Legal Philosophers: Savigny: German Lawgiver: Marquette Law Review
Legal Philosophers: Savigny: German Lawgiver: Marquette Law Review
Legal Philosophers: Savigny: German Lawgiver: Marquette Law Review
Volume 55
Article 5
Issue 2 Spring 1972
Repository Citation
Luis Kutner, Legal Philosophers: Savigny: German Lawgiver, 55 Marq. L. Rev. 280 (1972).
Available at: http://scholarship.law.marquette.edu/mulr/vol55/iss2/5
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Marquette Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in
Marquette Law Review by an authorized administrator of Marquette Law Scholarly Commons. For more information, please contact
megan.obrien@marquette.edu.
SAVIGNY: GERMAN LAWGIVER
I. INTRODUCTION
The great German jurist, Friedrick Karl von Savigny, stands
as the undisputed head of the influential historial school of juris-
prudence, which he pioneered in the first half of the 19th century,
and as the founder of the study of relations between social and legal
developments) A trail-blazing legal scientist, Savigny made many
lasting contributions to jurisprudence that greatly influenced all
the social disciplines as well. Among these contributions are in-
cluded the revealing of continuity between present legal institutions
and those of the past, 2 the laying of foundations for legal sociol-
ogy, 3 and the articulating of methods for historical research.' In
light of the work of Savigny, it is thus the intent of this paper to
present a full, in-depth profile of this legal scholar and his influence
on the law in society.
1. J. STONE, THE PROVINCE AND FUNCTION OF LAW 421-22 (1946) [hereinafter cited
as FUNCTION OF LAW].
2. Montmorency, Friedrich Carl von Savigny, in GREAT JURISTS OF THE WORLD 573-
74 (J. Macdonell & E. Manson ed. 1914) [hereinafter cited as GREAT JURISTS].
3. J. STONE, SOCIAL DIMENSIONS OF LAW AND JUSTICE 35-36 (1966) [hereinafter cited
as SOCIAL. DIMENSIONS].
4. Id. at 100-01.
5. GREAT JURISTS at 561.
1972] COMMENTARY
6. Id. at 562-63.
7. Id. at 563.
8. Id. at 572.
9. SOCIAL DIMENSIONS at 87.
10. Id.
11. GREAT JURISTS at 568. Austin declared this work to be "of all books upon law, the
most consummate and masterly." J. AUSTIN, PROVINCE OF JURISPRUDENCE DETERMINED
38 (3d. 1832).
12. FUNCTION OF LAW at 428.
13. R. POUND, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PHILOSOPHY OF LAW 213 (1922).
14. K. LEWELLYN, JURISPRUDENCE 177 (1962).
MARQUETTE LAW REVIEW [Vol. 55
ship between the law and the life of each particular society under-
mined natural law from the viewpoint of history and human experi-
ence. Thus, he.challenged the natural law idea of a universal code
because he thought, evidencing Hugo's influence, that the law
should reflect the unique needs and character of the people of each
nation. -9 Here, then, Savigny was able to masterfully turn around
the previously cited argument for codification by utilizing it instead
as an objection to a general code for all Germany on the grounds
that such a code would be a reckless importation and an imitation
of Napoleon's work in France and the other countries he
subdued."
In repudiating the 18th century doctrine of natural rights and
the law of nature 31-that which was truly to be honored in the
legal field 32-Savigny's school of thought substituted in its place
the notion of historical right: any individual exultation of natural
order would set that order in opposition to history, placing the
creations of history under constant threat of either violent or grad-
ual destruction.?
To the historical school, the law existed independent of the
state; it was the creation, not of nature or nature's God, but of the
naiional consciousness. The rule of law was, thus, mysteriously
begotten of this "spirit of the people" (or Volksgeist) in whom it
had already existed.34 Therefore, since law originated in the
unique spirit of the people it could not be made, and3the
5
Volksgeist
became the basis for study in all its manifestations.
Savigny's Volksgeist doctrine, the first to recognize each par-
ticular nation as having a continuity and uniqueness of experience
all its own, was a juristic expression of the romantic revival which
had an influence on Savigny, himself. 6 Indeed, the whole perspec-
tive of historical jurisprudence was a part of the romantic move-
ment which had begun in the latter period of the 18th century. In
Germany it took the form of a movement back to the simplest
tribal origins of the Germanic people, their folk songs and tales,
had decided that the time was not ripe in Germany for such legisla-
tive reform. 5
First, he specifically condemned plans for codification on the
ground that the "state of the public mind" of the German people
was "deficient" in "the law-making faculty" because it lacked the
legal consciousness upon which to base the new legislative formula-
tion. 6 While use of the power of the state could very well cut off
extra-code developments, 57 the state's function was merely to dis-
cover and enforce customary law. No amount of state authority
could produce a real, suitable, or stable code if the political ele-
ment were not mature. That the state of the German Volksgeist,
whose lives the code would govern, had not yet fulfilled this "politi-
cal" prerequisite was clearly emphasized by Savigny, who further
added that to ignore these limitations in attempting "to establish
an exhaustive system of legislation" would only mean that the code
would
inevitably attract all attention to itself, away from the real source
of the law, so that the latter, left in darkness and obscurity,
[would] derive no assistance from the moral energies of the na-
tion, by which alone it [could] attain a satisfactory state.58
Legislation and codes could, at best, only give verbal expression
to existing law. Opposed to "armchair legislation," Savigny fa-
vored the idea of continuity of experience, the mastery of which
was wholly essential for any progress. This belief that conditions
of time and place limited effective legal action stood as a forerun-
ner of socio-psychological doctrine. 9
Secondly, Savigny believed that a code could not be drafted if
the juristic maturity of the "technical element" were not available
to perform the task: what matter if even the political element were
adequate for codification when jurists of sufficient genius, well-
versed in the tradition and spirit of the law, were lacking. Codifica-
tidn presupposed a highly developed study of law so that the code
could be an adequate interpretation of the living law. This "techni-
cal" expertise Savigny believed his contemporaries lacked. 0 In
duced. A code drafted in this middle period would aid not that age,
itself, where it was not needed, but future declining ages when
"almost everything is wanting, the knowledge of the matter as well
as the language."6 Hence, codification could only be justified for
periods of cultural deterioration.69
Moreover, ripe though the materials of the law might become,
still needed were technical juristic knowledge, superb skill, and that
degree of precision appropriate to the subject matter to be codified.
This could be done only by extracting concepts and principles,
defining .them, and tracing their consequences and inter-
relations-a process which Savigny referred to as being one of the
most difficult in the area of jurisprudence. He felt that Thibaut's
.proposal of codification without such skills would, if adopted, re-
sult in contradictions, ambiguities, omissions, and confusion. This
would do grave harm because a bad code would insulate law from
its sources of popular consciousness. As a case in point, Savigny
cited, in Vom Beruf, the decay of juristic study in the German
states of Austria and Prussia, as well as in France. 0
Savigny's Vom BerufunsrerZeit directly influenced the course
of a country's legal development perhaps as no other single, com-
parable essay had. As was the author's intent, it delayed German
codification for more than half a century. Under the work of his-
torical jurists, older concepts of natural law and rights were re-
placed by legal ideas as an outgrowth of history. Germany became
distinguished for its great legal historians, as jurists soon turned
their attentions from "living law" to the law of the ancient Romans
and the German peoples. Not until 1896 did Germany adopt the
Code Civil, which became effective on January 1, 1900.7
One legal scholar has suggested that "Savigny might have
spared himself the trouble.of replying to Thibaut" because "[tihe
creation of a unified national law was then a political impossibility,
f6r there were no legislative organs in the German confederation
capable of accomplishing the task. '7 2 But this statement only
seems to buttress what Savigny said in opposing codification in the
first place. The same scholar also found it ironic that two decades
later it was Savigny who was entrusted with the work of codifica-
tion and that nothing came of the project. 73 However, it would be
doing Savigny an injustice here to assert that he simply opposed
any codification or legislation, 74 for he only opposed codification
for the Germany of his time. Indeed, he was not content with
merely negating 6odification in his Beruf, but even went so far as
to set down his own program for legal development in the German
75
states .
Savigny's constructive proposals for the development of the
German law involved the mastery of three sets of legal materials.
The first was the original Roman law, which was to serve as an
historical base and a model of refined techniques upon which the
jurists could build. Savigny emphasized the importance here of
"the confirmed habit of viewing every notion and every doctrine
in its proper historical light." The second, taking into account
continuity of experience, was the material of the less cultivated
Germanic law, as it was intimately related to the German people.
Finally, he included a modification of these two primary systems
of Roman and local law, believing that jurists should purge all
those materials 'produced through the mere ignorance and dull-
ness of uncultivated times without any real practical demand for
it." Savigny was convinced that once his program was executed,
the burden of German legal heritage could then-and only
then-be turned to a national advantage, resulting in acquisition
of a vigorous7 legal system, not "merely a feeble imitation" of the
Roman law. 1
Then, too, may future degenerate times be provided for and then
will be the time for considering whether this will be done best by
codes or in another form .
Although he might have doubted whether a code would ever be
desirable from a practical standpoint, Savigny always held out
hope for some future codification, his later works extending the
program he outlined in Vom BerufunsrerZeit. These works helped
73. Id.
74. For a discussimn of the question as to whether Savigny did deny the efficacy of
conscious creative legislation in general, see SOCIAL DIMENSIONS at 98-99.
75. FUNCTION OF LAW at 435-36.
76. Id. at 435-37.
77. Id. at 437.
COMMENTARY
engrossed in the source of the law that he forgot all about its
stream."8
After his history was completed, Savigny's next venture was
that of authoring a more elaborate treatise on the system of mod-
ern Roman law, System des heutigen romischen Rechts. This work
contained Savigny's theory of private international law and his
further study on possession and error.89 It was not, however, a text
on Roman law per se, for System only dealt with those parts of
the law which had been adapted to German life and modified by
German institutions. This being the case, Roman Criminal law and
all law not compiled before Justinian were, of course, excluded
because they had not been so "naturalized." 9 Given Savigny's life-
long preoccupation with the adaptation of Roman law to modern
conditions, he wished to discuss in hhese volumes how the Roman
law had taken root and grown in the soil of modern European
society." In sum, hherefore, this work represented an exposition on
that which Savigny had made his life's work: development of a
Roman Gemeinesrecht for Germany. Not without profound influ-
ence, the treatise was regarded as "a masterpiece of analytical
jurisprudence of a particular system." More importantly, System
was part of Savigny's program for bringing the law of modern
Germany into a better form through mastery of the legal materials
he had found to be wanting.
V. OTHER LATER WORKS AND LEGACY
upon them.17
In conclusion, it seems appropriate to quote the caveat which
Savigny left for future legal scholars when he noted that the study
of law was
of its very nature exposed to a double danger; that of soaring
through theory into empty abstractions of a fancied law of na-
ture, and that of sinking through practice into a soulless, unsatis-
factory handicraft.9 8