The Yale Law Journal Company, Inc. The Yale Law Journal
The Yale Law Journal Company, Inc. The Yale Law Journal
The Yale Law Journal Company, Inc. The Yale Law Journal
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
The Yale Law Journal Company, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to The Yale Law Journal
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Piercing the Veil
Madhavi Sundert
CONTENTS
1399
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1400 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
2. Textualism ..........................................................
3. Constructivism ................................................... ............ 1448
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1401
INTRODUCTION
1. See HENRY J. STEINER & PHILIP ALSTON, INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS IN CONTEXT
445 (2d ed. 2000) ("If notions of state sovereignty represent one powerful concept and a force that
challenges and seeks to limit the reach of the international human rights movement, religion can
then represent another."); David Kennedy, International Law and the Nineteenth Century: History
of an Illusion, 17 QUINNIPIAC L. REV. 99, 101 (1997) (describing the historical movement in
international law "from autonomy to community," and expressing concern that "there remain
those (often in politics, or in the third world, or new to the field) who would return us to a time of
sovereignty"). My use of the word sovereignty refers to its traditional sense as the right to be let
alone-what's new are the parties making these claims. Cf. ABRAM CHAYES & ANTONIA
HANDLER CHAYES, THE NEW SOVEREIGNTY: COMPLIANCE WITH INTERNATIONAL REGULATORY
AGREEMENTS (1995). In the words of Anne-Marie Slaughter (writing in her memorial to Abe
Chayes), Chayes and Chayes offer an evolving sense of the term in which "sovereignty no longer
means the right to be left alone, but rather the right and capacity to participate 'in the regimes that
make up the substance of international life."' Anne-Marie Slaughter, In Memoriam, 114 HARV. L.
REV. 682, 684-85 (2001) (quoting CHAYES & CHAYES, supra, at 27).
2. It is easy to forget that individual rights are of only recent vintage in international law. As
Louis Henkin reminds us:
[F]or hundreds of years international law and the law governing individual life did not
come together. International law, true to its name, was law only between States,
governing only relations between States on the State level. What a State did inside its
borders in relation to its own nationals remained its own affair, an element of its
autonomy, a matter of its "domestic jurisdiction."
LOUis HENKIN, INTERNATIONAL LAW: POLITICS, VALUES AND FUNCTIONS 209 (1989). But as a
general matter, human rights law is just one example of the gradual whittling away of traditional
notions of state sovereignty. See Anupam Chander, Diaspora Bonds, 76 N.Y.U. L. REV. 1005,
1039 (2001) ("While it is true ... that there was never an era in which nation-states had absolute
dominion over their territory, the last century saw a higher degree of legalization of intrusions into
territorial sovereignty, as well as a magnification of the number and breadth of such intrusions.").
3. Implementing the "strictest interpretation of Shari'a law ever seen in the Muslim world,"
the Taliban closed down girls' schools and banned women from working outside the home,
smashed TV sets, forbade a whole array of sports and recreational activities, and ordered all males
to grow long beards. AHMED RASHID, TALIBAN: MILITANT ISLAM, OIL AND FUNDAMENTALISM
IN CENTRAL ASIA 29, 50-51 (2000). A strict dress code was imposed on women, which required
them to wear head-to-toe veils, id. at 50, and people were required to blacken the windows of their
homes so women could not be seen from the street, id. at 70. Women were banned from general
hospitals, id. at 71, and their health suffered dramatically, see Physicians for Human Rights, The
Taliban's War on Women-a Health and Human Rights Crisis in Afghanistan, at
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1402 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112:1399
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1403
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1404 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112:1399
(2002); ROBERT C. CLARK, CORPORATE LAW 37, 71-85 (1986); and Robert B. Thompson,
Piercing the Corporate Veil: An Empirical Study, 76 CORNELL L. REV. 1036 (1991).
16. Arundhati Roy, The Algebra of Infinite Justice, GUARDIAN (London), Sept. 29, 2001,
Saturday Review, at 1 (arguing that Bush's ultimatum is "not a choice that people want to, need
to, or should have to make").
17. See discussion infra Section IV.A.
18. Here I refer to formal and informal laws, including custom and tradition.
19. See Lila Abu-Lughod, Do Muslim Women Really Need Saving? Anthropological
Reflections on Cultural Relativism and Its Others, 104 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 783, 789 (2002).
20. See, e.g., Diana L. Eck, The Multireligious Public Square, in ONE NATION UNDER GOD?
RELIGION AND AMERICAN CULTURE 3 (Marjorie Garber & Rebecca L. Walkowitz eds., 1999); id.
at 5 (remarking on "academic blindspots when it comes to religion"). Eck writes that "[t]aking
religion seriously as a category of analysis" means abandoning the "lfighly reified thing-ish notion
of religion as if 'it' were a bounded set of ideas, institutions, and practices." Id. Far from it, Eck
describes "religious traditions such as Christianity, Buddhism, and Islam" as "dynamic, more like
rivers than structures, constantly negotiating the terms and directions of change." Id.
21. I do not attempt to offer a study in Islamic law in this Article, but rather, focus solely on
legal constructions of religion. For introductions to Islam and Islamic legal systems, see KAHLED
ABOU EL FADL, SPEAKING IN GOD'S NAME: ISLAMIC LAW, AUTHORITY AND WOMEN (2001);
KAREN ARMSTRONG, ISLAM: A SHORT HISTORY (2000); DAVID PEARL, A TEXTBOOK ON
MUSLIM LAW (1979); and LAWRENCE ROSEN, THE JUSTICE OF ISLAM: COMPARATIVE
PERSPECTIVES ON ISLAMIC LAW AND SOCIETY (2000).
22. KAHLED ABOU EL FADL, REBELLION AND VIOLENCE IN ISLAMIC LAW 1 (2001).
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1405
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1406 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
27. Particularly after September Ilth, such a title could be characterized as everything from
trite to offensive. Indeed, by now the veil trope may seem exhausted. See, e.g., Jen'nan Ghazal
Read & John P. Bartowski, To Veil or Not To Veil, 14 GENDER & SOC'Y 395 (2000); Nicole
Gaouette et al., Voices friom Behind the Veil, CHRISTIAN SCI. MONITOR, Dec. 19, 2001, at 1;
Marilyn Gardner, Lifting the Veil on Women 's Subjugation, CHRISTIAN SCI. MONITOR, Nov. 28,
2001, at 15; Donna Gehrke-White, Behind the Veil, a Strength of Faith, MIAMI HERALD, Nov. 24,
2001, at IE; L.S. Klepp, Under the Veil, ENT. WKLY., Oct. 26, 2001, at 112: Stanley Kurtz, Veil
of Fears: Why the Veil, NAT'L REV., Jan. 28, 2002, at 36; Richard Lacayo, About Face, TIME,
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1407
I. GROUNDWORK
Today we are witnessing the rise of religion and culture as the New
Sovereignty at the very moment that we are hearing rumblings on the
ground of a New Enlightenment. While religious sovereignty is not new,
the conflict between religion and culture and the global recognition that
"women's rights are human rights" is growing.28 Unlike other rights,29
Dec. 3, 2001, at 34 (using the title "Lifting the Veil" on the magazine's cover); Pete Norman &
Eileen Finan, Veil of Tears, PEOPLE, Nov. 12, 2001, at 106; Atefeh Oliai, From Behind the Veil,
FEMINIST VOICES, Nov. 2, 1997, at 7; Sean Salai, Veiled Messages, WASH. TIMES, Aug. 2, 2002,
at A2; CNN Presents: Beneath the Veil (CNN television broadcast, Aug. 26, 2001).
28. Hillary Rodham Clinton, Remarks for the United Nations Fourth World Conference on
Women (Sept. 8, 1995), at gopher://gopher.undp.org:70/00/unconfs/women/conf/gov/
950905175653 (proclaiming the mantra of the conference: "If there is one message that echoes
forth from this conference, it is that human rights are women's rights. ... And women's rights are
human rights."). Women at the United Nations Fourth World Conference on Women held in
Beijing in 1995 popularized this phrase, but women's rights were first recognized as officially
human rights during the World Conference on Human Rights held in Vienna in 1993. See Vienna
Declaration and Programme ofAction, pt. 1, ? 11, U.N. Doc. A/CONF.157/23 (1993).
29. See Courtney W. Howland, The Challenge of Religious Fundamentalism to the Liberty
and Equality Rights of Women: An Analysis Under the United Nations Charter, 35 COLUM. J.
TRANSNAT'L L. 271 (1997) (comparing the refusal to accept religious or cultural justifications for
racial apartheid to the easy acceptance of such claims in the case of women's rights); Ann
Elizabeth Mayer, A "Benign" Apartheid: How Gender Apartheid Has Been Rationalized, 5
UCLA J. INT'L L. & AFF. 237 (2001) (juxtaposing the treatment of racial and gender apartheid in
international human rights law).
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1408 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112:1399
30. See Mayer, supra note 10, at 21-32 (describing the growing popularity of arguments to
curtail women's rights in the name of "Islam"); Yasmin Abdullah, Note, The Holy See at United
Nations Conferences: State or Church?, 96 COLUM. L. REV. 1835 (1996) (describing Vatican
campaigns against women's rights at international conferences in both Cairo and Beijing).
31. Thomas M. Franck, Are Human Rights Universal?, FOREIGN AFF., Jan.-Feb. 2001, at 191
(noting more cultural challenges to the universality of human rights); see also LOUIS HENKIN ET
AL., HUMAN RIGHTS 391 (1999) (writing that cultural relativism "presents a particularly acute
challenge in respect of women's human rights"); Berta Esperanza Hernmindez-Truyol, Human
Rights Through a Gendered Lens: Emergence, Evolution, Revolution, in 1 WOMEN AND
INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS LAW 3, 37 (Kelly D. Askin & Dorean M. Koenig eds., 1999)
("[W]omen's rights are especially fragile to a claim of 'culture."'); Arati Rao, The Politics of
Gender and Culture in International Human Rights Discourse, in WOMEN'S RIGHTS, HUMAN
RIGHTS: INTERNATIONAL FEMINIST PERSPECTIVES 167, 169 (Julie Peters & Andrea Wolper eds.,
1995) ("No social group has suffered greater violation of its human rights in the name of culture
than women."). The debate about whether human rights are compatible with "Asian values" has
been particularly heated. See generally THE EAST ASIAN CHALLENGE FOR HUMAN RIGHTS
(Joanne R. Bauer & Daniel A. Bell eds., 1999). For a trenchant reply to this claim, see Amartya
Sen, Human Rights and Asian Values, NEW REPUBLIC, July 14 & 21, 1997, at 33 (documenting
substantial theorizing about tolerance and freedom within Asian traditions).
32. See discussion infra Part II.
33. Madhavi Sunder, Cultural Dissent, 54 STAN. L. REV. 495, 498-500, 516-23 (2001).
34. See THOMAS M. FRANCK, THE EMPOWERED SELF: LAW AND SOCIETY IN THE AGE OF
INDIVIDUALISM 74-75 (1999) (identifying a new right of individuals to define their identities
outside of traditional identities).
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1409
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1410 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
40. See Sunder, supra note 33, at 509 (similarly noting, in the c
association law, that "increasingly, it will be law, not culture, that
borders and determines how much information, autonomy, and equ
community will enjoy").
41. See Madhavi Sunder, IP3 (2003) (unpublished manuscript, on fi
that while new technological and global architectures are empowerin
themselves as subjects, not objects, of culture, intellectual property
demands of traditional cultural producers in struggles to create and cont
42. See id.
43. Current law stresses alienability-the right to exit from and choose among competing
religions-at the expense of personhood, roots, and loyalty. For one critical perspective on this
approach, see Makau Wa Mutua, Limitations on Religious Rights: Problematizing Religious
Freedom in the African Context, in RELIGIOUS HUMAN RIGHTS IN GLOBAL PERSPECTIVE 417, 417
(Johan D. van der Vyver & John Witte, Jr., eds., 1996) (problematizing the "right to proselytize in
the marketplace of religions" at the expense of the cultural survival of less market-dominant
groups). See generally MARGARET JANE RADIN, CONTESTED COMMODITIES (1996).
44. See Hilary Charlesworth, The Challenges of Human Rights Law for Religious Traditions,
in RELIGION AND INTERNATIONAL LAW 401 (Mark W. Janis & Carolyn Evans eds., 1999)
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1411
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1412 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
win choice: to give up their faith altogether or to conform to the dictates of groups whose political
agendas are cloaked in religious discourse" (citations omitted)).
50. See, e.g., FAITH AND FREEDOM: WOMEN'S HUMAN RIGHTS IN THE MUSLIM WORLD
(Mahnaz Afkhami ed., 1995); Azizah al-Hibri, Islam, Law and Custom: Redefining Muslim
Women's Rights, 12 AM. U. J. INT'L L. & POL'Y 1, 3 (1997) (describing many Muslim women as
wanting "to be good Muslims, but [wanting] to have their rights as well"); Azizah Y. al-Hibri,
Deconstructing Patriarchal Jurisprudence in Islamic Law: A Faithful Approach, in GLOBAL
CRITICAL RACE FEMINISM: AN INTERNATIONAL READER 221, 229 (Adrien Katherine Wing ed.,
2000) (asserting that "the solution to Muslim women's human rights problems is not to ask these
women to cast away their deepest beliefs in search of a Western quick fix"); Radhika
Coomaraswamy, Different but Free: Cultural Relativism and Women's Rights as Human Rights,
in RELIGIOUS FUNDAMENTALISMS AND THE HUMAN RIGHTS OF WOMEN 79, 85-87 (Courtney W.
Howland ed., 1999) (rejecting an either/or approach that would "balance" women's rights against
freedom of religion in favor of an approach that embraces both religion and equality).
51. See discussion infra Part III. In highlighting the challenges of Muslim women activists to
traditional notions of religion and culture, I do not mean to essentialize them as more religious
than non-Muslims. In fact, women's rights activists in the Muslim world engage in numerous
strategies for women's rights "from the exclusively secular to the exclusively theological, with
many permutations in between." Farida Shaheed, Controlled or Autonomous: Identity and the
Experience of the Network, Women Living Under Muslim Laws, 19 SIGNS 997, 999 (1994).
52. Shaheed, supra note 49, at 442.
53. Id. (describing this as a "neglected area . . .both in scholarship and in activism"); see also
Bahia Tahzib-Lie, Applying a Gender Perspective in the Area of the Right to Freedom of Religion
or Belief, 2000 BYU L. REV. 967, 969 (2000) (arguing that "[dissenting] women who object to
certain interpretations of their religion or belief imposed by religious leaders or society or women
who are committed to a different religion or belief from that of the wider society" are often
overlooked in analyses of the "right to freedom of religion"); Bahia G. Tahzib-Lie, Women's
Equal Right to Freedom of Religion or Belief: An Important but Neglected Subject, in RELIGIOUS
FUNDAMENTALISMS AND THE HUMAN RIGHTS OF WOMEN, supra note 50, at 117 (observing the
absence of any global document addressing women's equal right to freedom of religion).
Abdullahi Ahmed An-Na'im's work is a notable exception. See ABDULLAHI AHMED AN-NA'IM,
TOWARD AN ISLAMIC REFORMATION: CIVIL LIBERTIES, HUMAN RIGHTS AND INTERNATIONAL
LAW 10 (1990); Abdullahi Ahmed An-Na'im, Human Rights in the Muslim World: Socio-
Political Conditions and Scriptural Imperatives, A Preliminary Inquiry, 3 HARV. HUM. RTS. J. 13,
15, 21 (1990) [hereinafter An-Na'im, Human Rights] (concluding that "human rights advocates in
the Muslim world must work within the framework of Islam to be effective" and asserting that "a
modern 'Shari'a' could be ... entirely consistent with current standards of human rights").
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1413
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1414 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1415
II. TRANSITION
A. Law's "Past"
of transnational state and nonstate actors). See also W. Michael Reisman, International
Lawmaking: A Process of Communication, The Harold D. Lasswell Memorial Lecture (Apr. 24,
1981), in SOURCES OF INTERNATIONAL LAW 497 (Martti Koskenniemi ed., 2000) (outlining the
New Haven School, or Communications Theory of international law, which envisions
international legal rules as "continuously being fashioned and refashioned by a wide variety of
global actors to suit the needs of the living"); discussion infra Part III, Section IV.A.
65. See JORGEN HABERMAS, THE PHILOSOPHICAL DISCOURSE OF MODERNITY: TWELVE
LECTURES 17 (Frederick Lawrence trans., MIT Press 1987) (describing the Peace of Westphalia
as the beginning of law and as a dismantling of the "world of the divine"); David Kennedy,
Images of Religion in International Legal Theory, in RELIGION AND INTERNATIONAL LAW, supra
note 44, at 145, 146; Hilaire McCoubrey, Natural Law, Religion and the Development of
International Law, in RELIGION AND INTERNATIONAL LAW, supra note 44, at 177, 179.
66. As David Kennedy quips, "Religion is something we used to have." Kennedy, supra note
65, at 145.
67. Kennedy, supra note 1, at 112 (describing "a pre-legal international world of politics,
war, religion, and ideology").
68. IMMANUEL KANT, An Answer to the Question: What Is Enlightenment?, in PERPETUAL
PEACE AND OTHER ESSAYS ON POLITICS, HISTORY, AND MORALS 41, 41 (Ted Humphrey trans.,
Hackett Publ'g Co. 1983) (1795) (defining enlightenment as "man's emergence from his self-
imposed immaturity").
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1416 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112:1399
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1417
B. Law's "Other"
Of course, law's transition from religion did not excise religion from
our lives. To the contrary, it simply excised religion from law, and vice
versa. In the real world, religion remains, but as an "extralegal field,"79
banished from the public and reserved to the private sphere.80 Seeking to
make a clean break with the past,8' law could separate from religion only by
definitional fiat, constructing religion as something wholly distinct from
law-that is, as law's "other."82
The Enlightenment facilitated this partition. At the same time that
international law emerged as a discipline governing the public realm,
Enlightenment theory did the important work of transforming the
conception of religion from political ideology to personal belief. As Talal
Asad recounts in his Genealogy of Religion, European historians contend
that "the constitution of the modem state required the forcible redefinition
of religion as belief, and of religious belief, sentiment, and identity as
personal matters that belong to the newly emerging space of private (as
opposed to public) life."83
According to Kant and his colleagues, one could acquire enlightenment
by transcending his religious passions and applying reason. Significantly,
enlightenment was fully attainable through the exercise of reason in the
76. The foundational documents of international human rights law-the United Nations
Charter (1945), the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (1976), and the
International Covenant on Cultural and Economic Rights (1976)--all reflect natural law origins.
See Hernindez-Truyol, supra note 31, at 21.
77. RHODA E. HOWARD, HUMAN RIGHTS AND THE SEARCH FOR COMMUNITY 12 (1995)
(writing that human rights "are derived from human thought about the nature of justice, not from
divine decree"). As Kennedy describes, modern human rights law reflects a "[p]ost-
enlightenment, rationalist, secular, Western, modern, capitalist" philosophy. Kennedy, supra note
14, at 114.
78. See HOWARD, supra note 77, at 12.
79. Kennedy, supra note 65, at 149.
80. David Kennedy, Losing Faith in the Secular: Law, Religion, and the Culture of
International Governance, in RELIGION AND INTERNATIONAL LAW, supra note 44, at 309, 313
("Religion was to be respected, even honored, in its own sphere-the domain of private
commitment and spiritual meaning.").
81. See Kennedy, supra note 65, at 146 (describing law's view of its own birth as pristine,
believing that it "shares nothing with the messy collapse itself').
82. See Gustavo Benavides, Modernity, in CRITICAL TERMS FOR RELIGIOUS STUDIES 186,
196 (Mark C. Taylor ed., 1998) (describing secularization as leading, not to the "disappearance of
religion," but rather to the "differentiation and narrowing of the institutional religious realm").
83. ASAD, supra note 71, at 205.
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1418 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
84. See KANT, supra note 68, at 42 ("Nothing is required for this enlig
except freedom; and the freedom in question is the least harmful of all, nam
reason publicly in all matters.").
85. Id.
86. Id. Kant defined the public use of one's reason as the use of reason before the public, or
"the entire literate world." He called "the private use of reason that which a person may make in a
civic post or office that has been entrusted to him"--that is, in the private sphere. Id.
87. Id.
88. That said, Kant (and Hume) may not have conceived of the stark separation of public and
private that we have today. For example, Kant described the following situation as "wholly
impossible" and unacceptable in an enlightened society:
But would a society of pastors, perhaps a church assembly or venerable
presbytery ... not be justified in binding itself by oath to a certain unalterable symbol
in order to secure a constant guardianship over each of its members and through them
over the people, and this for all: I say this is wholly impossible. Such a contract, whose
intention is to preclude forever all further enlightenment of the human race, is
absolutely null and void ....
Id. at 43.
89. See DAVID HUME, AN INQUIRY CONCERNING HUMAN UNDERSTANDING (Charles W.
Hendel ed., Prentice-Hall, Inc. 1995) (1748); IMMANUEL KANT, RELIGION WITHIN THE
BOUNDARIES OF MERE REASON (Allen Wood & George di Giovanni eds. & trans., Cambridge
Univ. Press 1998) (1793). Interestingly, preeminent scientists have made similar arguments in the
modem day. See STEPHEN JAY GOULD, ROCKS OF AGES: SCIENCE AND RELIGION IN THE
FULLNESS OF LIFE 111 (1999) (rejecting the "model of warfare between science and religion"
because what distinguishes the two is reason).
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1419
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1420 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112:1399
relationship, the line, the distinction, between international law and sovereignty .... ").
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1421
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1422 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112:1399
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1423
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1424 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1425
D. Cases in Point
1. CEDA W (Global)
124. Sheila Jayaprakash, The Right To Be Equal, HINDU, Apr. 23, 2000, at 4.
125. Most notable is CEDAW's Article 5(a), which provides:
States Parties shall take all appropriate measures:
To modify the social and cultural patterns of conduct of men and women, with a
view to achieving the elimination of prejudices and customary and all other practices
which are based on the idea of the inferiority or the superiority of either of the sexes or
on stereotyped roles for men and women ....
Women's Convention, supra note 4, art. 5(a), 1249 U.N.T.S. at 17.
126. OFFICE OF THE UNITED NATIONS HIGH COMM'R FOR HUMAN RIGHTS, STATUS OF
RATIFICATIONS OF THE PRINCIPAL INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS TREATIES (2002), at
http://www.unhchr.ch/pdf/report.pdf.
127. See Women's Convention, supra note 4, art. 5(a), 1249 U.N.T.S. at 17.
128. See HENKIN ET AL., supra note 31, at 362 (writing that as of April 1999, CEDAW "'has
attracted the greatest number of reservations with the potential to modify or exclude most, if not
all, of the terms of the treaty"' (quoting Belinda Clark, The Vienna Convention Reservations
Regime and the Convention of Discrimination Against Women, 85 AM. J. INT'L L. 281, 371
(1991))).
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1426 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
129. Many Middle Eastern and Islamic countries, for example. Ban
Kuwait, Libyan Arab Jamahiriya, Malaysia, Maldives, and Morocco, took
the Convention citing prejudice to Shari'a. United Nations, Convention on
Forms of Discrimination Against Women, Reservations and Declarations,
Depts/Treaty/final/ts2/newsfiles/part_boo/iv_boo/iv_8.html#J6G2eePat
2003) [hereinafter CEDAW Reservations and Declarations]. Other coun
Israel, and Singapore, took similar reservations on general freedom of r
addition, a small number of countries, including India, Kuwait, Morocco
Tunisia, expressed reservations based on customary laws and cultural m
subsume international human rights law under religious and customary
Muslim states, for example, have long asserted a right to religious and
defiance of universal rights. The most symbolic of their statements is the
of Human Rights in Islam. Authored by the Organization of the Isl
document protests the universality of international human rights and declar
are subsumed under the Islamic law of Shari'a. See Cairo Declaration on H
U.N. GAOR, 2d Sess., Agenda Item 11, U.N. Doc. A/CONF.157/PC/35 (19
130. See, e.g., An-Na'im, Human Rights, supra note 53, at 36-50 (fi
between Shari'a and international human rights standards, including in the
but arguing that it is possible to reinterpret Shari'a to be consistent with int
norms).
131. Article 19 of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties "provides that a state
ratifying a treaty may make a reservation unless it is 'prohibited by the treaty' or 'is incompatible
with the object and purpose of the treaty.' Section 313 of the Restatement (Third), Foreign
Relations Law of the United States (1987), is to the same effect." STEINER & ALSTON, supra note
1, at 439 (quoting Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, opened for signature, May 23,
1969, art. 19, S. EXEC. DOC. L, 92-1, at 16 (1971), 1155 U.N.T.S. 331, 336-37). In general,
tolerance of reservations has been urged in order to achieve greater participation in the treaty and
to enable a state to protect its interests as much as possible. See id. at 441. Article 28(2) of the
Women's Convention also expressly prohibits reservations that contravene its "object and
purpose." Women's Convention, supra note 4, art. 28(2). 1249 U.N.T.S. at 23.
132. See Mayer, supra note 29, at 271 ("[A]ttempts to deter the practice of reservations in
conflict with the object and purpose of CEDAW have met with resistance in the form of
accusations that these were tantamount to Western attacks on Islam and/or the Third World."
(citation omitted)).
133. See REPORT OF THE FOURTH WORLD CONFERENCE ON WOMEN, ? 130, U.N. Doc.
A/CONF. 177/20, U.N. Sales No. E.96.IV.13 (1995) (calling on states parties to CEDAW to
"consider withdrawing reservations ... [and] ensure that no reservation is incompatible with the
object and purpose of the Convention or otherwise contrary to international treaty law"); Press
Release, Commission on Human Rights, Commission on Human Rights Takes Up Integration of
Human Rights of Women and Gender Perspective, U.N. Doc. HR/CN/909 (Apr. 13, 1999), at
http://www.un.org/News/Press/docs/l 999/19990413.hrcn909.html (recommending that "all
Governments should ratify, without reservation, the Convention on the Elimination of all Forms
of Discrimination Against Women"). See generally General Recommendations Made by the
Committee on the Elimination of Discrimination Against Women, General Recommendation No.
4 (1987), at http://www.un.org/womenwatch/daw/cedaw/recomm.htm (expressing concern in
1987 over reservations to CEDAW and suggesting "that all States parties concerned reconsider
such reservations with a view to withdrawing them").
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1427
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1428 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
140. See Bano, A.I.R. 1985 S.C. at 945. For a fuller account of the Shah
its aftermath, see NUSSBAUM, supra note 47, at 172-73 (reporting that the
Muslim Personal Law Board organized widespread protest against the rul
violated their free exercise of religion"); and Martha C. Nussbaum, Ind
Equality Through Law, 2 CHI. J. INT'L L. 35, 44-47 (2001).
141. See, e.g., Edward A. Gargan, Hindu Rage Against Muslims Tra
Politics, N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 17, 1993. at Al ("Worried about Muslim suppo
the Parliament change the law to void the court's ruling."); Steven R. We
Moslem Divorce Ensnarls Gandhi, N.Y. TIMES, Feb. 9, 1986, at A3 ("Politi
with Mr. Gandhi say he will probably support legislation to reverse the effe
decision. But feminists have served notice that if this happens, his party w
represent women,' as one leader put it.").
142. The Muslim Women (Protection of Rights on Divorce) Act (1986), at
http://indiacode.nic.in/cgi/nph-bwcgi/BASIS/indweb/all/actretr/SF.
143. NUSSBAUM, supra note 47, at 173.
144. Nussbaum, supra note 140, at 45 (citation omitted).
145. See CEDAW Reservations and Declarations, supra note 129; UNIFEM, supra note 137.
146. UNIFEM, supra note 137.
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1429
While the United States does not expressly delegate the governance of
private matters to various communities through personal or customary laws,
deference to religious or other private communities arises nonetheless in a
number of contexts. The associational speech and religious freedoms
guaranteed by the First Amendment offer one principal mechanism for
halting public intervention. In EEOC v. Catholic University of America,'51
for example, Sister Elizabeth McDonough alleged sex discrimination and
retaliatory conduct in violation of Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964.
McDonough argued that she was denied tenure at Catholic University
because of her sex. But the Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia
Circuit dismissed the claim on the ground that its adjudication on the merits
would violate the First Amendment.152 Deferring to university authorities as
the arbiters of the organization's norms, the court upheld university leaders'
freedom of religion over the dissenting claim of Sister McDonough.
While it does not involve religion per se, tribal sovereignty for Native
Americans is yet another area in which U.S. law defers to traditionalists
within a culture over the claims of reformers. In Santa Clara Pueblo v.
Mkartinez.,53 a Pueblo woman and her daughter sought to apply the federal
Indian Civil Rights Act to challenge a tribal rule that granted tribal
membership to children of mixed marriages only when the father was
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1430 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1431
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1432 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1433
III. CONFRONTATION
But on the ground, women in the Muslim world are piercing the veil of
religious sovereignty. Far from reflecting a world in transition in which
formal laws (such as treaties and conventions) are imposed on individuals
at the grass-roots level, a close study of women activists in the Muslim
world demonstrates how they are confronting problems with formal laws
that often privilege the viewpoints and interests of traditionalists and
patriarchs. Rather than accepting the binary framework of religion (on
traditional leaders' terms) or rights (without normative community),
activists are developing strategies that enable women to claim both. Going
further, they are articulating new normative visions of women's human
rights that fundamentally challenge the Enlightenment premises of existing
laws. In contrast to the transition model, this confrontation brings to view a
far more dialogical model of interaction between formal human rights law
and informal human rights mechanisms; it suggests that strategic and
normative claims of "rights" on the ground may be ultimately distinct from
those articulated in formal law. Substantively, the dialogical model presents
new visions of law with which traditional law must reckon.
This Part presents two case studies that glimpse this dialogical model in
action. First, I highlight the human rights strategies of the transnational
network Women Living Under Muslim Laws (WLUML). WLUML
exemplifies an operational human rights strategy that provides women the
option of articulating and demanding freedom and equality within the
context of a normative (i.e., religious and/or cultural) community. Next, I
offer a close reading of Claiming Our Rights: A Manual for Human Rights
Education in Muslim Societies,"17 published in 1998. The Manual, like
WLUML, identifies and employs strategies for allowing women access to
both equality and community. But the Manual perhaps goes further than
WLUML by identifying the core principles and theories undergirding its
strategy. Reading them together, I identify a conceptually coherent theme in
171. MAHNAZ AFKHAMI & HALEH VAZIRI, CLAIMING OUR RIGHTS: A MANUAL FOR
HUMAN RIGHTS EDUCATION IN MUSLIM SOCIETIES (1998). In this Article, I will refer to this
manual as "Claiming Our Rights" or "the Manual."
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1434 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
172. See Anupam Chander, Whose Republic?, 69 U. CHI. L. REV. 1479, 1493-95 (2002)
(describing how the Internet helps nurture transnational communities).
173. See generally ANNELISE RILES, THE NETWORK INSIDE OUT (2000) (describing the rise
of national, regional, and international women's "networks" as a mechanism for pursuing human
rights after the United Nations Fourth World Conference on Women in Beijing in 1995); Anne-
Marie Slaughter, Globalization, Accountability and the Future of Administrative Law: The
Accountability of Government Networks, 8 IND. J. GLOBAL LEGAL STUD. 347 (2001) (noting the
expanding influence of "transgovernmental regulatory networks").
174. See Susan Sachs, Where Muslim Traditions Meet Modernity, N.Y. TIMES, Dec. 17,
2001, at B1 (describing how the world's Muslim women are increasingly "confident of their
religious judgment and use the Internet as a forum to promote an alternative vision of the rights of
Muslim women").
175. See generally Int'l Women's Human Rights Law Clinic & WLUML, Shadow Report on
Algeria: To the Committee on the Elimination of Discrimination Against Women (1999), at
http://www.nodo50.org/mujeresred/argelia-shadowreport.html.
176. See HILARY CHARLESWORTH & CHRISTINE CHINKIN, THE BOUNDARIES OF
INTERNATIONAL LAW (2000); PARTHA CHATTERJEE, THE NATION AND ITS FRAGMENTS (1993).
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1435
1. Identity Problems
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1436 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
2. Identity Strategies
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1437
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1438 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
195. Id.
196. Interview with Marimem H6lie Lucas, Author, in Montpellier, Fr. (June 25, 2002).
197. Id. This is similar to exercises in the Claiming Our Rights manual. See infra Section
III.B.
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1439
3. Identity Norms
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1440 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1441
208. Reformers characterize a purely textualist approach as too limited. "We can show that
what the Prophet said was a step forward" on a particular issue, such as slavery or women's rights,
Hdlie Lucas says. Interview with Mari6md Hl1ie Lucas, supra note 195. "But we cannot limit
ourselves to that. If the Prophet says 'beat your wife lightly,' or 'be kind to your slave,' a religious
approach would limit itself to these" instructions. Id. "Maybe within reinterpretation people can
go further than that. But a secular approach would be no slavery" under any circumstances. Id. In
addition, few Muslim women have the expertise or credentials to challenge traditional Islamic
interpretations. "If you are talking about reinterpretations, there the problem is historical-that
women have historically been excluded from interpretation, and they therefore lack the capacity in
terms of knowledge of Arabic, knowledge of jurisprudence, admission into colleges that teach
theology, etc.," says Balchin. Interview with Cassandra Balchin, supra note 193. "It's very
difficult if you don't know Classical Arabic. It's difficult if you don't have the legitimacy of
education at certain places." Id.
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1442 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
209. H61ie contrasts the network with the U.S.-based Catholics for a F
WLUML collaborates regularly. Interview with Anissa H61ie, supra n
between the two groups, Hdlie says, is that the members of Catholics f
believers, which is not the case in the Network. While many wom
indeed believers in Islam, there are also many people who choose a s
they may also be believers), and there are those who are not believers b
born and raised in a Muslim community, are assumed to be "Muslim
laws are applied. id.
210. WLUML, Introduction, WLUML DOSSIER 23/24, July 2001,
Lucas, What Is Your Tribe?: Women 's Struggles and the Constructio
DOSSIER 23/24, July 2001, at 49, 59 ("What is of most interest to m
different but complementary strategies [of Muslim feminists], only
getting most attention, most funding, most recognition. It is seen as th
best for 'Muslims.' Indeed, it is the strategy of religious interpretati
Politics of Theorizing "Islamic Fundamentalism".: Implications jb
Movements, WLUML DOSSIER 23/24, July 2001, at 64, 71 (critiquing
woman" whose identity is determined singly by religion); Farida
Identities-Culture, Women's Agencv and the Muslim World, WLU
2001, at 33, 34 (expressing concern that preoccupation with religiously
Muslim women at the expense of recognizing multiple strategies, inc
determines the role of Islam in the lives of women," and implies that "
to live in a world that is defined solely by a religious identity, is exclus
that is insulated from any other social political or culturally relevant inf
of power, the technological revolution, the culture of consumerism, etc.
211. Interview with Mariemd Hl1ie Lucas, supra note 195.
212. Id.
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1443
213. Id.
214. Id.
215. On consciousness raising as a feminist strategy for change generally, see CATHERINE A.
MACKINNON, TOWARD A FEMINIST THEORY OF THE STATE 83-105 (1989).
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1444 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112:1399
216. AFKHAMI & VAZIRI, supra note 171. The Manual, which was fir
has since been translated and adapted for use in countries as diverse as
Egypt, India, Iran, Jordan, Lebanon, Malaysia, Pakistan, Syria, the United
As of 1998, nearly 2000 women and men were estimated to have parti
pilot workshops. See id. at iii.
217. See Barbara Crossette, A Manual on Rights of Women Under Isl
29, 1996, at A4 (announcing the Manual's historic publication "with the
Islamic regime in Afghanistan hovering over the debate" on women's hum
world).
218. See generally KUMARI JAYAWARDENA, FEMINISM AND NATIONALISM IN THE THIRD
WORLD 2 (1986) (observing that feminism was "not imposed on the Third World by the West"
and detailing a far more complex history of feminism in the Third World); FATIMA MERNISSI,
BEYOND THE VEIL: MALE-FEMALE DYNAMICS IN MODERN MUSLIM SOCIETY 169 (Ind. Univ.
Press 1987) (1975) (describing acquisition of greater rights by women in Muslim communities as
"a random, non-planned, non-systematic phenomenon, due mainly to the disintegration of the
traditional system under pressures from within and without"); VALENTINE M. MOGHADAM,
MODERNIZING WOMEN: GENDER AND SOCIAL CHANGE IN THE MIDDLE EAST (1993) (noting that
Islamist feminist movements simultaneously seek to maintain authentic cultural traditions and
institutions while selectively incorporating from the West to advance women's rights); WOMEN,
ISLAM AND THE STATE (Deniz Kandiyoti ed., 1991) (highlighting the role of state building in the
development of feminisms in Muslim societies); Chandra Talpade Mohanty, Under Western Eyes:
Feminist Scholarship and Colonial Discourses, in THIRD WORLD WOMEN AND THE POLITICS OF
FEMINISM 51, 51 (Chandra Talpade Mohanty et al. eds., 1991) (positioning "the intellectual and
political construction of 'third world feminisms"' at the crossroads of two simultaneous projects:
one of deconstructing hegemonic Western feminist discourses and another of constructing
historically, geographically, and culturally grounded feminisms).
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1445
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1446 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
1. Translation
220. Id. at 1 (discussing the need to find indigenous concepts and ideas "to support"
international rights documents).
221. Id. ("The idea of a human rights education project for women in Muslim societies
originated during a series of meetings, discussions, and conferences held and sponsored by SIGI
since 1993.").
222. Id.
223. Id. at 85-89.
224. Id. at 91-99.
225. Id. at 101-15.
226. Id. at 117-27.
227. The sura are passages from the Qur'an. Id. at 53-73.
228. Id. at 75-78. The Manual describes hadith as "the term applied to the reports of the
Prophet Muhammad's words and actions." Id. at 75. Hadith were first recorded by the Prophet's
companions orally and later translated into writing. Because of the human intervention involved in
writing the hadith, the authenticity of many of them-of which there are thousands-remains a
subject of disagreement among Islamic scholars. Id.
229. Id. at 79-81.
230. Id. at 83-84.
231. The Manual does not limit the use of cultural examples in training sessions to those
examples it supplies. Instead, Manual facilitators are requested to "make a point of collecting
cultural materials-proverbs, quotes from literary works, biographies of role models, and/or
newspaper clippings" found in the cultural settings in which they are teaching. Id. at 13.
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1447
2. Textualism
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1448 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
3. Constructivism
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1449
4. Reconstructivism
246. See, e.g., id. at 27-29 (presenting a hypothetical conversation between Leila and her
friend Zahra, who has just been raped); id. at 33-35 (describing the dilemma of Ayda, a top
student who is denied permission to take a science class because of her gender); id. at 36-37
(presenting a hypothetical in which Fatima, a medical student, discovers she is being paid less
than half of what a male medical student is being paid for the same work in a local doctor's
office). There is an interesting coincidence of method here with the approach of some critical race
scholars, who also rely upon dialogue and narrative to promote rights consciousness. See, e.g.,
DERRICK BELL, AND WE ARE NOT SAVED (1987); RICHARD DELGADO, THE RODRIGO
CHRONICLES (1995).
247. AFKHAMI & VAZIRI, supra note 171, at 12.
248. Id. at 4. Rather than aiming at incontrovertible truths, it produces dialogical frames
where "ideas can be freely discussed and analyzed," the Manual states of its methodology. Id.; see
also id. at 5 (explaining that the model "does not aim to teach a particular truth but rather to
establish dialogue"); id. at 12 ("[T]his manual does not seek to impart truth.").
249. Id. at 9.
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1450 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 1 12: 1399
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1451
258. Id.
259. Id.
260. Id. at 44-46.
261. Id. at 46.
262. Id. at 49.
263. Id. at 29.
264. Id.
265. Id. at 5 (describing the Manual as "geared to ideas, structures, and actions that enhance
democracy and promote civil society").
266. Id. at 6.
267. Telephone Interview with Mahnaz Afkhami, Author (Aug. 1, 2002).
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1452 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
268. Id.
269. Id.; see also IN THE SHADOW OF ISLAM: THE WOMEN'S MOVEMENT IN IRAN (Azar
Tabari & Nahid Yeganeh eds., 1982).
270. Telephone Interview with Mahnaz Afkhami, supra note 267.
271. Id.
272. Id.
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1453
273. Id.
274. Id.
275. Id.
276. Id.
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1454 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1455
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1456 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112:1399
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1457
IV. FUTURES
"Imaginations of socially just futures for humans usually take the idea
of single, homogenous, and secular historical time for granted,"
Chakrabarty writes.294 But in presuming that the world's peoples are
marching in lockstep toward a singular future,295 we elide alternatives and
blind ourselves to incisive critiques of current law and of liberalism
itself.296 Viewed as confrontation rather than as transition, the claims of
women reformers in Muslim communities offer important new takes on
traditional law and its attendant notions of cultural relativism,
multiculturalism, imposed identity, and narratives of transition. This Part
highlights these contributions by offering the normative critiques of
reformers working in Muslim communities as a theoretical road map for
piercing the veil of the New Sovereignty. More broadly, it highlights their
contributions in the hopes of illuminating the importance of shifting from
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1458 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1459
But read another way, claims for women's human rights in Muslim
communities signify much more than a world "in transition." To be sure,
women from Muslim countries and communities embrace the universal
concepts of justice, equality, and democracy. But unlike traditional Western
lawyers, they seek to apply these concepts within explicitly religious and
cultural contexts, not in the public sphere alone. Feminists in Muslim
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1460 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1461
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1462 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1463
324. See Nussbaum, supra note 140, at 40 (explaining that the current "decentralized
situation dates back to the Raj, when the British codified commercial and criminal law for the
nation as a whole, but, in the spirit of divide and rule, encouraged the maintenance of separate
spheres of civil law in non-commercial areas"); see also KNOP, supra note 47, at 364 (describing
how indigenous women in Canada revealed that the Canadian Indian Act codified "not indigenous
customs" as claimed, "but European patriarchy").
325. Abu-Lughod, supra note 19, at 786-87.
326. See Minoo Moallem, Transnationalism, Feminism, and Fundamentalism, in WOMEN,
GENDER, RELIGION: A READER, supra note 112, at 119, 120 ("Feminisms and fundamentalisms
are now competing global forces, both attempting to find means to control the mechanism of
cultural representation.").
327. As Cornel West writes:
The crucial intellectual battles of the day... are no longer over Truth but rather over
the production of truths-and this truth-production is a fully historical and political
affair. That is, we do not passively accept the Truth from a static past, but rather we
contribute to the creation of new truths by reinterpreting old truths of dynamic
traditions in light of new circumstances and challenges.
Cornel West, Faith, Struggle, and Reality, 45 CHRISTIANITY & CRISIS 400, 401 (1985).
328. See, e.g., PAUL GILROY, AGAINST RACE: IMAGINING POLITICAL CULTURE BEYOND THE
COLOR LINE (2000); K. Anthony Appiah, Identity, Authenticity, Survival: Multicultural Societies
and Social Reproduction, in MULTICULTURALISM 149, 162-63 (Amy Gutmann ed., 1994) (asking
whether, if we take autonomy seriously, identity does not replace "one kind of tyranny with
another"); Janet E. Halley, Culture Constrains, in Is MULTICULTURALISM BAD FOR WOMEN?,
supra note 9, at 100, 103-04.
329. In this sense women's strategies reflect the view of West, who writes that identity
politics, "on the one hand, are inescapable and, on the other hand, still too limited." CORNEL
WEST, Christian Love and Heterosexism, in THE CORNEL WEST READER, supra note 90, at 401,
407.
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1464 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112:1399
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1465
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1466 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
1. Passive Proceduralism
337. This is Robert Cover's argument. Cover recognized that law is more often jurispathic-
killing off the "law" offered by dissenters-than jurisgenerative. See Robert M. Cover, The
Supreme Court, 1982 Term-Foreword: Nomos and Narrative, 97 HARV. L. REV. 4, 53 (1982)
(famously writing: "Judges are people of violence. Because of the violence they command, judges
characteristically do not create law, but kill it. Theirs is the jurispathic office. Confronting the
luxuriant growth of a hundred legal traditions, they assert that this one is law and destroy or try to
destroy the rest.").
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1467
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1468 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
2. Robust Proceduralism
338. See Madhavi Sunder, Intellectual Property and Identity Politics: Playing with Fire, 4 J.
GENDER RACE & JUST. 69, 94 (2000) (arguing against national laws that would limit access to
global media and technology in order to promote cultural survival).
339. I make this argument elsewhere. See Sunder, supra note 33, at 562 (arguing for a "right
to speak and to challenge oppressive cultural norms and practices" from within a cultural
association).
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1469
3. Substantive Prescriptions
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1470 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112:1399
343. Deirdre Evans-Pritchard & Alison Dundes Renteln, The Interpretation and Distortion of
Culture: A Hmong "Marriage by Capture" Case in Fresno, California, 4 S. CAL. INTERDISC. L.J.
1, 14 (1994) (describing such practices as involving a Hmong male's kidnapping of a woman
against her will, intending that she become his bride-where this custom is recognized, he will
obtain the sanction of both his and her family for their marriage at a later date).
344. Cf id. at 14-16 (describing this practice as only one among many marriage practices in
Hmong culture, with some allowing a woman much greater choice in the selection of a marriage
partner). Evans-Pritchard and Renteln critique the use of a "cultural defense" in such cases
because this approach all too often presents "a single uniform version of a marriage practice,"
despite contest within a culture over such practices. Id. at 21. The writers highlight that many
cases involved claims by Hmong women in the United States, including a prospective bride and
her mother, who appealed to American authorities not to recognize such marriages. Id. at 16.
345. Bill Ong Hing, Refugee Policy and Cultural Identity: In the Voice of Hmong and Iu
Mien Young Adults 48, 50 (Jan. 16, 2002) (unpublished manuscript, on file with author)
(describing young Hmong women, in particular, as "embracing gender equality" in the self-
conscious process of forming their cultural identity).
346. See supra notes 168-170 and accompanying text; see also Janine di Giovanni, Divine
Injustice, TIMES (London), Nov. 30, 2002, at 24 (chronicling protests against Lawal's stoning
sentence by Nigerian feminist organization, Baobab).
347. In the rare case of no cultural dissent, I do not, at this time, propose further substantive
intervention on the basis of my theory. Indeed, such cases are beyond the scope of my proposals,
which are not intended to cover comprehensively each and every instance of injustice in the
private sphere.
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2003] Piercing the Veil 1471
CONCLUSION
348. See Crane Brinton, Enlightenment, in 2 THE ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY 519, 519
(Paul Edwards et al. eds., 1972). Crane Brinton is the former President of the American Historical
Association.
349. For example, in an editorial on the importance of internal dialogue within religious
communities, Thomas Friedman contended that while "Christianity and Judaism struggled with
this issue for centuries... a similar internal struggle within Islam to re-examine its texts and
articulate a path for how one can accept pluralism and modernity--and still be a passionate,
devout Muslim-has not surfaced in any serious way." Thomas L. Friedman, Editorial, The Real
War, N.Y. TIMES, Nov. 27, 2001, at A19. That same day, on the pages of Friedman's paper,
another writer argued that Afghan women "have already shown their determination to create
change from within," stressing that "Western organizations can be more effective in helping
women if they ground their support in the positions of Muslim feminists." Rina Amiri, Editorial,
Muslim Women as Symbols--and Pawns, N.Y. TIMES, Nov. 27, 2001, at A19.
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
1472 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 112: 1399
350. In this sense I agree with Habermas that "the defects of the Enlight
made good by further enlightenment." Thomas McCarthy, Introduction to HA
65, at vii, xvii.
This content downloaded from 210.212.249.227 on Fri, 24 Aug 2018 05:09:50 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms