, and so on. For several years it
was surprising to find that the same part of the body projects to several
microzones. Why, for example, are several projections of the head required?
It was discovered that the projections corresponding to the parts of the
body involved in a precise motor action are grouped together. In other words,
they compose a synergy.10 For example, projections for whiskers, mouth, and
front paws are found side by side; they correspond to the action of cleaning.
Here again anatomy reflects activity, an element of the motor repertoire orga-
nizing actions and not isolated movements. “In the beginning was the Deed,”
says Faust. The choice of a strategy for action is thus simplified: all that is
needed is to sequentially activate these sets of contiguous neurons that con-
trol the repertoire of actions. Similarly, the very same sets of neurons can be
used to internally simulate movement because these sets are the neural mir-
ror of action. It is known that cortico-ponto-cerebello-thalamo-cortical loops
exist, within which internal simulation of movement can occur completely in-
dependent of its actual execution. These loops contain . . . here I do well to
hesitate, like Faust. “Representations” is too vague; “models” is modern but
probably vague as well; “images” is too visual; “schemas” is the term perhaps
most common in the literature; “kinesthetic series” would make Husserl
happy.
There is still a long way to go before it is understood how synergies and
strategies are assembled in the various parts of the brain that control move-
ment. How the rigidity of their repertoire is compensated by the plasticity of
the rearrangements, as revealed by recent findings from neurobiology, is still
unclear. A tantalizing scientific adventure awaits.
164 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
8
CAPTURE
When a hungry toad sees something moving, it has to decide whether the
thing is an earthworm (prey) or an eagle (predator). In the first case, it must
spring up and capture it; in the second, it must hide. If you have the time to sit
by a stagnant pond, you will notice that toads, despite their nonchalant ap-
pearance, are capable of making these decisions in a flash. The naïve psychol-
ogy of representation would claim that the toad recognizes the worm and the
eagle as such, and keeps central representations of them that it classifies as
prey and predator, such that identification of the object induces a reaction of
fight or flight.
Actually, the mechanism is much simpler and remarkably efficient. Specific
neurons are responsible for the behavior.2 They are located in the optic tec-
tum, a brain structure in the frog that is sensitive to visual cues from the retina
indicating the position and movement of objects. This structure is the ances-
tor of the superior colliculus in mammals and primates. The neurons of the
optic tectum are sensitive to a particular configuration of visual stimuli: longi-
tudinal movement of any elongated object. This is obviously a characteristic
feature of earthworms, so a lure such as a little rectangle of paper will also
serve, provided that it moves in the direction of its length. This assembly of
neurons in the optic tectum is responsible for orientation and capture.
Other neurons located in the posterior portion of the thalamus—an im-
portant neural center for multisensory convergence as well as a center for re-
laying sensory information to the cerebral cortex—are sensitive to another vi-
166 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
sual shape, which Ewert called “antiworm” because, unlike the worm, this
configuration corresponds to a large target, like an eagle or a large animal.
These neurons are connected to motor assemblies that induce avoidance be-
havior. An essential property of these systems is this: each inhibits the other.
The two behaviors of capture and flight are thus mutually exclusive.
Of course, one could say that the earthworm is represented at the central
level by neurons sensitive to the movement of an elongated object. However,
a genuine physiological interpretation of the brain would emphasize the fact
that this neural system is very simple. Receptors and first-order neural pro-
cessing detect the relevant variables directly. A few of the properties of the
neural networks—classification (the ability to recognize two sensory configu-
rations), neuronal connectivity, and a clever combination of elements of syn-
aptic inhibition and excitation—are sufficient to work out the mechanisms
that sensitize the animal to what I call expected sensory configurations, or
neural hypotheses. Schemas as Schmidt understands them guide the selection
of sensory configurations recognized by the system.3 Compared with more
highly evolved animals, the toad lacks the flexibility or capability to recognize
a fake worm. You can catch frogs using a bit of red cloth, but you cannot catch
a cat with a stuffed mouse.
The classification of perceptions (for example, of prey or predator) is de-
termined by the repertoire of possible actions (in this case, capture or flight).
Hence a further illumination of my proposition, perception is simulation of ac-
tion. But there is more. We capture first of all with our gaze. To study how
mechanisms of gaze control anticipate targets in motion, we constructed a vi-
sual game in the laboratory like the ones at a country fair where you have to
shoot at a line of ducks or pop multicolored balloons that an air current blows
around at random. Despite their simplicity, these games are difficult, which is
how the fairgrounds people manage to stay in business.
In our experiment, the subject first has to fixate on a spot in the center of
a screen on which, from top to bottom, a second spot appears that falls sud-
denly, like a ball. An auditory signal set off at various moments during the fall
instructs the subject to catch the falling target with an ocular saccade. During
the 150-odd milliseconds during which the eye remains fixated, the brain esti-
mates the velocity of the target, which moves toward the periphery of the eye.
You can do this experiment yourself by focusing on a point in front of you and
holding an object in your right hand above the horizontal. Let the object fall,
and then try to catch it with your gaze during its fall.
We observed that at the instant the auditory signal sounds, the eye moves
not to where the target is but further on in its trajectory. The brain guesses—
CAPTURE •
167
predicts—the future position of the target. How are perception and action
connected to be able to program a saccade toward the future position of the
target? We still do not know.
The toad thus exhibits two kinds of behavior that depend on prediction: cap-
ture and evasion. A second avoidance behavior is collision prevention. When
you are in an automobile, when do you brake to avoid running into a stalled
truck in the middle of the road? Lee’s hypothesis is that the brain uses an optic
variable, which he calls “time τ-to-collision.”4 In fact, Lee observed that if the
speed of the automobile is constant, τ is equal to the relation between the ob-
served diameter of the car in front and which you are approaching, and the
speed with which this diameter expands.
Time-to-collision is thus defined as the function of a derived distance.
Speed equals distance divided by time. If distance (the observed diameter of
the car on the retina) is divided by speed (the speed at which this diameter ex-
pands), the distance units cancel out, and pure time in seconds for small angles
is the result.
If movement proceeds at constant velocity, time-to-collision can thus be
evaluated by the speed with which the retinal image of the object expands. It
is a genuine optic variable. This expansion is detected by specialized neural el-
ements. In the monkey, neurons sensitive to this expansion of the image were
found in the parietal cortex, which as it happens was predicted by the Dutch
physicist Koenderink, an optic flow theorist.
What is new about Lee’s theory is that he estimates time without ever cal-
culating distance. Time τ to contact is given solely by retinal cues. I use the
word “given” to reiterate an expression of Husserl. It is a good example of
what can be given to perception in contrast with what has to be calculated, of
what is better explained by a biological, not computational, theory of the brain.
This does not mean that these processes cannot be represented using mathe-
matical methods or that the processes that take place in the nervous system
are not equivalent to mathematical operations. But a model remains a formal-
ization of a biological reality, accounting for some aspects of it.
This model was originally developed to describe an approaching obstacle,
but it obviously holds for estimating the time-to-collision (here, time-to-con-
tact) with a ball thrown toward someone (or an eagle diving toward a toad!).
If the motion is accelerated—a falling ball, for example—the time-to-contact
168 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
V
Z
Figure 8.1. Lee’s (1976) theory about the perception of time-to-collision during
a movement. Without having to estimate the distance, the driver of a car can
directly work out time-to-collision with a stalled truck based on optic flow. As
the car approaches the truck, the image of the truck expands on the retina at a
velocity proportional to that of the proximity of the two vehicles. If velocity V
is constant, time-to-collision is equal to the apparent diameter of the image of
the truck on the retina divided by the velocity of expansion of this image.
These two pieces of information are supplied by the retina and require no
knowledge of the distance.
depends on the current velocity of the target and its acceleration. Lee pro-
posed an extension of his theory to take this case into account. He assumes
that the brain uses what he calls the “τ margin.”
Returning to the definition Lee gives, suppose that I am driving a car at ve-
locity V (for example, 110 kilometers per hour) and that a truck suddenly ap-
pears in front of me (Figure 8.1). Given my velocity V, the time-to-collision, if
I do not brake, has a certain value τ. Now I must ask what margin of time (τm)
I need to brake and not run into the truck. If I need a certain time τ to begin
braking, and if the time required to avoid a collision is τm, the distance to the
collision is (τm − t)V, and the constant deceleration to avoid the collision is V/
2(τm − t). Lee’s calculations show that if the driver needs 2 seconds to begin
braking, it would be reasonable to use a margin τm of 4 seconds for speeds up
to 110 kilometers per hour, subject to the car’s ability to decelerate at about 4
meters per second per second. However, this deceleration is so high that it is
uncomfortable, and if one wishes to decelerate at less than 2.5 meters per sec-
ond per second, τm must be approximately 8 seconds.
Thus the question is whether the brain uses these optic variables, which
are directly measurable on the retina. Two experiments suggest that the brain
uses either τ or the margin value τm—that is, optic variables—and not the
physical variables that constitute the angles, velocities of targets, and their ac-
celerations.
CAPTURE •
169
Plummeting Gannets
Picture a gannet diving from different heights to the sea to catch fish. It begins
by adopting a posture that enables it to effectively battle air resistance while
still allowing it to direct its flight. But if it were to reach the water in this posi-
tion, wings spread wide, it could get hurt. So just before entering the water,
the gannet folds its wings and assumes another aerodynamic—or, rather,
aquadynamic—posture. How does it know the precise moment to assume this
posture?
Studies of films suggest that whatever the altitude above the sea from
which it begins its descent, the bird begins to fold its wings using the τ margin
given by the expanding retinal image of the surface of the water.5 The higher
the bird starts, the higher the altitude at which it reaches this value. The films
show that the higher the altitude at which it begins its descent, the sooner the
gannet begins to streamline. This strategy allows the bird a greater distance,
as it is falling, to ready itself for contact with the water, and it has two advan-
tages: it is simple, because it uses only one optic indicator on the retina, and it
is useful, because it reduces the risk of injury.
Catching a Ball
Does this theory apply to catching a ball? Early studies on catching objects in
motion borrowed their ideas from information theory. But investigation of
natural movement quickly revealed to experimenters the existence of anticipa-
tory mechanisms whose very nature defied description in terms of informa-
tion processing. For example, well before contact, the shape of the hand
adapts to the apparent shape of an object; the muscular activity of the arm is
always initiated at the same time (before contact), no matter what the velocity
of the target. The brain seems to extract information about the ball’s move-
ment from sampling the retinal slip during a segment of the trajectory and
processes this information. Geometrical features, such as asymmetries, can be
important for predicting impact. Although this apparent distortion of the ob-
ject may indicate a change of trajectory, that is certainly not the case when the
object moves at a precise distance from the body. In an attempt to resolve
these difficulties, several research groups applied Lee’s theory to games such
as baseball, tennis, and volleyball.6
Originally, the concept of τ margin was applied only to the case in which
the ball was aimed at a person, as in baseball. But what about when the ball
goes quite far into the so-called extrapersonal space, as is the case in tennis?
170 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
Studies reveal that here, too, the movement of the racket is remarkably con-
stant and independent of the approach velocity. Thus the beginning of the
movement may in fact be adjusted by the value of the τ margin. But some-
times the movement begins after a relatively flexible delay, and a connection
between perception and action enables a person to adjust the stroke or catch
according to the trajectory of the ball.
Now imagine that a volleyball player is leaping up to reach a ball in free
fall, thrown very high by the opposing team. Lee studied this case: He asked
the player to bend his knees, then to jump right up to the ball and strike it. He
measured the angles of the elbow and the knees to evaluate the temporal
course of the movement and connected that to the height from which the ball
fell. The results demonstrated that the simplest relationships between the ac-
tion of reaching the ball and the magnitude of the fall were again obtained us-
ing the τ margin and not the actual time-to-contact.
If the brain does extract dynamic information from the appearance of the
image in motion, it is helpful to know how much time is needed to gauge
these variables and to estimate the distance, or the time, to contact. For catch-
ing a ball, numbers of 240 to 300 milliseconds have been posited. To catch a
ball travelling at a speed of 10 meters per second, the athlete has a temporal
window of 50 milliseconds during which his hand must remain closed. If he
closes it too early, he will miss the ball; if he closes it too late, the ball will
bounce off his hand. A solution roboticists like Slotine have found is to assign
the hand a speed equal to that of the ball and to have a robot hand catch the
ball in this moving frame of reference.
An experiment was conducted to determine whether subjects do use the τ
margin to catch a ball. This experiment works best with a rubber ball whose
size changes as it approaches the subject (it deflates). If the τ variable triggers
the closing of the hand, the subject must close his hand later, when the ball
deflates, for its relative size diminishes and its speed of expansion is less. This
hypothesis has since been confirmed. The distance of the ball from the body
can also be perceived in units of object size. The brain operates not by seeking
the most perfect predictive information but rather the most useful informa-
tion for regulating the action. In this case, the information does not specify
“when to be where” but “how to be in the right place at the right time” with-
out worrying about where that place will be.7
Even if these ideas are disproved in the future, they are interesting because
they suggest that the brain does not construct Cartesian space or topographic
space, but units of space connected to action.
CAPTURE •
171
The Secrets of the Graceful Gesture
When we are trying to get close to an object to grasp it, we have to curb our
movement to reach the object at zero velocity relative to it. This is also true
for birds in flight who wish to alight on a tree branch or on the ground. Lee
recently became interested in the gentle deceleration that makes it possible to
reach a target without perturbing it thanks to these graceful postures. This
achievement amounts to maintaining a constant deceleration of the moving
body until it reaches zero velocity at a precise location. Pigeons landing on
their feeder, who have to slow down their flight to land gently; acrobats exe-
cuting perilous jumps, who have to control their landing so they do not frac-
ture their ankles; a person carrying a strawberry to his mouth, who wants to
grasp the fruit delicately—anyone or anything executing a gentle braking
must evaluate time-to-contact.8 Time will judge the correctness of this the-
ory. There are other alternatives, most recently ideas inspired by the theories
of advanced dynamics systems for the control of movement of Kelso9 and
Schöner10 (see the end of this chapter).
The theories of Lee and his successors give short shrift to gravity. Does the
brain use this basic acceleration, which acts on all moving bodies, to predict
their trajectory? Have we internalized certain properties of the gravitational
field? For example, what if instead of simply having watched the apple fall
Newton had tried to catch it? How would his brain have resolved the problem?
Imagine the following experiment: You have waited impatiently for au-
tumn, and now here you are, seated beneath an apple tree in Normandy, antic-
ipating the gust of wind that will knock an apple from the tree. You hold out
your hand, palm toward the sky. The wind rises and the fruit falls straight into
your hand. This problem is simple compared with our tennis problem—you
have only to place your hand within the vertical trajectory of the apple. You
do not even have to brake gently, just adjust the dynamic parameters of your
muscles to adapt the stiffness of your hand and arm so the apple does not
bounce. It will, however, be necessary to predict the time-to-contact and the
force of the impact. How does the brain do it?
An experiment provided the answer.11 A seated subject, forearm positioned
horizontally and hand turned toward the ceiling, was asked to track and catch
a falling ball. The trick of this experiment was to place a motor at the level of
the elbow that subjected the forearm to small, very short rotations that
172 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
stretched the biceps. The subject responded to these impulsive forces by a
reflex contraction. This made it possible to test the amplitude of the reflex,
stiffness of the muscles, and so on before, during, and just after the ball
dropped. The results showed that catching a ball is preceded by an anticipa-
tory muscular activity that prepares for impact and is followed by a reflex ac-
tivity induced by the impact. If Lee was right and if the subject’s brain uses a τ
margin, the longer the duration of the fall, the earlier the anticipation of con-
tact and initiation of the muscular reaction must be. The start of anticipatory
activity of the muscles is fixed, but subjects seem to base their response,
whether anticipation or reflex, on a prediction of the dynamic properties of
the ball under the influence of gravity.
Thus the brain anticipates the dynamic properties of the ball based on sev-
eral kinds of cues: its velocity (detected by vision), its mass (estimated based
on past experience and remembered relationships among its angle, mass, and
inertia), and the influence of gravity on both limb and ball. Here we encoun-
ter the role of memory. Lacquanti concludes:
This then suggests that . . . an internal model of the dynamic interac-
tion that is expected to occur at impact is built based on a priori knowl-
edge and available on-line information (such as visual information on
the velocity of the ball and the limb). The response of this model to the
actual perturbation is compared with the response of the limb to pro-
duce an error signal. This error is subsequently used to calibrate the pa-
rameters of the neural controller of the plant [the bones and muscles]
and to update the internal model. Thus, if the model does not accu-
rately predict the desired performance, possibly because of a faulty esti-
mate of the properties of impulsive impact, kinesthetic and cutaneous
information obtained with the first trial can be used to correct the esti-
mate.12
I believe the external constraints that have been most invariant through-
out evolution have become most deeply internalized, as in the case of
CAPTURE •
175
the circadian rhythm. Such constraints may be extremely general and
abstract: The world is spatially three-dimensional, locally Euclidean,
and isotropic except for a gravitationally conferred unique upright di-
rection, and it is temporally one-dimensional and isotropic except for a
thermodynamically conferred unique forward direction.16
Initial situation
Planned trajectory → motor command → controlled object → distorted trajec-
tory
Addition of an inverse model
Planned trajectory → motor command → inverse model → modified motor
command → controlled object → ideal trajectory
178 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
Addition of a feedforward model
Planned trajectory → motor command → inverse model → modified motor
command → model of the object → virtual trajectory → comparison with the
planned trajectory → error → internal correction of error → modified motor
command → controlled object → ideal trajectory
For the brain, the advantage of working with these kinds of internal mod-
els is that if one takes into account the properties of neurons, processing time
is on the order of 30 milliseconds—much less than a return using proprio-
ception or vision (on the order of 100 to 200 milliseconds). This mechanism is
also capable of learning and adapting. In fact, it is possible to correct these in-
ternal models by sending them error signals detected by the senses or by the
internal neural circuits that monitor relationships between command and exe-
cution.
More generally, how is it possible to imagine that the networks of neurons
in the brain can be adapted to the conditions of the physical world? This pro-
cess must be implemented in the baby. Walton and Llinás made an important
observation.19 They noticed that baby rats tremble when they are with their
mother in the first days of life. This trembling is the result of electrical oscilla-
tory properties intrinsic to the motor neurons of the medulla that involve all
the limbs. Movement, or the trajectory of the limb, results from the filtering
of these neural oscillations by the mechanical properties of the body. The rat’s
sensory receptors detect these movements and relay the information back to
the medulla. This return oscillation can be used to specify the difference be-
tween central activity and actual movement and to calibrate the neural net-
works by constructing an internal model. The implications of this idea have
not been studied, and how these internal models might be constructed is not
well understood.
Children’s first movements and play thus function both as training for mo-
tor programs and also as a way to construct these internal models. Their sig-
nificance and especially the variability of the skills that children acquire de-
pend on the internal models that they have managed to construct.
Dynamic Theories
This theory of internal models of mechanical properties of the body is one
way of accounting for the capacity of the brain to simulate relations with the
environment that it can use in anticipating. But it is not the only theory, and
its working assumptions (for example, that the brain contains a representation
of the trajectory of the arm) are controversial. For several years, another
CAPTURE •
179
school of thought has taken a different tack, that of the theory of dynamic
systems, which holds that the behavior of the nervous system is integrated
with nonlinear interactions of oscillators.
The main objective of this theory is to define a paradigm for studying the
neural basis of movement. It seeks to substitute a paradigm of paired oscilla-
tors for the stimulus-response paradigm. When these oscillators function in-
teractively, they have a tendency to revert to a stable state. This tendency to re-
vert to a preferred mode of oscillation when there is a deviation from its
functioning is considered a reflection of internal properties of the system.
The dynamic systems approach refers to this property.20 It considers diver-
sion of the system from a stable state to see how it reverts to that state or how
it reorganizes itself to reach another stable state. Stable does not mean mo-
tionless. Thus, the rhythm of walking is a (dynamically) stable state. Tap on
the table with one finger of each hand at the same time. You will see that you
have a natural tendency to adopt a particular rhythm of tapping; you establish
a dynamically stable state. Now try to tap a bit more quickly with the right
hand: you are upsetting this dynamically stable pattern. Moreover, it is known
that a particular region of the brain—the supplementary motor area—is im-
mediately activated when you make such a change.
Actually, dynamic theory assumes that the variables controlled by the ner-
vous system are not only intrinsic variables of the elements of the body
(length of the muscles, muscular force, angles of joints), but also variables
connected to the task and to the kinematics of movement. These last two are
the most important; the nervous system organizes motor activity by control-
ling these so-called coordination variables.
The biological relevance of this approach remains to be demonstrated, but
it is supported by many arguments. In fact, internal neural circuits do exist,
like those that connect the cerebral cortex, the basal ganglia, and the thalamus
(which projects in turn to the cerebral cortex), or that connect the cerebral
cortex to the nuclei of the brainstem (called pontine nuclei), which themselves
project to the cerebellum and, from there, to the cortex. Internal oscillation
generators cause rhythmic activity that sweeps through these circuits (see
Chapter 1). For example, the cortico-striato-thalamo-cortical circuit is swept
by an activity oscillating at 40 Hz, other motor circuits involving the inferior
olive are swept by bursts of activity at 10 Hz, those involving the hippocampus
and the limbic system by activities of 6 to 9 Hz, and so on (see Chapter 5).
180 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
9
T H E L O O K T H AT I N V E S T I G AT E S T H E W O R L D
I have demonstrated that the critical issue is not so much a matter of catalog-
ing sensors, but what questions the curious brain asks the world based on the
assumptions it develops and tasks it proposes to carry out. The brain not only
formulates hypotheses and tests them using the sensory receptors. Evolution
made the brain a machine for predicting, not just a machine to take account
of situations. It also made it an organ for detecting, predicting, and interpret-
ing movement, for there is no action without movement. Gaze orientation was
one of the first functions that required the development of a brain that could
predict, a brain that was curious, and a brain that could simulate action.
Gaze Orientation
182 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
ent visual signals produced by the brain (spiritus visibilis) at the level of the op-
tic chiasm penetrate the eye and interact with the visual waves produced by
the objects. This interaction is then sent back to the brain, where it combines
with that of the other eye to produce a perception.
The art of the Renaissance proceeds largely from the discovery of perspec-
tive. In contrast to the stilted view of earlier paintings in the East as well as in
the West, gaze came to life and became a way of looking at the world from
various vantages. It estimated proportions and guided architectural relation-
ships.
The theory of corollary discharge is a modern version of a theory of in-
teraction (see Figure 3.4). This theory is often attributed to von Holst and
Mittelstaedt,3 but it can be traced to Bell and to Purkinje (1823–1825). Bell and
Purkinje observed that external objects seem to move when the eye is made to
move, whereas they remain constant during active gazing movements (for
more on this subject, see Chapter 10).
A copy of the motor command is sent to the center of perception when
the movement is actively triggered by the brain. This copy makes it possible to
update representations of the object and to compensate the displacement of
its image by a virtual image that remains constant. Within the framework of
cybernetic theories of servo control, which have dominated thinking about
gaze mechanisms for 20 years, the copy of the motor command corresponds
to the concept of feedforward as opposed to feedback.
The capacity for actively exploring space via orienting movements, pro-
duced not in response to environmental stimuli but according to a person’s
intention, is important. Lorenz even suggested that the organization of a pro-
gression, that is, a locomotor trajectory—based on constructing a representa-
tion of space and requiring an associated sequence of orienting movements—
is the most highly evolved form of orientation reaction.
This idea turns up again in the development of gaze in infants. When
seated in a highchair, a baby first directs his gaze using his own body as a refer-
ence point. He turns his head and eyes about the axis of his body, an egocen-
tric frame of reference. But once he begins to walk, he can no longer explore
the world with his eyes in a fixed reference system and must develop a new
strategy for keeping objects constant in space. Before 18 months, he fixates on
a landmark (for example, a corner of a table) to which he anchors his progres-
sion around the room. This strategy is probably the first sign that he is con-
structing allocentric relationships (locating an object in the environment). If
his anchor point is hidden from him, the infant reverts to an egocentric strat-
egy (related solely to his own body). At 18 months the infant adopts a third
THE LOOK THAT INVESTIGATES THE WORLD •
183
Figure 9.2. The man is climbing the stairs while keeping his head stabilized—his
head does not turn in the vertical plane. The angle of his head is dictated by the
direction of gaze. The straight line drawn on the head joins the meatus of the
ear to the external corner of the eye socket. It indicates roughly the plane of
the horizontal semicircular canal. The direction of gaze is lower than this line.
(After photographs by Muybridge)
type of functioning. He no longer fixes his gaze, but is able to mentally update
his position in the room while he is walking, employing a mechanism of men-
tal rotation and translation.
In adults, gaze is not directed at random during locomotion, as shown in
the images I drew based on photographs by Muybridge (Figure 9.2). The gaze
of a person mounting a staircase or running, or of people carrying out a task,
is oriented toward a precise goal. It can be readily stabilized in space to enable
processing of optic flow and combining of information about movement (see
184 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
Chapter 4). It can be anchored to an object, even an object someone is carry-
ing. Enormous functional flexibility succeeds egocentric organization in the
infant.
Although we are freed from the constraint of having to fix our gaze, we con-
tinue to guide locomotion, or, rather, our direction indicates anticipation of
the trajectory. You can do the experiment yourself. Clear a space of around 3
meters by 3 meters in your living room and draw a circle on the floor with
chalk. Place yourself anywhere in the circle, and look at the circle. Then close
your eyes, and make two complete tours trying to stay within the circle.
You can do the same experiment by drawing a triangle or square 3 meters
on a side, which obliges you to walk in a straight line and then to turn corners.
During these different tasks both in the light and in the dark, a person’s gaze
turns toward the interior of the concavity about 300 milliseconds in advance
of the feet and the trunk. In other words, we head toward the place we are
looking, and not the contrary. The brain does not develop a simple motor pro-
gram that enables it to proceed along a circular trajectory. It follows an inter-
nal model of the trajectory just as you pursue a moving target using your
eyes or your hand. In other words, we mentally simulate the trajectory, and
we compare the actual movement executed by our feet with the predicted
movement.4
Eye-to-Eye Contact
Gaze orientation not only enables us to fix on a target selected from the envi-
ronment, it is also required to construct a coherent representation of space in
primates and in man, whose vision is fragmented owing to development of
the fovea. Analyzing the evolution of vision in vertebrates, Gibson reminds us
that fish have a fisheye, simulated today by camera lenses, which can take in
wide surroundings with a single glance. In the course of evolution, the ap-
pearance of foveal vision was accompanied by migration of the eyes from a
lateral to a frontal position, which enabled perception of depth, tracking, and
so on. But the disadvantage of frontal vision was that animals lost their pan-
oramic vision and had to reconstruct the visual environment based on a series
of restricted views. Orientation thus was not used solely to guide the mouth
or the body, but to explore the visual world. Coordination of exploratory
movements ensures the acquisition of successive images that, according to
THE LOOK THAT INVESTIGATES THE WORLD •
185
Gibson’s example, is essential to a coherent representation of the entirety of
the room in which one happens to be.
But gaze movements do not just serve for capture or for coordinating
points of view; they also govern relationships with others. One of the func-
tions of gaze is data gathering, but it also plays a fundamental role in inter-
actional equilibrium, for example, the exchange between a mother and her
child. I will come back to this example in relating the development of ocular
movements in the infant. This exchange has fascinated the research groups of
De Ajuriaguerra, Minkowski, and Lésine, and we are indebted to Saint Anne
Dargassies for one of the first reliable descriptions of it. De Ajuriaguerra calls
it “eye-to-eye contact.” It has long been known to so dominate the act of eat-
ing that infants are sometimes totally distracted from suckling. This eye con-
tact may be among the innate triggers of maternal response. But it is not
enough to be able to direct gaze; one must also be able to turn away from the
target that attracted it.
From studies of precommunication or communication modalities be-
tween mother and infant, with reference to gaze reciprocity, we find a
whole set of ambiguous problems in their mutual understanding: the
eye that touches and that encompasses, that takes and rejects, that hears
or that listens, that licks and devours . . . the infant can follow the other
through ocular scanning without being able to leave her; fascination
gives way to intrusion. For this the two gazes must encounter each
other. And thus vision becomes sorcery . . . The infant feels more com-
fortable once this fixation becomes reversible, movable, and relative;
and when, in the love-hate battle that is created over the course of life,
exchanges that safeguard control and intentionality are established. This
happens as soon as the infant is able to break away from the magnetic
hold of another’s gaze by turning his head and closing his eyelids.5
It is now known that development of the frontal cortex enables this evasion,
because patients presenting with lesions of these regions persevere in their
fixation.
The eye of the other is not always benevolent. All Mediterranean civiliza-
tions are familiar with the “evil eye.” In North Africa and in the Near East, it is
experienced as an ambivalent organ, both receptor for the physical world and
transmitter of a living force. It flows out like water from a spring for which
the eye is named in Arabic. First fascination, then desire, it brings on misfor-
tune. As early as the third century, Heliodorus of Emesa had summed up the
essentials of these Mediterranean beliefs: “After that, it is enough for anyone
186 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
to look at a beautiful object with an envious eye to communicate pernicious
qualities to the surrounding air; his breath spreads, full of bitterness, over his
neighbour, and, thanks to its subtlety, penetrates to the bones, even to the very
marrow. Thus it is that, frequently, this species of envy which has been called
by the name of ‘fascination,’ affects the health of those whom it attacks.”6 So
the glance exchanged may also be one of horror; the orientation reaction may
turn into an avoidance reaction.
This exchange also mediates the social status of the individual in a group.
Bourdieu describes the role of gaze restraint on the habitus of the Kabyles in
this way:
The virile man who goes right to the point, bluntly, is also one who,
ignoring looks, words, gestures, contortions, faces up to and looks
straight in the face of whomever he is about to welcome or toward
whomever he is heading; always on the alert, because always under
threat, he lets pass nothing of what goes on around him, a glance lost in
the air or glued to the ground being the mark of an irresponsible man
who has nothing to fear because he is of no consequence within his
group. In contrast, a properly brought up woman, one who does noth-
ing out of turn “neither with her head, nor her hands, nor her feet,” is
expected to go about slightly bowed, eyes lowered, to avoid any gesture,
any unwarranted movement of her body, head, or arms, looking no-
where but the place where she will put her foot, especially if it happens
that she has to pass in front of a group of men . . . In short, truly femi-
nine virtue, that is, “lah’ia,” modesty, restraint, reserve—orients [italics
mine] the entire female body downward, toward the earth, the interior,
the house, whereas male excellence—the “nif ”—is confirmed in move-
ment upward, outside, toward other men.7
The historical definition of the orientation reaction must thus include pro-
cesses much more general than simple movement of the eyes toward a target.
Pavlov provided one of the first physiological descriptions of the orientation
reaction.10 According to him, the appearance of a new stimulus immediately
evokes a searching reflex; the animal trains all its relevant sensory receptors to-
ward the source of the perturbation: pricking up its ears, directing its gaze to-
ward the source, and sniffing the air. For Sokolov, who devoted many studies
to the neural basis of the orientation reflex, the question is one of a general-
ized state of alertness that is not specific to any sensory modality.11 In the
Soviet literature, the orientation reaction is thus more preparation than execu-
tion; moreover, it involves structures, like the hippocampus, that process infor-
mation at the highest level of the brain and that are particularly sensitive to
novelty.
First off, the orientation reaction involves suspension of any ongoing
movement through an increase in muscular tonicity,12 which follows from
Bernstein’s sense of the word, regarding posture as a readiness to move. It also
involves a lowering of sensory thresholds, probably connected to the nature
of the source and to the selective redistribution of tonicity, to prepare to
move. This lowering of thresholds for certain inputs preselects the senses that
will be used for orienting movements. Two kinds of simultaneous processes
occur next: one is inhibition of cortical resting activity, indicated by character-
istic slow waves in recordings of electrical potentials on the surface of the
skull. (Indeed, researchers recently demonstrated the importance of cortical
and thalamic rhythms associated with states of alert attentiveness and empha-
sized alteration of these rhythms during transitions between waiting states
and orienting movements in the cat and the monkey [see Chapter 1].)13
At the same time as these changes occur in the oscillatory activity of the
brain, and perhaps sequentially, activity increases in numerous centers (for ex-
ample, the cerebral cortex and the colliculus) activated by the hippocampus—
that detector of novelty that compares configurations of actual stimuli with
stored configurations. The excitability of other specialized receptors (for ex-
ample, vision and hearing) is also increased. Moreover, alterations occur in vis-
ceral functions and in functions of the vegetative nervous system.
In this way the entire organism prepares itself for orientation. This re-
sponse to the orienting stimulus disappears with repetition. To explain this ex-
tinction, Sokolov introduced a basic concept in his “neuronal model of stimu-
lus.” That concept continues to play a role in many theories under the names
190 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
“internal model,” “central estimation,” “prediction,” “intrinsic hypothesis,”
and so on. “This neuronal model of stimulus can be conceptualized as a ma-
trix of potentiated synapses that encode the system with reference to proper-
ties of repetitively applied stimuli.” This model registers not only the basic
properties of stimuli, but also their recurrence and co-occurrence.
The orientation reflex thus involves not only short sensorimotor loops,
but also a connection between the neocortex (a basic mechanism for analyzing
signals) and the hippocampus, which detects novelty. The reflex results in a
mismatch—today it would be called an error—between the neuronal model
of stimulus and the external signal. The core idea of this theory is that the ori-
entation reflex must not be considered simply as a motor reaction that directs
gaze or attention toward a target, but as a mechanism that establishes a transi-
tion from one state of the organism to the other.
Read this line and answer the following question: Does this sentence contain
the letter w? To answer, you have to scan the line with rapid movements of
your eyes, which are called saccades. These gaze movements are guided here
by a high-level cognitive task; they are not simple orientation reflexes toward a
spot of light. Now, look at the word below and focus your gaze on the letter N
in the middle. Without moving your eyes, see if you can find the letter Z in
the word:
anemelectrobackuppedalocutwiNdshowershednailprotectedcycle
You will note that it is possible to examine the letters of the word, at
least those that are close to N, thanks to displacements of attention.1 These
displacements of attention are in reality ocular saccades whose mechanisms
are in part the same as those for exploratory saccades, but whose execution
is inhibited. Is it possible to understand the neural mechanisms of these
gaze movements? I will proceed by detailing the neural basis of ocular sac-
cades.
But before going into the details of how saccades are organized, I will first
examine the role of inhibition.
The brain is like a spirited horse that inhibition handles much the way a horse-
man handles his reins. Refinement of sensorimotor function is in part con-
nected to the appearance, over the course of evolution, of subtle inhibitory
mechanisms, the source of new motor competencies. It is easy to think that
the brain contains only excitatory neurons. Rarely is any other role accorded
to inhibition than that of suppression. This is borne out by the current expres-
sion “to be inhibited” in the negative sense of not being able to do something.
Yet neural inhibition is actually one of the basic mechanisms of production of
movement and its flexibility, and probably the main mechanism of sensori-
motor training. It is also the source of perceptual mechanisms of filtering and
selection and plays a decisive role in certain cognitive functions such as deci-
sion making.
MacKay assigns inhibition the leading role in his theory of mental nodes.2
Autoinhibition is necessary to ensure that centers of integration, called mental
nodes, are not superactivated by the echo of signals coming from nodes lo-
cated downstream in the network that controls action, or by sensory mes-
sages. So stuttering, for example, corresponds to an inability to inhibit such an
echo, leading to repetition or disruptions in language.
Inhibition takes extraordinarily varied forms in the nervous system. Local
inhibitory neurons were the first to be described. For example, the motor neu-
rons of the medulla (which activate the muscles) are inhibited by small local
neurons, called Renshaw neurons, that are activated by the motor neurons
themselves, whose recurring inhibition is their mode of regulation. Also in the
medulla, inhibitory interneurons called Ia inhibitory neurons combine infor-
mation from several sensory receptors with commands from the brain. They
play a fundamental role in organizing movements. In the cerebellum, inhibi-
tory neurons called Golgi neurons or basket neurons control the internal ac-
tivity of the organ. In the thalamus, inhibitory neurons contribute to the pro-
duction of oscillations, and so on. The full list would be long, but it would be
worth drawing up.
One of the first functional roles attributed to inhibition was reciprocal
innervation, that is, braking or blockage of antagonist muscle during a ges-
ture. This mechanism is very simple. When you want to lift your arm, you
have to activate the motor neurons of the biceps, but you also have to inhibit
the activity of the antagonist muscle, the triceps. Reciprocal innervation is as-
sured throughout the nervous system by inhibitory neurons. These neurons
are also found in mechanisms of gaze control. For example, they are found in
the vestibulo-ocular reflex: projection neurons called inhibitory second-order
vestibular neurons induce reciprocal innervation of the muscles of the eyes
(see Chapter 2 and Figure 2.4).
Ito’s discovery of the inhibitory nature of the Purkinje cell in the cerebel-
lum was a major finding.3 Eccles and his students had made a detailed study of
this remarkable cell, which is the sole neuronal exit from the cerebellum. This
VISUAL EXPLORATION •
193
neuron (whose morphology was revealed by the work of Sotelo in Paris,
among others) projects to several structures important in regulating and coor-
dinating movement. Moreover, it is now thought that the cerebellum also
plays a role in certain cognitive activities.4 The fact that the main projection
neuron of an organ as important as the cerebellum is inhibitory demonstrates
the importance of a form of neural activity that researchers of the time
thought could do no more than brake, or simply reverse, the direction of a
command or a signal.
Another form of inhibition probably plays a fundamental role in the selec-
tion of sensory messages that accompany the planning of action: inhibitory
neurons, located in the spinal medulla, inhibit sensory fibers just before they
synapse on the target neurons of the medulla. This presynaptic inhibition is a
gating mechanism for sensory input or modulation of its amplitude. Thus
there are at least two major mechanisms for controlling messages from the
proprioceptive receptors: γ and β commands on the spindles (see Chapter 2)
and presynaptic inhibition. The brain has many ways of selecting sensory
messages.
Cellular mechanisms of inhibition are also extraordinarily complex.
Twenty years ago, this inhibition was thought to result from regulating trans-
port of chloride ion across the neuronal membrane. The inhibitory neuron
produced a hyperpolarization of the neuronal membrane, which distanced it
from its firing potential and, consequently, prevented it from firing. It is now
known that numerous neurotransmitters are responsible for synaptic inhibi-
tion (GABA, glycine, and so on), that several can be present in the endings of a
single neuron, that inhibitory action can take diverse forms via blockage of
numerous ion channels, that two successive inhibitions can be expressed by an
excitation, that a combination of inhibition and disinhibition can have a multi-
plier effect or be used simply to introduce a delay, and so on. Molecular biol-
ogy is currently completely overhauling our ideas about the mechanisms of
inhibition. The work of Korn and his group in Paris also highlighted the pow-
erful role of inhibition in modulating the excitability and plasticity of neural
activity.5
It is impossible to broach this immense domain in just a few pages without
falling into one of two traps, either a surfeit of details or neural tourism. But I
will look at one example: the control of gaze, more particularly, the ocular
saccade, to show how inhibition operates as a mechanism of selection and in
what Piaget called “internalization” of sensorimotor behavior, and in motor
imagination.6
194 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
A Model of Perception-Action Relationships
A saccade is a change in the direction of gaze when the eye turns. It is rapid
(20 to 150 milliseconds) and attains angular velocities of 800 degrees per sec-
ond. It is the fastest movement humans are capable of producing. Each sac-
cade consists of a rotation, followed sometimes by a slight shift to adjust the
axis of gaze on the target, and sometimes other small correctional saccades if
the gaze has not reached its objective.
Look at a point straight ahead of you and make a big saccade toward an
object in the room. You will perceive neither movement nor change of posi-
tion in the room, even though its image has shifted on your retina. This per-
ceptual invariance is due to a mechanism called saccadic inhibition, which
blocks the neural messages from the retina during the saccade and prevents
you from being aware of the shift, seen but not perceived by the retina, be-
cause it remains blocked at the first visual relays. Moreover, a mechanism of
perceptual shift maintains the positional stability of the environment.
I have made the following observation, which I invite you to confirm. If I
focus on an object in the room for about 20 seconds, and then make a big
saccade to focus my gaze on another object in the room, at the start of the
first saccade, I actually have the impression that the world is moving slightly.
But if I repeat it several times, my perception of the world is remarkably sta-
ble. I think that in the latter case, I anticipate the displacement of my gaze,
which spares me the slight impression of shifting. I will examine the mecha-
nisms at the level of the parietal cortex that may account for this stabilizing
anticipation.
The results of the following experiment reproduce the observations of
pioneers such as Purkinje, Bell, Helmholtz, and numerous other physicists and
biologists who were all fascinated by these phenomena. Press laterally, rather
hard, on your eyes to displace them. Don’t be afraid—eyes aren’t fragile! If
you look straight ahead of you, you will see that during this passive move-
ment of your eyes, the room seems to move in front of you. In other words,
when your retinal image of the world is displaced, you have a perception of
displacement of the world. In contrast, when you are actively gazing, the
world looks stable despite retinal slip. Feedforward neural processes associated
with the production of movement thus ensure perceptual stabilization. Many
mechanisms have been suggested to explain this phenomenon. The most plau-
sible is the use of an efference copy or corollary discharge (see Chapter 3 and
Figure 3.4).7
VISUAL EXPLORATION •
195
These examples show what an interesting model the saccade is for study-
ing the most highly developed mechanisms of active perception. But it gets
even more interesting. Yarbus, a Russian psychologist, was the first (followed
by Stark at Berkeley, Jeannerod in France, and the neurologists Lhermitte and
Chain of the Salpêtrière Hospital) to show that the oculomotor path (the se-
quence of saccades) followed to explore a face is completely different depend-
ing on what the observer is thinking: whether she thinks that the individual is
rich, sad, or well-coifed, that his ears are protruding, and so on. Similarly, in
front of a landscape, the oculomotor path taken depends on what a person is
seeking. To explore a face or an environmental scene requires complex cogni-
tive decisions, so it is easy to see why the saccade is an interesting model for
studying motor selection and decision processes. These paths are altered in pa-
tients presenting with lesions of the brain.
Finally, the production of saccades, like all our actions, requires access to
memory. Visual memory is the first type: I can ask you to look at an image
that follows a precise oculomotor path with a defined rhythm, then, in dark-
ness, to repeat the same path.8 Vestibular memory is another: I can ask you to
focus on an object in front of you on the table, then to turn in your chair in
the dark and not move your eyes; then I can ask you to make a saccade toward
the memorized position of the object. In both cases, the saccades will be per-
fectly executed, which demonstrates the saccadic system’s access to spatial
memory.9 I touched on these mechanisms in Chapter 5.
Next, I will consider the principal stages in producing a saccade. I will not
go into particulars, but will roughly describe the general organization, as a
physiologist does, even though it means losing a little of the fine grain of the
analysis. I will start at the end—the motor centers of the brainstem—and
move little by little toward the cortex. This method, from the bottom up, is
contrary to the apparently more natural approach of examining the successive
stages of image analysis. But I want to show that saccades are indeed executed
hierarchically, which enables gating at different levels by inhibitory mecha-
nisms, and that the same neural structures are brought into play in imagined
movement of the eye as well as in actual movement.10 The brain does not only
carry out sensorimotor transformations; at several levels, motor commands in-
fluence how sensory data are processed. So, starting from the motor com-
mand comes back to thinking of action as an essential element of neural func-
tioning and enables us to study how it organizes perception instead of simply
trying to find out how perception defines action. A saccade is a decision to act,
not a response to a stimulus.11
196 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
Saccadic Generators in the Brainstem
Figures 10.1 and 10.4 summarize some of the neural operations involved in
the control of ocular saccades. My account is, of course, not exhaustive. I will
review the saccadic system briefly and then discuss the individual elements. I
use the word “neuron” to characterize each type of neuron, but what is in-
volved is populations; that is, groups of diffusely or centrally localized neu-
rons, or nuclei.
Let us begin with the last stage of execution: the ocular saccade is actually
produced by the firing of motor neurons, called motoneurons (Mn), which ac-
tivate motor fibers in the muscles of the eyes. These discharge with a very par-
ticular modulation of frequency made up of two successive parts.
First, a very intense burst of phasic activity (that is, a series of action po-
tentials of high frequency and short duration) penetrates the viscous eye. This
allows the saccade to be executed in a few dozen milliseconds. The premotor
neuron, which produces the phasic activity that moves the eye toward its new
position, is called the excitatory burst neuron (EBN) and is located in the
brainstem for horizontal movements (EBNH) and in the reticular formation
of the mesencephalon for vertical movements (EBNV). There are thus two
separate centers for the two types of movement. This is the same geometric
segregation I have mentioned in other chapters. The discharge of EBNs pre-
cedes the start of the saccade by around 10 to 15 milliseconds and projects di-
rectly to the ocular motor neurons. Their immediate frequency is connected
(depending on one’s interpretation) either to motor error or to the velocity of
the eye. Generating an accurate copy of the displacement of the eye simply re-
quires integrating the activity of these neurons (that is, adding up the number
of action potentials). These phasic neurons also project to the local inhibitory
neurons (called interneurons) situated in the vestibular nuclei. The functional
significance of this projection is important: it blocks the vestibulo-ocular reflex
during orienting movements. If not for this inhibition, the eye and head could
not be directed toward a target, because the vestibular-ocular reflex tends to
displace the eye in a sense contrary to that of the head (see Figure 2.4).12 This
is an example of the way in which inhibition achieves automatic coordination
between two motor subsystems that have opposing functions.
Second, a sustained tonic discharge is necessary to maintain the position
of the eye in its socket. The more the eye moves, the higher the tonic fre-
quency: this is the signal of movement that is sent to the motor neurons. The
two saccadic generators that receive a dynamic signal from the brain trans-
VISUAL EXPLORATION •
197
E
Coordination
∆E of responses SMA SEF
Short-term
memory
5 4 PM FEF Pre Fr
PO 7A LIP VIP +
Str
V4 V3 MT +
GPe
V2 Thal STN
V1 Suppression − + Disfacilitation
SNpr
LGN
Temporal Pul
and spatial
selection
− +
Fix
Dynamic SC
remapping − ?
TRSN P
Motor error −
and desired
eye velocity Cajal
V Eye
Mn
+
EBN LR
Corollary V Ph E Mn
discharge +
H
−−
EBN
H Proprioception
− IBN + ?
RSN
Coupling of
head and eyes
RSN
Nuchal command
NECK
Figure 10.1. Saccadic movement of the eye (lower right) is produced by phasic
excitatory neurons located in the pontine and mesencephalic reticular forma-
tion. The position of the eye is controlled by integrators. Copies of signals
about movement of the eye are sent to the colliculus and to the cortex (arrows
at right) and cause changes in the maps where position is encoded and where
the saccade is initiated. The saccadic generator can be inhibited at a first level in
the brainstem by the pauser neurons (P) and at other levels by a cascade of inhi-
bitions.
form it into continuous activity owing to a local neural mechanism called the
integrator. There is assumed to be one integrator for each of the two types of
movement, horizontal and vertical. These are indicated by the symbol ∫ in
Figure 10.1.
As with the integrator of the vestibulo-ocular reflex, the mechanisms at
work are still not well understood. They may involve properties of the neural
membrane as well as those of neural networks. It is known that if a lesion is
introduced to a small area close to the vestibular nuclei, the eye no longer
maintains its horizontal position after a saccade. By analogy with electronic
circuits, it is said that the integrator leaks. This appears to be a local mecha-
nism. The final position of the eye is thus developed very late in the process,
probably using internal models of the eye. You will see why this is interesting
for imagining movement.
200 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
neurons of the substantia nigra that inhibit the collicular neurons19 cannot sus-
pend their activity and trigger the saccade unless they are themselves inhibited
by the neurons of the caudate nucleus in the striatum.20 These neurons fire
during voluntary saccades and are also active during saccades toward memo-
rized targets. They are most likely involved in cognitive control of saccadic ini-
tiation.
But the process of saccadic selection is even more complex and subtle. Re-
cent findings reveal that, concurrently with the cascade of inhibitions involv-
ing the caudate nucleus and the substantia nigra, a second cascade of inhibi-
tion and excitation accompanies and reinforces selection. This pathway, whose
target is the colliculus and whose terminus is the subthalamic nucleus (STN),
is made up of an inhibitory neuron, located in the striatum and projecting to
the globus pallidus externus (GPe), which projects to another inhibitory neu-
ron that in turn projects to the subthalamic nucleus. The target neuron in the
subthalamic nucleus is excitatory and projects to an inhibitory neuron in the
substantia nigra that suppresses activity in the colliculus, just as the neurons
of the first pathway do. The STN also projects to the colliculus.
What is important is that the basal ganglia are not just components of
simple command pathways: they form part of the internal circuits that con-
nect the cortex, the basal ganglia, and the thalamus (Th), and that feed back to
the cortex. In Chapter 1 I mentioned the possible role of these circuits and the
sustained oscillations that traverse them in the development of mental repre-
sentations. Hikosaka recently asserted that signals connected to a reward can
influence them (Figure 10.2).21 According to Hikosaka, the basal ganglia play a
coordinating role among the different cortical areas involved in developing
motor strategies. These areas are functionally connected in the course of
training based on reward. The limbic system signals the basal ganglia as to
whether the chosen movement will lead to a reward. This method of selection
is thus even more complex and subtle than a simple gating mechanism at the
level of the brainstem or spatiotemporal selection at the level of the colliculus
(Figure 10.3).
The pleasure taken in looking at something, or the fear of what might be
seen, or how interesting an object is—all contribute to the selection of sac-
cades by these parallel cascades of inhibition and excitation.
It is not possible to describe here the totality of structures that contribute
to the development of saccades. For example, it is clear that the cerebellum
plays an essential role in regulating motor commands that modulate the am-
plitude, velocity, and duration of saccades. Lesions of the cerebellum cause
VISUAL EXPLORATION •
201
Brain 1
Motor
program Motor
outputs
Basal ganglia
Reward
Sensory inputs
Brain 2
Motor
program Motor
outputs
Prediction
of Basal ganglia
reward
Internal model
Reward
Sensory inputs
Figure 10.2. Evolution of the basal ganglia. In primitive animals (Brain 1), the
basal ganglia activate the elements of a genetically programmed repertoire of
movements. The efficiency and success of the movements are enhanced by in-
centives that adjust these behaviors under similar conditions. In higher animals
and in humans (Brain 2), the behavior is more complex. A new mechanism
(which probably involves the prefrontal cortex) makes predictions based on an
internal neural model that simulates the different possible movements and eval-
uates their chances of success. The consequences of the resulting behavior are
compared with this prediction and may modify the internal model.
202 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
Associative cortex
Limbic system
Motor cortex
many oculomotor signs. The reticular neurons that control saccades are mod-
ulated by the cerebellum, itself involved in regulatory circuits that originate in
and return to the cerebral cortex. Remember that the motor exit of the cere-
bellum is inhibitory (the Purkinje cells are inhibitory). Once again, inhibition
is involved in the control of movement.
Thus, concurrently with the hierarchical cascade of inhibitions of the
pausers and basal ganglia, there exists a supplementary regulatory mechanism
based on inhibition. Moreover, subdivisions of the cerebellum play different
roles in controlling the movement of eyes. The vermis (the median portion of
the cerebellum), which dates far back in evolution, probably regulates auto-
matic movements, and the lateral portions (the neocerebellum), which are
connected to the frontal cortex, probably regulate more complex gaze move-
ments, though this is pure speculation. If, as recent theories suggest, the cere-
bellum contains internal models of motor apparatuses and also facilitates the
temporal coordination of movements, this structure, together with the cere-
bral cortex, is crucial in preparing gaze movements.
VISUAL EXPLORATION •
203
Cortical Control of Saccades
To examine the contribution of the cerebral cortex in controlling saccades, I
will start with the retina. Two major pathways transmit information from the
retina to the colliculus: one goes directly from the retina to the superficial lay-
ers of the colliculus; the other projects the image of visual targets toward the
visual cortex through the intermediary of a relay called the lateral geniculate
nucleus (LGN) (Figures 10.1 and 10.4). Interestingly, neural activity connected
to the saccade itself has been found in this first visual relay. As with the vestib-
ular nuclei, the motor command modulates sensory inputs. In other words,
action modifies perception at its source. The brain is not constructed of simple
systems that transform sensory signals into motor commands, but of closed
circuits.
This reentrant information—these copies of the motor command that
represent eye movements—is perhaps used as a substitute for sensory inputs.
The movement of the eye is equivalent to that of a target, since moving my
eye 20 degrees to the right amounts to the same thing as moving the target 20
degrees to the left.22 Information on the position of the target is next transmit-
ted to primary visual area V1, from whence it activates the neurons of areas
V2, V3, then the parietal cortex, a very important relay in developing saccades.
The parietal cortex is an area of the brain that is essential in representing
space and relationships between the body and the external world.23 Although
from the early part of the century the parietal cortex was conceded a basic
role in constructing the body schema, opinion is still divided between theories
that further define that role as directing visual attention and others that see it
as planning movements. The parietal cortex is part of the dorsal system of vi-
sual information processing that is concerned with localizing objects, their
movements, and the relationships between objects and intended action. The
parietal cortex is not only involved in localizing objects (knowing where they
are) and their relationship to the body; it also contributes to preparing actions
(knowing how to grasp objects and handle them). Lesions of the right parietal
cortex cause hemispatial neglect (see Chapter 3).
Neuronal recordings reveal the involvement of the parietal cortex in visuo-
spatial behavior. Some authors posit that a change of coordinates occurs in the
parietal cortex that reconstructs the position of the target in space by sum-
ming its position in relation to the eye with that of the eye in relation to the
head and of the head in relation to the body, and so on.
The parietal cortex is divided into specialized zones connected to particu-
lar areas in the frontal cortex. Some are more specifically involved in preparing
204 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
V3a Parietal cortex
LIP
V1 L
7a
Occipital cortex V2
7b
CN
SN
-
LG
-
N
-
SC Tha
l
-
SEF FEF
-
Frontal cortex
-
PFC
Prefrontal cortex
EBN
Figure 10.4. The principal production pathways of the ocular saccade. The first goes di-
rectly to the superficial layers of the superior colliculus (SC), where it is transferred to the
deep layers whose neurons project to those that produce the saccade (excitatory burst neu-
rons, EBN). A second pathway traverses the lateral geniculate nucleus (LGN) in the
thalamus and projects to the visual areas of the occipital cortex (V1, V2, V3). From there,
the information is transmitted to the parietal cortex, where it is combined with informa-
tion concerning the movements of the head and body in space and with internal signals
(memory, general context of action, and so on). The centers of the parietal cortex them-
selves project to the supplementary eye field (SEF), which coordinates sequences of sac-
cades, and to the frontal eye field (FEF), located in humans in the precentral gyrus. The
precentral gyrus projects to the SC and also directly to the brainstem. The prefrontal cor-
tex (PFC) plays a role in the most cognitive aspects of the production of saccades, and a
mechanism containing a cascade of inhibitions facilitates their selection. It involves the
caudate nucleus (CN) in the striatum and the substantia nigra pars reticulata (SNpr), which
projects to the colliculus.
VISUAL EXPLORATION •
205
gaze movements, in particular saccades or ocular pursuit. The intensity of
their neuronal responses depends on the direction of gaze.24 So a signal of de-
tection of the position of the eye in its socket from the depths of the brain—
from the neural integrator of the brainstem—is added to the activity of the
neurons caused by vision. The position of the target in space is also encoded
by other visual areas.25 Recent findings have shown that this area is the center
of multisensory convergence where visual, vestibular, and proprioceptive mes-
sages are combined. The neurons of these areas contribute to preparing and
directing the saccade; they fire just before its initiation. Some say that the pari-
etal cortex forms and maintains spatial coordinates that enable localization of
objects and determine their position in space,26 and that the prefrontal cortex
(PFC) uses this knowledge to direct a response; others say that movements are
encoded in coordinates connected to the head, in particular to the eye itself,
and do not require any internal reconstruction of the position of the target in
spatial coordinates.27 Nevertheless, the question of the frame of reference in
which this system functions has yet to be resolved.
The lack of activity of certain areas of the parietal cortex during voluntary
saccades in the dark shows that they are mainly involved in visuospatial pro-
cessing. However, using positron emission tomography (PET), we have dem-
onstrated for the first time that they are also activated (together with frontal
areas) in humans during tasks of memorized saccades carried out in the dark.28
Successfully performing this task requires accessing the spatial memory that
recorded the position of the targets, and recalling their order; thus it means
producing a mental image of their positions to make a sequence of saccades.
Patients with lesions of the parietal cortex make less accurate, delayed sac-
cades.
Without summarizing the properties of the parietal cortex, which may
also be involved in the memory of movement and in spatial memory,29 in deci-
sions connected to the perception of movement,30 and so on, I will once again
consider the essential role of anticipation and prediction in the organization
of the brain. Indeed, I have shown from the outset that the senses detect the
derivatives of sensory signals, that in this way they can anticipate future states.
They can do this because motor signals modify sensory inputs, which alters
perception based on action, and inhibition selects messages based on intended
movement. But there is something even more remarkable: the nervous system
can ensure the stability of the perceived world during movement by updating
visual frames of reference in advance.
When the eye is stationary, visual objects are picked up by various neurons
of the visual system according to where the objects are in space. It is said that
206 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
these neurons have receptor fields (see also Chapter 3). These fields are small
for the first relays of the visual system (area V1), but become increasingly
larger over the course of successive stages of visual processing (areas V2, MT,
MST, and so on). Up to now the question was thought to be one of the rigid
properties of the neurons of the visual cortex, with fixed coordinates in the
retinal space. The localization in space of the receptor field of a neuron of the
parietal cortex is abruptly displaced before the saccade, in the direction of the
gaze movement about to be made.31 In other words, before the saccade that
leads the gaze from one point in space to another, the brain displaces the re-
ceptor field as if it wished to anticipate the consequences of movement.
The advantage of this transitory anticipation is that the retinal representa-
tion of the world remains stable during movement. In other words, the brain
places itself in the final reference system, adopting the vantage it will have on
the visual world even before making the movement.
More than 20 years ago, an experiment done in our laboratory predicted
these findings, which were obtained recently in the monkey.32 You can try this
experiment yourself. Look at the upper left corner of this page and make a
single saccade toward the right lower corner. If you hold the book in front of
you, the saccade will have an amplitude of about 40 degrees. Your eye will
move about 400 degrees per second and thus cannot make use of vision be-
cause of the considerable shifting of the image on the retina. We observed
that subjects could grasp words, although their eyes always moved faster than
200 degrees per second (which we recorded precisely using a magnetic field
technique that I introduced in France) even when they slowed down in the
middle of the page. We concluded from this that an active process of displace-
ment of the receptor fields enabled the brain to compensate for the image’s
shifting on the retina via an anticipatory mechanism connected to the in-
tended movement. In the 1950s, Verguiless and Zinchenko in Moscow spoke
of the “functional fovea.”
This is why I keep saying that the boundaries between sensation and mo-
tor function are disappearing. For the same reason, an internal copy of a
movement command signal can be used as a signal given by the senses, and is
itself influenced by movement from the first central neurons and, even, at the
periphery.
It does appear that the information needed to produce simple saccades to-
ward a visual target are transmitted from the parietal cortex to the frontal eye
field (FEF), which projects directly to the colliculus.33 Ferrier,34 then Penfield,35
showed that electrically stimulating the frontal eye field produces eye move-
ments. In the monkey, the frontal eye field contains several types of neu-
VISUAL EXPLORATION •
207
rons that fire in connection with saccades, ocular fixation, pursuit, and so on.
In humans, its activation during saccades was demonstrated through sev-
eral pioneering efforts.36 Its localization in the precentral gyrus is now well es-
tablished.37 Generally, this area is activated during all voluntary saccadic move-
ments.
The importance of this area is not due only to the fact that it projects di-
rectly to the colliculus. It is part of an internal circuit that I have mentioned
several times as being one of the neural bases important for the internal simu-
lation of movement. In fact, a circuit connects this cortical area with the basal
ganglia and the thalamus.
Another area important for anticipation and prediction in developing
movements is the supplementary motor area (SMA), located in the median
portion of the frontal lobe, in front of the actual motor areas. Its location was
studied by recording electrical (EEG) and magnetic (MEG)38 activity and by
PET.39 It is also important to remember that it is part of the circuits that con-
nect certain structures of the basal ganglia and the thalamus. Its function is
thus associated with theirs, and even with that of the cerebellum. It also func-
tions in connection with the parietal, prefrontal, and cingulate cortex.
The neurons of this area are arranged in a sort of map of the body as in
the motor cortex (somatotopy). For example, in humans and in monkeys, fa-
cial movements are obtained by stimulating the anterior portion. This area
may command groups of muscles and complex motor synergies. It is involved
in global actions, since it initiates, for example, activity of the muscles of the
left hand only when the movement mobilizes both hands. It also comes into
play when the subject must make a choice, or decide whether to make a move
(go–no go). Moreover, it is activated during sequences of movements.
In humans, lesions of the SMA cause alternating movement deficits of the
limbs, mutism, disordered language, and impairments in gestural sequencing,
bimanual coordination, memorized movements, and especially endogenously
produced movements (movements that are freely constructed by the brain
even in the absence of external stimulation). These findings have been con-
firmed by EEG recordings taken on the surface of the human skull. In the area
of the cortex that corresponds to the SMA, a slow electric potential (readiness
potential, discovered by Kornhuber and Deecke), precedes a simple finger
movement by about a second and a half. This area is strongly activated when
the subject is asked to do a bimanual tapping task with a different rhythm for
each hand, as in playing a piano piece.40 It scarcely registers in simpler move-
ments, which mainly activate the motor cortex.
It has been suggested that the motor cortex contributes primarily to en-
208 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
dogenous movements, whereas the premotor cortex contributes to move-
ments caused by sensory signals. This distinction could be profound and may
go far back in evolution. In the mammalian family tree, the SMA has its origin
in the hippocampus and a limbic root in the anterior cingulate cortex. The
premotor cortex probably had its origin in the piriform cortex and its root in
the insula. Subcortical inputs from the SMA mostly come from the basal gan-
glia via the thalamus, whereas the premotor cortex receives its inputs from the
cerebellum. The SMA connects to several areas of the cortex involved in per-
ception of space and of the body. This distinction indicates a possible special-
ization of these areas in endogenous movements for the SMA and exogenous
movements for the premotor cortex.
Whereas the posterior portion of the SMA is clearly involved in coordinat-
ing movements, the anterior portion contributes to more cognitive aspects.
The anterior portion (pre-SMA) is connected with the prefrontal cortex and
receives inputs from area 46 (anterior premotor cortex) and the anterior
cingulum involved in intended movement and attention, and perhaps in train-
ing sequences of new movements (playing a Bach fugue, or dancing choreo-
graphed steps). Electrical or magnetic stimulation of the pre-SMA arouses an
intention to move; subjects say, “I feel like moving.” Recent findings obtained
by PET suggest that the anterior portion of the pre-SMA is activated during
imagined movement of the fingers, and the posterior portion during the ac-
tual movement.
There appears to be a further subdivision of the SMA itself unique to gaze
movements. Stimulating this area produces ocular saccades that instead of
having a fixed direction, all converge toward a single point.41 In the monkey,
this area is called the supplemental eye field (SEF). Patients with lesions of the
SEF present with problems in executing sequences of two or three saccades
toward memorized visual targets,42 as well as saccades toward a memorized
target after a rotation; that is, after vestibular stimulation.
The SMA is also connected to the basal ganglia and to the thalamus via a
neural circuit that is probably involved in establishing new movements and in
assessing the rewards or outcome of an ongoing action (see Figures 10.2 and
10.3). A special circuit for eye movements exists among the basal ganglia-
thalamo-cortical loops specifically concerned with different motor functions.
Under the frontal cortex, the motor and parietal cortex are connected to a
region of the cortex called the cingulate cortex, whose anterior portion is in-
volved in attention and in perceptual decision making. It is associated with the
prefrontal cortex and perhaps also is involved in emotion. The median portion
has more to do with motor function, and its neurons probably contribute to
VISUAL EXPLORATION •
209
organizing movement of the hands, eyes, and head. In humans it is activated
during saccades43 and during endogenous (that is, produced by the subject)
movements of the fingers even in the dark, and thus contributes to creating
movements based on memory. The posterior portion is involved in perceptual
reorganization after a movement, or even following corrective control. In fact,
the neurons of the posterior cingulate cortex fire after ocular saccades, and
their activity depends on the characteristics of the preceding saccade.44 Thus
this region may contribute to integrating the consequences of action in a sen-
sory or motor context.
I have examined the role of the brainstem as an ultimate controller, the
colliculus as a visual-oculomotor interface, the parietal cortex as a predictor
and spatio-temporal transformer, and the frontal areas as preparatory centers.
I will now consider the role of the prefrontal cortex in the higher cognitive op-
erations that control gaze orientation. Findings from neurophysiology show
that in the monkey, neurons of the prefrontal cortex (PFC) are involved in orga-
nizing ocular saccades that are simple but are carried out with a delay.45 They
are also involved in training for sequences of movements or actions that obey
a rule,46 or require either memorizing a context or deciding among several
movements, which necessitates selective attention combined with memory.47
This function of representational memory and of work is thought to be one
of the main functions of the prefrontal cortex.48
Patients with lesions of this portion of the cortex have trouble refusing re-
quests—controlling themselves, one might say. They also have trouble making
decisions and especially changing the rules of conduct once they have decided
to act according to a certain rule or have established a plan of action. These
patients are often deficient in performing tasks that require making saccades
toward visual targets they must memorize49 or when they are expected to
make a saccade that corresponds to a rotation in the dark; that is, one based
on vestibular information (see the protocol for vestibular saccades described in
Chapter 5).50
They also fail at so-called antisaccadic tasks, which consist in making a
saccade in a sense contrary to that of the illuminated target.51 (Try it yourself:
Ask a friend to strike a match on your right and force yourself to direct your
gaze with a single saccade in a direction opposite to the match; for example, to
the left if the match is on your right.) Moreover, in the monkey and in hu-
mans, prefrontal regions are involved in the command not to execute a move
(no go).52 Thus, there are probably mechanisms for selection and control of
gaze orientation at this level that could be identified by imaging. Connections
210 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
of the prefrontal cortex with the hippocampus, the parietal cortex, the SMA—
all the areas involved in the voluntary production of saccades—suggest that a
cortical system is involved in the construction of exploratory paths taken
when we look at a visual scene, but probably also in spatial memory in gen-
eral.53 In any case, the prefrontal cortex surely contributes to the mental simu-
lation of movements and displacements.54
So the prefrontal cortex is involved in processes of decision in the course
of “voluntary” actions,55 and more specifically when we alter our gaze based
on affective or social constraints. Impairment of gaze organization observed in
persons with schizophrenia (for example, distraction and deterioration of the
ability to make predictions) are perhaps attributable in part to dysfunctions of
the prefrontal cortex.56 Understanding these mechanisms, which are funda-
mental to the development of thought and reasoning, will require new experi-
ments using brain imaging in humans and neural recordings in animals.
Now I will present the arguments supporting the idea that inhibition plays an
essential role in internal simulation of action. But first I will summarize. First
to appear were mechanisms that block saccades by means of pauser neurons;
that is, a blocking mechanism of the collicular orienting reflex to prevent the
animal from making a saccade the instant a visual target appeared. Then inhi-
bition enabled blocking of the vestibulo-ocular reflex. Both mechanisms were
required for a saccade to occur.
Next came inhibitory control by the substantia nigra of discharges of the
neurons of the colliculus. This control was more subtle, because it allowed
genuine selection of the part of the visual field toward which a saccade would
be made. Moreover, inhibitory cascades in the striatum probably enabled
working out the decision to make a saccade based on many other criteria im-
portant for the animal. At this stage of evolution, it was already possible to
simulate saccades without having to make them. Thus, displacements of at-
tention are saccades that are blocked at the lower premotor levels. I have pro-
posed a theory of the hierarchical organization of inhibitory mechanisms to
explain the common mechanisms of executed and imagined or simulated
movements, and to account for the possibility of selectively blocking the exe-
cution of movement at several levels of the sensory motor system. This
theory suggests that there is not a simple dichotomy between imagined and
executed movements but a hierarchical superposition of different levels of
VISUAL EXPLORATION •
211
possible blockage. This theory extends the motor theory of perception advo-
cated for eye movements by Rizzolatti and colleagues.57
Development of the cerebellum probably enabled modulation as well as a
choice of coordination between the saccade and other motor systems. Finally,
the entire neural machinery of the cortex was put into place. When the
colliculus is inhibited and the pausers are active, the set of cortical structures
can prepare and simulate oculomotor paths: no saccade is observed. Inhibitory
gating of execution thus permits the brain to imagine displacements of gaze
without carrying them out. You can see for yourself that you do indeed have
this option. Focus on a point in front of you and displace your internal gaze—
your attention, as some would say, your “functional fovea,” as Verguiless
would say. You will have the undeniable impression that your gaze is displaced
from one point of the room to the other.
The same neural structures thus ought to be used for imagined move-
ments and for actual movements, since it is possible to gate execution at differ-
ent levels without suppressing the functioning of internal circuits in which
gaze movements are developed and simulated. To check this assumption, we
compared the cortical areas activated during actual saccades and imagined sac-
cades.58 We measured ocular movements to make sure that the amplitude of
the saccade remained insignificant during the imagined movement. The sub-
ject was asked to focus on a point of light in front of him and, first, to make
voluntary horizontal saccades, then, with the target obscured by the dark, to
make imagined saccades similar to the actual ones. Under these conditions,
the oculomotor field, the SMA, and the cingulate cortex were activated during
the imagined movements just as they had been during the actual saccades.
So perhaps the motor theory of attention is true. When you look at the
long word that appears at the beginning of this chapter, focusing on the N in
the middle and looking to see if there is a Z, you bring into play the same cir-
cuits as those that are active during an actual saccade. But there may be alter-
native interpretations. Only experimentation will tell. I mentioned earlier that
there were possibly differences in the roles of the pre-SMA and the SMA.
VISUAL EXPLORATION •
215
11
BALANCE
What a proud look the young child displays to his admiring relatives the first
time he stands on his own: in an instant he has summed up several million
years of evolution, definitively freeing his hands for the use of tools and feats
of manual dexterity and art. Suddenly, escaping the caves of early infancy,
head in the stars, Caliban turned Ariel due solely to the play of muscles that
control posture, he triumphs over gravity, which up to now held him to the
floor and obliged him to sit down to touch objects and beings. What mecha-
nisms underlie this achievement?
The discovery by Sherrington and his school of the mechanism that causes
a muscle to contract when it is stretched led to a view of balance as the link-
ing up of a multitude of local reflexes: when the body bends under the effect
of gravity, muscle receptors as well as those of the joints, vestibular system,
and even vision detect this bending and cause a muscle contraction that rights
it. In the West, this conceptualization flourished until the 1950s, concurrently
with the spectacular growth in techniques of analytical neurophysiology that
described links between sensory receptors and muscles. Each time neuro-
physiologists stimulated a sensory ending, they obtained a muscular contrac-
tion with a more or less prolonged latency, which reinforced the idea of pos-
tural organization based on servomechanisms that detect errors through the
sensory receptors.
In reality, control of posture and its coordination with movement also
bring into play very different mechanisms of these reflex loops. Remarkable
biological solutions simplify this eminently complex problem. Mechanisms of
anticipation and internal simulation were devised and make maintaining bal-
ance a superb model for studying reflexive and cognitive cerebral functions.
Yet my teacher and friend, the neurologist Pierre Rondot, used to say that
as late as 1970 the postural manifestations of the major neurological ill-
nesses were still interpreted by imperial fiat: in the consulting rooms of the
Salpêtrière Hospital, the Mecca of French neurology, the “prince,” that is, the
senior consultant, explained the signs of this or that disturbance of balance
based on the wealth of findings established by the French neurologists Du-
chenne de Boulogne, Déjerine, Thomas,1 and so on. This qualitative semiology
is still viable, for it is remarkably effective. It would be interesting if today, in
cooperation with clinicians, a quantitative semiology of disturbances of pos-
ture and coordination of posture and movement were to be established.
A Physiology of Reaction
Go S1
G'
PROJECTOR x θ
RO O R1
mgk
θ
Figure 11.1. Device for studying the influence of visual movement on the con-
trol of posture. The subject is upright. Visual scenes in motion are projected
onto a screen, S. The scrolling velocity of the scenes (Vi) is controlled by a com-
puter. Mirrors create virtual screen images (s). In this way, the subject is in a vir-
tual tunnel and has the impression of moving forward or backward according
to the direction of visual movement. The tilting of the body that results is mea-
sured by potentiometers located at his ankles.
220 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
play in an orchestra and not be distracted by the movements of the other in-
strumentalists. To suppress this mechanism, I asked her to count backwards
from 100.10 And, as had other subjects, the flutist immediately responded to vi-
sual stimulation. It was then clear that for her, training to play the flute en-
tailed selection of sensory information that made her in some sense blind or
less sensitive to visual perturbations.11 It may also be that her resistance to vi-
sual perturbation was a true gender difference. Experiments from our lab
show that when subjected to visuo-vestibular conflict, women recalibrate their
perception of body rotation less than men.12
This observation is instructive for several reasons: first, postural mecha-
nisms depend on the general context of the action; second, people resolve the
problem of sensorimotor integration in their own ways. Captives of statistics,
researchers sometimes try too hard to define an average behavior, a typical
subject, and standard means and deviations in normal populations. Psycho-
physiology of sensorimotor integration must now move in new directions, in-
dicated in France by the differential psychology of Reuchlin.13 Researchers
need to take into account both general rules of behavior and individual solu-
tions. All the observations that have been made concerning postural strategies
in subjects with vestibular lesions, in astronauts during and after space flights,
and so on lead to a challenge. The challenge consists of constructing a physiol-
ogy of individual perceptuomotor strategies and of the common repertoire of
behaviors that these strategies draw on. The functional flexibility that makes
possible the choices and decisions characteristic of the brain of primates and
man must be fully explored. I will come back to this point in the chapter on
adaptation.
BALANCE •
221
when his subjects closed their eyes, he observed no difference in the amplitude
of their fall and concluded that vision made no contribution. In contrast, my
results indicated that vision played a very important role.
We had in common the fact that no one was the least interested in our re-
sults. So we began to talk. I felt compelled to criticize both his premise and his
conclusions. In fact, I explained to him that when a person closes his eyes, the
brain no longer has access to visual cues and thus reorganizes other cues that
it uses instead. I argued that if vision were preserved by inhibiting visual cues
about velocity, the brain, expecting this information, would make a mistake,
and a major perturbation would result. I made him a friendly challenge and in-
vited him to come and try the experiment, which, one year later, he did.
Together we constructed a novel device, placing the subject upright on a
platform that could be abruptly displaced.14 With respect to the paradigm of
postural perturbation, our device was nothing new. The trick consisted in sur-
rounding the subject’s head with a box made of light polystyrene that slid
from front to back. This box could be fixed in space or suddenly joined to the
movement of the head by an electronic command: the perturbation was trans-
mitted, the subject fell forward, and, right at that moment, an electronic de-
vice initiated the coupling between the subject’s head and the box. In this way
the visual world was stabilized in a transitory manner. The brain perceived no
movement by vision. We had fooled it. Only the proprioceptors of the mus-
cles and the joints, along with the vestibular sensors, signaled the movement.
The result was spectacular: the muscular reaction of the legs was cancel-
led for a short interval. Lacking visual information, the brain did not trigger a
compensatory reaction. This experiment convinced me that when vision is ef-
fective, the brain waits for a cue from this preferred sensor, together with oth-
ers, to initiate preprogrammed reactions of balancing. These signals require a
specific configuration and combination to trigger the reaction. Vision is both a
sensor of velocity and an analyzer that initiates responses when its stimulation
by a movement is conjointly signaled by several other sensors.
The multisensory control of balance is thus not due to a simple string of
responses to stimuli. It involves comparison of the state of the sensors with
prediction. Now a good many contradictory findings became clear. All the au-
thors before us who had claimed that vision played no role in rapid postural
reactions had asked their subjects to close their eyes. Comparing the eyes-
closed performance with the eyes-open performance revealed no differences.
My interpretation was that when the subject closes his eyes, the brain actively
reorganizes the configurations of sensors on which it bases its decisions and
222 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
expectations. Hence the new idea that the brain chooses sensory inputs ac-
cording to context.
This theory was reinforced by the so-called broom experiment proposed
by Vidal, one of my collaborators. He positioned a broom handle horizontally
before a subject. This broom handle constituted a stationary rod on a plat-
form, enabling the subject to stop himself with his arms. During a postural
perturbation, instead of activating the muscles of his legs, the subject reacted
exclusively with his arms, which caused a complete reorganization of his
postural reactions. This experiment was also conducted and published by
Cordo and Nashner. They called this flexible functional state “set,” or state of
preparation. It remains to reconcile the concept with the definition given by
Bernstein of the posture he called “readiness to move.”
BALANCE •
223
postural, organic, preparatory, task-oriented (Aufgabe), situational, goal-ori-
ented, temporary, permanent, reactive, perceptual, expectational, anticipatory,
intentional, and so on. It has also been defined as a preparatory state for re-
ceiving a stimulus that has not yet arrived.19 Discussions of the set concept
were accompanied by numerous studies of events associated with impending
movement.20
Concurrently with this research carried on in the West, a very original
program of research was developing in the Soviet Union, which at the time
was closed to scientific communication. The idea of a preparatory influ-
ence on perception and control of movement had already been suggested by
Sechenov: “When a stimulus is expected, the activity of any other mechanism
interferes with the phenomenon, and curbs and delays the reflex.”21
In the 1960s, Gurfinkel and his colleague Alexejev in Moscow established
the importance of anticipation, instruction, and a person’s mental state in the
control of posture. Indeed, if you say to someone, “Wait for the bus. It will be
here in two hours,” the gain of this reflex is much less than if you say to him,
“Watch out! I’m going to kick you!” This observation might appear trivial. But
the idea that rigid reflexes underlay the organization of motor function was so
anchored in people’s minds, when in fact they are modulated by a global plan
of action, that it led to a genuine revolution.
Control
of posture
(feedforward)
Reference points Orientation Stability
Multisensory
inputs
Vision
Local
Vestibular Head feedback
receptors Body schema
(geometry,
kinetics, − Neural
networks Local
Proprioception verticality, Trunk
for control feedback
frame of
reference) + of posture
Cutaneous
receptors Local
Limbs feedback
Graviceptors
Control of posture
(feedback)
226 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
different effectors. For example, I can write the letter A with my hand, or my
foot, or my mouth. I can even draw a letter A while walking on the beach.
This property fascinates neurobiologists specializing in motor function and is
considered to be proof that the brain encodes a motor structure (morpho-
kinesis) very generally, which then enables it to express the structure or to exe-
cute it using very different combinations of muscles. This property is also
valid for maintaining balance. The transfer of postural programs from the legs
to the arms demonstrates, once again, the global rather than local character
of mechanisms of balance and posture.
Posture is thus not a passive state of reactions initiated by reflexes. It is a
state of preparation to move based on internal simulation of predicted se-
quences of movement and general goals of action.
BALANCE •
227
the arm. Subjects with this condition also perceive a phantom arm, whose po-
sition does not coincide necessarily with that of the real arm. Gurfinkel con-
ducted the following experiment based on this condition.
Rest your right arm on the table and angle it about 45 degrees to your
right. Close your eyes and imagine that your arm is anesthetized and that
you perceive a phantom arm at 45 degrees to the left, that is, to the other side.
Lay a pencil on the table in front of you and move it to the left: it represents
your phantom arm (you will have to open your eyes briefly to arrange the
pencil). Now bring your left hand, that is, the one that is not anesthetized, be-
fore you, resting your finger on the table, right in front of you. If you have fol-
lowed the instructions correctly, your real right arm is to the right, the finger
of your left hand is in the center, and the phantom arm (the pencil) is off to
the left.
Gurfinkel asked his subjects to close their eyes and to displace their anes-
thetized arm toward the finger of the left hand; in your case, you will have to
move your right arm toward the center. The subjects who perceived the phan-
tom arm to the left made a move of the real arm toward the right; that is, this
movement was dictated by the position of the phantom arm in space. This ex-
periment shows that planning a movement is determined by the central repre-
sentation of the position of the body in space and not by its real position as it
is detected by proprioception.
The importance of the central representation of movement of the body
and its domination by peripheral sensory factors is also illustrated by illusions
of movement induced by the vibrations of muscles I described earlier.34 For
example, if the nape of the neck is vibrated, subjects perceive an illusory
movement of the head. The postural reactions of the legs caused by this vibra-
tion of the nape of the neck are consistent with the illusion of movement of
the head and not with the local motor reflexes caused by the vibration.
You can do another experiment that tests the same principle. Sit comfort-
ably in an armchair. Turn your head to the right and keep it there, eyes closed.
During the first few minutes, you will have the impression that your head is
turned to the right, and an electromyographic recording of the activity of
your legs would show a very slight asymmetry of muscle tone that reflects
your postural asymmetry. After 8 or 10 minutes, if you have the patience to
keep your head fixed to the right, you will experience the illusion that your
head is gently returning to the center and, after another 10 minutes or so, you
will have the distinct impression that your head has resumed its natural posi-
tion, facing front. At the same time, the muscular activity of your legs will
228 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
also regain symmetry. Here again, muscular activity follows the illusory per-
ception of the position of the head. It is as if you have a phantom head that is
looking straight ahead, even though your real head is turned to the right, and
postural regulation is following the phantom head and not your real head.
Gurfinkel and his collaborators also used hypnosis to show the importance
of the internal representation of the body. Hypnotized subjects were per-
suaded that their head was turned to one side, even though it was perfectly
straight. At the same time that the illusory percept was established, muscular
contractions were observed in the legs, of the kind that generally accompany
a real rotation of the head. The percept directed the postural activity.
Similar results were obtained using vestibular stimulation. It is well known
in neurology that pathways descending from the vestibular sensors and flow-
ing through the vestibular nuclei ensure postural reactions that keep the body
upright, stable, and in balance. They also initiate compensatory reflexes dur-
ing tilting of the body. These are the so-called vestibulospinal reflexes. In prin-
ciple, they are well-identified and depend on rigid neural networks that con-
nect each semicircular canal with the postural muscles and those of the nape
of the neck. It is thus reasonable to assume that in humans, stimulation of the
labyrinth by application of a constant current (galvanic stimulation) placed
close to the ear would induce highly stereotyped postural reactions. Yet these
reactions also change completely based on the illusory position of the head.
It follows that the internal representation of the body in space is capable
of altering the organization and direction of reflexes, which means that the
whole definition of reflex itself must be reconsidered.35
BALANCE •
229
trajectories even before they are executed.37 In this sense, the cerebellum
might thus contain unique elements of a body schema or a specific form of
body schema.
A third example is found in the thalamus, whose multimodal neurons inte-
grate sensory messages with motor activity.38 In fact, the grouping that com-
prises the thalamus, cortex, and basal ganglia, which are interconnected in the
form of circuits and traversed by sustained rhythmic activity (see Figure 1.3),
might also constitute an internal representation of the body and its possible
movements.
Finally, an even higher level is probably located in the parietal cortex,
where the body schema as such is situated in the context of external space,
whose properties are analyzed by vision. Head and others after him situated
the body schema in the parietal cortex probably because it contains the only
level of generality capable of directing motor behavior in an integrated way
toward an external goal. It is most likely at this level that a global body schema
is to be found, whereas in the medulla, the schema is local.
In all probability there is not one body schema but multiple body schemas,
each adapted to a particular function, just as there are multiple representations
of the body. This idea of multiple representations of the body was taken up
again recently in connection with patients with impaired body recognition, or
autotopoagnosia. This deficit is often associated with others such as aphasia,
apraxia, disorders of manual grasping, and hemispatial neglect. However,
autotopoagnosia is a specific impairment of body recognition. Some patients
cannot indicate a part of their body verbally but can move it if the examiner
touches it.39 The same subjects have trouble referring to parts of an object ex-
ternal to their body. The impairment is perhaps not unique to body function
but a general function of designating the parts of a whole. However, patients
may have specific difficulties in indicating a “discrete image of the body.”40
A recent observation also argues for multiple representations of the body.41
A patient whose cerebral lesions were diffuse could neither localize the parts
of her own body nor, moreover, those of other people, although she could
name them. In other words, she could not localize them spatially, but she
could identify them verbally. The authors of this observation suggest that
there are at least four types of processes that enable one to represent one’s
body. The first processes semantic and lexical messages about the parts of the
body; the second, specific visuospatial representations of a person’s own body
and also objects in the environment, that is, the location of parts in relation to
each other (for instance, the nose is in the middle of the face, the ears are on
each side of the head) and their boundaries; the third is a body frame of reference
230 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
based on a body schema; and the final process involves movements themselves,
which organize perception of the body.
Consequently, it is futile to seek a single biological reality underlying the
concept of body schema. Gross reached similar conclusions concerning the
frames of reference the brain uses to integrate sensory information (see Chap-
ter 4). There are as many sensorimotor spaces as there are limbs. Given the ex-
treme complexity of the construction of a single representation of the body,
especially when it is in motion, how is this coherence assured? This is an im-
portant but still unanswered question.
Figure 11.3. To the left is an aggressive dog; to the right, an affectionate dog
waiting to be petted. Note that each posture both expresses an emotion and
prepares for action: the posture of the aggressive dog is adapted to fighting,
that of the submissive dog to being petted. This is also the position taken by a
female in heat ready to receive the male, and it has been shown recently how
this posture involves activation of a special synergy of the back muscles.
Relationships between posture and emotions also have to be taken into ac-
count. Darwin showed how different postural synergies are used to express
feelings. The images of the aggressive dog and the affectionate dog in Figure
11.3 show how these expressive postures are also a preparation for action—in
the first case, preparation to aggress, and in the second to be submissive and to
be petted.
232 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
12
A D A P TAT I O N
One of the most important properties of the nervous system is its ability to
adapt. This term encompasses several mechanisms that complement one an-
other.
The first mechanism is diminution of activity over time. For example, tac-
tile receptors stop firing when pressure is maintained, which enables them to
avoid overloading the nervous system with perpetual signals. When you are
seated, you forget that your chair is supporting you, which is not a particularly
useful bit of information while you concentrate on reading this book! Simi-
larly, the membrane of motor neurons is endowed with adaptive properties
that under the control of numerous neuromediators act to diminish their dis-
charge in reaction to a sustained stimulus. The visual system is also equipped
with mechanisms that suppress the transmission of stimuli when they are pro-
longed, and so on.
A second mechanism regulates the sensitivity of the sensory receptors. For
example, in Chapter 2, I mentioned that the γ motor neurons control the ac-
tivity of the neuromuscular spindles, thus modulating the intensity of sensory
messages from the muscles and regulating the influence of proprioception on
the motor commands for walking and balance. Another example is mecha-
nisms of accommodation, which regulate the optic properties of the eye at a
distance from objects, just as other mechanisms regulate the amplitude of the
vestibulo-ocular reflex according to the distance from the object of regard. If I
want to look at my nose, the reflex has to be cancelled; if I wish to keep my
gaze fixed on a tree in the distance, my eye must make a displacement equal
to and in the opposite direction from that of my head.
A third mechanism involves changing strategies. For example, when I am
on a bus, I can respond to a slight braking with a simple contraction of my leg
muscles; but if the braking is abrupt, I respond by moving my foot forward. If
the target I am following with my eyes is moving too rapidly for ocular pur-
suit, I follow it with saccades. When an astronaut no longer has gravity to rely
on as a reference, he employs his own body as a frame of reference and uses
vision to anchor his moves in the space station, and so on.
The major physiological theories on adaptation all take into account this
diversity of solutions and considered phenomena of plasticity at the cellular
level, as well as higher-level mechanisms like functional substitution that in-
volve reorganization of behavior as a whole.
I will now examine a few examples to give an idea of the state of the art
of research on this subject and to show how the brain’s predictive functions
come into play in adaptation. Though this chapter barely touches on this im-
mense domain, it will at least contribute some additional information. The
brain possesses mechanisms enabling it to choose solutions that anticipate the
results of action, and that activity is a necessary tool for testing these assump-
tions. Adaptation to disturbances of our senses, to sensorimotor conflicts, or
to lesions triggers strategies that bring to light the underlying processes, which
alter local mechanisms through global direction of the organism.
The example that I propose is a familiar one. If you wear glasses, you will have
noticed that when you first put on a pair that magnify slightly, you need some
time—perhaps several days—to get used to this new vision. Hunters know
that it is practically impossible to walk while looking through binoculars, even
if they only magnify twofold. And if you are a lover of opera and theater, it
does not take you long to figure out that if you do not want to lose sight of
the actors while looking at them through opera glasses, you have to keep your
head still. Why? Very simple—because the amplitude of the vestibulo-ocular
reflex (see Chapters 2 and 4) that stabilizes the image of the world on the ret-
ina is, normally, exactly equal to that of the movement of the head. When an
error is introduced by glasses or binoculars, the brain has to automatically ad-
just the reflex to the new speed of visual motion. It detects the error, then im-
plements neural mechanisms that adapt the reflex to this new situation. Two
extreme conditions allow experimenters to probe the limits of this mecha-
nism.
The first consists in placing a subject, human or animal, on a revolving
chair inside an illuminated cylinder that moves with the subject. Under these
234 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
circumstances, the visual world is stable, and the reflex must be cancelled. In
the other experiment, subjects are asked to wear prism goggles called Dove
prisms that reverse the direction of visual movement. When the head turns to
the right, the visual world, instead of turning to the left as it would under nat-
ural conditions, turns in the same direction as the head. The brain not only
has to adjust the amplitude of the movement of the eye but also to reverse the
direction of movement. The entire anatomy of the vestibular neurons whose
remarkable arrangement I described in Chapters 2 and 4 is useless in this case.
The creation of millions of years of evolution has to be undone. How does
the brain do it?
At the beginning of this century, psychologists and ethologists showed
that chickens could quite easily adapt and peck at their grain or earthworms
while wearing prism goggles. In humans, wearing prisms induces profound
transformations that are adaptively reversible. Gonshor and Melvill-Jones con-
ducted a critical experiment that revealed this surprising adaptability of the
central nervous system.1 They had a subject wear prism goggles for three
weeks and tested his vestibulo-ocular reflex every day. The tests were con-
ducted in the dark, without allowing the subject any visual cues regarding the
actual movement of his head. After five or six days, the reflex was reversed. In
other words, an adaptive mechanism had totally altered the functioning of this
remarkable wiring.
A good dozen laboratories all over the world have been working for 30
years to understand the mechanism of this adaptation, which has become a
model for the neurobiology of sensorimotor plasticity. An experimental fact
very soon helped to focus the theories: a lesion of a small area of the cerebel-
lum—the flocculus—prevented this adaptation in animals (see Figure 2.4).
Why the flocculus? The answer came from anatomy and neurophysiology:
projections of the vestibular receptors reach the Purkinje cells of the flocculus
via the mossy fibers of the cerebellum and are combined with projections
from the accessory optic system described in Chapter 3. The flocculus is thus
the center for a visuo-vestibular convergence. What critical event happens at
this level to determine adaptation? What happens is that the flocculus projects
to the neurons of the vestibular nuclei, which are involved in the reflex.2 This
is an inhibitory projection, so it is able to modulate the amplitude of the
reflex. You can experiment with this modulation yourself. Hold a finger in
front of you and oscillate your head horizontally from one side to the other,
moving your finger with your head so that your finger follows your head’s
movement exactly. Under these conditions, you will notice that your gaze is
fixed in the socket. There is no longer a vestibulo-ocular reflex. Patients with
ADAPTATION •
235
lesions of the cerebellum lose this visual inhibition of the vestibulo-ocular
reflex.
In other words, the flocculus is part of a reflex control loop modulated by
stimuli that are both visual and vestibular. Ito subsequently suggested the so-
called flocculus hypothesis.3 He proposed that a synaptic mechanism detects
the difference between visual and vestibular inputs at the level of the Purkinje
cells and, based on this error signal, alters their influence on the reflex.
Ito later refined his hypothesis based on a mechanism he called “long-term
depression,” caused by the coincidence of two different synaptic events (those
associated with the climbing fibers and the mossy fibers, which are the two
main groups of neurons that convey visual and vestibular information to the
cerebellum) that initiate this alteration. Very fine molecular mechanisms un-
derlie this adaptive capacity, which Ito used as a general model of motor train-
ing. But the model was controversial. Some saw motor training as a more
complex function, not localized to a single synapse or a single long-term sup-
pressive mechanism. Others situated the critical synapse for adaptive changes
not at the level of the cerebellum but at the level of the brainstem, where spe-
cialized neurons ensure its regulation: according to this conceptualization, the
cerebellum is also implicated in alterations, but as controller.4 Adaptation thus
operates on at least two levels. Whatever their differences, these theories as-
sume that adaptation is the product of neurons situated within the networks
that control the reflex.
But there is another way of thinking about adaptation that leads to a com-
pletely different theory: with Melvill-Jones, I proposed that instead of revers-
ing the vestibulo-ocular reflex, the brain replaces it with a reverse pseudo-
reflex using another element of the oculomotor repertoire, such as saccades
or pursuit.
To prove this theory, we repeated the original experiment together, asking
subjects to wear Dove prism goggles. After putting the goggles on, the sub-
jects succeeded within several hours, and sometimes immediately, in produc-
ing an adaptive movement composed of a sequence of saccades that gradually
merged to approximate a vestibular reflex.5 The brain had suppressed the
vestibulo-ocular reflex via the mechanism described above involving the floc-
culus, instead using the saccadic system to construct a new adaptive move-
ment.
We hypothesized that this pseudo-reflex was guided not by visual targets
but by an internal simulation of the movement of targets; that is, by a percept
that directs adaptation from top to bottom just as the body schema controls
posture. A high-level mechanism, calling into play the cortical structures in-
236 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
volved in the representation of space and motor imagery, appeared to be re-
sponsible for this adaptation. We reasoned that the physical presence of visual
targets was not necessary to achieve adaptation, and that simply imagining the
target might be enough. Consequently, we asked subjects to sit in a revolving
chair that oscillated and to imagine that they were focusing on a target at-
tached to their nose. The conflict they experienced had to do with the fact that
their vestibular system was telling their brain that it was turning, thus causing
a vestibulo-ocular reflex that inhibited the very intention of fixing their regard
on the target attached to their nose. After several hours of this exercise, we
observed that the vestibulo-ocular reflex had changed. A simple internal men-
tal effort—subjects keeping their gaze focused in front of them during a rota-
tion of the head in the dark—was enough to cause adaptation.6 Here, as for
postural control, adaptation is caused by a percept of movement worked out
in the areas of the cerebral cortex involved in the representation of space and
not by low-level reflexes. We have recently shown that there is a great differ-
ence between men and women in their adaptation to a visuo-vestibular con-
flict. We have exposed both normal and anxious subjects (the anxiety level was
judged by standard psychiatric tests) to a conflict by turning their bodies by a
certain amount and turning the visual world in a virtual reality helmet by a
different amount. We tested their vestibular perceptions before and after the
exposure to the conflict and observed that men adapt their vestibular percep-
tion more than do women under these circumstances (or women remain
more independent). Also, anxious men adapt even more. We are performing
these studies on anxiety because I believe that part of the mechanism underly-
ing spatial anxiety is related to the difficulty of building a coherent perception
of the relation between the body and space and difficulties in coping with in-
congruous sensory inputs.7
The brain thus employs various mechanisms to adapt. Some are low-level
and promote neural plasticity; others are high-level and, especially in humans,
rely on remarkable capacities for functional substitution, based on internal
simulation of the signals to be controlled. In other words, the brain is not a
servo system for regulating variables; it is a composer that orchestrates the in-
struments at its disposal. The hierarchy of nerve centers developed over the
course of evolution enables the brain to find new solutions when adaptation is
required. Low-level mechanisms then stabilize the new solutions. In fact, brain
imaging has revealed that during motor training, the cerebral cortex is used at
the beginning of the training and gradually becomes silent; the activity is then
transferred to the basal nuclei and to the cerebellum, which leaves the cortex
free to confront new problems and find new solutions to them.
ADAPTATION •
237
For all these reasons, inter- and intraindividual differences must regain the
central status they have lost in the behavioral sciences and neurosciences. If
the brain does have this ability to choose solutions, we must vary our efforts
to find one or several solutions, rather than focusing on typical behavior, as we
have done. A diversity of strategies better clarifies the mechanisms at work
than does an average profile. However, it must also be recognized that the
number of possible solutions is not infinite. It is constrained by the genetic
legacy of sensorimotor subsystems. To what extent it is possible to escape
simple selection to achieve genuine invention is a fine subject, but it is a mat-
ter for another discussion.
Here we put our finger on the mistake of those who maintain that perception
springs from what is properly called the sensory vibration, and not from a sort
of question addressed to motor activity.
—H. Bergson
In this chapter, I maintain that perceptual illusions are solutions devised by the
brain to deal with sensory messages that are ambiguous, or that contradict ei-
ther each other or the internal assumptions that the brain makes about the ex-
ternal world. An illusion is generally held to be a sensory error, as in this text
by Sully, written in 1883:
We see, then, that in spite of obvious differences in the form, the pro-
cess in all kinds of immediate cognition is fundamentally identical. It is
essentially a bringing together of elements, whether similar or dissimi-
lar and associated by a link of contiguity, and a viewing of these as con-
nected parts of a whole; it is a process of synthesis. And illusion, in all
its forms, is bad grouping or carelessly performed synthesis. This holds
good even for the simplest kinds of error in which a presented element
is wrongly classed; and it holds good for those more conspicuous errors
of perception, memory, expectation, and compound belief, in which
representations connect themselves in an order not perfectly answering
to the objective order.1
I suggest that illusion is not an error or a bad solution, but rather the best
possible hypothesis.
Illusion: The Best Possible Hypothesis
Dynamic Illusions
Another illusion—this one a little more difficult to demonstrate—concerns the
change in the apparent position of a point of light in space. To do the experi-
ment, you will have to stand on an enclosed rotating circular platform or a
centrifuge and look outward, turning your back to the center of rotation. Un-
der these conditions, the vestibular receptors are subjected to a centrifugal ac-
celeration that goes from your ears to your nose. Now, if the lights are turned
off and you are told to follow a little point of light that moves along with you
in the compartment, you will suddenly have the impression that when the
platform or centrifuge starts up, the light is moving up or down according to
244 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
Ayz +z
Az = 1g
+α
GIF
−y
2
Ay = ω r
Gravito-inertial
force
ω (GIF)
Figure 13.1. Illusion of body tilt on a centrifuge. When the centrifuge turns
with an angular velocity ω, the acceleration of gravity Az (directed upward and
leading to a downward gravitational force) and acceleration due to rotation Ay
(directed toward the center and creating a centrifugal force) combine to pro-
duce a gravito-inertial acceleration Ayz tilted at angle α. This acceleration
causes a resultant gravito-inertial force that the brain interprets as the true ver-
tical.
Acceleration
Inertia
Gravity
(true vertical) Resultant (perceived vertical)
Figure 13.2. The ambiguity of otolithic messages can cause accidents. On take-
off, an airplane simultaneously accelerates and inclines. When takeoff occurs in
the dark or in fog, the pilot has only vestibular and tactile information to rely
on to detect the pitch of the airplane. The otoliths are stimulated by two accel-
erations: gravity and the forward motion of the airplane. The two component
forces (gravitational and inertial) combine in a resultant force that is perceived
by the brain as gravity (in the absence of any other visual cue to indicate up or
down). Thus, the pilot believes that his airplane is inclining very sharply. He
compensates for this illusory pitching, and the airplane crashes at the end of
the runway. Fortunately, modern instruments provide pilots with a measure of
the true pitch of the plane.
jet plane when it has finished its climb and suddenly levels off. Owing to the
plane’s circular or parabolic trajectory, centrifugal force combines with gravity
to produce a force oriented upwards. Under these conditions, the pilot, who
had the impression during the climb that he was sitting down, his bottom
pointing toward earth, suddenly has the illusion that he is upside down. This
illusion is also experienced in space flights: when gravity disappears, it is as if
there were an acceleration in a direction contrary to normal gravity. The brain
interprets the absence of gravity to be the result of acceleration in the oppo-
site direction, and the illusion of inversion felt by the cosmonauts is very often
associated with serious symptoms of motion sickness.
Another illusion, called the cemetery illusion because it has been the cause
of numerous catastrophes, may affect pilots in airplanes performing acrobatic
THE DISORIENTED BRAIN •
247
maneuvers descending in a helix. After several helical turns, the pilot loses the
sensation that he is turning. Indeed, if the angular acceleration is constant, the
sensations from the semicircular canals abate. When the pilot stops his rota-
tion, he receives a vestibular stimulus due to the combined effects of angular
deceleration and gravity that gives him the impression that he is turning in the
opposite direction, which leads to fatal accidents. This illusion, which occurs
in exceptional conditions, also occurs under more normal conditions when,
for example, the pilot makes a simple circle in a plane flying horizontally for a
fairly long while. After a time, the messages from the canals disappear, and at
the instant the plane resumes a straight-line trajectory, the acceleration caused
by straightening out gives the pilot the mistaken impression that he is inclin-
ing in the direction opposite to that of the circular trajectory. He inclines the
airplane further to correct it, which is obviously very dangerous.
Kohnstamm’s Illusion
An illusion that is very interesting because it causes observable movement was
described for the first time by a physiologist, Kohnstamm. The illusion is evi-
dence of a sort of motor memory, and it seized the imagination of neuro-
physiologists. Try the following experiment: Stand upright next to a wall, in
profile, the back of your hand against the wall and the palm of your hand
against your trousers (or skirt). You can also do the same experiment without
standing next to a wall, but leaning the back of your hand on the edge of the
table. Now, applying as much force as you can, push the back of your hand for
2 or 3 minutes against the wall or the table, as if you wanted to push it away
from your body. What you are doing is applying a sustained tonic force involv-
ing the extensor muscles of your arm. At the end of this time, move away
from the wall or the table, and relax. The experiment can be done entirely
with your eyes open, but it is better to do it with your eyes closed. You will
feel your arm lift all by itself, as if it were pulled by an invisible thread, and re-
main elevated for an instant. This illusion tells us something about the basic
mechanisms of postural control. It could in fact be called involuntary post-
contraction.5
The experiment can also be done with the feet, by sitting in a chair and
pressing very hard against a wall or a table. The illusion only results when the
muscle making the contraction is a proximal muscle—one that belongs to the
postural system. Kohnstamm’s phenomenon cannot be induced using the dis-
248 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
tal muscles of the hands or the feet. For instance, if you hang a 3-kilogram
weight from your foot and let the weight drop abruptly, the involuntary con-
traction appears in the quadriceps (thigh muscle). Similarly, if you hang a 3-ki-
logram weight from your hand for 5 minutes, the involuntary contraction
phenomenon is induced in the biceps muscle, not in the hand. Thus it is a mo-
tor reaction of the postural muscles. Why is this reaction the result of an illu-
sion? Why is it the solution to a problem of the nervous system?
The interpretation of this phenomenon is the following: During the phase
when your hand is pressed against the wall, you are exerting a constant force
on it. The brain adapts to this situation in which motionlessness is accompa-
nied by a constant muscular effort. When your hand pulls away from the wall,
the brain continues to apply this force, because the brain reads the force as
motionlessness, up to the point where the stretch receptors in the muscles sig-
nal clear movement.
In other words, while force is being exerted, the brain learns that motion-
lessness is accompanied by motor activity. Once the obstacle is removed, it still
believes this to be true.
These results are important for us because they confirm the revival of the mo-
tor theory of perception. They reinforce the concept of a prespecification of
sensory inputs during control of movement. Finally, they validate the idea that
illusions are solutions resulting from an endogenous repertoire of motor or
perceptual forms with which configurations of sensory inputs are compared.
250 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
nected to movement, whether visual or corporeal. Astronauts are susceptible
to it, and for most the only relief is medication.
The mechanism of this peculiar bodily reaction is still not known. One in-
teresting hypothesis that so far has not been rejected is called sensory conflict.
It explains motion sickness as a conflict between the sensory messages sup-
plied by the visual and vestibular systems (and possibly the graviceptors of the
abdomen) about movements of the head. More generally, this symptom is
produced by an incongruity between the messages relayed by the sensors of
orientation and those of movement. For example, the visual system of a child
sitting in the back seat of a car or a sailor below deck detects no movement,
whereas the vestibular and proprioceptive systems do detect movement. Simi-
larly, in the case of complex movements of the head that generate so-called
Coriolis accelerations, the brain cannot establish coherence between accelera-
tions detected by the vestibular system and those indicated by vision. In space,
it is the failure of the otoliths to detect tilting of the head owing to the ab-
sence of gravity versus the ability of vision and the other sensors to detect it
that is the cause of sickness, although cardiovascular reorganization may also
contribute.
Thus, difficulty in reconstructing a coherent perception of movement and
orientation is responsible for central nervous system activity leading to succes-
sive stages of motion sickness, from drowsiness to nausea. We still do not
know why this incoherence manifests vegetatively as it does. It has long been
known that dogs whose flocculus (the portion of the cerebellum that inte-
grates visual and vestibular information) has been removed do not get sick. So
it is possible that low-level mechanisms are responsible for motion sickness.
But I would like to propose another hypothesis.
The hippocampus contributes to the memory of configurations of sen-
sory information and others connected to action, and at this level visuo-
vestibular convergences are probably treated on a global level. For example, in
the monkey the neurons of the hippocampus discharge during movements of
translation and rotation, but only when the animal is in a certain region of the
room, or is heading toward a door.8 It is thus possible that motion sickness is
caused by much higher level mechanisms involving the entirety of the internal
system of simulation of global movement of the body in the space con-
structed by the hippocampus, the prefrontal cortex, and the parietal cortex.
Problems in establishing coherence might lead to vegetative effects whose ori-
gin is cortical.9 This hypothesis explains why training plays such an important
role in preventing motion sickness in space and, among other things, why it
254 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
14
A R C H I T E C T S H AV E F O R G O T T E N T H E P L E A S U R E O F M O V E M E N T
258 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
the curse of preemptory predictability. The brain is a biological forecasting
machine. It follows that its pleasure consists in taking gambles. And it can only
gamble on a reality in motion, ever changing. Shape, even motionless shape, is
an opportunity for mind shifts, for imaginative changes of direction, which
criminal architects would prevent us from enjoying.
I recently visited a renovated building that had a staircase going up to the
second floor. It was extended from the building’s original lower staircase. I
compared the two banisters. The more recent one was square, as rigid as an
insensitive person, sad and gloomy, going nowhere; the staircase that belonged
to the old building had that marvelous curvature you see in Parisian banisters,
the legacy of a thousand years of craftsmanship. It showed the way without
hesitation, its subtle helix contrasting with the drumbeat of the steps that sec-
tioned space and promised a difficult, jerky climb. The old banister was shape
and movement; already I felt in the palm of my hand the rounded curves that
embraced me as I got my spinal locomotor generator into gear. The banister
was refinement itself, the lover of the craftsman who had created her. She was
unlike any other, she was calm regularity, she was movement. I loved her.
What can I say about the grillwork on doors? The best example of failure
is that of several schools in Paris that shall remain nameless. For the hundreds
of children who cross its threshold each day, the schoolyard gate is the transi-
tion from family to school, between the city and this neutral and protected
place that the philosopher Alain was so fond of. The gate is the symbol of a
touching, eminently contradictory moment of transition between two worlds:
the place where parents wait, and the passage through which children take
flight at the close of school. It is a symbol both of enclosure and of liberation
from family constraints and the teacher’s clutches. This object must serve as a
border and a crossing, a versatile window on the city and a peephole for catch-
ing a glimpse of the sanctuary of school. The gate must be pleasing to cling
to, to resist, to rest one’s eyes on, to distract one’s gaze while waiting, or to
examine for symbols of a changing world. What have architects made of
it? Prison bars. Total renunciation of the unexpected gesture, the desired
meaning.
It took me a long time to understand why the architect André Bruyère was
so interested in doors, but now it is obvious to me. The door is one of the
most important elements in architecture, experienced as a front for emotions,
fading actions, and the construction of memories.
I understand about priorities. I understand the requirements of economies
of scale and of standardization. I understand that the straight line is the short-
260 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
C O N C L U S I O N : T O WA R D A T O L E R A N T P E R C E P T I O N
Now it is time to reflect upon the distance covered and try to sum up the ideas
presented in this book. To be honest, these ideas are more a work in progress
than a finished theory. Let me suggest some thoughts to begin the discussion.
In other words, Bergson accepts the idea that the brain is used in the inter-
nal simulation of movement, but he limits its contribution to this mental
structuring and refuses to grant that it plays any role whatsoever in the high-
est cognitive functions that are the exclusive domain of the mind. Moreover,
in the same passage he says that the whole of psychophysiology provides the
brain with a level of comprehension no greater than that of an observer
watching the comings and goings of actors on stage to understand the play.
Bergson is confident, however, that the brain is a tool for simulating. He
writes: “I should say that the brain is an organ of pantomime, and of panto-
mime only. Its part is to play the life of the mind, and to play also the external
situations to which the mind must adapt itself. The work of the brain is to the
whole of conscious life what the movements of the conductor’s baton are to
the orchestral symphony.”2 The computer metaphor also assumes an implicit
dissociation between the hardware (the neurons of the brain) and software
(the symphony).
There are more than five senses. Consider, for example, the vestibular sensors,
the proprioceptors of the muscles and joints, and, for certain species, other
senses such as echolocation and magnetic sense. But to give any meaning to
262 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
perception, what is needed most is a complete revision of the word “sense.” I
suggest returning to a classification of the senses that corresponds to percep-
tual function. So to the sense of taste and smell, touch, vision, and hearing,
add, as the vernacular already does, the sense of movement, space, balance, ef-
fort, self, decision, responsibility, initiative, and so on. This idea of the senses
shows the way, determined by the subject, toward a goal. To varying degrees,
separately and together, each of the senses calls upon the receptors, and even
certain properties of each receptor, that it needs. The brain filters the mes-
sages supplied by the senses according to its own plans. The mechanisms of
this selection have yet to be deciphered: we understand only a few forms of se-
lectivity.
In other words, we must completely change the way we study the senses.
We must begin by considering the goal of the organism, so that we may un-
derstand how the brain is informed by the receptors, how it regulates their
sensitivity, combines messages from them, and estimates their value, accord-
ing to an internal simulation of the expected consequences of action.
The relationships between perception and action require study that takes
into account several key features of the brain and their complementarity,
which no one yet has been able to characterize. According to so-called central-
ist theories, action is determined by internal plans of action (my projective
formulation of a schema) whose mechanisms are endogenous and are based
on a repertoire of innate and acquired behaviors characteristic of each species
and each individual. Functions are not confined to a single structure of the
brain but are the result of cooperation among specific structures. This cooper-
ation constitutes pathways for neural activity that is characteristic for each
structure. Many brain functions are not just the product of pathways along
which processing proceeds sequentially, but of closed circuits. Within these
circuits, structures that are activated sequentially, or in a synchronous way
through oscillations, are often connected by what Edelman calls “reentrant
loops.” These functional loops interact at several levels and thus influence
each other in multiple ways, and this interconnectivity is subtended by assem-
blies of very specific neurons. In other words, it is wrong to think that in the
brain everything is connected with everything else.
The subsystems that define a repertoire of sensorimotor behaviors are
subject to variability. The brain has mechanisms for exploiting this variability
and combining elements of the repertoire to form strategies that are specially
adapted to its current purposes. I think that functional flexibility, recently dis-
covered at the level of the cortex, is only a subsidiary manifestation of this
fundamental property. The brain can choose a variety of solutions to the same
CONCLUSION •
263
problem. This ability to choose is at the root of illusions, which are solutions
to problems of perceptions that are ambiguous or incompatible with environ-
mental cues. In contrast, hallucinations, like dreams, are creations that the en-
vironment cannot confirm.
The central issue is the neural basis of coherence. Indeed, all the findings of
neuropsychology and of modern neurophysiology confirm the multiplicity of
cooperating subsystems, the role of segregation, the modularity of cerebral
operations, and their interrelatedness. There are many frames of reference in
which the body is represented; the body schema may be nothing more than
the synthesis of multiple schemas through as yet unknown mechanisms. Each
sense breaks down perceptible reality into elements that are subsequently re-
constructed and connected. The concept of coherence is thus central. The
theory of temporal encoding asserts that temporal synchronization consti-
tutes de facto coherence through simultaneity.
I think that major illnesses like autism, schizophrenia, and agoraphobia
share disturbances of coherence that take diverse forms according to the prin-
cipal features of each illness.
Memory is essentially a tool for predicting the future. In this sense, the con-
cept of working memory and its association with the prefrontal cortex is im-
portant, but it accounts for only a portion of memory. Researchers began with
the idea that memory served the brain to recall bygone experiences of youth
in old age. Then it was discovered that this memory could in fact be broken
down into several categories associated with various parts of the brain, and ul-
timately one of these categories is working memory. I think that it is critical to
start with the idea that memory is a mechanism that enables us to predict the
future. The simulating brain uses memories to implement mental processes of
prediction. So the hippocampus—the highest level for encoding messages in
the nervous system, a supramodal level that takes into account the set of rela-
tionships between behavior and the messages encoded in each specialized sys-
tem—together with the prefrontal and parietal cortex might play a central role
in memory as a guide to future action: it reconstructs multisensory episodes
from partial elements, as in the example of Proust’s madeleine. But many
other centers participate in the memory of movement. The parietal cortex is
264 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
probably involved in long-term motor memory and in the mental simulation
of movements;3 the cerebellum, along with the basal ganglia, in manual dex-
terity, and so on.
We are far from understanding the relationships between perception and emo-
tion. Yet we have just entered a century that Malraux said would be either “re-
ligious or not be at all.” If recent expressions of religion betraying only intol-
erance, fanaticism, and hatred are any indication, this century, if it is religious,
will be a century of unprecedented violence. Citizens in every country have
an enormous responsibility. To be able to wander about with a bomb strapped
to one’s back as a young Palestinian fanatic did in March 1995, to murder
thousands of Muslims as the Serbs did, or a million Cambodians as did Pol
Pot, to murder a playmate in his backyard, like two French youths who were
caught up in a game of fantasy role playing, to kill hundreds of one’s own fol-
lowers—to commit such acts the mind must be so constrained by the percep-
tion that fascinates it that it suppresses any alternatives. The functioning of
the brain is corrupted, as it is with hypnosis. Perception and action should be
interesting not only to educators, ergonomists, or physicians, but to all those
who feel a responsibility to fight the hatred of others. My generation believed
that the basis of selfishness was economic. We were not completely wrong,
and the present return to the ruthless struggle between the strong and the
weak and the disappearance of feelings of solidarity can only result in sorrow
and suffering.
But there is more. The human brain operates with powerful mechanisms
of territorialism, of distrust toward those who are different, of selfishness that
precludes the open hand of generosity. The most bloodthirsty dictators are
supported not only by economic forces but by the forces of obscurantism,
which derive their hateful influence from archetypal images that are stiff,
petty, and grotesque, and which blot out consideration for the other and jus-
tify his destruction. In this book I have maintained that the brain projects its
internal perceptions onto the world, that it constructs its perceptions with ref-
erence to actions, much the same way that Lascaux man saw bison on the
walls of his cave. Unfortunately, this leaves the brain with a propensity for re-
treating into pre-established schemas that it then projects onto the world and
onto others. Skilled alchemists of the mind can thus manufacture ready-made
perceptions or caricatures, like those seen in the antisemitic exhibitions orga-
nized under the Vichy regime, or those presently being forced on people
CONCLUSION •
265
around the world to feed religious wars. The same process is probably at work
in sects, where gurus painstakingly brainwash their followers, distorting the
way others are perceived, so that perception of them is tainted by uncondi-
tional adoration of the master. And what is the point of playing this role, if
not to impose a schema for perception that defines the relationships the guru
compels a person to maintain with others? All these various social structures
have a common mechanism for restricting the operation of the brain within a
set of rigid interpretations, using methods somewhat akin to hypnosis. This
perversion of the faculty—the projective nature of perception—must be re-
sisted. It is a scourge graver than the gravest illness, for it does not merely de-
stroy the person; it leads its victims to destroy others.
Anger and hatred often lead us back to these perceptual prototypes, which
we suddenly project onto every object or every person in sight. When we do,
anticipation becomes a prison for perception and a trap for action; the serene
path of reason is abandoned for that of the emotions. Tolerance requires a
generous and benevolent appreciation of differences. Along with the pleasure
of discovering the mechanisms of perception and action, and the obligation to
enhance well-being, human beings also have a duty to understand the perver-
sions of the mind, so that this new century may be one of tolerance. Failing
that, we risk the worst.
266 •
THE BRAIN’S SENSE OF MOVEMENT
NOTES
WORKS CITED
CREDITS
INDEX
NOTES
Introduction
1. J. von Uexküll, Umwelt und Innenwelt der Tieren und Menschen (Berlin: Springer, 1934).
2. G. Châtelet, Les Enjeux du mobile—Mathématiques, physique, philosophie (Paris: Le Seuil,
1993), p. 39.
3. Johann Wolfgang von Goethe, Faust, trans. Randall Jarrell (New York: Farrar, Straus,
and Giroux, 1959), p. 61.
4. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Norman Kemp Smith (New York: St.
Martin’s Press, 1961), p. 47.
5. H. Bergson, The Creative Mind, trans. Mabelle L. Andison (New York: Philosophical Li-
brary, 1946), pp. 243–245. I have recently published an anthology of one hundred years
of the “Leçons inaugurales” [inaugural lectures] of the professors at the Collège de
France that indicate this central role of physiology in cognitive sciences in France. See
A. Berthoz, Leçons sur le corps, le cerveau et l’esprit (Paris: Odile Jacob, 1999).
6. T. Ribot, The Psychology of the Emotions, Contemporary Science Series (London: W.
Scott, 1897), p. 2.
7. J.-P. Changeux, L’Homme neuronal (Paris: Fayard, 1983).
270 •
NOTES TO PAGES 13–22
27. M. Wexler, S. Kosslyn, and A. Berthoz, “Motor Processes in Mental Rotation,” Cogni-
tion, 68 (1998): 77–94.
272 •
NOTES TO PAGES 31–46
37. A. J. Pellionisz and R. Llinás, “Tensorial Approach to the Geometry of Brain Func-
tion. Cerebellar Coordination via a Metric Tensor,” Neuroscience, 5 (1980): 1761–
1770.MM
38. B. W. Peterson, J. Baker, and A. J. Pellionisz, “Comparison of Spatial Transformation in
Vestibulo-ocular and Vestibulo-spinal Reflexes,” Proceedings of the Symposium on the Rep-
resentation of Three-Dimensional Space in the Vestibular, Oculomotor, and Visual Systems
(The Barany Society: Bologna, 1988). See also the chapter by Pellionisz in A. Berthoz
and G. Melvill-Jones, Adaptative Mechanisms in Gaze Control (Amsterdam: Elsevier,
1985).
39. A. J. Pellionisz and R. Llinás, “Brain Modeling by Tensor Network Theory and Com-
puter Simulation. The Cerebellum: Distributed Processor for Predictive Coordination,”
Neuroscience, 4 (1979): 232–348, “Tensorial Approach,” and “Space-Time Representation
in the Brain. The Cerebellum as a Predictive Space-Time Metric Tensor,” Neuroscience,
7 (1982): 2949–2970.
40. A. J. Pellionisz, “Coordination: A Vector-Matrix Description of Transformations of
Overcomplete CNS Coordinates and a Tensorial Solution using the Moore-Penrose
Generalized Inverse,” Journal of Theoretical Biology, 101 (1984): 353–375.
41. M. Arbib and S. Amari, “Sensorimotor Transformations in the Brain (With a Critique
of the Tensor Theory of Cerebellum),” Journal of Theoretical Biology, 112 (1985): 123–
155.
42. J. L. Barbur, A. J. Harlow, and L. Weiskrantz, “Spatial and Temporal Response Prop-
erties of Residual Vision in a Case of Hemianopia,” Philosophical Transactions of the
Royal Society of London. Series B: Biological Sciences, 343 (1994): 366–371.
43. E. Mach, Grundlinien der Lehre von den Bewegungsempfindungen (Amsterdam: E. J. Bonset,
1967).
44. D. N. Lee and E. Aronson, “Visual Proprioceptive Control of Standing in Human In-
fants,” Perception and Psychophysics, 15 (1974): 529–532; D. N. Lee and J. R. Lishman,
“Visual Proprioceptive Control of Stance,” Journal of Human Movement Studies, 1 (1975):
87–95.
45. J. Dichgans and T. Brandt, “Visual-Vestibular Interaction and Motion and Perception,”
in J. Dichgans and E. Bizzi, eds., Cerebral Control of Eye Movements and Motion Perception
(New York: Karger, 1972), pp. 327–338, and “Visual-Vestibular Interactions: Effects on
Self-Motion Perception and Postural Control,” in H. Heibowitz and H. L. Teuber, eds.,
Handbook of Sensory Physiology (Berlin: Springer, 1978), vol. 5, pp. 755–804; T. Brandt, J.
Dichgans, and E. Koenig, “Differential Effects of Central versus Peripheral Vision on
Egocentric and Exocentric Motion Perception,” Experimental Brain Research, 16 (1973):
746–491.
46. A. Berthoz, B. Pavard, and L. Young, “Perception of Linear Horizontal Self-Motion In-
duced by Peripheral Vision (Linear Vection),” Experimental Brain Research, 23 (1974):
471–489; B. Pavard and A. Berthoz, “Perception du mouvement et orientation spatial
(Revue bibliographique),” Le Travail humain, 2 (1976): 207–226, and “Linear Accelera-
tion Modifies the Perceived Velocity of a Moving Scene,” Perception and Psychophysics, 6
(1977): 529–540.
274 •
NOTES TO PAGES 57–66
Alert Monkeys Are Also Influenced by Missing Visual Field,” Brain Research, 71 (1974):
144–149.
17. Baker and Berthoz, “Organization of Vestibular Nystagmus”; A. Berthoz, K. Yoshida,
and P. P. Vidal, “Horizontal Eye Movement Signals in Second-Order Vestibular Nuclei
Neurons in the Alert Cat,” Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 374 (1981): 144–
156; A. Berthoz, J. Droulez, P. P. Vidal, and K. Yoshida, “Neural Correlates of Horizon-
tal Vestibulo-ocular Reflex Cancellation during Rapid Eye Movements in the Cat,” Jour-
nal of Physiology, 419 (1989): 717–751.
18. M. Magnin, M. Jeannerod, and P. T. S. Putkonen, “Vestibular and Saccadic Influences
on Dorsal and Ventral Nuclei of the Lateral Geniculate Body,” Experimental Brain Re-
search, 21 (1974): 1–18.
19. K. Yoshida, R. A. McCrea, A. Berthoz, and P. P. Vidal, “Interneurones Inhibiteur de la
saccade oculaire horizontale étudiée chez le chat éveillé à l’aide d’injections intra-
axonique de peroxydase,” Comptes rendus hebdomadaires de l’Académie des sciences (Paris,
série III), 290 (1980): 636–638, “Eye Movement Related Activity of Identified Second-
Order Vestibular Neurons in the Cat,” in A. Fuchs and W. Becker, eds., Progress in
Oculomotor Research (Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1981), pp. 371–378, and “Properties of Im-
mediate Premotor Inhibitory Burst Neurons Controlling Horizontal Rapid Eye Move-
ments in the Cat,” in Fuchs and Becker, Progress in Oculomotor Research, pp. 71–81; R. A.
McCrea, K. Yoshida, C. Evinger, and A. Berthoz, “The Location, Axonal Arboriza-
tion, and Termination Sites of Eye-Movement-Related Secondary Vestibular Neurons
Demonstrated by Intra-axonal HRP Injection in the Alert Cat,” in Fuchs and Becker,
Progress in Oculomotor Research, pp. 379–386; Berthoz et al., “Neural Correlates,”
pp. 717–751.
20. E. von Holst and H. Mittelstaedt, “Das Reafferenzprinzip. Wechselwirkungen zwischen
Zentralnervensystem und Peripherie,” Naturwissenschaften, 37 (1950): 464–476.
21. W. Penfield and E. Boldrey, “Somatic Motor and Sensory Representation in the Cere-
bral Cortex of Man as Studied by Electrical Stimulation,” Brain, 60 (1937): 389–443; W.
Penfield and T. Rasmussen, The Cerebral Cortex of Man. A Clinical Study of Localization
of Function (New York: Macmillan, 1957); W. Penfield, “Vestibular Sensation and the
Cerebral Cortex,” Annales d’otorhinolaryngologie, 66 (1957): 691–698.
22. B. H. Smith, “Vestibular Disturbances in Epilepsy,” Neurology, 10 (1960): 465–469.
23. J. Silberpfennig, “Contributions to the Problem of Eye Movements. III. Disturbance
of Ocular Movements with Pseudo-hemianopsia in Frontal Lobe Tumors,” Confinia
Neurologica, 4 (1941): 1–13.
24. L. Friberg, T. S. Olsen, P. Roland, O. B. Paulson, and N. A. Lassen, “Focal Increase of
Blood Flow in the Cerebral Cortex of Man during Vestibular Stimulation,” Brain, 108
(1985): 609–623; P. Tuohimaa, E. Aantaa, K. Toukoniitty, and P. Mäkelä, “Studies of
Vestibular Cortical Areas with Short Living Oxygen 15 Isotopes,” Otorhinolaryngologica,
45 (1983): 315–321; G. Bottini, R. Sterzi, E. Paulesu, G. Vallar, S. Cappa, F. Erminio,
R. E. Passingham, C. D. Frith, and R. S. J. J. Frackowiack, “Identification of the Central
Vestibular Projections in Man: A Positron Emission Tomography Activation Study,” Ex-
perimental Brain Research, 99 (1994): 164–169; E. Lobel, J. F. Kleine, D. Le Bihan, A.
Leroy-Willig, and A. Berthoz, “Functional MRI of Galvanic Vestibular Stimulation,”
Journal of Neurophysiology, 80 (1998): 2699–2709. Caloric stimulation, a technique com-
276 •
NOTES TO PAGES 71–72
stration of vestibular input on hippocampal formation was provided by E. Vitte,
C. Derosier, Y. Caritu, A. Berthoz, D. Hasboun, and D. Soulié, “Activation of the
Hippocampal Formation by Vestibular Stimulation: A Functional Magnetic Resonance
Study,” Experimental Brain Research, 112 (1996): 523–526 and V. V. Gavrilov, S. I. Wiener,
and A. Berthoz, “Whole Body Rotations Enhance Hippocampal Theta Rhythm Slow
Activity in Awake Rats Passively Transportated on a Mobile Robot,” Annals of the New
York Academy of Sciences, 781 (1996): 385–398.
30. P. Buisseret and M. Imbert, “Visual Cortical Cells: Their Developmental Properties
in Normal and Dark Reared Kittens,” Journal of Physiology, 255 (1976): 511–525;
P. Buisseret and E. Gary-Bobo, “Development of Visual Cortical Orientation Specificity
after Dark Rearing: Role of Extra-ocular Proprioception,” Neuroscience Letters, 13
(1979): 259–263.
31. X. M. Sauvan and E. Peterhans, “Neural Integration of Visual Information and Direc-
tion of Gravity in the Prestriate Cortex of the Alert Monkey,” in T. Mergner and F.
Hlavackà, eds., Multisensory Control of Posture (New York: Plenum, 1995), pp. 43–50.
32. J. S. Taube, R. U. Muller, and J. B. Ranck, Jr., “Head-Direction Cells Recorded from the
Postsubiculum in Freely Moving Rats. I. Description and Quantitative Analysis,” Jour-
nal of Neuroscience, 10 (1990): 420–435, and “Head Direction Cells Recorded from the
Postsubiculum in Freely Moving Rats. II. Effects of Environmental Manipulations,”
Journal of Neuroscience, 10 (1990): 436–447. L. L. Chen, L. Lin, E. J. Green, C. A. Barnes,
and B. McNaughton, “Head Direction Cells in the Rat Posterior Cortex. I. Anatomical
Distribution and Behavioural Modulation,” Experimental Brain Research, 101 (1994): 8–
23; L. L. Chen, L. Lin, C. A. Barnes, and B. McNaughton, “Head Direction Cells in the
Rat Posterior Cortex. II. Contributions of Visual and Ideothetic Information to the Di-
rectional Firing,” Experimental Brain Research, 101 (1994): 24–34.
33. A. B. Rubens, “Caloric Stimulation and Unilateral Visual Neglect,” Neurology, 35 (1985):
1019–1024; S. Cappa, R. Sterzi, G. Vallar, and E. Bisiach, “Remission of Hemineglect
and Anosognosia during Vestibular Stimulation,” Neuropsychologia, 25 (1987): 775–782;
G. Vallar, R. Sterzi, G. Bottini, S. Cappa, and M. L. Rusconi, “Temporary Remission of
Left Hemianesthesia after Vestibular Stimulation. A Sensory Neglect Phenomenon,”
Cortex, 26 (1990): 123–131.
34. Many theories have been proposed to explain spatial neglect. For reviews see M.
Jeannerod, Neurophysiological and Neuropsychological Aspects of Spatial Neglect (Amster-
dam: Elsevier, 1987), and G. Rizzolatti and V. Galeze, “Mechanisms and Theories of
Spatial Neglect,” in F. Boller and J. Gravman, eds., Handbook of Neuropsychology (Am-
sterdam: Elsevier, 1988), pp. 289–313.
35. G. Vallar, R. Sterzi, G. Bottini, S. Cappa, and M. L. Rusconi, “Temporary Remission of
Left Hemianesthesia after Vestibular Stimulation. A Sensory Neglect Phenomenon,”
Cortex, 26 (1990): 123–131.
36. Ibid.
37. G. Bottini, E. Paulesu, R. Sterzi, E. Warburton, R. J. Wise, G. Vallar, R. S. Frackowiak,
and C. D. Frith, “Modulation of Conscious Experience by Peripheral Sensory Stimuli,”
Nature, 376 (1995): 778–781.
38. Ibid., p. 781.
39. J. Gertsmann, “Problems of Imperception of Disease and of Impaired Body Territories
278 •
NOTES TO PAGES 75–87
pure, vol. 2, Recherches phénoménologiques pour la constitution (Paris: Presses Universitaires
de France, 1982), p. 207.
58. A. J. Mistlin and D. I. Perrett, “Visual and Somatosensory Processing in the Macaque
Temporal Cortex: The Role of ‘Expectation,’” Experimental Brain Research, 82 (1990):
437–450.
59. J. K. Hietanen and D. I. Perrett, “A Role of Expectation in Visual and Tactile Processing
within the Temporal Cortex,” in Ono et al., Brain Mechanisms, pp. 83–103; quotation
from p. 89.
60. A. Prochazka, “Sensorimotor Gain Control: A Basic Strategy of Motor Systems?” Prog-
ress in Neurobiology, 33 (1989): 281–307; quotation from p. 301.
61. J. MacIntyre, E. Gurfinkel, M. Lipshits, J. Droulez, and V. Gurfinkel, “Measurement of
Human Force Control During Constrained Arm Motion using a Force-Activated Joy-
stick,” Journal of Neurophysiology, 17 (1995): 1201–1222.
62. Proust, Marcel, Remembrance of Things Past, trans. C. K. Scott Moncrieff and Terence
Kilmartin (London: Chatto and Windus, 1981), p. 64.
63. J. Droulez and C. Darlot, “The Geometric and Dynamic Implications of the Coherence
Constraints in Three-Dimensional Sensorimotor Coordinates,” in M. Jeannerod, ed.,
Attention and Performance XIII (Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1989), pp. 495–526.
64. J. Droulez and V. Cornilleau-Pérès, “Application of the Coherence Scheme to the
Multisensory Fusion Problem,” in A. Berthoz, ed., Multisensory Control of Movement
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993), pp. 485–508; quotation from p. 490.
65. M. Abeles, Local Cortical Circuits (Berlin: Springer, 1982); C. von der Malsburg, “Ner-
vous Structures with Dynamical Links,” Berichte der Bunsengesellschaft für physikalische
Chemie, 89 (1985): 703–710; E. Bienenstock and C. von der Malsburg, “Statistical
Coding and Short Term Synaptic Plasticity: A Scheme for Knowledge Representation
in the Brain,” in E. Bienenstock, F. Fogelman, G. Weisbuch, Disordered Systems and
Biological Organization (Berlin: Springer, 1986): 247–272; Gray et al., “Oscillatory Re-
sponses”; W. Singer, “Search for Coherence: A Basic Principle of Cortical Self-Organi-
zation,” Concepts in Neuroscience, 1 (1990): 1–26. For further references, see G. Buzsáki,
Z. Horváth, R. Urioste, J. Hetke, and K. Wise, “High Frequency Network Oscillations
in the Hippocampus,” Science, 256 (1992): 1025–1027.
66. Frith, Autism: Explaining the Enigma, Cognitive Development (Oxford: Basil Blackwell,
1989), pp. 103–104.
67. Ibid., p. 110.
68. Ibid., p. 166.
4 Frames of Reference
1. N. Eshkol and A. Wachmann, Movement Notation (London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson,
1958).
2. Grüsser and Landis, Visual Agnosias and Related Disorders; Cutting and Vishton, “Per-
ceiving Layout and Knowing Distances.”
3. J. Hyvarinen, The Parietal Cortex of Monkey and Man (Berlin: Springer, 1982).
4. V. H. Mountcastle, J. C. Lynch, A. Georgopoulos, H. Sakata, and C. Acuna, “Poste-
rior Parietal Association Cortex of the Monkey: Command Functions for Operations
within Extrapersonal Space,” Journal of Neurophysiology, 38 (1975): 871–908.
280 •
NOTES TO PAGES 100–106
20. See Chapter 2.
21. J. R. Lackner and M. S. Levine, “Changes in Apparent Body Orientation and Sensory
Localization Induced by Vibration of Postural Muscles: Vibratory Myesthetic Illu-
sions,” Aviation, Space, and Environmental Medicine, 50 (1979): 346–354; J. R. Lackner,
“Some Contributions of Touch, Pressure, and Kinesthesis to Human Spatial Orienta-
tion and Oculomotor Control,” Acta Astronautica, 8 (1981): 825–830, “Some Proprio-
ceptive Influences on the Perceptual Representation of Body Shape and Orientation,”
Brain, 111 (1981): 281–297, and “Orientation and Movement in Unusual Force Environ-
ments,” Psychological Science,” 4 (1993): 134–142.
22. J. F. Soechting and B. Ross, “Psychophysical Determination of Coordinate Representa-
tion of Human Arm Orientation,” Neuroscience, 13 (1984): 595–604; J. F. Soechting and
M. Flanders, “Sensorimotor Representations for Pointing to Targets in Three-Dimen-
sional Space,” Journal of Neurophysiology, 62 (1989): 582–594.
23. D. I. Perrett, E. T. Rolls, and W. Caan, “Visual Neurons Responsive to Faces in the
Monkey Temporal Cortex,” Experimental Brain Research, 47 (1982): 342; D. Perrett, A. J.
Mistlin, A. J. Chitty, P. A. J. Smith, D. D. Potter, R. Broennimann, and M. H. Harries,
“Specialised Face Processing and Hemispheric Asymmetry in Man and Monkey: Evi-
dence from Single Unit and Reaction Time Studies,” Behavioural Brain Research, 29
(1988): 245–258.
24. D. I. Perrett, J. K. Hietanen, M. W. Oram, and P. J. Benson, “Organisation and Function
of Cells Responsive to Faces in the Temporal Cortex,” Philosophical Transactions of the
Royal Society. Series B: Biological Sciences, 335 (1992): 23–30.
25. S. M. Kosslyn, C. F. Chabris, C. J. Marsolek, and O. Koenig, “Categorical versus Coordi-
nate Spatial Representations: Computational Analysis and Computer Simulations,”
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 18 (1992): 562–577.
26. M. Arbib, T. Iberall, and G. Bingham, “Opposition Space as a Structuring Concept for
the Analysis of Skilled Hand Movements,” Experimental Brain Research, 15 (1986): 158–
173.
27. M. A. Arbib, “Interaction of Multiple Representations of Space in the Brain,” in
Paillard, Brain and Space, pp. 380–403; quotation from p. 380.
28. M. Jeannerod, “A Neurophysiological Model for the Directional Coding of Reaching
Movements,” in Paillard, Brain and Space, pp. 49–69; Goodale et al. [M. A. Goodale,
A. D. Milner, L. S. Jakobson, and D. P. Carey, “Neurological Dissociation between Per-
ceiving Objects and Grasping Them,” Nature, 349 (1991): 154–156] showed that patients
with cervical lesions dissociate between perception and scaling of grasp.
29. Arbib, “Multiple Representations of Space,” p. 385.
30. J. Droulez and A. Berthoz, “Servo-Controlled (Conservative) versus Topological (Pro-
jective) Modes of Sensory Motor Control,” in W. Bles and T. Brandt, eds., Disorders of
Posture and Gait (Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1988), pp. 83–97.
31. A. Berthoz, “Reference Frames for the Perception and Control of Movement,” in
Paillard, Brain and Space, pp. 82–111. The ability to switch frames of reference—to
change perspective—is surely one of the distinctive features of the human brain.
32. M. F. Levin and A. G. Feldman, “The Role of Stretch Reflex Threshold Regulation
in Normal and Impaired Motor Control,” Brain Research, 657 (1994): 23–30; A. G.
Feldman and M. F. Levin, “The Origin and Use of Positional Frames of Reference
282 •
NOTES TO PAGES 113–121
tational Displacements in Normal Subjects and Patients with Labyrinthine Diseases,”
in D. L. Tomko, B. Cohen, and F. E. Guedry, eds., Sensing Motion (New York: Annals of
the New York Academy of Sciences, 1992).
16. I. Israël, “Memory-Guided Saccades: What Is Memorized?” Experimental Brain Research,
90 (1992): 221–224; Israël et al., “Cortical Control,” pp. 472–484; C. Pierrot-Deseilligny,
I. Israël, A. Berthoz, S. Rivaud, and B. Gaymard, “Role of the Different Frontal Lobe
Areas in the Control of the Horizontal Component of Memory-Guided Saccades in
Man,” Experimental Brain Research, 95 (1993): 166–171.
17. A. Berthoz, A. Grantyn, and J. Droulez, “Some Collicular Neurons Code Saccadic Eye
Velocity,” Neuroscience Letters, 72 (1987): 289–294; I. Israël and A. Berthoz, “Contribu-
tion of the Otoliths to the Calculation of Linear Displacement,” Journal of Neuro-
physiology, 62 (1989): 247–263; I. Israël, N. Chapuis, S. Glasauer, O. Charade, and A.
Berthoz, “Estimation of Passive Linear Whole Body Displacement in Humans,” Journal
of Neurophysiology, 70 (1993): 1270–1273.
18. A. Berthoz, I. Israël, P. Georges-François, R. Grasso, and T. Tsuzuku, “Spatial Memory
of Body Linear Displacement: What Is Being Stored?” Science, 269 (1995): 95–98. I.
Israël, R. Grasso, P. Georges-François, T. Tzuzuku, and A. Berthoz, “Spatial Memory
and Path Integration Studied by Self-Driven Linear Displacement,” Journal of Neuro-
physiology, 77 (1999): 3180–3192. We have recently found [Y. P. Ivanenko, R. Grasso, I.
Israël, and A. Berthoz, “The Contribution of Otoliths and Semicircular Canals to the
Perception of Two-Dimensional Passive Whole-Body Motion in Humans,” Journal of
Physiology, 502 (1997): 223–233], using a combination of translations and rotations
(semicircular path) during passive transport in robots, that in humans there may be a
dissociation between the processing of information relative to translations and to rota-
tions, as found in the rodents (see note 12 above).
19. Poincaré, The Value of Science, p. 74.
20. J. Droulez and A. Berthoz, “The Dynamic Memory Model and the Final Ooculomotor
and Cephalomotor Integrator,” in H. Shimazu and Y. Shinoda, eds., The Oculomotor Sys-
tem (Tokyo: Japan Scientific Societies Press, 1990), pp. 1–19; A. Berthoz, “Hippocampal
and Parietal Contribution to Topokinetic and Topographic Memory,” in N. Burgess,
K. J. Jeffery, and J. O’Keefe, eds., The Hippocampal and Parietal Foundations of Spatial Cog-
nition (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), pp. 381–399.
21. M. F. Land and D. N. Lee, “Where We Look When We Steer,” Nature, 369 (1994): 742–
744. It is, in fact, easy to show that the curvature of the road is connected to direction t
of the point tangent to the trajectory of the car using the following expression: C = 1/
([d cos t] − 1/d) where the curvature (C) is the inverse of the radius of the bend of the
road and (d) is the lateral distance of the driver in relation to the bend. We recently de-
scribed a similar gaze anticipation during locomotion [R. Grasso, S. Slasauer, U. Takei,
and A. Berthoz, “The Predictive Brain: Anticipatory Control of Head Direction for the
Steering of Locomotion,” NeuroReport, 7 (1996): 1170–1174].
22. B. Milner, “Visual Recognition and Recall after Right Temporal Lobe Excision in Man,”
Neuropsychologia, 6 (1968): 191–209.
23. The hippocampus is a structure that is currently the subject of much interest owing
to its role in memory and especially the acquisition of memories based on events.
284 •
NOTES TO PAGES 127–130
32. R. N. Shepard, “Ecological Constraints on Internal Representation: Resonant Kinemat-
ics of Perceiving, Imagining, Thinking, and Dreaming,” Psychological Review, 91 (1984):
417–447; quotation from p. 433.
33. J. O’Keefe and M. Recce, “Phase Relationship between Hippocampal Place Units and
the EEG Theta Rhythm,” Hippocampus, 3 (1993): 317–330.
34. J. E. Lisman and M. A. P. Idiart, “Storage of 7 ± 2 Short-Term Memories in Oscillatory
Subcycles,” Science, 267 (1995): 1512–1515. High-frequency (200 Hz) oscillations in the
hippocampus have also been demonstrated by G. Buzsáki et al., “High Frequency Net-
work Oscillations.”
35. A. Michotte, Causalité, permanence et réalité phénoménales (Paris: Béatrice-Nauwelaerts,
1962).
36. The Essential Writings of Merleau-Ponty, ed. Alden L. Fisher (New York: Harcourt, Brace,
1969), pp. 257–258.
6 Natural Movement
1. The term “rule” is used here instead of “law” to stress the fact that it is not a question
only of the laws of mechanics but also of constraints connected to intrinsic processes
of the nervous system.
2. Ariane Mnouchkine maintains that Oriental theater is the only theater (from a play-
bill).
3. Poems of Pierre de Ronsard, trans. and ed. Nicholas Kilmer (Berkeley: University of Cali-
fornia Press, 1979), p. 201.
4. Slotine and Li, Applied Nonlinear Control.
5. C. Darwin, The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals (New York: Philosophical
Library, 1955).
6. E. J. Marey, Le Mouvement (Paris: Masson, 1894); La Machine animale (Paris: Revue EPS,
1993).
7. P. Viviani and C. Terzuolo, “Trajectory Determines Movement Dynamics,” Neurosci-
ence, 72 (1982): 431–437.
8. N. A. Bernstein, “Some Emergent Problems of the Regulation of Motor Acts,” Ques-
tions of Psychology, no. 6 (1957), reprinted in Human Motor Actions: Bernstein Reassessed,
ed. H. T. A. Whiting, Advances in Psychology (Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1984), vol.
17, pp. 354–355.
9. C. De Waele, W. Graf, A. Berthoz, and F. Clarac, “Vestibular Control of Skeletal Ge-
ometry,” in A. Berthoz and F. Clarac, eds., Posture and Gait (Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1988),
pp. 423–432; Berthoz et al., Head-Neck Sensory-Motor System.
10. F. Lacquaniti, J. Soechting, and C. Terzuolo, “Path Constraints on Point to Point Arm
Movements in Three-Dimensional Space,” Neuroscience, 17 (1986): 313–324.
11. Soechting and Ross, “Psychophysical Determination of Coordinate Representation”;
Soechting and Flanders, “Sensorimotor Representations.”
12. C. C. A. M. Gielen and E. J. Van Zuylen, “Coordination of Arm Muscles during
Flexion and Supination: Applications of the Tensor Analysis Approach,” Neuroscience,
17 (1986): 527–539.
t2
CF = 1 2 ∫ [(d3 x / dt 3 )2 + (d3 y / dt 3 )2 ] dt
t1
According to this expression, movement would be maximally smooth when the value
of the function is at a minimum. Calculus shows that only one pair of equations pro-
duces this minimum value for a given set of boundary conditions; that is, the condi-
tions that define the beginning and the end of movement. The trajectory, specified by
the horizontal and vertical components of a movement, is therefore expressed as a
fifth-order polynomial function of time. Such functions determine the value of various
parameters all along the trajectory, and the model provides a way to define the tempo-
ral structure of movement. This is how Edelman and Flash demonstrated in 1987 that
a simulation of natural motor activity—for example, writing—could be obtained using
this principle of minimum jerk.
286 •
NOTES TO PAGES 146–156
Allum, eds., Vestibulospinal Control of Posture and Movement, Progress in Brain Research
(Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1988), pp. 17–27.
5. E. von Holst, “Relations between the Central Nervous System and the Peripheral Or-
gans,” Journal of Animal Behaviour, 2 (1954): 89–94; Von Holst and Mittelstaedt, “Das
Reafferenzprinzip.”
6. W. Graf and R. Baker, “Adaptive Changes in the Vestibulo-ocular Reflex of the Flatfish
Are Achieved by Reorganization of Central Nervous Pathways,” Science, 221 (1983):
777–779.
7. E. V. Evarts, “Relation of Pyramidal Tract Activity to Force Exerted during Voluntary
Movements,” Journal of Neurophysiology, 31 (1968): 14–27, and “Role of Motor Cortex in
Voluntary Movements in Primates,” in V. B. Brooks, ed., Handbook of Physiology, sect. 1,
vol. 2, Motor Control (Bethesda, Md.: American Physiological Society, 1981), pp. 1083–
1120.
8. A. P. Georgopoulos, J. F. Kalaska, R. Caminiti, and J. T. Massey, “On the Relations be-
tween the Direction of Two-Dimensional Arm Movements and Cell Discharge in Pri-
mate Motor Cortex,” Journal of Neuroscience, 2 (1982): 1527–1537; A. P. Georgopoulos,
A. B. Schwartz, and R. E. Kettner, “Neuronal Population Coding of Movement Direc-
tion,” Science, 233 (1986): 1416–1429; J. F. Kalaska, R. Caminiti, and A. P. Georgopoulos,
“Cortical Mechanisms Related to the Direction of Two-Dimensional Arm Movements:
Relations in Parietal Area 5 and Comparison with Motor Cortex,” Experimental Brain
Research, 51 (1983): 247–260; A. P. Georgopoulos, “Current Issues in Directional Motor
Control,” Trends in Neurosciences, 18 (1995): 506–510.
9. A. P. Georgopoulos, M. D. Crutcher, and A. B. Schwartz, “Cognitive Spatial Motor Pro-
cesses. III. Motor Cortical Prediction of Movement Direction during an Instructed De-
lay Period,” Experimental Brain Research, 75 (1989): 183–194; A. P. Georgopoulos, J. T.
Lurito, M. Petrides, A. B. Schwartz, and J. T. Massey, “Mental Rotation of the Neuronal
Population Vector,” Science, 243 (1989): 234–236.
10. L. Rispal-Padel, F. Cicirata, and C. Pons, “Cerebellar Nuclear Topography of Simple
and Synergistic Movements in the Alert Baboon (Papio papio),” Experimental Brain Re-
search, 47 (1982): 365–380.
8 Capture
1. N. A. Bernstein, The Coordination and Regulation of Movement (New York: Pergamon
Press, 1967).
2. J. P. Ewert, “Neural Mechanisms of Prey-Catching and Avoidance Behavior in the Toad
(Bufo bufo L.),” Brain Behaviour and Evolution, 3 (1970): 36–56, and “Neuroethology
of Releasing Mechanisms: Prey-Catching in Toads,” Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 10
(1987): 337–405.
3. Schmidt, “A Schema Theory,” Psychological Review, 32 (1975): 225–260.
4. D. N. Lee, “A Theory of Visual Control of Braking Based on Information about Time-
to-Collision,” Perception, 5 (1976): 437–459.
5. D. N. Lee and P. E. Reddish, “Plummeting Gannets: A Paradigm of Ecological Optics,”
Nature, 293 (1985): 293–294; D. N. Lee and D. S. Young, “Visual Timing in Interceptive
Actions,” in D. J. Ingle, M. Jeannerod, and D. N. Lee, eds., Brain Mechanisms and Spatial
Vision (Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff, 1996), pp. 1–30.
288 •
NOTES TO PAGES 170–174
tional variables, a law of evolution is applied to predict a new state without taking into
account the new measurements; this first estimate is used to predict the information
supplied by the receptors with the help of an internal model of their functioning. The
spread between the predicted information and the actual measurements facilitates opti-
mal correction of the first estimate.
14. From Merleau-Ponty’s discussion of von Uexküll’s work in his book La Nature, pp. 220,
227. J. von Uexküll, Umwelt und Innenwelt der Tieren und Menschen (Berlin: Springer,
1934); Streifzüge durch die Umwelten von Tieren und Menschen (Berlin: Springer, 1965).
15. Merleau-Ponty, La Nature.
16. R. N. Shepard, “Ecological Constraints,” p. 422.
17. P. Viviani and N. Stucchi, “Biological Movements Look Uniform: Evidence for Motor-
Perceptual Interactions,” Journal of Experimental Psychology (Human Perception), 18
(1992): 603–623.
18. M. Kawato, K. Furukawa, and R. Suzuki, “A Hierarchical Neural Network Model for
Control and Learning of Voluntary Movements,” Biological Cybernetiks, 57 (1987): 169–
185; H. Gomi and M. Kawato, “Adaptive Feedback Control Models of the Vestibulo-
cerebellum and Spinocerebellum,” Biological Cybernetics, 68 (1992): 105–114.
19. Walton et al., “Identification of a Critical Period.”
20. Kelso, “Phase Transitions”; Kelso et al., “Action-Perception”; Schöner, “A Dynamic
Theory”; Buchanan and Kelso, “Posturally Induced Transitions.”
10 Visual Exploration
1. This word is the English translation of the name of a machine invented by the scientist
Cosinus in Georges Columb [Christophe pseud.], L’Idée fixe du savant Cosinus (Paris:
Colin, 1939).
2. D. G. MacKay, The Organization of Perception and Action (New York: Springer, 1987). For
more on this topic see Bergson’s observations in Matter and Memory.
3. J. C. Eccles, M. Ito, and J. Szentogothai, The Cerebellum as a Neuronal Machine (Berlin:
Springer, 1967); R. Llinás and C. Sotelo, The Cerebellum Revisited (New York: Springer,
1992).
4. J. Decety and D. H. Ingvar, “Brain Structures Participating in Mental Simulation of
Motor Behaviour: A Neuropsychological Interpretation,” Acta Physiologica Scandinavica,
73 (1990): 13–34.
5. H. Korn and D. S. Faber, “Organisation and Cellular Mechanisms Underlying Chemical
Inhibition in a Vertebrate Neuron,” in J.-P. Changeux, ed., Molecular and Cellular Interac-
tions Underlying Higher Brain Functions, Progress in Brain Research (Amsterdam: North
Holland, 1983); D. S. Faber, W. S. Young, P. Legendre, and H. Korn, “Intrinsic Quantal
Variability Due to Stochastic Properties of Receptor-Transmitter Interactions,” Science,
258 (1992): 1494–1498; R. Miles, K. Toth, A. Gulyas, N. Hajos, and T. F. Freund, “Differ-
ences between Somatic and Dendritic Inhibition in the Hippocampus,” Neuron, 16
(1996): 814–823. These researchers showed that inhibiting junctions have several ways
of acting on their neuronal target: controlling the base potential of these cells, oppos-
ing the effect of excitatory inputs when these are not sufficiently intense (that is, “sig-
nificant”), adjusting the rate at which these cells emit signals, and finally in synchroniz-
ing the activity of clusters of neighboring cells, which makes them more “effective.”
Moreover, inhibitory junctions evidence training and memory properties until recently
unsuspected.
6. J. Piaget, The Origin of Intelligence in the Child (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul,
1953).
7. Von Holst and Mittelstaedt, “Das Reafferenzprinzip”; B. Bridgeman, “A Review of the
Role of Efference Copy in Sensory and Oculomotor Control Systems,” Annals of Bio-
medical Engineering, 23 (1995): 409–422.
8. Israël, “Memory-Guided Saccades.”
9. I. Israël, S. Rivaud, P. Pierrot-Desilligny, and A. Berthoz, “Delayed VOR: An Assess-
290 •
NOTES TO PAGES 186–196
ment of Vestibular Memory for Self Motion,” in J. Requin and J. Stelmach, eds., Tuto-
rials in Motor Neuroscience (The Netherlands: Kluwer, 1991), pp. 599–607; I. Israël, S.
Rivaud, B. Gaymard, A. Berthoz, and C. Pierrot-Deseilligny, “Cortical Control of Ves-
tibular-Guided Saccades in Man,” Brain, 118 (1995): 1169–1183.
10. A. Berthoz, “Neural Basis of Decision in Perception and in the Control of Movement,”
in A. R. Damasio, et al., eds., Neurobiology of Decision-Making (Berlin: Springer, 1996),
pp. 83–100; A. Berthoz and L. Petit, “Les mouvements du regard: une affaire de sac-
cades. Un modèle pour l’étude des circuits de la décision et de l’imagination motrice,”
La Recherche, 289 (1996): 58–65.
11. Berthoz, “Neural Basis of Decision,” pp. 83–100.
12. See A. Berthoz, “Coopération et substitution entre le système saccadique et les réflexes
d’origine vestibulaires: faut-il réviser la notion de réflexe?” Revue Neurologique, 145
(1989): 513–526, for a detailed description of saccadic mechanisms in the brainstem.
See also Berthoz and Petit, “Les mouvements du regard,” pp. 58–65, for a detailed de-
scription of this schematic diagram.
13. I. S. Curthoys, C. H. Markham, and N. Furuya, “Direct Projection of Pause Neurons to
Nystagmus-Related Excitatory Burst Neurons in the Cat Pontine Reticular Formation,”
Experimental Neurology, 83 (1984): 414–422.
14. D. P. Munoz and R. H. Wurtz, “Fixation Cells in Monkey Superior Colliculus. I. Char-
acteristics of Cell Discharge,” Journal of Neurophysiology, 70 (1993): 559–575; M. A.
Segraves, “Effects of Frontal Eye Field Stimulation upon Omnipause and Burst Neu-
rons in the Monkey Paramedian Pontine Reticular Formation,” Society of Neuroscience
Abstracts, 18 (1992): 296.10.
15. Berthoz et al., “Saccadic Eye Velocity.”
16. A. Grantyn and R. Grantyn, “Axonal Patterns and Sites of Termination of Cat Supe-
rior Colliculus Neurons Projecting in the Tecto-bulbo-spinal Tract,” Experimental Brain
Research, 46 (1982): 243–256; A. Grantyn, R. Grantyn, V. Robine, and A. Berthoz,
“Electroanatomy of Tectal Efferent Connections Related to Eye Movements in the
Horizontal Plane,” Experimental Brain Research, 37 (1979): 149–172; R. E. Wurtz and
M. E. Goldberg, “Activity of Superior Colliculus in Behaving Monkey. III. Cells Dis-
charging before Eye Movements,” Journal of Neurophysiology, 35 (1972): 575–586; A.
Grantyn and A. Berthoz, “The Role of the Tecto-reticulo-spinal System in Control of
Head Movement,” in G. W. Peterson and F. Richmond, eds., Control of Head Movement
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987), pp. 224–244; E. Oliver, A. Grantyn, M. Chat,
and A. Berthoz, “The Control of Slow Orienting Eye Movements by Tectoreticulo-
spinal Neurons in the Cat: Behavior, Discharge Patterns, and Underlying Connec-
tions,” Experimental Brain Research, 93 (1993): 435–449; A. B. Moschovakis, A. B.
Karabelas, and S. Highstein, “Structure Function Relationship in the Primate Supe-
rior Colliculus. I. Morphological Classification of Efferent Neurons,” Journal of Neuro-
physiology, 60 (1988): 232–262, and “Structure Function Relationship in the Primate
Superior Colliculus. II. Morphological Identity of Presaccadic Neurons,” Journal of
Neurophysiology, 60 (1988): 263–302.
17. A. B. Karabelas and A. K. Moschovakis, “Nigral Inhibitory Termination on Efferent
Neurons of the Superior Colliculus. An Intracellular Horseradish Peroxidase Study in
the Cat,” Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 239 (1985): 309–329; J. M. Deniau and G.
292 •
NOTES TO PAGES 200–206
29. W. F. McDaniel, D. M. Compton, and S. R. Smith, “Spatial Learning following Poste-
rior Parietal or Hippocampal Lesions,” NeuroReport, 5 (1994): 1713–1717. See also our
recent findings from a mental locomotor task [O. Ghaem, E. Mellet, F. Crivello, N.
Tzourio, B. Mazoyer, A. Berthoz, and M. Denis, “Mental Navigation along Memorized
Routes Activates the Hippocampus, Precuneus, and Insula,” NeuroReport 8 (1997): 739–
744].
30. M. N. Shadlen and W. T. Newsome, “Motion Perception: Seeing and Deciding,” Pro-
ceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 93 (1996): 628–633.
31. J.-R. Duhamel, C. L. Colby, and M. E. Goldberg, “The Updating of the Representation
of Visual Space in Parietal Cortex by Intended Eye Movements,” Science, 255 (1992):
90–92.
32. P. Viviani and A. Berthoz, “Voluntary Deceleration and Perceptual Activity during
Oblique Saccades,” in R. Baker and A. Berthoz, eds., Control of Gaze by Brain Stem Neu-
rons (Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1977), pp. 23–28.
33. M. A. Segraves and M. E. Goldberg, “Functional Properties of Corticotectal Neu-
rons in the Monkey’s Frontal Eye Field,” Journal of Neurophysiology, 58 (1987): 1387–
1419.
34. D. Ferrier, Functions of the Brain.
35. Penfield and Boldrey, “Somatic Motor and Sensory Representation”; Penfield and Ras-
mussen, Cerebral Cortex of Man.
36. E. Melamed and B. Larsen, “Saccadic Eye Movements in Humans”; P. T. Fox, J. M. Fox,
M. E. Raichle, and R. M. Burde, “The Role of the Cerebral Cortex in the Generation
of Voluntary Saccades,” Journal of Neurophysiology, 54 (1985): 348–369.
37. L. Petit, C. Orssaud, N. Tzourio, G. Salamon, B. Mazoyer, and A. Berthoz, “PET Study
of Voluntary Saccadic Eye Movements in Humans: Basal Ganglia-Thalamocortical Sys-
tem and Cingulate Cortex Involvement,” Journal of Neurophysiology, 69 (1993): 1009–
1017; Petit et al., “Functional Anatomy,” pp. 3726–3741.
38. L. Lang, D. Cheyne, R. Kristeva, R. Beisteiner, G. Lindinger, and L. Deecke, “Three-Di-
mensional Localization of SMA Activity Preceding Voluntary Movement. A Study of
Electric and Magnetic Fields in a Patient with Infarction of the Right Supplementary
Motor Area,” Experimental Brain Research, 87 (1991): 688–695.
39. M. P. Deiber, R. E. Passingham, J. G. Colebatch, K. J. Friston, P. D. Nixon, and R. S.
Frackowiak, “Cortical Areas and the Selection of Movement: A Study with Positron
Emission Tomography,” Experimental Brain Research, 84 (1991): 393–402.
40. W. Lang, M. Lang, F. Uhl, C. Koska, A. Kornhuber, and L. Deecke, “Negative Cortical
DC Shifts Preceding and Accompanying Simultaneous and Sequential Finger Move-
ments,” Experimental Brain Research, 71 (1988): 579–587; W. Lang, H. Obrig, G.
Lindinger, D. Cheyne, and L. Deecke, “Supplementary Motor Area Activation While
Tapping Bimanually Different Rhythms in Musicians,” Experimental Brain Research, 79
(1990): 504–514.
41. J. Schlag and M. Schlag-Rey, “Evidence for a Supplementary Eye Field,” Journal of
Neurophysiology, 57 (1987): 179–200.
42. B. Gaymard, C. Pierrot-Deseilligny, and S. Rivaud, “Impairment of Sequences of Mem-
ory-Guided Saccades after Supplementary Motor Area Lesions,” Annals of Neurology, 28
(1990): 622–626; B. Gaymard, S. Rivaud, and C. Pierrot-Deseilligny, “Role of the Left
294 •
NOTES TO PAGES 210–211
dial Prefrontal, Cingulate Cortex, and Cingulum Bundle Lesions on Tests of Spatial
Memory: Evidence of a Double Dissociation between Frontal and Cingulum Bundle
Contributions,” Journal of Neuroscience, 15 (1995): 7270–7281; J. Mogensen, T. K.
Pedersen, S. Holm, and L. E. Bang, “Prefrontal Cortical Mediation of Rats’ Place
Learning in a Modified Water Maze,” Brain Research Bulletin, 38 (1995): 425–434.
54. E. Salzmann, “Attention and Memory Trials during Neuronal Recording from the Pri-
mate Pulvinar and Posterior Parietal Cortex (Area PG),” Behavioral Brain Research, 67
(1995): 241–253.
55. Frith et al., “Willed Action.”
56. S. Park and P. S. Holzman, “Association of Working Memory Deficit and Eye Tracking
Dysfunction in Schizophrenia,” Schizophrenia Research, 11 (1993): 55–61.
57. B. M. Sheliga, L. Riggio, and G. Rizzolatti, “Orienting of Attention and Eye Move-
ments,” Experimental Brain Research, 98 (1994): 507–522; A. Berthoz, “The Role of Inhi-
bition in the Hierarchical Gating of Executed and Imagined Movements,” Cognitive
Brain Research, 3 (1996): 101–113.
58. W. Lang, L. Petit, P. Hölliger, U. Pietrzyck, N. Tzourio, B. Mazoyer, and A. Berthoz, “A
Positron Emission Tomography Study of Oculomotor Imagery,” NeuroReport, 5 (1994):
921–924.
59. Droulez and Berthoz, “Concept of Dynamic Memory,” “A Neural Network Model of
Sensoritopic Maps with Predictive Short Term Memory Properties,” Proceedings of the
National Academy of Sciences, 88 (1991): 9653–9657, and “The Dynamic Memory Model
and the Final Oculomotor and Cephalomotor Integrator,” in H. Shimazu and Y.
Shinoda, eds., The Oculomotor System (Tokyo: Japan Scientific Societies Press, 1991),
pp. 1–19; L. E. Mays and D. L. Sparks, “Saccades Are Spatially, Not Retinocentrically,
Coded,” Science, 208 (1980): 1163–1165.
60. J. Piaget, “Le problème neurologique de l’intériorisation des actions en opérations
réversibles,” Archives de psychologie, 32 (1949): 242–258. Ferrier also became interested in
this idea. On page 285 of Functions of the Brain he wrote: “In these sentences, and par-
ticularly the last, Bain seems to me to have clearly indicated the elements of attention,
which I conceive to be a combination of the activity of the motor, and of the inhibi-
tory-motor centres.”
11 Balance
1. A. Thomas, Equilibre et équilibration (Paris: Masson, 1940).
2. Lee and Lishman, “Visual Proprioceptive Control of Stance.”
3. Dichgans and Brandt, “Visual-Vestibular Interaction.”
4. See Chapter 4.
5. Lee and Aronson, “Visual Proprioceptive Control of Standing.”
6. K. F. Hamann, P. P. Vidal, J. M. Sterkers, and A. Berthoz, “A New Test for Postural Dis-
orders: An Application of Visual Stabilization,” Agressologie, 20B (1979): 129–130.
7. Clément et al., “Adaptation of Postural Control.”
8. F. Lestienne, J. Soechting, and A. Berthoz, “Postural Readjustments Induced by Linear
Motion of Visual Scenes,” Experimental Brain Research, 28 (1977): 363–384; J. F.
Soechting and A. Berthoz, “Dynamic Role of Vision in the Control of Posture in
Man,” Experimental Brain Research, 36 (1979): 551–561.
296 •
NOTES TO PAGES 219–225
untary Arm Movements in Patients with Parkinson’s Disease,” in M. D. Yahr and K. J.
Bergman, eds., Advances in Neurology, vol. 45 (New York: Raven Press, 1986), pp. 371–
374; Clément et al., “Adaptation of Postural Control.”
24. L. Mouchnino, R. Aurenty, J. Massion, and A. Pedotti, “Is the Trunk a Reference Frame
for Calculating Leg Position?” NeuroReport, 4 (1993): 125–127.
25. J. Babinski, “De l’asynergie cérébelleuse,” Revue de Neurologie, 7 (1989): 806–816; see re-
cent findings on the physiopathology of this synergy in Bouisset and Zattara, “Bio-
mechanical Study”; Clément et al., “Adaptation of Postural Control”; Crenna et al.,
“Forward and Backward.”
26. Bazalgette et al., “Postural Adjustments,” pp. 371–374; F. Viallet, J. Massion, R.
Massarino, and R. Khalil, “Coordination between Posture and Movement in Parkin-
sonism and SMA Lesion,” in L. Deecke, J. C. Eccles, and V. B. Mountcastle, eds., From
Neuron to Action (Berlin: Springer, 1990), pp. 65–70; R. G. Lee, I. Tonolli, F. Viallet, R.
Aurenty, and J. Massion, “Preparatory Postural Adjustment in Parkinsonian Patients
with Postural Instability,” Canadian Journal of Neurological Sciences, 22 (1995): 126–135.
27. Massion et al., “La région de l’aire motrice supplémentaire.”
28. Y. Gahery and J. Massion, “Coordination between Posture and Movement,” in E. V.
Evarts, S. P. Wise, and D. Bousfield, eds., The Motor System in Neurobiology (Amsterdam:
Elsevier Biomedical Press, 1985), pp. 121–125.
29. Y. Paulignan, M. Dufosse, M. Hugon, and J. Massion, “Acquisition of Coordination be-
tween Posture and Movement in a Bimanual Task,” Experimental Brain Research, 77
(1989): 337–348.
30. G. Clément, T. Pozzo, and A. Berthoz, “Contribution of Eye Positioning in the Control
of Upside-Down Vertical Posture,” Experimental Brain Research, 73 (1988): 569–576.
31. H. Head and G. Holmes, “Sensory Disturbances from Cerebral Lesions,” Brain, 34
(1911): 102–244.
32. V. S. Gurfinkel, E. E. Debreva, and Y. S. Levik, “The Role of the Internal Model in the
Perception of Position and Planning of Hand Movements,” Fiziologiia Cheloveka, 12
(1986): 769–776; V. S. Gurfinkel and Y. S. Levick, “Perceptual and Automatic Aspects of
the Postural Body Scheme,” in Paillard, Brain and Space, pp. 174–162.
33. E. D. Adrian, The Physical Background of Perception (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1947),
pp. 93–94.
34. See Chapter 2.
35. A. Berthoz, “Coopération et substitution entre le système saccadique et les réflexes
d’origine vestibulaires: faut-il réviser la notion de réflèxe?” Revue Neurologique, 145
(1989): 513–526.
36. These experiments were continued by E. Bizzi’s group at MIT.
37. Gomi and Kawato, “Adaptive Feedback Control Models.”
38. J. Massion and L. Rispal-Padel, “Thalamus: fonctions motrices,” Revue Neurologique, 142
(1986): 327–336.
39. M. Poncet, J. F. Pellissier, M. Sebahoun, and C. J. Masser, “A propos d’un cas
d’autotopagnosie secondaire à une lésion pariéto-occipitale de l’hémisphère majeur,”
Encéphale, 60 (1971): 110–123.
40. M. I. Posner, M. J. Nissen, and W. C. Ogden, “Attended and Unattended Processing
12 Adaptation
1. A. Gonshor and G. Melvill Jones, “Extreme Vestibulo-ocular Adaptation by Prolonged
Optical Reversal of Vision,” Journal of Physiology, 256 (1976): 381–414.
2. See Figure 2.4.
3. M. Ito, “Cerebellar Control of the Vestibulo-ocular Reflex around the Flocculus Hy-
pothesis,” Annual Review of Neuroscience, 5 (1982): 275–296; The Cerebellum and Neuronal
Control (New York: Raven, 1984).
4. F. A. Miles and S. G. Lisberger, “Plasticity in the Vestibulo-ocular Reflex: A New Hy-
pothesis,” Annual Review of Neuroscience, 4 (1981): 273–299; S. Du Lac, J. L. Raymond,
T. J. Sejnowski, and S. G. Lisberger, “Learning and Memory in the Vestibulo-Ocular
Reflex,” Annual Review of Neuroscience, 18 (1995): 409–441.
5. Berthoz and Melvill-Jones, Adaptative Mechanisms in Gaze Control; G. Melvill-Jones,
D. Guitton, and A. Berthoz, “Changing Patterns of Eye-Head Coordination during
Six Hours of Optically Reversed Vision,” Experimental Brain Research, 69 (1988): 531–
544.
6. G. Melvill-Jones, A. Berthoz, and B. Segal, “Adaptative Modification of the Vestibulo-
ocular Reflex by Mental Effort in Darkness,” Experimental Brain Research, 56 (1984):
149–153.
7. A. Berthoz, “Coopération et substitution entre le système saccadique et les réflexes
d’origine vestibulaires: faut-il réviser la notion de réflexe?” Revue Neurologique, 145
(1989): 513–526; Viaud-Delmon et al., “Sex, Lies, and Virtual Reality”; I. Viaud-Del-
mon, Y. Ivanenko, A. Berthoz, and R. Jouvent, “Anxiety and Integration of Visual Ves-
tibular Information Studied with Virtual Reality,” Biological Psychiatry, in press.
8. Nudo et al., “Use-Dependent Alterations.”
9. J.-C. Baudrillard, D. Rousié, H. Foucart, C. Defache, J.-C. Hache, P. Van Tichelen, and
J.-M. Lerais, “IRM des canaux semi-circulaires dans les asymétries cranio-faciales et le
syndrome cranio-mandibulaire,” Journal of Radiology, 76 (1995): 579–585.
10. Ivanenko et al., “The Contribution of Otoliths.”
11. Vitte et al., “Recovery from Vestibular Deficits.”
298 •
NOTES TO PAGES 230–243
3. I. Krechevsky, “Hypothesis in Rats,” Psychological Reviews, 39 (1932): 517–532; quotation
from p. 528.
4. C. Darlot, P. Denise, J. Droulez, B. Cohen, and A. Berthoz, “Eye Movements Induced
by Off-Vertical Axis Rotation (OVAR) at Small Angles of Tilt,” Experimental Brain Re-
search, 73 (1988): 91–105, and “Motion Perception Induced by Off-Vertical Axis Rota-
tion (OVAR) at Small Angles of Tilt,” Experimental Brain Research, 73 (1988): 106–114.
5. A. Fessard and A. Tournay, “Quelques données et réflexions sur le phénomène de la
post-contraction involontaire,” L’Année psychologique, 50 (1950): 216–235. This illusion
was recently investigated by Lestienne and Gurfinkel.
6. J. P. Roll, J. C. Gilhodes, R. Roll, and F. Harley, “Are Proprioceptive Sensory Inputs
Combined into a Gestalt?” in T. Inoue and J. T. MacClelland, eds., Attention and Perfor-
mance XVI (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995), pp. 290–314; Lackner and Levine,
“Changes in Apparent Body Orientation.”
7. Roll et al., “Are Proprioceptive Sensory Inputs Combined?” pp. 307–308.
8. Rolls and O’Mara, “Neurophysiological and Theoretical Analysis”; O’Mara et al.,
“Whole Body Motion.”
9. The recent findings of Damasio regarding the significance of the prefrontal cortex
in relationships between vegetative and cognitive mechanisms and a rereading of
the work of the Sokolov school on relationships between the hippocampus and the
reticular formation stimulated this speculation.
10. H. Hécaen and J. De Ajuriaguerra, Méconnaissances et hallucinations corporelles:
intégration et désintégration de la somatognosie (Paris: Masson et Cie, 1952).
11. Shepard, “Ecological Constraints,” p. 436.
14 Architects Have Forgotten the Pleasure of Movement
1. Baron Georges Eugène Haussmann (1809–1891) was the French city planner whose re-
design of Paris between 1853 and 1870 resulted in the broad streets, radiating avenues,
and vistas for which the city is famous. [Trans.]
Conclusion
1. Bergson, Matter and Memory, p. 46.
2. H. Bergson, Mind-Energy: Lectures and Essays, trans. H. Wildon Carr (Westport, Conn.:
Greenwood, 1975), p. 58.
3. A. Sirigu, J. R. Duhamel, L. Cohen, B. Pillon, B. Dubois, and Y. Abid, “The Mental Rep-
resentation of Hand Movements after Parietal Cortex Damage,” Science, 273 (1996):
1564–1568.
WORKS CITED •
301
Bertenthal, B. I., and R. K. Clifton. “Perception and Action.” In Handbook of Child Psychol-
ogy, ed. D. Kuhn and R. Siegler. New York: Wiley, 1996.
Berthoz, A. “Coopération et substitution entre le système saccadique et les réflexes
d’origine vestibulaires: faut-il réviser la notion de réflexe?” Revue Neurologique, 145
(1989): 513–526.
———. “Reference Frames for the Perception and Control of Movement.” In Brain and
Space, ed. J. Paillard. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991, 82–111.
———. “La coopération des sens et du regard dans la perception du mouvement.” In Le
Corps en jeu, ed. O. Aslan. Paris: CNRS Editions, 1993, 17–25.
———, ed. Multisensory Control of Movement. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993.
———. “Neural Basis of Decision in Perception and in Control of Movement.” In
Neurobiology of Decision-Making, ed. A. R. Damasio, H. Damasio, and Y. Christen.
Berlin: Springer, 1996, 83–100.
———. “How Does the Cerebral Cortex Process and Utilize Vestibular Signals?” In Disor-
ders of the Vestibular System, ed. R. W. Baloh and G. M. Halmagyi. Oxford: Oxford Uni-
versity Press, 1996, 113–125.
———. “The Role of Inhibition in the Hierarchical Gating of Executed and Imagined
Movements.” Cognitive Brain Research, 3 (1996): 101–113.
———. “Hippocampal and Parietal Contribution to Topokinetic and Topographic Mem-
ory.” In The Hippocampal and Parietal Foundations of Spatial Cognition, ed. N. Burgess,
K. J. Jeffery, and J. O’Keefe. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999, 381–399.
———. Leçons sur le corps, le cerveau et l’esprit. Paris: Odile Jacob, 1999.
Berthoz, A., A. Amorim, S. Glasauer, R. Grasso, Y. Takei, and I. Viaud-Delmon. “Dissocia-
tion between Distance and Direction during Locomotor Navigation.” In Wayfinding
Behaviour, ed. R. G. Golledge. Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press, 1999, 328–
348.
Berthoz, A., R. Baker, and W. Precht. “Labyrinthine Control of Inferior Oblique Moto-
neurons.” Experimental Brain Research, 18 (1973): 225–241.
Berthoz, A., J. Droulez, P. P. Vidal, and K. Yoshida. “Neural Correlates of Horizontal
Vestibulo-ocular Reflex Cancellation during Rapid Eye Movements in the Cat.” Jour-
nal of Physiology, 419 (1989): 717–751.
Berthoz, A., W. Graf, and P. P. Vidal. The Head-Neck Sensory-Motor System. New York: Ox-
ford University Press, 1991.
Berthoz, A., A. Grantyn, and J. Droulez. “Some Collicular Neurons Code Saccadic Eye Ve-
locity.” Neuroscience Letters, 72 (1987): 289–294.
Berthoz, A., and A. Guell. “Space Neuroscience Research.” Brain Research Reviews, 28
(1998): 1–234.
Berthoz, A., I. Israël, P. Georges-François, R. Grasso, and T. Tsuzuku. “Spatial Memory of
Body Linear Displacement: What Is Being Stored?” Science, 269 (1995): 95–98.
Berthoz, A., I. Israël, T. Vieville, and D. S. Zee. “Linear Head Displacement Measured by
the Otoliths Can Be Reproduced through the Saccadic System.” Neuroscience Letters,
82 (1987): 285–290.
Berthoz, A., and G. Melvill-Jones. Adaptative Mechanisms in Gaze Control. Amsterdam:
Elsevier, 1985.
Berthoz, A., and S. Metral. “A Torque-Producing Stimulator for the Study of Muscular Re-
302 •
WORKS CITED
sponse to Variable Forces.” Proceedings of the International Symposium on Biomechanics
III. Basel: Karger, 1973, 158–165.
Berthoz, A., B. Pavard, and L. Young. “Perception of Linear Horizontal Self Motion In-
duced by Peripheral Vision (Linear-Vection).” Experimental Brain Research, 23 (1974):
471–489.
Berthoz, A., and L. Petit. “Les mouvements du regard: une affaire de saccades. Un modèle
pour l’étude des circuits de la décision et de l’imagination motrice.” La Recherche, 289
(1996): 58–65.
Berthoz, A., and T. Pozzo. “Intermittent Head Stabilisation during Postural and
Locomotory Tasks in Humans.” In Posture and Gait: Development, Adaptation, and Mod-
ulation, ed. B. Amblard, A. Berthoz, and F. Clarac. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1988, 189–
198.
Berthoz, A., and P. P. Vidal. Noyaux Vestibulaires et Vertiges. Paris: Arnette, 1993.
Berthoz, A., P. P. Vidal, and W. Graf, eds. The Head-Neck Sensory-Motor System. New York:
Oxford University Press, 1991.
Berthoz, A., K. Yoshida, and P. P. Vidal. “Horizontal Eye Movement Signals in Second Or-
der Vestibular Nuclei Neurons in the Alert Cat.” Annals of the New York Academy of
Sciences, 374 (1981): 144–156.
Bienenstock, E., and C. von der Malsburg. “Statistical Coding and Short Term Synaptic
Plasticity: A Scheme for Knowledge Representation in the Brain.” In Disordered Sys-
tems and Biological Organization, ed. E. Bienenstock, F. Fogelman, and G. Weisbuch.
Berlin: Springer, 1986, 247–272.
Bisiach, E., M. L. Rusconi, and G. Vallar. “Remission of Somatoparaphrenic Delusion
through Vestibular Stimulation.” Neuropsychologia, 29 (1991): 1029–1031.
Bizzi, E., N. Accornero, W. Chapple, and N. Hogan. “Posture Control and Trajectory For-
mation during Arm Movement.” Journal of Neuroscience, 4 (1984): 2738–2744.
Bloomberg, J., G. Melvill-Jones, B. Segal, S. McFarlane, and J. Soul. “Vestibular Contingent
Voluntary Saccades Based on Cognitive Estimates of Remembered Vestibular Infor-
mation.” Advances in Oto-Rhino-Laryngology, 40 (1988): 71–75.
Bonda, E., M. Petrides, S. Frey, and A. Evans. “Neural Correlates of Mental Transforma-
tions of the Body-in-Space.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 92 (1995):
11180–11184.
Bootsma, R. J., and C. E. Peper. “Predictive Visual Information Sources for the Regulation
of Action with Special Emphasis on Catching and Hitting.” In Vision and Motor Con-
trol, ed. L. Proteau and D. Elliot. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1992, 285–314.
Bottini, G., E. Paulesu, R. Sterzi, E. Warburton, R. J. Wise, G. Vallar, R. S. Frackowiak, and
C. D. Frith. “Modulation of Conscious Experience by Peripheral Sensory Stimuli.”
Nature, 376 (1995): 778–781.
Bottini, G., R. Sterzi, E. Paulesu, G. Vallar, S. Cappa, F. Erminio, R. E. Passingham, C. D.
Frith, and R. S. J. J. Frackowiak. “Identification of the Central Vestibular Projec-
tions in Man: A Positron Emission Tomography Activation Study.” Experimental Brain
Resarch, 99 (1994): 164–169.
Bouisset, S., and M. Zattara. “Biomechanical Study of the Programming of Anticipatory
Postural Adjustments Associated with Voluntary Movement.” Journal of Biomechanics,
20 (1987): 735–742.
WORKS CITED •
303
———. “A Sequence of Postural Movements Precedes Voluntary Movement.” Neuroscience
Letters, 22 (1989): 263–270.
Bourdieu, P. Le Sens pratique. Paris: Editions de Minuit, 1980.
Boussaoud, D., and S. P. Wise. “Primate Frontal Cortex: Neuronal Activity following
Attentional versus Intentional Cues.” Experimental Brain Research, 95 (1993): 15–27.
Bouveresse, J. Langage, perception et réalité. Nîmes: Jacqueline Chambon, 1995.
Bouyer, J. J., M. F. Montaron, J. M. Vahnée, M. Albert, and A. Rougeul. “Anatomical Local-
ization of Beta Rhythms in Cats.” Neuroscience, 22 (1987): 863–869.
Bradley, D. C., M. Maxwell, R. A. Andersen, M. S. Banks, and K. V. Shenoy. “Mechanisms
of Heading Perception in Primate Visual Cortex.” Science, 273 (1996): 1544–1547.
Brandt, T., J. Dichgans, and E. Koenig. “Differential Effects of Central versus Peripheral Vi-
sion on Egocentric and Exocentric Motion Perception.” Experimental Brain Research,
16 (1973): 476–491.
Brandt, T., and M. Dieterich. “Skew Deviation with Ocular Torsion: A Vestibular Brain-
stem Sign of Topographic Diagnostic Value.” Annals of Neurology, 33 (1993): 528–534.
Bridgeman, B. “A Review of the Role of Efference Copy in Sensory and Oculomotor Con-
trol Systems.” Annals of Biomedical Engineering, 23 (1995): 409–422.
Buchanan, J. J., and J. A. S. Kelso. “Posturally Induced Transitions in Rhythmic Multijoint
Limb Movements.” Experimental Brain Research, 94 (1993): 131–142.
Buisseret, P., and E. Gary-Bobo. “Development of Visual Cortical Orientation Specificity
after Dark Rearing: Role of Extra-ocular Proprioception.” Neuroscience Letters, 13
(1979): 259–263.
Buisseret, P., and M. Imbert. “Visual Cortical Cells: Their Developmental Properties in
Normal and Dark Reared Kittens.” Journal of Physiology, 255 (1976): 511–525.
Burnod, Y. An Adaptative Network, the Cerebral Cortex. Paris: Masson, 1988.
Buzsáki, G., Z. Horváth, R. Urioste, J. Hetke, and K. Wise. “High Frequency Network Os-
cillations in the Hippocampus.” Science, 256 (1992): 1025–1027.
Buzsáki, G., R. Llinás, W. Singer, A. Berthoz, and Y. Chrísten. Temporal Coding in the Brain.
Berlin: Spring, 1994.
Cajal, S. R. Histologie du système nerveux de l’homme et des vertébrés. Madrid: Raycar, 1972
[original pub. Paris, 1911].
Cappa, S., R. Sterzi, G. Vallar, and E. Bisiach. “Remission of Hemineglect and Anosognosia
during Vestibular Stimulation.” Neuropsychologia, 25 (1994): 722–732.
Celichowski, J., F. Emonet-Denand, Y. Laporte, and J. Petit. “Distribution of Static γ Axons
in Cat Peroneus Tertius Spindles Determined by Exclusively Physiological Criteria.”
Journal of Neurophysiology, 71 (1994): 722–732.
Changeux, J.-P. L’Homme neuronal. Paris: Fayard, 1983.
Châtelet, G. Les Enjeux du mobile—Mathématiques, physique, philosophie. Paris: Le Seuil, 1993.
Chatila, M., C. Milleret, P. Buser, and A. Fougeul. “A 10 Hz ‘Alpha-Like’ Rhythm in the Vi-
sual Cortex of the Waking Cat.” Electroencephalography and Clinical Neurophysiology, 83
(1992): 217–222.
Chen, L. L., L. Lin, E. J. Green, C. A. Barnes, and B. McNaughton. “Head Direction Cells
in the Rat Posterior Cortex. I. Anatomical Distribution and Behavioural Modulation.”
Experimental Brain Research, 101 (1994): 8–23.
Chen, L. L., L. Lin, C. A. Barnes, and B. McNaughton. “Head Direction Cells in the Rat
304 •
WORKS CITED
Posterior Cortex. II. Contributions of Visual and Ideothetic Information to the Direc-
tional Firing.” Experimental Brain Research, 101 (1994): 24–34.
Clément, G., V. S. Gurfinkel, F. Lestienne, M. Lipshits, and K. Popov. “Adaptation of Pos-
tural Control in Weightlessness.” Experimental Brain Research, 57 (1984): 61–72.
Clément, G., and F. Lestienne. “Adaptive Modifications of Postural Attitude in Conditions
of Weightlessness.” Experimental Brain Research, 72 (1988): 381–389.
Clément, G., T. Pozzo, and A. Berthoz. “Contribution of Eye Positioning in the Control of
Upside-Down Vertical Posture.” Experimental Brain Research, 73 (1988): 569–576.
Colby, C. L., J.-R. Duhamel, and M. E. Goldberg. “Oculocentric Spatial Representation in
Parietal Cortex.” Cerebral Cortex, 5 (1995): 470–481.
Columb, Georges [Christophe pseud]. L’Idée fixe du savant Cosinus. Paris: Armand Colin,
1939.
Crenna, P., C. Frigo, J. Massion, and A. Pedotti. “Forward and Backward Axial Synergies in
Man.” Experimental Brain Research, 65 (1987): 538–548.
Curthoys, I. S., C. H. Markham, and N. Furuya. “Direct Projection of Pause Neurons to
Nystagmus-Related Excitatory Burst Neurons in the Cat Pontine Reticular Forma-
tion.” Experimental Neurology, 83 (1984): 414–422.
Cutting, J. E., and P. M. Vishton. “Perceiving Layout and Knowing Distances: The Integra-
tion, Relative Potency and Contextual Use of Different Information about Depth.” In
Perception of Space and Motion. San Diego: Academic Press, 1995, 69–117.
Dai, M. J., I. Curthoys, and G. M. Halmagyi. “A Model of Otolith Stimulation.” Biological
Cybernetics, 60 (1989): 185–194.
Damasio, A. R. “The Brain Binds Entities and Events by Multiregional Activation from
Convergence Zones.” Neural Computation, 1 (1989): 123–132.
———. Descartes’ Error. New York: Putnam, 1994.
Damasio, A. R., H. Damasio, and Y. Christen. Neurobiology of Decision-Making. Berlin:
Springer, 1996.
Darlot, C., P. Denise, J. Droulez, B. Cohen, and A. Berthoz. “Eye Movements Induced by
Off-Vertical Axis Rotation (OVAR) at Small Angles of Tilt.” Experimental Brain Re-
search, 73 (1988): 91–105.
———. “Motion Perceptions Induced by Off-Vertical Axis Rotation (OVAR) at Small An-
gles of Tilt.” Experimental Brain Research, 73 (1988): 106–114.
Darwin, C. “Origin of Certain Instincts.” Nature, 179 (1887): 417–418.
———. The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals. New York: Philosophical Library,
1955.
De Ajuriaguerra, J. Résumés des cours. Paris: Collège de France, 1976.
Decéty, J., and D. H. Ingvar. “Brain Structures Participating in Mental Simulation of Motor
Behaviour: A Neurophysiological Interpretation.” Acta Physiological Scandinavica, 73
(1990): 13–34.
Decéty, J., M. Jeannerod, M. Germain, and J. Pastène. “Vegetative Response during Imag-
ined Movement Is Proportional to Mental Effort.” Behavioural Brain Research, 24
(1991): 1–5.
Decéty, J., M. Jeannerod, and C. Prablanc. “The Timing of Mentally Represented Actions.”
Behavioural Brain Research, 34 (1989): 35–42.
Deecke, L., D. W. F. Schwartz, and J. M. Fredrickson. “Nucleus Ventro-posterior Inferior
WORKS CITED •
305
(VPI) as the Vestibular Thalamic Relay in the Rhesus Monkey. I. Field Potential Inves-
tigation.” Experimental Brain Research, 20 (1974): 88–190.
Dehaene, S., and J.-P. Changeux. “A Simple Model of Prefrontal Cortex Function in De-
layed-Response Tasks.” Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 1 (1990): 244–261.
Deiber, M. P., R. E. Passingham, J. G. Colebatch, K. J. Friston, P. D. Nixon, and R. S.
Frackowiak. “Cortical Areas and the Selection of Movement: A Study with Positron
Emission Tomography.” Experimental Brain Research, 84 (1991): 393–402.
De Kleijn, A., and T. Magnus. “Uber die Funktion der Otolithen.” Pflugers Archiv, 186
(1921): 6–81.
Deniau, J. M., and G. Chevalier. “Disinhibition as a Basic Process in the Expression of
Striatal Functions. The Striatonigral Influence on Thalamocortical Cells of the Ven-
tromedial Thalamic Nucleus.” Brain Research, 334 (1981): 227–233.
Denis, M. “Approches différentielles de l’imagerie mentale.” In Cognition: L’Universel et
l’individuel, ed. M. Reuchlin, J. Lautrey, C. Marendaz, and T. Ohlman. Paris: Presses
Universitaires de France, 1989.
———. Image et cognition. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1989.
De Waele, C., W. Graf, A. Berthoz, and F. Clarac. “Vestibular Control of Skeletal Geome-
try.” In Posture and Gait, ed. A. Berthoz and F. Clarac. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1988, 423–
432.
Diamond, A., and P. S. Goldman-Rakic. “Comparison of Human Infants and Rhesus Mon-
keys on Piaget’s AB Task: Evidence for Dependence on Dorsolateral Prefrontal Cor-
tex.” Experimental Brain Research, 74 (1989): 24–40.
Dichgans, J., and T. Brandt. “Visual-Vestibular Interaction and Motion and Perception.” In
Cerebral Control of Eye Movements and Motion Perception, ed. J. Dichgans and E. Bizzi.
New York: Karger, 1972, 327–338.
———. “Visual-Vestibular Interactions: Effects on Self-Motion Perception and Postural
Control.” In Handbook of Sensory Physiology, vol. 5, ed. H. Leibowitz and H. L. Teuber.
Berlin: Springer, 1978, 755–804.
Dichgans, J., C. L. Schmidt, and W. Graf. “Visual Input Improves the Speedometer Func-
tion of the Vestibular Nuclei in the Goldfish.” Experimental Brain Research, 18 (1973):
319–322.
Dieterich, M., and T. Brandt. “Thalamic Infarctions: Differential Effects on Vestibular Func-
tion in the Roll Plane (35 Patients).” Neurology, 43 (1993): 1732–1740.
Di Pellegrino, G., L. Fadiga, L. Fogassi, V. Gallese, and G. Rizzolatti. “Understanding Mo-
tor Events: A Neurophysiological Study.” Experimental Brain Research, 91 (1992): 176–
180.
Di Pellegrino, G., and S. P. Wise. “Visuospatial versus Visuomotor Activity in the Premotor
and Prefrontal Cortex of a Primate.” Journal of Neuroscience, 13 (1993): 1227–1243.
Donders, F. C. “Beitrag zur Lehre von den Bewegungen des menschlichen Auges.” In
Hollandischen Beitragen zu den Anatomischen und Physiologischen Wissenschaften, vol. 1.
Amsterdam, 1847, 104–145.
Droulez, J., and A. Berthoz. “Servo-Controlled (Conservative) versus Topological (Projec-
tive) Modes of Sensory Motor Control.” In Disorders of Posture and Gait, ed. W. Bles
and T. Brandt. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1988, 83–97.
———. “The Concept of Dynamic Memory in Sensorimotor Control.” In Motor Control:
306 •
WORKS CITED
Concepts and Issues, ed. D. R. Humphrey and J.-J. Freund. Chichester: Wiley, 1990, 137–
161.
———. “The Dynamic Memory Model and the Final Oculomotor and Cephalomotor Inte-
grator. In The Oculomotor System, ed. H. Shimazu and Y. Shinoda. Tokyo: Japan
Scientific Societies Press, 1991, 1–19.
———. “A Neural Network Model of Sensoritopic Maps with Predictive Short-Term Mem-
ory Properties.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 88 (1991): 9653–9657.
Droulez, J., A. Berthoz, and P. P. Vidal. “Use and Limits of Visual Vestibular Interaction in
the Control of Posture. Are There Two Modes of Sensorimotor Control?” In Vestibu-
lar and Visual Control on Posture and Locomotor Equilibrium, ed. M. Igarashi and F. Owen
Black. Basel: Karger, 1985, 14–25.
Droulez, J., and V. Cornilleau-Pérès. “Application of the Coherence Scheme to the Multi-
sensory Fusion Problem.” In Multisensory Control of Movement, ed. A. Berthoz. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1993, 485–508.
Droulez, J., and C. Darlot. “The Geometric and Dynamic Implications of the Coherence
Constraints in Three-Dimensional Sensorimotor Coordinates.” In Attention and Perfor-
mance XIII, ed. M. Jeannerod. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1989, 495–526.
Duhamel, J.-R., F. Bremmer, S. Ben Hamed, and W. Graf. “Spatial Invariance of Visual Re-
ceptive Fields in Parietal Cortex Neurons.” Nature, 389 (1997): 845–848.
Duhamel, J.-R., C. L. Colby, and M. E. Goldberg. “Congruent Representations of Visual
and Somatosensory Space in Single Neurons of Monkey Ventral Intraparietal Cortex
(Area VIP).” In Brain and Space, ed. J. Paillard. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991,
223–236.
———. “The Updating of the Representation of Visual Space in Parietal Cortex by In-
tended Eye Movements.” Science, 255 (1992): 90–92.
Du Lac, S., J. L. Raymond, T. J. Sejnowski, and S. G. Lisberger. “Learning and Memory in
the Vestibulo-ocular Reflex.” Annual Review of Neuroscience, 18 (1995): 409–441.
Eccles, J. C., M. Ito, and J. Szentogothai. The Cerebellum as a Neuronal Machine. Berlin:
Springer, 1967.
Eckhorn, R., R. Bauer, W. Jordan, M. Brosch, W. Kruse, M. Munk, and H. J. Reitboeck.
“Coherent Oscillations: A Mechanism of Feature Linking in the Visual Cortex?” Bio-
logical Cybernetics, 60 (1988): 121–130.
Eichenbaum, H., S. I. Wiener, M. L. Shapiro, and N. J. Cohen. “The Organization of Spa-
tial Coding in the Hippocampus: A Study of Neural Ensemble Activity.” Journal of
Neuroscience, 9 (1989): 2764–2775.
Emonet-Dénand, F., Y. Laporte, P. B. C. Matthews, and J. Petit. “On the Subdivision of
Static and Dynamic Fusimotor Actions on the Primary Ending of Cat Muscle Spin-
dle.” Journal of Physiology, 261 (1977): 827–861.
Ernst, H. Les Principes de la mécanique (1894). Cited in R. N. Shepard, “Ecological Con-
straints on Internal Representation: Resonant Kinematics of Perceiving, Imagining,
Thinking, and Dreaming.” Psychological Review, 91 (1984): 417–447.
Eshkol, N., and A. Wachmann. Movement Notation. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson,
1958.
Etienne, A. S., R. Mowrer, and F. Saucy. “Limitations in the Assessment of Path-Dependent
Integration.” Behaviour, 106 (1988): 81–111.
WORKS CITED •
307
Evarts, E. V. “Relation of Pyramidal Tract Activity to Force Exerted during Voluntary
Movements.” Journal of Neurophysiology, 31 (1968): 14–27.
———. “Role of Motor Cortex in Voluntary Movements in Primates.” In Handbook of Phys-
iology, sect. 1, vol. 2, Motor Control, ed. V. B. Brooks. Bethesda: American Physiological
Society, 1981, 1083–1120.
Evarts, E. V., C. Fromm, J. Kroller, and V. A. Jennings. “Motor Cortex Control of Finely
Graded Forces.” Journal of Neurophysiology, 49 (1983): 1199–1215.
Ewert, J. P. “Neural Mechanisms of Prey-Catching and Avoidance Behavior in the Toad
(Bufo bufo L.).” Brain Behaviour and Evolution, 3 (1970): 36–56.
———. “Neuroethology of Releasing Mechanisms: Prey-Catching in Toads.” Behavioral
and Brain Sciences, 10 (1987): 337–405.
Faber, D. S., W. S. Young, P. Legendre, and H. Korn. “Intrinsic Quantal Variability Due to
Stochastic Properties of Receptor-Transmitter Interactions.” Science, 258 (1992): 1494–
1498.
Feldman, A. G., and M. F. Levin. “The Origin and Use of Positional Frames of Reference in
Motor Control.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 18 (1995): 723–744.
Ferrier, D. “Experiments on the Brain of Monkeys.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal
Society of London, 165 (1875): 433–488.
———. The Functions of the Brain. New York: G. P. Putnam’s Sons, 1876.
Fessard, A., and A. Tournay. “Quelques données et réflexions sur le phénomène de la post-
contraction involontaire.” L’Année psychologique (1950): 216–235.
Findley, L. J., R. Capildeo, and A. Tremor, eds. Movement Disorders. London: Macmillan,
1988.
Flor, H., T. Elbert, S. Knecht, C. Wienbruch, C. Pantev, N. Birbaumer, W. Larbig, and E.
Baub. “Phantom-Limb Pain as a Perceptual Correlate of Cortical Reorganization fol-
lowing Arm Amputation.” Nature, 375 (1995): 482–484.
Flourens, P. Recherches expérimentales sur les propriétés et les fonctions du système nerveux dans
les animaux vertébrés. Paris: Crévot, 1824.
Fogassi, L., V. Galese, L. Fadiga, G. Luppino, M. Matelli, and G. Rizzolatti. “Coding of
Peripersonal Space in Inferior Premotor Cortex (Area F4).” Journal of Neurophysiology,
76 (1996): 141–157.
Fox, P. T., J. M. Fox, M. E. Raichle, and R. M. Burde. “The Role of the Cerebral Cortex in
the Generation of Voluntary Saccades.” Journal of Neurophysiology, 54 (1985): 348–369.
Friberg, L., T. S. Olsen, P. Roland, O. B. Paulson, and N. A. Lassen. “Focal Increase of
Blood Flow in the Cerebral Cortex of Man during Vestibular Stimulation.” Brain, 108
(1985): 609–623.
Frith, C. D., K. Friston, P. F. Liddle, and R. S. Frackowiak. “Willed Action and the
Prefrontal Cortex in Man: A Study with PET.” Proceedings of the Royal Society of Lon-
don. Series B: Biological Sciences, 244 (1991): 241–246.
Frith, U. Autism: Explaining the Enigma. Cognitive Development. Oxford: Basil Blackwell,
1989.
Fuchs, A., and W. Becker, eds. Progress in Oculomotor Research. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1981.
Fukuda, T. Statokinetic Reflexes in Equilibrium and Movement. Tokyo: University of Tokyo
Press, 1983.
308 •
WORKS CITED
Funahashi, S., C. Bruck, and P. S. Goldman-Rakic. “Mnemonic Coding of Visual Space in
the Monkey’s Dorsolateral Prefrontal Cortex.” Journal of Neurophysiology, 61 (1989): 1–
19.
Fuster, J. M. The Prefrontal Cortex: Anatomy, Physiology, and Neuropsychology of the Frontal
Lobe. New York: Raven Press, 1996.
Gahery, Y., and J. Massion. “Coordination between Posture and Movement.” In The Motor
System in Neurobiology, ed. E. V. Evarts, S. P. Wise, and D. Bousfield. Amsterdam:
Elsevier Biomedical Press, 1985, 121–125.
Gavrilov, V. V., S. I. Wiener, and A. Berthoz. “Whole Body Rotations Enhance Hippo-
campal Theta Rhythm, Slow Activity in Awake Rats Passively Transported on a Mo-
bile Robot.” Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 781 (1996): 385–398.
Gaymard, B., C. Pierrot-Deseilligny, and S. Rivaud. “Impairment of Sequences of Mem-
ory-Guided Saccades after Supplementary Motor Area Lesions.” Annals of Neurology,
28 (1990): 622–626.
Gaymard, B., S. Rivaud, and C. Pierrot-Deseilligny. “Role of the Left and Right Supple-
mentary Motor Areas in Memory-Guided Saccade Sequences.” Annals of Neurology, 34
(1993): 404–406.
Georgopoulos, A. P. “Current Issues in Directional Motor Control.” Trends in Neurosciences,
18 (1995): 506–510.
Georgopoulos, A. P., M. D. Crutcher, and A. B. Schwartz. “Cognitive Spatial Motor Pro-
cesses. III. Motor Cortical Prediction of Movement Direction during an Instructed
Delay Period.” Experimental Brain Research, 75 (1989): 183–194.
Georgopoulos, A. P., J. F. Kalaska, R. Caminiti, and J. T. Massey. “On the Relations between
the Direction of Two-Dimensional Arm Movements and Cell Discharge in Primate
Motor Cortex.” Journal of Neuroscience, 2 (1982): 1527–1537.
Georgopoulos, A. P., J. T. Lurito, M. Petrides, A. B. Schwartz, and J. T. Massey. “Mental Ro-
tation of the Neuronal Population Vector.” Science, 243 (1989): 234–236.
Georgopoulos, A. P., A. B. Schwartz, and R. E. Kettner. “Neuronal Population Coding of
movement Direction.” Science, 233 (1986): 1416–1429.
Gertsmann, J. “Problems of Imperception of Disease and of Impaired Body Territories
with Organic Lesions. Relation to Body Scheme and Its Disorders.” Archives of Neurol-
ogy and Psychiatry, 48 (1942): 890–913.
Ghaem, O., E. Mellet, F. Grivello, N. Tzourio, B. Mazoyer, A. Berthoz, and M. Denis.
“Mental Navigation along Memorized Routes Activates the Hippocampus,
Precuneus, and Insula.” NeuroReport 8 (1997): 739–744.
Gibson, J. J. The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems. Boston: Houghton, 1966.
———. “The Theory of Affordances.” In Perceiving, Acting, and Knowing, ed. R. E. Shaw
and J. Bransford. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1977.
Gielen, S. “Muscle Activation Patterns and Joint-Angle Coordination in Multijoint Move-
ments.” In Multisensory Control of Movement, ed. A. Berthoz. New York: Oxford Uni-
versity Press, 293–312.
Gielen, C. C. A. M., and E. J. Van Zuylen. “Coordination of Arm Muscles during Flexion
and Supination: Applications of the Tensor Analysis Approach.” Neuroscience, 17
(1986): 527–539.
WORKS CITED •
309
Gladwin, T. East Is a Big Bird. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1970.
Glasauer, S., and H. Mittelstaedt. “Determinants of Orientation in Microgravity.” Acta
Astronautica, 27 (1992): 1–9.
Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von. Faust, trans. Randall Jarrell. New York: Farrar, Straus, and
Giroux, 1959.
Goldman-Rakic, P. “Circuitry of Primate Prefrontal Cortex and Regulation of Behavior by
Representational Memory.” In Handbook of Physiology, vol. 5, The Nervous System, ed.
V. B. Mountcastle, F. Plkum, and D. Humphrey. Bethesda: American Physiological So-
ciety, 1987, 373–417.
Gomi, H., and M. Kawato. “Adaptive Feedback Control Models of the Vestibulocerebellum
and Spinocerebellum.” Biological Cybernetics, 68 (1992): 105–114.
Gonshor, A., and G. Melvill Jones. “Extreme Vestibulo-ocular Adaptation by Prolonged
Optical Reversal of Vision.” Journal of Physiology, 256 (1976): 381–414.
Goodale, M. A., A. D. Milner, L. S. Jakobson, and D. P. Carey. “Neurological Dissociation
between Perceiving Objects and Grasping Them.” Nature, 349 (1991): 154–156.
Graf, W., and R. Baker. “Adaptive Changes of the Vestibulo-Ocular Reflex in Flatfish Are
Achieved by Reorganization of Central Nervous Pathways.” Science, 221 (1983): 777–
779.
Grantyn, A. “How Visual Inputs to the Ponto-Bulbar Reticular Formation Are Used in the
Synthesis of Premotor Signals during Orienting.” In Progress in Brain Research, vol. 80,
ed. J. H. J. Allum and M. Hulliger. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1989, 159–170.
Grantyn, A., and A. Berthoz. “The Role of the Tecto-reticulo-spinal System in Control of
Head Movement.” In Control of Head Movement, ed. G. W. Peterson and F. Richmond.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987, 224–244.
Grantyn, A., and R. Grantyn. “Axonal Patterns and Sites of Termination of Cat Superior
Colliculus Neurons Projecting in the Tecto-bulbo-spinal Tract.” Experimental Brain Re-
search, 46 (1982): 243–256.
Grantyn, A., R. Grantyn, V. Robine, and A. Berthoz. “Electroanatomy of Tectal Efferent
Connections Related to Eye Movements in the Horizontal Plane.” Experimental Brain
Research, 37 (1979): 149–172.
Grasso, R., C. Assaiante, P. Prévost, and A. Berthoz. “Development of Anticipatory Ori-
enting Strategies during Locomotor Tasks in Children,” Neuroscience and Biobehavioral
Review, 22 (1998): 533–539.
Grasso, R., S. Glasauer, U. Takei, and A. Berthoz. “The Predictive Brain: Anticipatory Con-
trol of Head Direction for the Steering of Locomotion.” NeuroReport, 7 (1996): 1170–
1174.
Grasso, R., P. Prévost, Y. Ivanenko, and A. Berthoz. “Eye-Head Coordination for the
Steering of Locomotion in Humans: An Anticipatory Synergy.” Neuroscience Letters,
253 (1998): 115–118.
Gray, C. M., P. König, A. K. Engel, and W. Singer. “Oscillatory Responses in Cat Visual
Cortex Exhibit Inter-Columnar Synchronization Which Reflects Global Stimulus Pat-
terns.” Nature, 338 (1989): 334–337.
Graziano, M., G. Yap, and C. Gross. “Coding of Visual Space by Premotor Neurons.” Sci-
ence, 266 (1994): 1054–1057.
310 •
WORKS CITED
———. “The Representation of Extrapersonal Space: A Possible Role for Bimodel-Tactile
Neurons.” In The Cognitive Neurosciences, ed. M. Gazzaniga. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press, 1994.
Grüsser, O. J. “Cortical Representation of Head Movement in Space and Some Psycho-
physical Considerations.” In The Head-Neck Sensory-Motor System, ed. A. Berthoz, P. O.
Vidal, and W. Graf. New York: Oxford University Press, 1991.
Grüsser, O. J., and T. Landis. Visual Agnosias and Related Disorders, vol. 12. Vision and Visual
Dysfunction. Basingstoke, UK: Macmillan, 1991.
Grüsser, O. J., M. Pause, and U. Schreiter. “Localisation and Responses of Neurones in the
Parieto-Insular Vestibular Cortex of Awake Monkeys (Macaca fascicularis).” Journal of
Physiology, 430 (1990): 537–557.
———. “Vestibular Neurones in the Parieto-Insular Cortex of Monkeys (Macaca
fascicularis).” Journal of Physiology, 430 (1990): 559–583.
Guitton, G., H. A. Buchtel, and R. Douglas. “Frontal Lobe Lesions in Man Cause Dif-
ficulties in Supressing Reflexive Glance and in Generating Goal-Directed Saccades.”
Experimental Brain Research, 58 (1985): 455–472.
Guldin, W. O., and O. J. Grüsser. “Single Unit Responses in the Vestibular Cortex of Squir-
rel Monkeys.” Neuroscience Abstracts, 13 (1987): 1224.
Gurfinkel, V. S. “The Mechanisms of Postural Regulation in Man.” In Physiology and General
Biology Reviews, ed. T. Turpaev. Chur, Switzerland: Harwood Academic Publishers,
1994.
Gurfinkel, V. S., E. E. Debreva, and Y. S. Levik. “The Role of the Internal Model in the Per-
ception of Position and Planning of Hand Movements.” Fiziologiia Cheloveka, 12
(1986): 769–776.
Gurfinkel, V. S., and Y. S. Levick. “Perceptual and Automatic Aspects of the Postural Body
Scheme.” In Brain and Space, vol. 12, ed. J. Paillard. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1986.
Hamann, K. F., P. P. Vidal, J. M. Sterkers, and A. Berthoz. “A New Test for Postural Disor-
ders: An Application of Visual Stabilization.” Agressologie, 20B (1979): 129–130.
Hanneton, S., A. Berthoz, J. Droulez, and J.-J. Slotine. “Does the Brain Use Sliding Vari-
ables for the Control of Movements?” Biological Cybernetics, 77 (1997): 381–393.
Haustein, W., and H. Mittelstaedt. “Evaluation of Retinal Orientation and Gaze Direction
in the Perception of the Vertical.” Vision Research, 30 (1990): 255–262.
Head, H., and G. Holmes. “Sensory Disturbances from Cerebral Lesions.” Brain, 34 (1911):
102–244.
Hécaen, H., and J. de Ajuriaguerra. Méconnaissances et hallucinations corporelles: intégration et
désintégration de la somatognosie. Paris: Masson et Cie, 1952.
Held, R., and A. Hein. “Movement-Produced Stimulation in the Development of Vi-
sually Guided Behavior.” Journal of Comparative Physiological Psychology, 56 (1963): 872–
876.
Heliodorus of Emesa. The Aethiopica, vol. 5. The Athenian Society’s Publications. Athens:
Privately printed for the Athenian Society, 1897.
Helmholtz, H. von. Treatise on Physiological Optics, trans. J. P. C. Sothall. New York: Dover,
1962.
WORKS CITED •
311
Henn, V., L. R. Young, and C. Finley. “Vestibular Nucleus Units in Alert Monkeys Are Also
Influenced by Missing Visual Field.” Brain Research, 71 (1974): 144–149.
Hertz, H. The Principles of Mechanics, trans. D. E. Jones and J. T. Walley. New York: Dover,
1956.
Hess, W. “Teleokinetisches und ereismatisches Kraftsystem in der Biomotorik.” Helvetica
Physiologica et Pharmacologica Acta, 1 (1943): C62–C63.
Hietanen, J. K., and D. Perrett. “A Role of Expectation in Visual and Tactile Processing
within the Temporal Cortex.” In Brain Mechanisms in Perception and Memory: From Neu-
ron to Behavior, ed. T. E. Ono, L. R. Squire, M. Raichle, D. L. Perrett, and M. Fukuda.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993, 83–103.
Hikosaka, O. “Role of the Basal Ganglia in Motor Learning: A Hypothesis.” In Brain Mech-
anisms in Perception and Memory: From Neuron to Behavior, ed. T. E. Ono, L. R. Squire,
M. Raichle, D. L. Perrett, and M. Fukuda. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993, 497–
513.
Hikosaka, O., M. Sakamoto, and N. Miyashita. “Effects of Caudate Nucleus Stimulation on
Substantia Nigra Cell Activity in Monkey.” Experimental Brain Research, 95 (1993): 457–
472.
Hikosaka, O., and R. H. Wurtz. “Visual and Oculomotor Functions of Monkey Substantia
Nigra Pars Reticulata. III. Memory-Contingent Visual and Saccade Responses.” Jour-
nal of Neurophysiology, 49 (1983): 1268–1284.
Hoffman, K. P. “Responses of Single Neurons in the Pretectum of Monkeys to Visual Stim-
uli in Three Dimensional Space.” In Representation of Three-Dimensional Space in the
Vestibular, Oculomotor, and Visual Systems, ed. B. Cohen and V. Henn. New York: New
York Academy of Sciences, 1988, 1–261.
Holst, E. von. “Relations between the Central Nervous System and the Peripheral Or-
gans.” Journal of Animal Behaviour, 2 (1954): 89–94.
Holst, E. von, and H. Mittelstaedt. “Das Reafferenzprinzip. Wechselwirkungen zwischen
Zentralnervensystem und Peripherie.” Naturwissenschaften, 37 (1950): 464–476.
Humphrey, D. R., and H. J. Freund, eds. Motor Control: Concepts and Issues. New York:
Wiley, 1991.
Husserl, E. Idées directrices pour une phénoménologie et une philosophie phénoménologique pure,
vol. 2, Recherches phénoménologiques pour la constitution. Paris: Presses Universitaires de
France, 1982.
Hyvarinen, J. The Parietal Cortex of Monkey and Man. Berlin: Springer, 1982.
Israël, I. “Memory-Guided Saccades: What Is Memorized?” Experimental Brain Research, 90
(1992): 221–224.
Israël, I., and A. Berthoz. “Contribution of the Otoliths to the Calculation of Linear Dis-
placement.” Journal of Neurophysiology, 62 (1989): 247–263.
Israël, I., N. Chapuis, S. Glasauer, O. Charade, and A. Berthoz. “Estimation of Passive Lin-
ear Whole Body Displacement in Humans.” Journal of Neurophysiology, 70 (1993):
1270–1273.
Israël, I., R. Grasso, P. Georges-François, T. Tzuzuku, and A. Berthoz. “Spatial Memory
and Path Integration Studied by Self-Driven Linear Displacement.” Journal of Neuro-
physiology, 77 (1999): 3180–3192.
Israël, I., S. Rivaud, A. Berthoz, and C. Pierrot-Deseilligny. “Cortical Control of Vestibular
312 •
WORKS CITED
Memory-Guided Saccades.” Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 656 (1992):
472–484.
Israël, I., S. Rivaud, B. Gaymard, A. Berthoz, and C. Pierrot-Deseilligny. “Cortical Control
of Vestibular-Guided Saccades in Man.” Brain, 118 (1995): 1169–1183.
Israël, I., S. Rivaud, C. Pierrot-Desilligny, and A. Berthoz. “Delayed VOR: An Assessment
of Vestibular Memory for Self Motion.” In Tutorials in Motor Neuroscience, ed. J.
Requin and J. Stelmach. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991, 599–607.
Ito, M. “Cerebellar Control of the Vestibulo-ocular Reflex around the Flocculus Hypothe-
sis.” Annual Review of Neuroscience, 5 (1982): 275–296.
———. The Cerebellum and Neuronal Control. New York: Raven, 1984.
Ivanenko, Y., R. Grasso, I. Israël, and A. Berthoz. “The Contribution of Otoliths and Semi-
circular Canals to the Perception of Two-Dimensional Passive Whole-Body Motion in
Humans.” Journal of Physiology, 502 (1997): 223–233.
James, William. The Principles of Psychology, vol. 2. New York: Holt, 1890.
Jami, L. “Golgi Tendon Organs in Mammalian Skeletal Muscle: Functional Properties on
Central Actions.” Physiological Reviews, 72 (1992): 623–666.
Janet, P. Les Débuts de l’intelligence. Paris: Flammarion, 1935.
Jeannerod, M. “The Posterior Parietal Cortex as a Spatial Generator.” In Brain Mechanisms
and Spatial Vision, eds. D. I. Ingle, J. Jeannerod, and D. Lee. Dordrecht: Martinus
Nijhoff, 1985, 279–298.
———. Neurophysiological and Neuropsychological Aspects of Spatial Neglect. Amsterdam:
Elsevier, 1987.
———. The Neural and Behavioral Organisation of Goal-Directed Arm Movements. Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1988.
———, ed. Attention and Performance XIII. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1990.
———. “A Neurophysiological Model for the Directional Coding of Reaching Move-
ments.” In Brain and Space, ed. J. Paillard. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991.
———. “The Representing Brain: Neural Correlates of Motor Intention and Imagery.” Be-
havioral and Brain Sciences, 17 (1994): 187–202.
Joliot, M., U. Ribary, and R. Llinás. “Human Oscillatory Brain Activity near 40 Hz Coexists
with Cognitive Temporal Binding.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 91
(1994): 11748–11751.
Jones, M. G., and K. E. Spells. “A Theoretical and Comparative Study of the Functional De-
pendance of the Semi-Circular Canal upon its Physical Dimensions.” Proceedings of the
Royal Society of London. Series B: Biological Sciences, 157 (1963): 403–419.
Joseph, J. P., and P. Barone. “Prefrontal Unit Activity during a Delayed Oculomotor Task in
the Monkey.” Experimental Brain Research, 67 (1987): 460–468.
Kalaska, J. F., R. Caminiti, and A. P. Georgopoulos. “Cortical Mechanisms Related to the
Direction of Two-Dimensional Arm Movements: Relations in Parietal Area 5 and
Comparison with Motor Cortex.” Experimental Brain Research, 51 (1983): 247–260.
Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Norman Kemp Smith. New York: St. Mar-
tin’s Press, 1961.
Karabelas, A. B., and A. K. Moschovakis. “Nigral Inhibitory Termination on Efferent Neu-
rons of the Superior Colliculus. An Intracellular Horseradish Peroxidase Study in the
Cat.” Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 239 (1985): 309–329.
WORKS CITED •
313
Karnath, H. O., K. Christ, and W. Hartje. “Decrease of Contralateral Neglect by Neck
Muscle Vibration and Spatial Orientation of Trunk Midline.” Brain, 116 (1993): 383–
396.
Kawano, K., M. Sasaki, and M. Yamashita. “Vestibular Input to Visual Tracking Neurons in
the Posterior Parietal Association Cortex of the Monkey.” Neuroscience Letters, 17
(1980): 55–60.
Kawato, M., K. Furukawa, and R. Suzuki. “A Hierarchical Neural Network Model for Con-
trol and Learning of Voluntary Movements.” Biological Cybernetiks, 57 (1987): 169–185.
Kelso, J. A. S. “Phase Transitions and Critical Behaviour in Human Bimanual Coordina-
tion.” American Journal of Physiology, 14 (1984): R1000–1004.
Kelso, J. A. S., J. D. Delcolle, and G. Schöner. “Action-Perception as a Pattern Formation
Process.” In Attention and Performance, ed. M. Jeannerod. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum,
1990, 139–169.
Kesner, R. P. “Paired Associate Learning in the Rat: Role of Hippocampus, Medial Pre-
frontal Cortex, and Parietal Cortex.” Psychobiology, 21 (1993): 183–192.
Korn, H., and D. S. Faber. “Organisation and Cellular Mechanisms Underlying Chemical
Inhibition in a Vertebrate Neuron.” In Molecular and Cellular Interactions Underlying
Higher Brain Functions. Progress in Brain Research, ed. J.-P. Changeux. Amsterdam:
North Holland, 1983.
Kosslyn, S. M., C. F. Chabris, C. J. Marsolek, R. A. Jacobs, and O. Koenig. “On Computa-
tional Evidence for Different Types of Spatial Relations Encoding: Reply to Cook et
al.” Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 21 (1995):
423–431.
Kosslyn, S. M., C. F. Chabris, C. J. Marsolek, and O. Koenig. “Categorical versus Coordi-
nate Spatial Representations: Computational Analysis and Computer Simulations.”
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 18 (1992): 562–
577.
Krechevsky, I. “Hypothesis in Rats.” Psychological Reviews, 39 (1932): 517–532.
Lackner, J. R. “Some Contributions of Touch, Pressure, and Kinesthesis to Human Spatial
Orientation and Oculomotor Control.” Acta Astronautica, 8 (1981): 825–830.
———. “Some Proprioceptive Influences on the Perceptual Representation of Body Shape
and Orientation.” Brain, 111 (1981): 281–297.
———. “Orientation and Movement in Unusual Force Environments.” Psychological Sci-
ence, 4 (1993): 134–142.
Lackner, J. R., and M. S. Levine. “Changes in Apparent Body Orientation and Sensory Lo-
calization Induced by Vibration of Postural Muscles: Vibratory Myesthetic Illusions.”
Aviation, Space, and Environmental Medicine, 50 (1979): 346–354.
Lacquaniti, F., M. Carrozzo, and N. Borghese. “The Role of Vision in Tuning Anticipatory
Motor Responses of the Limbs.” In Multisensory Control of Movement, ed. A. Berthoz.
New York: Oxford University Press, 1993, 379–390.
Lacquaniti, F., E. Guigon, L. Bianchi, S. Farraina, and R. Caminiti. “Representing Spatial In-
formation for Limb Movements: Role of Area 5 in the Monkey.” Cerebral Cortex, 5
(1995): 391–409.
Lacquaniti, F., and C. Maioli. “The Role of Preparation in Tuning Anticipatory and Reflex
Responses during Catching.” Journal of Neuroscience, 9 (1989): 134–148.
314 •
WORKS CITED
Lacquaniti, F., J. Soechting, and C. Terzuolo. “Path Constraints on Point to Point Arm
Movements in Three-Dimensional Space.” Neuroscience, 17 (1986): 313–324.
Land, M. F., and D. N. Lee. “Where We Look When We Steer.” Nature, 369 (1994): 742–
744.
Lang, W., D. Cheyne, R. Kristeva, R. Beisteiner, G. Lindinger, and L. Deecke. “Three-Di-
mensional Localization of SMA Activity Preceding Voluntary Movement. A Study of
Electric and Magnetic Fields in a Patient with Infarction of the Right Supplementary
Motor Area.” Experimental Brain Research, 87 (1991): 688–695.
Lang, W., M. Lang, F. Uhl, C. Koska, A. Kornhuber, and L. Deecke. “Negative Cortical
DC Shifts Preceding and Accompanying Simultaneous and Sequential Finger Move-
ments.” Experimental Brain Research, 71 (1988): 579–587.
Lang, W., H. Obrig, G. Lindinger, D. Cheyne, and L. Deecke. “Supplementary Motor Area
Activation While Tapping Bimanually Different Rhythms in Musicians.” Experimental
Brain Research, 79 (1990): 504–514.
Lang, W., L. Petit, P. Hölliger, U. Pietrzyck, N. Tzourio, B. Mazoyer, and A. Berthoz.
“A Positron Emission Tomography Study of Oculomotor Imagery.” NeuroReport, 5
(1994): 921–924.
Laporte, Y., F. Emonet-Dénand, and L. Jami. “The Skeletofusimotor or β Innervation of
Mammalian Muscle Spindles.” Trends in Neuroscience, 4 (1981): 97–99.
Lashley, K. S. Brain Mechanisms and Intelligence. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1929.
Lee, D. N. “A Theory of Visual Control of Braking Based on Information about Time-to-
Collision.” Perception, 5 (1976): 437–459.
Lee, D. N., and E. Aronson. “Visual Proprioceptive Control of Standing in Human In-
fants.” Perception and Psychophysics, 14 (1974): 529–532.
Lee, D. N., and J. R. Lishman. “Visual Proprioceptive Control of Stance.” Journal of Human
Movement Studies, 1 (1975): 87–95.
Lee, D. N., and P. E. Reddish. “Plummeting Gannets: A Paradigm of Ecological Optics.”
Nature, 293 (1985): 293–294.
Lee, D. N., and D. S. Young. “Visual Timing in Interceptive Actions.” In Brain Mechanisms
and Spatial Vision, ed. D. J. Ingle, M. Jeannerod, and D. N. Lee. Dordrecht: Martinus
Nijhoff, 1996, 1–30.
Lee, R. G., I. Tonolli, F. Viallet, R. Aurenty, and J. Massion. “Preparatory Postural Adjust-
ment in Parkinsonian Patients with Postural Instability.” Canadian Journal of Neurologi-
cal Sciences, 22 (1995): 126–135.
Lestienne, F., J. Soechting, and A. Berthoz. “Postural Readjustments Induced by Linear
Motion of Visual Scenes.” Experimental Brain Research, 28 (1977): 363–384.
Levin, M. F., and A. G. Feldman. “The Role of Stretch Reflex Threshold Regulation in Nor-
mal and Impaired Motor Control.” Brain Research, 657 (1994): 23–30.
Lisman, J. E., and M. A. P. Idiart. “Storage of Short-Term Memories in Oscillatory Sub-
cycles.” Science, 267 (1995): 1512–1515.
Livingstone, M., and D. Hubel. “Segregation of Form, Color, Movement, and Depth: Anat-
omy, Physiology, and Perception.” Science, 240 (1988): 740–749.
Llinás, R. “Possible Role of Tremor in the Organisation of the Nervous System.” In Move-
ment Disorders, ed. L. J. Findley, R. Capildeo, and A. Tremor. London: Macmillan,
1988, 475–477.
WORKS CITED •
315
———. “The Intrinsic Electrophysiological Properties of Mammalian Neurons: Insights
into Central Nervous System Function.” Science, 242 (1988): 1654–1664.
———. “The Noncontinuous Nature of Movement Execution.” In Motor Control: Concepts
and Issues. Chichester: Wiley, 1991, 223–242.
———. “Oscillations in CNS Neurons: A Possible Role for Cortical Interneurons in the
Generation of 40-Hz Oscillations.” In Induced Rhythms in the Brain, ed. E. Basar and T.
Bullock. Boston: Birkhauser, 1992, 269–283.
Llinás, R., and U. Ribary. “Coherent 40-Hz Oscillation Characterizes Dream State in Hu-
mans.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 90 (1993): 2078–2081.
Llinás, R., and C. Sotelo. The Cerebellum Revisited. New York: Springer, 1992.
Lobel, E., J. F. Kleine, D. Le Bihan, A. Leroy-Willig, and A. Berthoz. “Functional MRI of
Galvanic Vestibular Stimulation.” Journal of Neurophysiology, 80 (1998): 2699–2709.
Lorente de Nó, R. “Vestibulo-ocular Reflex Arc.” Archives of Neurology and Psychiatry, 30
(1933): 245–291.
Lorenz, Konrad. Behind the Mirror: A Search for a Natural History of Human Knowledge, trans.
Ronald Taylor. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1977.
Lotze, R. H. Medizinische Psychologie oder Physiologie der Seele. Leipzig: Weidemann, 1852.
Mach, E. Grundlinien der Lehre von den Bewegungsempfindungen. Amsterdam: Bonset, 1967.
MacKay, D. G. The Organization of Perception and Action. New York: Springer, 1987.
Magnin, M., M. Jeannerod, and P. T. S. Putkonen. “Vestibular and Saccadic Influences on
Dorsal and Ventral Nuclei of the Lateral Geniculate Body.” Experimental Brain Re-
search, 21 (1974): 1–18.
Malsburg, C. von der. “Nervous Structures with Dynamical Links.” Berichte der
Bunsengesellschaft für physikalische Chemie, 89 (1985): 703–710.
Marey, E. J. Le Mouvement. Paris: Masson, 1894.
———. La Machine animale. Paris: Revue EPS, 1993.
Marr, D. “Simple Memory: A Theory for Archicortex.” Proceedings of the Royal Society of
London. Series B: Biological Sciences, 262 (1971): 23–81.
Massion, J. “Postural Control System.” Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 4 (1994): 877–887.
Massion, J., V. Gurfinkel, M. Lipshits, A. Obadia, and K. Popov. “Stratégie et synergie: deux
niveaux de contrôle de l’équilibre au cours du mouvement. Effets de la microgravité.”
Comptes rendus hebdomadaires de l’Académie des sciences (Paris, Série III), 314 (1992): 87–
92.
Massion, J., and L. Rispal-Padel. “Thalamus: fonctions motrices.” Revue Neurologique, 142
(1986): 327–336.
Massion, J., F. Viallet, R. Massarino, and R. Khalil. “La région de l’aire motrice supplé-
mentaire est impliquée dans la coordination entre posture et mouvement.” Comptes
rendus hebdomadaires de l’Académie des sciences (Paris, Série III), 308 (1989): 417–423.
Mast, F., S. Kosslyn, and A. Berthoz. “Visual Mental Imagery Interferes with Allocentric
Orientation Judgements.” Neuroreport, 110 (1999): 3549–3553.
Matthews, B. L., J. H. Ryu, and C. Bockaneck. “Vestibular Contribution to Spatial Orienta-
tion.” Acta Orolaryngologica, 468 (1989): 149–154.
Mays, L. E., and D. L. Sparks. “Saccades Are Spatially, Not Retinocentrically, Coded.” Sci-
ence, 208 (1980): 1163–1165.
316 •
WORKS CITED
McCrea, R. A., K. Yoshida, C. Evinger, and A. Berthoz. “The Location, Axonal Arbori-
zation, and Termination Sites of Eye-Movement-Related Secondary Vestibular Neu-
rons Demonstrated by Intra-axonal HRP Injection in the Alert Cat.” In Progress in
Oculomotor Research, ed. A. Fuchs and W. Becker. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1981, 379–386.
McDaniel, W. F., D. M. Compton, and S. R. Smith. “Spatial Learning following Posterior
Parietal or Hippocampal Lesions.” NeuroReport, 5 (1994): 1713–1717.
McIntyre, J., E. Gurfinkel, M. Lipshits, J. Droulez, and V. Gurfinkel. “Measurement of Hu-
man Force Control during Constrained Arm Motion using a Force-Activated Joy-
stick.” Journal of Neurophysiology, 17 (1995): 1201–1222.
Melamed, E., and B. Larsen. “Cortical Activation during Saccadic Eye Movements in Hu-
mans: Localisation by Cerebral Blood Flow Increases.” Annals of Neurology, 5 (1989):
79–88.
Melvill-Jones, G., A. Berthoz, and B. Segal. “Adaptative Modification of the Vestibulo-ocu-
lar Reflex by Mental Effort in Darkness.” Experimental Brain Research, 56 (1984): 149–
153.
Melvill-Jones, G., D. Guitton, and A. Berthoz. “Changing Patterns of Eye-Head Coordina-
tion during Six Hours of Optically Reversed Vision.” Experimental Brain Research, 69
(1988): 531–544.
Merleau-Ponty, M. Le Visible et l’Invisible. Paris: Gallimard, 1964.
———. The Visible and the Invisible, ed. Claude Lefort, trans. Alphonso Lingis. Northwest-
ern University Studies in Phenomenology and Existential Philosophy. Evanston, Ill.:
Northwestern University Press, 1968.
———. Résumés de cours au Collège de France. Paris: Gallimard, 1968.
———. The Essential Writings of Merleau-Ponty, ed. Alden L. Fisher. New York: Harcourt,
Brace, and World, 1969.
———. La Nature: notes-cours du Collège de France. Paris: Le Seuil, 1995.
Mesulam, M. M. “A Cortical Network for Directed Attention and Unilateral Neglect.” An-
nals of Neurology, 10 (1981): 309–325.
Metcalfe, T., and M. Gresty. “Self-controlled Reorienting Movements in Response to Rota-
tional Displacements in Normal Subjects and Patients with Labyrinthine Diseases.” In
Sensing Motion, ed. D. L. Tomko, B. Cohen, and F. E. Guedry. New York: Annals of
the New York Academy of Sciences, 1992.
Michotte, A. Causalité, permanence et réalité phénoménales. Paris: Béatrice-Nauwelaerts,
1962.M
Miles, F. A., and S. G. Lisberger. “Plasticity in the Vestibulo-ocular Reflex: A New Hypothe-
sis.” Annual Review of Neuroscience, 4 (1981): 273–299.
Miles, R., K. Toth, A. Gulyas, N. Hajos, and T. F. Freund. “Differences between Somatic
and Dendritic Inhibition in the Hippocampus.” Neuron, 16 (1996): 814–823.
Miller, S., M. Potegal, and L. Abraham. “Vestibular Involvement in a Passive Transport and
Return Task.” Physiological Psychology, 11 (1982): 1–10.
Milner, B. “Visual Recognition and Recall after Right Temporal Lobe Excision in Man.”
Neuropsychologia, 6 (1968): 191–209.
Mishkin, M. “A Memory System in the Monkey.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Soci-
ety. Series B: Biological Sciences, 98 (1982): 85–95.
WORKS CITED •
317
Mistlin, A. J., and D. I. Perrett. “Visual and Somatosensory Processing in the Macaque
Temporal Cortex: The Role of ‘Expectation.’” Experimental Brain Research, 82 (1990):
437–450.
Mittelstaedt, H. “The Role of Otoliths in the Perception of the Orientation of Self and
World to the Vertical.” Zoologische Jahrbücher der Physiologie, 95 (1991): 419–425.
———. “Evidence of Somatic Graviception from New and Classical Investigations.” Acta
Otolaryngologica, 115 (suppl. 520) (1995): 186–187.
———. “Somatic Graviception.” Biological Psychology, 42 (1996): 53–74.
Mittelstaedt, H., and S. Glasauer. “Illusions of Verticality in Weightlessness.” Clinical Inves-
tigations, 71 (1993): 732–739.
Mittelstaedt, H., and M. L. Mittelstaedt. “Mechanismen der Orientierung ohne richtende
Aussensreise.” Fortschritte der Zoologie, 21 (1973): 46–58.
———. “Homing by Path Integration in a Mammal.” Naturwissenschaften, 67 (1992): 566–
567.
Mogensen, J., T. K. Pedersen, S. Holm, and L. E. Bang. “Prefrontal Cortical Mediation of
Rats’ Place Learning in a Modified Water Maze.” Brain Research Bulletin, 38 (1995):
425–434.
Moschovakis, A. B., A. B. Karabelas, and S. Highstein. “Structure Function Relationship in
the Primate Superior Colliculus. I. Morphological Classification of Efferent Neu-
rons.” Journal of Neurophysiology, 60 (1988): 232–262.
———. “Structure Function Relationship in the Primate Superior Colliculus. II. Morpho-
logical Identity of Presaccadic Neurons.” Journal of Neurophysiology, 60 (1988): 263–
302.
Mouchnino, L., R. Aurenty, J. Massion, and A. Pedotti. “Is the Trunk a Reference Frame for
Calculating Leg Position?” NeuroReport, 4 (1993): 125–127.
Mountcastle, V. H., J. C. Lynch, A. Georgopoulos, H. Sakata, and C. Acuna. “Posterior Pa-
rietal Association Cortex of the Monkey: Command Functions for Operations within
Extrapersonal Space.” Journal of Neurophysiology, 38 (1975): 871–908.
Müller, J. “Über das Aubert’sche Phänomen.” Zeitschrift für Psychologie der Sinnesorgane, 49
(1916): 109–249.
Munoz, D. P., and R. H. Wurtz. “Fixation Cells in Monkey Superior Colliculus. I. Charac-
teristics of Cell Discharge.” Journal of Neurophysiology, 70 (1993): 559–575.
Musil, S. Y., C. R. Olson, and M. E. Goldberg. “Visual and Oculomotor Properties of Single
Neurons in Posterior Cingulate Cortex of Rhesus Monkey.” Society of Neuroscience Ab-
stracts, 16 (1990): 1221.
Muybridge, E. The Human Figure in Motion. New York: Dover, 1957.
Myashita, Y. “Where Visual Perception Meets Memory.” Annual Review of Neuroscience, 16
(1993): 245–263.
Nashner, L. M., and A. Berthoz. “Visual Contribution to Rapid Motor Responses during
Postural Control.” Brain Research, 150 (1978): 403–407.
Neisser, U. Cognition and Reality. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1976.
Nudo, R. J., G. W. Milliken, W. M. Jenkins, and M. M. Merzenich. “Use-Dependent Alter-
ations of Movement Representations in Primary Motor Cortex of Adult Squirrel
Monkeys.” Journal of Neuroscience, 16 (1996): 785–807.
318 •
WORKS CITED
O’Keefe, J., and L. Nadel. The Hippocampus as a Cognitive Map. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1978.
O’Keefe, J., and M. Recce. “Phase Relationship between Hippocampal Place Units and the
EEG Theta Rhythm.” Hippocampus, 3 (1993): 317–330.
Olivier, E., A. Grantyn, M. Chat, and A. Berthoz. “The Control of Slow Orienting Eye
Movements by Tectoreticulospinal Neurons in the Cat: Behavior, Discharge Patterns,
and Underlying Connections.” Experimental Brain Research, 93 (1993): 435–449.
O’Mara, S. M., E. Rolls, A. Berthoz, and R. P. Kesner. “Neurons Responding to Whole
Body Motion in the Primate Hippocampus.” Journal of Neuroscience, 14 (1994): 6511–
6523.
Ono, T., B. L. McNaughton, S. Molotchnidoff, E. T. Rolls, and H. Nishigo. Perception, Mem-
ory, and Emotion: Frontiers in Neuroscience. Cambridge: Pergamon, 1996.
Ono, T., L. R. Squire, M. Raichle, D. I. Perrett, and M. Fukuda, eds. Brain Mechanisms of
Perception and Memory: From Neuron to Behavior. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993.
Orban, G. A., P. Dupont, B. De Bruyn, R. Vogels, R. Vanderberghe, and L. Mortelmans. “A
Motion Area in Human Visual Cortex.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences,
92 (1995): 993–997.
Paillard, J. “Les déterminants moteurs de l’organisation spatial.” Cahiers de psychologie, 14
(1971): 261–316.
———. “The Multichanneling of Visual Cues and the Organisation of a Visually Guided
Response.” In Tutorials in Motor Behavior, ed. G. E. Stelmach and J. Requin. Amster-
dam: North Holland, 1980, 259–279.
———. “Le corps et ses langages d’espace.” In Le Corps en psychiatrie, ed. E. Jeddi. Paris:
Masson, 1982, 53–69.
———. “Posture and Locomotion: Old Problems and New Concepts. Foreword.” In Pos-
ture and Gait: Development, Adaptation, and Modulation, ed. B. Amblard, A. Berthoz,
and F. Clarac. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1988, 5–12.
———. Brain and Space. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991.
———. “L’intégration sensori-motrice et idéo-motrice.” In Traité de psychologie
expérimentale, ed. M. Richelle, J. Requin, and M. Robert. Paris: Presses Universitaires
de France, 1994, 925–961.
Park, S., and P. S. Holzman. “Association of Working Memory Deficit and Eye Tracking
Dysfunction in Schizophrenia.” Schizophrenia Research, 11 (1993): 55–61.
Paulignan, Y., M. Dufosse, M. Hugon, and J. Massion. “Acquisition of Coordination be-
tween Posture and Movement in a Bimanual Task.” Experimental Brain Research, 77
(1989): 337–348.
Pavard, B., and A. Berthoz. “Perception du mouvement et orientation spatial (Revue
bibliographique).” Le Travail humain, 2 (1976): 207–226.
———. “Linear Acceleration Modifies the Perceived Velocity of a Moving Scene.” Percep-
tion and Psychophysics, 6 (1977): 529–540.
Pavlov, I. P. Les Réflexes conditionnés. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1927.
Pedotti, A., P. Crenna, A. Deat, C. Frigo, and J. Massion. “Postural Synergies in Axial Move-
ments: Short and Long-Term Adaptation.” Experimental Brain Research, 74 (1989): 3–
10.
WORKS CITED •
319
Pellionisz, A. J. “Coordination: A Vector-Matrix Description of Transformations of Over-
complete CNS Coordinates and a Tensorial Solution using the Moore-Penrose Gener-
alized Inverse.” Journal of Theoretical Biology, 101 (1984): 353–375.
Pellionisz, A. J., and R. Llinás. “Brain Modelling by Tensor Network Theory and Com-
puter Simulation. The Cerebellum: Distributed Processor for Predictive Coordina-
tion.” Neuroscience, 4 (1979): 323–348.
———. “Tensorial Approach to the Geometry of Brain Function. Cerebellar Coordination
via a Metric Tensor.” Neuroscience, 5 (1980): 1761–1770.
———. “Space-Time Representation in the Brain. The Cerebellum as a Predictive Space-
Time Metric Tensor.” Neuroscience, 7 (1982): 2949–2970.
Penfield, W. “Vestibular Sensation and the Cerebral Cortex.” Annales d’otorhinolryngologie,
66 (1957): 691–698.
Penfield, W., and E. Boldrey. “Somatic Motor and Sensory Representation in the Cerebral
Cortex of Man as Studied by Electrical Stimulation.” Brain, 60 (1937): 389–443.
Penfield, W., and T. Rasmussen. The Cerebral Cortex of Man: A Clinical Study of Localization
of Function. New York: Macmillan, 1957.
Penfield, W., and L. Roberts. Langage et Mécanismes cérébraux. Paris: Presses Universitaires
de France, 1963.
Peper, L., R. J. Bootsma, D. R. Mestre, and F. C. Bakker. “Catching Balls: How to Get the
Hand to the Right Place at the Right Time.” Journal of Experimental Psychology (Human
Perception and Performance), 20 (1994): 591–612.
Perret, C., and A. Berthoz. “Evidence on Static and Dynamic Fusimotor Actions on the
Spindle Response to Sinusoidal Stretch during Locomotor Activity in the Cat.” Experi-
mental Brain Research, 18 (1973): 178–188.
Perrett, D. I., J. K. Hietanen, M. W. Oram, and P. J. Benson. “Organisation and Function of
Cells Responsive to Faces in the Temporal Cortex.” Philosophical Transactions of the
Royal Society. Series B: Biological Sciences, 335 (1992): 23–30.
Perrett, D., A. J. Mistlin, A. J. Chitty, P. A. J. Smith, D. D. Potter, R. Broennimann, and
M. H. Harries. “Specialised Face Processing and Hemispheric Asymmetry in Man and
Monkey: Evidence from Single Unit and Reaction Time Studies.” Behavioural Brain Re-
search, 29 (1988): 245–258.
Perrett, D. I., E. T. Rolls, and W. Caan. “Visual Neurons Responsive to Faces in the Monkey
Temporal Cortex.” Experimental Brain Research, 47 (1982): 342.
Peterson, B. W., J. Baker, and A. J. Pellionisz. “Comparison of Spatial Transformation in
Vestibulo-ocular and Vestibulo-spinal Reflexes.” Proceedings of the Symposium on the
Representation of Three-Dimensional Space in the Vestibular, Oculomotor, and Visual Sys-
tems. Bologna: Barany Society, 1988.
Petit, L., C. Orssaud, N. Tzourio, F. Crivello, A. Berthoz, and B. Mzaoyer. “Functional
Anatomy of a Prelearned Sequence of Horizontal Saccades in Man.” European Journal
of Neuroscience, 16 (1996): 3726–3741.
Petit, L., C. Orssaud, N. Tzourio, G. Salamon, B. Mazoyer, and A. Berthoz. “PET Study of
Voluntary Saccadic Eye Movements in Humans: Basal Ganglia-Thalamocortical Sys-
tem and Cingulate Cortex Involvement.” Journal of Neurophysiology, 69 (1993): 1009–
1017.
320 •
WORKS CITED
Petrides, M. “Impairments on Nonspatial Self-Ordered and Externally Ordered Working
Memory Tasks after Lesions of the Mid-dorsal Part of the Lateral Frontal Cortex in
the Monkey.” Journal of Neuroscience, 15 (1995): 359–375.
Piaget, J. “Le problème de l’intériorisation des actions en opérations réversibles.” Archives
de psychologie, 32 (1949): 242–258.
———. The Origin of Intelligence in the Child. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1953.
Pierrot-Deseilligny, C., I. Israël, A. Berthoz, S. Rivaud, and B. Gaymard. “Role of the Dif-
ferent Frontal Lobe Areas in the Control of the Horizontal Component of Memory-
Guided Saccades in Man.” Experimental Brain Research, 95 (1993): 166–171.
Poincaré, H. The Value of Science, trans. George Bruce Halsted. New York: Science Press,
1907.
———. Science and Hypothesis. New York: Dover, 1952.
Poncet, M., J. F. Pellissier, M. Sebahoun, and C. J. Masser. “A propos d’un cas
d’autotopagnosie secondaire à une lésion pariéto-occipitale de l’hémisphère majeur.”
Encéphale, 60 (1971): 110–123.
Posner, M. I., M. J. Nissen, and W. C. Ogden. “Attended and Unattended Processing
Modes: The Role of Set for Spatial Location.” In Modes of Perceiving and Processing In-
formation, ed. H. L. Pick and I. J. Saltzman. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1988, 137–157.
Pozzo, T., A. Berthoz, and L. Lefort. “Head Stabilisation during Various Locomotor Tasks
in Humans. I. Normal Subjects.” Experimental Brain Research, 82 (1990): 97–106.
Prochazka, A. “Sensorimotor Gain Control: A Basic Strategy of Motor Systems?” Progress
in Neurobiology, 33 (1989): 281–307.
Proust, Marcel. Remembrance of Things Past, trans. C. K. Scott Moncrieff and Terence
Kilmartin. London: Chatto and Windus, 1981.
Rademaker, G. G. J. Réactions labyrinthiques et équilibre. Paris: Masson, 1935.
Reuchlin, M., J. Lautrey, C. Marendaz, and T. Ohlman. Cognition: L’universel et l’individuel.
Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1989.
Ribot, T. The Psychology of the Emotions. Contemporary Science Series. London: W. Scott,
1897.
Riehle, A., and J. Requin. “Monkey Primary Motor and Premotor Cortex: Single-Cell Ac-
tivity Related to Prior Information about Direction and Extent of an Intended Move-
ment.” Journal of Neurophysiology, 61 (1989): 534–549.
Rispal-Padel, L., F. Cicirata, and C. Pons. “Cerebellar Nuclear Topography of Simple and
Synergistic Movements in the Alert Baboon (Papio papio).” Experimental Brain Re-
search, 47 (1982): 365–380.
Rizzolatti, G., and V. Galeze. “Mechanisms and Theories of Spatial Neglect.” In Handbook
of Neuropsychology, ed. F. Boller and J. Gravman. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1988, 289–313.
Rizzolatti, G., M. Gartilucci, R. M. Camarda, V. Gallex, G. Luppino, M. Matelli, and L.
Fogassi. “Neurons Related to Reaching-Grasping Arm Movements in the Rostral Part
of Area 6 (Area 6a).” Experimental Brain Research, 82 (1990): 337–350.
Rizzolatti, G., L. Riggio, and B. M. Sheliga. “Space and Selective Attention.” In Attention
and Performance XV, ed. C. Umilta and M. Moscovitch. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1994,
232–265.
Roll, J. P., J. C. Gilhodes, R. Roll, and F. Harley. “Are Proprioceptive Sensory Inputs Com-
WORKS CITED •
321
bined into a Gestalt?” In Attention and Performance XVI, ed. T. Inoue and J. T.
MacClelland. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995, 290–314.
Roll, J. P., J. C. Gilhodes, R. Roll, and J. L. Velay. “Contribution of Skeletal and Extraocular
Proprioception to Kinaesthetic Representation,” in Attention and Performance XIII, ed.
M. Jeannerod. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1990, 549–566.
Roll, J. P., R. Roll, and J.-L. Velay. “Proprioception as a Link between Body and Extra-per-
sonal Space.” In Brain and Space, ed. J. Paillard. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991,
112–132.
Rolls, E. T. “A Theory of Hippocampal Function.” Hippocampus, 6 (1996): 601–620.
Rolls, E. T., and S. M. O’Mara. “Neurophysiological and Theoretical Analysis of How the
Hippocampus Functions in Memory.” In Brain Mechanisms of Perception: From Neuron
to Behavior, ed. T. Ono. New York: Oxford University Press, 1993, 276–297.
Rolls, E. T., and A. Treves. Neural Networks and Brain Function. New York: Oxford University
Press, 1998.
Ronsard, P. de. Poems of Pierre de Ronsard, trans. and ed. Nicholas Kilmer. Berkeley: Univer-
sity of California Press, 1979.
Rousseau, J.-J. Emile; Or, on Education. New York: Basic Books, 1979.
Rubens, A. B. “Caloric Stimulation and Unilateral Visual Neglect.” Neurology, 35 (1985):
1019–1024.
Sakata, H., and M. Kusunoki. “Organization of Space Perception: Neural Representation
of Three-Dimensional Space in the Posterior Parietal Cortex.” Current Opinion in
Neurobiology, 2 (1992): 170–174.
Sakata, H., H. Shibutani, and K. Kawano. “Functional Properties of Visual Tracking Neu-
rons in Posterior Parietal Association Cortex of the Monkey.” Journal of Neuro-
physiology, 49 (1983): 1364–1380.
Sakata, H., M. Taira, A. Murata, and S. Mine, “Neural Mechanisms of Visual Guidance of
Hand Action in the Parietal Cortex of the Monkey.” Cerebral Cortex, 5 (1995): 429–438.
Salzman, C., and W. T. Newsome. “Neural Mechanisms for Forming a Perceptual Deci-
sion.” Science, 264 (1994): 231–237.
Salzmann, E. “Attention and Memory Trials during Neuronal Recording from the Primate
Pulvinar and Posterior Parietal Cortex (Area PG).” Behavioral Brain Research, 67 (1995):
241–253.
Sans, A., and E. Scarfone. “Afferent Calyces and Type I Hair Cells during Development. A
New Morphological Hypothesis.” Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 781
(1996): 1–12.
Sartre, J.-P. The Psychology of Imagination. Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press, 1978.
Sasaki, K., and H. Gemba. “Electrical Activity in the Prefrontal Cortex Specific to No-Go
Reaction of Conditioned Hand Movement with Colour Discrimination in the Mon-
key.” Experimental Brain Research, 64 (1986): 603–606.
Sauvan, S. M., and E. Peterhans. “Neural Integration of Visual Information and Direction
of Gravity in the Prestriate Cortex of the Alert Monkey.” In Multisensory Control of
Posture. New York: Plenum, 1995, 43–50.
Schlag, J., and M. Schlag-Rey. “Evidence for a Supplementary Eye Field.” Journal of Neuro-
physiology, 57 (1987): 179–200.
322 •
WORKS CITED
Schmidt, R. A. “A Schema Theory of Discrete Motor Skill Learning.” Psychological Review,
32 (1975): 225–260.
Schöner, G. “A Dynamic Theory of Coordination of Discrete Movements.” Biological Cyber-
netiks, 63 (1990): 257–270.
Sechenov, I. M. Selected Works. Leningrad: State Publishing House for Biological and Medi-
cal Literature, 1935.
Segraves, M. A. “Effects of Frontal Eye Field Stimulation upon Omnipause and Burst Neu-
rons in the Monkey Paramedian Pontine Reticular Formation.” Society of Neuroscience
Abstracts, 18 (1992): 296.10.
Segraves, M. A., and M. E. Goldberg. “Functional Properties of Corticotectal Neurons in
the Monkey’s Frontal Eye Field.” Journal of Neurophysiology, 58 (1987): 1387–1419.
Shadlen, M. N., and W. T. Newsome. “Motion Perception: Seeing and Deciding.” Proceed-
ings of the National Academy of Sciences, 93 (1996): 628–633.
Shallice, T. Symptômes et modèles en neuropsychologie. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France,
1993.
Sheliga, B. M., L. Riggio, and G. Rizzolatti. “Orienting of Attention and Eye Movements.”
Experimental Brain Research, 98 (1994): 507–522.
Shepard, R. N. “Ecological Constraints on Internal Representation: Resonant Kinematics
of Perceiving, Imagining, Thinking, and Dreaming.” Psychological Review, 91 (1984):
417–447.
Sherrington, G. S. The Integrative Action of the Nervous System. New Haven: Yale University
Press, 1906.
———. “Observations on the Sensual Role of the Proprioceptive Nerve Supply of Extrin-
sic Ocular Muscles.” Brain, 41 (1918): 332–343.
Shinoda, Y., T. Ohgaki, T. Futami, and Y. Sugiushi. “Vestibular Projections to the Spinal
Cord: The Morphology of Single Vestibulo-Spinal Axons.” Vestibulospinal Control of
Posture and Movement, ed. O. Pompeiano and J. Allum. Progress in Brain Research.
Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1988, 17–27.
Silberpfennig, J. “Contributions to the Problem of Eye Movements. III. Disturbance of Oc-
ular Movements with Pseudo-hemianopsia in Frontal Lobe Tumors.” Confinia Neuro-
logica, 4 (1941): 1–13.
Simpson, J. “The Accessory Optic Systems.” Annual Review of Neuroscience, 7 (1984): 13–14.
Simpson, J. I., and W. Graf. “The Selection of Reference Frames by Nature and Its In-
vestigators,” in Adaptative Mechanisms in Gaze Control. Facts and Theories. Review of
Oculomotricity Research, vol. 1, ed. A. Berthoz and G. Melvill-Jones. Amsterdam:
Elsevier, 3–20.
Singer, W. “Search for Coherence: A Basic Principle of Cortical Self-Organization.” Con-
cepts in Neuroscience, 1 (1990): 1–26.
Sirigu, A., J. R. Duhamel, L. Cohen, B. Pillon, B. Dubois, and Y. Abid. “The Mental Repre-
sentation of Hand Movements after Parietal Cortex Damage.” Science, 273 (1996):
1564–1568.
Sirigu, A., J. Grafman, K. Bressler, and T. Sunderland. “Multiple Representations Contrib-
ute to Body Knowledge Processing.” Brain, 114 (1991): 629–642.
Slotine, J.-J. and W. Li. Applied Nonlinear Control. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1991.
WORKS CITED •
323
Smith, B. H. “Vestibular Disturbances in Epilepsy.” Neurology, 10 (1960): 465–469.
Soechting, J. F., and A. Berthoz. “Dynamic Role of Vision in the Control of Posture in
Man.” Experimental Brain Research, 36 (1979): 551–561.
Soechting, J. F., and M. Flanders. “Sensorimotor Representations for Pointing to Targets in
Three-Dimensional Space.” Journal of Neurophysiology, 62 (1989): 582–594.
Soechting, J. F., and B. Ross. “Psychophysical Determination of Coordinate Representation
of Human Arm Orientation.” Neuroscience, 13 (1984): 595–604.
Sokolov, E. N., and O. S. Vinogradova. Neuronal Mechanisms of the Orienting Reflex.
Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1975.
Squire, L. R., and M. Zola-Morgan. “The Medial Temporal Lobe Memory System.” Science,
253 (1991): 1380–1386.
Stein, B. E., and M. A. Meredith. The Merging of the Sciences. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press,
1993.
Sully, J. Les Illusions des sens et de l’esprit. Paris: Bibliothèque scientifique internationale,
1883.
Szentagothai, J. “The Elementary Vestibulo-ocular Reflex Arc.” Journal of Neurophysiology,
13 (1950): 395–407.
Tamura, R., T. Ono, M. Fukuda, and K. Nakamura. “Recognition of Egocentric and
Allocentric Visual and Auditory Space by Neurons in the Hippocampus of Monkeys.”
Neuroscience Letters, 109 (1990): 293–298.
———. “Spatial Responsiveness of Monkey Hippocampal Neurons to Various Visual and
Auditory Stimuli.” Hippocampus, 2 (1992): 307–322.
Tanaka, K. “Inferotemporal Cortex and Object Vision.” Annual Review of Neuroscience, 19
(1996): 109–139.
Taube, J. S., R. U. Muller, and J. B. Ranck Jr. “Head-Direction Cells Recorded from the
Postsubiculum in Freely Moving Rats. I. Description and Quantitative Analysis.” Jour-
nal of Neuroscience, 10 (1990): 410–435.
———. “Head-Direction Cells Recorded from the Postsubiculum in Freely Moving Rats. II.
Effects of Environmental Manipulations.” Journal of Neuroscience, 10 (1990): 436–447.
Thier, P., and R. G. Erickson. “Responses of Visual-Tracking Neurons from Cortical Area
MST-I to Visual, Eye, and Head Motion.” European Journal of Neuroscience, 4 (1992):
539–553.
Thier, P., and O. Karnath. Parietal Lobe Contribution to Orientation in 3D Space. Berlin:
Springer, 1997.
Thomas, A. Equilibre et équilibration. Paris: Masson, 1940.
Treves, A., and E. T. Rolls. “Computational Constraints Suggest the Need for Two Distinct
Input Systems to the Hippocampal CA3 Network.” Hippocampus, 2 (1991): 189–199.
———. “What Determines the Capacity of Autoassociative Memories in the Brain?” Net-
work, 2 (1991): 371–397.
Trotter, Y., S. Celebrini, B. Stricane, S. Thorpe, and M. Imbert. “Neural Processing of
Stereopsis as a Function of Viewing Distance in Primate Visual Cortical Area V1.”
Journal of Neurophysiology 76 (1996): 2872–2875.
Trullier, O., S. Wiener, A. Berthoz, and J. A. Meyer. “Biologically Based Artificial Naviga-
tion Systems: Reviews and Prospects.” Progress in Neurobiology, 51 (1997): 483–544.
Tuohimaa, P., E. Aantaa, K. Toukoniitty, and P. Mäkelä. “Studies of Vestibular Cortical
324 •
WORKS CITED
Areas with Short Living Oxygen 15 Isotopes.” Otorhinolaryngologica, 45 (1983): 315–
321.
Turvey, M. T., and P. N. Kugler. “An Ecological Approach to Perception and Action.” In Hu-
man Motor Actions. Bernstein Reassessed, ed. H. T. A. Whiting. Amsterdam: Elsevier,
1984.
Uhl, F., P. Franzen, G. Lindinger, W. Lang, and L. Deecke. “On the Functionality of the Vi-
sually Deprived Occipital Cortex in Early Blind Persons.” Neuropsychologia, 33 (1994):
256–259.
Umilta, C., C. Mucignat, L. Riggio, C. Barbieri, and G. Rizzolatti. “Programming Shifts of
Spatial Attention.” European Journal of Cognitive Psychology, 6 (1994): 23–41.
Ungerleider, L. G. “Functional Brain Imaging Studies of Cortical Mechanisms for Mem-
ory.” Science, 270 (1995): 769–665.
Vallar, G., E. Lobel, G. Galati, A. Berthoz, L. Pizzamiglio, and D. Le Bihan. “A Fronto-Pari-
etal System for Computing the Egocentric Spatial Frame of Reference in Humans.”
Experimental Brain Research, 124 (1999): 281–286.
Vallar, G., M. L. Rusconi, S. Barozzi, B. Bernardini, D. Ovadia, C. Papagno, and A.
Cesarani. “Improvement of Left Visuo-Spatial Hemineglect by Left-Sided Trans-
cutaneous Electrical Stimulation.” Neuropsychologia, 33 (1994): 73–82.
Vallar, G., R. Sterzi, G. Bottini, S. Cappa, and M. L. Rusconi. “Temporary Remission of
Left Hemianesthesia after Vestibular Stimulation. A Sensory Neglect Phenomenon.”
Cortex, 26 (1990): 123–131.
Viallet, F., J. Massion, R. Massarino, and R. Khalil. “Coordination between Posture and
Movement in Parkinsonism and SMA Lesion.” In From Neuron to Action, ed. L.
Deecke, J. C. Eccles, and V. B. Mountcastle. Berlin: Springer, 1990, 65–70.
Viaud-Delmon, I., and A. Berthoz. No title. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, in press.
Viaud-Delmon, I., Y. P. Ivanenko, A. Berthoz, and R. Jouvent. “Sex, Lies, and Virtual Real-
ity.” Nature, 1 (1998): 15–16.
———. “Anxiety and Integration of Visual Vestibular Information Studied with Virtual Re-
ality.” Biological Psychiatry, in press.
Vitte, E., C. Derosier, Y. Caritu, A. Berthoz, D. Hasboun, and D. Soulié. “Activation of the
Hippocampal Formation by Vestibular Stimulation: A Functional Magnetic Reso-
nance Study.” Experimental Brain Research, 112 (1996): 523–526.
Vitte, E., A. Sémont, and A. Berthoz. “Repeated Optokinetic Stimulation in Conditions of
Active Standing Facilitates the Recovery from Vestibular Deficits.” Experimental Brain
Research, 102 (1994): 141–148.
Viviani, P. “Motor-Perceptual Interactions: The Evolution of an Idea.” In Cognitive Science
in Europe, ed. M. Imbert, P. Bertelson, R. Kempson, D. Osherson, H. Schnelle, N.
Streitz, A. Thomassen, and P. Viviani. Heidelberg: Springer, 1987, 11–39.
Viviani, P., G. Baud-Bovy, and M. Redolfi. “Perceiving and Tracking Kinaesthetic Stimuli:
Further Evidence of Motor-Perceptual Interactions.” Journal of Experimental Psychol-
ogy, 23 (1997): 1232–1252.
Viviani, P., and A. Berthoz. “Voluntary Deceleration and Perceptual Activity during
Oblique Saccades.” In Control of Gaze by Brain Stem Neurons, ed. R. Baker and A.
Berthoz. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1977, 23–28.
Viviani, P., and T. Flash. “Minimum-Jerk, Two-Thirds Power Law, and Isochrony. Con-
WORKS CITED •
325
verging Approaches to Movement Planning.” Journal of Experimental Psychology (Hu-
man Perception), 21 (1995): 32–53.
Viviani, P., and R. Schneider. “A Developmental Study of the Relation between Geometry
and Kinematics of Drawing Movements.” Journal of Experimental Psychology (Human
Perception), 17 (1991): 198–218.
Viviani, P., and N. Stucchi. “Biological Movements Look Uniform: Evidence for Motor-Per-
ceptual Interactions.” Journal of Experimental Psychology (Human Perception), 18 (1992):
603–623.
Viviani, P., and C. Terzuolo. “Trajectory Determines Movement Dynamics.” Neuroscience,
72 (1982): 431–437.
von Uexküll, J. Streifzüge durch die Umwelten von Tieren und Menschen. Berlin: Springer, 1965.
———. Umwelt und Innenwelt der Tieren und Menschen. Berlin: Springer, 1934.
Walton, K. D., D. Lieberman, A. Llinás, M. Begin, and R. Llinás. “Identification of a Criti-
cal Period for Motor Development in Neonatal Rats.” Neuroscience, 51 (1992), 763–
767.
Wexler, M., S. Kosslyn, and A. Berthoz. “Motor Processes in Mental Rotation.” Cognition,
68 (1998): 77–94.
Wiener, S. I., V. A. Korshunov, R. Garcia, and A. Berthoz. “Inertial, Substratal, and Land-
mark Cue Control of Hippocampal CA1 Place Cell Activity.” European Journal of Neu-
roscience, 7 (1995): 2206–2219.
Wiener, S. I., C. A. Paul, and H. Eichenbaum. “Spatial and Behavioral Correlates of
Hippocampal Neuronal Activity.” Journal of Neuroscience, 9 (1989): 2737–2763.
Wurtz, R. E., C. Duffy, and J. P. Roy. “Motion Processing for Guiding Self-Motion.” In Brain
Mechanisms of Perception and Memory, ed. T. Ono, L. R. Squire, M. Raichle, D. I.
Perrett, and M. Fukuda. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993.
Wurtz, R. E., and M. E. Goldberg. “Activity of Superior Colliculus in Behaving Monkey. III.
Cells Discharging before Eye Movements.” Journal of Neurophysiology, 35 (1972): 575–
586.
Yasui, S., and L. R. Young. “Perceived Visual Motion as Effective Stimulus to Pursuit Eye
Movement System.” Science, 190 (1975): 906–908.
Yoshida, K., R. A. McCrea, A. Berthoz, and P. P. Vidal. “Interneurones inhibiteur de la
saccade oculaire horizontale étudiée chez le chat éveillé à l’aide d’injections intra-
axonique de peroxydase.” Comptes rendus hebdomadaires de l’Académie des sciences (Paris,
Série III), 290, D53 (1980): 636–638.
Yoshida, K., A. Berthoz, P. P. Vidal, and R. A. McCrea. “Eye Movement Related Activity of
Identified Second-Order Vestibular Neurons in the Cat.” In Progress in Oculomotor Re-
search, ed. A. Fuchs and W. Becker. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1981, 371–378.
Yoshida, K., R. A. McCrea, A. Berthoz, and P. P. Vidal. “Properties of Immediate Premotor
Inhibitory Burst Neurons Controlling Horizontal Rapid Eye Movements in the Cat.”
In Progress in Oculomotor Research, ed. A. Fuchs and W. Becker. Amsterdam: Elsevier,
1981, 71–81.
Young, L., M. Shelhamer, and S. Modestino. “M.I.T./Canadian Vestibular Experiments in
Weightlessness.” Experimental Brain Research, 64 (1986): 299–307.
326 •
WORKS CITED
CREDITS
Figure 1.2. Redrawn from N. A. Bernstein, “Some Emergent Problems of the Regulation of
Motor Acts,” Questions of Psychology 6 (1957).
Figure 1.3. Redrawn from R. Llinás and U. Ribary, “Coherent 40-Hz Oscillation Character-
izes Dream State in Humans.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA 90
(1993): 2078–2081; Fig. 4, p. 2080. Copyright © 1993 National Academy of Sciences,
U.S.A.
Figure 1.4. Redrawn from R. A. Schmidt, “A Schema Theory of Discrete Motor Skill
Learning.” Psychological Review, 32 (1975): 236. Copyright © 1975 by the American Psy-
chological Association. Adapted with permission.
Figure 3.1. Redrawn from M. Livingstone and D. Hubel, “Segregation of Form, Color,
Movement, and Depth: Anatomy, Physiology, and Perception.” Science, 240 (1988): 742.
Copyright © 1988 American Association for the Advancement of Science. Reprinted with
permission.
Figure 3.6. Redrawn from A. Grantyn, “How Visual Inputs to the Ponto-Bulbar Reticular
Formation Are Used in the Synthesis of Premotor Signals during Orienting.” In Progress
in Brain Research, vol. 80, ed. J. H. J. Allum and M. Hulliger. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1989,
159–170. Reprinted with the permission of the author and Elsevier Science.
Figure 3.7. Adapted from a figure in M. Graziano and C. Gross. Experimental Brain Research
97: 100. Copyright © Springer-Verlag, 1993. Reprinted with the permission of the author
and Springer-Verlag.
Figure 4.2. Redrawn from M. Graziano and C. Gross, “Multiple Pathways for Processing
Visual Space.” In T. Inui and J. L. McClelland (eds.), Attention and Performance XVI. Cam-
bridge, Mass.: MIT Press, p. 199. Reprinted with the permission of the authors and MIT
Press.
Figure 4.3. Redrawn from M. A. Arbib, “Perceptual Structures and Distributed Motor Con-
trol.” In Handbook of Physiology, sec. 1, The Nervous System, vol. 2, pt. 2, ed. V. B. Brooks.
Bethesda: American Physiological Society, 1981, p. 1468. Reprinted with permission of
the American Physiological Society.
Figure 5.1. Redrawn from L. R. Squire and M. Zola-Morgan, “The Medial Temporal Lobe
Memory System.” Science 253 (1991): 1381. Copyright © 1991 American Associaion for
the Advancement of Science. Reprinted with permission.
Figure 5.3. Redrawn from S. R. Cajal, Histologie du système nerveux de l’homme et des vertébrés.
Madrid: Raycar, 1972 [Paris, 1911].
Figure 5.4. Redrawn from E. T. Rolls, “A Theory of Hippocampal Function.” Hippocampus, 6
(1996): 601–620. Copyright © 1996. Reprinted by permission of Wiley-Liss, Inc., a subsid-
iary of John Wiley & Sons, Inc.
Figure 6.3. Redrawn from P. Viviani and T. Flash, “Minimum-Jerk, Two-Thirds Power Law,
and Isochrony. Converging Approaches to Movement Planning.” Journal of Experimental
Psychology (Human Perception), 21 (1995): 40. Copyright © 1995 by the American Psycho-
logical Association. Adapted with permission.
Figures 7.1 and 7.2. Redrawn from W. Graf and R. Baker, “Adaptive Changes of the
Vestibulo-Ocular Reflex in Flatfish Are Achieved by Reorganization of Central Nervous
Pathways.” Science, 221 (1983): 777–778. Copyright © 1983 American Association for the
Advancement of Science. Reprinted with permission.
Figure 7.3. Redrawn from T. Fukuda, Statokinetic Reflexes in Equilibrium and Movement. To-
kyo: Igaku-Shoin, 1981. Copyright © 1981 Igaku-Shoin. Adapted with permission.
Figures 10.2 and 10.3. Redrawn from O. Hikosaka, Figs. 30.5 and 30.9 in “Role of the Basal
Ganglia in Motor Learning.” In Brain Mechanisms and Memory: Cells, Systems, and Circuits,
ed. J. L. Gough, N. M. Weinberger, and G. Lynch. New York: Oxford University Press,
1992. Copyright © 1992 by Oxford University Press, Inc. Used with permission of Oxford
University Press, Inc.
Figure 11.1. From F. Lestienne, J. Soechting, and A. Berthoz, “Postural Readjustments In-
duced by Linear Motion of Visual Scenes.” Experimental Brain Research, 28 (1977): 363–
384. Copyright © 1977 Springer-Verlag. Reprinted with permission.
Figure 11.2. Redrawn from J. Massion, “Postural Control System.” Current Opinion in Neuro-
biology, 4 (1994): 877–887; Fig. 1, p. 878. Copyright © 1994 Elsevier Science. Reprinted
with permission.
Figure 11.3. Redrawn from C. Darwin, The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals.
New York: Philosophical Library, 1955.
Figure 13.1. Redrawn from LPPA and NASA documents.
328 •
CREDITS
INDEX
INDEX •
329
Brain (continued) Composite variables, principle of, 138
229–32; versus mind, 1–2; modulation of Conditioned reflexes, 11
sensory information by, 29, 35–36; predic- Consecutive optokinetic nystagmus, 55–56
tive power of, 57; processing of informa- Constructivism, 11
tion from sensory receptors, 5–6, 263; pro- Continuity, in perception, 92–93
cessing of movement by, 22, 23; as a Contralateral colliculus, 79
tensor, 48–49; use of memory by, 6 Coordination, of movements, 141
Brain imaging, 231–232 Cordo, P., 223
Braking (collision prevention), 168–172 Coriolis accelerations, 251
Brandt, T., 52 Coriolis forces, 6, 119
Broom experiment, 223 Cornilleau-Pérès, V., 92
Bruyère, A., 256, 259 Corollary discharge, theory of, 183
Cortical vision, 50
Capture: calculations to perform, 22–23; per- Cutaneous (skin) receptors, 26, 27, 29–31, 83–
ceptions in, 165–166; and tracking of tar- 86, 105–106. See also Touch
gets, 62–64 Cybernetic paradigm, 139, 174, 183
Caricature, 132 Cyon, E., 36
Catching a ball, 170–171, 172–173
Cemetery illusion, 247–248 Damasio, A. R., 7
Centralist theory, 31, 263 Dargassies, Saint Anne, 186
Cerebellum: and body schema, 229–230; de- Darlot, C., 91–92
velopment of, 212; function of, 64, 65, 164, Darwin, Charles, 32, 118, 139, 188, 232
201–203, 225, 265; inhibitions in, 193–194; Dead reckoning, 118, 120, 124
multisensory convergences in, 59, 82 De Ajuriaguerra, J., 83, 186
Cerebral imagery, 175 De animalium motu (Aristotle), 139
Chakyar community (Kerala), 189 Decision making, 7, 13, 95
Chance, 255 Deecke, L., 208
Châtelet, G., 2 Degrees of freedom, control of number of,
Children: development of movements in, 141–147, 142, 154
179, 214; teaching speed sports to visually Déjerine, J., 217
impaired, 51 Descartes, René, 3, 11
Chronography, 140 Dichgans, J., 52, 67
Churchland, P., 48 Directional sensitivity, 32–33
Cingulate cortex, 209–210 Displacement, 67, 92; of attention, 192, 211;
Cognition, 1–2; and language, 4 and balance, 225; memory of, 120–122,
Cognitive sciences, multidisciplinary nature 125. See also Acceleration; Velocity
of, 11 Distance perception, 76–77
Coherence: and autism, 93–96, 189, 264; Donders, F. C., 150
definition of, 56, 57–59, 94–95, 264; be- Dorsal motor nucleus, 65
tween seeing and hearing, 77–89; and spa- Dorsal terminal nucleus (DTN), 64
tial neglect, 74–76; and unity of percep- Dorsolateral pontine nucleus (DLPN), 63
tion, 90–93, 114. See also Perception Dorsolateral thalamus, 74
Collateral axon branches, 156–157 Dorsomedial pontine nucleus (DMPN), 63
Colliculus. See Contralateral colliculus; Infe- Dove prisms, 235, 236
rior colliculus; Superior colliculus Droulez, J., 91–92, 213
Collision prevention (braking), 168–172 Duchenne de Boulogne, 217
Comparator, 13–16, 14, 19 Dynamic illusions, 244–246
Compensation, 239–241 Dynamic memory, 212–214
330 •
INDEX
Dynamic systems theory, 179–180 Flatfish, 158–160
Dynamic vision, testing of, 51 Flavor. See Taste
Flocculus, 235–236, 251
Eccles, J. C., 46, 193 Flourens, P., 32
Efferent copy, principle of, 69 “Focus of expansion,” 60
Effort, sense of, 31–32, 88 Force, perception of, 30, 31–32
Egocentric frames of reference, 97, 99–100, Force feedback, 88–89
101, 113, 129, 241 Fovea, 62, 79, 148–149, 151, 156, 185
Einstein, Albert, 33, 38 Frames of reference: definition of, 97; selec-
Emotion: and gaze, 188–189; and movement, tion of, 109–114, 241; types of, 99–109,
7–8; and perception, 265–266; and posture, 110–114
139, 188, 232 Frequential filtering, 41
Empedocles, 135, 182 Frith, Uta, 94–95, 189
Encoding, definition of, 20–21 Frontal eye field (FEF), 62, 207–208
Endolymph, 33, 34, 38 Frontal oculomotor field (FOF), 63
Entorhinal cortex, 127 Fukuda, T., 43
Environmental frame of reference, 97 Functional flexibility, 162–163, 221, 263
Epilepsy, and visual illusions, 70 Functionalism, 4–5
Episodic memory, 6
Equilibrium point model, 16, 112–114, 223 γ motor neurons, 28–29, 32, 233
Ereismatic posture, 223 γ oscillation, 133
Eshkol, N., 97 Gannets, plummeting of, 170
Euclidean geometry, of vision, 36–37, 60 Gaze: absent, 189; anticipatory displacement
Evarts, E. V., 160 of, 148; and capture, 165–166; development
“Evil eye,” 186–187 of, 183–185; direction of, 68–69, 70, 81,
Ewert, J. P., 167 101; and emotion, 188–189; neural basis of,
Excitatory burst neuron (EBN), 197; horizon- 190–191; stabilization of, 155–157, 184, 195
tal (EBNH), 197; vertical (EBNV), 197 Gaze orientation, 6, 181–185
Exocentric (allocentric) frames of reference, Gaze reciprocity, 186
99–100, 128, 129, 241 Gaze stability, 44–46, 45
Explicit frames of reference, 112–114 Gender differences, in adaptation to visuo-
Extramission, theory of, 182 vestibular conflict, 221, 237
Extrapersonal space, 98–99, 170 Geocentric frame of reference, 101
Eye, development of, 147–151. See also Gaze; Geometry: internalization of, 176; of mus-
Sight cles, 145; of skeleton, 143–144; of space,
Eye muscles: development of, 149; geometry 100–101; of vision, 36–38, 48–49, 60, 65,
of, 72 71, 72
Eye-to-eye contact, 185–188 Gestalt theory, 11
Gestures, graceful, 172
Face recognition, 73, 109–110 Gibson, J. J., 11, 43, 52, 58, 59, 60, 125, 132,
Facial expressions, 188 177, 185, 254
Feedforward, 183 Globus pallidus externus (GPe), 201
Feelings. See Emotion Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von, 4
Feldman, A. G., 112–113 Golgi (basket) neurons, 193
Ferrier, D., 58, 104, 207 Golgi tendon organs, 26, 31–32
Fessard, A., 11 Gonshor, A., 235
“Filling in” capacity, 132, 134 Gravito-inertial differentiation, problem of,
Flash, T., 113, 147, 152 41–42, 101
INDEX •
331
Gravito-inertial receptor system, 33 Imagined movement, 211–212
Gravity: detection of, 38, 41; as frame of ref- Immobility, sense of, 41
erence, 100–102; illusions caused by, 244– Implicit frames of reference, 112–114
248; internalization of, 173–174; and pre- Inertia, overcoming, 3, 32, 33
diction of movement, 172; receptors in Inertial cues, 32, 33
stomach, 104–105; role in perception, 73 Inertial navigation, 119–120
Graziano, M., 109 Inferior colliculus, 78, 80
Grillner, S., 162 Inferior olive, dorsal motor nucleus of, 65
Gropius, W., 257 Inferior temporal (IT) area, 130
Gross, C., 85–86, 109, 231 Inhibition, of sensations, 87–88, 192–194
Grüsser, O. J., 72, 98 Inhibitory second-order vestibular neurons,
Gurfinkel, V. S., 22, 105, 107, 219, 224, 228, 193
229 Inner ear receptors. See Vestibular (inner ear)
receptors
Hallucinations, 253–254, 264 Interactive frame of reference, 97
Hartline, H. K., 35 Interneurons, 197
Haussmann, Baron G. E., 258 Inverse problem, 177–179
Head: restriction of, 143–144; stabilization of, Involuntary post-contraction, 248–249
101, 102, 111–112, 143, 184; tilt of, 38–42, Ischemia, 227–228
72–73, 92 Isochrony, principle of, 31, 147, 152
Head, H., 227, 230 Ito, M., 116, 193, 236
Hearing, 25, 77–82
Hein, A., 11, 58 Jackson, J. Hughlings, 126
Held, R., 11, 58 James, William, 9–10, 10
Heliodorus of Emesa, 186–187 Janet, P., 10, 241
Helmholtz, H. von, 9, 21, 25, 33, 77, 195, 243 Jeannerod, M., 11, 22, 110, 196
Hemianesthesia, 75 Jerk: definition of, 151; detection of, 33, 34–
Hemianopia, 75 35, 46; minimalization of, 151–152, 152,
Hemispatial neglect, 74 162
Heraclitus of Ephesus, 3 Joint receptors, 26, 27, 31–32
Hertz, H., 137 Julesz stereograms, 76
Hikosaka, O., 201 Jung, C., 52
Hippocampal formation, 73, 74
Hippocampus: anatomy of, 127; function of, Kalman filters, 174–175
126–136, 190, 191, 251, 264 Kandinsky, V., 257
Holmes, G., 227 Kant, Immanuel, 5
Husserl, E., 16, 87, 132, 168 Kathakali, 188–189
Hypothesis, best possible, 243 Kawato, M., 178
Hyvarinen, J., 98 Kelso, J. A. S., 172
Kepler, J., 140
Idiotropic vector, 104–105 Kinematic analysis, 140
Illusions, 6; of agoraphobia, 253; definition Kinematics, internalization of, 176
of, 242, 243; of dissociation of the body, Kinesthesia, 5, 25, 120
70; of epilepsy, 70; and hallucinations, 253– Koenderink, J. J., 168
254, 264; of moon size, 244; and theory of Kohnstamm’s illusion, 248–249
coherence, 91; types of, 244–254; of Korn, H., 194
vection, 52–53; of velocity inversions, 53; Kornhuber, A., 208
of ventriloquism, 58; of vertigo, 69–70, Kosslyn, S. M., 110
253; of waterfalls, 55, 252 Krechevsky, I., 243
332 •
INDEX
Lackner, J. R., 106–107 Milner, B., 126
Lacquanti, F., 173 Mind, 1–2, 95
Lampreys, 36 Minimum jerk, principle of, 151–152, 152,
Language, and cognition, 4 162
Lashley, K. S., 11, 19, 243 Mirror neurons, 20–21
Lateral geniculate body (LGB), 63 Mishkin, M., 128, 231
Lateral geniculate nucleus (LGN), 61, 204 Mittelstaedt, H., 69, 104, 105, 183
Lateral inhibition, 47 Moon illusion, 244
Lee, D. N., 52, 168–169, 172, 218 Motion sickness, 241, 247, 250–252
Lisman, J. E., 133 Motoneurons (MN), 197
Listing, J. B., 150 Motor control, 16
Listing’s plane, 150 Motor equivalence, 226–227
Llinás, R., 15, 16, 17, 48, 65, 178 Motor neurons, firing threshold of, 112–113
Local coherence, 94 Motor prediction: and superior colliculus, 77
Local invariance, 73–74 Motor schema, 17–19
Localization, 37 Motor theory of perception, 9–11, 250
Locomotion, 6, 29, 162 Mountcastle, V. H., 84, 98
Locomotor memory, 124–126 Movement: α models of, 112; in architecture,
Lorente de Nó, R., 44, 47 255–260; control and command of, 3–4, 16;
Lorenz, K., 76, 155, 181, 183 illusions of, 248–250; imagined and actual,
Lotze, R. H., 9 211–212; and inverse problem, 177–179; ki-
Lyapunov equation, 138 nematic phase constraints on, 144–145,
147; pleasure of, 137–138, 255–260; seeing,
Mach, E., 21, 22, 33, 36, 52 26, 33, 50–56, 60–64; and shifting point of
MacKay, D. G., 19, 193 equilibrium, 16. See also Action; Kinesthe-
Magnocellular pathway, 42 sia; Locomotion
Magnocellular zone, 61 MST (medial superior temporal) area, 61–62,
Magnus, T., 43 63, 71
Malraux, A., 265 MT (middle temporal) area, 61–62, 63, 71
Marey, E. J., 139–140, 177 Müller effect, 103
Marr, D., 127 Multisensory convergence, 57–59
Medial terminal nucleus (MTN), 64 Muscle receptors, 26, 27–32
Medulla: and body schema, 230; inhibitions Muscles: contraction of, 27–28, 31, 112–113,
in, 193, 194; multisensory convergences in, 216; equilibrium in muscular forces, 16,
59 223; geometry of, 145; involuntary post-
Meissner corpuscles, 30, 84 contraction of, 248–249; memory in, 115–
Melvill-Jones, G., 235, 236–237 116; and proprioception, 26, 27–32
Memory: brain’s use of, 6, 44; of movement, Muybridge, E., 101, 177, 184
55–56; and prediction, 115–117, 264–265; Myotatic reflex, 27, 217
types of, 115, 196. See also Spatial memory
Mental movement, 55 Nadel, L., 128
Mental nodes, theory of, 19–20, 193 Nashner, Lewis M., 221
Mental rotation, 24, 73, 161–162, 231 Natural frames of reference: connected to
Meredith, M. A., 78, 82 limbs, 107–109; gravity, 100–102; receptors
Merleau-Ponty, M., 11, 22, 77, 83, 85, 96–87, for, 104–107; vertical subjectivity, 102–104
115, 135–136, 175 Natural movements: definition of, 154; orga-
Mesulam, M. M., 231 nization of, 140; pioneering work in, 139–
Michotte, A., 135 141; pleasure of, 137–138
Midsagittal plane, perception of, 100 Natural selection, 3
INDEX •
333
Navigation, definition of, 119, 126 tion of, 33, 38–41, 101, 122. See also
Navigational memory, 117–120 Saccule; Utricle
Neisser, U., 19
Neocerebellum, 203 Pacinian corpuscles, 30, 84, 105
Neocortex, 191 Paillard, J., 101, 117, 124
Nervous system, symbolic and computational Paired oscillations paradigm, 180
conception of, 4 Parahippocampus, function of, 100
Networks, functional flexibility of, 162–163, Parapsychic phenomena, 76
221, 263 Parietal cortex, 63, 204–206, 227, 230, 239,
Neural barbarism, 2 264–265
Neural circuits, anticipatory, 9–10, 10 Parieto-insular vestibular cortex (PIVC), 71
Neural “compass,” 73–74 Parieto-insular zone, lesions of, 70–71
Neural integrators, 46–47, 116, 199 Parvocellular layer, 42–43
Neural memory, 16 Parvocellular zone, 61
Neural “noise,” 91 Path integration, 125
Neuroethology, construction of, 139, 155 Pause (P) neurons, 199, 211
Neuromuscular spindles, 26, 27–29, 68, 233 Pavlov, I. P., 11, 12, 139, 190
Neurons: existence of, 3; recording activity Pellionisz, A. J., 48, 65
of, 68; sensitivity of, 22–23; vectorial en- Penfield, W., 69, 207
coding by population of, 161 Perception: active exploration in, 85, 86–88,
Neurophysiology, 11, 139 110, 136, 165, 167, 204, 255, 263; direc-
Neuropsychology, 139 tional selectivity of, 72; of distance, 76–77;
Neurotransmitters, inhibitions by, 194 and emotion, 265–266; motor theory of, 9–
Newsome, W. T., 62 11, 250; multisensory nature of, 57–59,
Newton, Sir Isaac, 172 102–104, 115; of self-motion, 52–56; unity
Nociceptors, 30 of, 90–93, 114. See also Coherence
Nonlinear control of robotic movement, the- Perception-action cycle. See Action-perception
ory of, 31 cycle
Nucleus of the optic track (NOT), 63, 64 Perceptual actions, 10–11, 19
Nystagmus, 34, 46 Perceptual stability. See Gaze stability
Perceptual systems, definition of, 58
Object control, model of, 178 Peripheralist theory, 31
Obscurantism, 265 Perrett, D. I., 87, 109
Ocular pursuit, 62–64, 150–151 Personal space, 98
Ocular torsion, 149 Phantom limbs, perception of, 98, 227–229
Oculomotor path, 196 Phenomenology, 132
Odor. See Smell Physiological clock (pacemaker), 15
O’Keefe, J., 128, 133 Physiology, 7
Omnipause neurons, 199 Piaget, J., 11, 194, 214
Ia inhibitory neurons, 193 Piéron, H., 11
Opposition space, 110, 111 Place cells, 74, 128
Optic flow, 60, 65; restriction of, 143 Planning functions, 95
Optic tectum, 61, 78, 166 Plato, 5, 19, 182
Optokinetic reflex, 64 Poincaré, H., 36–38, 76, 123, 125, 244
Optokinetic stimulation, 52 Point of equilibrium theory, 16, 112–114, 223
Orientation reaction (reflex), 13, 181, 190– Pontine nuclei, 63, 64
191. See also Gaze Porro, Ricardo, 256
Otoliths: description of, 26, 27, 38, 39; func- Position, sense of, 27–29
334 •
INDEX
Postsubiculum, function of, 73 Retinal ganglia, 64
Posture: in absence of gravity, 103–104, 219; Reuchlin, M., 221
and emotions, 139, 188, 232; as first expres- Ribot, T., 7
sion of movement, 137; as readiness to Righting reflexes, 106
move, 190; stabilization of, 43–44, 64, 105– Rigidity, in perception, 92, 93, 99
106. See also Balance Rizzolatti, G., 20, 200, 212
Power gripping, 160 Robotic movement, theory of nonlinear con-
Pozzo, T., 225 trol of, 31
Precision gripping, 160 Rolls, E. T., 130
Predators. See Capture Rondot, Pierre, 217
Prediction, 57; and dynamic memory, 212– Ronsard, Pierre de, 138
214; memory for, 115–117, 264–265; in oc- Rotational memory, 120–122
ular pursuit, 151; of trajectories, 132–134, Rotations: detection of, 42–43, 46–47, 176. See
151, 185. See also Anticipation; Motor pre- also Mental rotation
diction Rougeul-Buser, A., 16
Prefrontal cortex (PFC), 121, 206, 210–211, Rousié, D., 239
264 Rousseau, J.-J., 9
Prehistoric cave art, 134–136
Preperceptions, 20, 132 Saccades: cortical control of, 204–211; defini-
Prepositus hypoglossi nucleus, 46, 47 tion of, 62, 192, 194, 195–196; inhibition of,
Presynaptic inhibitory mechanisms, 30, 195, 199–203; production of, 197–199
32 Saccadic inhibition, 195, 199–203
Prochazska, A., 88 Saccule: description of, 26, 27, 38; function of,
Proprioception, description of, 26, 27–32 33, 38–41
Proust, Marcel, 91, 132 Sailors’ illusion, 252–253
Prouvé, Jean, 257 Sakata, H., 257
Purkinje, 183, 195 Sartre, J.-P., 83
Putnam, Hilary, 261 Schema, definition of, 17–18, 18, 20
Pyramidal cells, 128 Schizophrenia, 211, 264
Pyramidal cortical neurons, 31, 132–133 Schmidt, R. A., 17–18, 18, 167
Schöner, G., 172
Rademaker, G. G. J., 43, 105 Sechenov, I. M., 58, 224
Ramón y Cajal, S., 155 Second-order vestibular neurons, 68, 70, 159,
Readiness potential, 208, 223 159
Recce, M., 133 Seeing. See Sight
Receptors. See Sensory receptors Segregation, of sensory signals, 42–43
Reciprocal innervation, 193 Selfishness, 265
Re-excitation (recurring excitation loop), Self-motion, perception of, 52–56, 218
47 Semicircular canals: description of, 26, 27, 32–
Reference frames. See Frames of reference 33; function of, 33–38, 44, 66–67, 92; ge-
Reflex actions, 10, 11–13 ometry of, 33–38, 60, 65, 71, 100–101; loca-
Regularity, 255 tion of, 143
Relative frames of reference, 110–112 Semiology, qualitative vs. quantitative, 217
Renshaw neurons, 193 Senses: ambiguity of, 90–91; function of, 25;
Representation, 12, 21–22 number of, 5, 262; revision of meaning of,
Residual vision, 51 263–264. See also Hearing; Sight; Smell;
Response, 11. See also Reflex actions Taste; Touch
Retina: function of, 60, 61 Sensory conflict, 251
INDEX •
335
Sensory receptors: adaptation of, 233–234; Sully, J., 242
configurations of, 5, 37, 107–109, 108, 130; Superior colliculus (SC): description of, 78;
location of, 26, 27; processing information function of, 61, 77–81; and inhibitions,
from, 19–20 199–200; multisensory convergences in, 59,
Sensory thalamus, multisensory convergences 80–81
in, 59 Superior medial temporal sulcus, 176
Sensory thresholds, 190 Superior temporal sulcus (STS), 87
Servo systems, theory of, 47, 49, 174, 183 Supplemental eye field (SEF), 209
Set (Einstellung), 223–224 Supplementary motor area (SMA), 208–209,
Shadlen, M. N., 62 225
Shepard, R. N., 132, 175–177, 253–254 Symmetry: perception of, 73, 228–229, 240;
Sherrington, G. S., 11, 27, 47, 216, 223, 227 preference for, 93
Short-term memory, 127–128 Synergies: coordination of, 162–164; defini-
Sight, 25; and hearing, 77–82; segregation of tion of, 44, 154–155, 164
sensory signals in, 42–43; in sense of move- Synergy, principle of, 154–155, 164, 224
ment, 26, 33, 50–56, 60–64; and touch, 83– Szentagothai, J., 46
89. See also Gaze
Simulation: definition of, 22–24, 37; of mus- Tactile perception. See Touch
cle contractions, 28–29 Targets, tracking of, 62–64
Skeletal geometry, 143–144 Taste, 25
Skin. See Cutaneous (skin) receptors; Touch Tecto-reticulo-spinal neurons (TRSNs), 79,
Slotine, J.-J., 31, 138, 171 199–200
Smell, 25 Temporal encoding, theory of, 264
Sokolov, E. N., 16, 190 Temporal selection, pauses in, 199
Somatoparaphrenia, 75 Temporal “windows,” 82
Somatotopy, 208 Temporonasal direction (orientation), 64
Sound. See Hearing Tensor: brain as, 48–49; definition of, 48
Space: extrapersonal, 98–99, 170; impaired Territorialism, 265
perception of, 74–76; personal, 98 Teuber school, 11
Spatial (cognitive) maps, 128–130 Thalamo-cortical circuitry, 15–16, 17
Spatial memory: definition of, 116–117; neu- Thalamus (Th): and body schema, 230; func-
ral basis of, 73–74, 126–136; types of, 117– tion of, 73, 166–167; inhibitions in, 193
126 Thales of Miletus, 256
Spatial neglect, 74–76, 100 Thermoreceptors, 30
Spatial representation, 70 θ rhythm, 132–133
Spatial selection, 200 Thomas, André, 101, 217
Stabilized vision, 219 Tilt, of head, 38–42, 72–73, 92
Stationary locomotion, 165, 182 Time, and coherence, 90
Stein, B. E., 78, 82 Time shifts, 81–82
Steps, initiation of, 225 Time τ-to-collision, 168–169
Stimulus, neuronal model of, 190–191 Toads, 166–168
Stimulus-response paradigm, 50, 139, 180 Topographic memory, 117–118
Strategies, definition of, 154–155, 224, 263 Topokinetic (topokinesthetic) memory, 125
Subcortical vision, 50 Touch: description of, 25, 29–31; and percep-
Subjective vertical, 41, 104, 218–219 tion of space, 105–107; and sight, 83–89
Substantia nigra pars reticulata (SNpr), 200, Trajectories, prediction of, 132–134
211 Transfer functions, 217
Substitution, and adaptation, 234–238 Translational memory, 122–124
Subthalamic nucleus (STN), 201 Translations, detection of, 42–43, 176
336 •
INDEX
Turvey, M. T., 59 Vestibulospinal reflexes, 43, 229
Two-thirds power law, 140, 146–147, 150–151 Vibrational sensitivity, 84
Vibrations, drawing with, 249–250
Umwelt (environment), 175 Vision. See Gaze; Sight
Utricle: description of, 26, 27, 38, 39; function Visually impaired children, teaching speed
of, 33, 38–41 sports to, 51
Visual memory, 196
Vection, perception of, 52–56, 218 Visual receptors: as necessary for sensing
Velocity: and coherence, 90; and isochrony movement, 26, 33, 50–56
principle, 147; sense of, 27–29, 33, 66–67; Visual vertical, 103
and vection, 53 Viviani, P., 9, 11, 29, 113, 146, 147, 152,
Ventriloquism, 58 177
Vertical, as multisensory construction, 102– VLSI (Very Large-Scale Integration), 22
104 von Holst, E., 69, 183
Vertigo, 69–70, 253 von Uexküll, J., 1, 175, 255
Vertigo a stomacho laeso, 105
Vestibular memory, 196 Waiter, problem of, 174–175
Vestibular memory-contingent saccades, 120– Walton, K. D., 179
121 Waterfall illusion, 55, 252
Vestibular nuclei, 67–68 Weber, E. H., 139
Vestibular (inner ear) receptors: description Weber, W. E., 139
of, 26, 27, 32–43; discovery of, 32; func- Weiskrantz, L., 51
tions of, 43–49; and visual movement, 64– Wiener, N., 139
69 Working memory, 6, 264
Vestibular signals, ambiguity of, 33, 40, 41–42 Wurtz, R. E., 52
Vestibulo-nuchal reflex, 48–49, 65
Vestibulo-ocular reflex, 44–46, 45, 48–49, 69, Yarbus, A. L., 196
155, 159, 234; inhibition of, 193, 197, 211; Young, L., 52, 174
suppression of, 236, 237
INDEX •
337