Myth in Platos Philosophy

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 7

DOI: 10.18468/investigacaofilosofica.2019v10n1.

p07-13 Artigo

Myth in Plato’s philosophy


Luiz Maurício Bentim da Rocha Menezes1

1 Doutor em Filosofia (UFRJ). Professor de Filosofia, Ética e Política do Instituto Federal de Educação, Ciência e Tecnologia do Triângulo Mineiro
E-mail: lmbrmenezes@yahoo.com.br . Orcid: http://orcid.org/0000-0003-4925-9876

ABSTRACT: The aim of this paper is the analysis of myth in Plato’s work based on a paper of Ludwig Edels-
tein. In his work, Edelstein presents to us the reason why Plato uses myth and its function in his philosophy.
The author contributes to the development of thought on the subject and provides development for later
studies on myth in Plato. We finished with a critical conclusion about the relation of dialectics and myth.
Keywords: Plato. Myth. Edelstein. Ancient Philosophy.

This work aims to study the function that myth plays in Platonic philosophy from studies of Edels-
tein. Although dialectic is central to Plato, he is also an adept of myth and has in this an important function
for his philosophy. Myth, in general, has the power of enchantment over its listeners and the author will
question what role of myth for philosophy is, since the role of enchanting and captivating through it is
originally from poetry. Philosophers before Plato had dismissed myth as worthless, and even sophists and
thinkers of the time sought to find a hidden meaning [ὑπόνοια] behind the myth that could lead to their true
interpretation1. Investigating the motive that leads Plato to retake myth as a way of thinking philosophy is
something we intend to investigate.
Before raising his own hypotheses in this regard, Edelstein will demonstrate how later he saw Plato's
use of his myths. For Hegel, the Platonic myths are appropriate only for the childhood of humanity, when
reason is still being born, after which they become obsolete. Neo-Platonic and Neo-Kantian will present
opposing views. For the former, Plato's myths are allegorical and there is in them true philosophical meaning.
For the latter, reason has limits, and problems of the soul and the cosmos can only be discussed through
images; myths of Plato are an instrument by which transcendental feeling is awakened and regulated. As for
Romanticism, Plato was not only aware of the limits of reason, he knew that myth was the inspiration that
the philosopher shared with the poet, leading to the revelation of the truth of supra-rational of the divine
(Edelstein, 1949, p. 463-464).
Divergent to these interpretations are all those which recognize the fact that the question of the
meaning of Platonic myths is linked with the related problems between reason and imagination2 between
philosophy and poetry. What for author puts two aspects to be analyzed: philosophical and aesthetic. For
him, Platonic myth is not an entirely artificial creation, but a response against tradition to traditional Greek
mythology. With this in view, Edelstein will begin his analysis by Plato's attitude to common beliefs.
According to him, at the time of Plato, mythology was still a living power founded on the traditional
religion demonstrated mainly by Homer and Hesiod (Edelstein, 1949, p. 465)3. Plato considered such religion

1 More on the subject can be read in Tate (1929, p.143).


2 Veyne (1987, p.12), demonstrates the relevance of understanding the imagination so that the myth can be unders-
tood. He tells us in his Preface: "I do not want to say that the imagination would announce future truths and that it
should be in power, but that truths are already imaginations and that imagination has been in power forever; it, and
not reality, reason or the long work of the negative".
3 To affirm this, it will use the passage 379th of the Republic, where Plato speaks of the types [τύποι] to be used when

Investigação Filosófica ISSN 2179-6742 https://periodicos.unifap.br/index.php/investigacaofilosofica Macapá, v. 10, n. 1, p. 07-13, 2019


8 Menezes

unholy and full of errors. In this way, mythology should be completely reformulated4, which causes Plato to
determine the models [τύποι] by which such myths should be constructed. He chooses not to make myth
merely an allegorical interpretation because children are not able to distinguish what is from what is not
allegorical. Myth must be made according to results of philosophy; stories must be told to children as a
reflection of dialectical truth. In this way, mythology could be used properly in education (EDELSTEIN,
1949, page 465). A philosopher, Edelstein said, must be able to distinguish what is from an allegory, for
Plato the allegorical interpretation of myth [ὑπόνοια] is a 'rustic kind of wisdom' [ἄγροικος σοφία]5. Myth for
Plato is formed by will, it is not an antithesis of reason, that way mythos it functions as an instrument of the
logos. For Edelstein, this means that myth does not possess certainty inherent in dialectic, and can only per-
suade (Edelstein, 1949, 466). But such persuasion is not for an inferior class of ordinary men and non-
philosophers, the philosopher must also believe in myth, for philosophical inquiry needs myth (Edelstein,
1949, 466). That said, Edelstein will deny the previous three theses: myth as allegory (Neo-platonic) is false
because Plato considers it a rustic wisdom; myth with a high knowledge (Kantian) is false, for reason is
supreme in Plato, myth being subservient to it; and myth as a mystery to be revealed (Romanticists), for to
Plato, myth is myth of the philosopher (Edelstein, 1949, p 467).
Denied the above theses, Edelstein will classify myths into two groups:
I) Those who report the creation of the world and the principle of humanity.
II) Those who deal with destiny of soul before and afterlife without having to do with metaphysics,
but with ethics.
Regarding the first group, he tells us, that human reason can only understand what is always and
does not change. If one intends to speak of what changes, characteristic of the history of the world, one can
only do this through an account of a myth. Not because it is self-consistent or exact, for what it presents is
imagined probabilities rather than ascertaining facts. An investigation into the beginning of history is mytho-
logy (Edelstein, 1949, p 468)6. About what is false or true in such accounts is somewhat uncertain, for
temporal events it is only possible to have standards of an eternal nature. "If taken as a symbol of eternity,
the world is understood correctly" (Edelstein, 1949, p 468). Facts themselves will always be conjectures,
which we can never be absolutely sure of the truth, for, as Edelstein tells us, "it is inherent in the nature of
human understanding that truth and falsehood are forever closely interwoven" (Edelstein, 1949, p.469).
Only gods, Plato said, are free from falsehood [ἀψευδές], being simple and true in words and deeds [ἀψ θεὸς
ἁπλοῦν καὶ ὰληθὲς ἔν τε ἔργῳ καὶ λόγῳ]7. The philosopher must demonstrate his responsibility and judgment
by not going beyond what his knowledge can take so that historical myths serve to clarify logical difficulties.
Edelstein will attempt to explain this using Plato's premise that nothing in the world exists without its

speaking of gods [περὶ θεολογίας]. Brisson (2003, p.26) will tell us that there is a manuscript T, XI made from manus-
cript A, the Parisinus 1807, which brings the correction of θεολογίας per μυθολογίας. "In any case," Brisson will tell us,
"although the correction is not accepted, it must be admitted that in this passage theologies are synonymous
with mythologies".
4 In Euthyphro, 6a-c, Socrates says he does not think such reports about the gods are true.

5 Such passage is taken from an interpretation of the Phaedrus, 229b-230a.

6 On this we can say that until today this is done. All science about man's prehistory or its beginnings is still an "advanced

mythology." In science fiction films, such as Stanley Kubrick's "2001: A Space Odyssey", such features are well explo-
red.
7 Republic, 382e. Greek text established by John Burnet, Platonis Opera, Tomvs IV Oxford: Oxford University Press,

1902. Other citations to the 'Republic' will be abbreviated by Rep.

Investigação Filosófica ISSN 2179-6742 https://periodicos.unifap.br/index.php/investigacaofilosofica Macapá, v. 10, n. 1, p. 07-13, 2019


Myth in Plato’s philosophy 9

opposite8. For something to exist, the other must exist. In the case, the serious one has as an opposite joke.
The written dialogues were composed carefully to capture the best, most convincing logos, so myths are
compounded with infinite care, to make fable that relates most likely. Seriousness and playfulness are posed
as a peculiar ambiguity of Platonic irony. They are two indissoluble aspects of human and perhaps of the
divine (Edelstein, 1949, pp. 470-471).
Plato discusses with various thinkers of the day as the philosophers of nature and critical historians
who have excluded the myth from their investigations. The most extreme would be Democritus who pro-
poses a rational analysis of nature and Thucydides that separates history from mythology. The important
point is that Plato thinks the reason of limitations where the old rationalism, as well as the modern rationa-
lism, detects the force of reason is combined with the experience. However, Plato does not value this reason
capable of proving the principles of an interpretation of natural and historical facts. For Plato, it is the task
of reason and myth to influence where Kant's rational causality reigns supreme. The reason is able to provide
principles of nature and history, even if such principles are given through myth. Thus, while the historical
tale is a practical value, the philosophical myth is intellectual fun (EDELSTEIN, 1949, p. 472).
As for the second group, concerning soul problems, Edelstein tells us that Socrates through the
thesis of the immortality of soul could refute anyone who tried to defend an amorality or injustice. To the
author, the ethical case is different from natural and historical science, for human reason is able to account
for its task, which is to provide knowledge. Ethical myth is an addition to rational knowledge; you do not
want to replace it, but support it. Transcendence, he shows through pictures and images, follows a rigid
standard of construction: that there is life after death and life before life (EDELSTEIN, 1949, p 473). Myth
completes the argument about the immortality of the soul. In this Edelstein will make us a question a relevant
both "is not ethical myth even more superfluous than cosmological and historical since ethical knowledge is
self-sufficient" (EDELSTEIN, 1949, p 473). Plato seems to see that rewards in this or other life do not
influence right actions; one must persuade oneself to moral law regardless of its consequences. With this, he
intends that righteous not only receive all rewards that virtue brings from man to man, but also those granted
by the gods. If the philosopher believes that gods are not indifferent to the destiny of man, he will find a
valiant undertaking to be full of good joys and will gain courage. He will exert all his strength in acquiring
virtue and wisdom in life (EDELSTEIN, 1949, p.474). The ethical myth speaks of passions of man; it is
directed to the irrational part of man in order to persuade it. For both the rational and irrational must be
cared for by the philosopher, since pleasure and fear can influence intellect and therefore must be directed
(EDELSTEIN, 1949, 474)9. Gods are free from passions, unlike men. This is one of the reasons why men
need myths and gods do not.
Edelstein will then present the reason for order myths in Plato. The scientific and historical myths
appear in the last writings of Plato since work of Forms was already better developed. Timaeus and Critias
with their myths intend to give an answer to the problem of creation of the world of phenomena, of nature
and of history, explaining Form of Good as cause of all existence (Edelstein, 1949, 475). Ethical myths arise
in Gorgias, Phaedo, Phaedrus and the Republic. In Gorgias, Plato recognizes that in human soul there are powers
capable of impending decisions of reason. In Phaedo, he speaks of the conflict of the soul with his passions.

8 Cf. Phaedo, 60b.


9 Brisson (2003 , 26) seems to agree with such a position by saying that "Plato presents this emotional fusion as effect
of an enchantment, which plays in the soul the role of remedy, of a fascination or simply of persuasion, aroused by
pleasure which the communication of myth provides to lower part of soul (epithymia)".

Investigação Filosófica ISSN 2179-6742 https://periodicos.unifap.br/index.php/investigacaofilosofica Macapá, v. 10, n. 1, p. 07-13, 2019


10 Menezes

In Phaedrus and in Republic, he develops the dogma of tripartition of soul and demonstrates that reason
must govern and passions must be governed. Myth in Protagoras, for Edelstein, despite having Plato's brushs-
trokes, is a historical reproduction of Protagoras's thoughts (Edelstein, 1949, pp. 475-476).
For Edelstein, myth is formed according to reason, this causes the irrational part to agree with the
rational part. In this way, using myth does not represent an anti-rational, but a necessary form of expression
of intellect. Edelstein's central thesis is that the function of myth in Plato is a dialectical structure (Edelstein,
1949, p477), but admits that a greater detail of his thesis is needed. The classification presented by Edelstein
seems to us good, but still insufficient, since it excludes myths that appear in dialogues, but cannot be placed
in either of two classifications. For this, we see two alternatives. The first would be to say that such myths
are not myths. But this seems to complicate and not solve the issue, omitting a more careful investigation
into them. The second alternative that, at first, we agree, is to classify them as a third group. This group
would include the non-philosophical myths, those that are in mouths of poets and of many (polloi). Such
myths should not enter just polis. As an example, we can cite myth of Ring of Gyges (Rep., 359b-360b),
which, being in the mouth of Glaucon and outside classifications given by Edelstein, would be a non-philo-
sophical myth and therefore would be outside just polis.
In this respect, Edelstein does not fail to admit that his analysis of Platonic myths was not sufficiently
detailed and presents a methodology to be followed, from his studies to those who take an interest in the
subject (Edelstein, 1949, p.447). Even so, rehearse a response minimally. For him, one must analyze Plato's
attitude of how mythology affects his judgment on poetry. Plato recognizes that it is the poet's task to
compose myths, not being the task of those who are founding the city10. However, we are left with the
question: who is the poet of the Republic? Being the philosophy different from poetry, cannot be a philoso-
pher also poet. The founders of cities establish myth models to be composed by poets, not those who make
myths but these. But Plato composes myths. So, is Plato a poet and a philosopher too? Is philosophy defi-
nitely separated from poetry? It seems that in this case, the answer is no. For Edelstein, Plato writes myths
for the realization of the philosopher, which should be used in the education of the guardian of just polis.
Their philosophical myths should not be limited only to the education of the young, but to go beyond and
educate citizen in general. It does not seem to us, however, that Plato is writing his dialogues for mass, so
why would he want to persuade himself through myth? Edelstein says it is not Plato's intention to be read
by children in school, but his myths are told. If we think of a global political sphere, perhaps we could accept
such an argument, after all, the myths were mostly sung by poets or reproduced by rhapsodies. But if we
take into account that Plato chose to write myths in his dialogues, not only reporting them and that at the
time when he wrote only Greek elite could read, it does not seem to him that he could be writing for mass,
which makes such an argument seem odd. For us, a myth written by Plato in his dialogues did not aim at
the masses as its main receiver, but rather those who are able to read it. Perhaps, in an alternative to Edels-
tein's suggestion, we may think that Plato was concerned to educate his readers to philosophy, and once
they were persuaded of its benefits, (re) produced their myths to the masses in an attempt to persuade them
good.
In Book II of Republic, in determining the terms of education, Socrates will come to the conclusion
that the best paideia is gymnastics for the body and music for the soul (Rep., 376e). Beginning with music, we

10Cf. Rep., 378e7-379a4. Ὦ Ἀδειμαντε, οὐκ ἐσμὲν ποιηταὶ ἐγώ τε καὶ σὺ ἐν τῷ παρόντι, ἀλλ’ οἰκισταὶ πόλεως∙ οἰκισταῖς
δὲ τοὺς μὲν τύπους προσήκει εἰδέναι ἐν οἶς δεῖ μυθολογεῖν τοῦς ποιητάς, παρ’ οὓς ἐὰν ποιῶσιν οὐκ ἐπιτρεπτέον, οὐ μὴν
αὐτοῖς γε ποιητέον μύθους.

Investigação Filosófica ISSN 2179-6742 https://periodicos.unifap.br/index.php/investigacaofilosofica Macapá, v. 10, n. 1, p. 07-13, 2019


Myth in Plato’s philosophy 11

will find that there are two kinds of logos: one true and one false. Both will be taught, but first logos. These
are nothing more than myths that will be taught to children (Rep., 377a). The counted myths are thus the
first education that children receive, and will be defined by Socrates in the following way:

τοῦτο δέ που ὡς τὸ ὅλον εἰπεῖν ψεῦδος, ἔνι δὲ καὶ ἀληθῆ. πρότερον δὲ μύθοις πρὸς τὰ παιδία ἢ γυμνασίοις
χρώμεθα.
in the whole, these are false, although they contain some truth. And we use myths for children before
we send them to gyms. (Rep., 377a)

We understand here that myth is not enunciation of false properly because falsehood itself and truth
are part of its structure and in itself are confused. In this, the myth has its own significant world, where such
classifications are not found, and it seems to be part of a third kind of logos, being neither true nor false. That
is, in its function, myth is not opposed to logos. That said, Socrates will continue:

Ουκοῦν οἶσθ’ ὅτι ἀρχὴ παντὸς ἔργου μέγιστον, ἄλλως τε καὶ νέῳ καὶ ἁπαλῷ ὁτῳοῦν; μάλιστα γὰρ δὴ τότε
πλάττεται καὶ ἐνδύεται τύπος ὃν ἄν τις βούληται ἐνσημήνασθαι ἑκάστῳ.
Now, do you know that in any enterprise, the most laborious is the beginning, especially for those who
are young and tender? For it is in this phase that one is molded, and buries the matrix that someone
wants to print on a person. (Rep., 377a-b)

We can see that greatest argon is principle [ἀρχή], which is linked to myths that are told to younger,
and it is according to these myths that apply the molds [τύποι] of the speech to the soul [ψυχή] of children.
If myths are good, then they will have good opinions [δόξαι], otherwise, they will be wrong (Rep., 377b).
Therefore, one should guard against authors of myths [μυθοποιοί] and select beautiful myths, refusing bad
ones (Rep., 377b-c).

τοὺς δ’ ἐγκριθέντας πείσομεν τὰς τροφούς τε καὶ μητέρας λέγειν τοῖς παισὶν καὶ πλάττειν τὰς ψυχὰς αὐτῶν
τοῖς μύθοις πολὺ μᾶλλον ἢ τὰ σώματα ταῖς χερσίν.
Those who are chosen will persuade mothers and mothers to tell them to children, and to shape their
souls through myths, much more carefully than bodies with their hands. (Rep., 377c)

Who is new is still deprived of reasoning [ἄφρων] (Rep. , 378a) is not able to distinguish what is
allegorical from what is not [ὁ γὰρ νέος οὐχ οἷός τε κρίνειν ὅτι τε ὑπόνοια καὶ ὁ μή] (Rep., 378d),but the
opinion [δόξα] you have learned in this age often indelible and unalterable [δυσέκνιπτά τε καὶ ἀμετάστατα] (
Rep. , 378e ) . Therefore, the earliest myths they hear should be composed as beautifully as possible, oriented
to virtue [ἃ πρῶτα ακοῦουσιν ὅτι κάλλιστα μεμυθολογημένα πρὸς ἀρετὴν ἀκούειν] (Rep., 378e).
In fact, Plato believed that myth contained truth, which, by its definition in the Republic, makes
myth an ambiguous structure: it is neither false nor true. It does not seem to us, therefore, that what distin-
guishes philosophical myth from other myths is the truth contained in it, but its beauty [καλόν] and its
usefulness [χρήσιμον]11. What you should censor and repudiate is lie without beauty [μὴ καλῶς ψεύδηται]

11To understand the argument of beauty to impart the passage of Rep., 377c-378e; for the utility argument see Rep.,
382c-d.

Investigação Filosófica ISSN 2179-6742 https://periodicos.unifap.br/index.php/investigacaofilosofica Macapá, v. 10, n. 1, p. 07-13, 2019


12 Menezes

(Rep., 377d), this being the true lie [ἀληθῶς ψεῦδος], hated by all gods and men (Rep., 382a). Finally, let us
remember that 'noble lie' [γενναῖον τι ἕν ψευδομένων] (Rep., 414b-c) precedes a philosophical myth, myth of
metals, and even so it ceases to be false. In the Republic, the truth contained in myth must be analyzed in
order of its utility for just polis.
With the advent of writing, the myths began to be recorded, which helped to consecrate them as
part of Greek literature. Brisson argues that myths are formed from the events that collectivity strives to
keep in mind (BRISSON, 1982, p.23). Therefore, there is a collective effort to remember, for, in an oral
civilization, memory is undissociated from oblivion, because what is not saved by memory is discarded and
forgotten (Brisson 1982: 25). This is an important point to emphasize: connection of myth with memory.
In Plato, although we cannot classify myths for a single cause (FRUTIGER, 1976, p.2), we can say that they
also have the same relation to memory. To understand Gyges' narrative in the Republic, for example, we
need to understand the relation of Gyges to Gyges' tradition. His deeds are remembered by lyrical and by
history, and have been recorded by writing; has a popular recurrence, which reinforces its memory among
many (polloi). However, the tradition of Gyges is near temporally of time in which he lived, not having with
lyrical a mythical relation for not being in an unknown past. Another factor is its historicity, since being a
historical figure, could hardly be considered a mythical figure. For Kirk, there is a distinction between what
can be considered myth and what can be a legend; historical or quasi-historical figures are not considered
myths, but they are in the class of popular legends (KIRK, 1990, pp. 23-4), so Gyges could not be considered
a myth, according to tradition. However, a tradition that consecrated Gyges for his riches and his great deeds
was recorded, and undeniably, was very much told among chicken. This made Plato take ownership of this
popular tradition, to compose his myth of Gyges’ ring, which marks an important element of argument he
is developing.
According to Morgan, "the philosophical myth is rational, implanted as a result of methodological
reflection and is a manifestation of philosophical concerns" (MORGAN, 2004, p.7). In Plato, myth usually
appears when one does not know the truth about the distant past (Rep., 382d); and, many times, to talk about
questions of the soul. By presenting different functions, Plato's myths cannot be classified into a single
theory. Edelstein's position seems strange when he says that there is no real dispute between philosophy and
poetry, as long as it passes through censorship of truth (Edelstein, 1949: 479). Or to say that "truth is the
supreme deity" (Edelstein, 1949, 480). Such statements do not seem to fit the text of Plato, for it is not the
truth, in our view, the paradigm that constitutes myths of Plato. Plato with his dialogues gave to the philo-
sophy a new mythology and, consequently, a new poetry. However, for us, this new poetry is not based on
the truth, since, according to Edelstein, Plato "was the last one to believe in truth contained in the myth"
(Edelstein, 1949, 481).
In conclusion, we can say that Platonic myths are philosophical resources for Plato can better deve-
lop his answers. For Edelstein, Platonic myths cannot be unified into a single theory. The author, however,
presents an interesting way of interpreting interior of Plato's philosophical work. There are other linguistic
devices, beyond dialectics, to be able to explain something. In this way we can understand that there is an
introductory moment to myth that is not the same as dialectics, both being acceptable in Plato's philosophy,
myth as being the analogy of truth achieved only by dialectics. And we have many aspects of myth in Plato
that can be left in a different way of interpretation, but myth is a symbolic explanation of pure reason of
dialectics. Dialectics is central to Plato's theory of knowledge. It is through dialectics that computer is in the
direction of maximum knowledge. Myth, therefore, does not function as a substitute for dialectics, but as a
didactic complement to the teaching of philosophy.

Investigação Filosófica ISSN 2179-6742 https://periodicos.unifap.br/index.php/investigacaofilosofica Macapá, v. 10, n. 1, p. 07-13, 2019


Myth in Plato’s philosophy 13

Our work does not pretend to account for the whole possible relation of the myth in Plato, but only
a brief overview of function of myth in his philosophy. The image has capacity to serve as a fantastic didactic
instrument and Plato was aware of it. That is why his philosophical myth is intended to serve as another
resource for teaching, as if it were an introductory apprenticeship to the path of philosophy.

Bibliography:

1. Editions and translations of Republic

BLOOM, A. (1991). The Republic of Plato. Tradução de Allan Bloom. New York: Basic Books.
BURNET, J. (1902). Platonis Opera, recognovit brevique adnotatione critica instrvxit: Ioannes Bur-
net, Tomvs IV. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

2. Studies

BRISSON, L. (2003). Religion as the Grounding of Philosophical Reflection and as a means of Poli-
tical Action in Plato's Laws. Translation by Cláudio William Veloso. Kriterion, n. 107, p. 24-38.
BRISSON, L. (1982). Platon les Mots et les Mythes. Paris: Librarie François Maspero.
EDELSTEIN, Ludwig. (1949). The Function of the Myth in Plato’s Philosophy. Journal of the History
of Ideas, Pennsylvania, v. 10, n. 4, p. 463-481.
KIRK, G. S. (1990). The Nature of Greek Myths. London: Penguin Books.
MORGAN, K. (2004). Myth and Philosophy. From Presocratics to Plato. Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press.
TATE, J. (1929). Plato and Allegorical Interpretation. The Classical Quarterly, Cambridge, v. 23, n.
3/4, p. 142-154.
VEYNE, P. (1987). Did the Greeks believe in their Myths? Translation by António Gonçalves. Lisbon:
Edições 70.

Artigo recebido em: 01 de julho de 2019


Artigo aceito em: 19 de julho de 2019

Investigação Filosófica ISSN 2179-6742 https://periodicos.unifap.br/index.php/investigacaofilosofica Macapá, v. 10, n. 1, p. 07-13, 2019

You might also like