The Great Philosophers - Nodrm
The Great Philosophers - Nodrm
The Great Philosophers - Nodrm
GENERAL PSYCHOPATHOLOGY
THE GREAT
PHILOSOPHERS
The Original Thinkers
PUBLIC
Copyright © 1957, 1964 by R. Piper & Co. Verlag, Miinchen y ^J^ m ^^L*
English translation copyright (c) 7966 by Har court, Brace & World, Inc.
"Nicholas of Cusa"
was originally published in Germany as Nil{plaus Cusanus;
the rest of this book, as part of
Die grossen Philosophen J.
and A. & C. Black Ltd. For the quotations from The Way of Lao Tzu, trans-
lated by Wing-tsit Chan, copyright © 1963, The Bobbs-Merrill Company,
Inc. For the quotations from Plotinus: The Enneads (third edition), trans-
lated by Stephen MacKenna, Faber and Faber Ltd. and Pantheon Books, a
Division of Random House, Inc. For the quotations from Plato and Par-
menides, translated with Introduction and running commentary by Francis
Macdonald Cornford, Humanities Press and Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd.
For the quotations from Benedict de Spinoza The Chief Wor\s, 2 volumes,
:
INTRODUCTION J
ANAXIMANDER 9
HERACL1TUS
1. The logos jy
2. Struggle, the salutary way 20
3. Characterization 23
4. Influence 23
PARMENIDES
1. Being 2$
2. The world of appearance 28
3. The decision 29
4. The insoluble difficulties 30
5. Influence 31
PLOT/MJS
I. Life and works 38
c. The categories 41
d. Spirit, soul, nature 42
e. Descent and ascent 43
V. Speculative Transcending 56
1. The categories 57
2. Categorial transcending 58
3. Transcending in images of the All 69
ANSELM
I. Life and Works 93
NICHOLAS OF CUSA
Introduction 116
Life iij
Works ug
PART ONE: PHILOSOPHICAL SPECULATION 120
I. God 164
1. Dialogue on the hidden God 164
2. On speculation 765
4. Individuals 188
tions" 201
SPINOZA
I. Life and Works 273
unity 291
V. Man 30J
a. Man is not substance but mode 30J
b. Human and divine thinking 308
c. Man is mind and body 30S
LAO-TZU
Life and Works 388
NAGARJUNA
I. The Operations of Thought 416
Summary of the Doctrine 420
BIBLIOGRAPHY 43$
ANAXIMANDER
HERACLITUS
PARMENIDES
PLOTINUS
ANSELM
NICHOLAS OF CUSA
SPINOZA
LAO-TZU
NAGARTUNA
INTRODUCTION
Ever since Kant revolutionized philosophy with his critique and the meth-
ods of modern scientific knowledge became clear, metaphysics has seemed
questionable. Many have rejected its speculations and constructions, and in
And indeed, honest metaphysical thinking can no longer have the same
form and content as before. Today any attempt to think in disregard of
Kantian critique and of cogent scientific knowledge can only end in con-
fusion. In our intellectual situation a metaphysics in the old style, considered
as knowledge of being, as a revelation of what underlies all being and
happening, can only degenerate into a brand of magic which, failing to see
through its illusions, follows in the groove of the older metaphysics, but
loses its earnestness. Where preconceived forms are not subjected to the
critical scrutiny that has become indispensable, they lead to an artificial
thinking without roots in existence. It is as though phantoms with a
strangely seductive appearance of life drank the blood of those who, afflicted
by their emptiness, hoped to find themselves by surrendering to the old
systems. Having exerted its seduction, the ghost vanishes. It is not a reality
elucidated through the existence of those who think it.
grounding can provide no guidance but merely fosters the historicist illu-
sion of a scientific metaphysics developing progressively despite interrup-
tions and setbacks. is based on the assumption that these
Such an approach
and solved; it presupposes an objective
are problems that can be investigated
standard by which the truth and error of metaphysical ideas down through
history might be judged with universal validity, as though they were scien-
tific statements.
A radically different approach is rooted in a metaphysical awareness which
goes back to the grounds and finds itself again in knowledge. The true
metaphysical discussion to which it gives rise is guided by a fundamental
knowledge with the help of which it re-enacts the questions and possible
answers, the arguments and counter-arguments, the decisions and questions
that have been left open. Such discussion finds what is always identical in
the divergent material; it sees all things in the light of this fundamental
knowledge, which it amplifies in the play of conceptual modifications,
elucidating the most meaningful ciphers of the various systems. Anyone who
expects to arrive at results resembling scientific findings will be disappointed.
To recapitulate metaphysical speculations in their original spirit is not a
scientific operation.
truth.
It is only through the earnestness of such metaphysics that a philos-
opher could attain to a realm where religion him by Church
as defined for
and cult, by holy sites, days, objects and dogmas, became
and books, by rites
superfluous for him, even if he did not reject it or combat it. In certain in-
stances the concepts of a philosophy that enabled a man to live by his own
reason and his immediate bond with transcendence were taken over by the
theological thinking of the Church and became instrumental in constitut-
ing Church dogma (e.g., Plotinus). Sometimes the ideas are subjected to
the requirements of Church authority and claimed as a part of it, or else
the philosophy was combated as inimical by the Church (Spinoza), re-
viled, subjected to all manner of suspicion, and suppressed by force when
possible. For a true philosophical independence built on the certainty of
God proper to the human reason is far worse than heresy and other, com-
peting religions. Authoritarian Church religion treats such an adversary
either as though he did not exist, or else it transforms his thinking into a
INTRODUCTION y
coherent whole. And he was also the first thinker to develop, in concepts,
a metaphysical vision transcending all sense perception; the first to give the
name of the Divine to what is achieved in the fundamental thinking that
transcends all that exists, or, in other words, to find the divine with the
help of thought, instead of accepting it as given in traditional religious
conceptions. He was the first Greek to find in prose the appropriate form
in which to communicate such insights. And he effected all these momentous
innovations of human consciousness quietly, without polemics against any-
one.
His point was an empirical knowledge which, by primitive
starting
standards, was already considerable. It provided him with material for
projections that reached out ahead of what he knew. Based on the notion
of proportional reduction, his map of the earth was a speculative geometrical
construction filled in with the meager and diffuse data supplied by Ionian
navigators. Thus it was soon superseded as more reliable data became avail-
able. The greatness lay in the general conception and in the discovery of a
9
io The Original Thinkers
earth but also the cosmos as a whole —he did so without empirical proofs,
on the basis of his inner vision, proceeding in accordance with the un-
formulated principle that the whole cosmos in all its parts must be subject
to the same spatial and numerical relations as the things we perceive around
us. In his view the earth has the shape of a cylinder, a kind of truncated
column, its thickness equal to one-third the diameter of its surface. We live
on the one surface. The earth is suspended in the center of the cosmos, at
rest because there is nothing to cause it to move. Around it the heavens form
a sphere (and no longer a bowl), or rather, three concentric spheres, the
sphere of the stars, which is closest to the earth,and those of the moon and
the sun, at intervals of 9, 18, and 27 diameters of the earth. There is no
absolute above and below.
This world came into being. After the separation of hot and cold, a part
of the cold damp interior was transformed into vapor by the heat of the
fiery sphere, and the vapor split the fiery sphere into rings. These rings
cloaked in vapor have breathing holes through which the flames shine. These
are the stars, the moon, and the sun. On the earth everything was at first
moist. The sun dried out some of the moisture. The evaporation created
wind. The remaining moisture was the sea, which became smaller and
smaller and will, in the end, disappear altogether. Eclipses of the heavenly
bodies occur when the air holes are temporarily stopped up; the phases of
the moon and reopening of the holes (Burnet).
are caused by a slow closing
Living creatures sprang from the moisture.The first were encased in a
prickly bark. Some moved to the dry land, the bark fell away, and they
changed their form of life. Man developed from animals of another species.
For if he had been originally as he is now, he would never have survived.
Unlike the animals, who from birth can find their food by themselves, he
alone requires a long period of suckling. Originally, says Anaximander,
man was similar to a fish.
There are innumerable worlds such as ours, coexisting at equal intervals;
and all these worlds, including ours, come into being and pass away in
periodic recurrence. The destruction of our world will be followed by a
regeneration.
Such views are imputed to Anaximander by other writers. Only one
sentence, though introduced in indirect discourse, is quoted verbatim, and
its content is entirely different. This venerable monument runs: Anaximander
said that "the material cause and first element (arche) of existing things
was the infinite (apeiron); but the source from which existing things derive
their existence is also that to which they return at their destruction according
to necessity; for they must pay the penalty and make atonement to one
another for their injustice according to Time's decree." This sentence
formulates a metaphysical vision. We do not know whether it is a maxim
or, as seems likelier, fragment of a larger exposition. In attempting to
a
understand it we —
are under a disadvantage we cannot help operating with
ANAX1MANDER n
the rigid concepts of later times and with our own thinking; nevertheless,
with the help of what other ancient authors have written about Anaximander,
let us attempt an interpretation.
i. What arc existing things {ta onto)} Everything: the events and con-
ditions in the polis, the stars, the water, the earth, men and animals, the
totality of present things.
things originated, according to the earlier Thales. But water was visibly
present in the world. Anaximander took the leap to positing a source that
was not only invisible but could not even be defined. Aristotle interprets:
The one cannot be a part of what springs from it (as in the case of water). It
cannot be a particular thing — if it were a particular thing, the whole could
not spring from it. It must encompass (periechein) everything, it cannot be
becoming would have an end. In order that becoming should not cease, the
ground of becoming must be infinite, inexhaustible. It is the origin of all
and has itself no origin. Accordingly Anaximander calls the apeiron immortal
and indestructible. Unlike all things in the world {ta onta) which come and
go, it is everlasting.
3. How are the things (of the worlds) related to the apeiron? Simplicius
writes: Anaximander "did not attribute the genesis of things to any change
in matter but said that the opposites were differentiated in the substrate,
which is an unlimited body." The differentiation of opposites is the origin
of existing things. It seems futile to inquire further how oppositions arise
in the imperishable apeiron that has been said to be free from opposition.
The oppositions within existing things are as such insuperable. Even as
I inquire, I am in them. I arrive at no better understanding by distinguishing
an "eternal motion" that leads to oppositions from the motion in the
existing, perpetually changing world. The emergence of things from the
apeiron and their return to it might perhaps be distinguished from the
emergence of things from one another. But whether we conceive of the
apeiron according to later concepts as matter (with which, however, no
form is contrasted), or as empty space (though without any energy to fill
it), or, in accordance with the earlier view, as chaos — its essential character-
that while free from opposition, it is the source of oppositions. The
istic is
world comes into being with the opposition between hot and cold. When
the oppositions annul one another, the world will have ceased to be. The
totality of things already in opposition {ta onta) is called physis. Physis is
destroy one another: hot and cold, air and water, light and darkness. The
predominance of one is injustice to the other. Hence they must make
atonement to one another. But the apeiron does not participate in this
struggle.
In this view certain authors (Nietzsche, Rohde) have seen an allusion
to the guilt that comes of individualization, the fall from grace involved
in entering existence: man's greatest guilt is having been born (Calderon).
conflicting things by making them atone for their wrongs to one another. In
the polis justice is administered and the penalty appointed by the judge.
Taking this reality as his guide, Solon taught the existence of a more en-
compassing dike, which is no longer dependent on human jurisdiction, for
it will inevitably be fulfilled in the course of time. The power of Dike is
pantheon. With the sober detachment that enabled him to overturn all
existing views, he saw the divine in a new way, but in two forms: on the one
hand the apeiron, on the other, the plurality of worlds.
Interpretations in terms of crystallized concepts tend to see too much or
too little in Anaximander —his wealth of potential meaning far exceeds
all such interpretations. Beguiled by the hidden possibilities, subsequent
thinkers have found all sorts of ideas in Anaximander. Some of these
interpretations are demonstrably false, some can be shown to be possible, a
few can be definitely substantiated.
Anaximander is the earliest philosopher perceptible as a personality,
though we know him only as a shadow of himself. It was he who first
entered the realm where philosophy and science in their Western forms
became possible. The known contents of his thinking are no longer an
indispensable element of philosophy; what speaks to us is the magnificent
originality of his thinking. He is the first Western philosopher whose style
of thought bears an unmistakable stamp.
Anaximander's profound impression on us flows from the whole of
his thinking, in which we perceive the awakening of Western reason; the
veils of mist are dispersed and the light is born. To his new way of thinking
no one else had been able to think
the simplest things were revealed that
of before. Once the leap was made, man was able to reach out for the
knowledge that would change his world completely. What is so exciting
is the beginning as such. At this moment man first learned to look at
himself and the world with detachment; thought came into its own and
Wherever this thinker turns, his mind shows equal power: in his observa-
tion of the sensuous here and now, in technical invention, in his devising of
convincing demonstrations, in his use of a primitive mathematics, in ordering
his intuitions (even if and in the pure speculative
these are unverifiable) ,
thinking that carries himground of all being. With the same energy
into the
he encompasses speculation and the world, metaphysics and empirical
thinking. It is by one and the same mode of thought that he produced the
map of the earth and the celestial globe, discovered that the world hung
free in cosmic space, gave concrete form to his view of the genesis of the
worlds, conceived of all existing things as grounded in the apeiron, and
looked upon the apeiron as the divine. The mind of a great philosopher is
one. No factor may be removed. In every direction of his thinking, Anaxi-
mander discloses this unity; the independence of the individual, provided
by the Ionian became the independence of thought which came to
polis,
grips with the world and allowed things to show themselves as they are.
Here we see our own Western existence as it began, manifesting itself in a
—
grandiose prototype a miracle, but a miracle whose content is perfectly
self-evident and natural. Anaximander confronted the real world with
—
measurement, observation, reason in short, with the human intellect.
He had the courage to formulate speculative schemas that were subject to
verification; with his magnificent Ionian open-mindedness, he was alive
to all the possibilities of his world.
In the ensuing period, this comprehensive thought, erupting from a world
of myth, was to make movements: the pure
possible highly varied intellectual
speculation of Parmenides and Heraclitus, cosmic views of the world,
scientific inquiry.
HERACLITUS AND PARMENIDES
Both lived at the turn of the sixth century, Heraclitus in Ephesus (Asia
Minor), Parmenides in Elea (southern Italy). Since "the coming of the
Medes" the Greek world of Asia Minor had freedom and lived
lost its
under a constant threat that was to be averted only by the Persian Wars.
Anaximander's polis had undergone a change. It had ceased to enjoy un-
disturbed freedom in an open Mediterranean; the internal consequences
of the threat were first democracy, then tyranny. Elea was a colony of
Ionian Greeks who had fled from the Medes. This was the situation in
which Heraclitus and Parmenides, at opposite ends of the Greek world,
did their thinking; philosophically, both were rooted in the Ionian soil.
15
HERACLITUS
/. The logos. Heraclitus sets out to "put words and deeds to the test" by
explaining "things each by its own nature and pointing out the real state
of the case." Looking at the whole, he sees what is; he sees the "logos that
is everlasting"and what it does. "All things come to pass in accordance
with this logos." The logos pervades all things and encompasses the whole
of Heraclitus' thinking. Logos can neither be translated into any other
term nor defined as a concept. Logos can signify: word, discourse, content
of discourse, meaning; reason, truth; law; even Being. In Heraclitus it is
not defined; it carries all these meanings at once and is never limited to
any one of them. The logos is the Encompassing, undefined and endlessly
definable (like all the great and basic terms of philosophy).
Always implicit in the logos is the unity of opposites. "Men do not
understand how what is at variance agrees with itself. It is an attunement
of opposite tensions like that of the bow and the lyre." "The hidden harmony
is better than the visible."
The is stated abstractly: "Whole and not
idea of the unity of opposites
whole —drawing and drawing apart, concord and discord
together . . .
From all one and from one all." It is also formulated in concrete, sensuous
terms: "Cold things grow hot, hot things grow cold, the wet dries, the
17
1 The Original Thinners
dead, awake and asleep, young and old; the former by their changing
become the latter, and the latter in turn are changed and become the
former." Pleasure springs from its opposite: "Sickness makes health pleasant
and good, hunger satisfaction, weariness rest." "It recovers through change"
(or in a different translation: "In changing it takes its rest").
be no harmony without high and low, nor any living creatures without the
opposites male and female."
Everything we know we know through its opposite. We would not
know justice if there were no injustice. From different points of view, we
can form diametrically opposite ideas of one and the same thing: "In the
circumference of a circle beginning and end are." "For the fuller's screw,
the way, straight and crooked, is one and the same." "The way up and down
is one and the same." Sea water is life-giving (for fish) and destructive
(for men).
In the ground of things, all is one: "Immortals are mortal, mortals are
immortal; each lives the life of the other, and dies their life." Hades (death)
is the same as Dionysus (jubilant life) in whose honor they rave and perform
Heraclitus does not expressly distinguish the ways in which the opposites
are linked or the ways in which one shifts into the other; he does not
state clearly in what sense it is possible to speak of the identity of opposites.
Thus the logos is the unity of opposites. It is also the source of law (notnos).
Rational thought takes hold of logos and nomos. Therein lies wisdom
(to sophon).
The logos is the essence of the world and the soul
The cosmological notions developed by the Milesian thinkers provide
Heraclitus with the material by which to apprehend the logos in the world.
He was not interested in concrete investigation, but only in discerning
the operation of logos and nomos in the world. For him fire is not merely
one state of matter, side by side with water andwhich the natural
air (in
philosophers found the substance of things), but the symbol, and at the same
time, the reality of world, life, and soul. Fire is the cause of cosmic order,
// E R A C LIT U S 19
presides over all happening. "Nature (physis) likes to hide." All that
happens is ordered according to the logos, even when men fail to know it
and act against But the logos can be manifested to man's reason. It is
it.
God's power is everywhere: "The things that crawl are protected by God's
whiplash." No one can escape it. "How can anyone hide from that which
never sets?"
The views of God and man are fundamentally different and incommensur-
able: "To God all men have
things are beautiful, good, and just; but
assumed some things to be unjust, others just." Men and gods are not, as
in the traditional Greek religion, taken as beings of the same kind (dis-
tinguished only by mortality and immortality). Man is completely and essen-
tially different from God.
2. Struggle, the salutary way. Heraclitus' vision of God and the world
isno mere contemplation of eternal being; it is itself in the world, a struggle
against falsehood and evil, a proclamation of the salutary way.
Accordingly Heraclitus pictures what is false in the world. Most men
(hoi polloi) do not understand the logos. "They know not what they are
doing when awake, just as they forget what they do in sleep." Though they
are in constant association with the logos, they are at odds with it. What they
encounter every day remains strange to them, they succumb to illusion.
Nor does Heraclitus' teaching help them. "Even when they have heard, they
do not understand. . . . Present, they are absent. . .
." "Even when they
hear it, they fail to grasp; but they suppose they have understood."
Men are under illusion when they act, yet their actions follow the
hidden logos. "Those who sleep are fellow workers (in the activities of the
world)." Hence the twofold aspect of the human world: "Time is a child
playing a game of draughts; the kingship is in the hands of a child."
"Human opinions are the games of a child." But what is fortuitous and
meaningless to those who do not know is actually hidden order: "A heap of
rubble piled up at random is the fairest universe."
In ignorance of the logos but unconsciously obeying it, all things and
creatures perform the appropriate actions: "Pigs in mud, wash themselves
birds in dust or ashes." "Donkeys prefer chaff to gold." "A foolish man is
startled at every meaningful word (logos) ." "Dogs bark at those they do not
recognize."
In practice, Heraclitus' insight into life as community in conflict is his
struggle. He seems to attack everything in the world around him: the
inherited tradition, the prevailing religion, the men and doctrines hitherto
HERACLITUS 21
regarded as great, the political condition of his native city, the thoughtless
behavior of men impelled by their passions.
1. Against prevailing religion: "They purify themselves by staining them-
selves with other blood, as if one were to step into mud to wash off mud."
"They talk to statues (of the gods) as if one were to converse with buildings."
He threatens the "night revelers, magicians, Bacchants, Maenads and
Mystics" with punishment after death. For "the rites accepted by mankind
in the Mysteries are unholy."
But often Heraclitus points to the truth in religion. "He called the
shameful rites of the Mysteries remedies." He distinguished "two kinds of
sacrifice; the one is offered by the few who are inwardly purified, the
great. "Homer deserves to be thrown out of the contest and beaten; likewise
Archilochos." Hesiod, Pythagoras, Xenophanes, Hecataeus all show that
much knowledge does not confer reason. Pythagoras, in particular, read
many books and established a wisdom of his own; he was the ancestor of
all swindlers. What is the thing they called reason? "They put reliance in
street singers and their teacher is the populace, for they do not know that
the many are evil and that only few are good."
gance is more in need of quenching than fire." "He called self-conceit epi-
lepsy."
Heraclitus combats the false and gives instruction for a life in truth. The
philosopher of the logos bids man to be awake. "Men should not act and
speak as though asleep." We should knowingly follow the hidden logos
that binds all, not sink into the individual; nor should we let ourselves be
driven unconsciously by the logos; we should open ourselves to the uni-
versal and partake of it knowingly; deep within the logos we should find
the universal which is already there but becomes the common, unifying
bond only in being discovered.
In regard to the true life his teaching hinges on three points: i. Par-
ticipation in the logos of struggle. 2. Participation in the logos of knowledge.
3. Fundamental knowledge.
a) "Men should know thatwar is common to all." "War is king and father
of all. And some he has made gods and some men, some slaves and some
free." The victor is free, the vanquished is a slave, and he who falls in battle
is immortal. For "the best choose one thing above all else: everlasting fame
rather than things mortal." Those who fall in battle are "honored by gods
and men."
b) "The greatest perfection (arete) resides in thinking wisely (phronein) :
to speak the truth and to act in accordance with nature (physis) — this is
wisdom."
c) Wisdom does not reside in the heaping up of information, which
makes for dispersion and distracts one from authentic knowledge. But this
rejection of pseudo-erudition does not imply that knowledge is unnecessary:
"Men who love wisdom must inquire into very many things."
Nor does wisdom consist in speculative construction. Reason is revealed
in physical actuality. Heraclitus rejects the cosmic constructions of the Mi-
"Those things of which there is sight, hearing, and knowl-
lesian philosophers.
—
edge these I honor most." He seems to be relapsing into vulgar empiricism
when he says that the sun as it appears to us has the width of a human foot
and that the sun is born anew each day. But perhaps such statements were
merely intended to provoke. For elsewhere he doubts the value of sense
perception: "The ears and eyes are poor witnesses to men if they have bar-
barian souls."
Knowledge is guided by something that is more than knowledge. "Most
of what is divine escapes recognition through unbelief (apistia)" "If a man
does not hope, he will not find the unhoped for, since there is no trail lead-
ing to it and no path." This is the import of the moving words: "A man's
ethos (character) is his daimon," that is, not something that is merely given
by nature, but something more. The daimon who guides me is not a strange
being outside myself; it is myself as I authentically am, though I do not know
myself as such.
All knowledge of logos and nomos is summed up in this one statement:
// ERACL1TU S 23
"If we are to speak with intelligence (nous), we must build our strength on
that which is common to all, as the polis on the law, but even more so. All
human laws are nourished by one, which is divine; for it governs as far as it
being, free from contradiction (and no philosopher who has attempted such
a construction has ever succeeded). Confident in his profound insight,
Heraclitus dispensed it in intermittent flashes of light.
He has only to ask and the answers are present. The questions are not
developed; instead, the answers are proclaimed.
Heraclitus' ethos draws nourishment in thought from the ground of being,
the logos, wisdom. Such thinking is a challenge. It strives toawaken, but
counts on few, if any. Though the logos is common to all and can be made
manifest, there is between two conflicting tendencies in Heraclitus
a tension
he wishes to announce the logos to men, to make them aware of it and so to
lead them to a better communal life; but at the same time, faced with the
many who resist change, he resigns himself to solitary ineffectiveness, re-
nouncing all hope of actualizing his vision of the logos except in the proud
reality of his own life.
cellent, and I am certain that what I have not understood is also excellent
but it requires a Delian diver."
The Stoics cited the authority of Heraclitus. Hegel admired him. Karl
Marx's earliest work was devoted to him. Lassalle wrote a book about him.
Nietzsche praised him extravagantly.
Two of his ideas, the logos and the dialectic of opposites, have had an
extraordinary influence, though his name has not always been explicitly
related to them.
i. The an enormous role since Anaxi-
principle of opposition has played
mander. was taken up by the Pythagoreans and Parmenides. But only in
It
Heraclitus did it become the dominant form of thought. All Western dialec-
tic goes back to Heraclitus and the successors of Parmenides. Heraclitus did
not systematically distinguish the modes of opposition; he lets them play side
by side and converge: contradiction, opposition, dichotomy, polarity, tension;
the whole-the part, unity-multiplicity, harmony-discord; life-death, wak-
ing-sleep, day-night. He did not differentiate the ways in which opposites
shift into one another, the modes of reversal, of dialectic movement in the
logical and in the real worlds. He expressed the notion of the opposites with
all the means at his disposal, including puns. Since Heraclitus touched upon
and to this day has not been elucidated in full systematic clarity.
In reference to Heraclitus, Aristotle wrote: Nature too seems to strive
toward the opposite; it produces harmony from opposites, not from likes:
for example, the male sex mates with the female. In painting, white is mixed
with black, yellow with red; in music high and low, long and short tones
are mingled to produce a unitary harmony; in the art of writing, vowels are
mingled with consonants.
Hegel claimed to have incorporated every one of Heraclitus' sayings in
his logic. And it is perfectly true that Hegel, with the help of the intervening
two thousand years of philosophical thought, developed his dialectic, or sys-
tem of the categories of opposition, from what first made its appearance in the
thinking of Heraclitus.
2. The Her-
Stoics (beginning in the third century b.c.) interpreted the
aclitean logos as all-pervading cosmic reason and
For Philo (c. 25 b.c. to
fate.
a.d. 50) the logos was the power of reason dwelling with God; it was the
first son of God, the second God, the mediator between God and man: the
word, God's eternal thought which created the world. In the Gospel of
St. John (second half of the first century) and from then on in Christian
theology the logos has been personalized as the incarnate word of God;
born into the world in Jesus, the logos is the second person of God.
Heraclitus had conceived the logos as a thought that opens the way to new
insights and extends man's horizons. In these historical transformations
it was objectivized, frozen into a philosophical doctrine.
PARMENIDES
Parmenides was a citizen of Elea, in southern Italy, at the turn of the sixth
century b.c. He came of a wealthy and distinguished family. Some one
hundred and thirty verses of his work in hexameters have been preserved.
The introduction to his poem relates the thinker's journey to the heavens:
as a young man, he mounts the chariot of the sun maidens, who drive him
from night to daylight, so swiftly that the axle "gave forth a pipe-like sound";
at the boundary between the two, they pass through a gate which Dike
opens for them, and he is led into the presence of the goddess, who receives
him graciously. From her lips he learns the truth "And now you must study :
all things: not only the unshaken heart of well-rounded truth (aletheia)
but also mortals' opinions (doxa), in which there is no true reliance." Accord-
ingly, the goddess' communication, and with it the poem, falls into two parts.
Considerable fragments of the first part and a few reports concerning the
second part have come down to us.
/. Being. The first fundamental idea is: "It is necessary to say and to think
that being is, for it is possible for it to be, but it is not possible for 'nothing' to
be." "Thou could'st not know that which is not nor utter it." "For never
shall this be proved: that things that are not are." In terms of formal logic:
being is or is not; its nonbeing, all nonbeing, is unthinkable; therefore
being is and nonbeing is not.
Especially in the original Greek, these lines can either seem wonderfully
meaningful or else startlingly empty. They bear witness to a profound emo-
tion and yet they state only tautologies. For the first time in the West a thinker
expresses his surprise that being is, that it is impossible to think that nothing
is. His statement of what most obvious is perfectly clear and at the same
is
time supremely puzzling. Being is and nothing is not; this, for Parmenides,
25
26 The Original Thinners
tinction to the false way, which is to think nonbeing), many signs (semata)
of being are disclosed. They follow
from the process of thinking:
necessarily
It is No
unborn. what birth of it wilt thou look
origin can be found. "For
for? In what way and whence did it grow?" Not from any existing thing,
for then there would be another, pre-existing being. Not from any non-
existent thing, for then there would be no cause or necessity impelling it to
spring sooner or later from nothingness and begin to grow. Only nothing
can spring from nothingness. Hence being must either be whole or not at
all. If it had been born at some time, it would not authentically be. Nor is it
limited to the future. In it, rather, becoming and passing away are annulled.
It is imperishable. It was not nor will be, "since it is now all at once, one, con-
tinuous."
Being is one, always identical, of equal power, cohesive. Being is insepar-
ably close to being. It is not sometimes stronger and sometimes weaker;
rather, it is everywhere wholly filled with being and indivisible. It is being
(on, so first used by Parmenides), not a multiplicity of existing things (onta,
as was said before Parmenides).
It is unique. For there is nothing and will be nothing outside of being.
It is whole. It is the extreme limit, hence complete on all sides. In other
words, it is not something to be ended (thus it is not endless), or to be com-
pleted.It is comparable to a sphere. "It is immovable in the limits of its
re-enacted and the experience of peace in being is attained. Along with nec-
essary contradiction and identity, the semata are images of thought not
based on visual perception. Parmenides' fundamental statement is not an
empty identity, but understood solely in its logical form, it is objectively
empty. It is a thinking action which was possible in the naivete (not primitiv-
ism) of creative beginning; it is though we cannot recapture
still possible,
the old candor. Logic and being merged, and both were unfolded in thought.
Logic was not yet empty because it was not yet intended as logic. Accord-
PARMEN1DES 27
ingly, the vision is not a metaphor, but a necessary part of the thought.
The tone of this thought is compounded of a compelling, imperious logic
and of jubilant certainty in the ground of all things. The inexplicable is
knows that his path leads "far from the path of mortals," and that to attain
it through Themis and Dike is a happy lot in contrast to the unhappy lot of
ignorant mankind. The story of the journey to the heavens, from darkness
into light, is not poetic ornament, but the sensuous, imaged form of the
thought itself: truth is imparted, divine powers help lead the thinker to the
goddess who communicates the pure truth; his own yearning for truth has
itself this divine character. It is not a long, slow journey, but swift and sud-
which though far off are yet surely present to thought. For you cannot cut
off being from holding fast to being." Thus in thought (the nous) being
itself is present as a whole; the absent is also present.
The greatness of Parmenides' conception of being is lost if we attempt to
put into it what is not truly his own. Measured by the logical richness of the
differentiated categories or the perceptual richness of the world, Parmenides'
being is so poor that it vanishes. For his boldly transcending thinking of this
being is directed toward an imageless pre-categorial, or trans-categorial
realm; yet transcendence in Parmenides is not somewhere else, it is wholly
28 The Original Thinners
present. But this presence does not lie in the plenitude of the sensuous, tem-
poral world. The radical distinction that gives Parmenides' thinking its
power is between the seriousness of being and the trivial world of opinion.
Parmenides' "thinking" of "being" is clarified by contrasts
In sharpest opposition to Anaximander's apeiron, this being is comparable
to a sphere bound by limits (peirata). Being is not apeiron but
and is
But in this they erred. These are mere names, established in the language
of deluded mortals who believe them to be true, as they believe of becoming
and passing-away, being and nonbeing, change of place and variation of
bright color, etc.: "Thus therefore, according to opinion, were these things
created and are now, and shall hereafter grow and then come to an end.
And from these things men have established a name as a distinguishing
mark for each."
Few details of Parmenides' cosmology have come down to us. As in
Anaximander, there were spheres occupied by fire, sun and moon, earth
and life. But in the middle is the goddess who governs all. First she created
Eros. Everywhere the goddess incites to mating. "Cruel birth and mating."
But why is there not only the one truth ? Why is there a world of appearance
and not only being? We find no answer in Parmenides other than the
description of the error. We can only construct an answer in the spirit of
j. The decision. Parmenides demands decision (\risis) between the two ways,
the way of truth (the thinking of being) and of error (the thinking of non-
being). But since the thinking of nonbeing is impossible, he has no more
to say about it. The great ubiquitous error, disastrous for all men, is a third
possibility, halfness, themixture of thinking of being and thinking of noth-
ing. Those mortals who know nothing wander on this way, "two-headed,
for perplexity guides the wandering thought in their breasts, and they are
borne along, both deaf and blind, bemused, as undiscerning hordes, who
have determined to believe that it is and is not, the same and not the same,
and for whom there is a way of all things that turns back upon itself." Here
Parmenides reduces the average man's opinion, lacking in self-awareness, to
its essential meaning, or rather unmeaning, in formulas that are to be found
The sun maidens (divine powers) drive the young man in their chariot
from the world of night world of light; and at the limit between
to the
the two, he is admitted by Dike, who opens the gate. What is revealed to
him within, the day, the light, pertains to the truth of being; what he has
left behind him, the darkness, the night, pertains to opinion and appear-
ance, that is, nonbeing. But in addition he learns that the difference between
day and night is itself appearance. From out of the realm of appearance,
remaining within appearance, he hears what makes even his ascent to the
light illusory.
This difficulty stands at the very beginning of speculative philosophy:
in the course of its operations, the philosopher's undertaking is destroyed
by the very truth it attains. In arriving at truth, philosophy meets failure
and vanishes. It speaks at the cost of departing from the truth it has already
gained.
Or to put the same thing in a different way: if we think something, we
must same time think something else, from which the first something
at the
ceases to be an opposition, for nothingness is not, only being is. With the
P ARM EN DES I 31
true thought of the one perfect being, free from opposition, the other
vanishes. If we take the true way, we perceive that it is the only way, that
there is no other. Where Parmenides thinks being, there is no longer a
decision. The imperative of transcending thought drives the thinker beyond
opposition into the realm where there is no opposition.
Yet interpret as we is not refuted. But far from destroy-
will, the objection
Thus what was originally a whole broke down into separate parts: first
logic, which sets forth compelling formal relationships; secondly, meta-
physical speculation, which looks upon itself as a methodical game that
makes the profoundly serious communicable; thirdly, the aesthetic view of
being and the world, the intellectual frivolity which traces an endless
variety of figures of thought, none of them binding.
content, not only effecting logical operations according to rules, but that
thinking puts us into the very midst of being. Thought is the reality in
which the whole of being is actualized as such. Being itself thinks.
Only when this thesis had been stated thus radically did it become
possible to oppose it and to ask whether being and thinking must not, on
the contrary, be conceived as separate if we are to discern the relation
between them (it was Kant who first stated this position with full clarity).
From this point of view, thought can no longer apprehend being, but can
gain valid insight only into certain manifestations of being, which are
accessible to it, while an intimation of being itself is conferred more by the
failure of thought than by our thinking of any thought content. Thinking
is no longer being, but a human activity oriented toward being. The idea
that being itselfis thinking becomes a cipher and ceases to be literal reality.
certainway be. The question of why being is and nothing is not attained
itsmost penetrating formulation in Schelling: Why is there something
and not nothing?
In order to fill out the thought of being, academic thinkers defined it
and determined its fundamental modes. In the seventeenth century, after
such thinking had been going on for two thousand years, it became known
as ontology. Parmenides' thinking is the beginning of "ontology," but in
the dogmatic, academic forms of ontology his provocative meaning was
lost.
Parmenides does not call being God. But what he conceived as the
5.
being and the illusion of the world, was later fixated in the so-called
theory of the two worlds. This became possible once a certain independent
reality was imputed to nature, i.e. the world of illusion, once illusion became
a natural phenomenon, i.e. an appearance, while being became a tran-
scendent realm, another being, a second world, a "world behind the
world." With this the Parmenidean unity of being and knowledge was
transformed into a dualism which, in a variety of forms, has run through
all Western history.
Thanks to the radicalism of his propositions and the acuteness of his
challenge, Parmenides was the great point of departure. Through him
thought achieved self-awareness as an independent power; compelling
in its conclusions, it unfolded its potentialities and so attained to the limits
—
where thought incurs failure a failure which Parmenides did not discern,
but which he invited with the enormous demand he made upon thought.
In the Theaetetus Plato erected a monument to Parmenides, whom he
regarded as the greatest of the pre-Socratic philosophers: "Parmenides is
there was a sort of depth in him that was altogether noble. I am afraid we
might not understand his words and still less follow the thought they
express." Nietzsche, on the other hand, sensed the extraordinary in Par-
menides and thought he understood it, but did not. He speaks of the "type
of a prophet of the truth, who seems however to be made, not of fire but of
ice," of "absolutely bloodless abstraction," of a "mind which logical rigidity
2. The common new element in their thinking. Essentially they achieved the
same thing, but by different means: Parmenides with logical identity and the
exclusion of the contradictory, Heraclitus with the dialectic that encompasses
contradictions. Both were alive to the power of pure thought; their thinking
is not determined by sense perception and concrete observation, which they
used merely as a language in which to clothe their meaning. Always by
rational means, both performed an operation that is not only rational.
They discovered the possibility of a thinking that transcends all knowledge
of the world, that looks into the world from somewhere else. They both
looked upon this thinking as the absolute truth.
Both took great pains in the molding of their language, seeking simplicity
and concentrating on the essential. This was the period of the severe
"archaic" style in sculpture and of the beginnings of Attic tragedy.
Parmenides wrote epic hexameters, Heraclitus wrote prose in the manner
of the ancient maxims of wisdom. The solemnity of Parmenides' poetry
has its counterpart in the dignity of Heraclitus' prose. Within the traditional
forms, both devised a new style. There had never been poetry like that of
4. Pure thought. Both move in the newly won area of pure thought.
Measured by the standards of definite, empirical object thinking, such think-
ing is incomprehensible. Its statements seem to say nothing. Others have
praised this mode of thinking, piously repeating its solemn figures, discern-
36 The Original Thinkers
prophetic self-certainty. Though they invoked not the authority of God, but
the force of their own insight, this insight was total and overpowering.
Parmenides puts it into the mouth of the goddess and Heraclitus, though
invoking no divinity, deposited his work in the temple of Artemis at Ephesus.
Both saw the source of their truth not in the voice of God but in the compell-
ing power of thought. The essential is not obedience to a divine word, but
revelation through thinking. Having discovered the truth by their own re-
sources, they felt far superior to other men. Favored with an unprecedented
insight, with an absolute certainty that made all further questions superfluous,
they took the attitude of intellectual tyrants. They knew their utterances to
be the language of being. Through their mouth spoke Truth itself, inspired
by the goddess (in Parmenides' image) or by all-pervading world reason
(in Heraclitus' conception). They saw an unbridgeable gulf between their
insight into the ground of things and the manner of thinking common to
other men. Thus, though their writings show a desire to convince and in-
fluence, they stood alone, beyond communication. They demanded obedience,
not friendship. They realized the form of existence of the solitary aristocratic
thinker, enhancing the aristocratic privilege conferred by right of birth
with the new claim to intellectual superiority. The self-sufficiency bestowed
by their certainty of being implied the right to dominate all others through
the truth which they alone had recognized.
Their attitude toward other thinkers was one of boundless arrogance.
Heraclitus cites many illustrious names, all with the most violent condem-
nation. Parmenides mentions no names, but seems to have disposed with
the utmost contempt even of Heraclitus (if Bernays is right) or of Anaxi-
mander (if Reich is right). Their work is permeated by exclusion, antago-
nism, a furious aggressiveness. There is a despotic spirit in both men.
With all the greatness of their insight, they failed to understand the nature
of such insight.
PARMENIDES 37
to us, belongs to the dead past. It is Heraclitus and Parmenides who gave
us the first texts with which we can still With their
directly philosophize.
simplicity, they arouse inexhaustible thought. The elucidation of their mean-
ing confronts us as an endless task. Here we find propositions that are as
actual and timeless as only great philosophy can be.
Nevertheless, these two, the earliest philosophers whose writings still
exert an Whereas
influence, can also mislead. Anaximander brought about
a revolutionary upheaval in man's thinking attitude toward things and
examined all the possibilities with universal openness, these two limited
their scope to metaphysics which they proclaimed to be the only true knowl-
edge. In so doing, they succumbed to a new prejudice, magnificent in its
way but dangerous. For though their speculation was deeper and clearer
than any that preceded it, even that of Anaximander, they showed nothing
but incomprehension and contempt for all the thought which, by virtue
of its intellectual weight and creative potentialities, was pregnant with the
future, condemning it as pseudo-knowledge or false erudition, fortunately
for us, in vain. For in our temporal existence the only way to follow
the marvelous paths that Heraclitus and Parmenides pointed out is to
assume the tasks of mankind and not haughtily to brush aside the realms
of politics and science and close our eyes to the world.
PLOTINUS
hoarse and blind, his hands and feet festered. His remaining students
avoided him, "since he still insisted on greeting everyone at close quarters."
He was isolated on the estate of his friend Zethos in Campania. Only his phy-
sician went to see him. He attached little importance to the care of his body.
He died two years after Gallienus at the age of sixty-six.
Even Porphyry, in his biography, tells strange stories about Plotinus, re-
calling the lives of the saints: he possessed a superior knowledge of spirits.
He could identify a thief in a crowd. He could predict what would happen to
young men in later life. A certain Olympius attempted by the use of magical
formulas to bring down the harmful influence of the stars on Plotinus.
Plotinus saw what was happening and the harm fell on Olympius. An
Egyptian priest decided to conjure up Plotinus' daimon in the temple of
Isis. "When the daimon was called, a god appeared. Happy art thou," said
the Egyptian, "who hast a god for a daimon and no guardian spirit of low
degree." A friend came to see Plotinus on his deathbed. When Plotinus told
him he would try to make his "divine-in-us" rise up to the divine-in-the-
universe, a snake glided under the bed and disappeared into a hole in the
wall. Plotinus was dead. (The snake was one of the forms taken by the soul
as it left the room of one who had just died.) Plotinus' own writings show
that he was utterly indifferent to magic. But soon after his death his philos-
ophy was appropriated by magical and theurgic sects, who wove such
legends into his biography.
The wor\: Plotinus and two other disciples were said to have pledged
themselves to keep the teachings of Ammonios secret. The others had broken
silence. It was only late in life, at the age of forty-nine, that Plotinus, in
response to the urgent pleas of his students, began to write. After his death,
Porphyry collected his work. He divided it into six groups of nine treatises
(Enneads). The whole work was written during a period of seventeen years.
According to Porphyry, the chronological order is established for some of
the groups.
Some of the writings are didactic treatises, others are brief lectures;
some seem carefully constructed, others are long critical exchanges; some are
vivid descriptions of intellectual visions, others ask question upon question,
present possibilities, and leave almost everything undecided. This "inquiring"
style also expresses meditative action, the presence of the thinking soul in
the realm of the essential. The same metaphysical mood pervades all the
writings. Not infrequently the style takes on a note of religious solemnity.
In addressing the logical faculty of speculative insight, Plotinus adjures the
40 The Original Thinners
a. Matter and the One: The world is being. It is not self-grounded but is
b. The scale of beings: The scale of beings extends from the Above-Being of
the One to the nonbeing of matter; in its center is the soul. The soul looks
upward toward the One through the intermediary of the nous (the spirit,
the intelligible world of pure forms) and downward toward matter through
the intermediary of nature (the corporeal world). Thus there are five de-
scending principles: the One, the spirit, the soul, nature, matter. Being em-
braces the three middle stages: spirit, soul, nature.
In the looking-upward of rational insight, the soul sees the timeless, self-
(the cosmos of the spirit). These forms are called Ideas. They are the
archetypes of all existing things, and as such they are true Being, while
everything that comes after them is a mere copy, having only apparent
Being.
In its looking-downward, the soul becomes the world-soul which gives
life to nature as a whole, while individual souls give living unity to all the
many beings. Entering into nature, which is spatial and temporal, the souls
become in part spatial and temporal. But in their true Being they are above
nature, timeless and immortal. In the course of natural existence, the soul
is wrapped in veils and ultimately, in its lowest descent, is hidden from
itself, but its innermost essence remains indestructible.
matter is the counterpart of the logos of spirit, not of the Supreme One.
For Plotinus there is only the One, whence beings are engendered and to
which they return in an eternal process.
d. Spirit, soul, nature are the three intermediate realms, the realms of being.
Though the one is above it, the spirit (nous) is true being. It is the timeless
life of the pure forms (archetypes or ideas). It is thought; therefore in the
spirit thinking and the object it confronts coincide; thinking and Being
become identical. The spirit does not think an Idea as something alien, but
as itself. It is self-consciousness. But since this self-thinking implies a
cleavage between thinking and its object, the spirit contains both the One
and the Other the : spirit is unity in multiplicity.
The spirit is praised as the most beautiful of all things. It dwells in pure
light. It embraces all being, of which the beautiful world of nature is
gives them life or departs from them. But the world as a whole does
not cease, because the spirit and the world-soul shine forever.
e. Descent and ascent: The question now arises: Why this descent from the
One? Why are the spirit, the soul, nature, matter? Plotinus' answers, though
abounding in formulations of the problem, ofTer no solution.
The One is motionless and self-sufficient. If there is something
a second
after it, it must come into being without any will or motion on the part of
the One. What comes after the One is an unwilled consequence. Those who
say that "the Creator decided at some time to bring it forth" are mistaken.
The "copy" has existed as long as the "archetype." In Plotinus there is
no Platonic demiurge who produces the world from matter while con-
templating the Ideas, nor a Biblical God who creates it from nothing, nor
does the world develop from eternal potentialities as in Aristotle. In
Plotinus die world comes into being by a process that was later termed
emanation. He himself had no concept for it, but merely set forth the
mystery in countless images:
The Other is like a radiance bursting forth from the One, like the light
surrounding the sun, or the heat radiated by fire, or the cold given of? by
a lump of ice, or the fragrance shed by a perfume. The greater the distance
from the One, the weaker becomes the light, until it loses itself in darkness,
emptiness, nothingness.
In another image, the universe flows from a source which feeds rivers
but never runs dry. Or it is which pervades the
like the life of a great tree,
whole, though its principle remains concentrated in the root and is not
dispersed. Or the One is compared to the center around which a circle
moves.
Other metaphors are based on generation, vision, and love: generation is
not a creation from nothing, or a fashioning out of some material, but the
mysterious process of transmitting life —the product is no less an independ-
ent being than is its source. A son is not an artifact depending for its
his father who brought him into being. Plotinus calls the One the father,
the nous the son, and the world-soul the grandson. But generation comes
to pass through vision. All Being is a product of seeing. Thus the One
engenders the nous. Standing still in order to see, it becomes nous and enters
into being. Looking upon the earlier stage as a prototype, each stage engenders
its copy in the following stage which sees in turn, vision engendered by
brought forth the world. But in overflowing the One incurred no loss
(like the sun, which remains unchanged despite the rays it sends forth).
Nor is any stage diminished in producing the next after it.
it has vision: this very seeing is the intellectual principle." The spirit should
not be derived from the One, but from the spirit itself. Thinking, the
spirit "begins as one, yet does not remain as it began, but unawares, as
though drunk with sleep, becomes many. It unfolds, because it wants to
possess all things."
From the nous the next step is to the world-soul and to nature. Looking
upon the archetypes in the Ideas of the nous, the world-soul engenders the
world without plan or activity, without sound or effort. Nothing escapes it.
this? Plotinus replies: It was impossible that the All should remain at
rest in the intelligible as long as something other could come into being in
the hierarchy of things. Every stage engenders the stage below it. Only
matter, because it is without energy, engenders no ensuing stage. In achiev-
ing maturity and fulfillment, all beings engender something other, for
they are not content to remain within themselves. So it is with the One.
For "how could the most perfect remain self-set the first good how — . . .
when the reversed and evil overcome, the One will stand all alone in
fall is
the world would have remained within it, hidden and formless; there
would be no beings.
Thus the world is a place of transition, situated at once in light and
darkness. It is beautiful and divine, because it originates in the One. It is
a shadow, a reflection, incomplete and full of failings, because it is every-
where vitiated by orderless matter, the untruth of nonbeing. In so far as
Being is formed, it is beauty, truth, the good; but in so far as every existent,
even the best, contains a vestige of unformed matter, it partakes of ugliness,
untruth, and evil.
Hence in Plotinus both are possible and true: love of the world's Being
in all its stages, as a revelation and reflection of the One (which in its
superabundance cannot but overflow), and the yearning to be free from the
world, to return from existence, considered as a shadow distorted by the
nonbeing of matter, to true Being and beyond it to the One, to cast off the
veil of illusion and become fullness of Being. (It would have been better, says
Plotinus, if the spirit had not unfolded its self; for in this unfolding, the One
was followed by the second, which ushered in the whole hierarchy of stages
and the cycle of the world.)
does not begin with a theorem from which corollaries are derived, but
with a vision which remains its sole source and goal. It does not select
an object to be examined, but in the objective world of appearances finds a
fullness that transcends subject and object.
Plotinus teaches us to make our way through representations that are
transcended, to attain, through the things of the world, to that which is
not an object. "Call on God . . . and pray Him to enter. And may He
come bringing His own universe with all the gods that dwell in it." We
speak of the One, but we do not utter it. We do not have it by knowledge,
but we are not entirely without it.
He tells us to start from the experience of our own reality. "Even when
we call the One the cause, we are saying nothing of the One itself; we are
merely affirming something that comes to us, for something comes to us
from it, whereas the One is self-enclosed. We who circle around it, so to
speak, from outside, may only interpret our own experience, as we alter-
nately approach and fall away from it." "To the best of our ability, we
it
the manner of mystics, who "know that they have something higher within
them, but do not know what it is."
is called union with the One. In it culminate all the stages of knowledge.
eternal forms, from motions to the first motion, from the many beautiful
things to beauty as such. Oriented by what is accessible, the way leads toward
that which is in principle inaccessible. Much use is made of metaphors,
images pointing to the archetype. "From the way the shadow of the Good
appears we must conceive what its archetype is like." As we approach the
cosmos of the spirit, we find this shadow playing around it. And once we
have "beheld the cosmos of the spirit (we) must inquire after the Creator
m. TRANSCENDING AS A WHOLE
For Plotinus as for Plato the process of transcending consists of two steps.
The first transcends sense perception and attains to that which cannot be
seen but only thought. A visible triangle is never exactly identical with the
48 The Original Thinners
Good. The soul strives toward it: "And as long as there is something that
is higher than what is present, (the soul) strives upward, but it cannot rise
awareness, not life, not motion. Whatever we can think, we must say: it is
not this.
Over and over again Plotinus enjoins us: Take away all other things
when you wish to speak of the One or to achieve awareness of it. And when
you have taken everything away, do not try to add something to it but
ask whether there might be something that you have not yet taken away
from it in your thinking. Even Being is imputed to it only "under the
pressure of words." Strictly speaking, we may not call it "this" or "that."
It is not different from something other, and there are no differentiations
within it. It does not think, it is not mind, for, since it is unwanting and re-
PLOT NU S 1 49
lated to nothing outsideit, it has no need to think; nor does it think itself,
is not. Thus Plotinus turns the "not" into a positive. Because the One is
more, it encompasses and does not exclude what it is not. "Yet it is not
unconscious, for all contents are in it . . . there is life in it ... it is a think-
ing turned upon itself, a kind of self-awareness; it signifies a thinking in
eternal immobility— different from the thinking of the intellect." Its nonbeing
is a superabundance: "The giver is not necessarily identical with what he
gives: . . . the giver is the higher, the given the lesser. ... If spirit is
life, the giver has given life, but he himself is more beautiful and of higher
value than life . . . the life of the spirit is his reflection, not his life."
What cannot be thought can also not be said. Thus discourse concerning
the unthinkable One is a perpetual saying and unsaying. To call it the
absolutely other is to inject the category of difference into it; in being
thought, the transcendent is reduced to immanence. Thus such turns of
speech as: it is it is "beyond all things," "it is entirely
outside of all categories;
different"; "more than" or "above"; it is the completion of all things
it is
transcending, but in the end they must be dropped because of their inad-
equacy.
One way in which Plotinus unsays such statements is to point out that
what is said of the One does not apply to the One itself but only to the One in
relation to us, not to the One as such but from our point of view. "It is not
good for itself; it is the good for other things." When we "call it the cause,
we are not saying what it does, but what is done to us." Here the cause is not
a cause, but only seems so from the standpoint of the effect. The relation of
the One to us is not a relation, but only appears to be from our point of
view. Yet this unsaying unsaid, for Plotinus speaks most emphati-
is itself
cally of the One as that "from out of which everything else is and lives."
"All beings yearn for it, as though suspecting that without it they could not
be."
In speaking of the One Plotinus, carried away by enthusiasm, speaks
from the depths of his soul, but in so doing renounces the possibility of
knowledge. His imagination is inexhaustible in paradoxes: The First loses
nothing, since the cause does not dissolve in the effect — it causes things to
become but need not — it overflows but loses none of its fullness. The One
50 The Original Thinners
perseveres in perfect rest and does not look down to what comes after it.
It would be all the same had been no second. It remains
to the First if there
undivided, loses nothing, and wants for nothing. But that which has become
turns to it and looks upon it and is filled with it.
How differently Plotinus' thinking appears to us when we describe
it objectively as a system of the universe, and when we participate in the
transcending thought itself. Only in the actual progress of the ideas and
actualizations is the basic riddle of existence disclosed in the Plotinian
manner, but never is an answer found that can stand as a content of knowl-
edge.
Plotinus also calls the One, the ultimate transcendence, God. Everything
visible, everything thinkable, everything we and can apprehend becomes
are
subordinate to the godhead. This transcending of all immanence, all glory
and greatness in the world and of all spirit toward the divine is by no means
self-evident, much less the radicalism with which, in Plotinus, transcend-
ence is safeguarded against any attempt to think it, to bring it closer, to
touch or embody it. There is nothing self-evident about ascribing all depth
and power and making it the one and only center.
to this transcendence
But God in Plotinus is also called the cosmos of the spirit (nous) and
the world-soul; the heavenly bodies are gods, and there are also the demons
that fill the atmosphere. In accordance with the Greek tradition, Plotinus
imputes multiplicity to the divine. Transcending takes place within the
divine as within all being. And only in this transcending is Plotinus en-
raptured by that which is the goal of all his thinking, but which he cannot
think or utter and for which "God" is only one name among many. This
name, however, is not expressly unsaid, although this godhead cannot be
considered on the same level as all the many gods. No philosopher has
lived more in the One than Plotinus. But his One is not the living God of
the Bible, it is not moved by anger, is not a bringer of mercy and redemption.
Plotinus' God is infinitely loved but does not love in return. Everything is
through Him, but not by virtue of His will. This one God has no cult and
no congregation. The soul takes flight with the One-in-it to the Only-One.
The godhead is reached by means of an ethical life and, in philosophizing,
through a speculative dialectic that forbids all intelligible, and a fortiori
sensuous, fixation. Prayer is a philosophizing self-movement toward God.
For us everything depends on God, on the One: "We are in higher
degree when we move toward him; to be far from Him signifies a lower
degree of being." Life on earth is homelessness, exile. But this God is not
a personal being who turns to us in love. "The Godhead does not yearn for
us as though it existed for us; we yearn for it, we exist for it." Like many of
the great philosophers (Aristotle, Spinoza), Plotinus recognizes no love of
God for man, but only the love of man for God, which is the foundation of
all authentic life.
PLOTINUS 51
takes of thought, it is more than thought; namely, union with the One;
every object vanishes and I myself with it; filled with the ground of all
being, both become one with it.
Thus thought occupies an intermediate position between Less-than-
thought and More-than-thought. What is thinking? It is a process which
distinguishes between itself and the object of thought and between one
object and another. Thought implies diversity.
In this intermediate sphere between sense perception and the unity
beyond thought Plotinus distinguishes mere understanding and reason,
spirit (nous). The understanding operates indirectly, through reflections
and inferences, it makes things with tools. Reason, on the other hand, be-
holds: it has immediate vision of the One in the many. As the Egyptians
see the thing itself in the hieroglyph, so vision apprehends its objects, not
by discursive thinking, but in a single act. In bringing forth the universe
the Creator does not think out one thing after another like an artisan
making things with his hands and with tools, but produces the whole at
one stroke. Such is the nature of man's vision when, transcending thought,
he apprehends the essence of things.
— —
But and this is crucial for Plotinus' thinking the goal is not achieved
in what would seem to be the highest thought, the vision of reason, the
thinking of the eternal forms or essences. For reason is thought and implies
otherness. The One of reason, copy of the undifferentiated One, is both
subject and object of thought; its objects are differentiated. Without duality-
cleavage and otherness— the One is silence. An immediate self-apprehend-
ing of the One would be "a simple, wholly identical act and would bear
no relation to thought."
Vision in Plotinus has two meanings: (1) the beholding of the essences
in objects, (2) union, beyond thought, with the objectless One. This union
is not achieved by thought; in it, thought is transcended and discarded.
Thus union with the One is also said to transcend vision.
To rise beyond thinking, beyond reason, beyond Being, to attain to the
52 The Original Thinners
tual activity, I ask myself how it happens that I am now descending and
how the soul ever entered into my body, although, even within the body,
it is the high thing it has shown itself to be."
2. The unioncompared to the experience of the adept who has left
is
the idols behind him and has become one with the divine in the inner
sanctuary (adyton). There beholding and beheld are one, perfect simplicity,
there is no object and no subject. "The beholder has become another, no
longer himself and no longer his own." But returned from the adyton,
he encounters the idols he had left behind him. "Thus these become the
second visions."
3. "But there is which he who has apprehended it
the truly lovable, with
and truly possesses it can remain united, for it is not veiled in flesh and
blood. He who has beheld it knows the truth of what I say, namely how the
soul receives a new life and needs no other. On the contrary, he must cast
off everything else, remain in this alone and become this alone. . . .
soul, attaining to the intelligible realm of the nous, puts all thoughts behind
it.
Having entered into the perfection of the One, the soul "no longer
perceives that it is in a body. Nor does it call itself anything else, not
man, nor living creature, nor being, nor the whole."
What no longer vision, thinking, or life, Plotinus calls a standing-out
is
"not be perceived with mortal eyes." Filled with God, the soul stands
serenely "in solitary repose and without change, nowhere deviating from
its essence, not even rotating round itself, everywhere standing fast as
though had become rest itself." "No longer itself nor belonging to
it itself,
becomes drunk in a way that is better than sober earnestness. The soul
beholds the One by muddling and dispelling, as it were, its intellective
faculty (reason, nous). Thus it attains to the One.
2. Plotinus compares: In the darkness or through closed eyelids our eye
can see a light that has no outside source but springs from within. It sees
unseeing, and it is then that it sees most authentically, for it sees light,
whereas other things, though light-like, are not light. "Thus reason, in
veiling itself from other things and withdrawing within itself, will see
unseeing; it something other, but a pure
will not see another light in
light of its own, which suddenly flares up from within."
3. Place and time disappear: When reason sees without seeing, when the
One is suddenly manifested, reason does not know where it comes from,
whether from without or within. And when the vision has passed, reason
says: It was within and yet not within. We must not ask whence. For
there no Whence. For it does not come and does not go; rather, it
is
appears at one moment, and at another it does not appear. It came like one
who does not come, for it was not seen as we see one who has come but
as we see one who has always been present. We must not try to pursue it,
but quietly, preparing ourselves for the vision, wait for it to appear as the
eye awaits the sunrise. Without coming it is miraculously here and nowhere;
yet where it is not, there is nothing! The soul in this life shuts itself off;
not so the One. —Only from its memory of the timeless Being in which it
54 The Original Thinners
forever partakes does the soul know of the One, in moments when time
is extinguished —such moments are not units of time. Here the soul finds
no "place," but spaceless presence. "He (God, the One) raises them so
high that they are neither in a place nor anywhere where one thing is in
another." The One is nowhere. "For what is not somewhere is nowhere
absent. ... If it is not absent from any thing and yet is not somewhere,
it must be everywhere, self -subsisting. It is whole and it is everywhere; no
thing has it and yet every thing has it, that is to say, it has every thing."
In all our thinking we involuntarily employ spatial images that are
often misleading. As Plotinus explicitly states, we posit a space and introduce
the One into it. Then we ask how it got there, assuming that it must have
come from above or below. But our vision of the One must be spaceless;
we must not situate it in any space whatever, whether eternally at rest
within it or recently arrived there; rather, we must presume that space,
like all other determinations, comes afterward. In thus thinking the space-
less One, we do not surround it with something. In our representations, to
be sure, everything takes on a spatial character and has its place, but in
reality space belongs only to the last stage of knowledge, the stage of nature.
4. "In the One there is no deception. What can the soul find that is
truer than the true? It is what it says, and it says this later; it says it
and it is not deceived in its well-being. Nor does it say this because
silently,
the body feels well-being, but because it has become what it was when it
was happy."
What Plotinus calls perfection, the source and goal, is for him absolute
reality, the highest stage, not Being, but before all Being. The soul knows
its authentic Being. It knows that its customary state of consciousness is a
decline. But in its participation in the source, it experiences deep satisfac-
tion: transcending everything that is, it experiences what has no further
goal beyond it. Plotinus' writings are an unexcelled record of this funda-
mental experience, which is understood and produced by philosophical
thinking. The experience he pursues is not one that is enjoyed as an
event in time; it pervades all the moments
and is the source of existence
of all meaning; it is which imprints finite
the absolute consciousness
consciousness. He actually experienced as a perfect whole what in this
immanent world we can know only in the duality of loving and loved,
beholding and beheld, that is, he experienced the goal that gives our im-
perfect yearning its direction.
This experience seems to permit of psychological description, but it is
state. The reverse is true. This state is experienced rather as a waking from
the customary mists of existence into another existence, in which I rise
V. SPECULATIVE TRANSCENDING
1. The categories: What I think and have before me as an object "is." The
self-evident appears to me as "Being." But what "is" Being? With this ques-
tion I turn away from objective, self-evident thinking to examine the mean-
ing of Being in all that is thought and thinkable. I set out to elucidate Being,
without new objective knowledge. Plotinus supports Aristotle's thesis "that
Being is not synonymous in all things." The categories serve to distin-
guish and classify the different kinds of Being. The purpose of each category
is to characterize a mode or class of Being, for example, substantive Being,
qualitative Being, quantitative Being, etc. The statement that something is
(or the term Being) does not always mean the same thing. But is there a
total body which develop coherently from a principle and can
of categories
be conceived as parts or classes of the one Being?
What may be called Plotinus' doctrines of categories is on the surface an
aggregate. He found doctrines of categories originating in Plato, elaborated
by Aristotle, modified by the Stoics. In his system, he stresses only one
original point. He puts forward a radical critique of all his predecessors
(with the exception of Plato) : "In their classification they do not speak of
the intelligible; thus they did not attempt to classify all modes of Being, but
disregarded the most important." For Plotinus there are only two classes
of thinkable Being: the sensory and the intelligible. Intelligible Being is
Being par excellence, archetypal Being; sensory Being is only reflected and
secondary. In considering every category, we must ask to which class of
Being it applies, the sensory or the intelligible, or to both, whether it is
ries that reside in the thing itself (motion, rest, quality, quantity, etc.), on the
other hand, the subjective categories (the \ategoremata), namely, the
categories of relation.
The two categorial worlds are not parallel. The categories of the sensory
world disappear in the intelligible world and are not transferable to it. Those
of the intelligible world, however, are present in the sensory world, but not
in the same way —the difference is that between archetype and copy.
In the intelligible world the fundamental categories are identity and dif-
ference. They occur also in the sensory world, but here they signify estrange-
ment, the separation of the many things from one another, while in the
intelligibleworld the opposites are not only logically connected, they are one.
This transformation of one and the same category from intelligible arche-
type to copy, that takes place in the sensory world, is brought about by space,
time, and matter. Free from space and time, the intelligible categories subsist
in the unity of opposites. Here, consequently, there no separation among is
things; they are not isolated from one another and do not clash with one
another. With space comes separation, with time generation and transience.
In the sensory world, matter is the principle of formlessness which disrupts
the formed figures, and of separation which dissolves their unity. The things
of the sensory world are not only thought but must also be perceived.
Thought and being are no longer identical.
within the realm of the thinkable, is only the first step in his doctrine of
categories.
The next and final step consists in a transcending to the unthinkable,
a thinking of the unthinkable. This is possible only if the thinker's orienta-
tion in the thinkable is such that the thinkable becomes a jumping-ofT
place. The thinkable can be transcended only with the help of elucidated
thinkables. In this transcending the thinkable world must shatter, but this
does not mean that thought gives way to a confused stammering; the think-
able is surpassed by the methods of dialectical speculation.
Thus Plotinus does not content himself with the orientation in the think-
able world provided by his system of categories. He makes use of other
categories, borrowed from traditional philosophy, which are not explicitly
included in his doctrine. These are: form and matter, reality and potentiality,
cause, life, and others. Plotinus has given us an abundance of speculations
in this direction. A few examples:
Unity: Everything that exists in the world is a unity of many. The amazing
principle that makes a thing one must be fundamental. "All beings are
beings by virtue of unity. What could exist at all except as one? Neither an
army, nor a chorus, nor a flock can be without unity, nor is there any house
or ship without it. The same is true of plants and animals, each of which
PL0T1NUS 59
itself a multiplicity —becomes a thing, the mystery of this "one out of many,"
leads Plotinus to the transcending leap: each particular unity comes about
through an absolute One, a principle of unity. It is through the transcendent
One that every existing thing is one.
No unity in the world of existence is the One. Rather, each thing or being
derives its rank in the scale of reality from its particular mode of being-one.
"Among the things that are said to be one, each is one in a particular way,
according to its nature." Thus the unity of the soul varies with its rank and
authenticity, but even the highest, most authentic soul is different from the
One and is not the One itself. Similarly, things are nearer to the One or
farther away from it according to the manner of their unity. "The discrete,
a flock, for example, is fartherfrom the One, the continuous is closer to it;
the soul is in still closer bond with it." Things partake of the One, they are
not the One itself. "When we apprehend the unity of plants, i.e. the endur-
ing principle, and the unity of animals and the unity of the soul, and the
unity of the all, in each case we are apprehending what is strongest and most
valuable in those things."
Transcending all modes of unity in the thinkable world, Plotinus arrives
at the one itself (hen) and questions it. At this point begins his speculative
dialectic: What one thinks in the category of unity ought to be transcendence
itself. But once thought, once conceived as a category, the One always takes
on a finite meaning: The One is opposed to the other; the number one is
opposed to the numerical series; the one that makes many into one is opposed
to the many. In any of these finite meanings, the One is no longer the tran-
scendent One. In each case it ceases to be the absolute One, for it is always
at the same time not-one, because it is connected with the other, with the
rather, the One is with itself in the Other; clarifying one another, they are
a totality; thinking and what is thought, subject and object, are not
differentiated.Here we have a rich and complex world of logical thinking,
which always derives its meaning from its one goal: to shatter against un-
thinkableness, which alone touches upon the essential.
Form and matter: Thanks to the artist, the shapeless marble takes on form
as a statue. By analogy, all perceptible being is considered as a whole,
consisting of intelligible form and the matter to which it gives shape. In
every object of thought, even in mathematical figures and numbers, a
distinction is made between form and matter. The opposition proves to
be universal. In every existing or thinkable thing the two factors are
present, but in an ascending scale, so that what in one case is form becomes
both created in so far as they have a source, increate in so far as their source
is not situated in time.
Beyond form and matter: By way of form Plotinus arrives at what
b)
is no longer form, because it is without matter, the Supreme One. By way
of matter he arrives at what is no longer matter, because it is without form,
the nonbeing of matter. Plotinus transcends the form-matter relationship
by dissolving it.
strive to think pure form and the mere matter of nonthinking. What is
thought in this way is outside of all being. But at the opposite poles, Above-
Being and nonbeing are named.
But since all existents are rooted in something that is not an existent,
the nonexistent cannot in either case be nothing. The nonbeing of matter
is not nothing (not an ou\ on but a me on). Plotinus writes: "But the
nonexistent is not absolute nonbeing, but only something other than Being;
it is as nonexistent as a copy of Being, or far more nonexistent." So much
for matter. Above-Being, the One, is also called nonbeing (me on). The
"above" indicates the direction of transcending; in content it too is a
negation of being: "This miracle confronting the mind is the One, because
it is nonbeing (me on)." The same operation of thought leads to opposite
extremes.
Where thought is transcended, the One is apprehended by more-than-
thinking, in fulfillment by e\stasis, hapldsis, henosis. Contact with matter,
on the other hand, is achieved neither by sensory perception nor by thinking,
but by a less-than-thinking, an "inauthentic thinking" (Plato), as when the
eye sees darkness.
The essential difference lies in what I myself am in the two opposite
processes of transcending. In confronting matter, I think unthinking; with
the undefined within me, I think the undefined outside me; I am lost. When
I confront the One, the failure of my thinking raises me above all thinking.
For Plotinus true transcendence is disclosed only in the One and in the
soaring of the spirit, and not in the other direction, which is characterized
perfect, undivided. "For no one will say that there is a potential One and an
actual would be absurd, in the realm of essential reality, to posit
One. It
and actuality are one. A logical relation (potentiality and actuality) serves
as a metaphor for something unfathomable. In seeking to express an
intuition of the unfathomable in terms of a thought content, we must avoid
the distinction between potentiality and actuality that is indispensable in
our thinking of Thus we arrive at the logically absurd proposition
existents.
(for which Cusanus coined the word "possest") that potentiality and actu-
ality are identical.
—
from its Being" applies equally to the emergence of the spirit and hence
of all existents from the One. But whatever Plotinus thinks in this connec-
tion is overshadowed by the true transcending in which thought shatters
against the identity of potentiality and actuality.
Being?— he replies: In the source, Being and the ground of Being are one.
Further questioning is futile. In other words: The category of the "ground"
becomes a form of transcending by virtue of the idea: "ground of itself."
For the understanding this idea is a contradiction or a vicious circle. For
a ground is no longer a ground when it is said to be identical with what it
grounds. By eliminating the questions "whence" and "why," this idea in
transcending encounters the ungrounded Being which, precisely because it
is ungrounded, ceases to be Being and becomes the ground of Being. This
whence. Either it must deny the object and rightly so when asked to —
—
objectify the unthinkable or it must inquire further as to its ground.
Whatever object is set before it or created by it, the understanding cannot
stop questioning.
The idea of the unthinkable is possible only through the failure of the
understanding. This statement is itself a tautology. Its meaning is not
apprehended by the understanding, but through the failure of the under-
standing, by reason. For the understanding it is nothing; it is fulfilled from
out of another source. The transcending idea, an impossibility from the
standpoint of the understanding, posits two entities, being and the ground
of being, and goes on to say that they are not two but one. By way of
clarifying this idea, Plotinus circles around it with the help of other
categories —contingency, necessity, freedom, selfness.
because it owes its Being to itself. But then again it does not possess
freedom, because it is the ground of freedom, not free but something
more than freedom. It is situated beyond those modes of being which we,
in connection with existent things, regard as contingent, necessary, or
free. It is itself. Plotinus has impressive formulations of all these ideas.
It would be wrong to say that the First is not master of its own becoming,
if only "because it never became." But in no respect may we say that "this
first nature is not master of what it is; that it does not take what it is from
itself; that it does or does not do what it is compelled to do or not to do."
For it "is not restrained by necessity; rather, it is itself necessity and for
other things the law." But it would also be wrong to conclude that this
necessity brought itself into existence: it does not even exist, for all existence
came into existence after the First and for the sake of the First. The First
is what it is, not because it cannot be different, but because it is the best.
Plotinus finally arrives at the following formula: "The Good created itself.
For if the will sprang from the Good and is its work, the Good provided
its own hypostasis. Consequently it is what itself willed." Is the First then
freedom ?
stance governs us. . . . But since in a way we ourselves are this substance
that governs us, we may be called masters of ourselves." From our freedom
we take the step to the freedom of the One. "That which is wholly what it
is, at one with its substance, is governed by its own Being and no longer
contingent on something else." Undivided, it is perfectly free. The One
In the second step, the transcending continues, but the positive statements
about the freedom of the One are withdrawn. No more than any other predi-
cate is the predicate "free" applicable to the One. Like all other formu-
lable concepts —the beautiful, the venerable, thinking, or Being—free will and
freedom are One. For freedom implies effect on some-
also posterior to the
thing else, it implies that something else exists, and that the effect, if free, is
unobstructed. But the One must be posited outside all relation.
These two steps are repeated: Our consciousness of freedom resides in
our striving toward the Good. If freedom is striving toward the Good,
we cannot deny freedom to that which is itself the supreme Good. It would
be still more absurd to deny freedom to the Good itself, the One, on the
ground that it remains within itself, feeling no need to move toward some-
thing other. But if we say that the freedom of the One is directed toward
itself, what we know as our freedom vanishes. We choose ourselves on the
basis of models and standards. But the One cannot be thought of in this way.
"Even if we assume that it chooses what it wishes to become, that it is free to
transform its own nature into something other, we are not entitled to
suppose that it would wish to become something other." For "Where there
is no two-as-one, but only One —
there can be no self-mastery." "The Good is
the willing of itself; it chooses itself, because no other is present to exert a
necessary attraction upon it."
Our choosing and willing of ourselves must have its ground in the First,
but it is not in the First. The First is "the truly self-governing power which
is what it wills," or rather, as Plotinus makes haste to add, "which relegates
its will to the world of existence, whereas in itself it is greater than all willing
Itself: The One which "in a manner of speaking creates itself, rests on itself,
and looks upon itself," "has nothing other, but is itself alone." "Other things
are in themselves inadequate to being, but even in its isolation this (the One)
is what it is." Just as it is above reason, it is above freedom and independence.
What for us finite rational beings is a formula for evil (Richard III: "I am
I") becomes thought the supernal principle which is the
in transcending
source of personal, loving, free life; yet it is not this life itself, but more than
this life, its ground. "Thus everything came forth from a source which did
not reflect but all at once provided the ground and with it being." This
First "is itself the ground of itself, through itself and for its own sake; for
66 The Original Thinners
itself and well pleased as it were with itself, and has nothing better than
itself."
and goings of existence, not even subject to the timeless intelligible cate-
gories, but theground of these too. Like is recognized by like. Accordingly:
"If each thing makes itself into something, it becomes clear that that [the
One] is primarily and originally a principle whereby all other things can
be through themselves."
All questioning into the ground of the One takes place in the shattering
category of the ground that is groundless. "It did not come in order that
you should ask: How did it come? What fate brought it about? For before
it there was neither fate nor chance."
Life: Plotinus sees life in plants, animals, man. Happiness is the lot of those
who live in higher degree: In the world of existence, the best is the authentic
and perfect life. The question of what this life is points to the supersensory
source. Though experienced and seen in this world, life has its source in the
intelligible. If I wish to understand life, I must transcend toward the intel-
ligible: the perfect, authentic, and real life resides in intelligible nature; all
Above-Being and toward death in the nonbeing of matter. Hence the am-
biguity of death, which ambiguity is annulled in transcending: for death
is more and less than life, the fullness of Above-Being and the emptiness
were" must be added. "For purposes of persuasion," names are used, "and
in our expression we are entitled to deviate somewhat from rigorous think-
ing." On pain of remaining silent, there is no other possibility for discourse:
"It is thus that we must speak of God, since we cannot speak of him as we
should like to."
As we follow these contradictory thoughts that ultimately dissolve into
nothing, we may be tempted to suppose that, because they have no object,
they are only empty and meaningless discourse. In answer to this, it must
be said that these are methods whose meaning lies in a fulfillment that
transcends thought.
A mind conscious of transcendence can achieve clarity through operations
of thought, without objective knowledge —for transcendence cannot be
known as an object. On and transcendence,
the dividing line between world
the thinker surpasses his consciousness of this limit: with logical methods
which may be purely formal from the standpoint of the mere understand-
ing, he enriches his awareness of the superabundance, depth, inexplicability
of transcendence, while at every step the nonabsoluteness of all thinkables
without exception becomes more compellingly evident. An obscure, formal
consciousness of the limit is transformed into a radiant, real, and effective
consciousness.
In the objective world, I continually think Being. This is never the ulti-
mate Being. And so I go further. In the ascent from one to the other, from
every attainment to its ground, my understanding can find no beginning
and source. I should have to decide on an ultimate, and at this arbitrarily
chosen point cease to question. Only if, instead of rising ad infinitum in this
series from object to object, I effect a leap by transcending from object to
nonobject, can I, without fixating an object, meditate my way into the
source, dreaming as I think. This is what Plotinus does: his First is not
an object, it is without predicate and cannot be thought. It is not the first
member of a series. To think it is not to think it. Thus in the pursuit of each
category it becomes necessary to effect a leap into the realm where thinking
ceases. The thinking of the understanding leads to the endless. But trans-
cending thought arrives at the source or goal where it finds rest.
The dialectic of this thinking that aspires to become nonthinking results
in: a shift of thinking into inability to think; a thinking that negates itself
to think the thinkables in such a way as to free ourselves from them and
overcome our tendency to find an ultimate and absolute in any object of
thought.
All speculative thinking as a logical construction has been and always
will be doomed to failure, if what is expected is a knowledge of something,
a derivation, an understanding of one thing through another, a determina-
tion in categories. However, such thinking derives new meaning from the
consequence of its failure. Yet this meaning cannot be preserved in dogmas,
but only through participation in the thinking of the creative metaphysi-
cians, which is always unique, though it loses its radiance and power in
being expounded and analyzed. Still, exposition and analysis are indispen-
sable, for they alone can provide us with the equipment with which to
understand the wonderful language of the great metaphysicians.
The levels of being are disclosed not through the process of search, but
through vision. At no cleavage between mythical vision
this point there is
for the fetters that bind us to this existence, it yearns to hasten away. When
the soul is seized with intense love of that place, it "casts off every form it
has, even the intelligible form." Only when the soul has freed itself from
what it has, is the One suddenly revealed to it.
But no will can induce immediate union with the One by design. It
comes as a gift. To seize it directly is "to fly as in a dream." In so doing, I
merely close myself off from the possibility of becoming God. The human
soul can become God "only insofar as the Spirit leads it upward; any
attempt to go beyond the Spirit involves a fall into the spiritless."
Here, in this existence, accordingly, we must content ourselves with
little. The only possibility of philosophizing lies in contemplation of the
One in the spiritual archetypes and beyond these in the speculative dialectic
of self-negating thoughts. We are limited to the upward
path of the knowing
soul in the world. If I must look upon "the divine
aspire to see the One, I
images closer to the periphery." Before the First, the One, I must stop
short of the First, the One, "and say nothing more concerning it, but
inquire how things came into being after it." The greatness of the One is
to be seen in that "which is after it and for its sake."
Anyone who has been in the realm of perfection, says Plotinus, knows
whither his yearning tends. There the flame was kindled, which dies down
when man redescends. "Why does man not remain there? Because he has
not wholly departed from here," because he is still "weighed down by the
body's unrest."
But if in this existence he has achieved an encounter with the One, a
tension arises between his yearning and his resignation. The fundamental
is transformed. It has knowledge of the essential. When
attitude of the soul
it is and has itself become the object of its yearning, "there is nothing
there
for which it would exchange this gift, even if someone were to offer it the
whole of heaven, for there is nothing better. For the soul can rise no . . .
higher, and only in its descent can it see those other things." From that
realm, a shadow of vanity falls upon all things in this world. "When the
soul is united with it (the One) and ceases to behold anything at all, it
vision docs not explain why individual souls, endowed with wills of their
own, break loose from the All-Soul, why, in addition to the necessary
descent of the cycle, there is a falling of the individual soul.
But conversely, if we take Plotinus' consciousness of freedom as our
starting point, it will elucidate the meaning of his cosmic vision. I myself
am responsible for my wretched state, and this guilt of mine implies a pre-
existential choice. It is the idea that I am free to rise or fall by my own
activity that engenders the cosmic vision as a means of interpreting life.
actually grounding
its principle. It is freedom that gives the schema truth
and meaning.
My awareness that the present state of my soul is not final transcends
existence and is explained by the origin of my soul: I did not spring from
nothingness; rather, it was by my own will, before my time, that I fell into
this condition; I still discern the workings of this will in motives which I
experience in my present existence, motives which I do not identify with
myself and from which, in my ascending movement, I strive to free myself.
Consequently Plotinus' vision of Being has two aspects which, though
constantly merging, are essentially different. First, the eternal presence of
the totality in its which lives and moves but changes
everlasting cycle,
nothing, and second, the and resurgence, in time, of individual souls
fall
through their own guilt and freedom. We must consider Plotinus' philosophy
in the tension between on the one hand the eternity of Above-Being and
Nonbeing, Spirit and world, and on the other hand the temporality of each
soul's supersensory destiny.
With
their conception of the creation and end of the world, Gnosticism
and Christian theology drew being into the temporal process; they combated
the doctrine that world and matter are eternal. Plotinus took the opposite
step, raising the temporal world, considered as the intermediate realm of
nature, above time. In his view the motion of the timeless whole is only
apparent, while motion in nature is temporal. Entering into nature through
its union with the body, the soul is caught up in temporal motion. Entering
into the corporeality of the world, the soul became involved in fate. But
something in the soul, its nucleus of eternal Being, remains intact, free from
temporal motion. This eternal Being is forgotten but not extinct. Within
thehusk of the body, the soul enacts its fate, in which the recollection and
reawakening of the center play a vital part. No decision is final. As low as
the soul may fall, its center cannot die. A return is always possible. The
soul has plenty of time, for the world is eternal.
Let us take a closer look at this view of fate and of the alternatives
facing the soul.
I merely observe a process that would take place without me. Nor is what
Nor is action free, for neither the conditions nor the situations nor the
consequences of action are in our power.
Yet there is freedom: "Freedom does not depend upon act, but is a thing
of the mind. Freedom and free will pertain not to action but to
in actions
inner activity, to the thinking and contemplation of virtue itself." Only
reason (the nous) has "no master over it." It is possible only as freedom.
"Freedom dwells in all those who conduct their lives according to
reason and a rational striving." "The soul becomes free when through
reason it strives unhindered toward the Good. Reason is free through
itself." Freedom, for Plotinus, is inviolable. "God gave us virtue, subject to
b. Twofold guilt and twofold freedom: "There is a twofold guilt for the
soul." The one consists in the from its super-
motive for the soul's fall
sensory home, the other in the crimes commits here in the world. The
it
soul atones for the first guilt by the sufferings it must bear in this world. It
atones for the second by rebirth in other incarnations. To these two kinds
of guilt correspond two kinds of freedom, the freedom of pretemporal
choice and freedom of action in the world.
The mystery of pretemporal choice: "What caused souls to forget God the
Father? The beginning of evil for them was their overweening pride,
. . .
the desire for change, the first otherness, and the craving to belong to
themselves. Rejoicing in their own splendor, they forgot that they were
descended from thence." They saw neither God nor themselves. From igno-
rance of their source, they did not honor themselves; they honored the
Other and admired everything more than themselves.
Freedom in embodiment: Against Stoic determinism and the astrologers,
Plotinus resolutely asserts our freedom. To be sure, Providence guides all
his earthly body. He is free in origin, but not outside the sphere of Provi-
dence.
arising from within it, but through something other. We are not the source
of evil; evil is anterior to us. "The evil that enters into men does not enter
into them by their will; nevertheless, there is an escape from evil for
those who are able, but not all men are able." This other, which is itself
evil, is matter.
In answer to those who assert that matter is not evil, that "we should
not seek evil in something other, but situate it in the soul itself," Plotinus
declares that the soul, by definition, is life and hence good. It is not evil
through itself.
Evil is a weakness of the soul. Weakness of the soul is not the same as
weakness of the body. The cause of the soul's weakness, however, is not
in itself, but in its bond with the body, whereby it has fallen into the
corporeality of the world. And this weakness does not spring from a
privation of something, but from the presence of something essentially
different, matter.
Plotinus explains how this came about. Matter and soul occupy the same
place. The soul inhabits a separate place only insofar as it does not dwell
in matter. The soul could not have entered into a process of change except
through the presence of matter. Soul and matter have merged into one.
Matter is like a weight attached to the soul. The matter that dwells with
the soul draws life from it and weighs down; matter strives
it to penetrate
the innermost core of the soul. The light emanating from the radiation of
the soul is darkened and enfeebled by matter. The radiation of the soul
was made possible by matter, for without matter the soul would not have
descended. That is the "fall" of the soul: to have entered into matter and to
have been enfeebled, to have been made evil by matter.
The consequences of an orientation toward matter spring from matter:
freedom is limited. "Without a body, it is its very own master, free and
outside of cosmic causes —drawn down into the body, it ceases to be in
every way its own companion is governed largely by
master. For its
contingencies." Composition with the body makes the passions more violent,
blunts the judgment, and gives rise to states of mind that vary according
as we are hungry or satisfied. Through the material body the soul is easily
aroused to desire, easily inclined to anger, overhasty in judgment, and
surrenders readily to turbid imaginings, just as among the creatures the
weakest succumb most readily to the wind or the heat of the sun.
To the argument that the soul should have mastered matter, Plotinus
replies: The soul is not in a pure state, hence its power of mastery is
diminished.
But the faculty of mastering matter is present. Freedom is not denied.
74 The Original Thinners
Hence, after the primal evil, the first evil, of matter, there is a second evil
springing from weakness of the soul. The first evil is the disorder of
matter, the second evil is that which becomes disorder by assimilation to
matter, or participation in matter. The first evil is darkness, the second is
A good soul resists under all these circumstances." We can act "under the
The soul deteriorates in consequence of the fall. Once it has fallen into
the body and been filled with matter, it remains in matter even when
separated in death from its present body, "until the day when it rises
upward and at some point averts its gaze from the muck." In consequence
of an evil life the soul is re-embodied in an inferior form: one who has
killed unjustly will be killed in another existence —unjustly as far as the
agent is concerned, but justly so for the victim. What I do, I must suffer.
The crime I inflict will be inflicted upon me. "For it should not be supposed
that anyone is by chance a slave, or by chance taken prisoner. One who
has slain his mother will himself become a woman in order to be killed
by his son, and one who has violated a woman will himself become a woman
and suffer the same fate." But transmigration is incidental in Plotinus. It
d.The two souls: The fall and regeneration of the soul are seen in terms of
—
"two souls" a fundamental conception with Plotinus. The one soul is
eternal, indestructible, and
remaining always in the intelligible
rational,
world; the other change and suffering, bound to the body
is subject to
in the world; it approaches the first soul or moves away from it, and passes
through many forms of existence. The second soul is suspended, as it were,
from the first, like its shadow; projected into the body, it takes on corporeal
existence; through the body it communicates with the sensory world. We
are a twofold being; an animal has attached itself to our godliness. We
carry the animal about with us.
The pure supersensory soul takes on the veils of spatiotemporal existence.
But evil pertains only to existence, not to the soul. The soul is indestructible
and merely changes its garment. "The changing souls become body now
in this, now in that form; when it can, the soul departs from the world of
change and remains at one with the world-soul."
In this world, however, the second soul suffers impurity. "Consider an
PLOT NU S 1 75
ugly, unrighteous soul, full of unrest, craven fear, petty envy, forever
occupied with base, transient thoughts, guileful, cringing in the byways,
a lover of impure pleasures, wholly dependent on bodily influences, a soul
that delights in ugliness: shall we not say that it has lost all purity of life
and feeling, that mingled with evil it leads an impure life shot through with
death, that it has ceased to behold what a soul should behold, that it cannot
remain in itself, because it is perpetually drawn to the external, earthly,
and dark?"
e. The twofold longing: The soul enters into the world, which partakes of
nonbeing insofar as it is evil but is not absolute nonbeing. In the opposite
direction, however, it attains not to something other, but to itself. It is
itself in its association with the One. Only its primal ground perceives the
primal ground, for like perceives like.
forgetfulness through the fall, its power to choose between the two directions
—in the old myths. The fall of the soul is compared to young Dionysus
looking into the mirror before being torn to pieces by the Titans. The bond
with the body is the water of Lethe; drinking it, the soul forgets its true
self. The soul allows itself to be carried away by nature: nature is Pandora,
whom all the gods unite in decking out. Seeking the divine in the beauty of
its own natural aspect, the soul is Narcissus, who flings himself into the
pool while trying to embrace his reflection. In its twofold longing, for
sensory beauty and eternal beauty, the soul is guided by a twofold Aphrodite,
the one begotten by Uranus, the other by Zeus. The soul in the world is
likened to Odysseus, who forsakes the carnal beauty of Circe and strives
heavenward. And it is comparable to Herakles, who dwells now with the
gods and now in Hades.
The soul rises through vision. Only from incapacity for vision, from weak-
ness, does the soul, dissatisfied, turn to activity; it begins to make things in
the hope of achieving what its Spirit could not. Thus "boys of lazy mind,
incapable of philosophy, turn to crafts and skills."
But the vision of the soul is love and creation. By way of the eye the soul
sees the visible forms of the beautiful. Loving, it perceives the imageless
in the image, and gazing toward it attains peace and perfection. As the
soul looks up at that which is above it, a copy of the archetype comes quietly
into being, as though of its own accord; love is the artist.
But this twofold direction of longing introduces an ambiguity into love:
76 The Original Thinners
f. The situation of the soul in the world: The one eternal soul achieves its
men, who have broken away from everything here below. But the "flight
of the One to the One continues even beyond that blissful life."
The existence of two souls has an extraordinary consequence: the one
soul is unaffected by all the evil in the world. Poverty and sickness mean
nothing to good men, for the soul that has turned back from its self-forget-
fulness is not touched by them. Yet like all evils, poverty and sickness benefit
the wicked, for they punish and teach. Just as there is no good for the
wicked, i.e., the self-forgetful soul that has descended to matter, so for the
good there is no evil. The soul that has awakened to the One bears all the
miseries of the world with patience, it attunes itself "to the natural law
of the All." was in the last period of his life, while desperately ill, that
It
to the fortunes assigned to it, attunes itself, ranges itself rightly to the
drama, to the whole Principle of the piece; then it speaks out its business,
exhibiting at the same time all that a Soul can express of its own quality,
as a singer in a song. A voice, a bearing, naturally fine or vulgar, may in-
crease the charm of a piece; on the other hand, an actor with his ugly voice
may make a sorry exhibition of himself, yet the drama stands as good a
work as ever: the dramatist taking the action which a sound criticism sug-
gests, disgraces one, taking his part from him, with perfect justice: another
man he promotes to more serious roles or to any more important play he
may have, while the first is cast for whatever minor work there may be."
PLOT IN U S 77
This similarity between life and a role in a play determines the inner
attitude of the man of insight: he does not complain of the particular role
assigned him at birth. Nor does any reasonable man find fault with the
other living creatures, which are beneath man but serve to beautify the
earth. In considering the plants, we do not ask why they have no feeling,
nor in considering the animals why they are not men. This would be as
absurd as to ask why men are not the same as gods. "Universal equality
there cannot be." The diversity of men is no ground for complaint; we do
not find fault with a play "because its characters are not all heroes, but
also include slaves and rustics."
A role has been assigned to us — let us play it well. This means that we
should see the situation in the world and fulfill it. From the vast diversity
of men, each man must draw the consequences for his role. For example:
Men who are like irrational voracious beasts wish to do violence to others.
The victims "are no doubt better than those who do them violence; if never-
theless they allow the wicked to defeat them, it is precisely because they
themselves are evil in certain respects and not truly good." Our role demands
that we fight for our own existence. Those who "from softness and in-
dolence let the wolves tear them to pieces like fatted lambs" are visited with
terrible sufferings for their inactivity. Since the world is governed by force,
"not even a god will defend unwarlike men. The divine law decrees that
those who fight bravely should be rescued from battle, not those who pray."
Similarly, where work is called for, the harvest is reaped by those who till
the soil, not by those who sit and pray. Would it not be absurd to follow
our own opinion in all other matters, even in opposition to the gods, and
then to expect the gods to save us? The gods gave us a commandment by
which to save ourselves —we did not obey it. The wicked prevail because
and not allow himself to be dominated by the wicked. But only those "who
do not understand serious things, who are themselves playthings," play the
role in earnest.
g. Philosophy is ascent to the One: Philosophy can find the upward path
and travel it. It supplies a knowledge which in itself bears the soul upward.
j$ The Original Thinners
journey; but the actual seeing is up to the man who has made the decision
to see."
Consequently the content of the doctrine is not in itself fulfillment.
The doctrine of the One supplies only "analogies, negations, knowledge
of its and of certain degrees of ascent." Essentially, it provides a
effects,
soul living in the world with two "demonstrations": it shows the vanity
of the things it now prizes and reminds the soul of its origin and worth.
These demonstrations are not logically compelling. They can succeed only
if the soul becomes one with what it is investigating.
But not all earth-bound souls are equally capable of discerning their
authentic being in the One. A soul must know "whether it has the power
to undertake such an investigation, whether it has an eye capable of seeing.
For if things are beyond its scope, what can its search avail? If it is bound
to them in inner kinship, it will be able to find them." Plotinus was pro-
foundly aware that we cannot adequately understand the teachings of
philosophy with our reason, but only with our own being. Only our daily
relation to ourselves and our memory of something that precedes all thought
can kindle the meaning of philosophy within us; but once this happens,
we in turn are magnified by our reflection on that meaning. In the temporal
world the soul awakens to something that was already present within it.
The soul in its embodiment is not a completed product which need only
be examined to be known; its very being hinges on the freedom that seizes
upon its potentiality. Refusal to seek ourselves in the ground of being is an
assertion of our own emptiness. Those who say defiantly: I am what I
am, cannot understand philosophy because they reject the possibility of
an ascending movement.
Ascending thought is oriented toward the Supreme One: "the presence
(parousia) that exceeds knowledge." "We must cast off all earthly veils,
stand in this alone and become this alone." "Impatient with our fetters,
we must Hence the often repeated demand:
hasten to escape from here."
"Let then him who can turn inward. Let him leave outside what the eye
beholds, nor turn back to what formerly appeared to him as the radiance
PLOT NU S 1 79
the copy."
Against materialism for transcendence: There are men, says Plotinus, who
look upon matter as the only true Being, the source of all things. That is
the fault of appearance; to their mind bodies are Being. Troubled by the
coming and going of corporeal forms, they conclude that Being is something
underlying these bodies, which endures amid change. This something is
matter.
Against the primacy of matter in the sensory world: Those who have
identified reality with matter have taken sense perception as their starting
point, but they do not find matter itself in sense perception. All perceptible
things are said to be merely the transient manifestation of imperceptible
matter. "The astonishing part of it is that those who make sense perception
the test of the true existence of all things, hold that Being cannot be
apprehended by sense perception." Either they indicate characteristics of
invisible matter that are perceptible to the senses (but when, for example
they impute the power of resistance to matter, they are mistaken, for this
too is a sensory quality like visibility, audibility, etc.), or else they try to
explain matter by reason, which they go on to explain on the basis of
matter. But is this not "an odd kind of reason, which gives matter precedence
over itself and attributes being to matter rather than to itself"? What faith
can one have in a reason which asserts its own nonbeing?
80 The Original Thinners
(of philosophy) the invisible god causes those who rely only on what they
see with the eyes of the flesh to doubt of his existence."
Against Gnosis in favor of the beauty of the world: Those who conceive
the supersensory in corporeal terms and then, setting one body against
another, reject the reality of the world are Gnostics. Their sensory vision
of the supersensory blinds them to the real world of the senses. A spiritual
vision of the supersensory, on the other hand, opens our eyes to the reflected
radiance of the sensuous world. Plotinus justifies nature despite its low
rank in the universal hierarchy and remoteness from pure being; in ithe
perceives the beauty of appearance.
PL0T1NUS 81
The world is not Being. Those who condemn the world can do so only
"because they do not know the hierarchical law extending from First to
last." To condemn the world because of the many evil things in it means
two things, first that we put too high a value on the world and second
that we are blind to its true value as a copy. It is a mistake to expect the
sensible world to resemble the intelligible world; let us recognize it,
mind do different things. We must not demand the same of things that
are not alike. Seeing is not the concern of the finger. Each has its own
function."Even the imperfect has its place. It is a mistake to condemn the
whole because of the parts, as though in looking at a man we were to con-
sider only a hair or a toe rather than the whole man.
The structure of the universe resembles that of the organism. In every
living being the parts, the face and head, are more beautiful than
upper
the rest, and lower parts do not resemble them. In the All, men
the middle
are in the middle, above them heaven and its gods, below them the scale
of living creatures extending down to the inanimate. Reason does not
wish everything to be equally good, any more than an artist in painting an
animal makes nothing but eyes. Reason does not people the All exclusively
with gods, but divides it among gods, demons, men, and animals, each in
turn, not out of envy, but because reason implies intellectual diversity.
The world is like a painting with its light and shadows; the shadows,
too, contribute to its beauty. The world is not uniformity but a harmony of
the dissimilar. Thus even evil is necessary in the world. If it were lacking,
the whole would be incomplete.
The world discloses all things in a process of change. Every particular
being is perishable. One thing limits and displaces another. All are en-
gaged in a reciprocal war of annihilation. Through spatial separation diver-
sity engenders hostility and makes friendship possible. "The part is not self-
to that which preserves it. By its passing away one thing enables another
to come into being." Each thing asserts itself in consequence of the will to
live. The consequences are pain, suffering, death. "Living creatures devour
one another, so that there is always war, which in all likelihood will never
cease or end."
Not only must there be differences, but oppositions as well. As harmony
82 The Original Thinners
arises from opposite tones, so the All accords with itself, while the parts
battle one another. Reason derives its unity from conflicting concepts. "For
if reason did not comprise multiplicity, it would not be a totality, it would be
no reason at all." Because there is good, there must also be evil; because
there is law and order, there must also be lawlessness and disorder.
Only particular beings perish. The world as a whole is eternal. "Perhaps
it is necessary that beings devour one another in order that they may inter-
change and replace one another, for even if they were not killed, they
could not endure forever. If they have benefited others, what ground is
there for complaint?" "Destruction is not an evil to what has come into
being through the death of something else; the fire that has been destroyed
is replaced by other fire."
the stage changes his costume and appears with another mask; in reality
he has not died. "The conflicts among mortal men indicate that all human
life is a game and show us that death is not bad, that by dying in war and
struggle one anticipates a little what happens in old age, that one leaves the
stage sooner in order to re-enter sooner. And as on a stage we must con-
sider the murders, the different kinds of death, the conquest and pillage of
cities, mere changes of scene, mere representations of sorrow and
all as
lamentation. For here too it is not the innermost soul that laments, but the
outward shadow of the man."
All happening in the world is governed by a law. Everything in the world
springs from reason and is therefore good, but at the same time everything
is matter formed by reason and therefore bad. Because matter retains a
The world-soul "governs this All without effort, as though by its mere
presence.
Viewing the whole, Plotinus says: "It is far better that beings and men
live as if from the very beginning they had not come into being. For life
came from thence, perfect among all living beings, sufficient unto myself,
needful of nothing, because everything is in me: plants and animals, many
gods, multitudes of demons, good souls and men blessed with virtue. The
earth is adorned with alland animals, nor has the power
manner of plants
of the soul stopped at the sea, leaving the air, the ether, and the heavens
without a soul, for there dwell all the good souls that give life to the stars.
Each thing within me strives toward the Good and each attains it according
to its ability."
one definable, the other serving to express the ineffable. Some of these are:
vision (seeing, contemplation), the One, the Good, Being, the First, etc.
Employed as means of thinking the unthinkable, they negate themselves
and must be withdrawn. This structure contradiction, tautology, vicious —
circle — is inevitable and appropriate when thought invites failure by trying
to express what is beyond thought. Examples
1. We are told that the One is attainable only through the negation of all
on the other hand Plotinus says: "Individual men differ not only because of
matter, but also by virtue of innumerable differences of form. They are not
related to one another as the portraits of Socrates to their original." Their
84 The Original Thinkers
difference springs rather from different primal forms. "Perhaps there are as
many forms as there are different particular things, insofar as the difference
does not rest merely on a lag behind the idea." "It need not frighten us that
the number of forms is necessarily infinite."
Consequently the souls' descent into the world has a twofold aspect.
Each individual soul is sent in order that the All may be complete; but
each one is also guilty through an act of freedom. The soul is sent down to
be a force in the beautiful world; at the same time, it has fallen through a
pretemporal choice that ought not to have been made. It sprang from an
original self-will, from pride and lust for change.
Both in the formation of the world as a whole and in the destiny of the
individual soul, freedom and necessity are one. "Each soul has its own
time: when that time comes, it descends as though at the call of a herald
and enters into the body that is fit to receive it." It descends neither volun-
tarily nor under compulsion. Freedom is not to be understood as free choice,
but is more "like" a natural drive, whether to mate or to perform heroic
deeds. "There is no contradiction between the voluntary and the involun-
tary character of the descent." "In accordance with the eternal laws of its
being," what it does freely, though "against its will," is necessary. What the
soul takes upon itself redounds to the benefit of the body. "Its descent may
be called a sending-down by God."
4. There is a contradiction in the concept of evil: Evil is only the less
good, that which throughout the scale contains less Being; matter is absolute
evil because it is Nonbeing. But elsewhere Plotinus departs from this
negative concept and speaks of positive evil. Evil is only the shadow of
the good, a necessary part of the total harmony; it is mere deficiency and
nothing in itself; and then again it is an active power of seduction, man's
subservience to which is the "second evil."
5. Plotinus' concept of the divine is equally contradictory. God is the One,
yet there are many gods. The One dominates all Plotinus' thinking, but
he reveres more than one god.
All these contradictions seem meaningful when Plotinus' vision of Being
is considered as a whole. Where he himself notices them, he overcomes them
by his doctrine of degrees or by his knowledge of the inadequacy of speech.
To disclose them is more to elucidate the philosophy of Plotinus than to
criticize it.
I
PLOT 1NU S 85
does not inquire into the particulars of nature, because he is concerned only
with the One. Consequently he takes over unquestioningly the mythical
conceptions of his time and its barbaric notions of science. He recognizes
demons and love magic.
But Plotinus was a man of natural good sense. In connection with the
nature of disease, astrology, demonological healers, etc., he expresses certain
criticaldoubts. He attacks the thaumaturges who "hypostasize diseases as
demonic beings" and the populace who let themselves be impressed by
their supposedly miraculous powers: "They will never convince anyone
who thinks clearly that diseases are not caused by overexertion, too much or
too little food, and processes of putrefaction."
But both the mythical-magical conceptions and the good sense apply
only to the subordinate world of nature, which is of no importance to men
of wisdom. This is the realm of material influences on the body-bound soul.
Those who would rather be guided by sensory experience than by philos-
ophy can also resort to oracles. But a man rises to the truth only by thinking,
that is, by immersion in the depths of his own soul and spirit, not through
the gods. That is why Plotinus takes no more interest in magic and astrology
than in empirical investigation and knowledge. All these fields of knowl-
edge occupy a low rank. Yet in dealing with them he shows the "simplicity
of character, combined with pure and clear thinking," to which he aspired
in all his philosophizing.
from his philosophy. The stream of
Plotinus excluded science and politics
the world process, springing from the One and returning to the One, is
ahistorical, pure actuality. The soul achieves self-certainty and transcend-
ence by thinking this one vast cipher of being. Plotinus is the purest and
most exclusive of metaphysicians.
Such serenity is possible, because the soul knows its home to be elsewhere.
Beholding the source of all things, it gains contentment in its intuition of
universal harmony.
But this contentment is that of an onlooker. The soul is twofold, affected
by sufferings, but in its innermost core unaffected, as a participant in the
world, involved in its torments, as an onlooker untouched. A wise man,
Plotinus quotes, is happy, even when slowly burned in the glowing bronze
The harmony of the whole is not disturbed by the dis-
bull of Phalaris.
harmony of the individual: Plotinus speaks of the "men who are the joy
of God, who bear all the miseries of the world with patience, even when
through the cyclical motion of the All they are afflicted with a necessary
86 The Original Thinners
evil. For our attention must be directed not at the desires of the individual,
the harmony of the whole if this harmony is not manifested in his actual
life? Who benefits by the concrete harmony which demands this terrible
mere deficiency, mere Nonbeing (and yet in the course of his thinking he
is sometimes compelled to recognize a positive evil). Anyone who ponders
the undeniable sufferings and injustices of the world cannot but rebel
against the Plotinian "peace in harmony."
In becoming a mere change of scene, death loses its sting. And this
present life loses its weight as the unique and only life. The eternal soul
has entered into this life as into one of many successive roles, its core is
unaffected. If it lives badly, it has the possibility of purification after death,
in new forms of existence. Both life and death lose their earnestness.
With this devaluation of our worldly existence and death, the particular
circumstances of life become indifferent. Bodily pain, mental torment, loss
of the necessities of life, "destruction of the city," death of our loved ones
all become meaningless appearance. Nothing in the world has absolute
importance. Only those lacking in wisdom can concern themselves seriously
with the world.
PLOT N U SI 87
The extreme situations which awaken man, but which, even after they
have brought home to him the earnestness of his existence and made
transcendence a reality tor him, never lose their real power to call everything
into question all over again, are veiled or spirited away by Plotinus' vision
of universal Being. Since fundamentally all problems raised by such a
vision are solved in advance, they lose their power. Such a system is a closed
circle: the belief in harmony annuls the extreme situations, while insensibil-
out of the world. This paradoxical union of time and eternity is unknown
to Plotinus. In his view the world is a mere stage, my life is only a role.
No decision I can make carries the weight of eternity. There is only a
rising and falling, the possibilities remain always the same. Nothing in
88 The Original Thinners
the world is really serious, the only thing that counts is purity of soul —and
this purity is situated in an innermost core, inaccessible to the world, which
finds fulfillment in incommunicable ecstasy.
Because the individual is without importance, Plotinus' conception of
love, directed toward the One, seems at once grandiose and empty. Our
love should be directed at the simple and absolute, not at anything partial
and contingent. We must see the beautiful as such, "not any of its finite
embodiments." That the "contingent," "partial," "finite" are the manifesta-
tion of an existence which is always historical, whose essential being is
distilled in the crucible of loyalty and integrity —
such an idea is alien to
Plotinus. The impersonal love of the One deprives marriage and friendship
of their meaning. Plotinus' love does not grow into the substance of the
soul through existential decision in an irreplaceable historical context; it
merely contemplates the eternal forms in degrees ranging from the genera-
tive power of nature to union with the One.
Thus it is characteristic of Plotinus that he should reject every indication
of the individual's historical substance or social setting. He declines to
speak of his own parents or origin. He refuses to love any woman, for
"there are no marriages in heaven." He cares nothing for
political existence
and unaware of its historicity. He does not know the profound meaning
is
sent by the transcendent God, who guides the soul upward from this world
created by an evil being. His purpose is purely philosophical, the self-
liberation of the individual soul; he acknowledges the splendor of this
world, and rejects both the Gnostic conception of a temporal history of
Being and the fanciful multiplication of intermediate stages which
later Neoplatonists took over from the Gnostics.
When we consider the philosophical life of his day, we can only agree
with Dodds that amid Philo's theosophical dreams, Tertullian's poisoned
fanaticism, Porphyry's amiable pieties, and the unspeakable inanities of
the Mysteries, Plotinus alone has the appeal of a true thinker; that he
rejected Gnosis and theurgy and resolutely raised the claim of reason as
instrument of philosophy and key to the structure of reality.
Both in his being and in his achievement, Plotinus was above his times.
Under the Emperor Gallienus, to be sure, art experienced a "renaissance,"
which was also the swan song of ancient classicism; but it is a far cry
from this sculpture, whose interest today is purely historical, to the philos-
ophy of Plotinus, which is an eternal monument of Western culture.
It would be mistaken to interpret the attitude of Plotinus as a weariness
reflecting the dying civilization of his age. Quite the contrary, his life and
thinking are an example of the irresistible vigor of philosophy. But his
thinking does have the power to help people in overcoming their world-
weariness.
Plotinus' influence down to our own day has been extraordinary. He
is the father of all "speculative mysticism," surpassed by none of its later
representatives. His influence is remarkable for its depth and also for the
distortions it has undergone.
Plotinus is regarded as the founder of "Neoplatonism." He lived in the
third century, Iamblichus in the fourth, Proclus in the fifth, Damascius and
Simpiicius in the sixth century. But "the influence of Plotinus' original
text on the Neoplatonists is almost non-existent. Actual quotations are
rare" (Harder). Plotinus' successors did not derive from his spirit. They
were chiefly interested in pagan religion, in transforming the
restoring
figures of the philosophers into saints, in founding a philosophical religion.
They were given to undisciplined flights of fancy. At the same time, they
developed a philosophical scholarship some of whose achievements are
still highly valued, and some of them were extraordinary teachers of
philosophy.
was also taken over by Christian thinkers, above all by Augus-
Plotinus
tine. Here the philosophical source was negated. Plotinus' transcendent
One was manifest to reason; the Christian God manifested Himself through
Christ. The new philosophy was based, not on philosophical inquiry as
such, but on faith in a unique revelation. Plotinus' Above-Being was
degraded to Being, the spiritual cosmos was elevated to become God's
thoughts. The two merged and became a personal God. Plotinus' three
hypostases (the One, Spirit, the World-Soul) were replaced by the Trinity;
Plotinus'emergence of all being, by the Creation and the mysterious
between the members of the Trinity.
relations
In Neoplatonism the materialization of Plotinian thinking found its
most impressive representative in Proclus (410-485). The ideas of Proclus
were taken up in the writings of Pseudo-Dionysius Areopagita (c. 500),
92 The Original Thinkers
Wor\s: The greater part of his work was written in the monastery of Bee.
His writings deal with God (Monologiutn de divinatis essentia, Proslogium),
with God and man (De veritate, De libero arbitrio, De casu Diaboli), As
archbishop he thought through the great dogmatic questions (in his contro-
versy with Roscellinus: De fide trinitatis, 1093; on the occasion of the Synod
of Bari with the Greeks: De processione Spiritus Sancti; in exile: Cur deus
homo and De conceptu virginali et originali peccato; finally, in the last
monks led a rich, active life, unrestricted by national frontiers. Born in Italy,
93
94 The Original Thinners
—
believe Him to be. Can pure thought unclouded by folly and uninfluenced
—
by the obedience of faith acquire certainty of God's being? Yes, says Anselm.
His demonstration is as follows:
Think: God is "a being than which nothing greater can be conceived
(Quo maius cogitari non potest)."
The fool replies: There is no God, because the idea of the greatest is
only a thought in the mind; merely by being thought, its content does not
become real.
To this we answer: It is one thing to exist only in the mind and another
A painter can have a picture in his mind without
to exist also in reality.
having painted But with the idea of God it is a different matter. The
it.
fool must admit "that something exists in the understanding at least, than
which nothing greater can be conceived." This admission suffices. For a
thing, than which nothing greater can be thought, cannot exist only in the
understanding. Why not? Because then the greatest thing that really is
would be greater than the greatest that is only thought and does not exist
in reality. If the greatest were only in the understanding, the greatest which
in addition really existed would be greater than that which is present only
in thought.
To conceive of a greatest that is present only in the understanding and not
which no greater can be conceived exists both in the mind and in reality.
This certainty is free from doubt. It is perfect certainty, because we cannot,
without contradiction, think that the greatest, beyond which no greater is
thinkable, does not exist.
The same idea can be expressed in a number of variants:
If the greatest beyond which no greater can be conceived, is not conceived
as existing, it is not the greatest.
It is so true that that beyond which no greater can be conceived really
Either I must abandon the idea, or I must conceive of its content as real.
the never visible far side of the moon, is "proved"; such a proof is immediately
refuted, because it cannot be confirmed by experience. Seen in this light,
stages, and does not strive for visions and ecstasies. His concern is pure
thought. He aims not at psychic experience, not at emotional intoxication,
but at sober, compelling clarity, in regard to the all-important.
is no other being besides God whose existence can be derived from its
essence. The nonexistence of every other object is thinkable. The existence
must be demonstrated by its existence in the world.
of every other object
But Anselm's idea is derived neither from universal premises nor from
experience.
The ontological proof had already been conceived as a mere universal,
that is, in rational abstraction, by Anselm's contemporary and adversary,
Gaunilon. In disagreement with Gaunilon, Anselm denied that the idea
of God as that being "than which nothing greater can be conceived,"
could apply to Gaunilon's "island which is more excellent than all islands."
According to Anselm, the existence of such an island does not follow from
its excellence. Invoking God, Anselm declares "Everything that is, excepting
:
AN SELM 97
thee alone, can be conceived as not being. Thou alone of all things hast Being
in the truest sense, and hence most of all."
Thus the idea cannot be dissociated from its content and stated as a
syllogism with the major premise: Every thing that is conceived as the
most perfect of its kind also has existence. This relation between being-
thought and being applies only to God. One who thinks of God can think
of Him only as being. Consequently all other existents, which can be
conceived also to be nonexistent, are other and poorer in being than God.
God's being or existence, or whatever we may choose to call it, is not
the mode an island
of reality of something, of any thing in the world, of
(Gaunilon) or of a hundred thalers (Kant). It alone is the being by virtue
of which it is impossible that it is not and that nothing is and which as —
such is a certainty in our thinking.
This impossibility of nothingness takes the form of the unthinkable
only in connection with God. It is manifested to thought, which is itself
being, though only created being. As an image of God's creative thinking,
it perceives the necessary being of God through itself.
4.No object: The "being than which nothing greater can be conceived"
{quo maius cogitari nequit) must be conceived in its authentic essence. It
is not, Gaunilon said, "greater than all beings" {maius omnibus).
as
For then would merely be a thing. If God is conceived as the highest
it
was made."
He cannot succeed in his meditation by his own strength. "I strove
toward God, and I stumbled on myself." "Enlighten us, reveal thyself to
us." "Teach me to seek thee, and unveil thyself to me, when I seek thee,
for I cannot seek thee, except thou teach me, nor find thee, except thou
reveal thyself.I will seek thee in yearning, and yearn for thee in my seek-
ing." Prayer and invocation are not only at the beginning and end; they
permeate the whole thought process. It is not a mere logical operation
applying to something seen from outside.
The treatise in which the idea is put forward is significantly entitled:
Proslogium, The Invocation of God; Anselm had originally meant to
call it "Fides quaerens intellectum ," "Faith Seeking Understanding,"
but this title was dropped. The work presupposes faith, not any dogmatic
article of faith (nor a logical premise from which the idea would be de-
rived), but a fundamental human state or attitude, or the being or essence
of man. With this as his basis, Anselm strives "to lift his mind to the
contemplation of God, and seeks to understand what he believes."
AN SELM 99
—
in order to understand. For this also I believe that unless I believe, I should
not understand." But at the end of the "proof" he writes "What I formerly :
makes possible the second at the end. But the second sentence tells us that
in his idea, once attained, Anselm sees more than a mere interpretation of
the ratio fidei.
the search for a thing which could not be found. But I wished to when
exclude this thought altogether then more and more, though I was
. . .
unwilling and shunned it, it began to force itself upon me, with a kind of
importunity. So, one day, when I was exceedingly wearied with resisting
its importunity, in the very conflict of my thoughts, the proof of which I
had despaired offered itself, so that I eagerly embraced the thoughts which
I was strenuously repelling." Anselm's biographer, Eadmer, writes: "This
thought allowed him neither to sleep, eat, nor drink and, what troubled
him still more, it interfered with his devotions at matins and at other times.
He believed that such thoughts might be temptations of the Devil and
endeavored to banish them from his mind entirely. But the more violently
he sought to do so, the more they besieged him. And one night, as he
lay awake, it happened: God's grace illumined his heart, the object of his
quest lay bared to his understanding, and his whole innermost being
was filled with boundless rejoicing."
This isfrom being the only instance of a fundamental philo-
far
sophical ideacoming to a thinker as a gift, after a long period of inner
—
struggle somewhat in the same way as prophetic revelation or conversion.
Parmenides built a temple in thanks to the god; Cusanus relates that his
fundamental idea descended upon him as an "illumination from above,"
on his return journey from Constantinople; while Descartes tells us that
ANSELM 101
his central idea came to him in winter quarters at Neuburg and that he
gave thanks for it by going on a pilgrimage. The mere fact that great
philosophers have attached so much biographical importance to cer-
tain thoughts forbids us to take them lightly.
The monk Gaunilon agreed with both these assertions but took them as
premises with which to develop his objections to Anselm. To his mind,
a thinking conscious of the reality of its object is not cogitare (understand-
ing) but intelligere (higher insight). If Anselm took thinking in this
specific sense as intelligere, he would not distinguish between the mere
possession of an object in thought and knowledge of its reality. For in
intellection the two coincide.
In answer to this Anselm said: It is the failure of thinking (in the sense
of cogitare) that first leads to authentic intellection. For in relation to all
finite things, the immediate knowledge (intelligere) of a reality does not
preclude the possibility of conceiving its nonexistence. Only in one case,
the knowledge (intelligere) of the highest being, is our knowledge (intel-
to become insight into the reality of God, which is radically different from
knowledge of the real things of the world.
Gaunilon did not doubt the reality of God, but denied that he could
gain insight into this reality through thought and demonstration. It is
impossible, he says, to gain an adequate idea of the Supreme Being. From
this it follows that I must conceive of this being as real, not that it really
exists. Actual reality does not follow from imagined reality or reality
True, they cannot really know what they are saying; but thinking (cogitare)
can impel them to perceive the vanity of their discourse and put them on the
path to authentic insight.
Gaunilon's arguments all have one thing in common. Based as they are
on pious faith, they seem more reliable than Anselm's philosophical argu-
ments. But they move in the realm of the understanding, into which they
also draw the distinction between cogitare and intelligere; for actually
Gaunilon's intelligere refers only to the reality of finite things. This pre-
vents Gaunilon from getting to the heart of Anselm's thought. For Anselm
arrives at his intelligere by way of cogitare.
With Gaunilon philosophical thinking breaks down into two parts:
on the one hand the empty formalism of correct or incorrect statements
(from which Anselm's meanings are excluded), and on the other hand,
the immediate, indubitable, unthinking certainty of God. But neither the
rationality of compelling but empty statements nor immediate unthinking
faith is capable of gaining certainty in thought or of philosophical tran-
scending. Such rationality degenerates into an indifferent correctness, while
unthinking faith culminates in blind obedience to an unknown authority.
The cleavage between the two stifles true, free philosophizing. It appeals to
common sense, the common sense of godlessness as well as authoritarian
faith. Where either of these becomes the supreme authority, philosophy
dies.
think He does not exist. This Thomas denies. In his view someone can
perfectly well think that God is not. He might think, for example, that
there is no being than which a greater cannot be conceived. Thus Anselm's
proposition actually starts from the premise that there is something than
which no greater can be conceived. Since Anselm assumes this, he does
not prove it. And elsewhere: according to Anselm, the knowledge that
God's name signifies God signifies also that God is. The name signifies
the being than which no greater can be conceived. What exists in reality
and in the mind is greater than that which exists only in the mind. Hence
from our insight into the meaning of God's name there follows the insight
that He is in reality. Thus God's existence is self-evident. In answer to
this, Thomas says: Granted that God is essentially His Being; but to us
who do not know what God is, it is not self-evident that He is. We cannot
assert that He really is unless we assume that there really is something
than which no greater can be conceived.
What is the meaning of Thomas' position? Anselm and Thomas are
one in the certainty that God is that being than which no greater can be
conceived. But whence this certainty? It may derive from something out-
side, from the reality of the world, which leads us to infer the existence of
—
God as Creator Anselm does not deny this possibility. For Thomas it
is the only way open to the natural intelligence. Or else it may have its
without faith. Since our thinking must always start from our experience,
all inferences must be based on sense perception in the world. These infer-
ences are classified according to their grounds: from the fact of motion,
we infer the existence of a first unmoved mover; from the series of causes,
thinking filled with the philosopher's own existence. Anselm trusts pro-
foundly in the unity of thought and faith in the source of reason, that is, of
philosophy. In the age of Thomas, the danger of thought for authority had
become more evident than in Anselm's day. Thomas tried to conjure
far
this danger, on the one hand by accepting common-sense thinking but defin-
ing its limits, and on the other hand by complementing it with the mystery
of revelation. He accepted common-sense thinking at the cost of subordinat-
ing all thinking to mystery. There was no longer room for Anselm's great
philosophizing. It slipped away between the two tangible corporeal realities.
It might seem as though Thomas had sensed the enormous danger for
Duns Scotus, and Hegel, which in many variants disclose a trace of Anselm's
spirit. I shall also pass over Spinoza, who simply made Anselm's funda-
mental idea into the first of his definitions, from which he constructs his
figures of thought: "By cause of itself I mean that whose essence comprises
existence or that whose nature can only be conceived as existing." Instead,
I shall consider Descartes and Leibniz, who both affirm Anselm's idea, but
degrade it into a proof of objectively compelling character, treating its object
as a fact and trying
improve man's understanding of this fact.
to
Descartes: Descartes held Anselm's proof to be correct. Only of the high-
est being, of God alone, can it be said that His essence includes existence.
have and this fact becomes the ultimate ground of Anselm's proof. The
it,
idea of the most perfect being, even the idea of a being more perfect than I,
cannot stem from myself and cannot come from nothing. It must have an
adequate cause. I who have this idea could not exist if there were not such
a being. "The whole compelling force of this proof lies in my recognition
that I myself with my nature —insofar as I have the idea of God in me—could
not possibly exist if God did not really exist." Existence as such, knowing it-
from existence, that is, from the thinking which experiences reality and not
mere logical necessity, or rather which in logical necessity experiences
something more. Both try characteristically to improve on the proof, inject-
ing a new presupposition that is supposed to give it full validity. Neverthe-
less,something of Anselm's substance remains; God's uniqueness and relation
to my own existence are still present. Without these, the proof, transformed
into an objective logical operation, becomes empty and meaningless. This
was understood by Kant, who did not know Anselm's proof in the original,
but only as paraphrased by the rationalists. Finding Anselm's idea in this
denatured form, Kant termed it the ontological proof of the existence of
God, and refuted it.
AN SELM 107
Kant: Like Anselm, Kant perceived the unique value of the idea over
against the many proofs of the existence of God. "If the absolute necessity
of a thing is to be known in theoretical consciousness, this might be done
solely on the basis of concepts a priori, never on the basis of a cause in relation
namely to the fact that knowledge of an object is possible through the expe-
rience of perception, can its existence be demonstrated. In speaking of an
object of sense perception, we would not confuse the existence of a thing
with the concept of that thing. But in dealing with an object of pure
thought, even ifwe impute every perfection to it, even if it is free from all
contradiction, we still have no means of proving it to be real. For reality
is not one of the predicates of a concept, but pertains to the relation of a
thing to our existence and experience. "A hundred real thalers do not con-
tain the least coin more than a hundred possible thalers. . . . My financial
position is, however, affected very differently by a hundred real thalers
than it is by the mere concept of them (that is, of their possibility)."
Here Kant radically rejects the possibility of attaining certainty of Being
by thinking pure and simple. For thought is as such objectless (mere possi-
bility) and, in order to gain objective significance, requires completion.
From an idea we cannot "pick out" the existence of a corresponding object.
The ontological proof must either take existence into the concept (the "most
108 The Original Thinners
real being") : then the thought itself would have to be a thing, which is
cannot know the transcendent as I know things in the world. I cannot gain
possession of it by knowledge and have it as I can have an object. It is
For Kant the question is very much the same as for Anselm: How shall
Between Anselm and Kant there is a kinship that skips over all the inter-
vening historical links. An indication of this is that for both of them there
is only one essential proof. This one proof is not a mere content of thought,
Our thinking moves in several directions, actuality is
but God's presence.
famous saying about the two things the starry heavens above
one. In his —
me and the moral law within me— that fill the heart with ever-renewed
wonder and awe, he adds: "I see them before me and link them directly
with the consciousness of my existence."
In the consciousness of their own Existenz, elucidated in thinking, both
gain certainty of God's existence. Kant, who rejects the ontological proof,
does not call his "ethical" demonstration of the existence of God a proof,
but a postulate. Because the certainty of God's existence is not grounded in
an objective proof of the understanding, Kant, after setting forth the
thought that leads to God, does not say "He is a certainty," but "I am certain."
Anselm and Kant apprehend the one source of a certainty that can be
expressed in rational terms but not demonstrated by reason. Their thinking
is not a thinking "about" something, but a thinking Existenz, in which what
they think becomes real for them. All the others, Thomas, Descartes, or
Leibniz, whether for or against Anselm's proof, think in a very different
way from Anselm and Kant.
These two in turn differ in their fundamental experience. Both attain
to being in thought, but Anselm does so in pure thought, which is not
cogitare but intelligere, Kant in practical thinking governed by an absolute
law. For Kant my thinking awareness of the law I ought to follow contains
something more than law, namely God. For Anselm, my thinking of the
being than which no greater can be conceived, contains more than thought.
In both cases, God becomes a certainty through their existence.
For neither thinker is God an acquisition of disinterested knowledge;
He is present only to believing reason. Certainty is sought in the never-
ending movement of our existence in time. For Anselm it requires purity
of heart, without which his "idea" cannot be realized. In Anselm reflection
is meditative and leads back to Christian faith. For Kant it is reflexive,
leading back to the rational existence of ethical action.
Such ideas may appear to be mere technical devices by which to gain
certainty of God's existence, but for those who first enact them, they are
events: these thinkers have found something never to be forgotten, that
sustains their lives for ever after. Later, such ideas are disseminated in a
rational simplification and become ineffectual, mere doctrine. Nevertheless,
them is an impulse,
they preserve an inexhaustible power, for hidden within
a spark, which can take any moment, whenever it falls on a soul
fire at
the area of Kantian critical thinking for Anselm's idea as Anselm intended
it: the power of logical thought to transcend thought with thought in an
attitude of prayer ?
His thinking treats of truth, free will, evil, and the doctrines of the God-
man {cur deus homo) and the Trinity. He believed that faith could be
made accessible to reason. When Kant writes of religion within the limits
of mere reason and Anselm seeks reason in the contents of faith (according
to the Augustinian principle: credo ut intelligam), the difference between
them is that one did his thinking before the cleavage into faith and reason,
theology and philosophy, the other afterward. In both the will to auton-
omous reason and were at work; both knew
a lofty concept of reason
that the reality of reason does not haveground in itself.
its
Anselm was the great original thinker of the Middle Ages. To be sure, the
continuity of Christian thinking paved the way for his philosophy. But
this was only the source of the power which enabled him, like Augustine,
to philosophize independently. Like Augustine, he saw faith as the source
and nominalism (the universals are mere names, nomind). The controversy
developed in connection with statements of Porphyry and Boethius. Con-
sidering that Plato speaks of an independent existence of ideas, separate
from things, and that Aristotle grants their existence only in things,
Boethius declared that he did not wish to decide whether they exist only
in our understanding (as mere words or names) or whether they exist
objectively (are real), whether, in other words, Plato or Aristotle was
right,and further whether they are corporeal or incorporeal.
Through the centuries the question was answered in radical antitheses
or in compromises. The one-sided standpoints are: (i) Only the universals
are truly real; particular things are only representations of the universal
that is identical in them all. (2) Only individuals are truly real. The
universals are words, which have reality only as audible, visible things
that signify something.
In both one-sided solutions a new fundamental problem makes its
appearance in opposite forms: (1) If the universal is the real, then the
question arises: Where do the individuals come from (the question of the
principium individuationis) ? (2) If the individuals are the real, the op-
posite question arises: What is the source of the universal (the existence of
the universal as names, signs, meanings derived by abstraction) ?
In the Middle Ages these sciences existed only in germ. But from time
immemorial man's natural drive for knowledge has rebelled against the
notion that science has no connection with reality itself. As early a thinker
as Gerbert of Aurillac (c. iooo) wrote that the classification of the things
of nature into genera and species was not the result of human designs but
of the Creator of all arts, who produced it as part of the nature of things,
where men of discernment discovered it.
Here we shall not enter into the question of the relation between knowl-
edge and reality, or of the kind of reality that is revealed to scientific
knowledge. Anselm and the great medieval thinkers who recognized no —
difference between philosophy and science, who in their philosophy looked
to the essential which even today is not accessible to any science saw this —
question in a very different light; for them it was of the utmost gravity for
faith and salvation.
To Anselm nominalist thinking was no true thinking at all. For it is
no thinking that declares its concepts to be empty, mere words (flatus vocis,
emissions of voice). Anselm attacks this manner of thinking, which he
regarded as unbelief or dangerous to belief. These men, he says, are so
ensnared by sensory images (imaginationibus corporalibus) that they cannot
tear themselves freefrom them. They cannot see what reason must con-
template in its own
light. In Anselm's dogmatic attacks on Roscellinus
To Anselm the most natural kind of thinking is that which does not
lose itself amid the emptiness of mere discourse or let itself be confined by
representations, but rises to the essential. He knows the peace deriving from
the identity of thought and object and attains to it by a kind of thinking
ANSELM 113
Such thinking attains to the place where truth is reality and there finds
fulfillment, in God. In the created world the truth is split: into things and
the knowledge of these things, into the reality of things and what they
ought to be. Hence all created things are still in quest of their being,
they are not yet that being; in our transient lives, we find it and lose it
again. But this is made possible only by the reality of the truth; everything
that is real without being perceptible to the senses relates to that reality,
which, however is not a subjective fiction, produced by thinking, but
objective reality for thinking.
This philosophical thinking is so different from finite object thinking
that from the standpoint of the latter it can only seem empty and absurd.
It presupposes that true being is itself the being of thinking, a thinking-
being, and that our thought is not a mere abstraction, but also something
very concrete, which penetrates to the thinking-being in the ground of
all things. Only under this assumption can man's thinking lay claim to a
higher reality than that of empirical events in time. If this presupposition
is taken away, authentic thinking ceases, and I fall back into an existence
which is real only to an outsider who thinks it, but which does not know
itself and, because it lacks true self-knowledge, is not master of itself.
ligere through the cogitart. As such it is a necessary element, but once this
aim is attained, there is no further need for it. To Anselm contradiction
was intolerable. It is not masked by factors of other origin, which hide
1
14
The Original Thinners
c. Authority: Man can live only under authority, and this has been true
at all times. If he is unwilling to accept authority, he will merely succumb
to a more external violence. The
being free from all authority
illusion of
causes men to fling most absurd and destructive
themselves into the
obedience. The claim that each individual is entitled to absolute freedom
of opinion dulls men's minds and leads to some form of total subjugation.
Man has only the choice of which authority to accept, that is, on what set
of beliefs to ground his life. There is no outside vantage point from which
to survey all authority. To stand outside means to stand in nothingness
and to be blind. But my choice of authority is not deliberate; I can only
gain a purified awareness of the authority in which I am already living,
that is, I can awaken the latent authority within me by recollecting the
ground of my being. I cannot look deep enough for this ground, because
it is there that what has absolute validity for me.
I shall find
In Anselm we see the bond of authority and the freedom of reason in
its acceptance. He knows that empty reasoning achieves nothing. But he
also knows that faith is not enough: "It strikes me as negligence if, once
we are secure in faith, we do not try to understand what we believe."
Anselm's faith is still sheltered in the authority of the Church. He finds
authority for his thinking in the Catholic Church Fathers. He desires above
all that what he himself thinks "should accord with what was written by
St. Augustine."
Anselm could not be aware of the special historical character of his
time. To him it could not seem extraordinary that in a still barbarous world
the Church, thanks to the self-sacrificing lives of the monastic orders,
should be the sole source of all intellectual greatness, of all philosophy and
education, and indeed of all reading and writing, and that not only the
most learned but also the noblest men of the day were members of the
clergy. The Church still signified an identity of spirit and power; this
most "catholic" of Western organizations still signified the power of the
spirit against raw violence. And it meant absolute certainty. To question
the Church and its monastic orders in those days would have been to
question everything that men live by.
tried to persuade him by his treatise on the Trinity. But faced with the
alternatives of martyrdom and hypocrisy, Roscellinus for fear of death, —
as he said later —chose hypocrisy.
Anselm's thinking is the free thinking of a man of the Church, whom the
reality of God's rule through the Church made humble, but at the same
time courageous and mighty in the struggle against the King and the world.
Anselm's attitude might be called grandiose naivete, were it not a sub-
limated awareness, lacking in only one thing, which in that age was un-
thinkable: doubt in the legitimacy of the kingdom of God claimed by the
Church, in the ethical rank of the Church as a real political power. Like
Plato's political venture in Syracuse, Anselm's struggle in behalf of the
Church was a phenomenon of transition, possible only once with true
integrity, without superstition and magic, without of dema-
the help
gogically aroused mass instincts. That such action was taken once, with
such human power, purity, and greatness, is inspiring forever, even if
the moment of its supreme action, the Church became an evil power. But
what was overpoweringly great in the idea, what for a moment achieved
reality in approximations, what fired men's enthusiasm while preserving a
endures for memory in the eternal realm of the spirit. In a new world, where
men seek transcendence under new conditions, this thing that once happened
can still serve as an orientation.
NICHOLAS OF CUSA
INTRODUCTION
Nikolaus Krebs (or ChryfTs) was born in Kues on the Moselle, the son of
a prosperous winegrower and boatman. He has come to be known as
Cusanus after Cusa, the Latinized form of Kues, his birthplace. He is the
only one of the great philosophers to have led a busy life in the world
from an early age to the day of his death. He served the Church as a member
of the Council of Basel, as cardinal, bishop, and vicar general in Rome.
The great Christian thinkers had all been members of religious orders;
monastic life left its imprint upon them. Cusanus was a secular priest.
Deeply religious, he enjoyed the friendship of monks. In his old age, a
monk's cell was always kept in readiness for him in Tegernsee in case
he should wish to retire into a life of meditation. Though his stormy politi-
cal activities and arduous travels might have sufficed to consume his energies,
he produced a body of philosophical writings whose great importance is
generally recognized today.
This work was not a hobby or avocation pursued in it grew
his free time:
out of his practical activities and was intended to give them meaning. But
while his quest for a union between theory and practice endows both with
a character of grandeur, his attempts to achieve that union proved more and
more disappointing as he grew older. He wished his actions to be an integral
part of the intellectual order embracing God and the world, man and the
Church. He must have been inspired by a fundamental impulse that tran-
scended both his thought and his action. Having failed in his primary inten-
tion, he fell back on philosophical speculation, but his philosophy was not
of a kind that could provide him with a constant serenity and equanimity
in dealing with things of the world.
His modesty, his renunciation of the ostentatious splendors attaching to
his position as a prince of the Church, his simplicity free from the rigors of
asceticism, gave him dignity. We cannot doubt his sense of responsibility
or the genuineness of his commitment. But the realities confronting him
were not what he believed them to be, and he was essentially unaware of
this fact and its consequences. What is "reality"? The question becomes
especially urgent when we consider this man whose worldly activities
were oriented toward God and eternity, yet in the end it remains unanswered.
116
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 117
LIFE
dence) in 1417 he went to Padua, where he studied for six years. In Padua
;
he was initiated into the intellectual world of his period. At least two of
his teachers became his friends —
Toscanelli, the physician, geographer, and
physicist, who was with Cusanus when he died, and Giuliano Cesarini,
later Cardinal and President of the Council of Basel, who sponsored his
put an end to the papal schism. Nevertheless, was clear that the world
it
reform and his defense of the rights of the Church against secular rulers
(such as Duke Sigismund of Austria) fired conflicts which did not cease
until shortly after Cusanus' death, when the Church agreed to a compro-
mise.
In 1451 and 1452 Cusanus traveled through Germany as papal nuncio,
charged with the mission of reforming the churches and monasteries, and
of promulgating the Jubilee indulgence of 1450. On the whole his mission
was a resounding failure.
Right down to his death he continued to work for the papacy, the last
six years in the post of vicar general in Rome, the highest ecclesiastical
office next to the papacy itself. During these last years he acted as the
most trusted adviser of Pius II (Enea Silvio de' Piccolomini), who had
been his friend for decades.
Cusanus died in the midst of his last mission, on August 11, 1464, at Todi
in Umbria. Three days later Pius II died in Ancona and the fantastically
unrealistic crusade against the Turks, which the Pope had championed
against Cusanus' advice, came to an inglorious end.
Some writers have described Cusanus in his last years as tired and re-
signed. I cannot agree. His last writings show the keenest intellectual energy
and concentration. They bear witness to an undiminished preoccupation
with fundamentals. For all his great disappointments in the field of active
politics, he never carried out his earlier plan of withdrawing to a monas-
tery in his old age. His turning away from the political activity which had
provided an outlet for the stormy exuberance of his youth had nothing in
common with weariness.
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 119
WORKS
Nicholas of Cusa was familiar with the scholastics and mystics, with the
philosophers of antiquity and the Church Fathers. He was interested in all
the sciences of his time. As and statesman and priest, he was a
a jurist
powerful and effective speaker. Nearly all his thinking revolved around
a single idea: God is revealed in everything that is, in everything that is
M54-57) •
The language and literary form of Cusanus' works are not classical.
images. But he can also lapse into traditional, schematic thinking or become
painfully long-winded.
It has been maintained, especially with reference to a statement about
himself at the beginning of De apice theoriae, that Cusanus' philosophy
develops progressively. I cannot accept this view.His writings as a whole
represent, rather, the continual transformation and enrichment of a single
insight. In each of them, one or another aspect is stressed, e.g., experience
or, on the contrary, the need to transcend the limits of our conceptual think-
ing. But this does not imply a progressive development in which earlier
theses are rejected as false, and new and purer truth attained.
A different question is whether the kind of thinking first disclosed in
De docta ignorantia now clearly and methodically, now soaring in full
flight, betokens a sudden advance in the development of Cusanus' thought.
comes all that is best, that I was led to conceive the incomprehensible in
an incomprehensible way in the knowledge of nonknowledge, by going
beyond [per transcensum] the indestructible truths as they are known in
the human way." Is this merely a literary effusion, or does it refer to some
reality such as we encounter in the autobiographical references of other
great philosophers (Anselm, Descartes, Kant, Nietzsche) ? I am convinced
that the latter is the case. The whose
illuminating power of the new idea,
development was now had left
to supply the content of his intellectual life,
an indelible impression. This was not just one more idea, it was a new
kind of thinking. It marked Cusanus' "initiation" into philosophy. His
extraordinary intelligence and his underlying faith remained unchanged;
but all this was now absorbed in a new intellectual perspective, carried
into a new dimension of depth. An insight into this new dimension is
tia oppositorum, or at least the idea that all opposites are transcended, is
make such discoveries in philosophical texts from Plato on, we are tempted
to ask the disabused old question: What, then, is really new? If we look long
and hard enough, we find that everything has already been said. And this
is true enough for the mere verbal formulations. But it is not true in respect
of the thought itself. The originality of an idea lies in the thinker's sudden
insight, perhapstouched off by something he is studying or perhaps by
something he once read and has since forgotten. The objective novelty of
an idea is recognizable by the fact that, when related to the other ideas in a
work, it discloses a unique, irreplaceable quality, a fundamental tone, so to
speak, which governs the development of the work as a whole. I shall try
to outline what is fundamental in Nicholas of Cusa's philosophical specula-
tions.
b. Beyond the domain of the finite. Such is the world as it appears to our
discursive reason. But to stay within it leaves us dissatisfied. We should
like to go beyond this world in which there is always a larger and a
smaller, into a world of the absolutely largest and the absolutely smallest,
122 The Original Thinners
that is, we should like to pass from the domain of limits to the unlimited,
from the domain of the finite to infinity.
c. Between the finite and the infinite there is no common term. This im-
pulse encounters strong resistance. We can have knowledge only of finite
between the world and God. Plato called it tmema (cut, incision).
"Thus, in the concrete, there is no ascent to the absolutely greatest and
no descent to the absolutely smallest. Therefore, just as the divine, abso-
lutely greatest being cannot be diminished to such an extent that it becomes
limited and finite, so the concrete cannot relinquish its concreteness to the
extent of becoming absolute" {De doc. ignor., Ill, 1).
awareness: it is that in the face of which our reason breaks down when we
try to understand and define it. It discloses itself in the awareness of the
thinker who, when his reason breaks down, discovers in himself a power
bursting the bonds of discursive reason, whose logic is valid only within
its own sphere. This power is the intellect, or speculative reason (intellectus) ,
which makes use of discursive reason (ratio) but is able to obtain insights
into what is not accessible to discursive reason.
The godhead is not accessible to discursive knowledge, but
infinity of the
the intellect can touch upon it as long as discursive reason is in a state of
ignorance. Now this ignorance is not the empty ignorance of someone
unaware of not knowing, or indifferent to what he is incapable of knowing.
It is, rather, a "learned ignorance" (docta ignorantia), which is developed
e. The "Wall." Cusanus had his own way of describing the boundary line
between the finite and the domain of the
objects of discursive reason
infinite to which the around the domain
intellect aspires. There is a wall
of the godhead, too high for us to climb over. Yet what lies behind the
wall is active, present, all-underlying. We fail when we try to break through
the wall, but in the process of coming up against it, we recognize it as the
sign of godhead.
Cusanus addresses God: God, because
"I give Thee thanks, my . . .
This place "is girt round with the coincidence of contradictories," and
this is "the wall of Paradise" wherein God abides. The spirit of discursive
reason guards the door, "and unless he be vanquished, the way in will
not lie beyond the coincidence of contradictories that Thou
open. Thus it is
1 The Vision of God. Translated by Emma Gurney Salter. Frederick Ungar Publishing Co., New
York. Republished i960 by arrangement with E. P. Dutton & Co., New York. First published
1928. The translation is here slightly modified.
124 The Original Thinners
conjunction alike are that wall of coincidence beyond which Thou existest,
set free from all that can be spoken or thought" (ibid., p. 53).
that is, by a polygon with ever more sides, but the polygon will never
coincide with the circle. Yet if the number of sides is infinite, the situation
is altered: a polygon with an infinite number of sides is identical with a
circle.
"The infinite polygon" —in which the opposites polygon and circle
coincide — is an inherently contradictory term. It is not an objective reality.
Which signifies: the One, the Greatest, is Unity, whence follows its unique-
ness.
This Unique One cannot be a compound. It is one and not many. It is
free from all relation to the Other. The infinite can have nothing outside
it. It is all and all is within it. Nor can it be opposed to any Other, to the
finite. Rather, it has transcended all oppositions within itself.
Because all opposites coincide in it, the greatest and the smallest also
coincide in it. In it the absolutely greatest and the absolutely smallest are
identical.
Cusanus makes use of this in his interpretation of Christ, the God-Man:
When God becomes man, visible in the world, the extreme opposites must
coincide in this mystery. "Then the smallest coincides with the greatest:
the greatest humiliation with the greatest elevation, the most ignominious
death of the pious with life everlasting, and the same is true of the rest,
as we are shown by Christ's life, passion, and death on the Cross" (De doc.
ignor., Ill, 6).
loc.cit., p. 4c)).
h. On and —
beyond what? whither? Speculative thinking leads to
on
points of rest where truth itself seems to be really present. But once stated,
the thought does not bring repose and gratification. Rather, the impulse
is aroused to carry speculation further, beyond what has been attained and
creation and existence are the same. "And creating and being created
alike are nothing else than the sharing of Thy being among all, that Thou
mayest be and yet mayest abide freed from all" (ibid.).
all in all,
In other words, on this side of the wall is the thinking that tries to
comprehend the creating creator; the wall itself is the coincidence of
opposites: creating and being created; beyond the wall lies unrestricted
infinity, to which no name is adequate, which cannot be seen through
He who approaches Thee must needs ascend above every limit and end
and finite thing. . . . He who ascends above the end, does he not enter . . .
The intellect knows that it is ignorant, and that Thou canst not be grasped
because Thou art infinity. For to understand infinity is to comprehend the
incomprehensible" (De vis. dei, loc. cit., p. 60).
Because God is infinite, He is the goal of our longing. "That which
sates the intellect, or that is the end thereof, is not that which it understands;
neither can that sate it which it does not understand at all, but that alone
which it understands by not understanding. For the intelligible which it
knows does not sate it, nor the intelligible of which it is utterly ignorant,
but only the intelligible which it knows to be so intelligible that it can never
be fully understood —this alone can sate it" (op. cit., pp. 78-79).
This is the paradox of Cusanus' thinking: By its power of attraction
the infinite engenders longing. When we accede to this longing, we are
brought into the presence of the infinite. Longing and repose coincide.
The hunt for wisdom does not bring results that can be possessed in the
form of ready-made knowledge; it only discovers movements of thought
that we must carry out, intellectual experiences that we must repeat.
Such thinking is a persistent contemplation, the movement of which
promotes the awareness of being that sustains life. The state of speculative
meditation leads to a consciousness freed from practical concerns, drawing
its contents from other sources. Cognition becomes love, and love engenders
cognition. What attains clarity in the calm of meditation is what has
always sustained life and must ever more consciously sustain all future
128 It he Original Thinners
We shall consider three questions in detail: (i) What is the mind which
experiences this kind of thinking? (2) What is the faith that sustains it?
a. The image of God, which \nows itself. If every created thing is an—
image of God, the human mind {mens) is one par excellence. For not
only is it His image; it also knows it is His image. Cusanus writes: Man,
the living and spiritual image of God, knows when he enters into himself
that he is an image of the same kind as its original (in se intrat et scit se
talem esse imaginem, quale est suum exemplar). He glimpses in himself
this original, his God (deum suum), whose likeness (similitudo) he is
(De ven. sap., 17).
Because man's knowledge is merely an image of divine knowledge, it
cannot resemble God's. This too he knows. When an animal does not
know, it does not know that it does not know. Only man knows that he
does not originally, fundamentally know. Through this knowing non-
knowledge he finds the way to truth.
When with the help of the method of the coincidentia oppositorum,
the mind goes beyond discursive reason, passes through the intellect, and
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 129
making use of itself in its capacity as an image of God's mind {De mente, 7).
d. Greatness of the human mind.— The power of the human mind, says
Cusanus, is admirable.
Although God creates real things {entia realia), man creates concepts
130 The Original Thinners
any form and create concepts of all things (De mente, 4).
f. Man as microcosm. —
When man as image of God's infinity discovers the
creative bent of his mind, he embraces the whole universe with it. Just as
he is a second God, so he is a second world, the microcosm (De con., II, 4).
Man, however, comprises the universe only in a limited human way.
Man is a world, but, because he man, he is not the concrete universe.
is
the otherness of the infinite One. The more it detaches itself from its other-
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 131
ness and ascends to the simplest One, the closer it comes to perfection.
Since the other can he known only in relation to the one, the human
mind, because of its otherness, can see itself only in relation to the divine
One. Man, however, cannot know the divine One in itself, but only as
theOne is humanly conceived (De con., II, 16). This signifies: Even when
the mind its truth, it does not become divine
attains the highest degree of
in thus coming God, it only comes closer to the best possible image,
closer to
which remains separated from the original by an unbridgeable gulf. Yet
in this copy— the human mind —
we find all things that are God and cre-
ation alike.
Cusanus sees, however, that the thinking of the finite becomes true only
in the light of the infinite, when discursive reason yields to the intellect.
Under the assumption of the infinite, the finite becomes truly known. The
mind possesses its faculty of an image of what
judgment only because it is
which it directs its attention, and according to which it can make judgments
concerning finite things.
How does this come about? This Cusanus explains with the help of an
analogy: If, in addition to rationally determined (dead, as it were) written
laws, there were also a living law, it would, as a living law, be able to read
in itself the decisions it has to make {De mente, 5). Thus discursive reason
is limited to the domain of the finite, which in itself is meaningless; but
the mindis the activity of intellectual thinking, which does not make
inferences from finite propositions, but judges on the basis of the infinite.
The same is true of measurement. Knowledge involves measurement.
But all finite standards of measurement originate in and are guided by
the standard of the infinite.As an image, the mind is a living standard of
measurement; it measures itself by itself (in the same way as a living
circle might measure itself by itself). The mind is an absolute standard of
hold in our minds. The same falling short may be noted when we compare
any finite knowledge with the divine intellection which apprehends things
in themselves.
Our knowledge is always inadequate, and yet, in so far as it is true, it
is linked with truth Our knowledge reflects in various ways the dis-
itself.
tance between what we know and what we are striving to know. Our
knowledge is conjectural. "Since exact knowledge of the truth cannot be
achieved, every positive human assertion about the true is a conjecture.
Therefore our knowledge of the unity of unattainable truth is knowledge
in conjectural otherness [alternate coniecturaliY (De con., I, 2).
The categories of our discursive reason permit us to conceive of things
only as finite. When confronted with the which we can neither
infinite,
other (as discursive reason demands), but coincide. Within the domain of
the finite, however, we can achieve only conjectural knowledge.
The knowledge is universal, but denotes
conjectural character of our
different things in different domains.Our knowledge comes close to the
truth even in sensory experience, and never quite attains the truth even
when the finite mind has ascended as high as it can. For then it comes up
against "the wall."
our mind just as the real world is produced by the divine intellect (De
con. ,1,3).
Our conjectural knowledge defines our limits; it separates us forever
from the infinite divine knowledge, but at the same time manifests the truth
to us. All positive assertions are mere conjectures, but as such they participate
created minds know the truth only in so far as it can be copied (De con.,
restless even in repose. All created things other than man desire nothing
beyond what they have received, that is, each is content with its particular
likeness to God. "But when our spiritual nature recognizes itself as the
living image of God, it has the power to become ever purer and closer in
form to God, although, being a copy, it never becomes the original, the
creator" {To Albergati, 7).
has taken the intelligibility of the world for granted and assumed that what
we do not yet understand will soon be understood.
For Cusanus intelligibility has a higher meaning, since according to
him human thinking consists in copying divine cognition. At the same
time, however, he stresses the unintelligibility of the world, since according
to him the imititative character of human cognition in relation to divine
cognition can can never be overcome. Attracted by divine truth, we achieve
knowledge through a process of conjecture. But because our knowledge
remains conjectural, we experience the unintelligibility of the world.
(1) In the structure of being everything that is, is a copy of the original
or a metaphor. The world is the eternally present language of the eternally
infinite being of the godhead. The finite human mind is an imperfect copy
of the infinite divine mind.
all. Thus in God the most tremendous motion is at the same time perfect
rest. Children's games reflect the order of nature, and the latter reflects God
(De possest).
Although these three types of the metaphoric (the metaphorical charac-
ter of all things, the mirror images and enigmatic words of our thinking,
the lessons to be learned from games) can be distinguished from one
another, they come together in the single field of speculative cognition,
where the metaphorical relation is a fundamental structure. The experience
of metaphorical being and the production of enigmatic images are the
substance of speculative philosophy. The invention of metaphors as vivid
illustrations is an integral part of speculative exposition.
Inspired by the living truth of metaphorical thinking, Cusanus says:
"To grasp the inner meaning we must rise above the power of words \ver-
borum] rather than be bound to the peculiarities of names [vocabulorum].
These can never be adequate to such great mysteries. And metaphors
should serve only to point the way: they have to be transcended, their
sensory meaning must be dropped if we are to ascend to simple intellectual
knowledge" {De doc. ignor., I, 2). But since no one way is right once and
—
for all "for what needs to be said cannot be expressed adequately" it is —
very useful to say things in many ways {De mente, 4).
And so we come to the final step, to which Cusanus never refers as such:
The fact that we speak of metaphors when interpreting speculative thought
and the appearance of things is itself a metaphor. This follows inescapably:
if everything that is, everything we imagine and think, is metaphorical,
then this statement itself is a metaphor. Only thinking which grasps the
metaphorical character of all thinking results in the perfect state of suspen-
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 137
sion, which enables us to move freely within every type of symbolism. But
as long as we express ourselves in words, we cannot go beyond "metaphor."
In a deeply moving letter to a young monk, written in 1463, a year before
he died, Cusanus said: "Keep inmind that in this world we walk in the
ways of metaphors and enigmatic images, because the spirit of truth is not
of this world and can be grasped by us only in so far as metaphors and sym-
bols which we recognize as such carry us onward to that which is not
known (To Albergati, 48).
And where is that? "When a man, in whom there is a living image of
God, recognizes himself as the living image of his creator, he contemplates
his creator by looking into himself, because he is carried onward from the
copy to the original." the summons: "Mind the living, spiritual
Hence
image of God within you. would not be a living spiritual image if it
It
b. —
Degrees of \nowledge. In his treatment of the mind, Cusanus follows
two lines. On the one hand, he describes it as a copy of the divine original.
The sense organs apprehend real things, those created by God; discur-
sive reason supplies its categories —forms, genera, species; when discursive
reason breaks down, the intellect brings us closer to godhead.
Sensory knowledge is inherently confused. As soon as it makes dis-
tinctions, reason is already present in it. Reason brings clarity by drawing
distinctions, noting oppositions, and excluding contradiction. The intellect
leads us to learned ignorance by demonstrating how opposites actually
coincide.
Sensory knowledge is entirely positive: it affirms. Discursive reason both
affirms and negates. The intellect goes beyond affirmation and negation.
Sensory knowledge does not question. Reason questions on the assump-
tion that either affirmation or negation must be correct. The intellect ques-
tions by inquiring into the presupposition of questioning. As questioning
progresses, it becomes evident that rational statements invariably presuppose
what can be clearly grasped only by the intellect.
138 The Original Thinners
An example: Only the absolute One makes cognition possible. The mind
cannot formulate any question that does not presuppose this underlying
unity."The very question whether it is, presupposes its being; why it is,
the ground; for what purpose, the purpose of all things. Thus, what is
presupposed in every doubt must be that which is most certain" {De
con.,I,j).
At each stage of cognition, our thinking is true only in respect of the
adequacy between thinking and object characteristic of that stage. For ex-
ample: when we speak about God at the rational stage, which is not
adequate to God, "We subject God to the laws of discursive reason, and
assert His Oneness, while negating His Otherness. This is what is done
by nearly all modern theologians" {De con., 1, 10).
But no stage of cognition is self-contained for us; the truth lies in none
of them taken singly. Rather, we attain to truth as we ascend and descend
the degrees of knowledge. Each stage contributes something indispensa-
ble, but its truth resides in the whole of which it is only a part. In the
ascending order: "The mind unifies the being-other of sense perception
in the productive imagination, it unifies the various images of the productive
imagination in discursive reason, it unifies the being-other of rational cog-
nition in simple intellectual unity." In the descending order: The unity of
the intellect descends into the being-other of discursive reason, the unity
of reason into the being-other of representation, the latter into the being-
other of the senses. "Because cognition begins with the senses, it is true
not absolutely but only relatively: rational in discursive reason, true in rep-
resentation after the manner of representation, and in the senses after the
manner of the senses" {De con., II, 16).
Each stage strives for autonomy. Thus "the intellect does not wish to
become sensory," but to remain "perfect intellect in full activity." And yet
it can achieve this activity only by calling upon the senses, "in order to pass
from possibility to reality." The slumbering discursive reason must be
awakened by the senses, which arouse it to wonderment. "Thus the intellect
comes back to itself via a circular movement" {De con., II, 16).
All this activity of the mind, the various stages of which form a cycle, has
its purpose and goal entirely in itself. "Just as God does all things for His
own sake, in order to be the spiritual beginning and end of all things, so the
unfolding of the conceptual world, which is produced by our mind in
comprehending it, is present for the sake of the creative mind itself. The
infinite intellect is the heart and core of the human mind" {De con., I, 3).
of the kind, it would be rather unreliable. For I have not yet been given
the taste of how friendly the Lord is." Thus, Cusanus himself denies having
had mystical experience, though he does not deny its reality.
On the subject of his own speculations, this is what Cusanus said to
the monks: "The study whose purpose is the ascent of our intellectual
mind to union with God is not completed so long as God is conceived in
rational terms." Where negation and affirmation (negative theology and
positive theology) coincide, there lies "the most secret doctrine of God, to
which none of the philosophers has access so long as the principle common
to all philosophy is recognized as valid, the principle that things that con-
tradictone another do not coincide." The man who investigates the doctrine
of God must "sacrifice himself and plunge into darkness." There he dis-
covers "that confusion is certainty, darkness light, and ignorance knowl-
edge." There, beyond the coincidence of opposites, lies the domain "of the
divine hunt," the perilous hunt. This movement is never completed; the
plunger is forever being deflected from the true way, into side paths which
lead to corrupting illusions.
2. Experience, not words or logic. —"We
are led on by the eternal and
infinite wisdom, which indeed from all things, giving us a kind
radiates
of foretaste of its effects, such that a wondrous longing impels us to meet
it halfway." This is the true life of the intellectual mind, its very own and
authentic life.
in words and not out of inner experience," are not wise; the wise are those
who, thanks to such experience, "know all things and to the same extent
know nothing at all" (ibid.).
adequate must remain conjectural, and this is true also of the word of
God. In the Bible God speaks in human language. Although, because they
are God's, the words are more exact than any others, nevertheless the
language remains conjectural.
3. The "goal" cannot be described. —The goal, the inner disposition
whereby the infinite, God Himself, is present, cannot be described as a
"something." It seems to be nowise the same in different persons. It may
be adumbrated more or less as follows: it awakens
becomes to itself; it
itself in endless variations. His thinking is forever trying to take of? and
soar into the unthinkable, the ineffable, failing again and again to do so,
resolutely pursues the second, combining the two in some way we do not
understand.
words, every other love finds its consummation in the love of God.
2. Description of love. —"In the lovable we find endless and ultimately
unfathomable motives for love." Happiness in love is mediocre where the
loved object is something conceivable and finite. Love is truly blissful only
where "the lovable quality in the loved object is beyond all measure,
illimitable, and inconceivable." It is learned, love-inspired igno-
infinite,
as the infant in arms thirsts for milk, so the intellect thirsts for wisdom.
"It has a kind of foretaste of it" (De sap.).
The spirit of love is not of this world. Love is "the power that illuminates
the man born blind and enables him to acquire sight through faith,
of the existent, that glows in the ratio, in the soul, and finally in all nature.
In reality everything is united with everything else. In the same way the
soul is linked with the body. The soul forms its own appropriate body just
as this particular body demands this particular soul. Accordingly, the
physiognomists are justified in making inferences about the soul on the
strength of the body (De con., II, 10).
Love, too, is linked with the body. One of his sermons (Basel edition,
p. 555) indicates the intricacy of Cusanus' thinking in this matter. He is
The statement that "even in perishable matter beauty attracts us in its own
way as absolute beauty attracts the mind" might apply both to the rapture
that is free from desire and to carnal union. One might suppose that here
for a moment even in the erotic union of lovers Cusanus recognized the
beauty of the world —the reality of living things as a reflection of eternal
beauty. But this is not the case.
The flesh is covetous and everywhere at odds with the spirit. The
choleric are easily angered, the sanguine are inclined to dissipation. "The
flesh is like an overheated pot, which seethes and bubbles. The soul is
continually throwing wood on the fire — namely, living nourishment which
it finds where it may. Thus it keeps the fire going: with beautiful colors
through the lovely melodies through the ears, tastes through the
eyes,
mouth, scents through the nostrils. All flesh is corrupt and impure.
. . .
Because the soul is warped and partial to the flesh, it is corrupted and
becomes bestial."
Whenever, on the basis of his philosophical views, Cusanus asserts the
from carrying him away, such love did not even arouse his wonder.
Confronted with reality, he fell back at once upon traditional views and
evaluations: the superiority of asceticism, marriage as the sole legitimation
of Eros. For the sake of another, different afterworld in the beyond, he
casts a veilover what is eternal in Eros here and now. He devaluates the
reality of existence in the world by absolutizing the ascetic way of life.
III. FAITH
Introduction
intellect. "No ascent, however high, can enable us to see God from the
natural standpoint otherwise than in an enigmatic image." The seeker's
vision is obscured by mist. How nevertheless can he gain a glimpse of the
invisible? Never unless God "makes Himself visible in the real world by
revealing Himself" (De possest).
We in our weakness cannot help ourselves. When man has abandoned
hope in himself, convinced that he "is sick, as it were, and entirely unable
N 1 Cll OLAS OF CU S A 145
to obtain what he longs for," he turns for help to the revealed God.
But there is only one such revelation: that of Jesus Christ. God the Father
discloses Himself in the Christ. Having begotten His Son, God dwells in
Him bodily (corporaliter) for He has assumed a body in which He "has
remained the perfect God" (Exc, IX, 637; Scharpflf, p. 484).
If, contrary to Cusanus' intentions, we were to separate his philosophy
from his faith, we might underestimate the earnestness both of his philos-
ophy and of his Christian faith.
cursive reason through the paradoxes of seeking and yet never finding,
of touching in nontouching, of knowledge in ignorance, of proximity in
distance. Inspired by his grandiose human self-confidence we may well
make his ideas our own, without ever thinking of Christ. And yet from his
point of view, this is quite inadmissible.
Is such a procedure justified? For the purposes of our own present
philosophical realization, assuredly, but not from the standpoint of adequate
historical understanding, not if we wish to provide a historical exposition.
To him everything was Christian, to us it is not. To Cusanus the implications
of his faith were fully realized in the Christian religion; to us, what he ex-
presses in Christian formulas often holds a truth that has no need of
Christian wrappings. Actually, the independence of reason characteristic
of a philosophical faith is as inseparable from Cusanus' thinking as are
its Christian underpinnings.
1. What is faith?
a. Faith and reason. —Even when the human mind is only moderately
endowed with reason, it is able to believe. If it has no reason at all, it
cannot believe, for then it cannot think, and hence cannot assent.
Just as nature reveals light to our vision, and just as a truth strikes
us as evident, so the pleasant and the useful disclose themselves to our
will. All this takes place spontaneously and implies no merit on our part.
We can speak of merit only when the nonvisible, the improbable, the
indemonstrable, the redemption that is not disclosed spontaneously by our
nature, is believed by virtue of faith.
Faith produces conflict in the mind. The mind assents necessarily to what
has been proved. But faith must struggle. The improbability of its content
clashes directly with discursive reason. Without courage in the struggle
that faith must wage, there is no victory.
Because of its weakness, discursive reason looks for points of support
in demonstration and proof. Because of its inherent strength, faith needs
no external support. Discursive reason that asks for proofs is like a money-
lender who demands security for a loan. The heathen demand such security
before they are ready to believe. Christians believe in God's revelation with-
out it.
b. Faith —
and will. "Faith is a kind of thinking that is associated with
assent" {cum assensione cogitare). Because the will is free, it lies in our
NICHOLAS OF CVS A 147
power to believe or not. God has conferred upon us this capacity for faith
the ability to grasp revelation when we hear it. In its pride, reason will
not believe what it does not understand. The humble man, however, does
not understand unless he believes. Adam and Lucifer fell because they tried
to live by their own knowledge. He who believes in the Resurection and in
life everlasting — beliefs which reason and experience refute, rather than
confirm —
must necessarily let this reason die away. "He must become as
a fool and a slave who renounces the freedom of his reason and willingly
lets himself be taken captive. This is the greatest combat, not against flesh
and blood, but against proud, presumptuous reason." The ability to believe
is our greatest virtue {maxima nostrae animae virtus); it is the power of
c. Faith is more than hearing and less than seeing. —To see God would
be to come face to face with Him. Merely to hear the Word is not yet to
more than hearing, but less than
believe. Faith is seeing. To believe what
we have only heard is to assent to what we have not seen.
Faith is the light of the soul. "Just as the eyes see the stars only thanks
to the light they emit, so we gain knowledge of the divine only in the
light of the divine." The light of the living faith surpasses "the natural light
of the senses and even of the intellect, as we see in the sacrament of the
Mass, where the senses are vanquished by faith." In this faith the visible
"coincides" with the invisible.
When we read what Cusanus says about faith, we are not unmoved. Al-
though his faith in revealed religion is alien to us, he seems to say things
in which we can recognize our own capacities for faith. How is this to be
interpreted ?
In order to go beyond discursive reason, Cusanus proceeds in two ways:
he appeals both to the dogmas of the Church and to the philosophical
intellectus. He
never discusses the relationship between the two. All we can
do is note what he actually does in his thinking.
148 The Original Thinners
world, with the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit. This twofold approach
is a general feature of Cusanus' thinking:
tf.lt is not theological thinking. For he does not interpret the articles
of Christian faithon the basis of the Biblical "word of God." He does not
employ the language of dogmatic theology. On the contrary, his thinking
takes the form of a philosophical thinking accessible to all men, Christians
and non-Christians alike.
His speculations aim from the outset to arrive at the point where the
dogmas, the Trinity and the Incarnation, for example, take on their true
meaning. In his treatment, the articles of faith seem to coincide with his
philosophical ideas.
His philosophizing does not presuppose particular articles of faith,
b.
Christian. Because Cusanus regards his mind as a copy of the divine orig-
inal, philosophical faith and revealed faith are for him identical. In the
Bible man is described as "made in the image and likeness of God." In
philosophy this serves as a cipher of human self-awareness.
What we call "the duality" of his thinking was to him no such thing.
He does not recognize multiple sources of faith, but only the one, the
Christian. He recognizes no philosophical faith. Not being in search of
one, he neither rejects nor accepts this possibility.
The interest in faith inherent in such a fundamental attitude is not the
same in the philosopher and in the religious believer. Nor is the founda-
tion of faith that gives the existential impulse to speculation by any means
the same in all the great thinkers, although they are often in agreement on
specific points.
Because Cusanus assumes that Pythagoras, Plato, and Proclus are essen-
tially in agreement with revelation, his ideas are developed so undogmati-
cally —and for long passages without reference to Church dogmas that a —
modern reader can easily forget he is reading a Christian author. It never
occurs to Cusanus that his philosophical ideas and his theological ideas
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 149
essential to this kind of thinking. He tells us what this is. A man who does
"what the intellect orders him to do," does not obey in the manner of a
slave; a slave is one who "is compelled for fear of punishment to obey a
law he does not understand because it contains something secret" (Exc,
V, 499; Scharpff, 412). The free man is the man who has achieved maturity,
who is capable of understanding. Although Cusanus' freedom illumines
the mysteries of faith in its own way, it does not dispel them by intellec-
tual ingenuity nor reduce them to a bloodless, purely logical freedom from
contradiction.
The freedom of this thinking becomes apparent when we compare it
would seem that John himself began in the end to waver on this score.
Cusanus may have been perplexed in given concrete situations, but he was
never uncertain about the truth of his philosophical thinking.
150 The Original Thinners
characteristic of all great metaphysics. But in him liberation does not con-
tent itself with metaphor. His speculation, which has just broken through
every barrier and overcome every difficulty to bring us face to face with
the infinite, is recaptured and fettered to dogmatic views or mysteries.
Whenever this occurs, there is a break in the continuity of thought. His
logical-alogical thinking opens up immeasurable spaces, which are gradually
filled with ciphers (enigmatic images, metaphors, signs). As these ideas
become available for specific contents of the revealed faith, the openings
are sealed up again.
thing.
Cusanus was one of a long line of Christian thinkers, faithful to the
teaching of the Church, who whether
resisted the inroads of superstition
from inside or outside the Church. He condemned many practices of the
Church of his day: "When consecrated things are used for purposes for
which they are not intended, we have superstition. For example, when holy
water is used as a remedy against sickness or to increase fertility. The same
holds true of the light of the Easter candle, of baptismal water, and other
things: bathing on Christmas Eve and Shrove Tuesday to combat fever or
toothache . . . begging the intercession of St. Valentine in a case of epilepsy
. . . carrying a cross around the fields in spring to ward off storms. There
is superstition, too, in certain offerings laid upon the altar, such as stones
on St. Stephen's day and arrows on St. Sebastian's day" {Sermons, pp. 158
ff .) . Firm adherence to the simple faith, as laid down in the teachings of the
Apostles, is quite enough. The rest is of no consequence, mere human in-
vention. Superstitious practices lead to idolatry {Sermon, Scharpff, p. 484).
They intrude on meditation and mystical experience, so fomenting fraud,
self-deception,and self-indulgence in the form of spurious visions.
Cusanus never draws a clear distinction between faith and superstition.
He does say, however "It is superstitious to accord divine honors to persons
:
other than God, indeed, it is idolatry" {Sermons, p. 197). But how are we
to distinguish God in His corporeal form from an idol? Nor does he state
clearly how superstition arises. The "human inventions" referred to above,
152 The Original Thinners
he says, are inspired by the Devil. Evil as well as good spirits induce
thoughts and images in the mind {Sermons, p. 195). Thus the origin of
superstition is accounted for by another superstition.
However, Cusanus dismisses this whole domain—superstition, demons,
the Devil —as of superficial importance. "We must recognize that the Devil
cannot penetrate the innermost sphere of the rational soul and be inwardly
present to Being; only God can do that. Only He who created the . . .
human mind can enter it. And because the Devil cannot do this, he
. . .
does not know the secrets of the human heart; God alone knows them.
No creature can know the secrets of conscience" {Sermons, pp. 192 ff.).
i
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 153
not a biological reality), the virgin birth, the resurrection from the dead
of a man who, after a short stay on earth, ascends to Heaven. Cusanus
forestalls all such objections: Because nothing is impossible to God, questions
such as these as to how events attested by believers actually came about are
irrelevant. To human thought, many things are inconceivable. Human
cognition is confined within modes appropriate to human understanding,
but this is not true of God. Therefore, the man who does not believe that
God is capable of acts unintelligible to man "is making a judgment about
himself rather than about God and is utterly in error" (To Albergati, 43).
The which Cusanus subscribes without reservation is
revealed faith to
based upon the Scriptures, the word of God, the Church, the body of
Christian tradition. Philosophical faith, on the contrary, though also based
on traditional views expressed in a variety of works, both sacred and
profane and assuming many contradictory forms, assimilates freely this
philosophical tradition. The speculative metaphors (ciphers) speak to phil-
osophical faith in the medium of its rationality and essential love for
freedom. This possibility is outside Cusanus' horizon when he speaks as
a Christian, though perhaps not when, hardly aware of what he is doing, he
speaks of man as an autonomous being, as a rational individual, different
from all others, and attuned to the language of all things whenever, that —
is, he philosophizes freely.
think as he wished.
the beginning of knowledge {fides est initium intellectus) ." And again:
"The man who wants to arrive at an insight must have faith, for without it
he will get nowhere." Hence, "Where there is no true faith, there is no true
knowledge."
berg, might have led to his condemnation. Cusanus was stung into refuting
the passionate pamphlet of this rationalistic scholastic —the only time he
ever did such a thing.
However, the Church paid no attention to Cusanus* ideas. In the nine-
teenth century, a few Catholic theologians took up the old attack again
and amplified it, but the Church remained silent. His thinking fell into
oblivion. After 1565 (date of the Basel edition of his works), neither the
Church nor any monastic order arranged for a new edition. The Heidelberg
A\ademieausgabe (begun in 1932) was initiated by non-Catholics.
Cusanus himself had no heretical leanings. His sincere quest for the
truth was inseparable from his determination to submit to the judgment
—
of the Church the visible, existing Church of his day. Entirely foreign
to him was the sort of radicalism that stops at nothing in its conflict with
the world as it is, envisages the possibility of revolution, and compels the
world to transform itself. He did not fight for the truth as such, only for
the truth within the Church. He did not champion the faith of the New
Testament against its corruption by the Church, which claims a monopoly
on Christianity and imposes its faith by brute force when it has the means
of doing so. Cusanus was not a revolutionary; his own reform activities
were carried on within the Church, on orders from his superiors.
truth which man has the innate capacity to understand. The layman utters
the truth, and the same layman expresses concern over its possible harmful
effect.
Faith based upon revelation demands obedience. "When we opt for faith
we submit to the Word, we willingly surrender both our reason and our
will" (Sermon, Scharpff, 482). Such a statement is surprising: for, as we
have seen, Cusanus demands that we should understand authentically, that
we should make insights our own, that our thinking should not be second-
hand.
Cusanus would presumably reply: Faith resides fundamentally in obedi-
ence itself. "Obedience" does not imply that we come by our faith at
right angles. Ifwe make one of the angles progressively greater, so that it
approaches in magnitude the sum of two right angles, the apex of the
triangle will move ever closer to the base, and finally the sides of the
triangle will coincide with the base.
The infinity of the figures in which the opposites of circle and straight
line coincide is seen by Cusanus as an expression of God's infinity. He
quotes Anselm, who likened God's supreme truth to an infinite straight
line, and others who likened Him to an infinite triangle, an infinite circle,
an infinite sphere. According to Cusanus, all these conceptions are correct,
and for all their seeming divergence essentially identical.
We cannot visualize a Cusanus says, the
circle as a straight line, but,
contact with God. The second course symbolizes the descent from infinity
to the finite: just as the longest, infinite line contains all other lines, so the
absolutely greatest, absolute infinity, contains all finite things.
infinity can be grasped only to the extent that specific concepts of infinity
(indicated by special signs) are employed for the solution of specific prob-
lems. But behind each symbol "for the infinite" that enters into mathematical
operations, there always remains another infinity that is beyond our grasp.
How mathematical infinity can become a symbol of divine infinity is
the divine mind, which produces the things themselves (not merely intel-
lectual and hence knows them as exactly as we know the
schemata)
mathematical figures we ourselves construct. "Since nothing in our knowl-
edge is certain save for mathematics," mathematics provides "an enigmatic
image for the hunting out of God's work" {De possest, Opera, 259; et
aenigma ad venationem operum Dei). Mathematical knowledge is
ilia est
the only exact knowledge,and in it the mind knows itself and its powers.
Because it is a copy of divine knowledge, the godhead reveals itself in
it {ibid.).
The copy is not so much the numbers and geometrical figures as the
activity of our mind in producing them. Cusanus denies that such math-
ematical entities could have "another, stillmore real being over and above
the mind" {De beryllo, 32). The truth they embody originates in the human
mind, and they owe their character of certainty to its creative power, not
to some other world. (Indeed there is here no alternative. A self-subsistent
ideal world of mathematical objects discovered by investigation, and such
a world constructed by the mind, are aspects of one and the same thing.
What we produce we also discover. What the mind creates is valid as such.)
constitutes the method of cognition itself" {De mente, 6). "Number is the
archetype of all our intellectual concepts."
Quantity is inseparable from finitude; whatever quantity we deal with,
we can always conceive of more or less. Discursive reason can give names
to things only because quantity (or "number") is one of their characteris-
tics. If number were something infinite, the greatest would coincide with
the smallest, and all determinations would be null and void. For it amounts
to the same thing to say that number is infinite or to say that it is nothing
at all {De doc. ignor., I, 5).
What is the origin of number? Mathematical number is a creation of the
human mind. But even as such, it is a copy of divine number. The latter
is inconceivable to us; we call it "number," just as we speak by a remote
analogy of the divine "mind" {De mente). Just as the mind as a whole is
a copy of the divine mind, so the mind's creations are copies of divine
creation. Mathematical number is a copy of the archetypal divine number,
which is the ultimate source of number as we know it.
The is different from the abstract
actual plurality of things, however,
plurality of number. In our cognition of things, plurality is our human
contribution. For only the mind enumerates. There is no such thing as
number in itself, in abstraction from the work of the mind {De mente, 6).
160 The Original Thinners
But the reality of the things which to us appear in the plural lies in the
divine mind. God is the original Creator of the real world of the human
mind, which is a copy of His mind. (That the archetype of real things in the
Creator's mind is number is proved by the beauty inherent in all things; for
beauty consists in proportion, and proportion rests upon number; De
mente.)
In brief, Cusanus says In the Creator's mind, the first pattern of things is
:
number, the archetypal number inconceivable to us. But the first pattern
of our knowledge of things (of the conceptual world created by us in the
likeness of things) is the number of our discursive reason (De doc. ignor.,
II, 13). The human mind accomplishes three things with the help of num-
ber. First: It gains insight into the mathematical world it creates. Second:
Number enables it to know finite created things. Third: With the help of
number our mind godhead whenever, guided by
obtains a glimpse of the
purely human imitative notions of number, it rises to an intimation of the
archetypal divine number.
I
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 161
may not be able to justify objectively; the capacity of the human mind, on
the basis of self-posited assumptions, to perform operations which lead to
the discovery of ever new splendors; the applicability of mathematics to
nature, in so far as it is governed by measure, number, and weight —
(partial) coincidence, which is anything but self-evident, between mathe-
matical laws and the laws we discover in nature, the fact that the same
laws and the same order are to be found in both.
All this provides an inexhaustible source of philosophical wonder. How
can this be? Why is it so? The answers arouse further wonder. No final
solution has been arrived Cusanus lived in just such an intellectual
at.
climate, which began with Western philosophy and is still very much alive
today.
lutely infinite, which God. He looks upon his mathematical and physical
is
l
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 163
lies the meaning and the achievement of his philosophizing. Is it futile be-
made knowable in the world. Cusanus hoped that his principle of the
coincidentia oppositorum would prove methodologically useful to this end,
though his own efforts to make it so appear to have been in vain. He
arrived at ideas of mathematical possibilities and anticipations of a future
mathematics, but he failed to find the crucial step which, indeed, is objec-
tively unrelated to his speculative assumptions.
For this reason a systematic exposition of his ideas on being would fail
to do him justice. It is possible to select passages from his writings and
shuffle them around until they seem to fall into a system. But to do so would
be unrewarding. There would still be many discrepancies, because the argu-
ments and the terminology of different works fail to harmonize as parts of
a systematic whole. There are schemata in his thinking, but there is no
construction of a systematic whole. His speculative mode of thinking opens
up experience. To be communicated this experience has to be objectivized.
Accordingly it will be worth our while to supply some explicit objectiviza-
tions.
This we shall attempt from several points of view. Our exposition will
necessarily be disjoined; we shall not attempt to deduce a single systematic
whole from one or more arbitrarily chosen principles. The "one idea" that
shines through constantly cannot be grasped directly. In our exposition of
the "whole of being" we shall resort to paraphrase, as we did in connection
with the "fundamental ideas."
In his early work, De docta ignorantia, Cusanus adopted a threefold
division: God, the World, Christ. We shall follow this division.
I. GOD
1. Dialogue on the hidden God
comes into being. He surpasses all that is and all that is not, and both obey
Him. He is not any of the things which follow from His omnipotence.
(2) Can God be named at all?— He is ineffable, because all namable
things are insignificant in comparison with His inconceivable greatness.
But He can be named over and above all things, since He is the original
ground of all things namable. He who confers names upon others cannot
Himself be without a name.
Then is God both ineffable and effable?— That is not the case either.
He is neither named nor not named, nor is He both named and not named.
Nothing that can be said is adequate to His sublime infinity, which lies
above every possible idea of Him.
(3) Then God cannot be subsumed under that which is? —He cannot.
—Then He is just nothing?— He negates these contradictory designations,
so that He neither is nor is not; similarly, it cannot be said that He both is and
is not, or that He is or is not. None of these statements attains to the source
For if there are any springs of being and nonbeing, God is prior to them all.
—
(4) Is not God the truth? No, He is prior to all truth. Nor yet is He
by any means something different from the truth. He is infinitely far above
and prior to everything we conceive of as truth.
(5) God, who is free from every sort of determination characteristic of
created things, cannot be discovered anywhere in the domain of creation.
All composite things in the world and every individual composite thing
are what they are only because of Him; He who is not Himself a composite
thing remains unrecognized in this domain. In the eyes of all philosophers,
God is the hidden God.
2. On speculation
—
Nothing can be said about God and there is no limit to what is said about
Him. Hence the thesis: No statement is applicable to the One. For every
statement implies otherness or duality. No name applies to that which is self-
posited. Even the term "the One" does not really apply to it {De princ.).
Whether we call it "the One," the "Non-Other," "Capability as such," the
"source," or something else, such names will always be inadequate. Cusanus
writes: "The unnamable source of the namable source cannot itself be named
source. For it is anterior to all that is namable and surpasses it" {De princ.).
Yet so peremptory a thesis is not allowed to stand in the way of a specula-
1 66 The Original Thinners
tion in the course of which infinitely many things are said about God; rather,
it serves to clarify the sense of such speculation. We learn what takes place
when speculation ventures the impossible and what it produces when it
breaks down —how our thinking deepens as it comes closer to the hidden
God, and makes us feel the overwhelming reality of what is hidden how —
what eludes the thinker attracts him ever more strongly.
Although the inability to make statements is taken seriously, the result
is not silence. Impressive images and categorial connections occur time and
again in the course of conceptual operations which lead to that abyss in the
sight of which all statements and existence itself become for the first time
transparent. —Also the statements of negative theology are made retroactive
and are freed from the "non." Positives and negatives are alike transcended.
The speculative ideas go in pursuit of what is hidden in concepts which,
though they cancel one another out when clarity has been attained, do so in
such a way that, in the light they produce, the world is transformed for the
thinker and the thinker himself is transformed.
The supreme art of pure thinking consists in giving lucid expression to
speculative experience in the sequence of propositions. Often in the last
two and a half thousand years such thinking has seemed to die out in the
Western world, but has repeatedly reasserted itself. It has often been choked
off by underbrush, shot through with the weeds of habit and idle fantasy.
sphere which God surpasses —those who remain under the sway of this
principle cannot possibly find God (De ven. sap., p. 13).
The magical phrase "coincidentia oppositorum" can either be dismissed
as nonsense or extolled as dialectical profundity. With reference to the
absolute to which the idea is supposed to lead us, it remains ambiguous.
At times it seems to mean: God is the coincidence of opposites. At other
times the idea is only a springboard from which we are supposed to leap
—
in order to touch the absolute no one can tell how. But whoever makes
the leap falls back to his starting point. We are left this side of "the wall."
!
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 167
This ambiguity hints at a reality the truth of which comes to life only
within ourselves through our thinking, yet which is not present merely
because we Thought is a sort of speculative knocking
think. at the door,
b. —
The non-other (non aliud). Cusanus calls God the non aliud. This
means: Without being other, God comprises everything within Himself.
The world is otherness (alteritas) because whatever is in it is either one
thing or another.
But the non aliud and otherness must not be allowed to freeze into rigid
opposition. For all things are in God. There is nothing outside Him, and
it, then neither infinity nor anything else could exist" (The Vision of God,
op. cit.,p. 62).
What is not in God is not in itself either. Otherness is not a positive
principle. Otherness derives its name from nonbeing (alteritas dicitur e non
esse)
If the non aliud were set in opposition to alteritas (an opposition we
cannot help stating the moment we talk about anything at all), we should
miss the point. The speculative attempt must break down as such in the
rational statement: only then is its full truth disclosed. Were we to overlook
the breakdown of rationality and interpret the statement literally, we should
be saying something that can never apply to God. For the statement as
such makes the infinite and turns God into a determined concept.
finite
inadequate, which has already escaped him, but which is destined to take
—
wing thanks to the horizons opened up by possibility.
Not so God. Here is perfect actuality. Every potentiality has become
actuality, everything that can be has already achieved being. Here, what
can be and what is are indistinguishable. Cusanus coins a new term to
designate this particular coincidentia oppositorum: possest. Only God
possest ("can-is") because He is actually what He can be. God cannot
become anything that He has not been for all eternity {De ven. sap., 13).
In one of his last works De apice theoriae ("The Pinnacle of Theory"),
Cusanus takes another speculative step forward. The capability that cannot
be surpassed by any limited entity, he now calls "Capability as such";
without it there can be no capability of any kind. Every other faculty pre-
supposes Capability Nothing antecedes, nothing is stronger,
as such.
more solid, more essential, more glorious than Capability as such, the
capability of the first ground and the first source, the capability of every
faculty. And in another passage he says the same thing: Nothing can be
anterior to Capability as such, nothing better, nothing more powerful,
more accomplished, simpler, clearer, better known, truer, more adequate,
more constant, more accessible. Because it is anterior to any and every
determined faculty, it can neither be nor be named, neither felt, imagined,
nor understood.
Capability as such is not potential being or living or understanding, it
understand.
(3) Capability as such in the mind. —All things are manifestations of
Capability as such, and nothing else. But one of these manifestations is pre-
eminent: "The living, discerning light that is called the mind contemplates
Capability as such within itself, and at the same time sees itself as its image."
Ability to see is the mind's highest capability. This is illustrated in parables:
ena in the world — is of two kinds. First: the things that have come into
being but in doing so have fulfilled their potentiality, for example, celestial
the things that have come into being but without fully realizing their
potentiality. These are forever defective, unstable, changeable. In these
things the process of coming into being has never fully attained its limit.
In the world as a whole the faculty of coming into being is fully actualized,
for there is indeed nothing that is greater than the world; but the things
that have come into being in the world are always singular and perishable.
The eternal (aeternum) is everything that comes into being, although it
does not itself come into being, but rather is the principle and end (terminus)
of every thing that can come into being. On the other hand, the faculty of
coming into being is ever enduring; it has its end (or reaches its pinnacle)
not in itself, but in eternity (De ven. sap., especially 37-39).
The eternal, the creator, or Capability as such cannot become nothing
or other than it is, because it is prior to nothingness and the ability to come
into being (De ven. sap., 39).
d. Origin. —In De
Cusanus discusses the meaning of the prop-
principio
osition that God is mean origin of the world
origin. Origin here does not
(creation). Before the world came into being, in eternity, God was origin
and origin of the origin, and that which originated in both (De princ., 11).
Cusanus elucidates: "Everything that is seen in eternity is eternity." The
origin in eternity cannot exist without that which originates in eternity. But
eternity is not some sort of extended duration, it is wholly simultaneity,
even at the source. We have an intellectual intuition of the origin that
has no origin and the origin of the origin (De princ., 10).
e. Being and nothing. —The origin must be itself, through itself. For if
anything at all (De princ, 18). Here Cusanus implicitly asks the question:
Why is there something, why is there not nothing? At this question no abyss
opens before him — God discloses Himself. We understand that something
is because God created it. But where does God come from? This question
Cusanus does not answer, for at this point the thinking of something
ceases. Yet thinking itself does not cease. The answer lies in the speculative
movement of Cusanus' thought.
Even before he comes in view of the abyss, of the possibility that nothing
is, he has led us away from it. He says: The Origin, Absolute Being, must
be One. "If this be eliminated, the intellect concludes that nothing can be"
(De princ, 7) Because this conclusion simply does not come under consider-
.
Cusanus then asks: Since nonbeing is, which comes first, being or non-
being? He answers: Nonbeing presupposes being. Without that which is
ing: beyond being {plus quam ens), beyond being and nothingness, beyond
substance, beyond the one, in short beyond each successive conceptualiza-
tion.
Only few terms seem for a moment to designate the absolute
a very
accurately enough to require no movement "beyond." The "infinite" is one
of these; yet each successive form of a determined infinite is transcended
as the mind moves toward an ever-receding infinite. The "itself" is another
such term (Being as such, Capability as such, the Origin as such, the One
as such), but this "as such" is more a pounding away at something that has
172 The Original Thinners
Cusanus addresses God: "I behold Thee and I know not what I see,
. . .
for I see nothing visible" (The Vision of God, op. cit., p. 58). Do such
meditations content him as assurances of the reality of God? God is real,
but in a unique, incomparable way, not like the real things in the world, not
as a hypothetically discovered reality, not as an object of thought. He is
that exists has fallen away, we discover God as the One who cannot be
understood. Our mind catches a glimpse of Him in shadow or in fog,
in darkness. The speculative vision veils the hidden God in mystery. If
N ICHOLAS OF CU S A 173
He Himself does not dispel the shadows with His light and reveal Himself,
He remains unknown to those who would
totally Him throughsearch for
intellectual insight. "All we have said amounts only to this, that we should
like to understand how He surpasses all understanding." But the "vision
which is so easy, and the only one that fills us with bliss" the vision of —
—
that which surpasses all understanding "was promised to all believers by
the truth itself, the Son of God, if only we will follow in His footsteps and
cleave to the path He showed us in His words and deeds" (De possest, end).
To Cusanus the content of his speculation coincides with the content of
revealed faith as interpreted by the Church. To us this is ambiguous. In
studying him we participate in a thinking which he intends to be universal,
authentic, independent. Yet in nearly all his writings we come to a point
in his reasoning —a point that is never so marked by him —where a sudden
break occurs, and where independent thinking gives way to the contents of
revelation.
As long as his philosophizing is related to age-old philosophical specula-
tion, which Christianity calls pagan (though it is not pagan at all, but
marks the highest refinement of speculative thinking), we recognize his
greatness, especially where he expresses a new self-awareness of man.
Viewed in the context of more than a thousand years of philosophy, his
speculations are meaningful, quite apart from their references to Christ.
Now it is true that such speculations cannot, by their very nature, be
self-resolving. What gives them their real weight and at the same time
supplies their motive power comes from elsewhere. We are reminded of
this by those of Cusanus' teachings in which we cannot follow him.
God (the eternal, the infinite, the One, He Himself) is "touched without
being touched" in the course of speculation. He is experienced in the think-
ing of the human mind which understands itself as a mere image. He is
seen in the world taken as the visible splendor of His invisibility. But
the revelation through which God spoke in the flesh, as Christ, at a specific
place and a specific time, is of crucial importance.
Revealed faith says: After the creation of the world, the "Origin" spoke
in time, to theJews ("Hear, O Israel, thy God is One") and to all men
through Christ, the Logos. He was present in the flesh. To the question,
Who art Thou? He answered: "Even the same that I said unto you from
the beginning" (John 8, 25). Jesus says: "Then shall ye know that I am"
(John 8, 28). Cusanus comments: Only he who owes his Being to himself
can say truly, "I am" {De princ.) .
But does the language out of the "Origin," which is Revelation, ade-
quately express this Origin? No, for this language is human, not divine.
In Cusanus' own words: "Human statements about the divine are inac-
curate. But concerning that which Christ said about the divine in human
language— since men can grasp it only in the human way— we must assume
that the statements in the Gospels, which are couched in human terms, are
174 The Original Thinners
more accurate than any others; for in them the word of God speaks about
(De princ, 18)
itself"
This is expressed as follows: Oneness is anterior to the one and the other,
and to the number one; equality is anterior to equality between different
entities, also to inequality; the nexus is anterior to the act of linking. That
which in graspable thinking is anterior or presupposed, is obtained again
in transcending the domain of the thinkable, where all is otherness,
distinction, and combination {De doc. ignor., 1, 7).
To conceive of a triune oneness we must transcend all concepts. We
must renounce everything that comes from the senses, the imagination,
and discursive reason, if we are to achieve the simplest, most abstract
insight, namely, that all things are one. In terms of this insight, the highest
One can be conceived only as triune {De doc. ignor., 1, 10).
b. Why not four in one? The triangle. — It might be asked: Why three in
one, why not four or five in one? That the latter alternatives are out of the
question is demonstrated with the help of a mathematical figure. The
simplest element in any polygon is the triangle. The triangle is the smallest
i,
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 175
polygon: no polygon can have fewer sides. Since the smallest coincides
with the greatest, the greatest polygon is the infinite triangle. It contains
all polygons. The quadrangle is not the smallest polygon, and hence it
cannot coincide with the absolutely greatest. The greatest triangle is the
simple measure of all triune things (De doc. ignor., I, 20).
The first figure is the triangle. All other figures can be reduced to it,
but the triangle cannot be broken down into figures having two angles
or one angle. "This shows that the beginning of mathematics is triune"
(De possest). The origin is the simple. The simple is that which is not
One any more than it is triune, and therefore is One. In the enigmatic
image of the triangle it is seen as the triune God (ibid.) .
d. How the Trinity is reflected in all things. —As the Trinity, threeness is
reflected in all things, and all things are reflected in it —objects, events,
and activities.
The unity of cognition comprises the knower, the knowable, and knowl-
edge. He who knows most is also he who is most knowable, and marks the
highest degree of knowledge.
The trinity of love includes the lover, the lovable, and the bond between
the lover and the lovable. Love is in essence triune (The Vision of God,
chap. 17). What is experienced in finite love is experienced most fully in
infinite love. The infinite capacity to love and the infinite capacity to be
loved are one in the infinite bond of love. The triune God is perfect love.
e. The Christian Trinity: Father, Son, Holy Spirit.— Concepts do not come
alive until they are visualized. There is no Trinity until we see it as God the
Father, God the Son, and God the Holy Spirit.
God the Father begets the Son, and the Holy Spirit lives and breathes in
them.
Trinity comprises Him whose selfhood presupposes no ground,
The
Him whose selfhood presupposes a ground, and Him who presupposes
the two others.
The one God is all-powerful in the triad. He begets Himself in the Word
176 The Original Thinners
(logos) which is the Son, in whom He sees Himself and all that can come
into being through Him. The Holy Spirit is the bond between them and
produces that which is love of God.
the Trinity created an uncommonly rich dogma of its mystery. Those who
do not share this faith can only shrug their shoulders and acknowledge
their inability to understand.
such, the more his philosophizing, like any other speculation, loses itself
I
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 177
Must we, then, conclude that God's infinity and the cosmos of finite things
are totally unrelated, one being above the other? The very fact that both
are referred to in such a proposition introduces a minimal relationship
into their unrelatedness. Cusanus' speculation is entirely focused on this
relationship, in an effort to do justice to its reality.
The God-World relation cannot be conceived in the manner of a relation
between finite things in the world nor yet as a relation between two worlds.
The very category of relation, which is a category of discursive reason,
must take on new meaning. With this category we arrive at a relation that
cannot be compared with any relation in the world.
a. Infinity of God and infinity of the world. —The absolute infinity of God
has its counterpart in the infinity of the world as an image. But how?
Is not everything in the world finite ? God's infinity and the world's finitude
remain infinitely far apart.
The infinite God might have created an infinite world. But the world,
because its possibility as such is not absolute, could not actually be infinite,
could not be greater or other than it is. Since the limitation of its possibility
originates in God and the limitation of its actuality in contingency, the world,
which is necessarily limited, is finite through contingency (De doc. ignor.,
11,8).
This finiteness, however, has a special character in Cusanus. Ascent to the
absolutely greatest or descent to the absolutely smallest is impossible. Rather,
in relation to every given finite thing, there is always a greater or a smaller
{De doc. ignor., II, 1). This results in another kind of infinity of the finite
world: we can always go further in the world. This is the endlessness of
the world. God's infinity is the archetype, perfection as infinity. The infinity
of the world is an image of God's infinity — it is mere endlessness.
Therefore the universe as a whole is neither finite nor infinite, but both
at the same time. It is infinite in the sense that it cannot be greater than it is
1
NICHOLAS OF CUS A 179
one and the other. There is nothing outside this oneness. It is anterior to
alteritas, hence alteritas is not its opposite. This "opposite" — without which
discursive reason cannot conceive anything — is unum et alterum (the one
and the other). The misleading expression {unum et alterum as the opposite
of unitas) is linguistically unavoidable to discursive reason. Because dis-
cursive reason invariably thinks in terms of relations, it inquires into the
relation between unitas and alteritas, and with this very inquiry leaves the
plane of knowing nonknowledge, which is that of speculative thinking.
Still, speculation is obliged to make use of the expressions it condemns.
The world is not Origin, but otherness. Nevertheless, each of its realities
"not far from every one of us For in Him we live, and move, and have our
:
of oneness, and the world out of God. The one and the numbers become
symbols for the production of the explicit from the implicit.
the number from which all numbers are unfolded; the point is the one
from which lines, surfaces, and bodies are unfolded; rest is the enfolding
of which motion is the unfolding; the now is the enfolding of time, from
which the successive moments in time are unfolded; identity is the enfolding
of difference {ibid.).
Just as the One, the point, rest, the now, identity, enfold that which is
produced from them, so from the absolute oneness of the infinite is unfolded
the manifold of the finite.
(2) Absolute and contracted. —The absolute of the godhead reappears
as the contractedness or concreteness {contr-actum seu concretum) of the
world. God is absolute Being, the world is contracted Being. Because this
concrete world receives from the absolute everything it is, everything that
is predicated absolutely of the absolute must be predicated of the contracted
contractedly {De doc. ignor., II, 4). Everything that is said of the absolute
may also be said of the world, but in an entirely different sense: thus the
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 181
( }) The one God and the universe. — Because there can be only one God,
there can also be only one world. God, as the simplest One, isin the one
world. He is, as it were, at the center of the world, in all things, and things in
their multiplicity are through the mediation of the one world in God {De
doc.ignor., 11,4).
plicity of things is produced by the divine mind, since God is the infinite
oneness. God seems to be multiplied, as it were, in things, and yet it is im-
possible that the infinite and supreme One should multiply itself {De doc.
ignor.,ll,i).
of the godhead; descending one arrives in the interior of the earth, in Hell.
Dante gave the most beautiful picture of this hierarchically ordered cosmos
in his poem describing his journey "down" into the innermost circle of Hell,
and then "up" again through each successive sphere to Paradise. This view
of the cosmos divided into layers, inhabited by intermediate beings in a
gradual progression from the world to God, was rejected by Cusanus in his
speculation. He presents a radically different picture:
At every level we remain in the world; the different modes of being
(a)
and modes of cognition relate not to the cosmos but to our existence in the
world.
(b) The cosmos is infinite. It has no center. The earth, or sublunary
sphere, and the celestial bodies are not ordered hierarchically according to
their nobility and purity. The cosmos is homogeneous.
(c) We are constantly soaring toward God or falling away
from Him, but
we are "immediate to God" —there
no mediation. There is only a leap over
is
the unbridgeable gulf: the gulf between God and all created things. This
conception, which has been recurrent from Plato down to the present,
allows the question, What is man ? to be answered in accordance with man's
existential answer to another question, Does he live in awareness of this
leap, or does it not exist for him ?
1 82 The Original Thinners
This sharp distinction between God and the world, the infinite and the
finite, leaves room for no intermediate beings. Cusanus speaks of angels
and demons in the traditional way, but as existing within creation, not as
intermediate beings between man and God.
(2) Levels of God's creation. —Rejecting the hierarchically ordered cosmos
does not imply rejection of the idea of levels or degrees. In creating the
world, God created the levels of being in the world. No individual thing
can be all things, for then itwould be God. Consequently God created levels
to which all things are assigned (De doc. ignor., II, 5). Every created
thing is held to be perfect in its kind, that is, according to its place in the
hierarchy of beings. The world is one. Nothing is separate, everything falls
within the system. Hence nothing is superfluous, everything is part of the
whole which could not exist without this multiplicity.
Development in the world leads to progress ad infinitum. Only between
God's infinity and the imitative endlessness of the world is there an un-
bridgeable gulf, not within the world. But within the world, it is only in
relation to God's infinity that all things are seen in their proper proportions,
at their right places, in hierarchical orders.
is as follows: God: beyond the opposites, Truth itself; mind: intellect and
discursive reason, the oppositions of reason transcended in the intellect; soul:
unfolding of the unity of the intellect and reflection in it; bodies: the final
unfolding which no longer contains anything else.
interpenetrate so that the apex of each touches the base of the other. On one
side light,
is on the other darkness. Or: The world is situated between God
and nothingness. This image shows that the progression of oneness into
otherness is simultaneously a progression in the opposite direction, from
otherness into oneness. The two contrary movements are disclosed in every
existent in the world, in all things. A realm of light and a realm of shadows
interpenetrate (De con., 1, 11 f.).
the human mind between the absolute actuality of God and the actuality
of individuals, which is the only real actuality in the world (De doc. ignor.,
11,6).
Motive power permeates the entire universe. This power is called nature.
Cusanus calls the movement of the universe a created spirit, without which
nothing is unity, nothing can subsist. This movement brings about the
loving union of all things. No individual thing moves entirely like any other,
but each in its own way shares in movement, so that we have one universe
(De doc. ignor., II, 10).
f. Why existence? The idea of the Creation. —Cusanus never asks, Why is
there anything at all, why is God ? Rather, he asks, Why is the world ? Imita-
tion, otherness, enfolding and unfolding, levels of reality — all these notions
are attempts to grasp what the world is. From this follows the question: Why
is the world ? The answer is the idea of the Creation.
184 The Original Thinners
the end of the flowing back; in the sensory one the end of the flowing out
and the beginning of the flowing back coincide."
All such images must be discarded when the unbridgeable gulf between
God and the world, between infinity and finitude, is resolutely asserted in
keeping with Cusanus' fundamental idea. Here we interpret his meaning as
follows: Because the world does not flow (emanate) from God, does not
develop from Him, it is not, as world, a process of the godhead. God is not
the seed from which the world grows, God is not a God in process of de-
velopment. Rather, the world, as a creation, is endlessly changing in time,
cutting across time but oriented toward God as an image to its original. It
is always turned toward the original in its endless movement, and yet it is
always the same and always a new reality. The world itself, as change, is not
a development in time with a beginning and an end. Its existence remains
essentially the same from the Creation to the end of the world. The ciphers
of the Creation and the end of the world are an intimation of the timeless
actuality of the infinite eternity, in which all temporality, which has neither
beginning nor end in time, is transcended.
I
N1 CHOLAS OF CU SA 185
The nature of the world (of the concrete, contractionis) cannot be known
unless the absolute original is known. Not only in our knowledge of God,
but also in our knowledge of the world, we must never lose sight of a non-
comprehension which lies within our comprehension (De doc. ignor., II).
Discursive reason cannot comprehend such matters as the following:
(1) God is totally free from ill-will (invidid), and yet the beings He
created disclose such features as divisibility, difference, plurality, imperfec-
Whence do these come? They cannot have a positive
tion, perishability.
cause.They have no cause at all, but are contingent (contingenter). But who
can comprehend the Creation, if it must be conceived at the same time as nec-
essary and as contingent ? Created beings, which are neither God nor nothing,
seem to be situated somewhere between God and nothingness. Yet they can-
not be compounded of being and nonbeing. Thus it seems that they neither
are nor are not. Discursive reason, which cannot transcend opposites, does
not grasp the being of created things (De doc. ignor., II, 2). "All we can
say is : The plurality of things is produced by the fact that God is in nothing-
ness" (De doc. ignor., II, 3).
(2) If God is all things, how can we conceive that created beings are not
eternal, since God's being is eternity itself? In so far as creation is the being
of God, it is eternity, but in so far as it is subject to time, it is not of God. Who
can comprehend that creation is from eternity and nevertheless in time ? (De
doc. ignor., II, 2.)
(3) Who can comprehend how God can be revealed to us through visible
creatures? God cannot be manifested in concrete signs, for such signs in-
11,3).
2. Cosmological ideas
a. Image of the infinite. Center and periphery. —The old metaphor "God
is an infinite sphere whose center is everywhere and whose periphery is no-
where" is not an analogy applied to the world, but an apt description of its
imitative character.
Because the cosmos is an image, it is infinite, but its infinity is of the
imitative kind, which denotes endlessness, the possibility of always going
further. In time, eternity is endless duration. In space, the infinite is the end-
1 86 The Original Thinners
tained between a center and a periphery. For God alone is both the center
and the periphery.
The earth is not the center of the world and the fixed stars do not constitute
the periphery of the physical cosmos. Neither the earth nor any other
place is the center of the cosmos.
c. The earth. —And now our own planet, the earth. Since everything in
the cosmos is in motion, obviously the earth too is in motion {De doc. ignor.,
II, n ). Because nothing in the world is mathematically exact, "the earth is
not in any sense the smallest or lowest part of the world" {De doc. ignor.,
NI C H O LAS OF CU S A 187
II, 12). Nor is the earth's darkness a proof of its inferiority. If we were on the
sun, we should not perceive the sun's great brightness, for the brightness
would be above us, as the region of fire is for us. If we were outside the earth,
we should perceive it as a bright star. "The earth is a noble star, which re-
ceives light, heat, and influences from all the other stars." But these influences
are not evidence of its imperfection, because, being a star, it in turn in-
fluences the sun. The influence is reciprocal. No star can subsist without the
others. The earth is as adequate a dwelling place for men, animals, and
plants as the other stars are for the living beings which inhabit them. "We
conjecture that no star is uninhabited."
What Cusanus calls "the world" is not just the world that is visible to us.
The one world contains many worlds invisible to us. We imagine that all
things refer to us and exist for us. But countless stars, far greater than the
earth we inhabit, have not been created just for this earth, but for the glory
of their Creator. The philosophers fail to grasp this when they interpret
everything solely from the point of view of the world visible to ourselves,
as if this earthly world were the crown and summit of all God's works
(De ven.sap., 22).
d. The smallest parts. —The infinite is present also in the smallest. "We
cannot arrive at the demonstrably simplest elementary units, which are en-
tirely in actu, because there is no absolutely Greatest or Smallest in re-
spect of the gradually different, even though discursive reason believes that
such exist" {De con., 1, 12).
The term "element" does not denote the same thing to the senses, to dis-
cursive reason, and to the intellect. What the senses regard as the elements
(fire, earth, water, air) are, to discursive reason, composite (elementata) ,
The world is eternal, but it is not eternity itself. It is eternal by virtue of its
participation in eternity. "The eternal world" is the world that cannot end,
that endures forever.
The world did not. begin in time, but time began with it. Hence we can say
both that the world has a beginning and that the world has no beginning.
For the world was not preceded by time, but by eternity (the term "pre-
ceded" has no temporal connotation here). The world is neither eternal
absolutely, of itself, nor has it a beginning in time. Time itself has no
beginning in time.
Cusanus carries this formulation still further. Time has its ground in the
1 88 The Original Thinners
world, not the world in time. The "duration" of the world does not depend
on For when the motion of the sky and time ceases, the world does
time.
not cease to be. But if the world came to an end, time too would come to an
end (De ludo globi, I).
The following statement by Meister Eckhart had been declared heretical:
"When God was and when He begat His Son, who is as eternal as Himself
and equal to Him in everything, at the same time He created the world as
1
well." Cusanus defends Eckhart's position. God and the world were in the
same now of eternity. For the world did not begin in another now of eternity,
but in the same now in which God is. "The assertion, Eternity is, was never
true unless the assertion, The world is, was true at the same time."
—
Such formulations like all speculative thought are absurd to discursive —
reason, because the representations which unavoidably guide such thinking
cannot be visualized. We speak in terms of time, although the things we
speak of cannot be represented under the category of time. This is made
evident by the questions which discursive reason, unguided by speculation,
asks:
Where was God before He created the world? The question is absurd
because it presupposes a time and place when they did not yet exist. The
appropriate answer is: God never "was" anywhere; "was" is a statement
about existence in time. Why did God not create the world earlier? The
question makes no sense, for "earlier" and "later" designate differences in
time; accordingly, He could never have created anything "earlier" or "later."
Such questions are suggested by the terms we use to express our rational
representations. The proper way to deal with them is not by condemning
them as "foolish" or "blasphemous," but by systematically elucidating the
speculative mode of thinking.
4. Individuals
1
Josef Koch, Sitzttng der Heidelberger Academic der Wissenschaften, Cusanus Texte I. Predigten.
1937. PP- 5i #.
NICHOLAS OF CUS A 189
harmony 'flutes' in the flute, and 'cithers' in the cither" (De con., II, 3).
Since each individual existent cannot actually be all things, because it is
cannot desire not to be. "Since he cannot be another spirit unless he ceases to
be what he was, his desire is enclosed in his being. Therefore he not only
does not desire to be different, but is happy in that he cannot be different.
Indeed, to have one's own being means to have being by participating in the
divine" (Exc, Basel edition, p. 696). Hence Cusanus exclaims in one of his
sermons: "Take, O man, all come your way as the gift of God
things that
and speak in admiration. . . . God gave me Being. ... I, who was nothing,
190 The Original Thinners
a. The earth no longer the center of the world. —The case of Cusanus
proves that removal of the earth from the center of the world did not
necessarily shake Christian faith. Actually, the new view originated in a
change, consistent with the Christian faith, in the traditional ideas about
the created world.
Nietzsche wrote: "Since Copernicus has removed the earth from the
center of the world, man has found himself, as it were, on an inclined
plane; he has been rolling ever faster away from the center —whither?
into nothingness?" But what has the position of the earth in the cosmos to
do with man's position in Being? Nothing at all, unless he is subject to the
superstition that God is present in the flesh —a superstition which, to be
sure, has deep historical roots.
the shifting of the earth from its central position (Cusanus believed the
center to be everywhere and nowhere) does not affect the position of man,
for man is still aware of his place in the totality of Being. Long before
Copernicus, Cusanus undermined the idea that the earth is the center, and
did so far more radically than the astronomer. (Copernicus still believed
the sun to be the center, not only of the solar system, but also of the cosmos.)
At the same time, however, Cusanus, unlike Nietzsche, saw man in his
unique greatness, as not in the least diminished by this change.
In Nietzsche the astronomical conception becomes the symbol of an en-
tirely different and very important experience: that of an existential nihilism
which has been steadily growing in modern times under the cover of super-
ficially retained traditions. The idea that astronomical and other scientific
in the finite, in that which the finite presupposes: this "pre" is the absolute
measurement, the condition of every finite measurement. It becomes possible
to experience God's absolute infinity in the world itself, when God's infinity
is seen as the original of the imitative endlessness of the world.
The fundamental attitude of insatiable curiosity in finite progress is not
abandoned, but placed in a higher perspective. The fundamental attitude
of a life in and pathways we
the infinite becomes a guide over the roads
find in the world, which lead endlessly in all directions. While essentially
different, progress and spiritual aspiration must be combined if progress
is to be a path upward rather than a servitude.
(4) The fundamental human situation implies both the urge to the
infinite, which draws man on ever further toward penetration of the
ground of being, and the urge to the finite, in which he feels more secure
because he is at home. Both are ciphers for man's openness to transcendence,
but cease to be so when they lead to mere endlessness or imprison man in
the worldly finite.
d. The splendor of the world. —God made the world as perfect as it could
be. Therefore it is very perfect {De ludo globi). Though it is an image, the
world is illumined by the splendor of God.
"In God is everything, outside Him nothing." He alone is "center and
circumference of the universe." Hence we know the world only in God
and in relation to God. Just as the splendor of the world, though it is
III. CHRIST
a. Christ —
and the world. By giving Christ the privileged position of a God
incarnate, Cusanus vitiates his conception of the world as a plurality of
individuals, none of whom is the absolutely greatest, none supremely per-
fect. He expounds in speculative terms what in fact is merely his dogmatic
persons which had been separate before and are now united, Man and God.
He could not be a union at all, for He is a self-contained individual person.
"This marvelous union is more sublime than all thinkable unions. Therefore
we must conceive of this concretely greatest as God, but at the same time
creature, and same time Creator, Creator and creature,
as creature but at the
Jesus Christ, can be rooted only in the divine intellect, which alone is all
things in actuality. Since the supreme intellect marks the culmination
(terminus, limit, end) of all intellectual nature, it must, like God, be all
in all.
194 The Original Thinners
This very greatest, which isman and God in one, can only be one —can
only be one man. For were He not unique, He would not be the greatest.
This one man, who is God, possessed a body appropriate to His spirit-
uality. He
was not begotten in the natural way. The Holy Spirit, which is
absolute love, formed a living body out of the Virgin's blood. The Mother
of God was necessarily free from whatever might have impaired the purity
of such a birth: she had never known a man and she was free from carnal
desire.
The one Man-God is a physical event in time. He is historical. But
He is also eternal. "The man could come forth from the virgin mother
only in time, from God the Father only in eternity!" (De doc. ignor., Ill, 5).
But the temporal birth required a special time: "the fullness of time."
When this time came, the Man-God was born, but He remained hidden
as such from all creatures.
What we call the immaculate conception and nativity "was not effected
in temporal sequence, as in the case of human conception, but in a single
moment of supra-temporal activity" {De doc. ignor., Ill, 5).
d. Why did all this ta\e place?— God enveloped the eternal Logos, the
word, His only-begotten Son, in human nature, because we could grasp
Him only in a form resembling our own. Thus He revealed Himself to
us in accordance with our capacity to receive Him (De doc. ignor., Ill, 5).
Two mysteries are associated with this revelation of God in Jesus Christ
and that of the Resurrection.
that of the Cross
The Death on the Cross. "The smallest coincides with the greatest, the
most ignominious death of the righteous with the glory of everlasting
Mic" (Dedoc.ignor.,U\,6).
And: "The voluntary and so undeserved, cruel and ignominious death
of the man Christ on the Cross, was the eradication, gratification, and puri-
fication of all the carnal desires of human nature."
For each man this means: the closer he comes to perfection through
steadfastness and courage, through love and humanity, the closer he comes
to Christ. "In the real Christian there is in fact only Christ." The Christian
must put behind him all the things of this world. "In such withdrawal into
himself he sees Christ without recourse to enigmatic images, because then
he sees himself in detachment from the world, as one who has taken on
the form of Christ" (De possest).
The Resurrection (De doc. ignor., Ill, 7) : Christ died in order that
human nature might be raised with Him
from the dead to life everlasting,
in order that the mortal body might become an indestructible spiritual
body.
Immortality can be attained only through death and the overcoming of
death in the Resurrection. If Christ, as God, had never died, He would have
remained mortal. Had He never died, He would not have been able to
I
N 1 CHOLAS OF CU SA 195
Among the precursors of modern science were the Paris nominalists, the
Italian artists who made discoveries in their work-
(such as Leonardo)
shops, the astronomer Copernicus, etc. One of the founders of modern
historical science was Lorenzo Valla, who proved the spuriousness of
the so-called Donation of Constantine. Ought we to place Cusanus among
such pioneers? He never carried out a systematic empirical investigation,
he never made a single real discovery. To this extent he has no place in
the history of any one science. Nor was he interested in a universal
scientific method, such as eventually came into being. But he occasionally
had penetrating insights and put forward tentative hypotheses. Above all,
The great theme of the treatise is really this: The world of the finite,
which by its very nature consists of the more and the less, should be studied
by counting, measuring, and weighing operations. The question of weights
should be given special attention. In this connection Cusanus anticipates
a line of development that was to prove extraordinarily fruitful. But he
does not follow up his own suggestions. He lacked the essential element
of modern science —the development of mathematical theory in conjunction
with controlled observations based on accurate weights, measures, and
computations. He does not anticipate measurement as a criterion for con-
firming or refuting a predictive hypothesis. Not until such a method was
evolved did science become exact science and embark on steady progress.
Cusanus gives us mere tabulations of weights (to no definite purpose),
along with an assortment of imaginary experiments, designed to make
ad hoc inferences possible. These are a mixture of shrewd anticipation and
nonsense. All this does not come to very much, because he did not actually
put any of his proposals to the test. The book has been noticed because
of its theme and was once reprinted in the sixteenth century, but it does
not seem to have inspired or stimulated any actual research.
d. —
Study of documents and critical history. Cusanus had experience of
documentary research in archives and libraries, and of historical investiga-
tion. He discovered a manuscript of Plautus' in 1426. Before Valla, he
But Marsilius thought along purely intellectual lines and, with the principle
of popular sovereignty as his point of departure, ended up by championing
the omnipotent state, so anticipating the anti-liberal ideas of a later day,
such as were first fully developed by Hobbes. Cusanus had in mind the
political realities of his own day, he himself and was politically active, his
thinking is permeated with the idea of man's dignity and the freedom of his
spirit in view of its perpetual bond with God.
c. Knowledge and power. —God's knowledge and God's will are inter-
changeable concepts. What God knows, He wills. His knowledge and His
will are not two separate things. Rather, His knowledge is also the reality
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 199
and will are separate. But man aspires to the original knowledge. "To share
in this knowledge is immortal joy." Here is an example of a knowledge
which is also will and hence power: The grammarian would be extremely
pleased if he could discover a simple rule that would enable him to under-
stand the whole of grammar in an instant; similarly the rhetorician would
be delighted if he could find a little word that would at one stroke make
him than Cicero (Exc, Scharpft", 492) A perfect mind, whose
a better orator .
h. Novelty and progress. —Modern science sets a high value on novelty, and
great importance is attached to priority in time. The scientist feels that
whenever he discovers something, no matter how insignificant in itself, he
has contributed to the progress of his discipline. Does Cusanus share in
this attitude ?
says: "I have made progress," his meaning is that his later treatises expand
and supplement his earlier work, that he has devised new forms and
concepts relative to the method of transcending. But this "progress" actually
consists of his own version of the same speculations on which as Cusanus —
—
himself recognized all the great philosophers before him had embarked
(especially Plato, Proclus, and the Pseudo-Dionysius). In his work he
aspires merely to enrich the method of exposition, to devise new comparisons
and modes of intellection, to replace some of the old categories with new
ones.
The historical very different from
sequence of the speculative systems is
a. —In Cusanus the essential is not the will to knowledge, but the symbolic
power of the knowable, considered as a copy of the divine. Speculative ideas
are mirrored in the empirical world.
He does not discover methods of actual investigation, his suggestions
for methods are formulated so vaguely that we cannot tell
possible
whether they are workable or not; he never develops, works out, or applies
methods of investigation. His thinking is dominated by speculative methods.
Actually— though Cusanus did not suspect this—his fresh approach to the
ancient themes of metaphysical speculation carried him even further away
from the attitude of a mathematician, scientist, historian, or political thinker.
What was dominant was his fundamentally religious attitude, his experience
of the world illumined by transcendence. As though imprisoned in his own
symbolic thinking, he seems to draw justification from the fundamentally
"conjectural" character of all reality and knowledge of the world.
awareness that we can investigate only objects in the world, not the world
as a whole. Although Cusanus has some surprising ideas, he does not
solve any scientific problems. Still, his mind blazes trails into unexplored
territory where marvelous possibilities seem to loom. He appears to be on
the brink of science.
"Speculative anticipations" should never be confused with actual antici-
pations of scientific discoveries. Scientific discovery is achieved solely on the
basis of a cogent, verifiable method which needs no philosophical justifica-
tion. Cusanus' so-called "anticipations" are not cognition but a playing with
ideas, a mixture of truths arrived at by accident and of inextricable fallacies.
a. Science is —
Cusanus condemns the indiscriminate curiosity of
a whore.
discursive reason; to him knowledge has meaning only when guided by
the intellect to wisdom in God: "J ust as carnal lust finds its consecration
and appeasement only when channeled in the sacrament of marriage, so love
of knowledge finds its appeasement only when channeled in true union with
the Bridegroom. So long as the mind indulges without restraint in vain
knowledge, it no more finds the object of its natural desire than does a man
who cohabits with every whore. There can be no true marriage with a fickle
woman, only with eternal wisdom" (Exc, V, 473; Scharpff, 492). This
comparison of the urge for knowledge with sensual lust condemns neither,
but is intended to show that the one achieves its true purpose only in the
sacrament of marriage, the other in faith. Discursive reason in itself is barren
because, for all its passion, it is endless and empty. It dissolves all things into
a multiplicity without constructive unity. It attains truth only in the trans-
cendent, which is objectively called "God," and subjectively "faith." Mere
discursive reason can momentarily stir up overwhelming desire, but it re-
mains fruitless. The pleasure it gives is vain and swollen with pride, it pro-
duces no divine joy.
Thus
science is a whore (when not guided by its ultimate purpose); it
is knowledge of God (when guided by its true purpose). Though these
statements originate in faith, the question implied in them is still timely.
But our answers are different and more complex.
I
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 203
conjectural. Modern science strives for ever greater accuracy, degrees of in-
accuracy being themselves objects of investigation.
To Cusanus, technical application is a matter of secondary importance. It
is symbolic of the mind's creative power. To modern science, technical appli-
cation leads to the creation of a new technological world. This technology
in turn serves to promote the advance of science.
To Cusanus, knowledge is certain of itself as an image of the divine
original. Modern science strives to find its own limits. Having reached a
limit on the one hand, driven to put further questions, whereby, time
it is,
and again, it surpasses new limits; and on the other hand, it runs into ques-
tions it cannot answer.
To Cusanus, the whole is eternity manifesting itself. Modern science
changes with the object to be known in an interminable process whose
movement affects both object and method.
To rest upon God and
Cusanus, the world and knowledge of the world
are sheltered in God. To modern science, the being of the world has no
roots, and the world is fragmented. The will to knowledge can take the
But what is this principle? Only in modern science has the meaning of
science become a great problem, one that does not admit of scientific solution.
Kant made an essential contribution toward its clarification with his doctrine
of the regulative Ideas and his insights into the radical difference between
systematic knowledge and scattered information about facts.
Discursive reason, the logic of contradiction, and rationalism as such can
at any time become ends in themselves, laying claim to the status of absolute
204 The Original Thinners
merely shows how they are related externally, according to the circumstances,
as grasped by measurement and other determinations.A man who believes
he can attain truth in this know what truth is.
way does not
A wise man is, rather, one who knows how ignorant this mode of knowl-
edge leaves him. But such a man also knows that without the truth he does
not attain to being, life, or insight. Therefore, as he becomes aware of his
ignorance, he longs with his whole being to stand in the truth. But he cannot
achieve this through external, discursive knowledge (cf. the treatise On the
Hidden God).
Cusanus is guided by the idea of a perfect knowledge, which only God
possesses; man knowledge is an image of the original divine
imitates it, his
knowledge. True knowledge is knowledge of God. All the roads of knowl-
edge, including the knowledge of ignorance, lead to knowledge of God.
The meaning of all knowledge of the finite is the experience of the infinite as
revealed in the finite. Knowledge of the finite is not self-contained, is not
i
N ICH OLAS OF CU S A 205
A man of purely scientific outlook might say: Why not stay within the
graspable bounds of the real world? Here lies our only certainty, because
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 207
I. THE INDIVIDUAL
a. To be oneself. —
Cusanus addresses God: "Thou makest reply within my
heart, saying: Be thou thine and I too will be thine [sis tu tuus, et ego ero
tuus]." This is his fundamental experience: I should be myself. Not until I
have come to be myself can I experience the reality of God. God's first gift
one thing gives us pause: Cusanus is speaking in general terms, not about
actual personal experience. He did not strive unremittingly to become
transparent to himself —an experience that is both disquieting and re-
vealing. This is perhaps why his actual life (which will be discussed in
Part Five) does not come up to the level of his self-certainty. The truth of
his magnificent statements would have been deeper had he ventured to
apply it to himself, to the historicity of human Existenz, which is always
individual and unique. Cusanus is too sure of himself, too bland in his
general statements. And yet they are a magnificent formulation of man's
task.
radical otherness. Because the original is infinity, the copy can be seen as
an infinite movement of the productive mind: because the copy knows that
it participates in the original, this movement is upward. The infinite is
present as the life of the finite.
c. The leap. — If man, whose thinking in the world is finite, does not lose
himself in forgetfulness of his situation, he has an ineradicable urge to
soar from the from the shifting soil of the finite to a firm
finite to the infinite,
support in the But the springboard for this leap is the world itself,
infinite.
thinking.
The abyss of nonknowledge serves as a bridge and yet remains an abyss.
In the world all cognition is comparative. It takes us ever further, without
arriving at the infinite. We cannot attain to the infinite by moving closer. The
leap from the finite to the infinite can be effected only by the leap from
discursive thinking to intellectuaal thinking (from the ratio to the intel-
lectus). We swing ourselves over the abyss, and leave the whole realm of
the finite behind.
This, however, is not accomplished by extravagant imaginings, but by
thinking. Unlike discursive thinking, which tolerates no contradiction and
attempts to eliminate it by posing finite alternatives, intellectual thinking,
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 209
through the coincidentia oppositorum, grasps the infinite beyond the world
of objects.
In this darkness is born the light which now illuminates all finitude and
is the source of our true awareness of being. It discloses truth in the finite
itself. For not until the birth of this light is the finite recognized as such by
virtue of its reference to the infinite, which is unlike any finite relation.
In the finite we become conscious of the infinite, in relative being of absolute
being, in rational knowledge of the supra-rational presuppositions which
give meaning to finite knowledge.
Although between the infinite and the finite there obtains no relation
that would enable us to think the infinite (which would then become finite)
by relating it to the finite, the infinite can guide us. Freed from limitations,
it sets the standards of the finite.
e. Man see\s God and God wants to be \nown. — Man is created in order
that he may seek God and find peace in this quest alone. Yet God is not to
be found in the world of the senses; discursive reason is too weak to know
God; our abstractions fail to arrive at any similarity to God. But if the
world of the senses and of discursive reason were of no use in the quest
for God, man would have been set down in the world in vain (De quaerendo
Deum).
What is the purpose of the world? Cusanus answers: God wants to be
known, to be seen in His omnipotence. Therefore simultaneously with
the world He created man, who comes to know the world and, through it,
God.
The world is the order of all existents, of every object of cognition,
210 The Original Thinners
f. Metaphors for the ascent through thought. —Just as our body needs food,
so our spirit needs spiritual nourishment. Our intellect is on the "hunt
for wisdom," guided by an innate knowledge of what kind of nourish-
ment it needs. By means of our thinking we strike out in every direction
{De ven. sap., i).
in our search for immortal food
Our way is illustrated by a comparison with a game
erratic search for the
Cusanus invented, "the ball game" (which is the title of one of his works,
De ludo globi). It is played with a wooden ball with a spherical hollow
off center. When the ball is bowled, it does not, since one side is heavier
than the other, roll in a straight line, but takes a spiral path. The players
toss the ball over a surface divided into ten concentric circles. At the
center is the king —Christ. The winner is the player whose ball has touched
number of circles and comes closest to the center.
the greatest
Our mind has the nature of fire. God sent it into the world for the sole
purpose of burning, of becoming a flame. The flame increases when the
mind is kindled by wonder. The wonder we experience in contemplating
God's works is the wind that increases our longing by turning it into
love for the Creator and into contemplation of wisdom {De quaerendo
Deum).
Man's consummation in the world is the joy we experience through
our senses of sight, hearing, taste, touch, and smell, through feeling, life,
and movement, and through the use of our discursive reason and our
intellect. Its culmination is an infinite, ineffable joy, in which all joy, all
Man "knocks at the door in fervent prayer, confident that he will not
be abandoned it only he continues without cease to enter into Christ"
{Dc possest).
Did we not believe in Christ as the Son of God, says Cusanus, we would
never follow His teaching as the teaching of the One true God. All the great
philosophers and sages were merely men, and "every man who is not God
may be a liar." We —
must therefore believe nothing can be more certain
that He is the Son of God. Therein lies our salvation (To Albergati, 37).
"No believer in Christ has ever been disappointed" (ibid., 54).
At the close of De docta ignorantia (III, 12) we read: "Nothing can
resist the man who enters into Christ, and nothing will be difficult for him,
neither the Scriptures nor this world, for he has been transformed into
Christ by the spirit of Christ that dwells in him, which is the goal of
intellectual yearning [intellectualium desideriorum\r
What is the meaning of "transformation into Christ"? What is the mean-
ing of "the spirit of Christ dwells in me"? Such questions cannot be
answered in other terms, but perhaps they can be elucidated indirectly.
We may call such expressions ciphers for the presence of the eternal
within me, for the experience of "absolute consciousness," manifesting itself
Christian.
To us the "Christian within me" signifies roughly a way of understanding
the eternal, not in the subjectivity of Existenz with the objectivity of ciphers,
but on the basis of an objective revelation. The physical presence of the
God-Man in time, the physical presence of the Church as the incarnation
intolerance. Even a man of Cusanus' stature did not wholly escape these
consequences (as we shall see in discussing the ideas advanced in De pace
fidei and elsewhere). And the Christian certainties have made possible a
kind of dishonesty unparalleled in history and disastrous to the entire Chris-
tian world. The remoteness of transcendence in spite of the nearness of
being-given-to-oneself excludes approximation to God and the possibility
of becoming godlike. Something far more difficult is required: the striving
to apprehend man's being in itself, to fulfill it, to advance in it without
knowing exactly what it is.
grandeur. But to create such a being God had neither a worldlymodel nor
particular treasures at His disposal. Above all, there was no place left on
earth for him, who was to make the universe the object of his contemplation,
to live in. For all the places were taken.
Therefore God made man in His image and likeness, ordained that he
should possess the endowments that every individual calls his own, and said
are free to degenerate to the basest animality or to rise to the highest spheres
of divinity. And after putting these words into the mouth of God, Pico
cries out jubilantly: What good fortune! Man can be what he desires. The
animals possess at birth all they will ever possess. The higher spirits are
from the first all they will be for eternity. In man alone God planted the
seed of every form of activity and the germs of every form of life. Who can
admire this capacity for
fail to change! It was for good reason that mankind
was symbolized by the figure of Proteus in the mysteries.
The Creation had been completed. Only then did God decide to do
something more than to create a world. Did He then proceed to create
something which, once created, would be removed from His control, namely,
freedom? Pico replies: It is a sign of His omnipotence that He was con-
fronted with a dilemma in creating the last living being a sign of His —
wisdom that He hesitated as to which gifts He should confer upon it—
sign of His love that He compelled Himself to endow that very being with
original sin from the outset.
Pico holds that man was not created according to a model; subject to no
standard, he is the inexhaustible possibility of freedom. He has unique
dignity, for thanks to God's creative will, man is entirely on his own. Pico
omits to tell us in what sense man is dependent on something other and
hence limited in his freedom, how he experiences the source of his freedom in
his very consciousness of freedom.
Though no less aware of the sublimity of man's task, Cusanus limits it
is not originally a part of a world complete in itself, but a later addition, set
down in a world that has no particular place for him. To Cusanus, man,
with his freedom and the possibilities it opens up, remains at a distance
from God as His image and likeness sheltered in the world by the Creator,
who also encompasses his freedom; for all the possibilities of his freedom,
man stands within the world. To Pico, he is opposed to the world as a
whole. He can make it an object of his cognition, but he can also shatter it.
II. PEACE
9
Fundamental reality of the Church. Cusanus thinking
in the Concordantia
activity on behalf of the Church. If both Church and Empire were adequate
to the divine archetypes, peace internal and external would be achieved
through the unity of Church and Empire.
In Cusanus' day, the Church as an eternal reality was taken for granted
by Western man. The deeply religious Cusanus was no different. The Pope
might be held prisoner, priests and monks might be openly abused and held
in contempt, but nobody rejected the Church. Men could neither live nor
die without it. The widespread dissatisfaction was not with the Church as
such, but with its condition at the time. The corruption of the Church, the
need for reform, was the great political issue of the day.
Cusanus, who lived in God's unity whose image is the one world, shows
us how this illumines all present reality, even now giving us an intimation
of eternal peace. Peace through unity is the God-created reality. The only
way to restore it in the world is to make
image a better likeness of the
the
original. However muddled the relations of Church and Empire may be
in reality, they owe their existence to this harmony which resides in the
—
cosmos in individual man and in the order of Church and Empire.
Although the individual becomes himself only in confrontation with God,
he is not on his own, but a member of the entire community of mankind.
While the individual is himself through participating in the infinite, his
participation in the world makes him a member of a community in bond
with God; every individual is united with every other within the world.
The harmony of this world, which is an image of the divine original, is
all-embracing concord (concordantia catholica) and manifests itself as the
agreement of all men (consensus omnium).
Nothing in the universe is to be loved save as an aspect of the unity and
I
NICHOLAS OF CU S A 215
order of the universe. No man is to be loved save as an aspect of the unity and
order of human nature. Every love has its truth in love of the One God who
is absolute, infinite love and the source of all unity.
Peace unites because in it oppositions are stilled. Through peace all
things are linked with the center, so that the whole is preserved from disin-
tegration. Peace is the object of our longing, for without it nothing can
subsist. Only in peace can truth endure. All those who have written subtly
about truth have for this reason sought to present in a peaceful way the
truth contained in divergent opinions. The philosopher who is caught up
in opposites cannot see peace. Peace, the home of truth, cannot be attained by
discursive thinking; it can only be intuited above and beyond all opposites
(Exc, V, 4S7; ScharpfT, p. 532).
On the other hand: Although God is at peace with all men, not every
man is at peace with God. For by virtue of his freedom, man can not only
move closer to peace, but can also move away from it. He has only one
recourse: "We are born as the children of wrath, but through faith in Christ
we are reconciled with the author of peace." Hence Cusanus' certainty: "For
the peace of Christ all things have been prepared from the beginning, so
that there may be one world and in it the final goal of Christ."
1. De concordantia catholica
faith and love all men are united with God. No man is grounded solely
upon himself.
The Church in its purity, as eternal order from the beginning of time
until the Resurrection of the Dead, is Christi ecclesia triumphans, but in
the world it is ecclesia militans. For as long as we live here below, there
must be a steady increase of faith and love. Every many must strive to
surpass the degree he has already achieved, knowing that there will be
no completion in time.
Among many vividly concrete metaphysical interpretations of the founda-
tion and early manifestations of theChurch, we shall mention only a few.
God, the and the saints in Paradise are the Church triumphant in
angels,
eternity. Within the Church in time, the sacraments correspond to God,
the priests to the angels, the people to the saints. Sacraments, priesthood,
and the body of the faithful are the principal elements of the Church
militant.
God alone knows the Christians united with Him through love. The
angels know those who are allied with God through faith. An act of
faith is like the striking of a chord which reverberates throughout the
heavenly kingdom. The angels perceive it the moment a believer touches
the chord.
b. The idea of unity. Pope and Council. —The main theme of the Council
of Basel was the relations between Papacy and Council. How can they work
together? Which should have precedence in the event of disagreement? From
what does each derive its legitimacy?
Fundamental and exceeding all else in importance is the idea of unity.
To Cusanus, the unity and harmony of all things are present everywhere
in the world. The unity of the Church is the unity of the faith. A difference
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 217
whose power surpasses that of all other princes. The emperor is the equal
of the Pope. In matters of government the emperor takes precedence; in
religious matters, the Pope. The latter 's claim to temporal power had been
based on the spurious Donation of Constantine. Imperial power, by its
very nature, is independent of the Church; it is dependent only on God.
posedly flowing from the divine spirit, become manifest? In practice, this
will is determined by advisory and executive bodies which are appointed
or elected. The characteristic of truth is unity, but here it becomes una-
nimity.
Cusanus reflected to an equal extent on the unifying spirit of the truth,
on the meaning of metaphysical repraesentatio, and on the technique of
elections. He desired institutions whose actual power would be legitimate
in a technical-juridical sense and sanctioned supernaturally. Such con-
gruence of secular and spiritual power cannot be realized in practice, ex-
cept at unusual, unpredictable, and short-lived moments when a whole
community acts unanimously.
this type can be varied almost at will. This lies in the very nature of symbolic
interpretation. It embraces opposite* and shifts the emphasis as needed
within one and the same over-all view. The dangers that result are two-
fold. First: When such a method is employed to justify practical measures,
Cusanus has full mastery over symbolic thinking. It gives spiritual force
to his ideas. Perhaps it is in his conception of the imitative, reflected,
metaphorical being of all finite things that his symbolic thinking achieves
its greatest clarity. Everything that is, everything that is thinkable, every-
thing that is to be done, he envisages in terms of metaphysical "meaning."
As we put it : he reads the ciphers. Yet, for all the magnificence of his images,
the fact that in his arguments and justifications he, like so many others
throughout history, mistakes this meaning for reality itself leads him time
and again to practical-existential confusion.
The metaphysical images, the juridical forms and arguments, the real
decisions are interrelated. Traditional faith, rational form, practical interest
support and combat one another. Any one of the three may prevail for a
time. On the plane of language they slip and slide into one another. In
concrete situations, the real will can be obscured by metaphysical ideas and
beguiled into surrendering to brute force. Conversely, practical interests
can make use of metaphysical ideas in the actual struggle, deceiving the
adversary without gaining the commitment of those who proffer them.
The power of the practical interests is veiled. Multiple interpretations on
the merely rational plane do not make for clarity. Because of their very
depth, metaphysical ciphers, unless their methodological character is clearly
recognized, can becloud vision and obscure the real powers at work.
Metaphysical interpretations cannot serve as arguments for a worldly
goal save by deceiving. No specific course of action can be adequately based
on them; their real function is to elucidate one's own faith. Universally
valid justifications in theworld cannot be based on historically documented
contracts, unless the principle that contracts are binding is accepted. Noth-
ing can be justified as a means to an end unless the end is recognized as
such, in terms rationally defined, by all the parties concerned.
Characteristic of this bewildering confusion is the double meaning of
220 The Original Thinners
f. —
Comparison with Dante. Cusanus' purpose is to encourage reform in
the Church and the Empire; his philosophical thinking is intended to
assist in this task. When we compare him with Dante, we see how very
Plato said: the Good will never attain to reality until the philosophers
have become rulers or the rulers philosophers. Dante aspires —though not
explicitly —to rule the world without holding office, through the authority
of his counsel, by virtue of his intellectual superiority, his earnestness,
and his poetic power. Neither Plato nor Dante envisaged the solution
which to Kant seemed the only practical one: a form of government which
Kant called "republican" (because it realizes political freedom in the public
interest res publica —
as the foundation on which everything else rests),
•Translator's Note: The symbolic Greyhound (Deliverer of Italy?) mentioned in Inferno, Canto
I, line 100.
222 The Original Thinners
to violence and despotism, can be humanized only through full and open
discussion of differences. This is merely to recognize that we are never
whole and entire.
in possession of the truth
Dante was under the delusion that his towering artistic and intellectual
gifts placed him so far above his contemporaries that by his own strength he
could achieve what is actually possible for finite men only through a process
2. De pace fidei
J
NICHOLAS OF CVS A 223
to find the truth by exercising choice upon which his freedom of will
depends. But man's situation is this: Since nothing in the world of the
senses is permanent, since views and conjectures, like languages and inter-
pretations, change according to circumstances, human nature requires
frequent re-examination of the essentials. Only thus are errors dissipated and
the truth enabled to shine through enduringly.
How is this to be accomplished? Since there is only one truth and since
every free will can apprehend it, it would be expedient to reduce all different
religions to the one true faith. Strange! No sooner has Cusanus opened
the door to the possibility of man's constantly testing himself, striving in
freedom for the truth, than he shuts it again by invoking the one truth,
which the free will must recognize as one and indivisible.
Cusanus does not condemn the existing diversity of religious faiths.
men, though engaged in loving struggle, will be able to live in peace with
one another. For all the disparity of their ways of life, they will try to
understand each other and learn to love one another. Disparity among
faiths and ways of life does not preclude peace, for peace requires only one
resolution: never to resort to violence in the name of religion, never to
subordinate religious belief to practical interests.
In the temporal world, my ultimate duty is communication
to enter into
with other men, never claiming to know what I myself am
definitively
or what the other is. In perceiving the transcendent meaning of the ciphers,
we can never attain universal validity. Transcendence is accessible to us
only through the reading of ciphers, but the meaning we derive is never
without ambiguity. All we know is what others say and what we ourselves
say, and in neither case can we be sure of understanding correctly. For the
speaker can misunderstand himself in the very act of expression. He comes
closer to himself through a process of understanding that never ceases to
test itself, he deepens his understanding by asking questions —whether to
defend himself against adversaries suspected of hostility to the truth or for
motives arising out of concrete situations. Only in this way can we learn
to know ourselves in the face of the transcendent which is hidden and
becomes clearer only in the experience of the ciphers. We live with one
another as companions in the journey of human fate.
but finite; they can be taken one by one, and in solving them we may be
guided by what is merely expedient. However, the will to peace as such has
a metaphysical source: although it leaves room for reasonable settlements
contention on the empirical plane? At just what point are spiritual attitudes
What kind of faith is needed to link all
perverted into practical claims?
men and to keep practical problems clearly separated from questions of
faith? What faith— or what element present in every variety of faith—must
be common to all men if mankind is to be united in peace ?
This element is faith in freedom, faith rooted in freedom. This is the
only faith that gives rise to demands for freedom
and political
at the social
levels. I shall not deal here with the idea of how political freedom reflects
those who are more accomplished or more outstanding, unity and peace
prevail without ill-will. But he adds directly: "In so far as this is possible."
For although peace is the power that makes possible the life of all men, it
religious customs and the true faith which is supposed to be the same for
all. This lack of clarity is not accidental. Human faith discloses an original
substantial diversity such that unification is impossible at the deepest level.
What limits Cusanus' perspective is his certainty that the Christian faith
is absolutely true, a certainty that excludes the other truth and seeks to
impose on all men its own unacknowledged limitations.
Cusanus does not distinguish between the diversity of individuals and
the plurality of the historical forms of selfhood. He gives magnificent
expression to the all-important philosophical idea of unity, but he weakens
it by positing a particular historicity as universal, thereby going counter
to his own will to peace.
The endless historical reality of a spirit is always more or less than such
ideal types disclose. They enable us to see the spirit of a whole as the result
of countless factors produced and handed down in the medium of education,
language, forms of social life, These produce
patterns of conduct, ideas.
the "spirit" of a historical epoch, and within it great men produce the
supratemporal in works and actions that break through the spirit of an
age or a community.
Did Cusanus' theories spring from his experience of life, and if so, did they
in turn influence it? At what points was there agreement, and at what
points not?
We whether he lived in accordance with his beliefs. His
are not asking
reflectionswere not such as to provide practical prescriptions for man's
conduct (nor does any real philosophy). What we are asking, rather, is in
what way his philosophical thinking affected his fundamental attitudes
toward life. Were his pious speculations matched by equal piety in his
practical activities ?
Did a specific practice of life attain self-understanding in this philosophy?
Did his philosophy help him to achieve self-certainty in respect of his
political activity, for example? To what extent did his life motivate and
I
N 1CH0LAS OF CU S A 229
Reality shattered nearly all his deeper convictions and practical aspirations.
Did his vision of Being turn out to be an illusion for not having withstood
the test of practice? Was he unable to immerse himself in his historical
tasks because he clung so fervently to the promise of eternal bliss held
out by Christian revelation ?
In the last analysis, such questions cannot be answered. All we can
attempt here is to look at the factual data in relation to which such questions
arise.
this activity was the concordat of 1447-48, a victory for Cusanus. The
Germans declared their obedience to the Pope. The Council of Basel
had disbanded in 1443.
Why had Cusanus defected from the conciliar party? The determining
factor was the threat of a new schism. In reality the Pope alone could
preserve the unity of the Church. The Council had failed. The consensus
omnium had given way to endless quarreling and sanctimonious faction-
alism. The Holy Spirit no longer seemed to be guiding the proceedings.
The authority of the Council to represent the entire Church had declined.
It no longer had any real power, although it continued to promulgate
decrees. At the time when Piccolomini was still undecided and wrote "There
was no Christian there who did not weep, the Holy Spirit could not have been
among us," and "God sees where the truth lies, I do not," Cusanus had
already made up his mind.
The unity of the Church was the all-important consideration. Unity could
not survive unless backed up by power. As a mere article of faith, a mere
opinion, it was meaningless. If there was power anywhere now, it was not
with the Council but with the Pope, however objectionable his personal
character may have been. To work for unity does not mean to believe in
it and do nothing. It has to be fought for in the real world, with the world's
own methods, that is, politically. Cusanus did just that. His actions were
widely interpreted as a betrayal of his ideal conception of the Church,
but in shifting his position on this particular question he remained faithful
to his primary objective of unity. As he saw it, this now required a new
orientation on the plane of reality.
a. His arguments: (1) Is the Pope above the Council or is the Council
above the Pope? —The question presupposes unanimity regarding Church
organization. In the discussions of that time no one contested the principle
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 231
of the One Church, unique and infallible, not to mention the theological
status of God or Christ or the Gospels, or the dogma of the Church as the
mystic body of Christ.
Both Pope and Council possess their high and inviolable significance.
Both are in their temporal reality represented by persons whose "spirit"
must have qualities that meet the requirements of the institution.
The Pope must not fail to carry out his duties as Vicar of Christ, as
interpreted by the decisions of his predecessors and the early Church
councils whose decrees are binding upon him. The councils, under the
guidance of the Holy Spirit, must express unanimously the inner disposi-
tions of their members, and their decrees, moreover, must be universal,
must represent the entire Church.
But what is to be done when one of the two chief authorities —or the men
who embody authority — fails to act in accordance with the principles
stated above? Can Pope? Can the Pope dissolve
the Council depose the
the Council? Who is which of them is right? There exists no
to decide
authority superior to both, no supreme court of judgment, to which
appeal can be made in the case of conflict between Pope and Council.
The idea of the One Church, in which Pope and Council are interrelated
parts of a single whole, loses its force when a state of corruption prevails
in the body of the Church. In the event of conflict a judge is needed to
settle it. But his verdict can be enforced only if Pope or Council is clearly
question of power and political adroitness; which party will gain the sup-
port of princes and governments? The weaker "the spirit," the more
decisive becomes the role of brute force. And this is what happened at that
time.
—
(2) The contradictory formulations. From the outset Cusanus looked
upon Pope and Council as the highest authority within the One Church.
He regarded them as equally indispensable. But faced with actual situations,
he arrived at contradictory formulations.
the head of the ecclesiastical hierarchy (Posch, 165 ff., report on the letter
The most significant statements are quoted by Posch from the records
of the imperial diets. Cusanus now grants the Pope constitutional rights
he had formerly denied him, and develops this new idea in great detail.
The Pope, for example, has the right to grant prebends (that is, he is not
bound to respect the choice of the local chapters). And a council represent-
ing all of Christendom save the Pope would not be a council.
But this is the crucial point: The question of how the Church is to
proceed against a bad Pope should not even be discussed; to do so would
be disrespectful and unedifying. At a diet in Frankfurt he said: "The
Council can do nothing about a fallible Pope" (Posch, 170). He does not
deny that the Pope, like any other man, may be fallible (deviabilis), but
"We are to asume that he is less fallible than other men" (Kallen, 81).
The Pope holds his powers directly from Christ, whereas the powers of
the Council derive from the Pope. The Council without the Pope is like a
tree without leaves. It would be absurd to maintain that the power of
individual leaders in the Church can equal that of the Supreme Pontiff.
He rules absolutely. To argue that he both rules and obeys would be
absurd. Within the Church each separate authority is valid only when it is
subordinated to the single supreme authority.
(3) An example: the argument involving the role of Peter. No man —
who does not worship at the throne of Peter is a believer; such a man
stands outside the unity of the Church (De cone, cath., I, 14; Basel edition,
p. 685). There is only one cathedra of St. Peter. All of St. Peter's successors
to the throne have the same rights as he. Just as Peter was prince among
the Apostles, so the Bishop of Rome is prince among the bishops (De cone,
cath., 1, 15).
Yet, in another passage of the same work, these emphatic statements on
the position of the Pope are seemingly retracted by a number of finely drawn
symbolic distinctions concerning the role of St. Peter. Their eflect is to
limit the extent of papal power. The rock of the Church is Christ. Just as
Christ is the truth and the rock (petra) is a figure or symbol (figura sive
significatio) of Christ, so the Church is the rock of Christ and Peter is a
figure or symbol of the Church. Or again: Just as Christ is the truth and
the rock His figure and symbol, so the rock of the Church is the truth
and Peter is a figure and symbol of the truth. This shows clearly that
NICHOLAS OF CU S A 233
the Church is above Peter, just as Christ is above the Church (De cone.
cath.. II, 18; Basel edition, 739).
(5) Free elections and the majority. —A universal council can be con-
vened only through elections. All lawful authority is based on free election
(De cone, cath., II, 19; Basel edition, p. 687).
the Council can overrule the Pope, because it is a more reliable and less
fallible repraesentatio (representation, manifestation, presence) of the
Church (De cone, cath., II, 18; Basel edition, p. 687). But later Cusanus
condemns the majority principle (holding that the minority at the Council,
to which he himself belonged, represented the truth). Where the unity
of the Church is at stake, he says, mathematics has no bearing. Only the
practical consequences of a course of action decided upon by the ballot can
determine whether it furthers the cause of unity. For example: from the
standpoint of the Council for uniting the Latin and Greek Churches,
planned in opposition to the Council of Basel, the Council of Basel was a
mere incident without universal significance.
of discursive reason, make all arguments futile. In the end everyone does
what he wanted to do in the first place, putting forward arguments as a
smoke screen. When this point is reached, all the parties to the dispute
work inadvertently toward their own destruction.
Interpretations derived from thinking in ciphers are by nature dialectical
234 The Original Thinners
in the sense that opposites are combined to form a unity, so that one
opposite tilts over into the other and opinions change while the underlying
will to unity remains unchanged. The shift of opinions becomes sophistical
when it serves the will to power, which is not itself dialectical. It can avoid
sophistry only if it remains within the bounds of some substantial spiritual
whole.
It does not seem likely that Cusanus was aware of the dialectical
relativity of the various positions he maintained theoretically. That he had
a dim intimation along these lines may be attested by his use of expressions
like "the basis of this consideration" (jund amentum huius considerationis,
Basel edition, p. 687).
Only with meaningful, not sophistical dialectics, rooted in a sense of the
whole, could Cusanus have served both the conciliar and the papal party
without dishonesty. Actually his idea of unity— which, being metaphysical,
is adequately grounded only in the coincidentia oppositorum —remains un-
changed. Unity has to be realized unconditionally, though just how depends
on the situation. Thus there is nothing to show that Cusanus was unfaithful
to his fundamental goal when he shifted allegiance. His faith remained
the same; he merely altered his means of attaining it in finite reality.
(2) Source and logic. —The source of faith and of a will grounded in it
cannot be rationally justified. The doctrine is not the faith itself, but only
one manifestation of it.
The force of logic is compelling only to the extent that it avails itself
(4) Cusanus touches upon the problems of truth and freedom but does
—
not grasp them. Because Cusanus believed the truth he possessed through
revelation and speculative thinking to be the voice of God in the world,
he was unaware of this great problem: Since only the individual can gain
—
insight into truth, freedom, and peace not an isolated individual, but
—
only one who shares his thinking with others how can the best individuals
concerned with community welfare gain the support of the many? How
can the co-operation of the best and the many produce not merely external
decisions, but rather express the inner moral and political reality of the
community? In discussing the conciliar controversy, he touches upon the
questions of institutional freedom and of the way in which the co-operation
of all the faithful is to be attained, but these problems are never brought to
full awareness.
(5) Cusanus did not disguise the shift in his allegiance, but obscured the
fundamental human situation. After Cusanus' defection, his adversaries in
the Council criticized him for his inconsistency, and rightly so.
Did Cusanus try to conceal the fact that he had turned his back on his
236 The Original Thinners
earlier position? Did he refuse to admit that his opinions had undergone
a radical change ? Did he dodge the issue ? I believe that his manner of think-
ing prevented him from attaining clarity on this score. This was why, on the
one hand, he felt that he had not contradicted himself with respect to the
inner disposition of his faith, and why, on the other hand, he did not take
seriously the contradictions that are so clearly evident when his statements
are considered from a rational point of view.
Logically unclear statements as to the relations between Pope and Council
occur both before and after his shift of allegiance. In the course of his
hesitations, he occasionally encompasses the two opposites, but then he also
speaks as an extreme advocate of each position.
He never grasped clearly the dialectical character of his approach to
practical problems. The reason for this (we shall discuss it in greater detail
later) seems to be that his metaphysics postulates a harmony realizable in
the world. He thus loses sight of the fundamental situation of our existence
in the world.
2. Brixen
astrous to the province of South Tyrol. He was opposed by the clergy who
had been bullied into accepting him, by the monastic institutions (especially
one convent under an energetic abbess) which he tried to reform, and by
the Archduke Sigismund of Austria from whom Cusanus tried to regain
certain prerogatives ofwhich the Church had been deprived. His miserly
financial policy was unpopular. He gained the support of a number of
peasants and of some enemies of the Habsburgs, such as the Swiss who —
made use of him to the same extent as he tried to make use of them. In
the struggle he applied the harshest measures, including excommunication.
He enforced a ban on foreign trade, so that the province lost the income it
had derived from commerce between Venice and the north. With the loss
of prosperity political and moral standards declined. Violence and contempt
for the Church increased (Jaeger, I, 4). Cusanus himself was absent for
long periods; at first his duties as him traveling in
papal legate kept
Germany, and his last years Rome.
were spent in
When he died, the new Pope and the Emperor quickly settled the
conflict. The
claims Cusanus had fought so stubbornly to have recognized
were abandoned. A partisan of Cusanus, who realized what a great blow
this was to the prestige of the Church, wrote: "Ah, if only they had never
begun this dispute that has come to so shocking an end" (Jaeger, II, 432).
During the years in Austria, Cusanus was often exposed to personal
danger. In 1457 he went to Innsbruck to negotiate with the Archduke
N1CH O LAS OF CU SA 237
(Koch, 63 ft".; Mcuthen, 15) and on his way back he saw some armed men.
On the basis of rumors he publicly accused the Archduke of plotting to
ambush and kill him. Koch, who studied all the relevant documents,
wonders whether the Cardinal was not more frightened than the situation
called for, and suspects that he exploited it for all it was worth. Koch
believes that the incident was deliberately staged to intimidate the unpopular
foreigner and severe reformer. Cusanus tells us, however, that he escaped
only with God's help. The castle of Buchenstein on the southern boundary
of the diocese seemed to provide him with some measure of safety. He
resided there for a year, and in September 1458 moved to Rome.
From there he carried on his struggle against the Archduke. He returned
to his diocese in 1460, taking every precaution to protect his life. The
journey was anything but a success. When the Archduke laid siege to the
castle of Bruneck, Cusanus capitulated. He signed an agreement
giving
in on all points at issue, and when the Curia protested, he defended the
Archduke. But once back on Italian territory, he declared that he had
been made to sign the agreement under duress. The episode marked the
lowest point in his career; both materially and spiritually it was a defeat.
For he was well aware of how badly he had behaved. In a letter to the Bishop
of Eichstatt, dated June 11, 1460, he writes: "I had hoped to end my days
with a glorious death in the cause of justice, but I was not worthy of that
honor" (Jaeger, II, 62). A short time later he said (De ludo globi):
A Christian is a man who puts the honor of Christ above his own life. The
test is how he stands up to persecution. "Christ lives in him, he himself
does not live." A Christian despises this world and this life. "It is a simple
matter for one who has the true faith. But it is impossible . . . for a non-
believer." Are we to conclude that Cusanus broke down when put to the
test because he did not truly believe, but only believed in faith —that he
failed at the crucial moment ?
Yet same letter he goes on to say: "I did not wish I had not
in the
suffered what happened to me, I was glad of my suffering. Moreover, . . .
Alms for the poor, not the wealth of the bishops, are what ought to be
increased. Therefore, I rejoice in my misfortune, because it has enriched
my knowledge. ... At the time I did not see my error, but I see it now,
for I was punished for it. . . . This is what I thought, to comfort myself
and to recover my peace of mind, and we can congratulate each other that
God has been willing to show us our imperfections by sending us such
little trials" (Jaeger, II, 62).
There are also glimpses of Cusanus* thoughts about himself in his letters
addressed a few years earlier to his friend the Abbot of Tegernsee: "If
only I might hope for some results, I would not be deterred by the work,
for after all there is no peace anywhere in this world; but to spend oneself
238 The Original Thinners
for nothing at all is absurd. ... I bear the difficulties with patience, sooner
or later I shall surmount them with God's help" (1458). A year later: "It is
impossible for me to concentrate and get on with it [the composition of the
work]. If I am not given more freedom, I shall be lost . .
."
(1455).
Do not such reflections sound like those of a man who is uncertain of
his goal and, instead of striving to become transparent to himself, falls
back on traditional ideas ?
disarms' failure on both the material and the spiritual plane teaches us
to see moreclearly how difficult the task of the truth is, what tremendous
obstacles must be surmounted by those engaged in it. Quite possibly no
one has ever surmounted them. Socrates and Jesus came closest. But we
also learn that all evil springs from lack of sufficient truthfulness.
When Piccolomini became Pope, his main goal was to launch a crusade
against Turks. Cusanus saw that the project was unfeasible and
the
repeatedly warned the Pope against vain hopes. He advised, for example,
against convoking a congress of princes at Mantua, predicting that not even
the Emperor would attend. And indeed, the congress proved a humiliating
failure for the Pope.
A crusade could have been successful only had there been political peace
West and if the Church had been reformed and unified. An internally
in the
united West conscious of its common danger would have been strong
enough to carry out such a crusade. Cusanus saw clearly how unrealistic the
project was because he knew that Europe was divided. Faithful to his
principles,he nonetheless served the Pope obediently in his hopeless cause.
He accompanied him to Mantua and conducted himself thereafter as though
he shared the Pope's views about the crusade.
The humanist Pope dreamed his irresponsible dream. As he lay dying in
Ancona on the Adriatic coast, a few Venetian ships he had long been
awaiting suddenly appeared in the harbor. With he reflected:
tragic irony
Formerly I had crusaders but no fleet, now I have a fleet but no crusaders.
It had been Cusanus' responsibility to look after the penniless adventurers
who rallied to the Pope's banner, to keep them out of trouble and prevent
them from pillaging the countryside. A few days before Pius II, Cusanus
himself died, quietly and undramatically, in Todi, while on his way to
join the Pope.
5. Ecclesiastical benefices
—
Cusanus lived on revenues from benefices as was perfectly normal for a
Church dignitary. As early as 1427 (when he was twenty-six years old)
he obtained a dispensation granting him the right to hold several mutually
exclusive benefices. During the 1430s he was given more benefices (Munster-
240 The Original Thinners
maifeld, St. Martin in Worms) When . he took over a richly endowed arch-
deaconry in Liege, the local clergy found fault with him for being unable to
administer the office himself.
An exchange of with Jacob von Sirck, Archbishop of Trier (1453),
letters
deals with a benefice which Cusanus had verbally promised to turn over to
the Archbishop. He wished nevertheless to keep it for himself, and his
attitude in the matter is ambiguous. To Sirck: "I will be giving up the
archdeaconry one of these years." On the same day, to a friend in Rome:
"I have no intention of rushing my resignation." Although he had promised
to pass on the benefice to Sirck, he wrote to Rome that he would submit
his resignation to the Pope —
which meant that another candidate would be
appointed. When Sirck learned of this, he was indignant. And actually
Cusanus held on to all his benefices until he died. He gives several reasons
why he could not surrender them. The most important was the home for
the aged he founded at Cues: "What God hath given should go to the
poor" (Koch).
Despite his influential position in the Curia (which rested solely on his
friendship with Pius II), Cusanus never amassed a personal fortune. But
in acquiring his comparatively modest benefices, he showed himself at
times to be a scheming realist, inconstant, and occasionally untrustworthy.
The consequences of his Christian philosophizing did not reach into these
domains.
as elsewhere. In the end the Renaissance Popes, who carried this kind of
individualism to extremes, discredited the Church completely, though they
helped to produce an unprecedented flowering in the arts. Ruthless repre-
sentatives of territorial and national particularism reduced the office
of Emperor to a purely decorative function. The Emperor enjoyed a
measure of authority only in the country he ruled by hereditary right;
otherwise he was scarcely more than a figurehead. Nevertheless those who
were eligible aspired to the title, for it retained a certain traditional prestige
and various prerogatives that could be exploited. Within the Church there
were conflicts, both major and minor —occasioned
by the conciliar move-
ment, the Hussites, and contending and secular claims. In
ecclesiastical
Rome there were rivalries between the cardinals, and intrigues of French,
Italian, and Spanish factions. The Papal State was involved in conflicts
with many city states and tyrants, and problems of world-wide importance
were interwoven with local Italian interests. Particular interests might join
in common cause or press their claims separately, depending on the situation
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 241
the thick of all this complicated activity, which historians find so pictur-
esque.
seriously than the humanists, Thomas More was far superior to him in his
—
conduct of life. Cusanus lacked the consuming seriousness of faith. He
lacked the courage of his convictions, the courage of the truly responsible
statesman. He was a man of half-measures, too easily satisfied. No doubt
it was quite an accomplishment for a boy from a village on the Moselle
to become a cardinal and the vicar general in Rome. But, except for
persuading the neutral Germans to support Pope Eugenius, he failed in
all his undertakings, and brilliant representative of the Church that he
to his Church, to his faith, to his vision of the world order. He was not
motivated by a will to communication, such as strives for the peaceful co-
was that of a
existence of fundamentally different faiths. Rather, his faith
doctrinaire Churchman. In pronouncing the words "We Christians," he
was so sure of his cause and of himself that he was incapable of active
tolerance. He had no sympathetic understanding of other religions, no
readiness to recognize that they are fully entitled to their different rituals
and customs, whose importance he minimized. He failed to see that other
faiths may be just as wholehearted, true, meaningful, and comprehensive
as his own. For all his concessions, he naively assumed and asserted the
absolute truth of Christianity in the specific form of his own Church. To
achieve peace he did not resort to communication but, in the last analysis,
to violence.
To carry out his reforms he needed the support of the princes, a secular
power at the disposal of the Church. He appealed to them in vain; they
refused to help him. Again, it was naive of him to take for granted that the
secular princes would serve his (and the Church's) will to power. Clearly,
he did not rely solely on the freedom of faith and the word, on the power
of philosophical arguments.
In actual fact Cusanus took the path of compulsion. But he had no power.
We shudder to think what his life and character would have been had he
possessedpower and made use of it!
As a philosopher Cusanus was more understanding, more profound, and
more communicative than he could ever be in his practical activities. In his
bestworks he often moves us deeply by his magnificent open-mindedness
and the vast range of his vision. The obtuseness of his political practice is
something else again. Was he lacking in the honesty that is inseparable
from the unremitting will to understand oneself? Was he incapable of
seeing how incompatible his philosophy was with his ecclesiastical practice?
(3) Down to the last year of his life, as some of the finest and most mature
of his minor works show, he meditated with undiminished energy. But
there was no point of contact between his philosophical meditation and
his politics. He conceived of philosophy as the one and only possible
happiness in the world. It was an accompaniment to his practical activi-
ties but did not influence them. The hours and days he was able to devote
into which the Church had fallen gave rise to demands for internal reform
whose need no one contested. The impotence of the Empire, the arbitrary
power of the German princes, of the city tyrants in Italy, and of the King of
France had undermined all secular authority. Each of these potentates was
determined to assert himself in his own way and to rely on himself alone.
Since the rediscovery of Cusanus (in the nineteenth century) he has
been looked upon as a transitional figure between the Middle Ages and the
modern era— sometimes as the last great medieval thinker and sometimes
244 The Original Thinners
as the founder of the modern era. To Cusanus himself the notion of the
Middle Ages was entirely unknown. He was not conscious of living in a
transitional age, at the dawn of the modern era. It was only the genera-
tion after him that became aware of its novelty and referred to the Middle
Ages as a thing of the past.
We may Cusanus a last culminating point of the Christian eccle-
see in
siastical faith,which was still Catholic and constitutive of the unity of the
West, illumined with the clarity of philosophical understanding for one
last time, before "modernism" made its appearance on the stage of history.
He never doubted that he was at home in eternity; in the teeth of all evidence
he asserted the essential unity of life in its plurality, and was confident that
the existing organic whole would survive. He perceived the language of
God everywhere in the world, incorporated within one all-encompassing
Church. The vision with which he sought to temper and surmount the
chaos of his age was one of the noblest concord, uniting a universal authority
which understands and educates all men with sublime freedom under God's
guidance.
No less impressive, however, is the other, opposite aspect of Cusanus.
Measured by the spiritual coherence and infinite richness of Thomas
Aquinas, Cusanus' thinking marks a decline. He lived with a consciousness
of the whole, but no longer made use of it to create an all-embracing system.
We have seen that, although he did not take the path of modern science,
he contributed to the intellectual climate which heralded the advent of
modern science (and philosophy), especially by his conception of the mind
as creative activity. He sensed that mathematics could be an important tool
of investigation, that the world is infinite, that individual beings are the
true reality — all insights that foreshadowed the science to come. His spec-
ulative ideas are harbingers of subsequent modern philosophizing (Bruno,
Leibniz, Hamann, Schelling).
To Cusanus, the two aspects of his intellectual world (as we think of
it today) —the medieval —
and the modern were not incompatible. Whatever
tendencies to "modern" aggressiveness and destructiveness might be
detected in his thinking are still entirely overshadowed by his faith, which
is safely wrapped in official Christian doctrine. True, his passion for finding
the truth at the source by independent inquiry and his discovery of the
"layman" point to a later anti-authoritarian, revolutionary element. But
none of his ideas has explosive force.
The view that Cusanus represents a transitional figure between the
Middle Ages and the modern era does not strike me as very fruitful. It is
in fact misleading if the spiritual essence of this great metaphysician is taken
to reflect the inner conflict of his epoch. Such a view would imply that
Cusanus, as the last medieval thinker, was engulfed in contradictory currents
which he neither understood nor tried to surmount, and that as the first
modern thinker he was buried under the ruins of the medieval tradition.
I
N 1 CH O LAS F CU SA 245
Both these pictures are false and obscure Cusanus' originality. It is not
true that the duality of his nature resulted from the transitional character
of his epoch.
The truth is that his thinking displays features that can be met with in
2. On historical interpretation
Historical views of the course of things as a whole are often plausible but
never compelling. The idea of a historical necessity, ascertainable by men,
is a fallacy that deprives historical thinking of its meaning: "trends" are
never inevitable. The unexpected, the "leap," "the miracle" of the fresh
start are essential characteristics of knowable history, within which particu-
lar chains of causal necessity and meaningful relationships which are
always susceptible of different interpretations play a part.
The idea of absolute historical (the content of which can
necessity
never be known) is by man's authentic possibilities. By
contradicted
virtue of his faith and his reason he can fight against the allegedly in-
evitable, against ideas intended to make him follow a path determined in
advance. Those who are caught up in such ideas try to persuade him that
he has no alternative. Some enthusiastically applaud history; others resign
themselves to its absurd "necessity"; both views are paralyzing. Authentic
men are those who take risks in their thinking or their actions, those who,
far from being "shown up," are on the contrary transfigured by failure, who,
perhaps by their very failure, exert a real influence on the future of mankind.
When philosophers are explained in terms of their epoch or national
origin, this done under the tacit assumption (which, today, under the
is
the shoals of pure historicism in dealing with the greatest —Plato, Spinoza,
Kant— than in approaching philosophers who fall short of classical clarity
and simplicity in their language, thinking, or conduct of life. But even
these, if they are in any sense philosophically significant, cannot be treated
as mere by-products of history. To take a purely historical view of
Cusanus would be to relegate him once again to oblivion, to lose sight
of what he really was and thought. Our task is to let him speak for himself.
Like all important philosophers, Cusanus is neither old nor new, neither
medieval nor modern. Living in time, he is timeless in spirit, one of those
who, clad in the raiment of their day and nation, meet as equals over the
millennia to discuss the destiny of man.
So long as we remain aware of their limited significance, we can formulate
historically meaningful comparisons without deluding ourselves. They
serve merely as ideal types, intellectual constructions that never do full
justice to reality. Such constructions combine particular insights with over-
all metaphorical views. With their help we, inspired by our own tendencies,
our own complaints and accusations, and our own hopes, ask questions of
history. Let us attempt to formulate a few such questions.
a. The —
For all practical purposes, Cusanus'
decision at the Council of Basel.
choice was between corruption through conciliar rule and corruption
through papal rule. Either way he was bound to fail, whether he opted for
the idea of unity or for that of internal reform.
Had
he decided to go along with the conciliar movement, however, his
failure would have reflected personal impotence in a corrupt world. He
might have become a monk, devoted himself entirely to philosophy and
meditation, composed works revealing the corruption of the conciliar,
papal, and governmental powers, and thereby run the risk of being branded
a heretic and incurring martyrdom. Then, with his intellectual clarity he
would have disclosed the seemingly inevitable evil and proclaimed the
truth of the original Biblical faith with all its historical consequences. He
would have become a beacon to all thoughtful men and have helped to
awaken moral and religious impulses.
But because he decided in favor of the papacy his failure was associated
with a prominent position in a corrupt world. He became powerful amid
the confusion and blundering of the epoch, but was powerless to realize the
truth and the good. A man of vast knowledge, but not a thinker striving
for concrete clarity at any cost, he became unwittingly "coresponsible" for
what actually happened.
He was not in the least aware of this either-or. Our formulation implies
no accusation. But it characterizes Cusanus in his historical situation.
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 247
one of serene piety and inspiring faith. The spirit of the Catholic Church
was still, to some extent, truly universal.
The Reformation came as a storm because the reforms so long clamored
forand fitfully attempted for more than a century had all failed. But the
Reformation itself led into new blind alleys; it curtailed and finally did
away with the freedom that had prevailed in the medieval world. The
unleashed forces spent themselves in religious wars between the various
sects, and Catholicism ceased to be anything more than a sect. A new and
not that of rectilinear progress toward an ever better future, but the idea
of a steady, ever renewed ascent to the ideal. What he has in mind is not
I
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 249
the modus operandi of such an ascension, but the idea of the whole to
which we come ever closer by virtue of our spiritual essence.
Shallow rationalism loses sight of the intellect by raising discursive reason
an absolute and by exalting sensory experience. It believes in
to the level of
progress, rejects speculative philosophy along with theology, and allows the
roots of personality to become stunted. Cusanus was the very opposite of
all this.
c. The "crisis" since Cusanus: (1) From Cusanus to our own day. —
Cusanus can seem modern because he thought at a time of progressive
moral and political decline (a time like our own), and because the purpose
of his thinking was to check this decline. His insights lacked the power to
penetrate the deceptions of his time. His thinking could not become real in
the hearts and minds of his contemporaries. He followed paths that did
not lead to the centuries succeeding his own.
Protestantism took hold of the people with a violence long unknown in
religious matters. The Catholic world exploded in a series of schisms. The
Empire, meanwhile, gave way to an aggregate of regional absolutisms.
A new, seemingly stabilized European world emerged from the chaos.
Just as the medieval order attained a seeming perfection in the twelfth and
thirteenth centuries, so in the seventeenth century a European order at-
tained its apogee, after which it too was destroyed. Once again, in the nine-
teenth century, the semblance of a liberal order came into being despite the
Revolution, and its contemporary situation,
collapse in turn has produced the
no longer produce a European
a state of affairs which, in theory at least, can
but only a world order. In each historical instance, seeming perfection and
stability concealed the seeds of self-destruction, brought about by its own
shortcomings.
The age of Cusanus may major spiritual crisis of
appear as the first
was a first upsurging of the flood that has repeatedly risen and threatened
to overwhelm us, though each time in a different way. Since Cusanus
much the same situation has occurred several times. Light-mindedness and
half-measures have led to anarchy, the reaction to which was violence
justified in terms of fanaticism. By recourse to violence the state (with
the help of the Church
some similar institutionalization of doctrine,
or
Marxism being the latest) managed for a time to enforce an absolute order.
In the end, the revolution of the Enlightenment, which was rooted in
reason, engendered political revolution and its reign of terror justified by a
degenerated discursive reason.
Later, liberalism gave rise to a more sophisticated totalitarian rule. Our
picture of the course of things is that of a whirlpool which changes shape
from time to time, but engenders no lasting order.
Until now the ineradicable forces of darkness have been repeatedly
victorious in the world. They have triumphed over reason, humanity, and
freedom, over all such "weakness," which they despise.
(2) The crisis generated by the sciences. —Cusanus has no place in the
history of modern science, nor did he correctly understand its spirit; at
the same time, his philosophy is relevant to the scientific world which has
developed since his epoch.
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 251
The attitude toward life characteristic of the modern world was shaped
by a science and a philosophy independent of revealed faith. This world
has generated evils against which it has carried on titanic struggles. The
human spirit became confused when it lost its existential roots, science
became meaningless when it lost sight of its goal, philosophy ceased to be
serious when it conceived of itself as a science and behaved accordingly.
Freedom turned to anarchy and irresponsibility, liberal-mindedness into
doctrinaire liberalism, the intellect into mere discursive reason. This vast
fragmentation has led to radical reversals that ostensibly re-established an
order: as formerly it led to absolutism, so in our time it has led to total
domination.
Freedom has been replaced by command and obedience. Like the mon-
arch's under absolutism, so the Leader's under totalitarianism is
will
recognized as the supreme law, whether or not it happens to be expressed
in laws. The people have been freed from freedom. All, those who command
as well as those who obey, are turned into slaves. The road to such a con-
dition is paved with illiberal thinking and violent conduct in the little
things of everyday life. Neither those who command nor those who obey
are amenable to reason. They break off human communication, ceasing
Anyone who is willing to think can free himself from such conceptions.
All he needs to do is remove the scales of falsely self-evident truths from
his mind's eye. It cannot be accomplished in the manner of a Baron von
Munchhausen swamp by his own pigtail, but
pulling himself out of the
in communication with other thinking people, who can achieve in common
and in freedom what an individual cannot achieve for himself alone. This
is not a Utopian idea. The alternative is to despair of humanity.
an end in itself, or when science asserts that it leads us to true faith, true
art, true poetry, true happiness, true Being.
Authentic science, which is aware of its limits and does not transgress
them, does not leave the world disenchanted. It clears the way for new
ciphers and does not destroy the old ones when it shows that they fail to
provide us with tangible, real knowledge; it does not destroy the miracle
which beyond everything we call "meaning."
lies
To pure science, things are no more than what we know of them finite, —
fragmentary phenomena. We can never know things as an all-encompassing
whole embracing all phenomena. To the questions What is this whole? —
What is the meaning of the world? or What do the things we know
signify? —science gives no answer. The answers are given in ciphers.
These are understood at the level of human Existenz, the "meaning" of
which transcends all meaning.
Transcendence is not encountered by science, but can be apprehended in
the meaning of the ciphers. The ciphers do not exist in themselves, but for
Existenz, just as the objects of science have no universally valid existence
in themselves, but only as phenomena for consciousness as such.
In Cusanus there is no trace of the modern "disenchantment" of the
world. Following him in his speculations, we enter a world where all
and a purer science have become possible, and a purer philosophy as well.
To be sure, "the crisis in the sciences" signifies that the process of dis-
enchantment with the world has become complete within the scientific
framework itself. But complete disenchantment, including the rejection
of all unproven metaphysical assumptions, such as the absolute validity of
causality, is necessary to clear the way, so that a further domain long —
—
obscured by scientific superstition can at last be experienced and eluci-
dated: the domain where all things and the existence of science itself become
ciphers. At this point, however, universal validity ceases, though it does
not necessarily follow that we must surrender to ever-changing subjective
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 253
fantasies. Here begins a struggle of powers, which no man can ever survey
as a whole.
It is in this domain that Cusanus is situated with his magnificent cipher
world. But because he himself was unaware of this, he did not achieve
complete philosophical freedom.
4. Lack of influence
For all the brilliance of his career, Cusanus remained a secondary figure
in the history of his times. Highly respected for his superior mind, he
had no real power even as a prince of the Church, because he was not
sufficiently wealthy. Toward the end of his life he exerted a certain influence
as favored adviser to Pope Pius II, an old friend.
Nor, apart from a few monks, did his philosophical ideas exert any
influence. As we have seen, Cusanus was not a precursor of such Western
developments as the Reformation, the Counter-Reformation, absolute mon-
archy, the Enlightenment, and modern science. Nor is he cited by those
who at an early date chose the path of human reason and freedom (certain
humanists, Italian humanist heretics, the great philosophers beginning with
Spinoza). Only one of the great figures remembered him
(we need at all
not count Faber Stapulensis and Bovillus). The famous eulogy by Giordano
Bruno (in his speech at Wittenberg) stands alone across the ages: "Where
is there to be found a man comparable to that native of Cusa, who was the
less accessible the greater he was? If his priestly robe had not now and
then veiled his genius, I would go so far as to say that he was not the equal
of, but far greater a figure than, Pythagoras." Through Bruno's writings,
Cusanus' ideas became known to others who had no direct knowledge of
him —Leibniz, Hamann, Schelling. Probably the first to rediscover him
was Schlegel, though nobody paid attention at the time. Why was Cusanus
forgotten for so long ?
It would be rash to say that metaphysical speculation as such cannot
influence the multitude. Speculative thought does exert a powerful influence
when it is originally embodied in a way of life (as in the case of the
Buddhists), or when it constitutes a real cultural world (as in the case of
the Roman Stoics), or when it is expressed in a religious way of life (as in
the case of Christianity). It is through such practice that speculative thought
gains in influence.
On the other hand, when speculative thought serves only to procure
aesthetic gratification, when it
is pursued as a mere hobby or avocation, it
a kind of liberation, it is not a real liberation because it does not put its
appropriate the truth of their insights without falling into their historically
conditioned errors.
INTRODUCTION
knew that speculative truth can be elucidated only in the form of contra-
diction.
False contradictions arise only when ideas that are paradoxical from
the standpoint of discursive reason, though meaningful from that of the
intellect, are perverted into rational concepts or imaginary physical realities.
c. Cusanus did not believe that the negations of "negative theology" mark
a terminal point of thinking, beyond which we are left in a vacuum. On
reaching the point where he was confronted with a choice between mysti-
cism (in the sense of an experience from which the world and the self
are absent, perhaps infinitely meaningful but completely incommunicable)
and the world as a reality without transcendence, Cusanus rejects both
alternatives, and embarks upon the way of speculation, which is the medium
of lucid human Existenz in the world.
from mankind by an unbridgeable gulf: the infinite and the finite are
incommensurable, and God is unknowable. But at the same time God is
present in the world He created. He can be known by human beings, and
all things reflect His essence, for God is in all things. God is completely
separated from the world, yet God is in the world the contradiction is —
stated too unmistakably to be overlooked. Our human limitations being
what they are, we cannot avoid falling into this contradiction, but we can
be aware that we are doing so. When we reach this point, the contradictory
I
N ICHOLAS OF CU SA 257
terms cancel each other out, and the intellect is free to go on in pursuit of
speculative insights which transcend this form of objectivity.
seem to result from shifts in linguistic usage (they are not real contradictions
and their clarification merely requires a certain effort); and (3) false con-
tradictions, which demand correction, have nothing to do with the specu-
lative method, and occur on the rational plane purely as a result of
negligence (they lead to error and obstruct the course of the meditations).
One defect in Cusanus' philosophizing is that he does not distinguish
between contradiction and such related concepts as difference, polarity,
and opposition. Nor does he put his thinking to test categorially and system-
atically (we have to go to Hegel to gain clarity on this point). He
sometimes identifies opposition {oppositio) with contradiction (contradictio)
9
The philosophical limits disclosed in Cusanus life,
times seven or forty-nine years; the fiftieth year is the Sahbath that com-
pletes the laborious cycle). Jesus was twelve years old when He appeared
in the Temple: these twelve years correspond to the first six hundred years
of our era, down epoch of Gregory the Great. For the next seventeen
to the
The Passion of Christ will be repeated. The Church will seem to have be-
come extinct. The holy apostles will desert it and flee. There will be no
successor to St. Peter upon the throne.
But this will not be the end. Holy men will gather their strength and
repent, because they will see the Church rising anew, in greater brilliance
than ever before. Peter will shed bitter tears at having fled, and so will
the other apostles, the bishops, and the priests. Gloriously resurrected, the
Church will calmly envisage eternal peace. But the consummation will not
come at once. First the Church, the bride of Christ, must become worthy
of her bridegroom, cast off her blemishes. Then Christ will come to judge
the living and the dead, and to destroy the world by fire. He will take the
Him in all His Glory, so that she may rule with Him for all eternity.
bride to
This "Resurrection" will coincide with the thirty-fourth Jubilee corre- —
sponding to the Resurrection of Christ —that is, it will come after 1700
and before 1734.
This is how Cusanus interprets the present and foretells the future.
Characteristically, he calls such interpretation "conjecture." For, he says, we
should refrain from "curious investigation of the future," if only because
almost all who have so far tried to predict the course of future events have
been mistaken, even the Fathers of the Church, whose holiness of life and
profound learning we lack entirely. And yet such thinking is not repre-
260 The Original Thinners
hensible. Although the decrees of God remain hidden even to the wisest
men, "He, in His great kindness, permits us, worms that we are, to make
conjectures about things He alone knows." Only God sees all things
from outside time. Only He can determine the moments of time. In such
traditional schemata of history Cusanus sees catastrophe ahead; but it is
followed by apotheosis.
So general a characterization of the epoch may seem to us mere trifling,
but his inner attitude toward contemporary events was serious. In a letter
to Jacob von Sirck, dated October 1453, he had the following to say of the
Turkish peril after the conquest of Constantinople: "I fear greatly that
this violence may defeat us, for I see no possible uniting in resistance. I
believe that we must address ourselves to God alone, though He will not
hear us sinners." What does he mean? His insight into the situation does
not result in an urgent appeal for action. He speaks in general terms of
sinners, not of the need to contemporary sins, which
understand very specific
must be surmounted if men are to unite against a deadly peril. The only
—
action he recommends is prayer though he himself judges it to be ineffec-
tual under the circumstance. A keen appreciatioon of impending disaster
simmers down into passivity.
sap., 15).
comforted as Christ was and be filled with joy, victorious over the death of
the body and the sufferings you have taken on yourself."
But what if the experience is not merely mental, but actual? We must
not forget how Cusanus conducted himself when his life was threatened.
Did Cusanus even remotely imitate Christ? Did he not, rather, evade the
concrete situation by taking refuge in a metaphysical magnificence un-
justified by his own existential experience?
What does mean "to be victorious over
it death"? We have found the
following three ideas in the texts just referred to: The first is impersonal,
a vision of nature, a cipher of the eternity of Being; it expresses an attitude,
unmarred by transient self-interest, of serenity in the face of death. The
second idea contrasts soul and body. The body denotes everything that is
is called predestination, fate, ill fortune. "For every man has the freedom to
choose, namely, to will or not to will. He should choose the good and shun
evil. For he has within him the king and judge over these things. Because
the animals do not know all this, this power is a human attribute" (De
ludo globi)
2. Evil has no real existence. —What is evil? Cusanus gives the old
answer: Evil exists, but has no reality of itsown. "Being is good and noble
and precious. Hence everything that is has some value. Nothing can be
without having some value" (De ludo globi).
NICHOLAS OF CUSA 263
actual because if reflects Capability as such. "What does not reflect it has no
essential original being." "Futility, defectiveness, error, vice, sickness, death,
corruption, and other such things lack all the quality of being" (De apice
theoriae). In this view, which identifies misfortune, suffering, defect, and
error with evil, evil is flattened and shorn of all reality.
Ideas that assert the nonbeing of evil greatly reduce its significance, unless,
in die face of the reality of evil, they scan its abysses and ciphers and reach
out beyond all ciphers.
sinner, then, strays from Thee and departs afar off" (The Vision of God,
chapter V, op. cit.).
4. The origin of evil: chance. —
Does evil arise solely through misuse of
freedom? Cusanus sees another source which evil has in common with
all bad things, all disasters, all imperfections. None of these things comes
from God. For things derive from God their essence, their unity, their
perfection —but not their finiteness. And the origin of finiteness is chance
(contingentia). In De ludo globi, Cusanus
comes about. tells us how this
God creates all things, including things subject to otherness and change
and passing-away, yet he does not create otherness and changeability and
passing-away, as such. It is by chance that things perish, change, become
imperfect. God does not produce defectiveness, but only opportunity
(opportunitas) or possibility. Defectiveness is only one consequence of
and is added only by chance. "Evil and potential sin and death
possibility,
We have here two points of view. On the one hand, an objective analysis
of finitude which reduces all imperfections to a common denominator (and
one of these imperfections is the possibility of freely choosing evil) ; on the
other, a more subjective analysis of freedom, which is attributed exclusively
to man. When the two points of view are combined, the meaning of freedom
is lost. We ask: Is freedom possible only thanks to the imperfection of the
finite world, with chance marking the point at which evil can enter? This
would be the kind of freedom that is supposed to characterize the motions
of intra-atomic particles and that is today foolishly asserted to be the con-
dition of the possibility of human freedom.
Or does Cusanus here touch upon an idea of which he is not conscious,
does he for a moment attain an extreme point without seeing it ? This idea,
which is alien to Cusanus, can be formulated as follows: Is not finitude in-
separable from order just as infinitude is inseparable from chaos? Are both
inseparable from the truth of the being in which we find ourselves? The
concrete answers of our Existenz and the speculative answers of our meta-
physical thinking are true only if both —
finitude and order on the one hand,
—
and infinitude and chaos on the other are not lost sight of. Existential
seriousness does not deal with chaos by denying its reality.
The order of finite things must be wrested from chaos, there is continual
struggle between the two; similarly, there between
is a continual struggle
the light of existential reason and the darkness of passion which is all- and
self-destructive. The struggle may take place with no communication between
the two, each side aiming only at destruction of the other; it may take the
form of a frank exchange of views, without practical results; or finally, the
form of a life and death struggle, tempered only by awareness of a common
purpose transcending the inevitable conflict. We shall not go into all this
here, but merely note the limitations of Cusanus' thinking: When he fails
harmonious whole.
goal of eternal peace has already been achieved. In this view, knowledge is
inseparable from faith and love. The single articulated totality of Cusanus'
harmony casts its light over every one of its elements, even rationality,
even sensuous beauty, even the vital impulses. What may appear to us as
on the plane of the
transitory finite, remains for him an image of the original
and, seen with the eyes of faith and love, reflects its light. Nothing is
destructive of the truth of the whole. Here violence begins and peace
becomes impossible.
Visions of universal harmony can function as ciphers. Their beauty
appeals to us at certain moments, but soon we come to question their truth.
At all times two ciphers of the world have been current. One is expressed in
the philosophical view that the world and all things in it are governed by a
fundamental harmony; the other, in the view that the world originated in
deviltry and that its existence is a kind of fraud. Both must be rejected. They
are to be taken only as symbolic expressions or ciphers of passing experiences;
apart from this, they have no validity.
The image of a harmonious universe is a cipher; as such, it may appeal to
us because of its reassuring quality, but we must not be seduced by it. Be-
cause it gains the upper hand consistently in Cusanus, it sets limits to his
philosophy.
Harmonious to whom? Even to men driven to despair by suffering and
death, tortured, abandoned by all? Or only to a God who takes pleasure in
the hideous sport, for whom the dissonances are resolved in a whole unknown
to us, yet into which we are helplessly flung? To men given to the practice
of false humility and existential self-deception ?
3. As we have said, Cusanus takes the truth of official Christian doctrine
for granted. His faith is anything but a belief in Christ softened by in-
tellectual liberalism. It seems absolutely unreflective, childlike, imperturbable,
and this proves a barrier to the speculative movement of his reflections,
though Cusanus never seems aware of it (save perhaps occasionally in
sermons addressed to listeners whose faith is in danger). He does not
transcend the endless movement of reflection. Nor does he have any sense
of the fermenting forces which were undermining the Christian faith and
every faith —forces such as asserted themselves with fanatical savagery a
century later, in Protestantism and in the Counter-Reformation. To these
earnest believers Cusanus' faith in universal harmony must surely have
seemed superficial.
266 The Original Thinners
burden of responsibility?
Against the background of his belief in universal harmony, how are we
to account for his peculiar helplessness in practical action, for the uncer-
tainty that overwhelmed him at crucial moments despite the firmness of his
claims? He
fought for the power of the one Church rather than for the
authenticity of Existenz, and yet the potential grandeur of Existenz is ex-
pressed in his philosophical thinking.
X I CH O L A S () F C U S A 267
everyone represents a party and seeks support for it. The completely open
mind is at best a sky beneath which everyone in the world must occupy the
place he does occupy. All that reason can do for a man is to help save
him from falling entirely under the dominance of his place and party,
from losing his selfhood. The open mind does not supply us with un-
ambiguous, tangible principles. In so far as it aspires not only to understand
everything but also to penetrate to the great heart of things, it accomplishes
nothing. The strangely grandiose conception of a wholly rational man goes
hand in hand with failure in matters of practice.
Or is all this untrue? Are we not, in accusing reason of weakness, blaming
rather our own weakness, our inability really to rise to the level of reason?
The weaknesses of the rational mind are inherent in the reality of this
mind itself. They show that it is not rational enough, not mind enough.
Once it believes it has attained the truth, it settles into self-complacent
certainty instead of testing and renewing itself in the light of the resistances
and incompatibilities it encounters in practical life. When it insists on the
absolute validity of a specific point of view, it is anti-rational, it loses its
grip on reality.
To what extent all this applies to Cusanus is shown by his limitations.
—
Although his pure speculation a mode of thinking that is by nature
—
timeless makes him at times free and open, it does not keep him suffi-
ciently free and open in the flux of life. He soars to marvelous heights but
cannot remain for long in the realm where all is metaphor and enigmatic
image and even this metaphoric world is a metaphor for the state of
detachment he has achieved.
His speculation becomes impure, tainted with foreign elements. It lapses
into defense of the established Church and its dogmas, and because he
the historical character of his own faith, he cuts himself off
fails to realize
Because Cusanus was not a hero, not a martyr, not a sage, not a saint,
the failure of his reason to run the risk of total lucidity constitutes a weak-
ness. His reason failed to assert its rights against the brutality and super-
stition of his time —nor does it help us to cope with such forces as they
appear today.
Yet, for all his weaknesses, he is never base. There is genuine exaltation
in his finest flights, in his knowledge of his true home, in the enthusiasm
with which he pursues his philosophical path. how, for briefWe see
moments, he and openness,
attains to great clarity but we also see how, in
his life, he remained satisfied with the traditional dogmas. We see him
animated by good intentions in his efforts to reform the Church. He is
confident of success, and his failure does not shake his confidence but
merely puts him in a bad temper.
On the whole, Cusanus is not one of those philosophers whose greatness
is so pure that merely to think of them is gratifying.
he did not achieve the grand style of the statesman. To an ever greater
extent in the course of his life, his acts were incompatible with his ideas.
Nor were his acts those of a man wholeheartedly concerned with realizing
his goals —furthering political and moral salvation through education,
institutions, laws.
speculative vision, are we not at the same time dismayed because this
vision is not pure, because it is cluttered up with elements that have no
connection with it, but come from a different source?
I hesitate to answer such questions by a simple affirmation. I feel, to be
sure, that Cusanus is far from the purity of Plotinus or Spinoza or Kant.
But what is true in his speculation is convincingly so. His limitations
seem due not to any great tragic guilt, not to the violence of some powerful
passion, but to commonplace shortcomings, such as forgetfulness, distraction,
lack of consistency, conformism.
adviser to his friend Pius II and engaging in the struggle against the
Archduke, he expressed distaste for what he was doing. He wrote to the
Bishop of Padua (quoted from Meuthen, 108) "If I manage to make peace :
you are capable of listening to me, I want you to know that I dislike every-
thing that goes on in this Curia; no one does his duty as he should; neither
you nor the cardinals care anything about the Church. All are a prey to
ambition or greed. When I try to speak about reforms in the consistory, I
cannot bear this kind of life. Let me withdraw, and since public life is
mind you must Wherever you may go, you will find no peace unless
escape.
you temper your impetuousness and tame your spirit. Go home now, and
you may come to see us again tomorrow if you so decide."
Cusanus wept. Silently, his features expressing shame and grief, holding
back his tears with great he made his way through the assembled
effort,
Cusanus is not fully characterized when we list the issues of his day in
which he was involved: humanism, secular scientific curiosity, mystical
piety, conciliar and papal politics, the idea of universal reform, the rise of
individualism. Our purpose has been to expound his metaphysics, to know
and understand it, and only incidentally to raise questions that have a positive
or negative bearing on it. Philosophy cannot be separated from the philos-
opher, but Cusanus' greatness lies wholly in his metaphysics.
The "authentic arrive at a fundamental questioning
metaphysicians"
which takes nothing for granted. In permanent ciphers of thought, they
find answers on which everything seems to hinge. The peaks were Parmen-
ides and Heraclitus, Plotinus, Spinoza, and some Asian thinkers. In their
all-encompassing thinking the "seminal thinkers," as we call Plato, Au-
gustine,and Kant, are also metaphysicians, and not lesser ones. But precisely
because they were so encompassing, we do not include them in this series.
They go deeper than metaphysics, which to them was a mere instrument.
Cusanus is one of the "original metaphysicians," and no more. In the chain
of the great metaphysicians he is an irreplaceable link. He projected in
cipher a great and original vision of Being, which is of enduring value
even without the Christian trappings.
Cusanus exerts a powerful attraction through his grasp of these funda-
mental truths:
First: Man's self-awareness in the face of transcendence. As the image and
likeness of the Creator, man can be certain of his own creative powers, can
be a second God. Yet as an image of the original, in his otherness, he is
points the way to the truth, sees it unseeing in its ground, touches it without
touching it; piety, because truth has its ground only in the Encompassing
One; peace, because all things must come together.
272 The Original Thinners
Third: The rapture of \nowledge. With the freedom of the created mind
(Cusanus knows himself as such) he takes wing in the sphere of the finite
and soars into the sphere of the infinite. Speculative meditation makes him
aware of his origin and goal. In it he experiences the meaning of cognition
and of all science. All essential cognition by the intellect is achieved in
images, metaphors, and symbols. It never attains the precision that character-
izes divine cognition, but stays within "the conjectural."
Fourth: Mans tas\. In his finite existence as image and likeness of God,
man has an obligation to move as close to the original ashe can, though the
process has no end, to discover in the unity of the ultimate ground the
order of peace in which all things are joined.
In Cusanus' speculation we feel awareness of freedom certain of itself.
This does not entitle us to look upon him as belonging to our own world,
as though he intended and were able to guide it. Our world tries tofound
its existence upon political freedom, attains to the unrestrained freedom of
the sciences and to the venture of unrestrained power to produce through
knowledge, and plunges into the maelstrom of the inexhaustible pos-
sibilities of the mind. Our freedom has become license because it has no
roots. It is already far gone toward its own destruction.
We are faced with the question of our destiny: Is it possible to save
freedom on the freedom of the individual's Existenz? We still
basis of the
need help, which can only come from the ground of things. This help
cannot be known. Hence we cannot rely upon it or compel it or obtain it
by prayer. We trust in it when we trust ourselves. We hope to obtain this
help to the extent that we truthfully and lovingly do what we can do in
order to be free and deserve our freedom.
Freedom can be elucidated by metaphysical speculation which encompasses
it. It can also be paralyzed by irresponsible retreat into the bliss of pure
intellectual exercise. Freedom lives in the great millennial metaphysics of
Europe and Asia, to which Cusanus bore witness. He is one of its
Witt's promise and renounced his claim. Whereupon they decided to meet
their obligation. Spinoza lived very simply. "The cloak does not make the
man. Why a costly covering for a worthless thing?" But he did not neglect
his person. He was neat and orderly in his dress and domestic arrangements.
Spinoza spent money freely on only one thing: he left behind him a choice
and valuable library.
After his excommunication Spinoza led a quiet, modest life in rented
rooms in various parts of Holland: 1656-60, in a country house between
Amsterdam and Ouverkerk; 1660-63, in Rijnsburg near Leiden; 1663-69,
in Voorburg near The Hague; and finally in The Hague, first, from 1669
to 1671, boarding with a widow, then, after 1671, in the house of the painter
Hendryk van der Speyk, where he kept house for himself. Here he died
of tuberculosis in 1677 at the age of forty-five.
Spinoza did not choose his fate but accepted it it meant
as inevitable:
exclusion from any community and from his
of faith, blood, or tradition,
own family. Rejected by the Jews, he did not become a Christian. But he
was a Dutch citizen, determined to perform the duties and assert the rights
of a citizen.
The Dutch state had developed in struggle against Spanish oppression.
The moral force behind the Dutch independence movement had not been
nationalism, but a striving for political freedom, justified by religious faith.
At the time when
the state was founded under the leadership of the house
of Orange, the paramount consideration had been military strength. Once
Dutch independence had been recognized in the Peace of Westphalia
(1648) and the new state began to feel secure, military organization and
unified leadership ceased to seem all-important. The republican party
(the Dutch patriciate, the oligarchical party) triumphed over the house of
Orange. For twenty years the republicans under Jan de Witt maintained a
regime of peace and prosperity. Military expenditure was reduced, the
state was secured by foreign alliances. Unlike the Orange party, which in
practice had been extremely intolerant, the republicans stood for true reli-
gious freedom. This gratifying state of affairs came to a sudden end when
Louis XIV, in alliance with the King of England, invaded Holland.
Regarded as a traitor, Jan de Witt was murdered by the mob (1762). The
Orange party returned to power, but the republican spirit preserved a
considerable influence.
Spinoza participated in politics. The T heologico-Political Treatise (1670)
is not only a philosophical investigation; was conceived and published
it
in support of the political aims of his friend Jan de Witt and the republicans.
Jan de Witt was dependent on public opinion for his power. It was
essential that the spirit of the government should find an echo in the
spirit of the population. Freedom of conscience and independence of the
racy. At the time of his death he was about to investigate the third type,
democracy.
Spinoza was a Dutchman, not by descent but by political right. No
longer a member of the Jewish community, he had no other source of
security than justice in the political existence of his state. As a man left to
his own resources, he recognized his human bond with every other man,
and for him this human bond was the self-certainty of reason. Spinoza had
not chosen to uproot himself, but when this lot was thrustupon him he
found new roots in the eternal reason that is accessible to man as man. His
thinking became a refuge for rejected individuals, compelled to stand
entirely on their own feet, an orientation for every man who seeks in-
dependence. He found the self-certainty of reason in philosophy, which
illumined and guided his life. When someone, wishing to convert him to
the Catholic faith, accused him of regarding his philosophy as the best, he
replied: "I do not claim to have found the best philosophy, but I do know
that I recognize the true philosophy."
made good only by the political security
Spinoza's uprootedness could be
and by personal relations of a purely human kind.
of a constitutional state
Spinoza had numerous friends and acquaintances, and he carried on an
extensive correspondence. He was welcome among the Collegiants, an
association of nondenominational Christians. He was a lover of philosoph-
ical companionship. "It is essential to my happiness that I make every
effort to bring it about that many others should have the same insights as
I. and that their knowledge and will coincide completely with my knowledge
276 The Original Thinners
and will." He never forced his teachings on anyone. But what he said
carried conviction. And no one could escape the nobility of his personality;
even his enemies could not help respecting him. He liked to associate with
simple people. When his landlady asked him if she could find salvation in
her religion, he replied: "Your religion is good. There is no need to look
for another as long as you lead a quiet life in devotion to God." Although he
had good friends, he suffered cruel disappointments in his human relation-
ships; he was misunderstood, exploited, forsaken; toward the end Leibniz
came to see the remarkable Jew, whom he was later to disavow completely.
It is not easy to put the right interpretation on Spinoza's desire for
independence. He wished to think and to live nothing other than the
truth, which for him meant: to be in God. This independence, this confi-
dence in his own judgment: this was the godly was not con- life. He
cerned with his own person. This man, who was was so entirely himself,
without self-seeking. He was free from pride and violence and seemed
never to think of himself. He wished his Ethics to appear only after his
death and without his name. For the truth is impersonal. It does not
matter who first formulated its propositions. He did not claim to possess
the truth (it is a very different matter with scientists and mathematicians
who justifiably claim priority for their achievements as mere achievements).
Spinoza concluded his letters with a seal inscribed with the Latin word
caute. He was indeed cautious, for he wished to live in peace. He was very
careful to whom he communicated his ideas and gave his manuscripts
to read. He postponed publication, and most of his work appeared after
his death. He had no desire to be a martyr: "I believe that each man should
live as he sees fit; and let those who will die for their happiness, if only
I may be permitted to live for the truth." Although he had been assured of
full freedom, he declined a call to the University of Heidelberg (1673)
"I have misgivings," he wrote to the Palatine minister, "about the limits
to be imposed on the freedom to philosophize. ... I do not hesitate
because I hope for better fortune, but for love of a tranquillity which I
think cannot be preserved in any other way."
Spinoza was neither a solitary eccentric nor an active statesman. He
undertook no other occupation than to develop his ideas systematically
and set them down on paper. In other respects, he was an independent
man, a citizen, a friend, who reacted to the situations of life with natural
—
good sense and always in an attitude of piety.
His quiet dignity seems to have been as much an innate disposition as
the consequence of his philosophy. But a number of anecdotes show that
his serenitywas not apathy, that his nature was not lukewarm, that he was
not lacking in temperament. At the murder of Jan de Witt, he burst into
tears. He wrote a handbill addressed to the mob, beginning: ultimi bar-
barorum, and was going to rush out and post it. When his landlord locked
him in his room to save him too from being killed, he came to his senses.
SPINOZA 277
Of the portraits that have come down to us, the one in Wolfenbuttel
shows the noble Sephardi. But even such a picture can give only an intima-
tion of the nobility and purity of soul to which his life and work bear
witness.
Worlds: In his lifetime he published under his own name only the didactic,
mathematically formulated Principles of Descartes' s Philosophy (1663)
and anonymously the Theologico-Political Treatise (1670). Immediately
after his death, the Ethics, the Political Treatise, On the Improvement of
the Understanding, Letters, and Compendium of a Hebrew Grammar
appeared in one volume. In 1852, the Treatise on God and Man and
Man's Happiness was found.
Chronology: From the period before the anathema nothing has come down
to us. The oldest document is the Short Treatise, found in 1852 (written
before September, 1661, probably between 1658 and 1660), the earliest
Philosophy was implicit in Spinoza's life; it was his only means of attaining
hold on what was sure for the sake of something then uncertain." Riches,
fame, the pleasures of sense seem to be certainties. But it is not certain that
the highest good is to be found in them. For sensual pleasure results in a
confusion and blunting of the mind. Wealth calls for more and more
wealth. In search of honor, I must incline to the opinions of men, avoid
278 The Original Thinners
what they avoid and seek what they seek. If I am to strive in earnest for the
I must renounce
new, the truly good, all these things. For they are so demand-
ing that the mind preoccupied with them cannot think any other good.
Thus my quest for the true good requires me to sacrifice a good that is
uncertain by its very nature for a good which is also at first uncertain, but
which is not by nature uncertain. In the midst of a life fettered to question-
able, perishable goods, which are certain to melt into nothingness, I shall do
well to seek salvation along the new path as a remedy, although it too is
uncertain.
The first question is: On what
do happiness and unhappiness depend?
And the answer: On the nature of the objects thatwe love. There are two
kinds of object. In our love of perishable objects and of those which all men
cannot acquire in equal measure, we expose ourselves to envy, fear, and
hatred. "But love toward a thing eternal and infinite feeds the mind wholly
with joy, and is itself unmingled with any sadness." Experience taught
Spinoza that though the mind, enlightened by such insight, can turn away
from perishable things, it cannot abolish them. His moments of liberation
became longer and more frequent, but he became truly free only after he had
gained a second insight, namely, that the acquisition of money, the pleas-
ures of the senses, and honors, are harmful only as long as they are pursued
as ends in themselves. For once they are treated as means, they are moder-
ated and cease to be harmful. This attitude of natural moderation is charac-
teristic of Spinoza. His highest good does not destroy everything else. It is
not to be expected in the beyond, but to be seized upon and fulfilled in this
world.
What is good? In his youth Spinoza stated the answer briefly:
this highest
insight into the unitywhich binds the human spirit to all nature and
enables me, in community with other men, to participate in nature. What-
ever comes my way should be considered as a means to this end; I should
concern myself with it only insofar as it is necessary as a means. From this
certain conclusions can be drawn:
We must understand as much of nature as is necessary in order to bring
about the highest possible nature in man.
We must establish the kind of society that is necessary if many men are to
attain this end as easily and surely as possible.
We must find an ethical philosophy and a doctrine of education leading
in this direction.
We must promote medicine for the sake of men's health, which is far
from means to our end.
negligible as a
We must improve mechanics in order to make difficult things easy, so
saving much time and trouble.
We must find means to purify the understanding, in order that it may
know things readily, without error, and as completely as possible.
Thus all the sciences should be oriented toward a single aim, which is the
highest human perfection.
SPINOZA 279
and theological.
a child by the Biblical tradition, this experience of God became for him
the one thing on which everything else depended.
and modes.
280 The Original Thinners
—
The being of Being or of substance, as Spinoza calls it is for him not a —
mere idea; it is the overwhelming, all-encompassing, infinitely rich intuition
of God, which finds confirmation in all thought and experience, whenever
we look into their ground.
Attribute: What we know of the one substance we know through its
Mode: Modes are the individual things, these modes of thought and
these bodies.They are "that which is in another thing through which also it
is conceived." Substance and its attributes are eternal and infinite, the modes
are temporal and finite. Since substance is God, Spinoza says: "Individual
B. God
1) God exists. Why is the thinking of substance or of God one with the
knowledge that He exists?
That something exists is made certain by our existence. But our existence
is transient; each individual existence is not necessary but contingent. We
can think that it is not. Its Being must have a ground. We can find a ground
of this existence in another, and of this second existence in still another, and
so on ad infinitum, without ever arriving at an absolute ground. Such an
absolute ground can lie only in a necessary existence, that is, an existence
which does not exist contingently through something else, but through
itself. But such an existence is necessary only if it is impossible to think
that there is nothing. If nothing could be, Being would not be necessary.
Let us recapitulate: If we attempt to think that the mere finite beings we
are and those we encounter in the world exist necessarily, it "follows that
things finite are more powerful than the absolutely infinite Being." Only
infinite, not finite, beings can exist necessarily. Hence the conclusion : "Either
nothing exists, or Being absolutely infinite also necessarily exists."
Once substance is thought in earnest, doubt must vanish. "If anyone, there-
fore, were he possessed a clear and distinct, that is to say, a true idea
to say that
of substance, and that he nevertheless doubted whether such a substance
exists, he would forsooth be in the same position as if he were to say that he
had a true idea and nevertheless doubted whether or not it was false."
In this fundamental idea concerning the existence of God we must dis-
tinguish two elements: (1) it starts from the existence of finite things, but
(2) the existence of the infinite substance as such is absolutely necessary.
The derivation is only a thread guiding us from what is self-evident to our
everyday consciousness (our existence) through the question of the ground
of this existence (since there is nothing to be gained by an endless regress
from object to object in the world) to the idea of necessary existence. For
Spinoza the idea of substance or God is a certainty, not through derivation,
but in itself. The idea of God requires no grounding or derivation. Rather,
it precedes everything else. It is clear and certain in itself. Consequently,
Spinoza rejects the proofs in which God's existence is inferred from the
existence of the world. When theologians working with such proofs accused
Spinoza of atheism, he attacked them on the strength of his original cer-
tainty of God's existence. He expressed surprise that they should call him an
atheist;on the contrary, he said, those who needed such threadbare proofs
were not certain of God's existence.
not, it would not exist through itself alone, but in relation to something
282 The Original Thinners
other. Nor would it be total being, that is, all reality. Substance or God is
be the infinity of His action, which is both free and necessary, but a deter-
minate choice between possibilities, a lapse into the finite.
God's infinite action is indivisible and omnipresent. "Thus it is just as
impossible for us to conceive of God not acting as of God not being."
—
and circles had consciousness says Spinoza, varying the old ideas of
—
Xenophanes they would conceive of God as triangular or circular. The
notion of Jesus as a God-man is just such an error. "Certain churches
maintain that God took on human
I have stated expressly that I
nature.
do not know what they mean. In fact, quite frankly, what they say strikes
me as just as absurd as if someone were to tell me that a circle had assumed
the nature of a square."
They conceive of God's faculty of free will roughly as follows: God can
do what He wills. He has a right to everything that is; He has the power to
destroy everything and send it back to nothingness. They look upon God's
power as the power of kings. In opposition to this, the purity of Spinoza's
idea of God impels him to say "No one will be able to understand properly
:
what I have in mind unless he takes good care not to confuse God's power
with human power or the right of kings."
The basic reason for such error is that God cannot be imagined but can
only be thought. In thought nothing could be clearer and more certain.
But every representation or imagination limits Him: "To your question
whether I have as clear an idea of God as I have of a triangle, I answer in
284 The Original Thinners
the affirmative. But if you ask me whether I have as clear a mental image
But revelations and cults and churches with their representations of the
divine are a part of man's life. The people are attached to them. Spinoza
acknowledges that this is necessary, a consequence of our finite essence.
And he does not say that these representations are devoid of truth. He
combats only the intolerance and violence which result from them. We
shall have more to say of this in connection with Spinoza's philosophy
of politics.
It is a mark of the radical difference between God and the world that
of God's infinitely many attributes only two are accessible to us; it is a
sign of His nearness that these two are wholly present to us as attributes
and modes of the divine substance. The infinitely many attributes signify
God's transcendence, the two known attributes His immanence. Our
human thinking is grounded in the infinite mode of thought, which in
turn has its ground in the attribute of God's substance. Our thinking is
radically different from God's thought, but it is a mode and expression of
God's thought.
Doctrines which assert God's immanence in the world are termed pan-
theistic. Is Spinoza a pantheist? Such formulas are inapplicable to great
philosophy. Spinoza is a pantheist only insofar as for him the world is
in God, but he does not believe that God's being in the world is the
whole of His being. On the contrary, God's Being in the world is to God's
authentic Being as the two attributes are to the infinitely many attributes.
sequence it is. In this world of modes things come and go, but the whole
remains. God is eternal and unchanging as in the great Biblical visions.
Spinoza's God is without personality, because He is without determina-
tions, without imaginable qualities. In His infinity, He is to clear thinking
the greatest of certainties, the only cause which is everywhere effective.
—
beyond everything we know? the answer must be sought in Spinoza's
life and judgment and concrete insight.
Spinoza has been accused of atheism on the ground that his substance
is "incapable of all predicates worthy of God." In view of Spinoza's
all-encompassing idea of God, in whose presence the world disappears,
Hegel thought it more accurate to call this philosophy acosmism than
atheism. Spinoza's philosophy cannot be subsumed under either of these
terms. It breaks through all such definitions.
Consequently there is more truth in such poetic judgments as: "Spinoza
was a God-intoxicated man" (Novalis). "Perhaps it is here that God has
been seen closest at hand" (Renan). "The infinite was his beginning and
end" (Schleiermacher).
sists of infinite attributes, nor for the present can I explain the matter more
clearly."
by God." That is a fallacy. For there can be no substance outside of God, nor
can any be conceived of. Hence extended substance must be one of God's
attributes.
In order to understand this correctly, we must bear in mind the meaning
of "attribute" for Spinoza: in the attribute of extension substance remains
infinite and indivisible. Only if we suppose extension to be finite and divisible,
confusing it with the modes, do the contradictions arise which make it
God cannot be acted upon. No, only the modes are acted upon, and not in-
divisible, infinite substance. While modes as affections of substance are finite,
divisible, and particular, corporeal substance (in the attribute of extension,
matter) can only be everywhere the same, infinite, indivisible, one. It would
be absurd to conceive of it as manifold, composed of finite parts. Conse-
quently, it is not unworthy of the divine nature. Thus it is false to say that
by attributing extension to God Spinoza "naturalized" Him, if we take
account of what the attribute of extension meant to Spinoza.
might further be asked whether the supposed equality of all the
It
it would seem, must be thought, whereas only thought thinks itself. Thus
extension and all the other unknown attributes seem to confront thought
as an attribute unique in its kind. This is another question that Spinoza
does not ask. The only other attribute known to us is extension. In Spinoza
it does not occupy a lower rank than thought.
All these arguments against Spinoza have the value of showing what
Spinoza is not talking about. It must be admitted that Spinoza invited such
criticism by his method of mathematical proof, which cannot help moving
in the area of finite determination. If Spinoza has nothing to say in the face
of such arguments, it is not, as one might think, because they are well
founded, but only because the vision of God, which he is trying to explicate,
makes him regard them as nonessential.
d. The modes
Individual things taken together (omnia) are the world. They are modes.
Let us now examine in some detail the process in which the world is con-
stituted, from substance and passing through the
starting attributes of
thought and extension, to the modes.
Individual beings are finite. The totality of these finite beings, each of
which exists through another, is endless. Finite individual beings belong to
the totality of the finite, which and infinite. This infinity is a
itself is endless
consequence of God's grounded in a third infinity, that
infinity, but is itself
of the infinite modes, which are not God's infinity and not the endlessness
of individual things, but between the two. They are: the infinite intellect
(intellects infinitus), corresponding to the attribute of thought, motion and
rest (mot us et qnies), corresponding to the attribute of extension, and the
whole of the world (facies totius universi). The individual things (res
particulares) are situated in the whole of the world.
Thus Spinoza conceives of a series extending from substance as natura
SPINOZA 289
naturans to natura naturata as the totality of the modes, and another series
within it, from the infinite modes to the individual things. In the world of
individual things the two attributes of substance are expressed as ideas and
bodies. On the one hand, the series runs from thought (the attribute of
(as an infinite mode) to ideas as finite
cogitatio) to the infinite intellect
modes {modi cogitandi) on the other, from space (the attribute
of thought ;
of extension) to motion and rest (as an infinite mode) to the finite modes
of bodies. Both series run from substance through the whole of the world
(infinite mode: fades totius universi) to the individual things, which,
according to their aspect, we see as ideas or bodies.
The whole of the world or of nature is "one individual, whose parts, that
is to say, all bodies, differ in infinite ways, without any change of the whole
individual."
The totality of nature would be known if we knew how every part is
related to the whole and to the other parts. But such knowledge "is beyond
me, for it would require a knowledge of all nature and of all its parts."
Thus all that can be obtained is the conviction "that each part of nature
accords with the whole and with the other parts." But this conviction is
of the world's Being (in the first case, enduring fundamental ignorance, in
the second total and ultimate conviction), his propositions are not without
contradiction. In particular, it remains unclear to what extent the investiga-
tion of the relation between body and soul is possible in practice and in what
sense the parallel between two independent but coinciding series is to be
taken. Mistakenly, yet encouraged by statements of Spinoza, the proponents
of the so-called theory of psychophysical parallelism in nineteenth-century
psychology invoke his authority. In any event it is necessary, in studying
Spinoza, to distinguish between those conceptions of the world which are
elements in his vision of metaphysical being and those of his ideas which
are subject to confirmation or refutation in scientific experience.
290 The Original Thinners
E. Time; necessity
The world is seen under aspects of spatial extension and thought. Time does
not pertain to Being itself, to substance, but only to the modes. What is
duration in time is eternity in the realm of Being. Thus under the concept of
duration we can only explain the existence of the modes; we can conceive of
substance only under the concept of eternity. We can conceive of the duration
of the modes as longer and shorter, but substance admits of no such concep-
tions. "In eternity thereno when nor before nor after." To know things
is
place by the laws alone of the infinite nature of God, and follows from the
necessity of His essence." This necessity and these consequences are timeless;
they follow "in the same way as it follows from the nature of a triangle from
eternity to eternity, that its three angles are equal to two right angles." Hence
causa and ratio are here the same (for where thought in categories goes
beyond categories, the determinateness of the category ceases). The idea of
SPINOZA 291
F. The cleavage between God and the world and the question oj their unity
that is to say: the infinite contains existence in itself; the finite has its existence
from another finite thing; the infinite is apprehended in itself, the finite
through another. The infinite is unlimited, the finite limited by something
else; the infinite is unconditioned, the finite conditioned. And everything
that exists is either the one or the other, "is either in itself or in something
other." Being-through-itself and being-through-something-other designates
the absolute cleavage between God and things in the world.
Only the finite is individualized; the infinite is one. Hence where there
is individuation, there is finiteness. "Every species of which more than
one individual can exist must necessarily have an outward cause for its
existence." Infinity and uniqueness go together, as do finiteness and indi-
dividuation.
In its perfect positiveness the infinite excludes all determinations. The
"determinations" of the infinite, the attributes, are themselves infinite and
hence not determining predicates, but manifestations. Every determination
is limitation, hence negation (omnis determinatio est negatio), and pertains
to the finite. In the infinite there is no negation, but only positiveness. Any
predicates that are imputed to it must be withdrawn forthwith (in the
manner of negative theology)
This is the greatness of such thinking as Spinoza's: ordinarily we see
the positiveand concrete in definite finite figures. The Encompassing is
in danger of becoming empty for us. Since we find nothing tangible in it,
we suppose it to be nothing. Only what we can demonstrate, take hold of,
differentiate has reality for us. Spinoza, to be sure, enters into this manifold
292 The Original Thinners
just as we do, but coming from somewhere else, from God. For him God
alone wholly positive, and measured by God, every concrete thing is
is
(hen \ai pan), became the motto of those who shared Spinoza's faith.
Every single finite thing is caused by another finite thing ad infinitum
("transitive cause"). But the finite taken as a whole is caused by God
("immanent cause"). Thus if everything that exists exists in God, the
question arises: Are God's infinite attributes different from the finite indi-
vidual things? For these too are in God, or else they would not be. But their
being-in-God is of a different nature, because the relation of finite individual
things (the modes) to God is not only direct, but also indirect, by way of
finite connections. Spinoza states this as follows: "The idea of an individual
thing actually existing has God for a cause, not insofar as it is infinite, but
insofar as it is considered to be affected by another idea of an individual
thing actually existing, of which idea also He is the cause insofar as He is
which deals in defined concepts, because, seen from outside, they reveal
contradictions. Such is also the case with Spinoza.
He seems to reject all the positions noted in the above schema: creation,
for God has neither intellect nor will; the descending overflow, for the
connection is eternal, while time exists only in the series of the modes; up-
ward development, for Being is eternal presence, there has been no progress.
And Spinoza would also have to reject the notion that the world is illusion.
For he explains it not only on the basis of human representation, but as the
eternal necessity of a mode of existence which does indeed exist. Spinoza
expressly rejects the unity of God and world as one substance, whose parts
are individual things. God is not world matter, from whose division the
things come into being; He is indivisible substance, while the individual
things are not substance but modes, divisible, coming into being and passing
away.
But what does Spinoza think? In vain we look for a precise formulation
of the question and an unequivocal answer. He speaks in metaphors which
indicate that all existing things must be understood as a consequence of the
one substance. There are not two modes of being, God and world, hence he
cannot inquire into the relation between them; there is only the one being,
which expresses itself, explicates itself, has necessary consequences. According
to Spinoza, everything follows as necessarily in eternity as it follows from
the concept of the triangle that the sum of its angles is equal to two right
angles. Yet this too is a metaphor; the two consequences are not the same:
the metaphysical consequence is "as" the mathematical consequence.
An explanatory derivation of the world from its source in God is im-
possible, nor does Spinoza achieve any such thing. His thinking has its
source in his original awareness of God, and the content of his expressed
thought is a guide to that source.
Thus it is impossible to start from a source, however concretely con-
ceived, in order to encompass all things in one. But it is still possible to
think toward a source.
Where philosophy has misunderstood itself and derived the world from
its ground, the metaphysical idea has degenerated into a hypothesis for the
explanation of phenomena. Such a hypothesis has methodological justi-
For an under s
g of philosophical ideas, it is important that these
famil p should be clearly known; but they must be kept distinct
from the speculative ideas to which, h daey may serve as guides.
The three stages are set forth in the early treatise, On theImprovement
of the Understanding. First, the delusion of opinion and imagination,
fed only by hearsay or isolated experience. Second, true belief. Third,
:.ti: ::.: :j:a;: «;- : -'.tizt 7:.: ~\tzr„z.z :: --- ;::::; -• r.::,\ti :?.
an example. Given the problem, 2:3 = 4:3s, following the dictate of au-
thority, I find the value of x by multiplying the second and third figures and
ng by the first, and verify by repetition and observation (first stage);
drawing the correct inference from the rule of proportion (second
stage); or else I ;:: die fourth term on the strength of my intuition of
proportion (third stage). In the first case, the arithmetical principle is not
a truth for me but a mere opinion; in the second case, the truth is derived,
in the third it is intuited- "But we term clear insight only that insight
which tl not by rational conviction, but by feeling and intuition of
things themselves this : is far superior to the others."
In the later works, the three stages are further characterized. First stage:
rerceive individual things in a mutilated, confused way through the
senses —here we have "knowledge deriving from uncertain experience."
Or signs and words remind us of such things and we imagine them with
equal imprecision. This is the stage of opinion and imagination. Second
stage: We have clear and distinct common concepts (notiones com-
munes)', these are adequate ideas of things.We operate with them in the
second kind of knowledge, reason (ratio). Third stage: Intuitive knowledge
(seientza tntuhiva) attains "to an adequate knowledge of the essence of
surdity.
Within the limits of our human existence, knowledge of the third variety
can be communicated and acquire self-certainty only in the forms of reason
(the second variety). Hence rationality is the eternal medium for what is
more than rationality (namely, the intuitive thinking of the intellect). With-
out this "more," mere rationality is endless and empty. Rationality, medita-
all these," since reason hasno power to lead us to the attainment of our
well-being, which results "from a direct revelation of the object itself to our
intellect. And if that object is glorious and good, then the soul becomes
third and provides the field in which what is "seen" in the third is communi-
cated, Spinoza sometimes speaks of them in one breath, or seems to use
them interchangeably. (If we translate Spinoza's intellectus as "understand-
ing —as he himself does in his Dutch letters —and his ratio as "reason,"
his use of the terms becomes the opposite of Kant's. Insofar as a comparison
is possible, Kant's "understanding" is Spinoza's "reason," and conversely.)
B. Ideas
By idea Spinoza means "a conception of the mind which the mind forms
because it is a thinking thing." But Ideas also have objective existence
(there are Ideas in God) : they "are the same and will continue to be so,
even if neither I nor any man has never thought of them." The Ideas in
themselves are adequate or inadequate; they are from the start a unity of
idea and will, active insofar as they are adequate, passive insofar as they
are inadequate; adequate Ideas possess perfect certainty, capable of with-
standing all doubt.
Adequate and inadequate ideas: By an adequate idea Spinoza means "an
idea insofar as it is considered in itself, without reference to the object."
As such, it "has all properties of a true Idea." These are "internal signs,"
whereas that which is external, the agreement, namely, of the idea with its
object, "must be excluded." But a consequence of the truth is that "A true
idea must agree with its object."
By inadequate ideas Spinoza means mutilated (incomplete) and confused
ideas. Among its modes of thought, our mind encompasses love, desires,
and all the affections, which, however, are dependent for their existence on
our idea of a loved or desired thing. A pure idea, on the other hand, can
exist without the presence of any other mode of thought. There are ideas
without affections. When in the common order of nature the human mind
perceives and is acted upon by the outside objects with which it acciden-
tally comes into contact, or when it knows itself amid the affections of the
body, its ideas are confused and inadequate. Only when the mind is moved
from within, as when it considers several objects at once, and understands
their similarities and the differences and oppositions between them, can it
have adequate ideas.
The nature of this pure thinking of the ideas is clarified by Spinoza's
distinction between common notions and universal notions. Universal no-
tions are generic concepts such as horse, man, dog. Since they designate only
what is universal in things, they are incomplete concepts, accompanied by
dillcrent representations in each man who thinks them. Other universal
concepts are essence, thing, something. They arise because the limited
human body can form only a limited number of clear images at once.
SPINOZA 299
Where the limit is passed, the images become confused and are collected, as
it were, under a concept such as essence, thing, something. "These terms
signify ideas in the highest sense contused."
The common concepts <,m\ the other hand arc those that are common to
all men; they are complete and form the basis of pure thought. In contrast
to the mutilating abstraction of the universal, they designate the common
essence of things. Such common concepts are extension and thought and in
the highest degree God. "The human mind has adequate knowledge of
God's eternal and infinite essence."
Idea and will: In Spinoza idea and will are one and the same. Will is
more than desire, it is the power to affirm or negate. But affirmation and
negation are bound up with ideas. "In the mind there is no volition or
affirmation and negation excepting that which the idea, insofar as it is an
idea, involves." An idea is not a static image, "a mute painting," but acts
by affirmation and negation. An adequate idea is not passive but expresses
an action of the mind.
The usual distinction between intellect and will (and the resulting op-
position between intellectualism and voluntarism) is not relevant to Spinoza.
Pure volition resides in pure thought, and conversely. An idea that is not
effective is not an idea; a will that is no
not illumined by the purest idea is
will. Only confused, passive thoughts and impulses are left when the One,
which is at once idea and will, is veiled.
Hence necessity is an attribute both of the will and of the idea, and this
in the highest degree in connection with God, who is free from all obscurity.
Hence "God acts and understands Himself with the same necessity." God
never acts arbitrarily like a despot, who has it in his power to destroy every-
thing and restore it to nothingness; He has the freedom of necessity.
Spinoza attacks Bacon and Descartes for asserting that the will is free
and superior to reason. Acts of the will, he says, do not have "the will" as
their cause. Each particular act of will must have a cause of its own. The
will is not, as Descartes supposed, the cause of error. An inadequate idea is
c. Relation to God
follows from it. Hence particular things as such do not disclose the neces-
sity of thought. However, the existence of the modes as a whole is conceived
knows things to be real "in relation to a particular time and place." But
when the mind conceives these things from the standpoint of eternity, it
knows them to be necessary.
Particular things do not exist without God and cannot be conceived of
without God. However, God does not belong to their essence. Hence the
twofold aspect of particular things: on the one hand they can be investigated
endlessly, but on the other hand we can have complete and fundamental
knowledge of their mode of being.
Since everything is in God and known in God,
becomes necessary "toit
observe the right order in philosophizing." Spinoza, who from the outset
orients his entire inquiry toward the knowledge of God, denies that indi-
vidual things can be properly known without the knowledge of God. God
is the first, the fundamental. The sciences of things in the world become
aimless and meaningless if only their never concluded findings are consid-
ered. They are all ways to the knowledge of God, and take on meaning as
such. Accordingly, Spinoza attacks those who
have reversed the order of
knowledge: "For although the divine nature ought to be studied first, be-
cause it is first in the order of knowledge and in the order of things, they
J
I
SPINOZA 301
think it last; while, on the other hand, those things which are called
objects of the senses are believed to stand before everything else. Hence
it has come was nothing of which men thought less than
to pass that there
the divine nature while they have been studying natural objects, and when
they afterwards applied themselves to think about God, there was nothing
of which they could think less than those prior fictions upon which they
had built their knowledge of natural things, for these fictions could in no
way help to the knowledge of the divine nature. It is no wonder, therefore,
if we find them continually contradicting themselves."
definitions and axioms for which he lays claim to immediate evidence. Thus
the geometrical exposition is a great circle which recapitulates, and fills with
concrete content, what must be granted from the first. But the fundamental
concepts themselves lack the unequivocal clarity of geometrical definitions
and axioms (and are from being constructed according to the rules
far
governing a modern system of mathematical axioms). Quite on the contrary,
they are ambiguous, or unthinkable in rational terms, or plethoric —as
metaphysical concepts have always been. Spinoza's basic concepts with their
speculative character —which means precisely that they are rationally un-
thinkable —are not concepts of the kind that serve for unequivocally com-
pelling operations, but inherent paradoxes by which to attain metaphysical
certainty.
Spinoza's proofs leave us indifferent if we interpret them as compelling
rational proofs,and moreover, if this is done, they prove not to be compelling
at all. The proofs have force as a form of actualization. Spinoza carries out
gory. But the proofs have meaning only when this last is present as a guide.
The demonstrations as such are concerned with objects, oppositions, contra-
dictions. But in this medium, there is a recollection or anticipation of in-
tuitive knowledge, the world-transcending knowledge of God, and an appeal
to the motives underlying a right conduct of life. It does not suffice to carry
out the simple rational operations with the concepts as defined. We under-
stand only if we are moved by the contents which these operations serve
to elucidate.
One may judge this method to be unsuitable for philosophy. Descartes
expressly rejected it. He points out that in mathematics simple, self-evident
aim
principles are the point of departure, while in philosophy they are the
and goal (only once did Descartes employ the mathematical method of
exposition, and then playfully). And it must indeed be admitted that
Spinoza's method is inappropriate where others have tried to imitate it
(cf. Schelling in his early works).
If nevertheless this unique work makes a profound impression, it is
Being and of life. Still, it must be admitted that the constant references to
previous theorems make continuous reading very difficult. (By dropping
the geometrical form and inserting the theorems to which Spinoza refers,
Carl Gebhardt in his translation has obtained a readable text. But he has
omitted many of the demonstrations, and moreover the work loses much of
its expressive power when shorn of its geometrical form.)
mental metaphysical experience, in which things are seen "from the stand-
point of eternity." In rationality the thinker gains certainty of what rational-
ity as such can never attain.
we have and state our knowledge of objects in the world, of things that can
be perceived by the senses, and of concepts that can be logically defined. When
this is done, what in Spinoza was existential actuality in thinking loses all
validity.
The Neo-Kantians have attacked Spinozism as uncritical dogmatism.
Kant himself had no relation to Spinoza and scarcely studied him. Kant's
criticism applies only to Spinozist perversions in which the philosophical
core of Spinoza's thinking had been lost.
There is no doubt that Spinoza, who was far removed from critical
of communicating his insight; his is the beatitude which finds its fulfill-
ment and justification in amor intellectualis. To call Spinoza a rationalist
is to forget that his philosophy, conceived intuitively in the third category
of knowledge and expressing itself through the second {ratio), is neither
exhausted nor ultimately grounded in these kinds of knowledge.
Certain of Spinoza's positions remind us of Descartes and Malebranche
(Descartes: cogitatio and extensio; Malebranche: the knowledge of all things
in God). But their thinking moved background of ecclesiastical
against a
faith; they supported its authority without restriction. Their thinking could
not achieve the philosophical earnestness of Spinoza, for it did not embrace
man's most central concerns. In Pascal, on the other hand, authoritarian
faith was carried to its most unexpected consequences, which most others
have veiled, and so thought was devaluated. Spinoza differs from all these.
For him thought is the summit of human power, God is in thought, and
nothing is left in the background. Such thinking was bound to be different
in every phase from that of the thinkers who set their faith in authority.
Spinoza had the perfect earnestness which made possible complete peace and
a purity of personal existence that cannot spring from a philosophy which
already possesses a faith somewhere else, so that, robbed of its philosophical
core, it degenerates into a factual discussion, questionable from the stand-
point of science and irrelevant to faith.
What Spinoza does in his thinking: Our is immersed in
usual thinking
darkness. It moves in abstractions, and words which
schemata, types,
distort even our perception. Governed by conventions and prejudices, its
vision and concept are blind.
All great philosophy strives for deliverance from the veils of distortion
and forgetfulness, from the endless thinking which is meaningless for lack
of aim or fulfillment, which loses itself because at every step its direction
changes, and despairs when it takes stock of itself. But it is not enough to
I
SPINOZA 305
fully disclosed only in pure thought. For "we do not need experience for
that whose existence is not differentiated from its essence. Indeed, no ex-
perience can ever teach us anything about it."
But as finite modes, we are beings of mind and body, living in nature,
hence bound to place and time, which we transcend in pure insight but do
not for one moment leave.
On transcending with categories: The godhead is said to be without
determinations, to be pure cause and necessity, without purposes. But each
one of these statements effects a determination. Inevitably, when I think, I
only as the principle of causality, not identical with it. To think the absolute
is to effect differentiations that can give only a distorted
in definite categories
view of it, such as we obtain in our representations. Thus categorial deter-
mination can be taken only as a comparison.
2. In another method different or opposite categories are identified.
Spinoza says causa sive ratio, intelligere sive agere, deus sive natura, and so
306 The Original Thinners
on. Here cause and logical ground, thought and action, God and nature, are
conceived as identical. It is easy to point out the "fallacy" in such identifica-
tions. Descartes made abundant use of this sive as a means of doing away
with scholastic distinctions (e.g. notiones sive idea, intellectus sive ratio, est
sive existit) ; here the identification is merely a leveling, which prepares the
way for new concepts, and the loss of essential insights must be regarded as
a negative element in Descartes. In Spinoza such identifications are powerful
instruments of transcending thought (except in cases where inattention leads
him to equate concepts —
such as ratio and intellectus between which he —
himself has drawn an essential distinction).
This method of positing differentiated and opposed categories as identical
runs as follows: As differentiated and opposed, they can be determined; in
the identification they become rationally unthinkable; their meaning becomes
indeterminate, but thanks to their differentiated origins they do not become
empty. Thus they become signs for the determination of the indeterminable.
The statements are untrue (because contradictory) as assertions of fact, true
possible, because his thought does not transcend but is fundamentally rooted
in transcendence. He does not think toward God, but comes from God in
his thinking of things. He knows that every determination makes for
finiteness (omnis determinatio est negatio) and knows that thought operates
in determinations. But all determinations are a guiding thread which enables
us, by negating them, to arrive at the place where the thought that expresses
itself in discourse (the thought which applies to the modes) is transcended
in the authenticthought of that which is without determination.
But why did Spinoza prefer the categories of substance, necessity, ground,
and eternity, and reject those of purpose and volition? A transcending in
categories should after all be possible in all categories. This too we can only
interpret as grandiose naiveteon the part of Spinoza, who in the one group
of categories finds his consciousness of Beingand his view of life confirmed,
and in the other impaired. Quite apart from their function in his method of
transcending, the categories become realities for him instead of remaining
symbols of thought. In this he resembled all original metaphysicians. If with
a method in view we undertake to transcend in categories and actually find
this possibility in all the categories, we take the method as our starting
point and our thinking becomes an unreal game, or else we are merely build-
V. MAN
On the basis of what follows necessarily from God, of the infinite which
follows from the infinite in infinite ways, Spinoza now sets out to explain
that "which may lead us as it were by the hand to a knowledge of the
human mind and its highest happiness." What man is, his consciousness of
himself if he is authentic, that is, if he thinks in God, must guide his action
and his life.
that he does not exist." Hence, "the Being of substance does not pertain to
the essence of man."
That men are not substances is further demonstrated by the fact "that
they are not created but only engendered, and that their bodies existed
previously, though shaped in another way."
Spinoza's intention is to show that man is infinitely remote from God and
at the same time infinitely close to Him. No created things can exist and be
thought without God, but God's nature does not belong to their essence.
This is true also of man. Substance, or God, is infinitely more existent or
more powerful than all the modes and hence also than man. But both are
true: Godis utterly other, infinitely remote with His infinitely many at-
Being to man as to all other modes and interpret this unsubstantial "mo-
dality" of man as absolute remoteness from God.
The two views seem to contradict each other. On the one hand, Spinoza
negates the infinite difference between God and man, and on
the other, he
degrades man to the level of an unsubstantial mode, lacking the natural
spontaneity of an independent being.
Such objections, which can be found in any number of variations, turn
Spinoza's concepts into an objectively determined apparatus, a model. The
meaning of the concepts is lost. For the only plausible interpretation is
The vast difference between divine thought and human thought is that
human thought, because of its origin in a determinate mode, can attain
only to two of God's attributes. "In order to understand something that is
Like all things, so also "the essence of man is grounded in certain modifica-
tions of God's attributes."
Cogitatio and extensio, thought and extension (taken over from Descartes,
not as substances, but as attributes of substance), mark the evident difference
between inwardness and outwardness. They are not two beings: mind (or
soul) and body. Rather, they are one thing in two aspects; one is never
present without the other. This is true of all things. All bodies have mind,
allminds have body. At any one time our knowledge can be directed only
toward one of the two aspects, the mind or the body. But through the inner
SP1 X OZ A 309
actually existing particular thing. And the object of this idea, in which the
human mind is grounded, is the body or a certain actually existing mode of
extension. ("But the human mind or the idea of the human body" ex-
presses no other attributes of God besides the two attributes, thought and ex-
tension.) Mind and body are accordingly "one and the same thing, con-
ceived at one time under the attribute of thought, and at another under
that of existence."
These statements make it very clear that mind and body are two aspects
of the same thing but that there is an unbridgeable difference between them
mind and body cannot act upon one another; the mind and body are both
closed systems, each with its own causal relationships, but the two coincide
"The body cannot determine the mind to thought, neither can the mind
determine the body to motion or At every moment, to be sure, we are
rest."
convinced by our immediate action that at a mere sign from the mind the
body sometimes moves and sometimes rests. But: "Nobody knows by what
means or by what method the mind moves the body.'" We do not know how
what we think we are doing at any moment comes about. But, according to
Spinoza's fundamental principle, what in the body seems to be caused by
the mind can and must have its ground in the body itself. The immediate
experience, in which we suppose our mind to be moving our body, does
not carry our knowledge one step further. In investigating ourselves as
what we are, as a mode, we can proceed only within one or the other aspect.
the mind or the body. To mix the two is confusing for knowledge and
fruitless. In investigating the modes, we must remain within one or the
other aspect; we must explain all bodily phenomena by the body and all
mental phenomena by the mind.
If it is argued that those bodily phenomena which are clearly under-
only to the aspect of the mind, not to that of the body. It is impossible to
understand bodily phenomena by interpreting them as signs in a context
of thought. We can investigate only within one or the other aspect, under one
or the other attribute. Any inquiry that shuttles back and forth between one
domain and the other ends in confusion.
Here one cannot but ask: If mind and body are two aspects of the one,
should not this one entity that unites them both be investigated? But this
one thing does not exist separately or before or after, as an independent
object of investigation. The unity of body and soul is true only as funda-
mental philosophical knowledge; considered as an object of investigation, it
nor devotion to the body as the only reality. He recognizes neither a dis-
SPINOZA 311
embodied will of the mind nor a mindless body. He sees the unity of the
two, which is grounded in the unity of God's substance.
To sum up: Philosophically, we know the unity of body and soul only in
Being as a whole. Man is not a substantial part of God, he is not substance.
For man is not a source; only God is the source. In considering the mind
and body of man, the thinker looks toward the ground in God, but not
toward a substance in man. Spinoza goes beyond man, in order to arrive at
a fundamental understanding of man.
We remain modes and are in God; that is, we are finite modes within the
infinite modes, namely, within the infinite intellect (corresponding to the
attribute of thought) and in "motion and rest," corresponding to the at-
Since according to Spinoza all things in this world of modes are at once
mind and body, man takes his place in the scale of natural beings. The
gradations are explained as follows: "In proportion as one body is better
adapted than another to do or suffer many things, in the same proportion
will the mind at the same time be better adapted to perceive many things,
and the more the actions of a body depend upon itself alone, and the less
other bodies co-operate with it in action, the better adapted will the mind
be for directly understanding." Thus far there is no fundamental difference,
but only a difference in degree, between the divers modes and hence between
man and other beings. But the difference between animal and man is never-
theless radical for Spinoza, for man can think and therefore has affects
The hallmark of man is that he knows that he knows; he has reason. The
more rational he is, the freer he is, the more real, the more perfect. Here
the question arises: "Why did God not create men in such a way that they
would be governed only by the guidance of reason?" Answer: "Because He
did not lack the matter with which to make everything from the highest to
the lowest degree of perfection, or, to speak more accurately, because the
laws of nature were so all-embracing that they sufficed to produce everything
that could be understood by an infinite intellect."
Everything arises of necessity, in accordance with God's eternal laws.
This applies equally to the actions of the pious, that is, of those who have a
clear idea of God, by which all their thoughts and actions are determined,
and to the godless, that is, those who do not possess an idea of God, but
merely ideas of the earthly things by which their thoughts and actions are
determined. The acts of these two groups are different not in degree but in
content. Within the necessary consequences of God's substance, in the
infinite universe of nature, there is a natural necessity, which is the necessity
of a rational life. But what diversities there are among men and nations,
only experience can tell us. It teaches that men of authentic reason, philoso-
phers, are rare. It teaches that some peoples are freedom-loving and others
servile. This diversity becomes an essential element in Spinoza's political
thinking.
It may be asked: Does the imperfect exist because everything that is
possible should exist? In other words, does it exist for the sake of the
richest possible diversity, and not of the good? Or in order that there should
be an unbroken scale from best to worst, in which everything occurs and
has its place? Spinoza gives but one answer: Everything follows necessarily
from God. The evaluations, however, spring from the mind of man. Eter-
nal necessity is beyond good and evil, beauty and ugliness.
The soul, Spinoza writes in the early Treatise, has the choice of uniting with
the body, whose idea it is, or with God, without whom it cannot subsist or
be conceived of. If it is it must die with the body.
united only with the body,
But if it unites with immutable and enduring, it will
something that is
necessarily endure with it. This is what happens when the soul unites with
God; then it is reborn in knowing love of God. For its first birth was to be
united with the body; in the second birth, we experience the effects not of
the body but of love, which corresponds to the knowledge of that incor-
poreal object.
This line of thought is made clearer in the Ethics by the distinction between
immortality as duration and eternity as timeless existence. The body-soul
SPINOZA 313
unit is utterly mortal. Only as long as the body endures can the soul
imagine anything and remember things past. Thus it is not possible for us
to remember that we existed before the body: "Only insofar, therefore, as it
involves the actual existence of the body can the mind be said to possess
duration, and its existence be limited by a fixed time, and so far only has it the
power of determining the existence of things in time, and of conceiving them
under the form of duration." Thus, inevitably, "the present existence of the
mind and its power to form ideas are annulled as soon as the mind ceases to
affirm the present existence of the body."
Nevertheless we feel ourselves to be eternal, "for demonstrations are the
eyes of the mind by which it sees and observes things." Although we do not
remember having existed before the body, we feel that our mind, insofar as
it knows and encompasses the nature of the body under the form of eternity,
is removed from time. Hence "the human mind cannot be absolutely de-
which we already and at all times belong. The brighter our rational insight
and concomitantly the power of our love, the more perfectly we attain to
it. In our existence as modes, we remain imprisoned in inadequate ideas,
in a limited faculty of knowledge. But in this same existence we, as rational
beings, gain adequate ideas, though they are always limited. With them we
partake of that Being which, in our immediate relationship to God, in God,
in substance, we ascertain through thought. By thinking, we pass from
existence as a mode to the Being of substance. We ourselves do not become
314 The Original Thinners
From the standpoint of corporeal existence in time, the desire of all things
to assert their existence is the passion to go on living as long as possible. But
in the ground of this existence there speaks the certainty of eternal being,
unrelated to duration, memory, imagination; this certainty is elucidated in
thought.
"We can be more certain of the existence of no thing than of the existence
of the absolutely infinite or perfect being, that is, of God." But it is Spinoza's
perpetual concern that this idea of God should not be perverted, that God
should not be degraded and sullied by our imaginations. If the idea of God
becomes false, all judgments become false.
The pure idea of God implies His necessary existence. He exists and
acts solely by the necessity of His nature. He is the free cause of all things.
Everything is in God, so that without Him it can neither be nor be under-
stood. Everything is predetermined by God, not, however, through an
arbitrary choice, but through God's unconditioned nature or infinite power.
This idea of God is obscured by men's prejudices, which all in turn
spring from one prejudice: the common assumption that all things act, like
men, for a purpose. Thus men suppose that God guides everything toward
a definite end; that God created all things for the sake of man and man in
order that man might worship Him.
The source of this human prejudice is that all men come into the world
without knowledge of the causes of things and that they all seek their
profit, that is, they act for a purpose and are conscious of this drive in
themselves. Accordingly, they look upon everything in nature as a means to
their own profit, and when they find something useful that they themselves
have not produced, they believe that another being of their own kind has
made it for their benefit. Their understanding of things is based on the
utility of these things to themselves, hence on final causes. Consequently
they do not inquire into their own cause. This prejudice turns to supersti-
tion when men meet with harmful things, such as storms, earthquakes,
disease. They imagine that the gods who have made things for their benefit
are angry because men have offended them. They cast about for ways of
SPINOZA 315
pleasing the gods. Believing that the gods provide useful things in order to
obligate men and so receive their highest veneration, men have devised
different ways of worshiping God, each group in the hope that He will
love them more than all others. They imagine the gods and nature to be
as insane as they themselves. And this conception is not corrected by the
daily experience that useful and harmful things come in equal measure to
those who perform such superstitious worship and to those who do not.
They cling to their deep-rooted prejudice, saying that the judgments of the
gods are far beyond human understanding.
Spinoza opposes such prejudice with the conviction, supported and
elucidated by his whole philosophy, that all final causes are nothing but
human imagination. Everything in nature happens with eternal necessity
and supreme perfection. God acts, but has no purpose. For He needs no
other. There is nothing that He lacks.
Although Spinoza denies the "purpose" in Being, he understands purpos-
ive thinking in human existence as a part of man's situation of finiteness
and deficiency. In the substance of being, in God, there is no deficiency,
hence no purpose. Nor has nature any purposes. All natural reality is free
not only from purposes but from values. Spinoza shows how we transfer
our value judgments to nature, as though values were given objectively in
nature : A man intends to build a house. If it is not yet finished, the builder
will say it is imperfect. Once universal models of houses have been con-
ceived, structures are to the degree to which they corre-
judged according
spond to such models. In thesame way, men form universal ideas of natural
things, which they look upon as models, and when things in nature do not
agree with such ideas they say that nature has blundered. Good and evil
are not positive properties of things; they are modes of thought.
By transferring their judgments of things to Being itself, men color the
world with values that are unrelated to its intrinsic reality. But though
Spinoza denies the independent existence of values, he recognizes them as
modes of thought in our limited existence.
The deformation of God into a purposive, hence deficient being, who
obligates men, benefits them, or is angry with them, who allows Himself
to be influenced by men's and devotions, results in a distorted view of
acts
everything. For values are thus removed from the perspective of a being
who exists as a mode circumscribed by time and space and desires His
profit, and transformed into things endowed with objective, independent,
and absolute existence, which are called by such names as good and evil,
order and confusion, beauty and ugliness, virtue and vice. But any such per-
spective is alien to God. To transfer it to God is to remove God's sublimity
from the view of reason.
Only in our limited perspective do we suppose that we find an order in
things themselves. For, because it is easier and hence pleasant, we prefer
order to confusion, as though there were an order in nature apart from its
316 The Original Thinkers
thinking beings we know it, understand it, and can thereby rise above it.
He compares our state with that of a fictitious worm in the blood stream,
which has the faculty of sight in order to differentiate the components of
the blood, and reason in order to observe how they act upon one another.
"This little worm would live in the blood as we live in this part of the uni-
verse." It would observe the blood but fail to notice that our movements
and other outward modifications affect the blood as a whole. We are com-
pelled to understand all natural bodies in the same way as this worm does
the blood. But because the nature of the universe is not limited like the
nature of the blood, but absolutely infinite, each particle is governed in an
infinite way and compelled to suffer infinite modifications. Thus the human
body is a part of infinite nature and likewise the human mind, namely of
the infinite mode of thought. The infinite intellect (intellectus infinitus)
contains all nature objectively within itself. The human mind is this same
power, but only as a finite part of the infinite mind. Hence it does not
SPIN ()'/ A 3*7
Here Spinoza has taken over an ancient concept of reality. In his view,
318 The Original Thinners
empirical things in space and time either have reality or have not, they are
without degrees of reality, but the reality of substantiality in the modes is
graduated. Thus from different standpoints Spinoza can say: "All happen-
ing in nature is supremely perfect." But on the other hand: "That effect is
more conscious he is of himself and of God, that is, the more perfect he is."
Thus Spinoza's view of the identity of reality and value is twofold in its
consequences; on the one hand there are no values, but on the other hand,
value judgments are repeatedly put forward, on the supposition that they
apply to degrees of reality.
able to encompass the infinity of the modes, and can only go forward end-
lessly, while remaining ignorant of the whole.
Because man is a finite mode which
amid bodily affects, but is at the
lives
same time a rational being that loves God, Spinoza's sentences contain a
persistent contradiction (which can be overcome only by the differentia-
tion of the second and third classes of knowledge).
In line with his fundamental idea, Spinoza is constantly effecting a shift
SPINOZA 319
"I shall consider human actions and appetites just as if I were considering
lines, planes, or bodies." "Most persons who have written about the affects
which phenomena, though inconvenient, are yet necessary, and have fixed
causes."
Spinoza envisages an attitude "beyond good and evil." He does not wish
to condemn, to judge, to appraise, for he takes the philosophical attitude
implied by knowledge of God. If everything happens according to the eter-
nal laws, according to God's necessity, it becomes possible to view events
as Spinoza viewed two spiders that he had put into the same net, watching
them fight until one had enmeshed, killed, and eaten the other. But in this
attitude, two elements are involved: devotion to God's necessity and striv-
ing for the truth of objective scientific knowledge, which suspends all
value judgments and purposes in order to apprehend things in their pure
objectivity.
What Galileo inaugurated in the natural sciences when he contested the
320 The Original Thinners
pre-eminent rank that had hitherto been accorded to spheres and circles,
and what Max Weber completed in the humanities when he showed how
value judgments could be investigated without recourse to values, would
have met with Spinoza's approval. But Spinoza had much more in mind:
not only a suspension of one's own evaluations during the hours of investi-
gation and every moment inward and general
of objective judgment, but an
attitude of mind, in which value judgments are not only suspended for a
limited time, but transcended as a whole: the affirmation of everything
that is, because it follows from God's necessity in accordance with the laws
of nature.
It is valid to ask whether there is an inner relationship between the
greatness and force of the idea of God and the possibility of a science truly
free from value judgments, and the question can be answered in the affirma-
tive. Nevertheless, we are dealing with two different things on two dif-
Spinoza's fundamental intuition that Being is free from purposes and that
not solved by the possibility of choosing one's way of life arbitrarily. Quite
the contrary, the highest good also springs necessarily, in the nature of
things, from reason. The evaluation that occurs on the way to it is a factor
in the all-embracing reality that must be regarded as free from values. But
what distinguishes the highest good from all other goods and values is that
as the ultimate purpose it ceases to be a purpose. Not only does it serve no
other purpose, but, insofar as it is willed, it is already present. It is not
willed as something else; rather the will to it, reason, is itself. The highest
good is present in rational thought, which is always at the same time action.
It cannot be intended unless in a certain sense it has already been attained.
The crucial problem is freedom. The contradiction in Spinoza seems
unbridgeable. He denies freedom and asserts it. His whole philosophy is
based on freedom. In thought and work and practice, his ethos aims at the
explains why freedom of the will is self-deception: "Created things are all
determined from without. From an external cause a stone receives a certain
quantum of motion. The stone's perseverance in motion is necessary, be-
cause it is determined by the impact of the external cause. Now let us . . .
imagine that the stone thinks while continuing to move, and knows itself
On the other hand: There is freedom. But what does Spinoza mean by
freedom? Freedom is one with necessity. A distinction is made between
322 The Original Thinners
the adequate cause of his action in clear knowledge of its cause and effect.
But he is unfree insofar as he thinks and acts on the basis of inadequate
ideas, moved by affects from inside and outside, in the endless interaction
of the modes. Since man in his existence as a whole is never, in the lucidity
of adequate ideas, the sole and complete cause, he is always unfree.
But even if man is not perfectly free, he can become freer by conceiving
adequate ideas, that is, by becoming rational. In reason he knows necessity.
Consequently, there is no freedom, everything is necessary; but man's in-
sight into the necessity of his own essence is itself freedom, for freedom is
knowing participation in necessity. The will to freedom, which is identical
with the will to knowledge, understands itself as necessity. Freedom consists
in looking upon all things and events as necessary, in understanding even
value judgments and purposive thinking as conditioned by the necessity
of modal being; finally, freedom is the self-understanding of reason as the
necessary nature of man.
Spinoza's conception of freedom and necessity is complicated by the
notion of an "ought." The moral law ordains something that does not
necessarily happen, but can also not happen. According to Spinoza, there
are two kinds of laws: those which determine the invariable course of
things, and those which are norms according to which men should, but do
not always, act. We ordinarily suppose that our freedom resides in our
ability to follow the moral law or not. What Spinoza means by freedom is
first made clear by his conception of law: only laws that cannot be trans-
gressed are divine; those that can be transgressed are human. Freedom
consists in union with divine necessity; it acts without choice. Where I
not incurred but enacted. For adequate knowledge is identical with action,
not with passivity. It is realization of the soul in accordance with divine
necessity. Achieved through thought, freedom is an actively self-conscious
element of divine, all-embracing, absolute necessity.
But to suppose that God promulgates laws like men, that He rewards
obedience and punishes disobedience to these laws, is one of the false
notions that spring from the transference of human action and human
limitation to God. It is first of all a diminution of God, for everything that
happens happens really in accordance with His own de-
and irresistibly
fied in finding fault with God for giving him a weak nature or an im-
potent mind. This would be as absurd as if a circle were to complain that
God had not given it the properties of a sphere." "Men are unpardonable
before God if only for the reason that they are in God's power, as clay in
the hands of a potter, who from the same mass makes vessels, the ones to
His honor, the others to His dishonor." Against Spinoza it may be argued
here that if man is necessarily as he is, he is pardonable. Spinoza answers:
"Men can always be pardonable and nevertheless want for happiness and
be tormented in many ways."
Spinoza has a certain inclination to Calvinism. He writes that the view
that everything depends on God's judgment is closer to the truth than the
opinion thatGod does everything with a view to the good. For this latter
view assumes the existence of something outside of God, which does not
depend on Him, but to which He looks as to a model. "In practice this is to
subordinate God But there is a radical difference between
to blind fate."
Spinoza and Calvin: Spinoza knows no preference on the part of God, no
arbitrary decision, no "decretum horribile" but only necessity. But a more
profound difference is to be found in the very core of their doctrine: in
Calvin, consciousness of sin and the need of redemption through faith; in
Spinoza, fundamental freedom from all consciousness of guilt or sin and
the peace bestowed by freedom grounded in the certainty of God.
garded this section as an unexcelled analysis of the affects and included the
whole of it in his Handbook of Physiology (1833-40).
The fundamental principles are as follows:
1. All finite modes produce each other, help and destroy one another.
No thing can be destroyed by itself. Rather, each thing strives to endure
in being for an indeterminate time. The striving for self-preservation is
considered, it also has many other names. Accordingly, says Spinoza, "it
Spinoza calls the state of the human essence affection (whether the state is
perfection it ceases.
3. "I acknowledge only three primary affects, those of joy, sorrow, and
desire . . The others spring from these."
.
What gives rise to these affects? The mind represents objects, which
govern the movement of the affects. In relation to the striving for self-
The mind strives to represent what will increase the effectiveness of the
mind-body totality, and Thence result
resists the contrary representations.
the first fundamental, objectively determinedand hate. Love is affects: love
4. The principal dividing line between the affects is created by the dif-
ference between adequate and inadequate ideas. Desire (striving for self-
assertion) and joy and sorrow are either actions or passions (active or
passive). The mind experiences joy in adequate ideas, through which it is
b. Description of bondage
The growth and the duration of every passion are determined by the
power of the external cause in proportion to our own power. A passion,
or affect, can so exceed all a man's other actions as to cling to him per-
326 The Original Thinners
manently. Affects can only be resisted and eliminated by other, opposed and
more powerful affects. Consequently, an affect can be resisted by a true
knowledge of good and evil when this knowledge itself takes the form of
an affect.
Things present have greater power than those that are absent. An affect
relating to something that is immediately present in space and time is more
powerful than one relating to something that is swiftly approaching or to
something that is far removed from our actuality. That is why an opinion
produced by an object that stands before us is so much more powerful than
true reason. As the poet said "I see the good and approve of it, but I cede to
:
evil."
For Spinoza a man who follows his affect and opinion is "in bondage."
One who lives solely in accordance with his reason is free. The former acts
without knowing what he is doing. The latter, obedient only to himself,
does only what he regards as most important in life and consequently
desires most.
The decrees of reason are grounded in the necessary fact that everyone
strives to preserve his being to the best of his ability. Since "all our strivings
follow from the necessity of our nature," "the foundation of virtue (virtus,
power) is that endeavor itself to preserve our own being, and happiness
consists in this —that a man can preserve his own being." "To act according
to reason is nothing but to do those things which follow from the necessity
of our nature." There is no nobler motivation than the striving for self-
preservation. "Since reason demands nothing which is opposed to nature,
it demands, therefore, that every person should love himself, should seek
his own profit." To act according to the guidance of reason, to pre-
serve one's being, to live —these three mean the same thing, to act according
to virtue. Spinoza knew himself to be at variance with the prevailing ethical
view. "Many suppose that the principle which obliges every man to seek his
profit, is the basis of immorality and not of virtue and sense of duty." But
the truth, he declares, "is the exact opposite."
It may be argued that there is no need to strive for what will happen in
any case according to natural necessity. This seeming paradox in Spinoza
is explained by the twofold meaning of nature and necessity, which may
be either the unconscious necessity of inadequate ideas or the conscious
necessity of adequate ideas. For Spinoza demands that we seek the profit
"that is truly profit," that we should not desire blindly, but strive for
"what truly leads man to greater perfection," that we should not take finite
aims our ultimate goal, but only reason itself and what is revealed to it.
as
Spinoza expounds this ethos in three ways: (1) he indicates procedures,
SPINOZA 327
makes recommendations, and sets up rules of life; (2) he recalls over and
over again that all truth has its ground and point of reference in the cer-
tainty of God; (}) he sets forth a model of the rational life.
them. Impulses and desires are passions only insofar as they spring from
inadequate ideas; they may all be counted as virtues as soon as they are
aroused or created by adequate ideas. In the soul there is no other power
than the power to think and to form adequate ideas. In the course of time,
clear ideas gain the upper hand over the unclear ideas of the affects.
In thinking I become master of my affects by following certain proce-
dures, which can be clearly elucidated:
I overpowered by an affect when all my thinking is chained to the
am
external object to which I relate the affect. I become free when I "detach
the affect from my thought of its external causes and connect it with other
thoughts." Then love and hate of the external cause are extinguished.
I am overwhelmed by blind chance. What has happened to me need not
have happened. But once I recognize the necessity of things, I suffer less
from my affects and gain power over them. Thus "grief over a lost
possession is diminished as soon as the man who has lost the possession
considers that he could not have preserved it in any way."
I am taken unawares. Suddenly I am assailed by something that offends,
angers, frightens me. To defend myself against it, I must order my affects,
that is, project in my mind a sound mode of life or certain rules of con-
duct, imprint these on my memory, and apply them to every situation that
occurs.
Spinoza rejects certain emotions that are generally held in high esteem:
pity, as such, is evil and A wise man strives not to be moved by pity,
useless.
for it is a weak affect that weakens. He endeavors, rather, to obey the pure
decree of reason in performing the helpful action that he knows to be good.
To pity no one, but to do good. He adds, however: "But this I say ex-
pressly of the man who loves according to the guidance of reason. For he
328 The Original Thinners
not a virtue, for it does not spring from reason and is a source of weakness.
Repentance is not a virtue; one who repents of an action is doubly
wretched and weak.
Highly characteristic of Spinoza is his discussion of the theorem: What
brings joy is good. In the ordering of our thoughts and representations we
should, as far as possible, consider only the good in each thing, in order
that the affect of joy should impel us to act. To revile, accuse, despise is not
only useless, but results from an unnoticed perversion. The most ambi-
tious of men deplores the vanity of the world when he is unsuccessful. A
man forsaken by his loved one reviles the inconstancy of women, but all
is forgotten the moment she takes him back. The complaints of those who
suffer an adverse fate are an expression of weakness. Hence a man desirous
of freedom tries to fill his mind with the joy that comes from a sound
knowledge of the virtues and their causes; he will not expend his powers
in considering the failings of men, in disparaging men, and in enjoying a
false appearance of freedom. He will avoid listing the failings of men and
sighs, fears . . . ;on the contrary ... to make use of things and to de-
light in them as much as possible ... is the part of a wise man."
cause." Or rather, this knowledge is itself this love of God. Hence the
not the reward of virtue, but is virtue itself." Consequently the rational,
ethical life is to be sought after for its own sake, not for the sake of some-
thing else. When it is regarded as a means to something else, it ceases to
Activity and serenity: Spinoza teaches the potential wise man to live en-
tirely with God and entirely in the world. "A free man thinks of nothing
less than of death, and his wisdom is not a meditation upon death but
upon life." His conduct is not determined by fear of death; rather, he
desires to do good, to live, and to preserve his being.
Spinoza bids the wise man to look upon all things, all events, and himself
as necessary and invariable in their eternal essence and to find peace in this
necessity, to participate in modal existence, recognizing its manifest neces-
sity, to observe it and be above it. In Spinoza (as elsewhere throughout
history) the idea of absolute necessity is a spur to activity; I am active
because I know that I am doing what is necessary. The great difference
between Spinoza and other believers in necessity (Calvin or Marx, for
example) lies in their view of what is necessary.
Thus the intuition of necessity results in activity, but also in serenity:
evil, folly, failure, the experience of my own ruin, all are necessary; conse-
quently do not revile my enemy, or the treacherous man, or the blind
I
independent of hope, to free us from fear, [so that we may] command our
fate to the best of our powers."
This we shall do if we regulate our actions and our thoughts and our
imaginations "according to the clear counsel of reason." We shall meet
contrary fortune with equanimity if we are aware that we have done our
best and that our strength was not sufficient to enable us to avoid misfor-
tune.
It is essential that we should be wholly permeated by the knowledge
"that all things follow from the eternal decree of God, according to that
same necessity by which itfollows from the essence of a triangle that its
three angles are equal to two right angles." Insight demands only what is
SPINOZA 331
necessary. Consequently, the striving "of the better part of our self" is
consonant with the order of nature as a whole. For "whatever a man, who
is after all a part of nature, does for his own sake, for his self-preservation,
or what nature does to him without his participation, all this is effected
only by the divine power which operates in part through his human nature
and in part through external things." The highest happiness resides in
harmony with divine necessity. But for Spinoza absolute necessity is God's
being, substance, not the idea of some natural or historical process.
Insight into this necessity makes for fortitude, that is, the inspiring,
powerful, active affects. Fortitude, for Spinoza, consists of strength of mind
(animositas), which enables a man to live according to the decrees of
reason, and generosity, which causes him, in sole obedience to the decree
of reason, to help his fellow men and join with them in friendship.
The man of fortitude hates and envies no one, is angry with no one,
underestimates no one, and is free from pride. He knows "that everything
he conceives to be good and bad, and everything which appears to be dis-
orderly, horrible, unjust, and shameful, springs from his disordered, per-
verted, and confused view of things." This confusion vanishes once he
has understood the necessity of things. Then, indeed, "he will find nothing
deserving of hatred, mockery, or contempt, nor will he pity anyone;
rather, he will endeavor, to the best of his ability, to act well and be happy."
4. Characterization
The fundamental attitude recommended by Spinoza is distinguished
from Stoic equanimity, to which
might seem related, by Spinoza's con-
it
ception of God, which is different from the Stoic doctrine of God, just as
Spinoza's third class of knowledge (scientia intuitiva) differs from Stoic
reason, and as Spinoza's serene self-assertion differs from the Stoic assertion
of a punctual, absolute self.
Spinoza lacks the violence of the Stoics. He does not teach men to
drive or repress themselves. To
mind, such compulsion is ineffectual
his
(an affect can only be combated by another affect) and fraught with dis-
astrous and unnatural consequences. Reason does not combat an affect but
lets it die away. Consequently, Spinoza's prescriptions are directed solely
Nor can Spinoza's thinking be equated with the ethical demand of reason
in Kant. Spinoza denies that any absolute demand springs from reason it-
self. Consequently he knows rules of life but no absolute imperatives, no
prohibitions, no obedience to the recognized ethical law, nor the self-
held that Christ possessed such perfection as no other man. "No one except
Christ received the revelations of God without the aid of imagination,
whether in words or vision."
What Christ experienced, He translated into words, in large part adapted
to the comprehension of the multitude. He "was not so much a prophet as
a mouthpiece of God." He "perceived truly what was revealed for a . . .
should be neglected by almost everybody? But all noble things are as dif-
ficult as they are rare."
of the longest and most powerful of the works that he himself published,
the T heologico-Political Treatise, and of his last, unfinished work, the
Political Treatise.
Man two laws: the law arising from his bond with
finds within himself
God and that arising his bond with other men. The first bond is
from
absolutely necessary, not so the second. For the law according to which a
man lives before God and with God must be borne constantly in mind;
whereas the law which springs from his bond with other men in the
world of modes "is not so necessary, inasmuch as he can isolate himself
from men." All his life Spinoza remembered these two laws, though he
dropped the idea (expressed in his youth) that an individual can cut him-
self of? from other men. He came to recognize that "for man nothing is
more useful than man" We can never arrive at the point where we re-
quire nothing from other men for the preservation of our existence. Our
intelligence would be less complete if the mind knew nothing but itself.
Without mutual aid men can neither live their lives nor develop their
minds.
But despite this unique value of man for man, a reliable common bond is
not achieved simply by free association among men. With all their simi-
larity, men differ from one another. The same thing seems good to one
and bad to another; to the one ordered, to the other confused; to the one
pleasant, to another unpleasant. Hence such sayings as "Many men, many
minds"; "Each man to his taste," and so on. This only goes to show that
men would rather imagine things (according to the disposition of their
minds) than know them (according to reason). Imaginations separate
men, only reason brings them together. From the affections of the imagina-
tion spring disputes and ultimately skepticism; from reason spring harmony
and true insight.
Consequently, the great impulse to agree with others is ambivalent. In
the realm of the imagination it has an opposite effect: "Each man strives to
the best of his ability to bring it about that others should love what he
loves and hate what he hates. But inasmuch as all strive equally to this
end, they impede one another equally; and inasmuch as all wish to be
praised and loved by all, the outcome is mutual hatred." But in the realm
of reason, the impulse attains its goal. It fulfills itself in the community by
causing the one common truth to be revealed to all. There is nothing more
desirable and "more precious for the preservation of (men's) being than
that all should agree with all in such a way that all seem to form a single
mind and a single body." Men who are guided by reason "seek nothing for
themselves that they do not also desire for other men."
But such rules are not a sufficient foundation for real community. For
men's life together seldom determined by reason, but more often by the
is
state is indispensable to all men, to the rational as well as the irrational and
antirational. For the state alone possesses a power that can check the power
and arbitrary will of individuals.
The advantage of an ordered political community is far greater than the
disadvantage. "Let satirists scoff at human affairs, let theologians denounce
them, and let the melancholy praise a life rude and without refinement,
despising men and admiring brutes, men will nevertheless find out . . .
that it is only by their united strength that they can avoid the dangers
which everywhere threaten them." To give up the state would be as absurd
as the action of the young man who, after a scolding from his parents,
leaves home and joins the army, preferring tyrannical discipline to domestic
discomforts and the admonitions of his parents. The rational attitude is to
accept offenses at the hands of men and the state with equanimity and
zealously do what fosters harmony and friendship. "A man who is
guided by reason is freer in a State where he lives according to the common
laws than he is in solitude, where he obeys himself alone."
Toward the state as toward our destiny, Spinoza seems to demand a
contradictory attitude: on the one hand, we should recognize its necessity
and bear this necessity without fear; but on the other hand, we should
conceive models and ideas of the best possible state, hence of the state that
will prove best in our concrete situation, and act in accordance with it.
Accordingly, Spinoza says that his philosophy is "of no little benefit to the
political community, insofar as it teaches in what way the citizens are to be
governed and guided, namely, in such a way that they should not serve as
slaves, but should voluntarily do what is best." To the necessity of known
events (events in the world of modes) he opposes the freedom of the active
man, but both are included in all-encompassing divine necessity.
Thus this philosophy aspires to bring reason into political life by recog-
nizing the nature of events in the world of modes, and arriving, on the
basis of this knowledge, at norms according to which it is reasonable to
act in making laws and shaping institutions.
individual, the ultimate goal is clear: that as many men as possible should
be philosophers, living in the perfection of reason based on the knowledge
of God. But the norms are ambivalent. For in the ever-changing life of
states there are several forms offering relative permanence; and here, as in
the study of nature, no particular form can exhaust the infinite possibilities.
There are several models, hence their virtue is relative, and in practice
none can attain perfection. There is more than one path to betterment.
The states and institutions that can be arrived at along these paths
should be judged by ideal types set up in accordance with the criteria of
such inherent necessities as permanence, security, and freedom (Spinoza
attempted to do this in his last political treatise).
Spinoza starts out by examining the requirements of political life inde-
SPINOZ A 335
pendently, but after his initial exposition, religion occupies a central posi-
tion in his discussion of the state. Hence the title of his most important
work: Theologico-Political Treatise.
Here again we find an apparent contradiction, namely, between Spi-
noza's purely philosophical thinking and his theologico-political thinking.
For when in a political context he discusses the origins of religious
the pure concept. For existence does not follow from the concept of essence
(except in the case of God); the reality and subsistence of things are
manifested only to experience. Consequently "statesmen have written
much more aptly about politics than have philosophers." Because they had
experience, they taught "what is consonant with practice." Spinoza held
Machiavelli in high esteem. He himself aspired to supply nothing new, but
"only to represent in a sure and incontrovertible way what is most com-
patible with practice."
His starting point, in the Political Treatise, is the observation of human
nature: In their overwhelming majority, men are guided not by reason,
but by passions. Every man would like others to live according to his
opinion; consequently, men come into conflict and do their utmost to
oppress one another. They pity the unfortunate and envy the fortunate,
but incline more to vengeance than to compassion. "Although all are per-
suaded that religion teaches every man to love his neighbor as himself
... yet this persuasion has little power over the passions." It asserts itself
on the deathbed, when sickness has quelled the passions and a man lies
helpless, or in church, "where men do not deal with one another, but not at
all . . . in the law-court or the palace." Reason, to be sure, can do a good
deal to moderate the affects, but its path is always an arduous one. It is
any man does after the laws of his nature, he does by the highest natural
right."
c. Reason as such is the greatest might. Its weakness is that it is so rare
among men. But it is not entirely powerless. Statesmanship treats both
reason and the passions as factors, the latter being so much more powerful
only because in practice they are so much more widespread. Both are
natural. In this connection no distinction is recognized "between desires
springing from reason and those springing from other sources."
"If nature had been so constituted that man should live according
human
to the mere dictate of reason ... in that case natural right, considered as
special to mankind, would be determined by the power of reason only.
But men are more led by blind desire than by reason: and therefore the
natural power or right of human beings should be limited not by reason,
but by every appetite whereby they are determined to action."
d. The origin of the state should be understood on the basis of natural
right, not of a rational plan. Because all men create some sort of political
institutions, "we must not try to derive the causes and natural foundations
of the state from doctrines of reason, but must take them from the universal
nature and disposition of man." Men are by nature enemies in envy, anger,
and hatred. My worst enemy is the man I most fear. A man strives in vain
to defend himself singly against all. Hence the natural right of the individ-
secure the land they inhabit and cultivate against all violence and live
according to the common will of the community. In such countries all
may be said to live according to one mind.
e. In this political condition the individual has "only as much right to
nature as the common law accords him." He is subject "to the concerted
will of the community charged with care commonwealth," namely
for the
the right laws, to decide on questions of
to make, interpret, and repeal
war and peace. This government can be a democracy (government by an
assembly constituted by the whole people) or an aristocracy (government
by a few privileged persons) or a monarchy (government by one man).
f. It is only through the state that there exist laws, which are not neces-
sarily compelling laws of nature, but civil laws which demand but do not
the citizen does not compel the state itself. Hence the treaties and agreements
between states "remain valid so long as the will of him who gave his word
remains unchanged. For he who has authority to break faith has, in fact,
relinquished nothing of his own right, but only made a present of words.
If then he, being by natural right judge in his own case, comes to the
conclusion thatmore harm than profit will come of his promise, by the
judgment of his own mind he decides that the promise should be broken,
and by natural right he will break the same." (One who orders his life
according to the rules of reason acts differently; even when no power
compels him, he keeps his promise.) The state is compelled for its own sake
to inspire fear and respect. However, the rules for doing so do not pertain
to the domain of civil law, but to that of natural right. Fear and respect are
maintained only through the right of war. "In order to remain free, a
commonwealth must order its conduct according to no one but itself, and
consider as good and bad nothing other than what it recognizes in its own
mind as good and bad."
In accordance with natural right, the same independence toward laws and
contracts applies in the relation of a state to its citizens. The state is not
bound by what binds all its citizens. "Contracts or laws, by which the popu-
lace transfers its rights to a council or an individual man, must be broken
as soon as thecommon good demands it."
But who decides what the common good requires? "No private citizen is
entitled to judge." Only the possessor of state power is free to interpret the
laws, which are not in fact binding upon him.
338 The Original Thinkers
subject to no other rules than man in the state of nature. But above all it
and strength of mind are private virtues. Security is the virtue of the state."
Reason of state is necessitated by the passion itself, by the passionate
will of a ruler who desires the permanence and security of his own power.
But reason as such is to be expected neither of the multitude nor of leading
politicians. For both are driven by passions.
Fear alone holds them in check. Commenting on the dictum "Terrible
is the crowd when it is not afraid," Spinoza says: To suppose that the
populace is without moderation, that it serves slavishly or rules arrogantly,
that it is terrible when it is not afraid, is to limit "all errors to the common
people" and to forget that nature is the same in all. All men are arrogant
when they rule and terrible when they are not afraid, and everywhere "truth
is most falsified by the embittered and by servile minds."
Thus it is the passion for secure power that necessitates the realization
of reason in the state. This is a necessary consequence of the enduring
tension in political life. Every individual, to be sure, has made over to the
state the right "to live as he pleases," at the same time entrusting the state
with "the power to defend him." But "no one can be robbed of the right
to defend himself to such a degree that he ceases to be a man." Con-
sequently, "the subjects have retained, by natural right as it were, what
cannot be taken from them without great danger to the state." Just as the
anarchic self-will of the individual leads the state to intervene against him,
so the arbitrary power of the rulers leads to the rebellion of the people.
The state does not exist through reason alone; the concept of a state
does not suffice to bring one into existence. coming-into-existence and "The
survival of natural things cannot be deduced from their definition. For
their conceptual essence remains the same." But what has power as its
origin requires power for its survival. "In order to endure, things require
the same power as they needed in order to enter into existence."
Spinoza's political thinking encounters an antinomy. On the one hand,
the natural foundations of the state "cannot be derived from the principles
of reason but must be taken from the universal nature of men." And on
the other, a stable state endures solely through reason, which, to be sure,
is not its foundation, but is necessitated by the ruling power's need for
security and permanence.
j. Encompassing necessity
Wemay speak of natural right but not of natural wrong. Everything has
right insofar as it has might. Wrongdoing, injustice, presupposes the ex-
istence of the state as a law-giving power. But all this right and wrong are
encompassed in the right of necessity.
Though laws may be given by states and proclaimed by prophets, they
all exist through the power of God. But God's right, the power that encom-
passes all others, is superordinate to every particular law and to every legal
order. When we obey the laws of the state and the laws of God as
34° The Original Thinkers
natural laws? Only by God's infinite intellect, says Spinoza, not by us.
For neither by experience nor by its concepts can our finite understanding
know the infinite reality of the cosmos, though it is well able to arrive at an
itself. For Spinoza the magnitude
adequate theoretical conception of infinity
of all-encompassing nature more than known nature and than
is infinitely
fact, what our reason pronounces bad is not bad as regards the order and
laws of universal nature, but only as regards the laws of our own nature
taken separately," because we "should like to see everything directed accord-
ing to the rule of our reason." Nature "is not subject to the laws of human
reason, which aim only at the true profit and preservation of man; but to
innumerable other laws, which relate to the eternal order of universal
nature."
The finite known to us, relate to something
laws of nature, which are
that is and freedom. But the encompassing
inferior to philosophical reason
divine law of eternal necessity is above everything we can definitely know.
It encompasses and transcends all finite knowledge and its utilization as a
means to ends as well as every law that is given in the form of ethical
obligation in society.
Spinoza elucidates this fundamental situation in detail. "Man, whether
a wise man or a fool, is a part of nature." Reason and desire are equally
subordinate to nature. "Whether governed by reason or by mere desire, man
always acts in accordance with the laws and rules of nature, that is, accord-
ing to natural right."
It is a mistake to suppose that fools do not follow but only confuse the
SPINOZA 341
was not in the first man's power to make proper use of his reason; he was
just as subject to the passions as we are."
sity God, or nature: According to the finite and limited judgment of his
of
own understanding, man is subject to what is for him the most terrible
of evils, namely, total annihilation. But he is not caught up in a chaos of
blind natural forces. For even if he should fall from all humanly sheltered
and sheltering existence, he cannot fall away from the world and from God.
He is always in the hand of God, because he partakes of eternal necessity,
from which he cannot escape and in which he finds himself. By philosoph-
ical insight he knows that he and everything that befalls him are part of
eternal necessity. This knowledge appeases his spirit and gives him peace.
Spinoza does not complain, he does not find fault with things as they are.
In him there is nothing of a Job. But his serenity is not the indifference of
an irrationalist or amoralist; it springs from the love of God.
is termed reason, true virtus, and the true life of the mind."
i. Freedom: Spinoza elucidates the nature of political freedom:
of the good state was stability. But the goal of the ideal state is freedom. This
primacy of freedom throws a new light on the criterion of stability, for the
essential now is not stability as such but freedom in stability. Mere stability
can be deceptive. Where political freedom is at stake, Spinoza, who does not
wish "to condemn, lament, despise, or deplore," hands down radical judg-
ments. In this connection his love of peace, which elsewhere seems uncon-
ditional, is suspended. For a state can have stability without freedom. Turkey
is an example. "A commonwealth whose peaceful condition depends on the
cowardice of its subjects, who let themselves be led like cattle and learn only
to serve, can more aptly be called a wilderness than a state." "Peace is not
freedom from war but a virtue, which springs from strength of mind." "If
SPINOZA 343
slavery, barbarism, and desolation are called peace, then there is nothing
more pitiful far man than peace. For peace does not consist in the absence of
war but in a unity and harmony of minds."
Spinoza once drew a picture of himself dressed as Masaniello, the then
famous Neapolitan revolutionary. This peace-loving, reasonable man, who
desired nothing more than harmony with his fellow men and peace in God,
knew that where rational, political freedom was at stake he had the strength
of a rebel within him.
Spinoza discusses publicity, because he regards it as essential to political
freedom. Only a ruler intent on absolute domination maintains that the
on in secret. He praises
interest of the state requires his affairs to be carried
Machiavelli, who "was for freedom and gave the most salutary counsels
for its defense." This "very astute man" showed "how unintelligently many
persons act, who try to do away with a tyrant when they have been unable
to do away with the causes that make a prince into a tyrant." But above all
Machiavelli wished to show "how very careful a free people must be not to
entrust its welfare unreservedly to one man." Spinoza attaches little impor-
tance to the question of whether monarchy, aristocracy, or democracy is the
best form of government. The all-important question is to establish, within
each of the three forms, the best possible type from the standpoint of stability
and freedom.
3. For whom did Spinoza write? For whose benefit did Spinoza divulge
his ideas? By whom did he wish to be read? He said: "I know that it is
impossible to rid the people of superstition and fear. I know that the per-
severance of the people is obstinacy, and that they are not guided by
reason but carried away by blind passion for better or worse. Consequently,
I do not invite the people or any of those who share the same affects to read
this." Despite its relevance to the political situation of Holland, the Theo-
Spinoza had great praise for Machiavelli but borrowed few ideas from him.
He scarcely mentions Hobbes, with whom many of his own ideas clearly
originated. The only plausible explanation is that Spinoza felt a kinship of
mind with Machiavelli and not with Hobbes. Purely rational ideas are as
such a means of communication; in their universality they are mere forms,
to which no right of possession can be acquired. It is worth-while to examine
the difference between Spinoza and Hobbes.
344 The Original Thinners
For Hobbes the ultimate motive of political life is security against violent
death; for Spinoza it is freedom. Thus in Spinoza all the elements taken
from Hobbes acquire a new meaning:
For both, the purpose of the state is the preservation of life. But for Spinoza
this is not the ultimate end. To his mind, government loses its meaning when
men cease to be rational beings and become subjects obeying out of fear. For
the ultimate end of the state is not security but freedom, in which men can
develop the powers of their body and mind and attain to reason.
Hobbes' reason constructs and calculates the conditions of security, one of
which is absolute rule. Spinoza's reason is the knowledge of God and the
love of man. Thus in the medium of a natural theory of the state, which
largely coincides with Hobbes, Spinoza develops aims that are alien to
Hobbes. Hobbes' reason is calculating and utilitarian, interested primarily
in securing the peace. Spinoza's reason, which is his first and all-embracing
concern, is an intuition and certainty of God.
Hobbes does not deal with religion, except to say that if peace and security
are to be guaranteed, all questions of cult and dogma must be decided ex-
clusively by the state. Spinoza is in the religious tradition, whose true content
he develops as philosophical reason. Hobbes looks upon religion as largely
superfluous. Spinoza recognizes its necessity for the multitude who lack
insight and are incapable of philosophical reason.
Hobbes looks upon all men as equal: every man is capable of killing
another; all have the same faculty of thought; through proper methods of
thought, every man can become the equal of every other; there are no
natural differences among men. For security in the state it suffices to elabo-
rate a proper apparatus of institutions and laws. Spinoza concedes that
because most men are incapable of philosophy, they require something which
is not philosophy but religion, and which differs from vulgar superstition
they must fear nothing so much "as a free army of the people, which has
created the glory of its fatherland by its courage, its effort, and its blood."
Hobbes condemns all breach of contract, because its consequences are
harmful under all circumstances. Spinoza recognizes it as a necessity which
is in keeping with natural right, whether embodied in the will of the
rulers concerned with the welfare of the state or in the rebellion of the
people — and this necessity can be judged only by its consequences, accord-
ing as they tend to preserve, save, or destroy the state. He recognizes,
however, that a philosopher, living by the ethos of reason, is not prepared to
break any treaty.
Hobbes mastery of nature and looks into the
sees progress in the technical
future with amazing optimism. Spinoza regards man's mastery over nature
as a significant task, but for him it does not assume central importance.
In his vision, the future is overshadowed by the present task (in Holland),
and by eternal necessity, which knows no history.
appear. Reason does freely and reliably what religious obedience does un-
freely and —because of the tendency to sectarianism inherent in all super-
stition —unreliably.
Spinoza quotes Quintus Curtius Rufus, the Roman biographer of Alex-
ander the Great: "Nothing controls the crowd more effectively than
superstition." He recognizes the all-dominating reality of revealed faith
in Judaism, Christianity, Islam.But is this superstition? Yes, says Spinoza.
But he on the basis of this revelation, love and justice are
also says that,
demanded and through obedience partly obtained. Thus in practice this
belief accords with reason, though it lacks the theoretical knowledge of
reason. Spinoza therefore does not simply criticize revealed religion out of
existence, he recognizes its rational core and declares it to be indispensable
to the building of a free society.
order to understand, must previously, without the words, have known who
God is. Thus Spinoza says it is impossible that God should have revealed
Himself to man by any outward sign. Only the intellect of man can know
God, since the intellect can neither exist nor be conceived of without God.
Nothing is so close to the intellect as God. In order to reveal Himself to
man, God needs Himself alone, not words, miracles, inspirations, or any other
created thing.
Yet because men, the rulers as well as the ruled, are as they are, neither
revelation nor miracles are to be despised in the ordering of state affairs, and
not only because these imaginings are ineradicable, but also because super-
stition can take on a form compatible with the truth of philosophy (which is
love, joy, peace, moderation, and loyalty to all, nevertheless quarrel most
bitterly among themselves" —that "each one, whether Christian, Turk, Jew,
or heathen, can be recognized only by his outward appearance and his
cult; in other respects all have the same mode of life"
—"that the people con-
sider it part of religion to look upon Church offices as dignities and bene-
fices and to hold the clergy in high honor."
This universal superstition gives rise to tyranny, which, where the
means are available, restricts the freedom of each man to develop in accord-
ance with his own nature, forbids free thought, and strives for control over
the state.
In the face of this politico-theological reality, Spinoza devotes his thinking
to the cause of freedom. "It is utterly contrary to universal freedom that
every man's free judgment should be restricted by prejudices or curtailed
in any way . . . that opinions should be considered punishable after the
manner is why differences of opinion lead to disorder and
of crimes." This
rebellion. Such
would be impossible if, in accordance with the law of the
evils
state, "only acts were judged, but words exempted from punishment."
Spinoza sets out to show that freedom (of judgment, and freedom to
348 The Original Thinkers
ence and only a very few attain to a virtuous way of life by the mere guidance
of reason, we should have to doubt of the salvation of almost all men if we
did not have the testimony of Scripture." It would be folly, "merely because
it cannot be demonstrated by mathematics, not to recognize something which
has been confirmed by the testimony of so many Prophets, which has brought
so much consolation precisely to those who are not strong of mind, which
has been of no little utility to the state, and which we can believe without
harm or danger." If we are to order our lives wisely, we may not accept
as true only that which there is
—
no reason to doubt "As though most
of our actions were not highly uncertain and a prey to chance."
Yet from a philosophical standpoint Spinoza regards revelation as impos-
sible. Such statements as the above are made only in a political context,
and he recognizes revelation only in a particular sense. (1) He is able to
describe and characterize revelation as one of the innumerable phenomena
existing in the world of modes, but he cannot explain it except in relation
to the needs of finite thinking beings. (2) In discussing these things, Spinoza
knowingly speaks "according to the comprehension of the multitude," and
here "multitude" includes the circle of enlightened men for whom he is
writing this particular work. (3) Spinoza takes the point of view of the
oligarchical party, where a liberal, tolerant faith was taken for granted.
But the essential point for Spinoza is that he finds the Biblical laws of
love and righteousness to be in full agreement with the prescriptions of
reason, and sees "the word of God," not in certain canonical writings, but
only in these prescriptions. The Prophets, he declares, "taught no morality
that is not in perfect agreement with reason. For it is no mere accident
that the word of God in the Prophets agrees perfectly with the word of God
that speaks within us."
But then Spinoza turns to the disastrous struggle of the denominations
and their theologians against those whom they regard as heretics. By way
of putting an end to such disputes, he regards a clear separation between
reason and revelation as expedient and necessary. They are two different
realms: "Reason is the realm of truth and wisdom, theology that of piety
and obedience."
SPINOZA 349
seek "to justify authority by proofs, in order to rob reason and natural en-
lightenment of their authority." Or they pretend to submit theology to
the rule of reason, on "the supposition that the authority of theology has
radiance onlywhen illumined by the natural light of reason.'*
But theology gains nothing by such attempts to overstep its limits and
become knowledge. In matters of insight, only reason can testify. Anyone
who invokes another witness speaks from the prejudice of his affects. "But
in vain, for what sort of altar can that man build who offends against the
majesty of reason?"
Jews, Catholics, and Protestants base the claims of their faith on the Bible.
All argue with Bible quotations. The interpretation of the Bible is a power
not only for faith, but also for political ends. In order to avert the harm
done by this power in creating conflicts, often with bloody consequences,
Spinoza advocates the "right interpretation of the Bible."
Exegesis can be based on two fundamentally different assumptions. The
question arises: Are they mutually exclusive, or can they be reconciled?
The first assumption is that the Bible is the word of God. Being of
fundamentally different origin from all other books written by men, it
alone is Holy Scripture. Since it is the word of God, it can contain no
contradictions. Everything in it is true.
The second assumption is that the Bible is a collection of books written
by men, and originally no different in character from other works of litera-
ture.
Interpretation of the Bible according to the first assumption involves
the following methods:
i. If no contradiction is admissible in the Bible, the exegete must eliminate
the numerous contradictions that actually occur (as well as the objectionable
passages) by invoking an allegorical sense in addition to the literal sense.
2. The irrationality of the text is interpreted as a mystery. The exegete en-
deavors "to explain the absurdity" by supposing "the profoundest mysteries
to be concealed in the text." 3. An attempt is made to adapt Scripture to
reason, for example, to Aristotelian or Platonic speculations. Because Scrip-
ture is divine, hence true throughout, the exegete assumes that study of it
conceived opinions of the exegetes, and that the meaning of Scripture cannot
be gathered from Scripture itself.
those to whom the Prophets and the Apostles preached the word of God,
in order that men might accept it without resistance and with their whole
ing righteousness and love." Accordingly, Spinoza says that "the authority of
the Prophets is meaningful only in questions of life conduct and true virtue,
that in other matters their views are of little concern to us." In particular, he
interprets the mass of Mosaic legislation (in contradistinction to the Ten
Commandments, which are concerned with the right conduct of life) : it
was "solely the legal order of the Hebrew kingdom," which accordingly had
no reason to be accepted by anyone but the Hebrews, and to which "they
themselves were bound only so long as their state endured."
Spinoza interprets some of the contradictions in the Bible historically,
by considering in what situation and for what reason a statement was made.
The oldest books of the Bible breathe a warlike spirit. But Jesus said:
"Whosoever shall smite thee on thy right cheek, turn to him the other
also" (Matthew 5: 17). Here He speaks not as a lawgiver (for He did not
wish to destroy the law of Moses) but as a teacher of oppressed men in a
corrupted state, whose destruction He held to be impending. In Lamenta-
tions, Jeremiah spoke similarly in a similar situation. But only in such times
would Jesus and Jeremiah have bidden men to suffer injustice. In a good
state, they would have said the exact opposite.
C. FREEDOM OF THOUGHT
Spinoza's interest in the understanding of the Bible had its source in the
bloody conflicts over interpretation and in his rejection of all interpretations
based on authority, regardless of where they originated.
Since men are different, said Spinoza in opposition to all authoritarian
claims, each man must be granted freedom of judgment and the opportunity
to develop the foundations of his faith as he sees fit. He justifies this thesis
esteemed by all."
to which every citizen should bow, and the false authority of religious
dogmas and laws. The law of the state relates, and rightly so, to outward
actions; religion is concerned with an inner attitude, from which acts of
love and righteousness follow freely, and not through coercion.
SPINOZA 353
The laws of Moses were once state laws. They then rightly claimed public
authority. "For if the individual had the right to interpret public law as
he saw fit, do state could endure." The old Hebrew state is no more; our
states are no longer theocracies. Religion today has relevance solely to
"simplicity and trueness of heart," to love and righteousness. But "no one
can be coerced into beatitude." Instead of force, "fraternal admonition" is
dividual.
3. This free interpretation, implying also the science and criticism of
the Bible, is possible only in a free state. "In a free state every man is allowed
to think what he will and to say what he thinks." Spinoza argued this
position with passion
a) Freedom of thought is a part of the natural right of every individual,
and cannot be alienated even to the natural right of the state. For according
to the highest natural right, every man is master of his thoughts. Conse-
quently "the supreme powers will never cause men to renounce the right to
judge things as they see fit, in accordance sometimes with one and some-
times with another affect."
b) It is true that the supreme powers have the right to consider everyone
as an enemy who does not in all his actions agree with them uncondition-
ally. But government is tyranny if it extends to men's minds, that is, tries
to prescribe what each mind should accept and what it should reject as
false.
Where such laws prevail, peace becomes impossible. Where the state
authorities seek to settle quarrels among scholars by laws, conflicts arise,
not through zeal for the truth but through lust for domination. The true
breakers of the peace in a state are those who wish to destroy freedom of
judgment, which cannot be repressed.
d) Freedom of thought must be distinguished from freedom of action.
In respect to action Spinoza formulates the following fundamental situa-
tion: In a state, each man, pursuant to reason, decides once and for all to
transfer his right to act according to his own judgment to the decision of
the supreme power. To be sure, unanimous decisions are rare; "but every
decision is looked upon as a decision of the whole community, of those
who have voted against it as well as those who have voted for it." But
since in human societies the decision of all can in practice be determined
only through the majority, its application is limited. It is applicable only to
actions and not to thoughts. Moreover, each decision is made with the
reservation "that it will be modified if something better should appear."
Those who are outvoted comply in their actions, not in their thoughts.
Accordingly, a state must be so governed "that men whose opinions are
openly at variance may nevertheless live in harmony."
But Spinoza sets limits to the free expression of opinion. Freedom of
faith and freedom to philosophize remain unrestricted. But it should be
determined what opinions in the state are "subversive" to the state order
and the freedom of all, or, in other words, to what extent each man can be
allowed the freedom to speak without prejudice to the peace of the state.
Unrestricted freedom of thought and hence of speech is permitted each
man only on condition "that he speak or teach simply and with the sole
help of reason, but not put forward his opinion with deception, anger,
and hatred." The restriction of affective speech is no less necessary than
freedom of rational speech for the preservation of peace.
Science and philosophy were for Spinoza, as for all the thinkers of his time
(and for many even today), the same. Spinoza spoke in the name of the
one which through natural reason presupposes, and tries to find,
science,
one truth that is valid for all reason. But Spinoza is doing two very different
things when on the one hand he employs the methods of science, interpreted
as universally valid knowledge, to attack the assertions of the theologians
and this power is indeed inescapable for every thinking man (when, for
only in science. But this agreement does not apply to men in their whole
being; it resides only in an everywhere identical, abstract area of understand-
ing, which is removed from the richness of life or rather does away with it:
men, for example, are agreed as to the rules governing the atomic process,
but this does not prevent them from dropping atom bombs on each other's
cities. It is a mistake to suppose that science brings men together. A very
different matter is which wholly permeates man's being, which
the reason
is the medium of each man's irreplaceable existence, the reason which is
but in order that through understanding he may gain for himself the
greatest possible scope, clarity, and certainty; for this reason does not aspire
to level and destroy.
Spinoza regarded philosophy as one, and this knowable by reason
one as
and exclusively true. In this belief, he confused it He was
with science.
able to convince certain critics (Jacobi, Lichtenberg) that if reason were the
foundation of all life, it could lead only to Spinozism. This is a philosoph-
ical fallacy. In the study and acquisition of Spinoza we must differentiate:
i. Where he is dealing with scientific questions, he is fundamentally
right, though not in detail. Even this is valid only for those who strive
without restriction for science, who regard a bond with scientific possibili-
ties as the condition of all integrity, who take an affirmative attitude toward
science and find human dignity in pursuing it. Those who are unwilling
cannot be convinced, because they close themselves off from thought and
communication is broken; there is nothing for it but to leave them to
themselves. Unconditional support of scientific truth is an element of philo-
sophical faith. In this respect Spinoza is one of the long line of men who
have worked for knowable truth against error. This attitude has given rise
to great transformations in our world view (Copernicus; the discovery of
the whole earth, the discovery of other, entirely different men; realistic
history and its extension over unknown millennia). Where such changes
are felt to be unbearable, the old truths that they put in jeopardy cannot be
356 The Original Thinners
thinker, but which once formulated is not universally valid for all.
that their opposition to the theology of any church takes two fundamentally
different forms. Science opposes theology insofar as it makes statements
about realities in the world or hands down supposedly logical demonstra-
tions, which in both cases can be compellingly refuted to the satisfaction
of every thinking mind. In this realm theology regularly gets the worst of
the argument and tends to adapt itself. Philosophy also opposes theology,
but not in reference to particular positions; what philosophy attacks is the
authority of its ground. While in the first case better knowledge triumphs
over ignorance, in the second case philosophical faith opposes ecclesiastical-
authoritarian faith. When philosophical faith, which gains self-certainty in
thinking from the source, takes itself for and soon
science, it is in error
comes into a position of inferiority to theology. When it understands itself
on the basis of its own origin, it holds its ground. But then there are not
two adversaries, one of whom must triumph; there is a living polarity, in-
herent in the possibilities of human existence. The independence of science
is always particular, relating to the knowledge of those objects that are
within its reach. The independence of philosophy is total, relating to the
quest for the source of metaphysical and ethical knowledge. The independ-
ence of knowledge might be reconciled with authoritarian theo-
scientific
logical knowledge; but the same can hardly apply to the independence of
philosophical faith once its twofold nature has become clear. An example of
magnificent original naivete is Anselm; the first great example of a truly
modern philosophical independence is Spinoza.
When orthodox faith and Spinoza's rational insight are considered on
—
the same plane on the plane of faith, for on no other is such a comparison
justified —
we see that conflict is inevitable. But a consequence of their diver-
gent origins is that not only their methods of discussion but also their
existential implications in the conflict with violence are fundamentally dif-
ferent. Philosophical faith gives battle only intellectually, its attitude toward
violence is defensive; theological faith makes offensive use of violence.
Failing to suspect the difference between science and philosophy and
hence the ground of his philosophical faith, which he identified with scien-
SPINOZA 357
tific evidence, Spinoza looked upon his philosophy not as the best but as
the only true philosophy. This is why he takes such a resolute stand against
scepticism, which he rejects as pusillanimity. But skepticism can have two
meanings: it can mean doubt in the objective and universal validity of
philosophical truth, and then it is not pusillanimity, but the force of faith,
which has achieved self-awareness by drawing a distinction between scien-
tifically valid statements on the one hand and philosophical statements on
the other. Or skepticism can be a doubt in the reliability of our scientific
knowledge; in this case it is a force for improved methods in specific
sacrificium intellectus is exacted, that is, where the mind is called upon to
submit to something that is an absurdity for any thinking man. Here the
consequence can only be a common bond in the absurd (while it lasts) or
a break in communication. Discussion has become impossible. Men behave
358 The Original Thinners
as though they were no longer men, that is, thinking beings —and this while
invoking something which they assert to be the will of God.
Philosophical discussion requires "correctness" as an indispensable instru-
ment; it operates with scientific knowledge, but aim is something
its essential
else. The communication with
truth of one possible existence enters into
another. How this can come about it is hard to explain, for there is no
great concrete example in history (except in Plato and Kant, and even so
their vision of a community was never realized in practice)
Spinoza could not seek such communication; he was not aware of com-
munication as a task, because he thought himself to be in possession of the
true and explicit philosophy.
SPINOZA AS A SCIENTIST
Boyle had discovered by new methods, and it was in this manner that he
made his own fruitless experiments in connection with Boyle's problem.
To be sure, Spinoza understood the endlessness of investigation in the
world of modes, stressed our enduring ignorance, and left room for all
the new knowledge But his false method of dis-
that could be gained.
cussion was not in keeping with this insight. For he continued to treat
natural science as a fundamentally closed and complete body of knowledge.
Formerly it had been the Aristotelians, now it was the Baconians who
thought in this manner. His attitude was approximately that in which
Siger of Brabant defended the independence of natural science against
SPINOZA 359
yet unsuspected. While Bacon was less interested in scientific progress than
in speculations about future technological developments, Spinoza attached
little importance to the progress of science, because in his view the essential,
the fundamental, the whole was already established: like the ancients, he
confused philosophical speculation with scientific knowledge. Thus in its
basic attitude Spinoza's natural science is not science in the modern sense,
but natural philosophy.
Yet Spinoza was touched by the breath of modern science. He seems to
have had modern science in mind when he said that his method of explain-
ing the Bible differs in no way from the method of explaining nature. But in
his philosophy all this has the air of a garment that can be changed at will, or
of a means of communication which he employs without being committed
to it.
The necessity, into which reason has insight as into divine eternity, is
beings at all times. Finally, when Spinoza speaks of the "fictions of Aristotle,
Plato, or others of their ilk" and of "Aristotle's buffoonery," it is not in the
spirit of the modern sciences, but in the independent spirit of his century,
/. The importance of Biblical science for faith: Either of the two conflicting
assumptions on which Biblical exegesis is based (the Bible as the word of
God or as a literary document) can lead to a profound knowledge of the
360 The Original Thinners
Bible. In both ways it is possible to read the Bible, to study it, and to reflect
upon Both are justified in calling themselves Biblical science. But the
it. first
assumption implies an acquisition that will sustain the student's whole life,
in this belief. Most, sharing the esteem of their age for science, held that
historical knowledge of the Bible was useful to the religious reader. Others,
however, felt that historical Bible criticism is in itself an expression of un-
belief. The same assertion was made from the opposite standpoint by the
average proponents of enlightenment: science has refuted Biblical faith.
Those historical critics who regarded themselves as believers were faced with
a new question: How can faith itself be made more authentic by this new
historical knowledge?
Spinoza did not ask the question in this way. Nor could he have done
so, for the Bible criticism that he helped to found was not yet an established
discipline. He seldom seemed to respect the pious interpretation. He held it
conditions and origins and shows how the tenets of faith change, how they
gain and lose in depth. To relinquish reason is to lose your authenticity by
closing your eyes to reality. But in such an exchange both are mistaken.
Might not both ways lead to insights that can coexist in one mind without
clashing, since they relate to totally different realities, on the one hand
the eternal reality of Godon the other, the empirical reality of the
in faith,
Bible as an object of inquiry? The two conceptions of reality become in-
compatible only when confused and identified.
Spinoza neither asked this question clearly nor answered it. For one thing,
he did not clearly differentiate his own rational, philosophical interpretation
from the orthodox interpretation, and he distinguished neither of these
strictly from a scientific determination of facts or from the (always hypo-
Spinoza made such distinctions, to be sure, but he did not hold them fast
in developing his ideas.
that resides in the realm of modes —and this would include all political
determinations, limitations of God: thou shalt not make unto thyself any
graven image. In Spinoza as in the Bible, God-given reason opposes nature
gods, demigods, and demons, which vanish in the face of God's reality.
Every abasement of God is forbidden, not by any so-called enlightenment,
but by the very idea of God.
Biblical consciousness of God in philosophical form takes Bible criticism
as a historical means of approaching the source. No science of the Bible
SPINOZA 363
ing that runs through the whole Bible: the one God, in whose faith are
grounded love and justice among men, and who is the foundation of men's
peace, solely because He is.
Bible criticism teaches us to understand the contradictions that occur
throughout the Bible, either as a meaningful unity of polarities in faith or
as a consequence of the changing historical garments through which faith
has passed. A thorough knowledge makes the one God shine all
historical
the more radiantly and enables us to accept or reject the whole with greater
clarity.
live without prayer in the pure ether of thought. In this rarefied medium
he found the cool yet radiant reality of God that dominated his life. This
divine reality, manifest in pure thought, is the focal point at which all
serene, loving acceptance of the infinity which is God, inner consent, and
serene indifference toward all finite things.
But Spinoza's transcendence does not take the form of an irruption into
the world from elsewhere or of a revelation to man; it is not present as a
divine commandment or mission. Further, there is in Spinoza no absolute
ethical injunction to act in the world against the world, no unconditional
obligation, no Kantian categorical imperative; for Spinoza's freedom is
the action of reason as the natural essence of man; man is not a funda-
mentally different being, but one natural being among others. Finally,
transcendence is for Spinoza not a reference point for eternal decision; for
in his view there is no eternal decision in time, and consequently no existential
historicity.
Spinoza did not expressly reject these conceptions that we have found
lacking in him; they were simply outside his field of vision. It may reasonably
be asked, however, whether the alternative between immanence and tran-
scendence is applicable to Spinoza's thinking. For Spinoza's love of God
is not a universal love, if by universe we mean the totality of the modes.
When Spinoza says deus sive natura, he has in mind God as natura naturans,
not naturata. "It is utterly false," he writes, "to suppose that it is my intention
to equate God and nature" (taken to mean some mass or matter). By this
he means that God "does not manifest Himself outside of the world in an
imagined and represented space," but rather, as St. Paul says, that we "live
and breathe in God." The pantheist formula "One and All" (hen \ai pan)
would apply to Spinoza only if the "One" preserved its transcendence and
the "All" were not interpreted as the totality of finite things.
5. The loss of historicity: The idea of God has been embodied in two op-
posite ways.
366 The Original Thinners
the equanimity and activity of reason, both free from mythical, dogmatic,
legal ciphers. There is in Spinoza a superior truth but if this truth is to —
live, it cannot remain an empty abstraction; it must be filled with human
sustained Spinoza, where a life such as that of Jesus, where such power to
remain true to oneself in the midst of suffering, where such willingness
to draw the extreme consequence, such love, capable of every sacrifice,
such fire of the soul is not only conceived of, not only present as an echo,
a theoretical interpretation of one's own existence, but utterly real, where
men like Jesus (the Jesus of the synoptic Gospels) occur most frequently,
we may answer They are everywhere exceedingly rare, but the most striking
:
examples are among the Jews. With this in mind we shall miss in Spinoza
an eye for the Jewish soul, we shall miss the love that perceives such love.
unfathomable but also an angry and a jealous God (Thou shalt have no
other gods before me), a giver of laws. He is a terrible God. Man knows
not only the law of the day, but also the passions of the night; God is
manifested in both. But Spinoza denies the jealous God, he takes away God's
368 The Original Thinners
sting. He knows only the love, not the fear of God. He cannot understand
the execution of heretics by pious men acting out of a sense of responsibility
to God, nor does he understand the terrible purpose of the anathema ex-
cluding the godless man from the community. Spinoza seeks only appease-
ment, consolation, and happiness.
In reply to this it can be said: Spinoza perceives the hardness of necessity:
when he looks on as flies are strangled in a spider web, when he senses
the kinship between his thinking and the Calvinist theory of predestination
(though without the concept of sin). But actually Spinoza lives without
fear of the extremes whose existence he states. He rejects fear as irrational.
Fear does not lead to the truth, the goal is equanimity. This criticism
combines heterogeneous factors which have nothing in common but
their irrationality. It cannot be denied that in respect to the passions of the
night Spinoza lacks the openness of reason which, though well aware
that communication with the irrational is in all likelihood impossible,
attempts it nevertheless. In the face of the sufferings and injustices (by
human standards) of existence he is without the spirit of rebellion, which
calls peace of mind an evasion and rejects all veiling of the world's horrors.
He does not know Job's rebellion with God against God, which seeks
salvation not in peace of mind but in God's mercy.
Spinoza, this criticism goes on, disregards the Thou, man's dialogue with
God in prayer. Thus he
loses the covenant with God, which is the founda-
tion of both Jewish and Christian life, and with it the self-consciousness of
the historical person, which comes to itself only in dialogue with the
personal God.
Further, it is argued, Spinoza knows only the love of man for God, not
the love of God for man. He tried to prove that "He who loves God cannot
strive that God should love him in return." According to Spinoza, God
loves or hates no one, because He is moved by no afTects of joy or sorrow.
However, in speaking of the true love with which amor intellectualis dei
and its consequences suffuse our whole attitude toward men and the world,
he said that "God, insofar as He loves Himself, loves men and consequently
that the love of God toward men and the intellectual love of the mind
toward God are one and the same thing."
All these criticisms show a tendency to reject Spinoza. They spring, to
be sure, from the ineradicable drives of finitemen, who need the language
of ciphers and historical actuality in space and time. But man can transcend
all these in figures of thought. Spinoza's figures of thought are among the
greatest ever produced and are in turn historical.
torical process whereby the Biblical idea of God has undergone continuous
purification. In this process Spinoza, like Jesus, played a vital part as one
of the true prophets,who have taken seriously the second commandment
Thou shalt not make unto thee any graven image or any likeness — for
though it is beyond human strength to fulfill this commandment, without
the idea expressed in it every form of belief in God becomes superstition.
The Bible laid the foundations of a faith which rejects the falsehood re-
siding in a confusion or amalgamation of belief in God with belief in
sacred books, rites, cults, nations, churches, or sacraments. Spinoza was
one of the world's truly pious men.
his critics may be right in saying that Spinoza neglects the middle
Still,
links which connect man, in the finiteness of his thoughts and imaginations,
with God. Spinoza took the step to supreme transcendence whither, as he
knew, only few can follow. He did not take part in the difficult task of
helping, in the community of men, to transmit images and metaphors and
to influence the structure of life. The supreme abstraction of thought is
indeed unique. It can form a bond between all those who understand it.
It provides a horizon in which a historical embodiment can no longer be
In the course of his life Spinoza made decisions which determined his
personal destiny and were also of fundamental historical importance. The
reality of his life became a symbol by which many men in a new age have
37° The Original Thinners
to write the Ethics and the T heologico-Political Treatise. He would have be-
come what innumerable others had already been. But might he not have
waited and written his philosophy first? No, his thinking was possible
only if he could enjoy free speech and refrain from attending divine
services. And so, before any of his work came into being, he compelled
Spinoza's sober view of the nature of the state was in keeping with this
situation. His state is far from Platonic. Nor is it ecclesiastical; it has no
religious foundation, but requires, as the conditions of peace and freedom,
tolerance toward all faiths and denominations. It is not absolutist as in
372 The Original Thinners
We cannot help looking for Jewish motives in his thinking, for the influence
of Jewish religious and political sentiment on his way of life.
equate this assertion of a people's existence with a covenant which God con-
cluded with the Jews. He would not identify the sheltering certainty of
God's existence with belief in a God who gave my people and myself
guarantees for existence. Even in the face of the destruction of his own
people, he would say with Jeremiah: "The Lord saith thus: Behold, that
which I have built will I break down, and that which I have planted I will
pluck up. . . . And seekest thou great things for thyself? seek them not.
.
." Spinoza would say that in a situation of threat the concept "Jew"
.
embraced believers and unbelievers alike, who belong together because and
insofar as they are marked by demonstrable historical origin and are united
by the threat and reality of extermination.
Spinoza would see only the struggle for existence under the natural right
which alone where peoples wish to live and to live in their own
prevails,
way, and desire freedom because they are not barbarians. No people's right
is greater than its might. Peoples live by the same right as fishes the larger —
eat the smaller.
Hence there is no superordinate authority which guarantees my rights.
For right exists only in the state and through the state, as far as its might
extends. The superordinate authority is all-encompassing divine necessity,
in which everything that happens has its place. It is above all civil laws,
which are valid only in states. The particulars of this authority of divine
necessity cannot be inferred from any known natural law (for complete
knowledge is situated in the infinite). Man can only do his best and accept
what happens in accordance with the supreme authority of divine necessity.
Thus destiny remains hard and terrible and ambivalent, and Spinoza's only
response to this destiny is equanimity based on certainty of God's existence.
But philosophical insight cannot countenance the delusion that there exists
any halfway reliable superordinate authority to guarantee right. All argu-
ments seeking to derive a right without might are mere self-deception. They
inspire the mightless with feelings of resentment, unjustified because based
on the principle of a nonexistent superior right, through which the impotent
expect to gain prestige and power. Or on the side of the mighty, eager to
increase their momentary power, such arguments encourage an unwarranted
belief in a principle of legitimacy based on superior value (race, election,
descent from the gods). They strive to enhance their real power by marking
its holders with a character of eternal superiority and merit. Both delusions
blind those who harbor them to the realities which in both cases are those
of natural right, and so cause both the mighty and the mightless to neglect
the measures necessary to the assertion of their existence. Such self -exaltation
induces confusion through inadequate ideas, or affects, and invariably leads
to disaster.
2. Spinoza on the Jews. But Spinoza himself spoke of the destiny of the
Jews. This is his view:
Moses established the Hebrew state by his covenant with God. "God alone
374 The Original Thinkers
held dominion over the Hebrews, whose state, by virtue of the covenant,
was called God's kingdom, and God was said to be their king; conse-
quently the enemies of the Jews were said to be the enemies of God, and the
citizens who tried to seize the dominion were guilty of treason against
God; and, lastly, the laws of the state were called the laws and command-
ments of God. . Civil and religious authority were one and the same.
. .
The dogmas of religion were not precepts, but laws and ordinances. . . .
Anyone who fell away from religion ceased to be a citizen and on that
ground alone was accounted an enemy." This specific historical condition
had extraordinary consequences for the inner attitude of the Hebrews.
"The love of the Hebrews for their country was not mere patriotism, but
also piety, and was cherished and nurtured by daily rites until, like their
hatred of other nations, it must have passed into their nature." Not only
was the daily cult of the Hebrews entirely different from the cults of other
peoples; it was also directed against them. "Such daily reprobation naturally
gave rise to a lasting hatred, deeply implanted in the heart: For of all
hatreds none is more deep and tenacious than that which springs from
extreme devoutness of piety, and is itself cherished as pious." Other peoples
responded with hatred to the hatred of the Jews, which was thus further en-
hanced.
Spinoza believed the situation of the Jews to be entirely different in his
day. Since the loss of their state, he held, the Hebrews exist only through
their religion. "Today, there is absolutely nothing that Jews can arrogate to
themselves beyond other nations." "As to their continuance so long after
dispersion and the loss of empire, there is nothing marvelous in it, for they
so separated themselves from every other nation as draw down upon
to
themselves universal hate, not only by their outward rites, which conflict
with those of other nations, but also by the sign of circumcision which they
most scrupulously observe." Spinoza regarded the sign of circumcision as
"so important that I could persuade myself that it alone would preserve
the nation for ever."
He believed that he could prove by the events in Spain and Portugal that
the chief reason for the survival of Jewry was the hatred of other peoples:
"When the King of Spain compelled the Jews to embrace the state religion
or go into exile, a large number of Jews accepted Catholicism. Now, as
these renegades were admitted to all the native privileges of Spaniards and
deemed worthy to fill all honorable offices, they soon became so inter-
mingled with the Spaniards as to leave of themselves no relic or remem-
brance. But exactly the opposite happened to those whom the King of
Portugal compelled to become Christians, for they always, though converted,
lived apart, for they were considered unworthy of civic honors."
Spinoza understands the "election" of the Jewish people as applying only
to their native country and material welfare. "If anyone wishes to maintain
that the Jews, from this or from any other cause, have been chosen by God
SPINOZA 375
tor over, I will not gainsay him if he will admit that this choice, whether
temporary or eternal, has no regard, insofar as it is peculiar to the Jews, to
anything but dominion and physical advantages (for by such alone can one
nation be distinguished from another), whereas in regard to intellect and
true virtue, every nation is on a par with the rest, and God has not in these
respects chosen one people rather than another." But today, says Spinoza,
they have lost the land of Palestine. Their election is suspended. Yet Spinoza
thought the Jews would probably survive. "I would go so far as to believe
that if the foundations of their religion have not emasculated their minds
they may even, if occasion offers, so changeable are human affairs, raiseup
their empire afresh, and that God may a second time elect them."
Jews than any other of the countries overrun by Hitler with the exception —
of Italy.
4. Spinoza's abandonment of his bond with Jewry. The Jews, but not
Spinoza, lived by the covenant which their people had made with God
through Moses, which gave them confidence that insofar as they obeyed
God they would, as the chosen people, find happiness also in earthly ex-
istence. They interpreted the calamities that struck them as God's punishment
for disobedience and questioned themselves as to their guilt. But then it
the knot, but gives satisfaction by the mere fact that He is. We may ask Is :
is innate in all men. Spinoza also recognized the historical and political
function of revelation, but he did not presuppose revelation on the strength
of his own belief. Spinoza submitted Judaism, as he did all things human,
such as Christianity and the state, to the highest authority, that of philosoph-
ical reason.
thought expresses the absolute and is itself authentic reality, this thought
is amor intellectualis dei and as such beatitude. This thought is freedom
its completion as reason in the third class of knowledge, in the free specula-
tion of loving intuition. Such thinking was bound to be more than the
compelling logical thought which on the surface it always remained.
Spinoza transcended thought, insofar as thought is taken as a universally
valid operation with fixed concepts. His thinking is a new form of the
age-old philosophical contemplation which is an inner action and shapes
the whole man.
We have encountered Spinoza's mode of fundamental certainty, built on
rational proofs. Let us recapitulate in Spinoza's own words: "Once I am
in possession of a reliable proof, I cannot fall back into such ideas as ever to
make me doubt this proof. Consequently I am perfectly satisfied with what
my understanding shows me, without the least anxiety that I might have
been mistaken in it. . . . And even if I should once mistakenly invent the
fruit that I have gained from my natural understanding, it would still
make me happy, because I strive to spend my life not in sorrow and grief,
but in peace, joy, and serenity, and so up by degrees. In so doing I rise
recognize (and this is what gives me the and peace of greatest satisfaction
mind) that everything so happens through the power of the most perfect
being and of His immutable decision."
Spinoza lived and thought on the basis of the fundamental certainty for
which God's reality is present in the third class of knowledge as the one
all-embracing reality. Starting from this reality, Spinoza takes three courses
in the world: to metaphysical knowledge, to personal existence, to the
political order. In the language of the second class of knowledge, he develops
without the security of authority and revealed faith, without any misleading
concessions to the powers of the time. He was the great, truly independent
thinker representative of the Occident, who found in philosophy what
churchgoers called their faith. In him was renewed the independence of
philosophy, which has no need of ecclesiastical faith, because it is itself faith.
because he is certain of it before all else. He does not rise up from the world
(through investigation pressed to the limits) to derive the ground. Nor
is it only in extreme situations that he glimpses a cipher of Being, which
provides us with a wavering light. Before all investigation of things and
all experience of the failure of thought in extreme situations, he is sheltered
in the all-embracing reality of God.
Through certainty of God, this philosophical religion of Spinoza brings
peace, joy, acceptance of everything that is. "Insofar as we understand that
God is the cause of sorrow, we rejoice." From the consciousness of necessity
arises the serenity which demands nothing. Amor intellectualis dei leads to
Nietzsche's amor jati: to desire nothing to be different from what it is.
From the very beginning, from his first utterance, this miraculous peace is
present, this purity of soul, this freedom from purpose even in his volition.
Spinoza's philosophy means the self-assertion of the individual through
his experience of God, it means independence of the world through security
in the ground of all things. This self-assertion is not individualist pre-
occupation with his own no inclination toward egocentric
existence; there is
reflection, but instead the most perfect devotion, in reason, to God. Nor does
it mean withdrawal into his own existence from the reality of human
society; his interest in mankind was just as great as but no greater than —
his interest in his own existence.
Thinking oriented toward the well-being of the individual and political
thinking go hand in hand. But here there is no cult either of the state or of
the individual. The realities of practical life are seen with sobriety. But this
sobriety itself springs from amor intellectualis dei, which does not allow
380 The Original Thinners
him to set anything else in God's place or to forget the hierarchical orders
of reality, but compels him to keep always in mind the all-embracing eternal
reality.
_?. Caution and solitude. From the very beginning Spinoza's philosophy
was ethos. This is attested by the explanation that he gave in his youth for
his decision to takeup philosophy, and by the title of his main work, the
Ethics. We have tried to show the depth of this ethos. It includes features
that do not spring from Spinoza's innate being but are a consequence of
Spinoza's contact with the world.
God that was present in Spinoza's whole
Caution: Despite the love of
view of the world, despite the benevolence he felt toward every man he
met, Spinoza also felt keen distrust; for he knew the reality of the world.
Hence his caution without defiance or blame.
Spinoza gave freely of himself but did not squander his strength: he
was on his guard against negligence, and reasonably so, for he knew the
harm that can spring from it.
He renounced all idea of fame. Even academic activity involved too much
danger in those days, and so he declined it. He delayed publication of his
works, but he wrote them without haste — —in the hope of broadening
the scope of reason in the world.
Not a recluse, but solitary: Spinoza was formerly regarded as a recluse.
The studies of the last half-century have exploded this legend. Not only
was Spinoza in touch, through friends and acquaintances, with the whole
cultural world of Europe, but he also took part in political activity. There
was nothing of the eccentric about him; wherever he went his bearing was
easy, natural, noble; he was not only respected, but loved as well.
It is a different matter to say that Spinoza was a solitary man. In his
philosophizing he gained a "standpoint outside," in God, and he did not
relate his philosophy to worldly affairs. On the one hand he was perfectly
many
independent thanks to his certainty of God, on the other hand he had
human contacts which sufficed him, but did not take away his solitude.
The consequence is that for us Spinoza seems to lack the love which
unites men in their uniqueness, which through companionship and com-
munity of destiny leads to unconditional historical commitment. Spinoza
was always himself. And what he thought and set forth was the universal,
the cool but utterly satisfying realm of thought, the amor intellectualis dei,
which was his life itself in its highest aspect, in reason. In conversation
Spinoza must have been very different from Kant or Max Weber, for ex-
ample. His almost superhuman calm would elate us. Imperturbable in all
situations, he would speak from the standpoint of eternal truth. He would
not concern himself seriously with actual realities, but pass them over as
nonessential. We should sit in silence, increasingly aware of our own re-
belliousness against fate.
SPINOZA 381
it.
it was able to carry him off at any early age, but not to affect his nature).
5. The ideas that Spinoza borrowed. The origin of nearly all Spinoza's
ideas can be determined: from the Stoics he took his attitude of equanimity
based on reason, from the Bible the one God, from Scholasticism such
concepts as substance, attribute, mode, of natura naturans and natura naturata,
from Giordano Bruno the infinity of the cosmos, from him and Leo
Hebraeus the doctrine of Eros, from Bacon empirical method and the re-
jection of prejudices, from Descartes the distinction between extension and
thought and his regard for mathematical certainty, from Machiavelli and
Hobbes his political thinking. It might appear as though Spinoza's entire
thinking could be derived from someone else. But Spinoza's thinking is
authentic and spontaneous, and his highly original work fused all these
rationally definable elements into the language of the One. The totality
of this thinking, the fundamental insight, is present from the first. There
is development only insofar as the figures of thought are imperceptibly
modified, more richly elaborated, clarified and purified. There are no breaks
or reversals.
It has been said that with Spinoza for the first time reason stands on its
own foundation. But this had long been the case in the "science," the
"critique" and "unbelief," that characterize the Renaissance. Spinoza had
little in common with this aggressive independence, which for the most
part was poor in faith. His thinking was more a continuation of ancient
philosophical reason, now clothed in the garments of modern science and
critique, and constructed as metaphysical reason. The meaning and aim
but all these, yet in the service of the One which alone is important, of cer-
tainty in God and ethical practice, of the true good.
If we wish to understand Spinoza, we must make no mistake. His
foundation is not that of modern science whose nature and method he
did not really know (even though the sciences received powerful impulses
from certain of his insights, such as his idea of an infinite, never to be
completed progression whereby we gain knowledge of the modes in their
endless multiplicity and his insistence on freedom from values). He him-
self was not a scientist and did not possess the scientist's immense capacity
for factual knowledge. Spinoza was blind to the special character of exact
science and hence ignored it. He did not base his philosophizing on mathe-
matics, even though he employed a supposedly mathematical method of
expounding it. He was also a stranger to the spirit of construction, which
made Hobbes and Leibniz such great builders and so inventive. Though
all these thinkers provided him with ideas, these ideas were incorporated
into his metaphysics. It is great because it is authentic and one with his
life. He thought necessity in rational concepts subservient to the intuition
of his third class of knowledge. He is the only great metaphysician of
modern times; both in his life and in his work, his style is simple, clear,
convincing — and inimitable.
B. Spinoza s limitations
ligion be conceived and actually constructed in order that the wise man
may be unmolested in his private life? Epicureans and skeptics may have
looked at the state in this light, but neither Plato nor Spinoza. They did
not seek to guarantee the security of the philosopher by showing that
philosophy and politics are incommensurable and advising philosophers to
SPINOZA 383
withdraw from the world (except in particular times and under particular
circumstances). They are concerned, rather, with philosophical politics over
against blind politics; they have in mind all men and aspire to a state in
which all will obtain their proper place and right according to their gifts,
insight, and aflectivity. The impulse which has been mistaken as a striving
for the philosopher's security (which can be safeguarded only by private
caution) is rather the impulse to promote reason in the world.
Another criticism is that Spinoza's "Being" is geometrical and static,
2. The limits of reason. Spinoza's limits are the limits of reason. Because
Spinoza does not seem to see the limits of reason, perhaps reality as a whole
is closed to him. This is where the profoundest criticism of Spinoza sets in.
The limits of reason can be seen by reason itself. Spinoza seems to have
an inkling of this when, in speaking of the infinity of the modes, he says
that our ignorance of the endlessness of finite relationships is everlasting
and that so many — in fact, nearly all — particulars are incomprehensible to
us. But this ignorance is only a consequence of finiteness. In principle,
knowledge of these matters is possible, because everything comes from God
and is rational.
Spinoza seems to see beyond reason still more clearly when he considers
that all our reason is encompassed in divine necessity and represents our
human reason as helplessly at the mercy of the necessity of all nature, which
it is powerless to understand. But Spinoza seems to take it for granted that
this necessity is also divinely rational. The irrational only appears to be
irrational to our finite understanding. The encompassing God is not a dark
abyss. He is not accessible by any obscure ways, but only through the light
of reasonitself, which if it could overcome its bond with the limited mode
reason, source of reason but also of everything else. God in Spinoza is reason
itself. His consciousness of God does not transcend reason.
Thus convinced of the absoluteness of reason, Spinoza anticipated a day
when all men would necessarily unite in reason a grandiose assumption, —
but only in reference to practical endeavor, not as an insight into the
universe and mankind as a whole.
Another aspect of Spinoza's belief in the absoluteness of reason was the
pure, passionless joy of his awareness of God. To him freedom was freedom
from affects, pure unclouded clarity, beatitude. Freedom is not decision,
not the basis of destiny.
Finally, Spinoza's rationalism made him despise all feelings of wonder-
ment. A reasoning man tries to understand the things of nature "with wis-
dom," "not to gape at them like a fool." "If ignorance is removed, amaze-
ment is also taken away." Amazement becomes harmful when it induces
blind subjection to authority, miracles, and supernatural forces.
the inner action of loving ascent to God. Spinoza knows necessity, but he
does not know uncertainty, hope, and failure in the active historicity of
Existenz. Time is effaced, but it should also be preserved, because without
it there can be no true consciousness of eternity. There can be no historicity
in a life which moves from metaphysics to metaphysics without striking
meaningful roots in temporal reality. Historicity is absent when activity is
limited to reasonable thinking without a driving will, when the great ven-
ture of reason is not experienced as historical destiny. Consequently Spinoza
is not attracted by the depth and grandeur which (as in the Jewish Prophets)
are still obscure and demand that a man venture all and sacrifice all.
Wholly taken up by pure reason as the type of human being and of all
being, he is blind to the passions of the night, which to him are mere irra-
tional affects. He is blind to evil.
Spinoza rejected not only the anticipation of an actual Messiah and the
corresponding expectation of a second coming of Christ as religious im-
aginations incompatible with philosophical reason, but also the cipher of
Messianic thinking. He had no passion to work actively for the transforma-
tion of the world. He knew no hope of a better world grounded in human
responsibility. A man who lives in eternity cannot live in the future. God
is immutable and His actions are themselves eternal. Immutable is the
existence of the infinite modes,though within the unchanging whole all
modes are subject to perpetual change.
the finite
c) Spinoza knows no extreme situations. He knows no abyss of terror,
no despair in the face of the void, no struggle with God, no power of the
absurd manifested to reason itself as no absolutely
a positive possibility,
hidden mystery. His peace is in the positive immensity that is God. But
God is seen only in reason and as reason — all horror is reduced to mere
inadequate ideas, the irrational, antirational, suprarational are simply thrust
aside. And yet they leave man no peace. His certainty in the ground of all
X. SPINOZA'S INFLUENCE
What carries conviction is not the abstract thought, but the reality lived
with this thought. What appeals to us in Spinoza's work is not his solution
of so-called objective problems, but the power of philosophical striving
for certainty. Men's reactions to Spinoza, as to no other philosopher of
modern times, were determined by the philosopher he really was. No other
aroused so much warm affection and so much bitter hatred. The name of
no other has so unique a ring, no other has been so despised and so loved
by Christians and Jews alike. He became almost a mythical figure. No one
who knows him can remain indifferent to him, for in connection with
Spinoza even expressions of indifference mask a self-protective aggressive-
ness.
Spinoza had no "school." There have been no Spinozists among pro-
fessorsof philosophy in the sense that there have been Cartesians and
Leibnizians. But a furious distaste resulted in incomprehensible injustices
and misrepresentations, even on the part of Bayle, who effectively distorted
the image of Spinoza for many years to come. Spinoza was the "ill-famed
Jew" (Leibniz), he was a "miserable atheist," "a malignant spirit," a
"ridiculous chimera" (Malebranche). Down to the second half of the
eighteenth century nearly all those who mentioned the name of Spinoza
were immediately at pains to disavow him. With few exceptions no one
wanted to be associated with him. Even Brucker (1767) speaks of the
"scandalous success of Spinoza's godlessness."
Spinoza was first taken up by a few pastors of the Dutch Reformed
Church, by mystics, and among artisans in "a movement which stirred up
the Dutch people and aroused the Church, and whose after-effects extended
into the nineteenth century" (Freudenthal). As late as 1862 there are reports
SPINOZA 387
of small groups "in which Spinozist mysticism is the only balm of the soul."
But Spinoza's great influence was on German philosophy and literature.
Lessing, Herder, Goethe held him in high esteem. Goethe: "I feel very close
to him although his mind was far deeper and purer than mine" (1784).
"The figures of this world pass; I should like to concern myself only with
the lasting relationships, and so, in accordance with the teachings of Spinoza,
gain eternity for my (from Rome, 1787). As late as 1817 he said that
spirit"
the two men who had most influenced him were Shakespeare and Spinoza.
Spinoza, in whom he found "boundless selflessness," gave him "appease-
ment and clarity."
Kant was scarcely touched by Spinoza, whose work he hardly knew. But
German philosophy after Kant was equally influenced by Kant and Spi-
noza. Jacobi (1785) believed that only Spinoza's philosophy was consistent
and thus exposed error and inadequacy. Lichtenberg said the same in a
positive sense: "The universal religion will be purified Spinozism. Left to
itself, reason can lead nowhere else" (1901). Fichte was fascinated by the
great objects of philosophy and showed the greatest regard for him as long
as he lived. Hegel regarded Spinoza as absolutely indispensable. "Every
thinker must have taken the standpoint of Spinozism, that is the essential
beginning of all philosophizing." "Either Spinozism or no philosophy."
Kindled by Spinoza, the philosophy of German idealism turned against him.
The influence of Spinoza's Biblical science is without philosophical im-
portance. Actually, few of the theologians who have raised the historical
study of the Bible to such magnificent heights ever mention him. Johannes
Muller, the physiologist, included a translation of Spinoza's theory of the
afreets in his once famous Hand buck der Physiologie des Menschen (1833-
40), but despite this evidence of admiration for Spinoza, he did not make
use of his analysis in his own work. Certain psychologists of the nineteenth
century mistakenly traced their sterile theory of psycho-physical parallelism
back to Spinoza. Here again we cannot speak of a philosophical influence.
LAO-TZU
said to have lived in the sixth century b.c. (the traditional view, for this
alone would make possible the conversations between him and Confucius,
which others put down as legendary), but other traditions place him in the
fifth (Forke) or even the fourth century. The question will probably never
tradition.
The authorship of the Tao Te Ching and the authenticity of certain parts
have been contested. However, its inner cohesion is so convincing that
despite possible interpolations and distortions —one cannot doubt that it was
created by a thinker of the highest rank. The man seems to stand before us
and speak to us.
Tao Te Ching, the Book of Tao and Te, is a work of maxims of varying
length, divided into eighty-one short chapters. The arrangement follows no
one system. Sometimes, as toward the end of the "political" section, there
are groups of connected chapters. The essential is stated at the very be-
ginning and then recurs in richly meaningful amplifications. Although there
is no argumentative development, only aphoristic statement of the com-
same idea in numerous modifications gives a
plete thought, repetition of the
388
LAO-TZU 389
Tao is and goal of the world and all things, hence also of the
the origin
thinker. The philosophy
tells us first, what Tao is; secondly, how all being
proceeds from it and moves toward it; thirdly, how man lives in Tao, how
he can lose it and regain it, both as an individual and in a political society.
Thus in Western terms, it deals with metaphysics, cosmogony, ethics, and
politics. In Lao-tzu all these are one in the all-pervading fundamental idea.
In a single short chapter all four elements can appear at once. While in an
exposition we must differentiate these factors and treat them successively, in
the book as in the philosophy they are one fundamental idea. An exposition
can be considered successful if it conveys an awareness of this fundamental
unity.
1. The Tao
Penetrating to the remotest depths, the book begins: "The Tao that can be
told of is not the eternal Tao; the name that can be named is not the eternal
name. The Nameless is the origin of Heaven and Earth" (1). In these lines
390 The Original Thinners
the author declares not only all over-hasty knowledge, but in general the
mode of knowledge with which man approaches finite things, to be inappli-
cable to the Tao. "I do not know its name; I call it Tao" (25).
If we are to speak of it, it can only be in negative statements (as in saying
that it is unnamable, that is, inaccessible to human naming). For example:
"We look at it and do not see it; Its name is The Invisible. We listen to it and
do not hear it; Its name is The Inaudible. We touch it and do not find it; Its
shape we can understand. "This is called shape without shape, form without
objects. It is The Vague and Elusive. Meet it and you will not see its head.
Follow it and you will not see its back" (14).
What for usbecomes an object is finite: for us and defini-
differentiation
tion constitute being. A rectangle is by virtue of its by virtue
angles, a vessel
of its image by virtue of its
content, an form. But when an object becomes
infinite and undifferentiated like the Tao, it loses its distinctness, ceases to
be what it was when differentiated. Thus to think of an object that has be-
come infinite can guide us to the thinking of the Tao; Lao-tzu says:
"The great square has no corners. The great implement (or talent) is slow
to finish (or mature). Great music sounds faint. Great form has no shape"
(41)-
Insofar as being is what we see, hear, and grasp, insofar as it is image
and form, Tao is nothing. Only in the Tao that is free from being is the
source attained. This source is not nothing in the sense of not-at-all, but in
the sense of more-than-being, whence come existing things: "And being
comes to nonbeing" (40).
Nonbeing is the source and aim of all being. In itself it is essential
being and as such beyond being. After such statements by negation about
this nonbeing a load of seemingly positive statements is put upon it. Tao is
unchanging. "It depends on nothing and does not change" (25). It does not
age (30, 55). Tao is dependent on itself, while man, earth, heaven, and all
things outside of the Tao are dependent on something else (25). Tao is
repose (25).
But the repose of Tao cannot be the opposite of motion; for then it would
be merely negative, less than being. Tao moves, but in motion it is at the
same time at rest; its motion is "reversion" (40). It moves, but not because
it wishes to attain something that it is not and has not, for Tao is without
need, "without desires" (34, 37).
In Lao-tzu's day Tao was already a traditional concept. The original mean-
LAO-TZU 391
ing of the word was "Way"; then it came to mean the order of the cosmos
and, what was seen as identical, the right conduct of man. It has been trans-
lated as reason, logos, God, meaning, right way, etc. It has even been
interpreted as a personalized deity, either female or male.
Lao-tzu gave the word a new meaning. He used it as a name for the
ground of all being, although the ground of being is as such nameless and
unnamable. Using this word, he transcended everything that was called
being, including the universe, and even the Tao as cosmic order. He re-
tained, to be sure, the concept of cosmic being and the idea of its all-per-
vading order, but both of these are rooted in the transcendent Tao.
Tao antecedes the world, hence antecedes all differentiation. It can neither
be confronted with anything else nor can it be in itself differentiated. In it,
separate and opposed in the world are one before the world; identical are
the law according to which everything happens and the law according
to which everything ought to happen; identical are the order that has
been from all eternity and the order that remains to be ushered in by
true ethical action. But this unity of opposites cannot at the same time
be a particular reality in the world nor can it be the whole of the world. It
remains the source of the world and the goal of the world. To become
world means to separate and to be differentiated, it means cleavage and
opposition.
For us the multiplicity of things in the world results from separation and
opposition. Tao is called empty, because it is undifferentiated, without ob-
ject, without opposition, because it is not world. In fulfilling itself, Tao
posits objects, produces the world. But Tao itself is never filled in this way
(4). If it could be filled by the created world, it would become one with it.
Itwas before Heaven and Earth came into being (25); it was even before
Ti, theLord on High, the supreme god of the Chinese (4). But Tao is not
something inaccessible and totally other, it is present. Imperceptible, it can
nevertheless be experienced as the true being in all being. Present in all
things, it is that from which all things, whatever they may be, derive their
a. // is present as nonbeing: Eye, ear, hand seek the Tao in vain, but it is
utility of the vessel depends on the empty space which it contains and the
utility of the house depends on the emptiness of doors and windows (n).
Thus the nothingness of Tao is the nonbeing that first gives things being.
It is comparable to something that would permeate even the most mas-
sive and unporous body: "Nonbeing penetrates that in which there is no
space" (43). Because it is like nothingness, no existing thing resists it.
"Though its simplicity seems insignificant, none in the world can master
it" (32). "It operates everywhere and is free from danger" (25).
b. // acts as though not acting: "Tao invariably takes no action, and yet
there is nothing left undone" (37). It acts imperceptibly as though power-
less. "Weakness is the function of Tao" (40). Tao is infinitely active because
it produces all things, but it acts with discreet quietness that does nothing.
Although Tao is the superior power that produces all things, it leaves all
things free, as though each thing were what it is not through Tao but
through itself. Hence the worship of Tao is instilled in all beings by their
origin, but each being is left free to worship according to his own essence:
"Tao is worshiped not by command but spontaneously" (51). Tao brings
about the free compliance of beings: "For it is the way of Heaven not to
strive but none the less to conquer; not to speak but none the less to get an
answer; not to beckon; yet things come to it of themselves" (73).
Tao is able to move beings without constraint because it makes itself dis-
appear in their presence, as though it did not act and had never acted.
It "produces but does not appropriate, it acts but does not rely (on the
result), and raises (beings) without lording it over them" (51). "It accom-
plishes its task, but does not claim credit for it. It clothes and feeds all
and blends with the surroundings: "It blunts its sharpness, subdues its
c. Tao is the source of the One within all oneness: All things have being
insofar as they are held by the bond of oneness, of the One, which is the
productive form of the Tao, not one as a number, but Oneness as essence.
"Of old those One: Heaven obtained the One and became
that obtained the
clear. One and became tranquil. The spiritual beings
Earth obtained the
obtained the One and became divine. The valley obtained the One and be-
came full. The myriad things obtained the One and lived and grew. Kings
and barons obtained the One and became rulers of the empire" (39).
d. All existence derives its being from Tao: "It is bottomless, perhaps the
ancestor of all things!" (4). "It may be considered as the mother of the uni-
verse" (25). All things owe their preservation to this father —or mother.
"Tao gave them birth; the power of Tao reared them . . . developed them"
LAO-TZU 393
(51). Without Tao all things are lost; but "it does not turn away from them"
(34). "The essence is very real; in it are evidences" (21).
E. Tao is beyond good and evil but is infinitely helpful: All beings without
exception, both good and evil, have their being through Tao; in it they have
their foundation, hence a kind of permanence. "Tao is the storehouse of all
things. It is good man's treasure and the bad man's refuge" (62).
the
Though termed love, faith, reliability, Tao is not moved by human com-
passion, it prefers no one and does not take sides. This is shown in the image
of the cosmos; the coming and going of all things is endless and vain:
"How Heaven and Earth are like a bellows! While vacuous, it is never ex-
hausted. When active, it produces even more" (5). The cosmos is indif-
ferent to individuals: "Heaven and Earth are not humane. They regard all
things as straw dogs" (5). "The Way of Heaven has no favorites. It is
always with the good man" (79). "The Way of Heaven is to benefit others
and not to injure" (81).
Thus the principal signs of the existence of Tao in the world were all-
pervading nonbeing, the imperceptible nonaction that accomplishes all things,
the all-producing power of oneness, the power beyond good and evil which
sustains the beings "that come and go."
Lao-tzu strives to go beyond his vision of Tao in the world to the cosmo-
gonic process, to the riddle: Why did the world spring from Tao? But he
merely hinted at such speculation, he did not develop it constructively. He
did not ask why Nor did he ask how things strayed from the
the world is.
a. There are two Taos, which were originally one: First the Tao that is not
namable, nonbeing, and secondly, the Tao that can be named, or being. The
unnamable Tao is called "origin of Heaven and Earth," the namable is
called the "mother of the ten thousand things" (1). This "mother" is being:
"All things in the world come from being" (40); nonbeing has no name:
"And being comes from nonbeing" (40). The Tao is not namable as such
but only as manifested in being. The emergence of things from the namable
Tao is itself the ever-recurring genesis of the namable: "As soon as Tao be-
gins to create and to order, it has a name. Once the block is carved there
will be names, and as soon as there are names they will be known" (32).
394 The Original Thinners
Both the unnamable and the namable Tao, nonbeing and being, "are the
same, but after they are produced, they have different names" (i). Viewing
the unnamable through the namable, thought penetrates to the unfathom-
able: "They both may be called deep and profound" (i).
Elsewhere the cosmogonic process is outlined as follows: "Tao produced
the One. The One produced The two produced the three. And
the two. the
three produced the ten thousand things. The ten thousand things carry the
yin and embrace the yang, and through the blending of the material force
they achieve harmony" (42).
b. The productive Tao bears within it the elements of being, which may
be conceived of as forms, images, substances, or forces: "Eluding and vague,
in it are things. Deep and obscure, in it is the essence. The essence is very
real; in it are evidences" (21).
"The All-embracing quality of the great virtue follows alone from the
Tao" (21). High virtue, authentic life (te), is unison with Tao. Only with
Tao can man follow the right path. Thus the salient characteristics of the
—
Tao action through nonaction, being through nonbeing, strength through
softness —
will reappear in the True Man.
But man does not, like nature, follow the Tao by necessity: man can fall
away from Tao; most men have already done so, but they can again become
one with the Tao.
a. The from Tao: intention and self-striving: The original fall from
fall
"The man of superior virtue is not (conscious of) his virtue, and in this
way he really possesses virtue. The man of inferior virtue never loses (sight
of) his virtue, and in this way he loses his virtue" (38). In other words, what
I pursue as a purpose, I lose, inasmuch as the content of this purposiveness is
true reality. Only finite, perishable things can be taken as purposes, not
eternal being.
Thus purposive willing of the essential destroys it. Similarly, self-reflec-
LAO-TZU 395
forsaken, the living action that flows from the Tao is impaired. Authentic
life is destroyed.
The purposive man loses his encompassing awareness of opposites. He sees
alternatives, always clinging to one as correct. In the world the Tao is mani-
fested in antinomies, and a life rooted in the Tao embraces opposites. Thus
to void opposites by purposive pursuit of one term, or to close one's eyes
to them, is to fall away from the Tao. In order to take something as a
purpose, I must differentiate.Thus the intentional man splits the organic
pairs of opposites and isolates the terms. He ceases to see one in the other
and to act accordingly; instead he sees one or the other, or vacillates be-
tween the two. This is to live on the surface of things and to lose the Tao.
Instead of opening myself in devotion to the encompassing reality, I try to
grasp reality in the form of a particular manifestation which I know.
finite particular things in the world, can gain fundamental reality only if
The antithesis between "action" and "nonaction" may suggest some sort of
rule. But the origin to which this word refers cannot be subsumed under
any law. It is not possible to give a rule for wu wei that would demand one
thing and exclude another. For this would be to bring it back into the realm
of purposive zeal, which precisely it transcends. What embraces the oppo-
sites cannot be adequately uttered in the oppositions of language. Thus Lao-
tzu says of Tao: "Tao invariably takes no action, and yet there is nothing
left undone" (37), and correspondingly he says of the Superior Man: "No
action is undertaken, and yet nothing is left undone" (48). The nonaction
of the Superior Man is an action of nonaction: "Therefore the sage man-
ages affairs without action" (2)
If purposelessness denotes the activity that springs from the origin, pur-
posiveness characterizes the activity that born of particularizing, con-
is
fining, intentional thinking. The former occurs unwilled and guides the pur-
posive will; the latter is willed, but is ultimately without guidance and
396 The Original Thinners
grounded in Tao and one with it, not on suffering and sacrifice. Lao-tzu's
nonaction is a living force out of the depths, while nonaction that "does
not resist evil" becomes a weapon, a means of conquering by abandoning
resistance, by shaming the enemy.
The collecting of testimonials to one's good actions and suffering in sacri-
fice are both highly intentional. Perhaps in no other philosophy is uninten-
tionality, this concept so puzzling in its simplicity, taken so resolutely as the
foundation of all ethical action. But this absence of all intentions cannot be
defined, it cannot be invoked as a prescription. One can speak of it only in-
directly.
c. Wu wei and unison with the Tao: It is as hard to characterize the Sage
—the Saint, the Superior Man, the Perfect Man, etc. —as it is to speak of the
Tao. Unison with Tao can never be taken as one of two opposites. Here
there is no choice between two possibilities of equal rank. The description
of the Saint is without clear contours; his reality conceals itself in opposi-
tions. To put the accent on either of the two terms is to misunderstand it.
For example:
"What is most perfect seems to be incomplete. . . . What is most full
(45)-
"The Tao which is bright appears to be dark. . . . Great virtue appears
like a valley (hollow). Great purity appears like disgrace. Far-reaching
virtue appears as if insufficient. Solid virtue appears as if unsteady" (41).
We shall again encounter such antitheses in descriptions of the Sage.
Taken literally, such statements are misleading, because they seem to press
for rational decision between opposites or to play with paradoxical reversals.
What they actually express is the very simple principle, which transcends all
withered and dried. Therefore the and the hard are companions of
stiff
death. The tender and the weak arecompanions of life. The strong . . .
and the great are inferior, while the tender and the weak are superior"
(76). Or: "The female always overcomes the male by tranquillity, and by
is underneath" (61).
tranquillity she
Often weakness is likened to water. "There is nothing softer and weaker
than water, and yet there is nothing better for attacking hard and strong
things" (78). "The great rivers and seas are kings of all mountain streams
because they skillfully stay below them" (66). "Tao in the world may be
compared to rivers and streams running into the sea" (32). "The best is like
water. Water is good; it benefits all things and does not compete with them.
It dwells in places that all disdain" (8).
Selflessness: The Superior Man lives by the example of Tao: "Therefore
the Sage places himself in the background but finds himself in the fore-
ground. He puts himself away, and yet he always remains" (7). Thus there
are two selves, the desiring, self-seeking, self-reflecting self which seeks
riches and prestige, and the true self which comes to the fore only when
the other dies away. "He who conquers others is strong; he who conquers
himself mighty" (33). This
is self-conquest has a number of consequences:
Freedom from desire: "The five colors cause one's eyes to be blind. The
five tones cause one's ears to be deaf. The five flavors cause one's palate to be
spoiled.Racing and hunting cause one's mind to be mad. Goods that are
hard to get injure one's activities. For this reason the Sage is concerned
with the belly and not the eyes" (12). "To force the growth of life means ill
omen. For the mind to employ the vital force means violence" (55). "It is
only those who do not seek after life that excel in making life valuable"
(75). "Only he who rids himself forever of desire can see the Secret Es-
sences; he that has never rid himself of desire can see only the Outcomes"
(1). "When there are music and dainties, passing strangers will stay. But
the words uttered by Tao, how insipid and tasteless!" (35).
Freedom from vanity: "He does not show himself; therefore he is lumi-
nous. He does not justify himself, therefore he becomes prominent" (22).
"He accomplishes his task, but does not claim credit for it" (77).
suit of learning is to increase day after day. The pursuit of Tao is to de-
crease day after day. It is to decrease and further decrease until one reaches
the point of taking no action" (48). "In penetrating the four quarters with
your intelligence, can you be without knowledge?" (10). "A wise man has
no extensive knowledge; he who has extensive knowledge is not a wise
man" (81).
Knowledge of Tao is not acquired from outside; it grows up within:
"One may know the world without going out of doors. One may see the
Way of Heaven without looking through the windows. The further one
goes, the less one knows" (47).
Knowledge of Tao is not a dispersed knowledge of many things; it is a
knowledge of the One: "To know eternity is to attain enlightenment" (55).
"He who does not know eternity runs blindly into disaster" (16).
All this means that the depth of Tao is disclosed only to the depth of
man. Tao withholds itself from man's surface thoughts and wrong thoughts,
from his desire and self-seeking, from his self-regard and acquisitiveness.
But in a man's depth rests the possibility of a knowledge that is one with
the source. If this depth is choked up, the waves of worldly life pass over it as
though it did not exist.
Consequently true self-knowledge is possible only with knowledge of the
Tao. "He who knows others is wise; he who knows himself is enlightened"
(33). This self-knowledge, which has nothing in common with self-reflec-
tion, with a desire to possess oneself by knowledge of oneself, is the knowl-
edge of being oneself in Tao, which sees through and does away with the
false striving for selfhood. "To know that you do not know is the best. To
pretend to know when you do not know is a disease. Only when one
recognizes this disease as a disease can one be free from the disease. The
Sage isfrom the disease. Because he recognizes this disease to be disease,
free
he is free from it" (71). Only the self-knowledge rooted in the primordial
source, the mother of all things, is positive: "When a man has found the
Mother, he will know the children accordingly; though he has known the
children, he still keeps to the Mother" (52).
Openness to all things: He who has regained Tao and thus extinguished
his self-striving and become himself lives amply. He sees things in their
fundamental being: "Knowing eternity, he is all-embracing. All-embracing,
he is without prejudice" (16). This comprehensiveness has far-reaching im-
plications:
"The Sage has no fixed ideas. He regards the people's ideas as his own"
(49). There is no limit to his participation in the lives of others: "All things
arise, and he does not turn away from them" (2). He forsakes no man, for
"none is rejected" (27).
He is not afraid to treat all men alike: "I treat those who are good with
goodness. And I also treat those who are not good with goodness. ... I am
honest to those who are honest, and I am also honest to those who are not
LAO-TZU 399
honest" (49). And he goes still further to demand of himself: "Repay hatred
with virtue" (6$).
But this breadth of scope also implies detachment. Perceiving and loving
the essence, he sees through the finite appearance and becomes impervious to
the particular. This indifference is not empty; it is filled with the Tao; imi-
tating the Tao, he is beyond good and evil. He is not indifferent, but his
profound vision of justice and love is concerned only with the essence:
"Heaven and Earth are not humane; they regard all things as straw dogs.
The Sage is not humane; he regards all people as straw dogs" (5).
The general attitude of the Sage: The Enlightened One behaves like the
masters of antiquity: "Cautious, like one crossing a frozen stream in the
winter, being at a loss, like one fearing danger on all sides, reserved, like one
visiting. Supple and pliant, like ice about to melt. Genuine, like a piece of
uncarved wood, open and broad, like a valley, merged and undifferentiated,
like muddy water" (15). Or: he has "three treasures, guard and keep them:
the first is deep love, the second is frugality, and the third is not to dare to be
ahead of the world" (67) The Sage does not talk much.
. "Much talk will of
course come to a dead end" (5).
The Sage is as simple and unself -conscious as a child: "He returns to the
state of infancy" (28)."Can you be like an infant?" (10). "He who possesses
virtue in abundance may be compared to an infant. . . . His bones are weak,
his sinews tender, but his grasp is firm" (55).
The Sage is steadfast: ". . . it is impossible either to be intimate and close
d. The fall: Lao-tzu's premise is that the world of men has fallen away from
the Tao. Most men and consequently official opinion are far from the Tao.
"Few in the world can understand the teaching without words and the ad-
vantage of taking no action" (43).
Why the fall? Antiquity possessed the Tao and lived in it (14, 15). The
fall was brought about by men, but this event did not take the form of a
natural catastrophe that happened once and for all in the past; rather, it
happens every day. The fall is brought about by intentionality, self-reflection,
and self-seeking.
According to Chuang-tzu, Lao-tzu stated the power and impotence of in-
tentionality in his conversation with Confucius: "Finding the Tao is not a
simple happening that can be willed; similarly losing the Tao is not a
simple happening, but it can be willed." Which means a man cannot come :
to the Tao by intentional willing. But finding Tao is not an automatic proc-
ess; it is effected by the Tao within me and the Tao outside me. Nor does
loss of the Tao take place of its own accord: it is brought about by a man's
—
own action "you can will it" by your intentionality and self-striving.
400 The Original Thinners
But whence comes this intentionality ? Lao-tzu does not inquire. He does
not ask whether the Tao might have remained one with world and man,
whether the fall need not have taken place. For him the fall is a plain fact.
Stages in the jail: "He who follows the Tao becomes one with the Tao;
he who follows virtue becomes one with virtue; he who follows corruption
becomes one with corruption" (23). This means that intentional right con-
duct, or virtue, lies halfway between the Tao and corruption. Definite vir-
tues and rules of conduct arise only when the Tao is forsaken. Indicative
of a fallen state, they represent an attempt at partial salvation. Man has
duties only after he has fallenaway from the Tao. The seemingly noblest
virtues are signs of a lower stage of humanity, which achieves authentic
being only in unity with the Tao. "When the great Tao declined, the doc-
trine of humanity and righteousness arose. When knowledge and wisdom
appeared, there emerged great hypocrisy. When the six family relationships
are not in harmony, there will be the advocacy of filial piety and deep love
to children. When a country is in disorder, there will be the praise of loyal
ministers" (18).
Thus Lao-tzu develops a hierarchy descending from the lofty existence
that moves in the Tao
("exalted virtue") to decreed virtue and the conven-
tional respectabilitywhich ultimately uses force against those who do not
comply with it: "The man of superior virtue takes no action, but has no
ulterior motive to do so. The man of inferior virtue takes action, and has an
ulterior motive to do so. The man of superior righteousness takes action,
and has an ulterior motive to do so. The man of superior propriety takes
action and when people do not respond to it, he will stretch his arms and
force it on them. Therefore when Tao is lost, only then does the doctrine
of virtue arise. When virtue is lost, only then does the doctrine of humanity
arise. When humanity is lost, only then does the doctrine of righteousness
arise" (38).
The hierarchy is also characterized from another point of view: "When
the highest type of men hear Tao, they diligently practice it. When the
average type of men hear Tao, they half believe in it. When the lowest type
of men hear Tao, they laugh heartily at it" (41).
The way bac\ to the Tao: No one is utterly rejected (27). In all men
there is an inclination to esteem Tao voluntarily— without any command
from outside (51). The essence is always unconsciously present even if it is
consciously despised. The element of Tao that was instilled in creatures at
birth is never wholly lost. Why should a man be rejected for his wickedness?
"Why did the ancients highly value this Tao? Did they not say, 'Those who
seek shall have it and those who sin shall be freed'?" (62).
Lao-tzu offers no instructions, no methods for finding the way back to
the Tao, because unintentionality cannot be produced intentionally. He
shows what is needful. But since this cannot be willed as a finite purpose,
as a clearly knowable something, it is not possible to indicate a systematic
LAO-TZU 401
method. Any method would be a perversion. Images and metaphors are not
instructions.
Still, there is one apparent recipe: to follow the masters of antiquity: "Of
old those who were the best masters were subtly mysterious and profoundly
penetrating; too deep to comprehend. And because they cannot be compre-
hended, I can only describe them arbitrarily" (15).
However, there is an ambiguity in this turn back to ancient times. As
Strauss says, it does not mean to repeat the past identically through knowl-
edge of the literary tradition —that is the way of Confucius — it means to
renew the eternal beginnings by retracing the threads of the Tao, which run
through all history : "Hold on to the Tao of old in order to master the things
of the present. From this one may know the primeval beginning (of the
universe). This is called the bond of Tao" (14).
—
thereby avoid danger to one's life this is called practicing the eternal" (52).
"To control the vital breath with the mind means rigidity. (For) after
things reach their prime, they begin to grow old, which means being con-
trary to Tao. Whatever is contrary to Tao will soon perish" (30)
Immortality here is an expression for participation in Tao, for rest in the
timelessness of eternity, not an endless prolongation of existence either in
another world or through a cycle of rebirths. The nature of immortality is
never indicated in an image. Only the consciousness of eternity is eluci-
dated. To life belongs death: "Man comes in to life and goes out to death"
—
(50). But unchanging is what when a man is at one with the Tao re- —
lieves life and death of their danger, what remains when the body dies: "I
have heard that one who is a good preserver of his life will not meet tigers
or wild buffaloes, and in fighting will not try to escape from weapons of
war. The wild buffalo cannot butt its horns against him, the tiger cannot
fasten its claws in him, and weapons of war cannot thrust their blades
into him. And for what reason? Because in him there is no room for death"
(50) . Here the "body" is taken metaphorically. Though his body may die, a
man who is at one with Tao has no spot where death can strike. He is
fearless because itno longer means anything to him to lose his body.
and government have lost their truth, that is, no longer follow the Tao;
not because he is a maverick, but because the desires and pleasures, pur-
poses and impulses of the crowd are far from Tao. Like Jeremiah and
Heraclitus, Lao-tzu was one of the early solitary men, not because he wished
to be, but by necessity.
few remarkable and very personal sentences Lao-tzu has described
In a
the of the Sage in this world: "The multitude are merry, as though
life
tude all have a purpose; I alone seem to be stubborn and rustic. I alone
differ from others, and value drawing sustenance from Mother (Tao)" (20).
In another passage Lao-tzu speaks of being misunderstood: "My doctrines
are very easy to understand and very easy to practice, but none in the world
can understand or practice them. My doctrines have a source; my deeds
have a master. It is because people do not understand this that they do not
understand me. Few people know me, and therefore I am highly valued.
Therefore the Sage wears a coarse cloth on top and carries jade within his
bosom" (70).
According Ssu-ma Ch'ien, when the young Confucius came to see Lao-
to
tzu, Lao-tzu his projects for reform and said: "When the Sage
condemned
finds his time, he rises; when he does not find his time, he lets the weeds
pile up and goes. Away with the master's weeds and with fanciful
. . .
The truth— unison with the Tao —can be present in rulers, in govern-
ments, in the economic system, and even in warfare. Thus the truth of
government resides in nonaction, in release, in imperceptible influence, in
short, in weakness. The ruler is a single person. His character and conduct
determine the life of the whole state. The sum of human affairs in the state
a. The ruler: The quality of rulers is shown by the way in which the
people see them. "The best are those whose existence is (merely) known by
the people. The next best are those who are loved and praised. The next are
.
LAO-TZU 403
those who are feared. And the next are those who are despised. . . . They
accomplish their task; they complete their work. Nevertheless their people
say that they simply follow Nature" (17). "And the world will be at peace
of its own accord" (37).
A perfect ruler "takes no action and therefore does not fail" (64). He acts
by nonaction. "Can you love the people and govern the state without knowl-
edge? (10). "Administer the empire by engaging in no activity" (57).
Accordingly a good ruler is humble, makes himself inconspicuous, de-
mands nothing. "Therefore, in order to be the superior of the people, one
must, in the use of words, place himself below them. And in order to be
ahead of the people, one must, in one's own person, follow them. Therefore
the Sage places himself above the people and they do not feel his weight.
He places himself in front of them and the people do not harm him" (66).
Such a ruler, who knows his rank but humbles himself and therefore calls
himself "the Orphan," "the Lonely One," "the Destitute One" (39), "be-
comes the valley of the world" (28).
Only one who does not desire to govern can succeed in governing by
nonactivity. If he is concerned with winning power and fears to lose it, he
cannot truly govern. "They are difficult to rule because their ruler does too
many things" (75). Elsewhere Lao-tzu speaks more severely of the bad ruler:
"The courts are exceedingly splendid, while the fields are exceedingly
weedy, and the granaries are exceedingly empty. Elegant clothes are worn,
sharp weapons are carried, foods and drinks are enjoyed beyond limit, and
wealth and treasures are accumulated in excess. This is robbery and extrav-
agance" (53).
harmony with Tao guides not only the kingdom but nature and all things
upon the right course. It is the source of good harvests and prevents floods,
drought, plagues, and wars. This magical conception is also to be found
in Lao-tzu (if this passage is authentic and not a later addition): "If Tao
is employed to rule the empire, spiritual beings will lose their supernatural
power. Not that they lose their spiritual power, but their spiritual power
can no longer harm people" (60). In Lao-tzu, however, this magical con-
ception is secondary, though it is nowhere expressly disavowed.
The value of great models is often stressed. "Hold fast to the great form
(Tao), and all the world will come" (35). "Virtue becomes deep and far-
reaching, and with it all things return to their original state. Then complete
harmony will be reached" (65). The influence of the Superior Man and
404 The Original Thinners
consequently the imitation of the Tao put the realm and the people in order.
By virtue of his inner being, man is the carrier of the model image. "The
adherence of the empire garnered by letting-alone" (57)
is
plans, which precedes all definite action, which is neither passivity nor plan-
less action. It is an intervention not according to mere finite ends, but rising
from the source, the Tao itself. Any attempt to define the operation of this
nonaction more closely would be out of place. Like the speculation that
tries to penetrate into the Tao and the elucidation of individual nonaction,
this political thinking is oriented toward the inerrable and undifferentiated.
Only at the next lowest step does differentiation set in —here definite
discourse becomes possible. In negations : "The more taboos and prohibitions
there are in the world, the poorer the people will be. The more sharp
weapons the people have, the more troubled the state will be. The more . . .
laws and ordinances are promulgated, the more thieves and robbers there
will be" (57). Or the same statement is made in a positive but indefinite form:
once intervention, prohibition, and command cease, all will become true
and authentic "of its own accord." "I take no action and the people of them-
selves are transformed. I love tranquillity and the people of themselves be-
come correct. I engage in no activity and the people of themselves become
prosperous. I have no desires and the people of themselves become simple"
(57). In contrast with this, only an external causality is expressed in the
words: "The people starve, because the ruler eats too much tax-grain" (75).
Anyone who takes Lao-tzu's maxims as rules of conduct is bound to ob-
ject: All that is impracticable, men are simply not made that way. But to
raise such an argument is to forget that these are not rules for purposive
action. Lao-tzu's maxims, which find their norm in not acting, not planning,
not intervening, can only become meaningless if taken as a summons to act
and to plan. Lao-tzu points the way to a possibility which is not a program
for the understanding but, preceding all purposive political action, an appeal
to the source within each man. Conceived as a concrete institution, realizable
by finite means, his ideal would be a futile Utopia of magical inactivity. But
it is a truth insofar as it gives an intimation of the human possibility in
may sound fantastic when Lao-tzu says: "If kings and barons
political life. It
would hold on to it, all things would submit to them spontaneously. Heaven
and Earth unite to drip sweet dew. Without the command of men, it drips
evenly over all" (32). But anyone who actively and by design introduced
anarchy into the world on the supposition that men would automatically
keep order because they are good, would merely be showing that he had
misunderstood this philosophy. And even more so if he used force to quell
the ensuing chaos. If the one who misunderstood Lao-tzu and introduced
anarchy were a "saint," if he were sincere and consistent and men gave
LAO-TZU 405
c. U'jr and punishment: How does Lao-tzu observe the ideal of nonaction
in connection with the indispensable acts of political violence: in connection
with war abroad and punishment at home? How is the principle "to act,
not contend," manifested here?
War is in any case evil: "Fine weapons are instruments of evil, they are
hated by men" (31). "Wherever armies are stationed, briers and thorns grow.
Great wars are always followed by famines" (30). But there are situations in
which even a Sage cannot avoid war. "When he uses them [weapons] un-
avoidably, he regards calm restraint as the best principle" (31). But once he
makes up his mind, he imposes limits on his manner of fighting and con-
quering. "A good [general] achieves his purpose and stops, but dares not
seek to dominate the world. He achieves his purpose but does not brag
about it. . . . He achieves his purpose but only as an unavoidable step" (30).
Even by nonaction applies. Since "the weak
in battle the principle of action
and the tender overcome the hard and the strong" (36), since "the softest
things in the world overcome the hardest things in the world" (43), Lao-
tzu concludes with surprising consistency: "Therefore if the army is strong,
it will not win. . . . The strong and the great are inferior, while the tender
and the weak are superior" (76). "For deep love helps one to win in the
case of attack, and to be firm in the case of defense" (67) Offensive warfare .
is expressly condemned. And even in batde one should act as little as possi-
ble : "A strategist of old has said : 'I dare not take the offensive but I take the
defensive; I dare not advance an inch but I retreat a foot.' This means: 'To
march without formation, to stretch one's arm without showing it, to con-
front enemies without seeming to meet them; to hold weapons without
seeming to have them' " (69).
Lao-tzu describes the good warrior: "A skillful leader of troops is not
oppressive with his military strength. A skillful fighter does not become
angry. A skillful conqueror does not compete with people" (68). "Even
when he is victorious, he does not regard it as praiseworthy. . For the . .
slaughter of the multitude, let us weep with sorrow and grief. For a victory,
let us observe the occasion with funeral ceremonies" (31).
The internal violence of the state is manifested in punishments, especially
acquitted criminal will not evade punishment: "Heaven's net is indeed vast.
Though its meshes are wide, it misses nothing" (73).
d. Action in the changing world of things: Men move away from the eternal
Tao and return to it. It is essential to return each day afresh, but this does not
mean to make the world over into something entirely new. For Lao-tzu and
the Chinese there is no unique course of history, no undecided future, but
only the eternal, infinitely agitated life of the Tao. In this life men fluctuate
between harmony with Tao and deviation from it. Nonaction brings about
perfect harmony.
Nonaction is not the repose of the onlooker but the dominant ground of
action. Political life is fraught with unrest: enemies of the government, seeds
of new enmity, changing conditions. Political nonaction is therefore attended
by constant tension. While frantic activity never really accomplishes any-
thing but imagines that by pursuing its comes into possession of
aims it
Huang-Ti, but a "spiritual thing.' "He who acts on it harms it. He who
1
holds on to it loses it" (29). Lao-tzu had before him the decaying feudal
regime, whose original condition he regarded as in keeping with the Tao.
The general political condition was that of a number of small states
connected by the one Empire. The best: "A small country with few people"
(80). In order that life should be happy in this small state: "Let there be
ten times and hundred times as many utensils but let them not be used.
a . . .
Even if there are ships and carriages, none will ride in them. Even if there
are arrows and weapons, none will display them" (80). The relation between
large and small states must be the right one: "A big state can take over
a small state if it places itself below the small state. And the small state can
take over a big state if it places itself below the big state" (61). Happy
countries live quietly side by side; their people do not grow restless and
enter into relations with one another: "Though neighboring communities
overlook one another and the crowing of cocks and barking of dogs can
be heard, yet the people there may grow old and die without ever visiting
one another" (80).
from the indifferent quietism of a mere onlooker, who sees only his imagin-
ings and rejects all visible reality.
We
must try to consider such sentences in the light of the teachings as a
whole and recognize the twofold meaning of the "primordial." The primary
408 The Original Thinners
is used as a metaphor for the first, is confused with it. Despite the power of
his philosophical thought, despite his insight into the source of the highest
human potentiality, Lao-tzu's sentences sometimes obscure and distort
his original vision — and it is perfectly possible that the thinker himself
was sometimes led astray.
a. The contradiction: to spea\ of the ineffable: "He who knows does not
speak. He who speaks does not know" (56). Lao-tzu repeatedly utters this
The Sage "spreads doctrines without words" (2).
basic insight:
Thus Lao-tzu condemns his own attempt to communicate the deepest
knowledge by way of what can be said. And indeed, every sentence that
is spoken distracts from the fundamental truth. To take the statements
literally is to tie oneself to objects. One must transcend both statement
and object, that is, attain to the ineffable, in order to perceive the truth.
Thus every statement must vanish in the ineffable if it is to become true.
Why, then, does Lao-tzu write a book? He offers no justification. It is
only the legend which tells us that he did not wish to, that it was the frontier
guard who demanded it, and that nolens volens Lao-tzu complied. We may
answer: He meant these written statements to induce the reader to tran-
scend them, he meant them to guide us, through reflection, to the ineffable.
will, which aims at purposes and acts according to plans. Lao-tzu addresses
the source within us, which is obscured by understanding and purposes.
Hence he aims not at self-domination by the power of the will, but at a
deeper examination of our impulses themselves.
What can thus be awakened lies dormant within us. Otherwise —though
this Lao-tzu does not say — there is only an emptiness in which there is
tion that flow's from the all-embracing source. They combat the blind
rage, thoughtless activity, and violence of those who see only the finite things
about them.
These maxims can act as correctives to the tendency to regulate every-
thing by laws and decrees. They can make us aware of the need to let
by activity and into perplexity in the face of the question: What for? Lao-
tzu reminds us of what man must hold fast to if he is not to sink into the
void.
LAO-TZU 411
can only express its being in the ground of nonbeing by saying that it is
determines itself. This circular reasoning is an expression for the Tao's cir-
cling within itself. Thus: "Tao is a law unto itself" (25). I know it "through
itself" (21); I know it "by itself" (54). If the veils are drawn aside and per-
versions done away with, if the will conforms to the Tao, the source is laid
bare. And what awaits us there is not Nothingness but "itself."
The forms of progression, antinomy, reversal, and circular reasoning are
means of bringing us closer to the source. This source is One. Hence Lao-tzu
does not distinguish between metaphysics, ethics, and politics, as we have
done in expounding his thought. Repeatedly Lao-tzu weaves them together
in a few sentences. Consequently his thinking is always whole, whether he
is speaking of politics, ethics, or metaphysics; that is to say, since in every
case he is concerned with the common ground, he is always speaking of
the same thing. When things are joined in the Tao, nothing is separate.
When they are forsaken by the Tao, one separates from another and falsely
2. Lao-tzu s successors
of all beings, it is source and shelter, end and perfection. But this peace is no
passive peace of indifference, it is not vitalist contemplation of vegetative
existence, but rest amid the unrest of suffering at the hands of a world alien
to the Tao. It is present even in the suffering of loneliness, in the necessity
to live like a fool in a world that has become a stranger to the Tao.
In the following misunderstandings, the meaning of Lao-tzu is diamet-
rically reversed : Freedom from desire, said Lao-tzu, is the condition of vision
of the Tao. From a distortion of this idea it is inferred that a man without
passions or a man who does nothing comes closer to the source. Lao-tzu
suffered, but he did not hide away from the world or deny its existence. In
a distortion of his thinking, the world was absolutely rejected for its corrup-
Hermits and monks took up his maxims in disregard of their meaning.
tion.
From time immemorial China had known its hermits, who broke with family,
community, and state, to live alone in the wilderness. Solitude is praised in
the ancient songs of the Shih Ching: "Solitude by brook and rivulet is
the serene choice of the Saint. He is alone in his sleeping, his waking and
his speaking solitude on the mountain slope
. . . . . . Solitude on the lofty
summit ." There have been monks at all times in China. Chinese monas-
. .
ticism was exclusively Taoist until the advent of Buddhism. The Taoist
monks invoked the name of Lao-tzu.
The "Epicurean": Conversely, the repose of the Tao could also be found
in the world. Then the Tao was interpreted as a refined art of spiritual
enjoyment of life under all conditions. Real life is not taken as a task, as
a set of duties to be performed and state. The indi-
in family, profession,
vidual achieveshappy and peaceful life by adapting himself to all
a
sorts of realities which are not to be taken seriously in themselves. This
achieving of the beautiful life is developed into a high art. One is reminded
of the old story about the three vinegar drinkers. Vinegar is the symbol of
life. Confucius finds it sour, Buddha bitter, Lao-tzu sweet. Down through
the centuries the Confucians have attacked Lao-tzu, whom they identify with
an artificial discipline of living. Chu Hsi (1131-1200) declared that Lao-
tzu, whether speaking of emptiness, purity, nonaction, or self-abasement,
thought only of his own advantage, that he came into conflict with no one
and always went about with a satisfied smile.
The man of letters: Chuang-tzu was the most famous of Lao-tzu's
disciples. Unlike the Tao Te Ching, he is easy to read even in translation,
witty, exciting, imaginative, rich in fluent disquisitions and sharp aphorisms,
skillful in modulating his ideas and in varying his forms. An inventive
LAO-TZU 413
tarian lines based on technical planning, had the Confucian books burned
but preserved the Taoist scriptures along with works on military, agricul-
414 The Original Thinners
torted into tangible prescriptions. But down through the ages he has re-
His limits are its limits: his mood is one of serenity amid suffering. He
knows neither the threat of Buddhist rebirths, and hence the urge to depart
from this wheel of torment, nor the Christian Cross, the dread of inexorable
sin, man's dependence on the grace of redemption by the sacrificial death
of the incarnate God. One might be tempted to say that the Western and
Indian conceptions are hideous nightmares measured by the naturalness of
the Chinese and regard the early Chinese as fortunate for having escaped
such phantasms. But this absence of the historical intuitions of Indian and
Western mankind more than an absence of the unnatural and absurd.
is
Roughly from the first to the eighth century a.d. a philosophy based on
grew up in India, both among the Hindus (the Nyaya
logical operations
school) and among the sects of Mahayana Buddhism. The most famous
of the Buddhist thinkers were Nagarjuna (roughly second century a.d.),
Asanga, Vasubandhu, Dignaga, Dharmakirti (seventh century). The lit-
erature has come down to us not in its original form but in later works,
which became the fundamental texts of philosophical Buddhism, especially
in China.
In this world of dialectical logic as the conscious expression of a way of
life, the Shunyavadin, the sect to which Nagarjuna belonged, drew the
most radical conclusions from the assumptions common to all Buddhist
sects. All is empty, they taught. Things have only a momentary, phantom
existence without permanent substance. Consequently true knowledge lies
in Emptiness. Iit by detachment, that is, by a thinking that is
acquire
free from signs and signification, stirred by no inclination or goal. This
doctrine is called the "diamond-splitting Perfection of Wisdom"; it also
calls itself the middle way {mad hy ami\a) between the two theses that
life is and that life is not: emptiness {shunya vada) has neither being nor
nonbeing. Perfect Wisdom lies in perfect freedom from conflict.
N AG ARJU N A 417
they are nothing at all. But if the designation is said to be a mirror image,
as a mere image it is again false. Thus what is thought and differentiated
under a false designation cannot truly exist.
Since designation and thing designated can be neither one nor different,
distinctions between things designated —such as coming and going, becom-
ing and perishing —are also untenable. To live by signs is to live in illusion,
farfrom Perfect Wisdom. But every man lives by signs when he lives in the
—
realm of appearance whether he assumes that "appearance is a sign," or
that "appearance is empty," when he lives in the assumption "I live" or
"I am conscious."
With the resources of language there is no escape from speech through
demonstrated by evidence: things are not one, they are not different; there
is no coming, there is no going, etc.
This is impossible. For what being can there be without being-as-such and
N AG A RJU N A 419
Something is. 2. It is not. 3. It both is and is not. 4. It neither is nor is not. Thus
every possibility of a final valid statement is excluded.
The consequence is that everything can be formulated negatively and
positively. The Buddha taught one thing and the opposite as well. Not only
is the opposition between true and false transcended but also the opposite
of this opposition. In the end no definite statement is possible. The four
statements are repeated and rejected in connection with each dharma. For
example: There is an end; there is no end; there is and is not an end; the
end neither is nor is not. Or: After Nirvana the Buddha exists; he does not
exist; he exists and does not exist; he neither exists nor does not exist.
e) : What is refuted: The operation is constantly repeated, but the content
varies —modes of thought, opinions, statements, in short, the categories of
Indian philosophy, are refuted in turn. Just as the nature of a flame depends
on the kind of fuel consumed, so the operation of refutation depends on what
is refuted. Many of these categories are familiar to us, others are not; but
it must not be forgotten that translation obscures the specifically Indian
coloration of such concepts as being and nonbeing, becoming and perishing,
causality, time, matter, self,, etc.
420 The Original Thinners
a) There are two truths: the veiled worldly truth and the highest truth.
According to the veiled truth, all the dharmas have a cause. According to the
highest truth, they are perceived to be without cause. But the highest truth
cannot be obtained independently of the veiled truth. And Nirvana is not
obtained without the highest truth. Thus the Buddha's doctrine is depend-
ent on two truths, or in other words, the true can be attained only through
the false. But this path can be traveled only with the help of enlightenment,
which comes to me from the highest truth. Thanks to this enlightenment,
I cease, even in my thinking of the inherently empty dharmas, to accept the
illusion of the world; even while I think the dharmas and participate in
them, I cease to cling to them.
b) Thus the one is conceived in terms of two truths. But this conception
leads to two opposed views: all things do and do not possess independent
being. If things exist independently and as such, they are without cause
and condition. Then there is no cause and no effect, no action and no
agent, no becoming and no perishing. If things are held to be nonexistent,
all becomes phantasm. Nagarjuna rejects both these views in favor of
to employ terms that are inadequate from the standpoint of his own method,
as when he sums up the doctrine: "Without becoming, also without perish-
ing, not eternal, also not cut-off, not one, also not differentiated, without
coming, also without going — who can thus teach conditioned becoming,
the quiet extinction of development: before him I bow my head."
This view of the emptiness of things becoming" saves
in "conditioned
For if there
the reality of the conquest of suffering, the reality of the way.
were independent being, there would be no coming-into-being and no pass-
ing-away. What exists through itself, cannot come into being and will endure
forever. Thus if there is independent being, nothing further can be attained,
nothing more can be done, because everything already exists. If there were
independent being, living creatures would be free of diversity. There would
be no suffering. But if things are empty, there is becoming and perishing,
nothing authentically is, must we not infer the nonexistence of the Buddha,
of the doctrine, of knowledge, of ritual practice, of the congregation, of
monks, of the Sages who have attained the goal? The answer is that they
do exist in emptiness, which is neither being nor nonbeing. Because there
is emptiness, the Buddha exists. If things were not empty, if there were no
becoming, no perishing, and no suffering, there would be no Buddha; nor
would there be his doctrine of suffering, the negation of suffering, and the
way to the negation of suffering. If suffering existed independently, it
could not be destroyed. If the way existed in itself, it would not be possible
to travel it, for eternal being precludes motion and development. If we
postulate independent being, there is nothing more to be achieved. Hence
the Buddha, his teaching, and what is achieved by his teaching are all in
emptiness. Only when a man sees all the dharmas as conditioned becoming
in emptiness, can he see the doctrine of the Buddha, the Four Noble Truths,
and transcend suffering.
Those who take the Buddha's doctrine of unsubstantiality as an argument
against that same doctrine, have not understood it. Their argument ceases
to apply if all thought, representation, and being are seen in emptiness.
Those who accept emptiness accept everything, the worldly and the
transcendent. To those who do not accept emptiness, nothing is acceptable.
Those who differentiate the four views of the logical schema move in
veiled truth. They are beset by many kinds of representations. They still
cling to the alternative: "If this is true, the other is false." But for those in
whom the eye of Perfect Wisdom has opened, the four views disappear.
The spiritual eye of those who suppose that they see the Buddha through
developments such as: being —nonbeing, eternal —not eternal, body — spirit,
etc., has been injured by these developments. They no more see the Buddha
than a man born blind sees the sun. But those who see conditioned becoming,
see suffering, its coming-into-being and the manner of its annihilation, that
is, they see the way, just as a man endowed with eyes is enabled by the
shining of a light to see the appearances of things.
the discipline that is beyond discipline" (The Sutra of the Forty-two Chap-
ters, 1 8).
Actually, the doctrine was set forth as a doctrine, both orally and in
writing, and was also reflected in exercises and in ethical practice. "A Bo-
dhisattva must above all hear this Perfection of Wisdom, take it up, bear it
in mind, recite, study, spread, demonstrate, explain and write it" (Pr. 36-38)
But this is only the first stage. Hearing the doctrine, the monk who is not
yet at the goal "follows his trust" (Pr. 38). He is not yet in the truth. The
truth is not arrived at by any knowable, logically determined content, but
"awakens suddenly to unexcelled perfect enlightenment" (Pr. 41).
This process of hearing and learning until the truth itself is kindled is a
process of thought upon the whole man. The operations as
which seizes
such leave nothing in place, they confuse the mind and make it dizzy. Accord-
ingly: "If, hearing these thoughts, he is not alarmed and does not take
fright . . . , if in the presence of such a doctrine he does not sink down in
terror, if mind is not broken
the backbone of his then this man should . . .
own which is in keeping with the content of the doctrine. The logical element
itself is seldom clearly and systematically developed. The dialectic takes the
form of mere lists. This is perhaps appropriate to the mode of thought. For
this negative logic prepares the way, not for a positive insight developed
in logical terms, but for a silence filled from another source. Here all reason-
ing annuls itself.
has given the truest answer and becomes the patriarch's successor. —Or:
Bodhidharma speaks with the Emperor Liang Wu Ti. The Emperor says:
I have never ceased to build temples, to commission the writing of sacred
books, to give new monks permission to enter monasteries. What is my
merit?—None at all. All this is only the shadow that follows the object and
is without true being. —The
Emperor: What then is true merit? To be —
surrounded by emptiness and stillness, immersed in thought. Such merit
cannot be gained by worldly means. The Emperor: What is the most —
N AG A RJU X .1 423
pv.35).
(Pr. 3S). When he has arrived at that point, the Bodhisattva "stands fast in
the sense of not-standing" (Pr. 48) ; "he will not stand somewhere; in Perfect
Wisdom he will stand in the mode of not-standing."
The teacher of this doctrine contradicts himself whenever he speaks, and
such self-contradiction becomes a deliberate method. Questioned from the
standpoint of any dharma whatsoever, he can always find a way out. Because
he is independent of all the dharmas he does not, in speaking, come into
contradiction with the essence of his doctrine, although he does contradict
all statements, even his own. Consequently, every false statement is justi-
Amid the clarity which is possible today, but which as mere clarity remains
an empty pastime, the depth that is discernible in the Indian texts for all
their cloudiness might well become a spur to self-reflection.
5. The uses of logic: To the analytic mind which thinks in terms of alter-
natives, such concepts as motion, time, the One are unthinkable. In the
Western world the search for logical operations with which these problems,
always under specific assumptions, can in some measure be mastered, has
opened up magnificent fields of finite knowledge, in which even the in-
finite, in certain forms or under certain aspects, has become an instrument
of finite thinking.
In India the barest beginnings were made toward the consideration of
these problems. These beginnings served an entirely different purpose from
the solution of specific problems (a purpose which might, in view of the
subtle logical insights of recent centuries, be revived in a sense which today
cannot be foreseen).
Operations which shatter all definite statements, so that everything dis-
solves into otherness, opposition, contradiction, so that all determinations
vanish and no position stands fast, must ultimately lead either to nothing-
ness or to an intimation of authentic being, even if it can no longer be
NAGARJUNA 425
called being. Or to put it in another way: The end is either a playful concern
with "problems" or a state of mind which in such methods finds a means
of understanding and actualizing the self, an attitude of perfect superiority
to the world] of perfect detachment from all things and from one's own
existence, and hence of perfect superiority to oneself.
In Asia the visible embodiment of this way of thinking may be a monastic
life of meditation enhanced by practice, or form of rites
it may take the
and magic and gestures. But the dialectic of the philosophers served
cults,
neither the one nor the other. Within these embodiments, its aim was
negative: the rejection of all metaphysics as a knowledge of another, objective
being distinct from myself (as in the Hindu system); and positive: the
acquisition of Perfect Wisdom which may be termed nonthought, because
through thought it has become more-than-thought.
to our insight. The Vedantist on the other hand denies the reality of the
world of appearance only in order to establish the true being of Brahman.
The Buddhist says: Knowledge is undivided; only to our deluded eye
426 The Original Thinners
does it present itself in the cleavage of subject and object. The Vedantist
says, however: The whole world is a simple substance that never ceases;
the division of consciousness into subject and object is mere illusion.
burden is cast off; that Thoughts are made free, mastery over
is the goal.
all thought is gained in the detached knowledge which masters itself. The
fetters of existence have vanished, impurities fall away, freedom from torment
To call it nihilism is to forget that the alternative between being and nothing-
ness has been dismissed.
How in Perfect Wisdom "being" is experienced as the emptiness of the
world is illustrated in images. To the Bodhisattva all things are like an
echo, he does not think them, he does not see them, he does not know them
(Pr. 75). He lives in the world as in the "emptiness of a city of ghosts"
(Nag. 27). The "illusory nature" of things, the fact that they at once are and
are not (and are adequately conceived in none of the four views), is com-
pared with the materializations (regarded as real in India) of a magician
(Pr. 46): a magician at a crossroads conjures up a large crowd of people
and makes them disappear again; so is the world. No one has been killed or
destroyed by the magician; so without destroying them, the Bodhisattva
makes multitudes of beings disappear.
The Bodhisattva knows, sees, and believes all things by virtue of a concept
which is contained neither in the concept of a thing (dharmd) nor of a
non-thing (adharma). The right attitude would be achieved by one who
could fully explain lines like the following: "The stars, darkness, a light,
an illusion, dew, a bubble, a dream, a streak of lightning, a cloud" (Pr. 157).
N A G ARJU N A 427
In keeping with this attitude worldly values are disparaged. The Buddha
is quoted as saying: "In my eyes the dignity of a king or prince is no more
than a grain of dust in the sun; in my eyes a treasure of gold and jewels is
no more than clay and shards ... in my eyes the thousand systems of the
cosmos are no more than the fruit of the myrobalan ... in my eyes the
ritual objects (of Buddhism)
no more than a heap of worthless treasures
are
... in my Buddhas is no more than the sight of a
eyes the path of the
flower ... in my eyes Nirvana is no more than a waking from sleep by
day or night ... in my eyes the error and truth (of the various schools)
is no more than the game of the six dragons" (Hackmann).
Are we entitled to say that the possessor of such wisdom sees nothing
but a vast unutterable nothingness? That he is submerged in the shoreless
ocean of the undifferentiated? We must hesitate. The thinker whose aim
is redemption from the fetters of the dharmas is beyond our understanding
and our judgment. "His way, like that of the birds in the air, is hard to
follow" {Dharnmapada 92). But it is certain that in perversions of the
original thought futility and meaninglessness soon make their appearance.
in life and never at an end. One who takes this attitude looks upon life
does this come about? They hear and speak of absolute emptiness but do
not understand its source. They express such skeptical thoughts as: If all
is empty, how can we distinguish the consequences of good and evil? They
can ask such questions only from a worldly point of view, because for the
worldly there is no difference between worldly truth and absolute truth.
In other words, what was intended speculatively they understand as purposive
knowledge. In objectivizing thought, they lose the meaning of the doctrine
of emptiness, because, in their attachment to mere logical propositions,
they draw conclusions that have nothing to do with emptiness. They fail
to understand that to include the Buddha, the doctrine, the congregation
in emptiness, is not to deny them but to consider them as dharma and as such
to bring them into a state of suspension. Such a state of suspension is
possible Only if we refrain from absolutizing any representation, idea, or
proposition. This is to travel the true path, in dharma, toward the dis-
But they lose this light by their attachment to the word of the doctrine.
Ceasing to take the doctrine as a sign, an indicator, and looking upon it as
an object of knowledge, they lose the thought.
Concern with the profound doctrine is salutary, but also dangerous. When
it is not properly understood, it kills. For if emptiness is seen imperfectly,
it leads those of little understanding not only into error but into destruction,
just as poisonous snakes, if improperly handled, and magic and conjuring
if improperly executed, lead to destruction (Nag. I, 151).
What emptiness ultimately came to mean in popular Buddhism is shown
by a Chinese book of wisdom written in the twelfth century: He who has
understood the emptiness of corporeal things ceases to set any store by
opinions; he will refrain from all activity and sit still without a thought
(Hackmann).
manifested through figures of thought and metaphors. All ideas are immersed
in an atmosphere without which they would wither away. They throw
light on the presupposed attitude of the thinker, which without this thinking
he would be unable to maintain.
The fundamental view is seemingly gained by logical thought. The in-
tention is to destroy logic with logic and so demonstrate that thinking is
itself illusion; to prove that nothing can be proved, that nothing can be
asserted, and that nothingness can also not be asserted.
With all this, logical necessities are discovered, which have validity as
NAGARJUNA 429
such. But they are no more than a rational game, concerning which it
In the Asian form of this thinking, we see a surface picture which mis-
leads us as to the origin: in discussion, whatever another may assert is
house he enters be forsaken, deserted, and empty; and let every dish he
touches be empty and without content." Here man's sensibility is likened
to an empty village; this emptiness does not signify a denial of being, but
indifference, insipidity, imperviousness. "Animitta" ("without definite
suchness," "signlessness") means in the Pali Canon: nonattachment to
the attributes of perceived things; it does not mean a denial of their
existence, but a mode of practical behavior, in which the monk, like a
vigilant gatekeeper, bars access to the sensory stimuli streaming in on him
from without. "Maya" (magic) means comparison of the world to a
phantasm, as an expression of the arbitrariness and futility of being, not as
a denial of its reality. Here it should not be forgotten that the Indians looked
upon images, echoes, and dreams as realities. Existence is not denied; what
is denied is its authenticity.
8. Survey of the Buddhist sects and the ultimate meaning of all doctrines:
The Shunyavadins are one sect among many. What is common to all is
the Buddhist striving for redemption, the knowledge of suffering and of
the insignificance of the world's reality. On this common ground, reflection
on the possibility of knowing reality had resulted in numerous opinions:
The outside world is real and can be known directly through perception
(the Sarvastivadins) ; it is not perceived by the senses but its existence can
be inferred through perceptions (the Sautrantikas) ; only consciousness
is certain and the source of this certainty is consciousness itself; only the
inner world is real, and object has no real
the difference between subject
existence (the Yogacaras); neither outside nor inner world can be recog-
43° The Original Thinners
ence. Once we have reached the other shore, the boat is superfluous. Since
the doctrine belongs to the illusory stream of worldly existence, to take
it along with us on the other side would be as foolish as to carry the boat on
our shoulders as we leave the shore to enter the new country. The Sage
abandons it to the stream which lies behind him. The doctrine is useful in
helping us to escape, but there is nothing to be gained by holding it fast.
Historical Comparisons
In this way he has created in the modern world a spiritual situation which he
himself brought about in the belief that the best way to overcome nihilism
was to carry it to its ultimate consequences. But Nietzsche, who without
systematically elaborating this dialectic set out to employ it as an instrument
for the complete liberation of mankind, conceived of this liberation as a step
not into an unthinkable otherness, but rather into a worldly reality, the full
b. The structure of being, the categories: The Buddhists have their so-
called formula of causality (the circle of the fundamental categories of
being). The Yogacaras speak in particular of the primordial consciousness,
the germinal consciousness, whose unfolding brings with it the illusion of
the world. The development of this idea shows the nature and form of a
world that does not truly exist, the structure of all appearances. This Indian
conception has been likened to Western idealism. And indeed, Kant con-
ceives the whole world as appearance, its forms defined by the categories of
consciousness as such. All knowable objects are produced, not as to their
being but as to their forms, by the subject. So-called transcendental idealism
created a systematic schema of this reality that unfolds in thought.
But the analogy at once discloses a difference. The Indians devised this
structure in order to divest scientific knowledge it is dream
of its truth, for
and illusion. Kant conceived and developed his similar structure in order
to justify scientific knowledge within the limits of possible experience. For
him the world is appearance, but not illusion. The idealists who followed
Kant did not conceive these categorial structures as limited to appearance,
but as the eternal truth itself, as God's thoughts. Neither view bears any
kinship to Buddhist thinking. For the German idealists justify knowledge
of the world and activity in the world, while the Buddhists on the contrary
stand for abandonment of the world, for renunciation of scientific knowl-
edge, which they look upon as unrewarding because fundamentally false;
they reject action in shaping the world, which is not only futile but holds
us in a state of captivity.
which is as infinitely open as emptiness. Both listen, both respect the opinions
of others. But the difference is this: the Buddhist Sage goes through the
world duck; he no longer gets wet. He has transcended the world
like a
by dropping He seeks fulfillment in an unthinkable unworld. For West-
it.
ern man, however, reason finds its fulfillment, not in any absolute, but in
the historicity of the world itself,which he gathers into his own Existenz.
Only in historical realization, becoming identical with it, does he find
his ground; he knows that this is the source of his freedom and of his
relation to transcendence.
d. Detachment: Detachment from the world and myself, the inner libera-
tion that I achieve by dissociating myself from everything that happens to
me in the world and everything I myself do, think, and am, is a form which
was embodied in very different ways.
The Bhagavad Gita praises the warrior who remains indifferent and
aloof despite his impetuous heroism, who plays the game conscientiously
and acts energetically, while regarding all activity as vain. In Epicurus —
the fundamental attitude is: I have passions, but they do not have me. In —
St. Paul, I act and live in the world as though I were not there. Nietzsche —
regards detachment from oneself as the hallmark of the aristocratic soul.
Despite this analogy in the form of detachment, the fundamental attitude
of the Buddhists and of Nagarjuna is an entirely different one: the accent
is on the impersonal; as the world becomes a matter of indifference, the
self is extinguished. The detachment has its source not in a "myself," but in
EDITOR S NOTE!
The Bibliography is based on that given in the German original. English trans-
lations are givenwherever possible. Selected English and American worlds have
been added; these are marked by an asterisk?.
The Pre-Socratics:
Anaximander —Heraditus—Parmenides
sources:
Diels, Hermann: Die Fragmente der Vorso\rati\er, griechisch und deutsch, ed. with
additions by W. Kranz. 3 vols. 6th ed. Berlin, Weidmannsche Verlagsbuch-
handlung, 1956-9.
•Freeman, Kathleen: Ancilla to the Pre-Socratic Philosophers: A Complete Translation
of the Fragments in Diels, Fragmente der Vorso\rati\er. Oxford, Blackwell, 1956.
•Kirk, G. S., and J. E. Raven: The Presocratic Philosophers: A Critical History with a
Selection of Texts (in Greek and English). Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press, 1962.
Diogenes Laertius: Lives of Eminent Philosophers, trans, by Robert Drew Hicks.
(Loeb Classical Library.) 2 vols. Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press;
London, Wm. Heinemann, Ltd., 1950.
Capelle, Wilhelm: Die V orso\rati\er Die Fragmente und
: Quellenberichte. Leipzig,
Kroner, 1935.
Nestle, Wilhelm: Die griechischen Philosophen. Vol. 1: Die Vorso\ratiker. Jena, E.
Diederichs, 1908; 4th ed., Diisseldorf-Cologne, E. Diederichs, 1956. Vol. 2: Die
So\rati\er. Jena, E. Diederichs, 1923. Vols. 3-4: Die Nachso^ratiJ^er. Jena, E.
Diederichs, 1923.
Grunwald, Michael: Die Anfange der abendlandischen Philosophic: Fragmente und
Lehrberichte der Vorso\rati\er. Zurich, Artemis- Verlag, 1949.
Snell,Bruno: Herahjit: Fragmente , Griechisch und Deutsch. Munich, Heimeran Ver-
lag, 1926; 2d ed., Munich, Heimeran Verlag, 1940.
Parmenides, in Plato and Parmenides, trans, with introduction and running com-
mentary by Francis Macdonald Cornford. London, Routledge & Kegan Paul;
New York, Liberal Arts Press, 1957.
435
436 The Original Thinners
SECONDARY WORKS:
Bernays, Jacob: Die hera\litischen Briefe: Ein Beitrag zur philosophischen und reli-
gions gesc hie htlic hen Literatur. Berlin and London, 1869.
Burnet, John: Early Gree\ Philosophy. London, A. & C. Black, 1892; 4th ed. Lon-
don, A. & C. Black, 1930; New York, Meridian Books, 1957.
*Cherniss, Harold Frederick: Aristotle's Criticism of Presocratic Philosophy. Baltimore,
Johns Hopkins Press, 1935.
•Cornford, Francis Macdonald: Principium Sapientiae: The Origin of Gree\ Philo-
sophical Thought, ed. by W. K. C. Guthrie. Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press, 1952.
: Plato and Parmenides. London, Routledge & Kegan Paul; New York, Liberal
Arts Press, 1957.
Frankel, Hermann Ferdinand: Wege und Formen friihgriechischen Den\ens. Mu-
nich, Beck, 1955; Munich, Beck, 1962.
2d ed.,
* : Dichtung und Philosophic des friihen Griechentums: Eine Geschichte der
griechischen Literatur von Homer bis Pindar. (American Philological Association,
Philological Monographs, No. 13.) New York, American Philological Associa-
tion, 1 95 1.
•Freeman, Kathleen: The Pre-Socratic Philosophers: A Companion to Diels, Frag-
mente der Vorso\rati\er. 3d ed. Oxford, Blackwell, 1953.
Fritz, Kurt von: "Nous, noein and Their Derivatives in Pre-Socratic Philosophy (ex-
cluding Anaxagoras)," in Classical Philology, XL (October, 1945), 223-42; XLI
(January, 1946), 12-34.
Gigon, Olof Alfred: Untersuchungen zu Herahlit. Leipzig, Diederich'sche Verlags-
buchhandlung, 1935.
: Der Ur sprung der griechischen Philosophic von Hesiod bis Parmenides. Basel,
Benno Schwabe, 1945.
Jaeger, Werner: Paideia: The Ideals of Gree\ Culture, trans, by Gilbert Highet. 3
vols. New York, Oxford University Press, 1944.
: The Theology of the Early Gree\ Philosophers, trans, by Edward S. Robinson.
New York, Oxford University Press, 1947.
•Kirk, G. S.:"Some Problems in Anaximander," in Classical Quarterly, New Series V
(1955), 21-38.
• : Heraclitus: The Cosmic Fragments. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press,
1954.
Nebel, Gerhard: "Das Sein des Parmenides," in Der Bund, Jahrbuch, pp. 87-119.
Wuppertal, Marees Verlag, 1947.
Reich, Klaus, "Anaximander und Parmenides," in Marburger Winc\elmann-Pro-
gramm, 1950-51 , pp. 13 ff.
Plotinus
sources:
Plotini Opera, ed. Paul Henry and Hans-Rudolf Schwyzer. Porphyrii vita Plotini;
Enneades I-V. 2 vols. Paris, Desclee de Brouwer, 1951-9.
Enn<\uics. Vols. I-VI, text and French trans, by £mile Brehier. Paris, Societe d'edition
"Les belles lettres," 1956-63.
Schriften, trans, into German by Richard Harder. 5 vols. Leipzig, Meiner, 1930-7.
Schriften, text and German trans, with commentary. 5 vols. Hamburg, F. Meiner,
1956-64.
*The Enneads, trans, by Stephen MacKenna. 3d ed., rev. by R. S. Page, with foreword
by E. R. Dodds and introduction by Paul Henry. London, Faber and Faber,
1962; New York, Pantheon Books, Inc., n.d.
Longinus: On the Sublime, trans, by A. O. Prickard. Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1906.
SECONDARY WORKS:
Alfoldi, Andreas: "Die Vorherrschaft der Pannonier im Romerreich und die Reaktion
des Hellenentums unter Gallienus," in Eunfundzwanzig Jahre Rbmisch-Ger-
manische Kommission. Berlin, 1930.
•Armstrong, Arthur Hilary: The Architecture of the Intelligible Universe in the
Philosophy of Plotinus. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1940.
Brehier, £mile: La Philosophic de Plotin. Paris, Boivin, 1928. English trans.: The
Philosophy of Plotinus, trans, by Joseph Thomas. Chicago, University of Chicago
Press, 1958.
Dodds, E. R.: "The Parmenides of Plato and the Origin of the Neoplatonic 'One,'"
in Classical Quarterly (London), XXII (1928), 129-42.
*Henry, Paul: Plotin et V Occident. Louvain, "Spicilegium sacrum lovaniense," 1934.
*Inge, William Ralph: The Philosophy of Plotinus. 2 vols. 3d ed. London and New
York, Longmans, Green, 1929.
Kirchner, Carl Hermann: Die Philosophic des Plotin. Halle, H. W. Schmidt, 1854.
Kristeller, Paul Oskar: Der Begriff der Seele in der Ethi\ des Plotin. Tubingen, Mohr,
1929.
Nebel, Gerhard: Plotins Kategorien der intelligiblen Welt: Ein Beitrag zur Geschichte
der Idee. Tubingen, Mohr, 1929.
Oppermann, Hans: Plotins Leben: Untersuchungen zur Biographie Plotins. Heidel-
berg, C. Winter, 1929.
Richter, Arthur: Neu-Platonische Studien. 5 vols. Halle, Schmidt, 1864-7.
Rodenwaldt, Gerhart: "Zur Kunstgeschichte der Jahre 220 bis 270," in Jahrbuch des
Deutschen Archaologischen Instituts, Vol. LI, 1936.
*Schwyzer, Hans Rudolf: "Plotinos," in Realencyclopadie der classischen Altertums-
wissenschaft, ed. by Pauly-Wissowa, Kroll, Ziegler, Vol. XXI. Stuttgart, J. B.
Metzler, 1951.
438 The Original Thinners
Anselm
sources:
Opera omnia (vols. 1-2). Vols. 158-9 in Patrologiae cursus completus {Series Latino),
ed. by Jacques Paul Migne. Paris, 1863-4.
Opera omnia S. Anselmi Cantuariensis archiepiscopi, ed. by Franciscus Salesius
Schmitt. 5 vols. Edinburgh and London, Thomas Nelson & Sons, 1940—51.
*Eadmer: Life of St. Anselm, Archbishop of Canterbury, ed. with introduction, notes,
and a translation, by R. W. Southern. London and New York, Thomas Nelson,
1962.
*Basic Writings, trans, by Sidney Norton Deane. 2d ed. La Salle, 111., Open Court
Publishing Co., 1962.
SECONDARY WORKS:
Barth, Karl: Fides quarens intellectum: Anselms Beweis der Existenz Gottes im
Zusammenhang seines theologischen Programms. Munich, Kaiser Verlag, 1931.
•Clayton, Joseph: Saint Anselm: A Critical Biography. Milwaukee, Bruce Publishing
Co., 1933.
Daniels, Augustinus: Quellenbeitrage und Untersuchungen zur Geschichte der Gottes-
beweise im dreizehnten Jahrhundert, mit besonderer Beruckjichtigung des Argu-
ments im Proslogion des hi. Anselm. Miinster, 1909.
*Gilson, fitienne: History of Christian Philosophy in the Middle Ages. New York,
Random House, 1955.
Hasse, Friedrich Rudolph: Anselm of Canterbury, trans, by W. Turner. London,
1850.
Koyre, Alexandre: L'Idee de Dieu dans la philosophic de Saint Anselme. Paris, 1923.
Steinen, Wolfram von den: Vom heiligen Geist des Mittelalters : Anselm von Canter-
bury; Bernard von Clairvaux. Breslau, Ferd. Hirt, 1926.
Spinoza
sources:
Spinoza, Benedictus de: Opera, ed. by Carl Gebhardt. (Heidelberger Akademie.) 4
vols. Heidelberg, C. Winter, 1925.
*Opera quae supersunt Omnia Bcnedicti de Spinoza, ed. by Karl Hermann Bruder.
3 vols. Leipzig, Bernhard Tauchnitz, Jr., 1843-6.
•Van Vloten, J.: Ad Benedicti de Spinoza Opera quae supersunt Omnia Supplementum.
Amsterdam, Fr. Muller, 1862.
SECONDARY WORKS:
Altkirch, Ernst: Maledictus und Benedictus: Spinoza im Urteil des Voltes und der
Geistigen. Leipzig, Constantin Brunner, 1924.
•Arnold, Matthew: "Spinoza and the Bible," in Essays in Criticism. First Series. Lon-
don, Macmillan, 1937.
Back, Leo: Spinozas erste Einwir\ungen auf Deutschland. Berlin, Mayer, 1895.
•Brunschvicq, Leon: Spinoza et ses contemporains. 4th ed. Paris, Presses Universitaires
de France, 195 1.
•Chartier, £mile A.: Spinoza. Paris, Mallottee, 1929.
Cohen, Hermann: "Spinoza tiber Staat und Religion, Judentum und Christentum,"
in Judische Schriften, Vol. Ill (1924).
Dunin-Borkowski, Stanislaus, Graf von: Randglossen zu Spinozas Schrijt uber die
Freiheit des Philosophierens. No place, no publisher, 19 10.
: Spinoza. 4 vols. Miinster, Aschendorfr", 1933-6.
Erdmann, J. E.: "Spinoza," in Versuch einer wissenschaftlichen Darstellung der
Geschichte der neueren Philosophic 7 vols. (Facsimile of 1834-42 ed.) Stuttgart,
Frommann, 1933.
Fischer,Kuno: Spinozas Leben, Wer\e und Lehre. 5th ed. Heidelberg, C. Winter,
1919.
Freudenthal, Jacob: Die Leben sgeschichte Spinoza's in Quellenschriften, Ur\unden
und nichtamtlichen Nachrichten. Leipzig, Veit, 1899.
:Spinoza, Leben und Lehre. Heidelberg, C. Winter, 1927.
•Froude, J. A.: "Spinoza," in Short Studies
on Great Subjects. First Series. 3d ed.
London, Longmans, Green, 1868.
Grunwald, Max: Spinoza in Deutschland. Berlin, S. Calvary, 1897.
•Hampshire, Stuart: Spinoza. Harmondsworth, Middlesex, Penguin Books, 1951.
• : "Spinoza and the Idea of Freedom," in British Academy (London), Proceed-
ings, XLVI (i960), 195-215.
•McKeon, Richard: The Philosophy of Spinoza: The Unity of His Thought. New York,
Longmans, Green, 1928.
•Pollock, Sir Frederick: Spinoza: His Life and Philosophy. 2d ed. London, Duck-
worth; New York, Macmillan, 1899. 2d ed., corr. and reissued, London, Duck-
worth, 1 912.
•Roth, Leon: Spinoza, Descartes and Maimonides. Oxford, 1924; New York, Russell
& Russell, 1963.
• Spinoza. London, Allen & Unwin,
: 1954.
440 The Original Thinners
Serouya, Henri: Spinoza, sa vie, sa philosophic New ed., rev. & augm. Paris, A.
Michel, 1947.
Strauss, Leo: Die Religions\riti\ Spinozas als Grundlage seiner Bibelwissenschajt.
Berlin, Akademie-Verlag, 1930.
Verniere, Paul: Spinoza et la pensee francaise avant la Revolution. Paris, Presses Uni-
versitaires de France, 1954.
*Wolf, Abraham: Spinoza, Benedictus de: Short Treatise on God, Man and His Weil-
Being, trans, and ed. with introduction, commentary and a life of Spinoza by
Abraham Wolf. London, A. & C. Black, 1910.
*Wolfson, Harry Austryn: The Philosophy of Spinoza. 2 vols. Cambridge, Harvard
University Press, 1934; 2 vols, in 1, New York, Meridian Books, i960.
* :Spinoza: A Life of Reason. New York, Modern Classics, 1932.
Nicholas ofCusa
sources:
Nicolai Cusae cardinalis opera. 3 vols. (Reproduction of 1514 ed., Parisiis in Aedibus
Ascensianis.) Frankfurt am Main, Minerva, 1962.
Nicolai de Cusa Opera Omnia, ed. by Ernst Hoffmann and Raymond Klibansky. 14
vols. Leipzig, F. Meiner, 1932-64.
Texte seiner philosophischen Schriften, ed. by Alfred Petzelt. Vol. I. Stuttgart, Kohl-
hammer, 1949.
*The Vision of God, trans, by Emma Gurney Salter. New York, F. Ungar Publishing
Co., i960 (first published, 1928).
*0f Learned Ignorance, trans, by Germain Heron. London, Routledge & Kegan Paul,
1954.
*Unity and Reform: Selected Writings, ed. by John Patrick Dolan. Notre Dame, In-
diana, University of Notre Dame Press, 1962.
*Oeuvres Choisies de Nicolas de Cues, French trans, by Maurice de Gandillac. Aubier,
Editions Montaigne, 1942.
Schriften des Nikplaus von Cues in deutscher Uebersetzung, ed. by Ernst Hoffmann.
Leipzig, F. Meiner, 1936.
Predigten 1430-1441, German trans, by J. Sikora & E. Bohnenstadt. (Vol. 2 of
Schriften. .) Heidelberg, 1952.
. .
Heidelberg, 1949.
Die Kalenderverbesserung, German trans, by Viktor Stegemann. (Vol. 3 of Schrif-
ten. . Heidelberg, 1955.
. .)
Marsilius of Padua: Defensor Pads: Der Verteidiger des Friedens (Latin with Ger-
man trans., trans, by Walter Kunzmann), ed. by Horst Kusch. Berlin, Riitten &
Loening, 1958.
*Vxe\ itc-Orton, C. W., ed.: The Defensor Pacts of Marsilius of Padua. Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 1928.
•Enea Silvia Piccolomini: Commcntarii return ntcmontbilium: The Commentaries of
Pius II, trans, by Florence Alden Gragg, with historical introduction and notes
by Leona C. Gabel. Smith College Studies in History, XXII (Nos. 1-2, October,
1936-January, 1937); XXV
(Nos. 1-4, October, 1939-June, 1940); (1947); XXX
XXXV (1951); XLIII (1957). Northampton, Mass., Smith College Department
of History, 1936-57.
*Gabel, Leona C, ed.: Memoirs of a Renaissance Pope: The Commentaries of Pius II:
An Abridgment of the Translation by Florence A. Gragg. New York, Putnam,
1959.
*Enea Stlvio Piccolomini, Papst Pius II: Ausgewahlte Texte aus seinen Schriften, ed.
and trans, by Bertha Widmer. (Latin and German.) Basel, Benno Schwabe,
i960.
SECONDARY WORKS:
*Bett, Henry: Nicholas of Cusa. London, Methuen, 1932.
Bredow, Gerda von: Das Sein der Freiheit. Diisseldorf, L. Schwann, i960.
Cassirer, Ernst: Individuum und Kosmos in der Philosophic der Renaissance; Liber de
mente (Nicolaus Cusanus) trans, into German as Vber den Geist by Heinrich
Cassirer. Leipzig and Berlin, Teubner, 1927; 2d ed., Darmstadt, Wissenschaftliche
Buchgesellschaft, 1963.
Creutz, Rudolf: Medizinisch-physifalisches Den\en bei Nicolaus von Cues. (Sitzungs-
berichte der Heidelberger Akademie der Wissenschaften. Philosophisch-historische
Klasse, Jahrgang 1938/39.) Heidelberg, C. Winter, 1939.
Falckenberg, Richard: Grundzuge der Philosophic des Nicolaus Cusanus mit be son-
derer Beriic\sichtigung der Lehre vom Er\ennen. Breslau, W. Koebner, 1880.
Fromherz, Uta: Johannes von Segovia als Geschichtsschreiber des Konzils von Basel.
(Basler Beitrage zur Geschichtswissenschaft, Vol. 81.) Basel and Stuttgart, Hel-
bing & Lichtenhahn, i960.
Gandillac, Maurice Patronnier de: La Philosophic de Nicolas de Cues. Aubier, Edi-
Montaigne, 1941.
tions
Glossner, Michael: Nicolaus von Cusa und Marius Nizolius als Vorlaufer der neueren
Philosophic Minister, 1891.
Haubst, Rudolf: "Johannes von Segovia im Gesprach mit Nicolaus von Kues, und
Jean Germain iiber die gottliche Dreieinigkeit und ihre Verkiindigung vor den
Mohammedanern," in Munchener Theologische Zeitschrift, II (2d year, No. 2,
1951), 115-29.
* : Das Bild des Einen und Dreieinen Gottes in der Welt nach Ni\olaus von Kues.
Trier, Paulinus-Verlag, 1952.
Hoffmann, Ernst: Nicolaus von Cues und seine Zeit; Nicolaus von Cues und die
deutsche Philosophic (Two H. Kerle, 1947.
lectures.) Heidelberg, F.
:Cusanus-Studien, I. Das Universum des Nicolaus von Cues. (Sitzungsberichte
der Heidelberger Akademie der Wissenschaften. Philosophisch-historische Klasse,
Jahrgang 1929/30.) Heidelberg, C. Winter, 1930.
Der Streit des Cardinals Nicolaus von Cusa mit dem Herzoge Sigmund
Jager, Albert:
von Osterreich als Grafen von Tirol. 2 vols, in 1. Innsbruck, 1861.
Kallen, Gerhard: Nikolaus von Cues als politischer Erzieher. (Wissenschaft und Zeit-
Kallen, Gerhard: Die politische Theorie im philosophischen System des Nikolaus von
Cues," Historische Zeitschrijt (Munich), CLXV (1942), 246-77.
:Die handschriftliche Vberlieferung der Concordantia catholica des Nicolaus von
Kues. (Sitzungsberichte der Heidelberger Akademie. Philosophisch-historische
Klasse, Jahrgang 1963.) Heidelberg, C. Winter, 1963.
Kleinen, Hans, and Robert Danzer: Cusanus-Bibliographie ig20-ig6i: Mitteilungen
und Forschungsbeitrage der Cusanus-Gesellschaft, Vol. I, published by R. Haubst.
Mainz, Griinewald, 196 1.
Klibansky, Raymond: Ein Promos-Fund und seine Bedeutung. (Sitzungsberichte der
Heidelberger Akademie der Wissenschaften. Philosophisch-historische Klasse,
Jahrgang 1928/29.) Heidelberg, C. Winter, 1929.
Koch, Josef: "Nikolaus von Cues 1401-1464," in Die grossen Deutschen, I, 275-87.
Berlin, Propylaen-Verlag, 1935.
: "Nikolaus von Cues als Mensch nach dem Briefwechsel und personlichen
Aufzeichnungen," in Humanismus, Mysti\ und Kunst in der Welt des Mittel-
alters, pp. 56 ff. Leyden, Brill, 1953.
VogtS, I Kins: "Hospital St. Ntcolaus Ell Cues," in Deutsche Kunstjuhrcr an Rhrin
ufiJ Moscl, Vol. IV. Cologne, Augsburg, and Vienna, Filter, 1927.
Zimmermann, Robert: "Cardinal Nicolaus Cusanui als Vorlaufer Leibnitzens," in
Sttidien und Kriti^cn zur Philosophic und Acsthctily, I, 6 1 -83, 1 vols, in 1. Vi-
enna, W. Braumuller, 1870.
Lao-tzu
sources:
Tao te King, German trans, with commentary and introduction by Victor von
Strauss. Leipzig, Fr. Fleischer, 1870; reprinted, Leipzig, Verlag der "Asia Major,"
1924.
Lao-tszes Buck vom hochsten Wesen und vom hochsten Gut (Tao-te-\ing) , trans.
with introduction and commentary by Julius Grill. Tubingen, Mohr, 1910.
Laotse, Tao te King, das Buck des Alten vom Sinn und Leben, trans, with commen-
tary and introduction by Richard Wilhelm. Jena, E. Diederichs, 1913.
•Lin Yutang, trans.: The Wisdom of Laotse. New York, Random House, Modern
Library, 1948.
Chan, Wing-tsit, trans.: The Way of Lao Tzu. Indianapolis, Bobbs-Merrill Company,
Inc., 1963.
Nagarjuna
sources:
Die Buddhistische Philosophic in ihrer geschichtlichen Entwic\lung. 4 vols. Heidel-
berg, C. Winter, 1904-27. Vol. 2: Die mittlere Lehre des Nagarjuna, trans, from
the Tibetan version by Max Walleser (1911). Vol. 3: Die mittlere Lehre des
Nagarjuna, trans, from the Chinese version by Max Walleser (1912).
*Radhakrishnan, Sarvepalli: Indian Philosophy, Vol. I. New York, Humanities Press,
1958.
INDEX OF NAMES
445
446 Index of Names
Freudenthal, Jacob, 386 Kierkegaard, Soren, 35, 161, 268, 294, 360
Fromherz, Uta, 149 Koch, Josef, i88n., 237, 240
I philosophers vol. 2
Division of
Reference and Research Services