SSRN Id3304243
SSRN Id3304243
Brian Leiter
bleiter@uchicago.edu
to appear in P. Mindus & T. Spaak (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism
7/21/2019
By “legal positivism,” I mean the view about the nature of law that H.L.A. Hart
articulated most powerfully in 1961 (while learning from and modifying the work of Hans
Kelsen), and that Joseph Raz developed further in the 1970s and 1980s, according to which (1)
where a legal system exists, there exists a “rule of recognition” specifying the criteria in virtue of
which norms are valid law; and (2) a rule of recognition is nothing more than a complex psycho-
social artifact constituted by the practice of officials, in particular, the criteria of legal validity
they converge upon and which they treat as obligatory (in Hartian lingo: that they accept from
“an internal point of view”).1 That means laws and legal systems rest at bottom on the
By realist theories of law, I mean theories which: (1) describe without sentimental or
moralizing illusions what law is and how it actually operates in human societies (descriptive
adequacy takes priority over moralizing sermons); (2) recognize that law is never adequate to
explain how courts adjudicate all cases that come before them; and (3) account for law and
adjudication within the constraints of a naturalistic theory of the world, i.e., one that eschews
appeal to any entities or properties that do not find a place in successful empirical scientific
accounts of natural and social phenomena. Both the American and Scandinavian (self-
1
I take Hart’s view to be an improvement on Kelsen’s kind of positivism in several crucial respects, most
importantly, in naturalizing the notion of validity via appeal to certain kinds of social practices (Hart, in this regard,
has more in common with the Scandinavian Realist Alf Ross than he acknowledges, a point to which I return,
below). I do not view other self-proclaimed positivist views as serious contenders.
different ways, a point to which I return. Hart was a critic of both American and Scandinavian
legal realisms, though in both cases he missed his mark. The irony is that Hart’s legal positivism
is also a realist theory of law (more in the American than Scandinavian sense), and once we sort
out the misunderstandings and confusions, it will be clear that legal positivists and realists form a
unified theoretical front against the moralizing and ideological obfuscators about law, from Lon
Fuller to Ronald Dworkin.2 It will also turn out that one of Raz’s additions to Hart’s theory,
namely, the idea that law necessarily claims authority in Raz’s “Service Conception” sense,
Hart’s theory of law as developed in The Concept of Law (1961) is a realist theory in four
important respects.
First, Hart recognizes that law in modern societies operates primarily outside the courts,
namely, as a way of guiding ordinary people (sometimes with the help of lawyers) as to what
they can and cannot do and, in particular, how they can acquire various legally created powers,
such as the power to get married (and accrue the associated legal and tax benefits) or the power
to dispose of their property after their death. Any general theory of law that focuses primarily on
courts is not realistic. It is not simply that courts decide only a miniscule fraction of all legal
disputes (massive agreement about what the law requires, after all, is the norm in functioning
legal systems: see Leiter 2009: 1226-1228), it is that the primary function of law in modern
societies is to help people organize their affairs to avoid disputes, either with other citizens or
with the state: in other words, to avoid adjudication. Law tells people what they need to do to
2
This is not true of every view that self-identifies as either legal positivism or legal realism, but it is true for
the core cases discussed in the text.
also sets conditions under which their freedom can be restricted or their property seized.
Second, adjudication of some legal disputes inevitably involves judgments that are not
constrained by law but instead require the exercise of discretionary judgment, informed by non-
legal considerations: the law is sometimes rationally indeterminate (i.e., the class of legitimate
legal reasons underdetermines the decision the adjudicator must reach [Leiter 2007: 9-12]). Any
heaven is not realistic. Rules determinate in their application in most instances can never be
without uncertainty, unless they adopt patently absurd approaches, such as, “When the rule is
unclear, the plaintiff wins.” Hart saw, correctly, that indeterminacy in law was inevitable—
though he was wrong in thinking the “open texture” of language was its primary cause (a point to
which I return)—and he also saw correctly that this was not a feature of law anyone should try to
remedy (Hart 1961: 128-130): we are far better off with officials who can produce authoritative
resolution of disputes that no one anticipated than we would be with a system that tried to settle
Third, the social phenomenon of law is explicable in wholly naturalistic terms, without
recourse to objective moral values, or Kantian transcendental conditions on judgment: law and
legal systems exist entirely because of psychological and sociological facts about persons. On
one reading, the claim that law is part of the natural order is bound to seem trivial (theists and
others in the grips of religious illusions to one side): is not everything part of the “natural order”
of the world? But positivists and realists understand this claim in a more demanding way:
everything real is part of the causal account of nature developed by successful empirical
sciences, whether physics or biology or psychology. There are no facts outside the causal order
imposing, for example—but this is a complicated psychological and sociological fact about
persons, not a fact about the world apart from those psycho-social facts about persons. Any
theory that posits transcendental conditions on legal judgment (e.g., Kelsen) or mind-
Fourth, Hart recognizes that law is not necessarily a good thing, that governance by law has
costs, and as a result we should never presuppose that law is morally good or obligatory. This
has been the central idea of the positivist tradition in legal theory: we can say what the
normative system called “law” requires while recognizing that what the law demands may not be
what we should do. Talk of law not being “morally binding” must of course be given a non-
cognitivist gloss, consistent with Hart’s actual way of marking normative practices.3 Any
theory, like Dworkin’s, that builds the justification of coercive power into the nature of law is not
realistic.
Hart contributed to the perception that legal positivism was not a realist theory of law by
his famous, but ultimately misguided, criticisms of the American and Scandinavian legal realists.
The fault is not entirely his, to be sure: the American legal realists were rhetorically exuberant,
rather than analytically precise, and an unfortunate translation of Alf Ross’s Of Law and Justice
3
Recall that for Hart the ascription of the “internal point of view” to agents is based entirely on behavioral
criteria, i.e., what actors do and say. This no doubt betrays the influence of Gilbert Ryle’s behaviorism in
philosophy of mind.
4
See the discussion in Leiter & Etchemendy (2017: section 5.1), drawing on the work of Jakob
Holtermann.
Scandinavian, when, in reality, they have almost nothing in common: calling them both
instances of “realism” is mainly an accident of intellectual history and a confusion about words.
While the Scandinavians adopted the label “realism” to signal their opposition to metaphysical
idealists, who thought the nature of reality was dependent on the human mind and its categories, 5
-as being candid about what really happens (especially when courts decide cases), without
sentimental or moralistic illusions (cf. Leiter 2012). The latter is the sense of realism I am
The difference should hardly be surprising given the very different professional and
intellectual backgrounds of the two groups. The major American Realists—Karl Llewellyn,
Jerome Frank, Herman Oliphant, Max Radin, Underhill Moore, William O. Douglas, among
others—were law professors, lawyers and jurists, with no philosophical training and, rather
obviously, no aptitude for or interest in philosophical questions.6 What they were all interested
in was how courts actually decide cases, and what lawyers and law students needed to know if
they were to reliably advise their clients about how they would fare in the courts. They advanced
no theses about the nature of law apart from these practical litigation-oriented concerns, though it
is striking that their tacit assumptions about the nature of law were all positivist ones, a point to
5
Hägerstrom is a case in point: see Mindus (2009: 48). Mindus also notes other writers skeptical about
the lumping together of Scandinavian and American Realism, id. at 137 n.2.
6
Felix Cohen was the exception—although his philosophy PhD served him badly. See, e.g., (Cohen 1935),
which arguably adopts an indefensible version of rule-skepticism. For discussion, see Leiter (2007: 68-73).
formal training in philosophy, and all were primarily academics and scholars who conceived of
1998), they were occupied with variations on what philosophers call the “location problem,” that
is, the problem of how to locate some phenomenon—e.g., consciousness or moral value—in a
world naturalistically conceived, that is, conceived in the causal terms described by the empirical
sciences. So, for example, philosophers interested in the location problem might ask how we
make sense of subjective conscious experience, or of the idea that something is morally wrong,
in a world that is exhaustively explained by physics, chemistry and biology? Or, how can we
locate the experience of Beethoven’s 9th Symphony as beautiful, or the sense that genocide is a
moral abomination, in a world thought to be composed of nothing other than physical, chemical,
For the Scandinavian Realists, the precise issue was how to locate a legal system of
norms in a world so conceived. The Scandinavians were philosophically diverse on some issues,
so generalizing about them will no doubt run roughshod over some individual differences. Yet
there are two basic issues at stake: metaphysical (do these norms really exist?) and semantic
(what is the meaning of legal statements mentioning such norms?). On the metaphysical
question, there are elements of eliminativism in the views of Olivecrona (1971) and Ross (1959).
Just as the eliminativist about religious discourse thinks that the entities that religious discourse
refers to (gods, souls, spirits) do not exist, and so should be eliminated from any realistic picture
of what the world is like, the legal eliminativist thinks that legal obligations, legal rights, and
legal duties do not really exist either, since such concepts play no role in a scientific explanation
views according to which statements about legal obligations, rights and duties do not really try to
refer to anything, but are simply the expression of the “attitudes” of legal actors.7 So, for
example, judgments about legal obligations and duties are interpreted as expressing certain non-
cognitive attitudes or feelings: a court’s judgment of the form, “Mr. Smith has a contractual
obligation to pay Mr. Jones $5,000 for those widgets” really means something like, “I, the judge,
feel the force of the legal demand that Mr. Smith pay under these circumstances, and if he
doesn’t, I will sanction him!” The psychologism of some of the Scandinavians held that legal
norms, both their existence and their effects on behavior, were to be explained in terms of the
psychological states of persons who accepted these norms, rather than the reality of the norms:
that X believes or feels he has a duty or obligation is what is explanatory of behavior, not the
existence of the duty (cf. Mindus 2009: 142 n. 31). A similar kind of psychologism is, I think,
implicit in Hart, though he sometimes cannot quite acknowledge it, perhaps because of the
influence of J.L. Austin’s ordinary language philosophy on his thinking. This requires further
explication.
Hart was a metaphysical anti-realist about moral norms: such norms do not really exist,
since the best explanation of the world would not include facts about what is morally right and
wrong. This might suggest that the normativity of morals—the ability of what is morally right
psychological terms, i.e., as a psychological fact about what particular people believe and feel
when they are told that, “It is morally wrong to do X” or “It is morally right to Y.” The most
charitable reading of Hart should understand him as accepting something like this view, since,
7
See the more detailed discussion in Leiter & Etchemendy (2017: section 5.1). See also Spaak
(2011: 163-165; 2009: 493-494). As Patricia Mindus reminds me, Hägerstrom is an unusual case,
opting for an error theory about “rights,” but a kind of emotivism about judgments of moral value.
conjoined with non-cognitivism about the semantics of normative judgment: to judge that doing
X is morally (or legally) wrong is just to express a certain kind of attitude or feeling, presumably
one tied—psychologically—to motivation and action (cf. Toh 2005). Hart did, of course, reject
the view he attributed to Alf Ross, namely, that legal validity consists in “a verifiable hypothesis
about future judicial behavior and its special motivational feeling” (Hart 1959: 165). (Hart
failed to realize that this was a stipulative account in Ross, not an ordinary language account:
Ross wanted to show how we could “locate” doctrinal or “external” statements about what the
law is in a world naturalistically conceived, a point to which I return.) For Hart, to say that a
legal rule is valid is just to say that it satisfies the criteria of legal validity in the Rule of
Recognition. But neither I nor Ross is denying Hart’s conceptual point about judgments by legal
actors about legal validity, namely, that its meaning is not reducible to predictions about
behavior: even Ross’s treatment of such judgments was non-cognitive, like Hart’s (Ross 1959:
6-9). Rather, the point at issue here concerns what an anti-realism about norms, which Hart
accepts, entails about motivation and action. On the realist/naturalist view, to the extent an
agent’s judgment that X is morally right (or legally obligatory) has normative force for the agent,
that normative force is explicable in terms of certain psychological facts about the agent. Hart
sometimes seems to deny this, e.g., when he says that “the internal character of [normative legal
judgments, like, ‘You must stop at the red light’] is not a mere matter of the speaker having
certain ‘feelings of compulsion’; for though these may indeed often accompany the making of
such statements they are neither necessary nor sufficient conditions of their normative use in
criticizing conduct, making claims and justifying hostile reactions by reference to the accepted
standard” (Hart 1961: 167) But Hart is best understood here as simply revealing his
‘internal point of view’ simply in virtue of using the right kind of normative language and
making the right kinds of justificatory or critical comments about, respectively, conforming or
deviant behavior vis-à-vis some rule. Contemporary naturalists have no reason to accept the
domains.
In sum, the Scandinavians have deeper affinities with the great Austrian legal positivist
Hans Kelsen and the great English legal positivist H.L.A. Hart than they do with the American
Realists: the latter want to figure out why courts decide as they do, and then let lawyers in on the
real causes accordingly; while all the former—that is, Kelsen, Hart, and the Scandinavians--are
interested in traditional philosophical questions about the metaphysical nature of law and (in the
case of Hart and the Scandinavians) how it can be located within a naturalistic worldview, that is,
one that takes for granted that the world is, more or less, as the sciences describe it. Hart and the
Scandinavians differ from Kelsen in their willingness to think the answer can involve
“naturalizing” certain normative concepts in law, that is, understanding them as complicated
psychological and sociological artifacts, and thus as part of what Kelsen would have understood
Hart attributes to legal realism a view he calls “rule-skepticism,” a view he deems correct
in certain instances (consistent with his own realism about adjudication). Hart considers two
different kinds of rule-skepticism. One, which I will call “Conceptual Rule-Skepticism,” holds
that “talk of rules is a myth, cloaking the truth that law consists simply of the decisions of courts
and the predictions of them” (Hart 1961: 133). The second is the only important kind for his
8
I’ve explored that possibility as well: see the essays in Part II of Leiter (2007).
this view, “Rule-scepticism has a serious claim on our attention, but only as a theory of the
function of rules in judicial decision” (Hart 1961: 135); more precisely, this realist/skeptic claims
“that it is false, if not senseless, to regard judges as themselves subject to rules or ‘bound’ to
Scandinavian Realists. Conceptual Rule-Skepticism is a claim about the nature of law, i.e., that
it consists only in what courts say or in predictions of what courts will do. Hart’s critique of this
view (cf. Leiter 2007: 69-73): such a theory of the ordinary concept of law cannot account for
how judges think about what the law “obligates” them to do, or about the way in which lawyers
and citizens criticize judicial conduct by reference to the law. But did either the Scandinavians
Alf Ross, as we have seen, did proffer something like this, but not because he thought it
was adequate to the “ordinary” usage of the concept of law, or because he was insensitive to the
statements about what the law is by scholars and observers, one that would make sense of its
about “duties” and “obligations” as empirical predictive claims, Ross aimed to show that law
was not polluted with metaphysical nonsense. Ross was not doing ordinary language
philosophy about how things looked to legal insiders; Hart was. Hart criticized Ross as offering
an implausible analysis of the “ordinary” concept; Ross would have agreed. Hart offered no
direct response to the actual “location problem” Ross was concerned with.
10
fairness to him, at least one Realist, Felix Cohen, was, arguably, a Conceptual Rule-Skeptic,
although Cohen is nowhere cited by Hart: Hart’s American Legal Realism relies on an
amalgamation mainly of Frank, Holmes, and Llewellyn. Plainly these writers do talk about the
importance of “predicting” what courts will do. The question is whether, in so talking, they are
fairly read as offering an analysis of the concept of law. Only Hart’s grossly anachronistic
The idea that philosophy involves "conceptual analysis” via the analysis of language (or
analytic philosophy of the twentieth-century; indeed, as practiced by Hart, it really reflects the
influence of fashionable views in philosophy of language current at Oxford in the 1940s and
1950s. The American Realists were not philosophers, let alone analytic philosophers, let alone
students of G.E. Moore, Russell, and Wittgenstein, let alone colleagues of J.L. Austin. The idea
that what demands understanding about law is the “concept” of law as manifest in ordinary
language and ordinary intuitions would have struck them as bizarre. While the Realists had
much to say about adjudication and how legal rules work in practice, they had nothing explicit to
say about the “ordinary” concept of law or our intuitions about it.9
So what did the American Realists mean in talking about ‘prediction’? In Law and the
Modern Mind, Jerome Frank cautions the reader early on that he “is primarily concerned with
‘law’ as it affects the work of the practicing lawyer and the needs of the clients who retain him”
9
Raz and his followers often obscure this point. Raz, for example, claims that the argument for his “hard”
or “exclusive” positivism “is not an argument from the ordinary sense of ‘law’ or any other term. It relies on
fundamental features of our understanding of a certain social institution, the primary examples of which are
contemporary municipal legal systems....” (1979: 50). But all his examples are examples of ordinary or familiar
distinctions people draw between law and other normative systems, between legal and other kinds of normative
competence. The giveaway is the appeal to “our understanding of a certain social institution”: what could that
possibly be other than an armchair report of what Raz takes people to say and believe about law
11
about the meaning of law to lawyers who will “appear before judges, or...advise people in such a
way as to keep them out of court” (1897: 457). Against this background, infamous statements
like Llewellyn’s--”What these officials do about disputes is, to my mind, the law itself” (1930:
3) --make perfect sense. Theirs is not a claim about the “concept” of law, but rather a claim
about a practical heuristic, how it is helpful to think about law for attorneys who must advise
clients what to do. For your client the franchisee in Connecticut doesn’t simply want to know
what the rule on the books in Connecticut says; he wants to know what will happen when he
takes the franchisor to court. So from the practical perspective of the franchisee, what one wants
to know about the “law” is what, in fact, the courts will do when confronted with the franchisee’s
grievance. That is all the law that matters to the client, all the law that matters to the lawyer
advising that client. And that is all the American Realists wanted to emphasize.
Ironically, it turns out the American Realists could not have been Conceptual Rule-
Skeptics, because their arguments for the indeterminacy of law actually presuppose the
positivist’s concept of law. The central claim of legal indeterminacy is the claim of rational
indeterminacy: the claim that the “class of legal reasons” fails to justify a unique outcome in
some or all cases. The “class of legal reasons” is the class of reasons that are taken to properly
justify a legal conclusion (and thus “compel” it insofar as legal actors are responsive to valid
legal reasons). So, for example, appeal to a statutory provision or a valid precedent are parts of
the class of legal reasons in the United States, while appeal to the authority of Plato’s Republic is
not: a judge is not obliged to decide one way rather than another because Plato says so. Any
argument for indeterminacy, then, presupposes some view about the boundaries of the class of
legal reasons. When Herman Oliphant (1928) argues, for example, that the promise-not-to-
12
prevalent in the commercial culture in which the disputes arose, this only shows that the law is
indeterminate on the assumption that the normative reasons the courts are actually relying upon
are not themselves legal reasons.10 So, too, when Holmes chalks up judicial decisions not to
legislative policy” (1897: 467) he is plainly presupposing that these policy concerns are not
themselves legal reasons. The famous American Realist arguments for indeterminacy which
focus on the conflicting, but equally legitimate ways, lawyers have of interpreting statutes and
precedents11 only show that the law is indeterminate on the assumption either that statutes and
precedents largely exhaust the authoritative sources of law or that any additional authoritative
norms not derived from these sources conflict. It is the former assumption that seems to
motivate the Realist arguments. Thus, Llewellyn says that judges take rules “in the main from
authoritative sources (which in the case of law are largely statutes and the decisions of the
courts)” (1931: 13). In short, the American Realists presuppose something like the positivist
idea of a rule of recognition whose criteria of legality are exclusively ones of pedigree: a rule (or
canon of construction) is part of the law in virtue of having a source in a legislative enactment or
Matters are more interesting with respect to what I am calling Empirical Rule-
10
According to Oliphant, the courts found ways to enforce promises by sellers of business not to compete
with purchachers, because this made good economic sense: there would be no point to the transaction otherwise.
By contrast, courts found ways to invalidate promises not to compete by employees by employers, since such
arrangements were disfavored by trade guilds and took unfair advantage of the bargaining position of employees.
11
The classic discussions are Llewellyn (1930: 72-76); Radin (1930); Llewellyn (1950: 395-406).
12
One difference is that most positivists recognize customary practices as sources of valid law, whereas it is
not clear what the Realists think about this.
13
circumscribe the open texture [of language in which rules are framed]: so that it is
decide cases as they do. They may act with sufficient predictable regularity and
uniformity to enable others, over long periods, to live by courts’ decisions as rules.
Judges may even experience feelings of compulsion when they decide as they do, and
these feelings may be predictable too; but beyond this there is nothing which can be
Empirical Rule-Skepticism on this rendering, then, involves two claims: (1) legal rules are
indeterminate; and, as a result, (2) legal rules do not determine or constrain decisions.
Obviously (1) is not an empirical claim, but a philosophical or jurisprudential one. But
(2) could be true even if (1) were false (that would be pure Empirical Rule-Skepticism, we might
say). Yet Hart is surely correct that most American Realists endorse both (1) and (2).
Unfortunately, Hart is mistaken about the Realist argument for (1), and thus underestimates the
amount of indeterminacy in law. And the real dispute, if there is one, between the American
Remember that Hart acknowledges that legal rules are indeterminate, but claims that is a
phenomenon at “the margin of rules” (1961: 135); the realist skeptic, on Hart’s rendering, is
simply “a disappointed absolutist” (1961: 135), someone who set the bar for legal determinacy
too high. But the American Realists, with some exceptions (notably Jerome Frank), recognized
that law was mostly rationally determinate; they pointed out that it tended to be indeterminate,
however, in those cases that reached the stage of appellate review. And they argued for that
proposition based on the empirical evidence of lines of appellate cases that could not be
14
According to Hart, legal rules are indeterminate because “there is a limit, inherent in the
nature of language, to the guidance which general language can provide” (1961: 123).
There will indeed be plain cases constantly recurring in similar contexts to which
general expressions are clearly applicable (“If anything is a vehicle a motor-car is one”)
but there will also be cases where it is not clear whether they apply or not. (“Does
‘vehicle’ used here include bicycles, airplanes, roller skates?”). The latter are fact-
some of the features of the plain cases but others which they lack. (1961: 123)
Language is “open-textured” in that while words have “core” instances--aspects of the world that
clearly fall within the extension of the word’s meaning--they also have “penumbras,” cases
where it is unclear whether the extension includes the aspect of the world at issue. In cases in
which the facts fall within the penumbra of the key words in the applicable legal rule, a court
“must exercise a discretion, [since] there is no possibility of treating the question raised...as if
there were one uniquely correct answer to be found, as distinct from an answer which is a
While some writers have challenged the implicit semantics that informs this argument for
the indeterminacy of language (a fortiori of law),13 I think we should agree with Hart that legal
rules must necessarily be indeterminate in some measure given the indeterminacy of language
itself, and that this type of indeterminacy resides “at the margin of rules” (1961: 132). What
13
For criticism of such approaches, see Leiter & Etchemendy (2017: section 5.3).
15
The American Realists located the indeterminacy of law not in general features of
language itself, but in the existence of equally legitimate, but conflicting, canons of interpretation
that courts could employ to extract differing rules from the same statutory text or the same
precedent.14 Indeterminacy resides not in the rules themselves, but in the ways we have of
characterizing what rules statutes and precedents contain. Llewellyn, for example, argues that
any precedent can be read “strictly” or “loosely,” and that either reading is “recognized,
legitimate, honorable” (1930: 74). The strict interpretation characterizes the rule of the case as
specific to the facts of the case; the loose interpretation abstracts (in varying degrees) from the
specific facts in order to treat the case as standing for some general norm. But if “each precedent
has not one value [that is, stands for not just one rule], but two, and...the two are wide apart,
and...whichever value a later court assigns to it, such assignment will be respectable, traditionally
sound, dogmatically correct” (1930: 76), then precedent, as a source of law, cannot provide
reasons for a unique outcome, because more than one rule can be extracted from the same
precedent.
Llewellyn thinks the same is true of statutory interpretation, where one can find
“‘correct,’ unchallengeable rules of ‘how to read’ which lead in happily variant directions”
(1950: 399). By mining the cases, Llewellyn shows that courts have endorsed contradictory
canons of construction, like “A statute cannot go beyond its text,” but also “To effect its purpose
a statute must be implemented beyond its text” (1930: 90). But if a statute can properly be
construed in contradictory ways to stand for different rules, then reasoning from the statute will
16
legitimate legal argument. The assumption is that if lawyers and courts employ some form of
form of argument is legitimate in any and all cases. Put in this strong form, the assumption
cannot be right: not every strict construal of precedent will be legally proper in every case.
Even Llewellyn must recognize this, as suggested by his famous--but clearly facetious--example
of the strict reading that yields, “This rule holds only of redheaded Walpoles in pale magenta
Buick cars” (1930: 72). But that would never be a legitimate construal of a precedent (barring
some bizarre scenario in which all these facts turned out to be legally relevant), and Llewellyn
surely knows as much. The claim cannot be, then, that any strict or loose construal of precedent
is always valid. It must only be that lawyers and judges have this interpretive latitude often
Notice that the Realist argument for Empirical Rule-Skepticism is actually conceptually
severable from the claim that the law is indeterminate. For centrally, it is based on the
observation that the decisions courts reach do not fall in to patterns that correlate with the rules
they invoke; rather the decisions reflect judges’ response to the underlying facts of the cases.
This was the point of Oliphant’s example of the promise-not-to-compete cases mentioned earlier;
it is Llewellyn’s point too in his discussion of the New York sales cases.16 What causes judges
15
In an unpublished paper, Leslie Green has objected that there appears no principled explanation why
the indeterminacy should not go “all the way down,” as it were. But the key is that the argument depends on a
“sociological” notion of which interpretations of sources are “legitimate,” meaning accepted by most lawyers and
judges. Lawyers and judges may, of course, treat interpretive moves as acceptable even without a principled basis
for doing so.
16
Llewellyn (1960: 122-124). According to Llewellyn, a series of New York cases applied the rule that a
buyer who rejects the seller’s shipment by formally stating his objections thereby waives all other objections.
Llewellyn observed that the rule seemed to have been harshly applied in some cases where the buyers simply may
not have known at the time of rejection of other defects or where the seller could not have cured in any case. Upon
looking at the underlying facts of the cases, however, Llewellyn discovered that in each case where the rule seems
17
fair on the facts of the case at hand. All American Realists agreed on this point. Judge
Hutcheson claimed that “the vital, motivating impulse for the decision is an intuitive sense of
what is right or wrong for that cause” (1929: 285). Frank invoked the example of “a great
American judge,” Chancellor Kent, who had confessed that, “He first made himself ‘master of
the facts.’ Then (he wrote) ‘I saw where justice lay, and the moral sense decided the court half
the time; I then sat down to search the authorities....but I almost always found principles suited to
my view of the case....;” (1930: 104 note). Llewellyn noted that to understand what appellate
courts are really doing, one must appreciate “how far the proposition which seems so abstract has
roots in what seems to be the due thing on the facts [before the court]” (1930: 29). As a result,
Llewellyn’s advice for the lawyer was “on the facts...[to] persuade the court your case is sound,”
even if the lawyer must also provide a “technical ladder” to the “sound” result (1930: 76).
Frank pointed out that the very same advice had been given by a former President of the
American Bar Association (1930: 102 note). In short, the core of the Realist defense of
Empirical Rule-Skepticism is, in fact, empirical: they looked at what the courts (primarily the
appellate courts) really did, and found that legal rules were clearly not the determining factors in
to have been harsly applied what had really happened was that the market had gone sour, and the buyer was
looking to escape the contract. The court, being “sensitive to commerce or to decency” ((1960: 124) applied the
unrelated rule about rejection to frustrate the buyer’s attempted violation of a basic norm of commercial conduct:
namely, parties should honor their commitments even under changed market conditions. It is, in short, the
“background facts, those of mercantile practice, those of the situation-type” (1960: 126) that determine the court’s
decision.
17
Some legal rules, of course, structure the presentation of facts to the court, and thus “the facts of the
case at hand” are unintelligible without legal rules. Conceding this point does not change the fact, however, that
there still may be a disjunction (as the Realists claim) between the substantive rules of law that judges invoke in
their decisions and the real bases for their decisions.
18
did not overstate the irrelevance of rules. For one thing, the American Realists were (generally)
clear that their focus was indeterminacy at the stage of appellate review, where one ought to
expect a higher degree of uncertainty in the law. Cases that have determinate legal answers are,
after all, less likely to be litigated to the stage of appellate review. Most of the time, the Realists
seemed to understand this point. Thus, Llewellyn explicitly qualified his indeterminacy claim by
saying that, “[I]n any case doubtful enough to make litigation respectable the available
authoritative premises...are at least two, and...the two are mutually contradictory as applied to the
case at hand.” (1931: 1239). And Max Radin noted that judicial “decisions will consequently be
called for chiefly in what may be called marginal cases, in which prognosis is difficult and
uncertain. It is this fact that makes the entire body of legal judgments seem less stable than it
really is” (1942: 1271). Empirical Rule-Skepticism is surely more plausible when it is not
Notice now that even if we agreed with Hart that the open-texture of language affects
rules only “at the margins” (whatever that means, a point to which we return), the Realists have
now given us an additional reason (beyond Hart’s) to expect indeterminacy in law. If the
Realists are right, then not only do legal rules suffer from the open-texture that Hart describes,
canons of interpretation) seems sufficient to move indeterminacy from the margins to the center
19
In response to Llewellyn’s point, for example, that a court can interpret a precedent both
“loosely” and “strictly” and thus extract two different rules from the same prior decision, Hart
says simply this: “in the vast majority of decided cases there is very little doubt [as to the rule of
the case]. The head-note is usually correct enough” (1961: 131). Alas, a first-year litigation
associate knows that this approach to precedent would be a recipe for disaster. To extract
“holdings” without regard to the facts of the case--which is all a head-note typically provides--is
mediocre lawyering. Skillful lawyers know exactly what Llewellyn describes: that the “rule” of
a prior case can be stated at differing degrees of specificity, and so made to do very different
So both Hart and the American Realists acknowledge indeterminacy in law, and both
acknowledge, accordingly, that rules do not determine decisions in some range of cases. Hart
seems to think they disagree over the range of cases about which these claims hold true, but that
is not entirely clear. Consider Hart’s ultimate rejoinder to Realist skepticism about the influence
[I]t is surely evident that for the most part decisions...are reached either by genuine effort
reached, are justified by rules which the judge was antecedently disposed to observe and
whose relevance to the case in hand would generally be acknowledged. (1961: 137)
There is, alas, no argument here: “it is surely evident” is simply a denial of what the Realist
affirms, yet offers no evidence for the denial other than Hart’s armchair confidence in the
20
surprising, but I now think it the most plausible interpretation, given the clear Realist elements in
Hart’s own views, and the clear positivist elements in the views of the American Realists. After
all, when Hart limits indeterminacy to the “margin of rules,” this is against the backdrop of one
of his central insights, namely, that law exists mainly outside the courts as a way for individuals
to plan their affairs and guide their conduct. The American Realists sometimes make the
“American mistake” (think of Dworkin) of focusing far too much on courts, but if we put that
parochial prejudice aside, they have no theoretical reason to deny Hart’s insight. And that
insight is compatible with recognition that cases that reach the stage of appellate review are
especially likely to be ones where the law is indeterminate, precisely for “selection effect”
reasons: parties have more incentive to pursue further litigation when the law is unclear and the
result could go either way. Hart has no theoretical reason to deny this latter point.
Remember also that the American Realists explicitly did not discount the role of rules in
adjudication. Llewellyn is representative when he asks, “Do I suggest that...the ‘accepted rules,’
the rules the judges say that they apply, are without influence upon their actual behavior?” and
answers, “I do not” (1930b: 444). The Realist approach, says Llewellyn, “admits...some relation
between any accepted rule and judicial behavior” but then demands that what that relation is
requires empirical investigation, since it is not always the relation suggested by the “logic” (or
content) of the rule (1930b: 444). As he puts the point elsewhere: Realists deny that
(1931: 1237). But to deny only this claim is to admit that rules play some causal role in
decisions.
21
jurisprudence, that of Hart’s positivism and the Legal Realists. Both Hart and the American
Realists agree that valid legal rules (i.e., those with the relevant pedigree) matter, that they are
often determinate in their application, and that at the higher levels of adjudication, indeterminacy
obtains and judges must exercise discretion. In addition, the Scandinavian Realists can agree
that Hart has a satisfactory account of the “ordinary” concept of law, while disagreeing whether
the best attempt to solve the location problem for law in a world conceived naturalistically
requires the theoretical artifice of recasting normative talk in law in predictive terms or whether a
non-cognitivist approach, that arguably Hart favors, will suffice for statements about the law by
both legal actors and observers. And all the realists and the positivists agree that law does not
always suffice to explain what happens in adjudication and all reject the objectivity of moral
values. Even if there can be reasonable doubts about whether the muddle-headed American
Realists understood all these points, or whether the Scandinavian Realists, in the grips
(generally) of logical positivism, did, we can affirm that sensible realist jurisprudence can and
In the recent positivist tradition, the most influential contribution to the theory comes
from Hart’s student Raz, who argued, against Hart, that no rule of recognition at the foundation
of a legal system could incorporate moral, or content-based, criteria of legal validity (Raz 1985).
validity that they converge upon and treat as obligatory—it cannot, on Raz’s view, rely on
criteria of legal validity that require judges to assess the content of the norms to determine their
legal validity. According to Raz, law necessarily claims authority, even if it ultimately lacks a
22
the possibility of law claiming authority. A legal system can only claim authority if it is possible
to identify its directives without reference to the underlying (“dependent”) reasons for that
directive. This is a “prerequisite” for claiming authority because what distinguishes a (practical)
authority in the first place is that its directives preempt consideration of the underlying reasons
(including, e.g., moral reasons) for what we ought to do, and in so doing actually makes it more
likely that we will do what we really ought to do. But Hart’s “soft positivism,” as well as
Dworkin’s view, makes the identification of law depend on the very reasons that authoritative
directives are supposed to preempt, and thus makes it impossible for law to fulfill its function of
providing authoritative guidance. Thus, to the extent judges purport to treat norms as legally
blinding based on their appealing moral or other normative content, they are simply exercising
Soft positivists, defenders of Hart’s own official view in his “Postscript,” have lodged
various objections to Raz’s argument, but from a realist point of view, the real worry about Raz’s
argument is that it presupposes a highly moralized and unrealistic conception of what it is for law
to claim “authority.” Raz understands authority in terms of what he calls “the Service
“reasons” for acting in accordance with what Raz calls “right reason” than the subject would
arrive at without the intermediation of the authority (Raz 1985). (We can gloss, for purposes
here, “right reason” as what one really ought to do.) We can bracket for a moment the
extravagant metaphysics of reasons such a view requires—though it is hard to see how to make
sense of the objective existence of such reasons from a naturalistic point of view (Leiter 2015)--
and make a more modest objection: why think that when law claims authority it is claiming to
23
of the world to think this is implausible: of course law claims authority in the sense of claiming
the right to tell those subject to its jurisdiction what they must do, but the idea that this claim to
In defense of Raz’s view, one might note that legal systems do claim that what they
demand of their subjects is what they really ought to do. No legal system, after all, adopts as an
explicit principle: “Do this, even though it is wicked and unreasonable.” Most legal systems, in
fact, adopt the posture, “Do this,” without much further qualification at all, but let us concede the
point: it is still not sufficient to motivate Raz’s Service Conception even on its own terms.
Legal systems may often claim that they are requiring people to do what is morally right, or
God’s will, or in the public interest, and so on; but they do not claim that their subjects are more
likely to do what is morally right or God’s will or in the public interest by following the law’s
demands. Legal systems claim authority to direct their subjects’ behavior, but they do not do so
on the basis that they are thereby performing a “service” for their subjects.
This response exposes Raz’s repudiation of realism in legal theory: for, against Hart’s
conceptual and normative argument” (1986: 63) such that the account “does not necessarily
account in singling out important features of people’s conception of authority” (1986: 65). Of
course, no theorist thinks their descriptive account conforms “to everyone’s notion…in every
detail,” so this is just a distraction. But where is the evidence that Raz’s account even captures
some “important features of people’s [which people?] conception of authority”? Raz, I fear, has
24
subjects—without even the pretense that it satisfies even lax evidential demands of a “descriptive
Does that mean Hart was correct in the “Postscript” that rules of recognition can
incorporate content-based criteria of legal validity?19 Not quite, though not for the reasons I
have given previously. Hart himself, recall, agrees that a satisfactory account of law must
explain how the law fulfills an epistemic function, i.e., enabling at least officials to recognize
what the law is in many if not all cases. (Hart himself in “The Postscript” thought soft
positivism was compatible with such an epistemic function.) But I now reject the argument I
defended in Leiter (2007: 126-127), about what I called the “Extreme Scenario.” In this
scenario, it would be part of the conventional practice of officials to treat “Natural Law” as the
obligatory criterion of legal validity. Of course, the whole history of the world shows the
requirements of the putative “natural law” are a subject of massive controversy (because there is
no such thing), which might appear to mean that if a rule of recognition treated “Natural Law” as
the sole criterion of legal validity, it could not discharge any epistemic function. The problem
with this kind of objection—apart from its trading on conceptual possibilities not nomic
18
Moralized in the sense that its main aim is to explain why deference to authority by rational subjects can
be justified.
19
Shapiro (1998) offers a slightly different argument against soft positivism, one that relies not on a claim
about authority but on a claim about what it is to be “guided” by a rule (as he notes [1998: 487) “Hart...has
always claimed that the essence of law is the guidance of conduct.”) According to Shapiro, one is “motivationally”
guided by a legal rule when one’s “conformity is motivated by the fact that the rule regulates the conduct in
question” (1998: 490). Shapiro argues that on Hart’s view, the rule of recognition must provide motivational
guidance to officials (1998: 492) but that a rule of recognition incorporating content-based criteria cannot make a
“practical difference” to the judges: “The rule makes a practical difference to one’s practical reasoning [reasoning
about what one ought to do] only if, in this counterfactual circumstance, the agent might not conform to the rule”
(1998: 495). But, argues Shapiro, a rule of recognition incorporating moral criteria could provide no motivational
guidance, since judges are already motivated to do what morality requires. It should be obvious why this
argument fails, even if its conceptual claim about “providing guidance” is correct: first, it is unrealistic, indeed
preposterous, to think that judges are already motivated to do what morality requires; and second, even if
individual judges were motivated to act morally, there is no evidence that their understanding of morality
coincides with what the rule of recognition demands of them.
25
what they take to be “natural law,” and thus appeals to natural law can serve an epistemic
function. Hart’s own view of meaning--in terms of what competent speakers of a language
would take to be extensions of particular terms--should have led him to realize as much: “due
process” and “equal protection” may have bigger penumbras than “vehicle,” but they still also
have a core set of applications which speakers of the same language—and thus adherents to the
same moral ideology manifest in that language—will agree upon. And that means that content-
based tests of legal validity are not all the same: some are really ideological covers for exercises
of discretion (as hard positivists have always correctly emphasized), but others may simply
involve exactly the same kind of interpretive approach as with respect to any rule with the right
pedigree, i.e., appeal to a competent speaker’s understanding of the term (except, of course,
where pedigreed rules of interpretation dictate otherwise). We may still, from a positivist/realist
point of view, reject the idea of genuine content-based criteria of legal validity but that would be
on the grounds of the explanatory fruitfulness of that way of demarcating the legal from the non-
legal (Leiter 2007: __-__) and not from claims about the concept of authority. Law claims
authority, but not in Raz’s sense; judges sometimes treat moral considerations as criteria of legal
validity, but in the same way they treat the ordinary understanding of “vehicle” as a criterion of
applied legal validity in a particular case; and the best explanation of law does not need to
countenance as “law” those cases where judges treat moral considerations as criteria of legal
validity where that judgment depends entirely on substantive moral judgment and argument.20
References
Cohen, Felix. 1935. “Transcendental Nonsense and the Functional Approach,” Columbia Law
20
Thanks to participants in the conference in Stockholm in November 2018 for useful discussion and
comments—especially Patricia Mindus, Torben Spaak, and Kevin Toh. Thanks also to Michael Sevel for helpful
discussion of Raz’s views.
26
Hart, H.L.A. 1959. “Scandinavian Realism,” reprinted in his Essays in Jurisprudence and
-----. 1961. The Concept of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press). Citations are to the 3rd
Leiter, Brian. 2001. “Legal Realism and Legal Positivism Reconsidered,” Ethics . Reprinted
in Leiter (2007)
-----. 2011. “The Demarcation Problem in Jurisprudence: A New Case for Skepticism,”
-----. 2012. “In Praise of Realism (and Against ‘Nonsense’ Jurisprudence),” Georgetown Law
Journal
of Philosophy
----. 1930b. “A Realistic Jurisprudence—The Next Step,” Columbia Law Review 30: 431-465.
-----. 1950. “Remarks on the Theory of Statutory Interpretation,” Vanderbilt Law Review
27
Mindus, Patricia. 2009. A Real Mind: The Life and Work of Axel Hägerström ( ).
Olivecrona, Karl. 1971. Law as Fact, 2nd edition (London: Stevens & Sons).
Radin, Max. 1930. “Statutory Interpretation,” Harvard Law Review 43: 863-885.
-----. 1942.
Ross, Alf. 1959. On Law and Justice (Berkeley: University of California Press).
Spaak, Torben. 2009. “Karl Olivecrona on Judicial Lawmaking,” Ratio Juris 22: 483-__.
-----. “Karl Olivecrona’s Legal Philosophy: A Critical Appraisal,” Ratio Juris 24: 156-__.
28