STUMP, E. Aquinass Account of Freedom - Intellect and Will
STUMP, E. Aquinass Account of Freedom - Intellect and Will
STUMP, E. Aquinass Account of Freedom - Intellect and Will
1. Introduction
It is difficult to develop a comprehensive and satisfactory account of
Aquinas's views of the nature of human freedom.
For one thing, contemporary discussions of free will tend to belong
to an older, non-Thomistic tradition of thought about the topic. In this
tradition, human freedom is a property of just one component of human
mental faculties, namely, the will; and freedom consists in an agent's
ability to will autonomously in general and independently of the intellect
in particular. The influence of this tradition persists in contemporary dis-
cussion, both for libertarians and for their opponents, with the result that
Aquinas's account tends to be interpreted by its lights. Consequently, the
lineaments of his theory are obscured. For Aquinas, freedom with regard
to willing is a property primarily of a human being, not of some particu-
lar component of a human being. Furthermore, the will is not independent
of the intellect. On the contrary, the dynamic interactions of intellect and
will yield freedom as an emergent property or a systems-level feature.
Another reason why interpreting Aquinas's account is difficult is that
he gives a complicated analysis of the several acts of will he takes to be
associated with a free bodily action. Scholars sometimes pick out a subset
of these acts or even just one of them as if for Aquinas freedom of the will
were lodged in that sort of act of will alone. So, for example, it is
sometimes said that Aquinas has a particularly full treatment of free will
in De malo q.6 because in that text he discusses at length liberum arbitrium.1
But there is something anachronistic about trying to identify liberum
arbitrium with free will in our sense;2 volitions characterized by liberum
arbitrium are associated for Aquinas with only one sort of voluntary act,
namely, the sort he calls electio. De malo q.6 is therefore not about
freedom of the will as a whole but only about one of the acts of will,
is an appetite for the good and they are presented to it as good. For this
reason the intellect is said to move the will not as an efficient cause but as
a final cause, because its presenting something as good moves the will as
an end moves an appetite.5 This is one reason for calling the will a 'moved
mover' (as Aquinas notes that Aristotle does), because, in moving what is
under its control, the will is moved by an object intellectively apprehend-
ed as good, or an "intellectively cognized appetible,"6 as Aquinas puts it.
Understood in this way, the will can be seen as part of a larger
scheme. Because all things are created by a good God who wills what is
good for his creatures, all things are created with an inclination of their
own to the good, but of very different sorts. Some, like plants or even
inanimate things, have a built-in inclination to the good apart from any
cognition of the good. Aquinas sometimes calls this inclination a natural
appetite. (The sort of thing he has in mind is exemplified by plants
naturally turning toward sunlight.) Higher up the ladder of being are
animals of certain sorts which are naturally inclined to the good but with
some (sensory) cognition.7 They can cognize particular goods, although
they lack the ability to reflect on them or to think of them as good. Incli-
nation dependent on limited cognition of this sort Aquinas calls 'sensory
appetite'. Higher still are human beings whose inclination to the good is
dependent on intellect, which allows them not only to cognize particular
goods but to think about them reflectively as good. This inclination is
rational appetite, and it is what Aquinas takes the will to be.8 So close is
the association between intellect and will for Aquinas that he often speaks
of the will as being in the intellect,9 and he thinks that anything which has
intellect must also have will.10
Understood as rational appetite, the will is the primary mover of all
the powers of the soul (including itself) except the nutritive powers," and
it is also the efficient cause of motion of the body. Most important for our
purposes, the will exercises some degree of efficient causality over the
intellect. In some circumstances, it can command the intellect directly to
adopt or to reject a particular belief.12 It can also move the intellect by
directing it to attend to some things and to neglect others,13 or even to stop
thinking about something altogether. So, for example, while you are reading
a magazine, you come across an advertisement asking for money for
children, with an emotionally powerful picture of a starving child. Your
intellect recognizes that if you look at the ad for very long, you are likely
to succumb to its emotional force. Intellect sees the goodness of con-
AQUINAS'S ACCOUNT OF FREEDOM 579
tributing to the charity, but it also recognizes that if you give money to this
charity, you won't have it for the new computer you have been coveting.
Your desire for the new computer is strong and influences intellect to rank
saving money for the computer as best for you now. In consequence of the
finding on intellect's part, and with this influence from the passions, will
directs intellect to stop thinking about the charity, and (after a further in-
teraction of intellect and will) you turn the page of your magazine.
As this example shows, in addition to control over intellect by will,
the passions—sorrow, fury, fear, greed, etc.—can also influence the intellect,
because in the grip of such a passion, something will seem good to a
person which might not seem good to her otherwise.14 The intellect,
however, typically isn't compelled by the passions in any way;15 it can
resist them, for example, by being aware of the passion and correcting for
its effects on judgment, as one does when one leaves a letter written in
anger until the next morning rather than mailing it right away. Further-
more, the passions are themselves theoretically subject to the will. In other
animals, Aquinas says, motion follows directly from the sensitive appetite's
positive or negative reaction. In human beings, however, the sensitive
appetite awaits the act of the will, which is the superior appetite. The
lower appetite, Aquinas thinks, isn't by itself sufficient to cause movement
in other powers unless the higher appetite, the will, permits that movement.16
That is why, for example, human beings can go on hunger strikes and stay
on them to the point of starvation.
I raise the subject of the relation of the passions to intellect and will,
however, only to put it to one side. Although Aquinas has many interest-
ing things to say about the moral psychology of the passions, his account
of the intellect and will and the freedom that emerges from their interac-
tion is more than enough for our focus here. I will therefore introduce the
passions into the discussion only when it is necessary to do so in order to
understand what Aquinas has to say about intellect and will.
Just as the will can affect the intellect in various ways, so the intellect
can move the will (as a final, not an efficient, cause) in more than one way.
The will can be moved to will as distinct from not willing—the "exercise"
of its act; or it can be moved to will this rather than that particular thing—
the "specification" of its act.17
There is nothing in this life that invariably and ineluctably moves
every human will to the exercise of its act, because it is always in a
person's power to refuse to think of the thing at issue.18 Since will wills
580 ELEONORE STUMP
something only in case intellect presents it as some sort of good, the fact
that will can command intellect to stop thinking about something means
that will can, indirectly, turn itself off, at least with regard to a particular
action or issue. This is only a limited ability on the part of the will,
however, since the apprehensions of the intellect can occur without any
preceding act of will and so in some cases may force the issue back on the
agent's attention. That is why, for example, the prisoner who wants not to
think about what is happening next door where other prisoners are being
tortured will find that their screams make him recur to what he wants to
stop thinking about.19
As far as the specification of its act is concerned, there is no object,
other than happiness in this life and God in the next, which by its nature
necessarily moves every human will to want that.20 Because God has
created the will as a hunger for the good, every human will by nature
desires die good. And whatever is good to such a degree and in such a way
mat a person cannot help but see it as good, the will of that person wills
by natural necessity. One's own happiness is of this sort,21 and so a person
necessarily wills happiness.22 But even things which have a necessary
connection to happiness aren't willed necessarily unless the wilier is
cognizant of their necessary connection to happiness.23 Except for
happiness and things so obviously connected with it that their connection
is overwhelming and indubitable, it is not the case that every human will
is in general determined to one thing because of its relation to the intellect.
On Aquinas's account, the will wills only what the intellect presents at
that time as good under some description. Acts of will, then, are for
something apprehended or cognized as good at a particular time in partic-
ular circumstances, as distinct from something which is good considered
unconditionally or abstractly. Besides happiness and the vision of God, all
other things are such mat they can in principle be considered good under
some descriptions and not good under others, so that mere is nothing
about them which must constrain the will of any agent always to want
them. So, for example, the further acquisition of money can be considered
good under some descriptions in some circumstances—e.g., the means of
sending the children to school—and not good under others—e.g., wages
from an immoral and disgusting job.
Finally, the will can move itself in more than one way. It can move
itself indirectly by commanding intellect to stop thinking about something,
as we've just seen. It can also move itself indirectly because in virtue of
AQUINAS'S ACCOUNT OF FREEDOM 581
willing a certain end it moves itself to will the means to that end. That is,
the will wills a certain means because it wills a particular end and because
intellect presents that means as best for attaining that end.
But a more direct control over itself is possible for the will, too. All
the higher powers of the soul, Aquinas holds, are able to act on them-
selves.24 So, for example, intellect is able to cognize itself.25 By the same
token, the will can will to will.26 In fact, Aquinas confronts a problem that
has troubled some contemporary hierarchical accounts of the will, namely,
that there may be an infinite regress of higher-order willings. I can will
that I will something, and I can also will that I will that I will something,
and so on, apparently ad infinitum. But in such an apparently infinite
series, the will is not actually taking ever-higher orders of volition as its
object. At some point, Aquinas thinks,27 the apparently higher-order
volitions collapse, and the object of the will is just whatever action was at
issue at the beginning of the series of volitions.
If intellect does present something to the will as good, then, because
the will is an appetite for the good, the will wills it—unless will directs
intellect to reconsider, to direct its attention to something else, or to stop
considering the matter at hand. Will's doing such things, of course, is a
result of intellect's presenting such actions on the part of the will as good,
and that act of intellect may itself be a result of previous acts on the part
of the will directing the attention of the intellect. On Aquinas's view,
every act of willing is preceded by some apprehension on the part of the
intellect, but not every apprehension on the part of the intellect need be
preceded by an act of will.28
It is apparent, then, that on Aquinas's account, the will is part of a
dynamic feedback system composed primarily of the will and the
intellect, but also including the passions. The interaction between will and
intellect is so close and the acts of the two powers so intertwined that
Aquinas often finds it difficult to draw the line between them. So, for
example, he says that
. . . it happens sometimes that there is an act of the will in which something
of the [preceding] act of reason remains . . . and, vice versa, there is
[sometimes] an act of reason in which something of the [preceding] act of
will remains.29
That is why it sometimes looks as if, for Aquinas, will engages in acts of
apprehension and intellect engages in acts of willing.
582 ELEONORE STUMP
tests. In that case, his aversion may influence the intellect to give a divided
verdict: on the one hand, it would be good to undergo the tests, because
they are important for health; on the other hand, it would be bad to
undergo the tests because they are painful or disgusting. In such cases,
there may be considerable interaction among intellect, will, and passions,
until, in consequence of such iterated interaction, one side or another of
the divided intellect becomes strong enough to override the other. This is
a process familiar enough to anyone who has had to talk himself into
doing something he originally feared or disliked.
an act of the will is nothing other than an inclination which proceeds from an
interior cognizing principle .. . .but what is compelled or violent is from an
extrinsic principle.45
If something extrinsic to the agent were to act on the will with efficient
causation, then the tie of the will to the intellect, from which acts of will
get their voluntary character, would be broken, and so the act of the will
wouldn't be voluntary—or to put it more nearly as Aquinas seems to think
of it, in such a case it wouldn't be a real act of the will at all.
We might wonder here why Aquinas wouldn't grant that an act of
will could be voluntary even if it were caused by an extrinsic principle,
provided that the extrinsic principle produced its effects by operating
directly on the agent's intellect and only thereby, indirectly, on the agent's
will. Aquinas considers something like this question himself when he asks
whether Satan could bring it about that a human being sin.46 Aquinas sub-
scribes to the demon-possession theory of mental illness, so he supposes
that Satan can causally determine a human intellect (to one degree or
another) by possessing it. But this is to destroy it as a human intellect; an
insane person has lost his reason. At any rate, if some external agent S has
taken over entirely the intellect of some human H, then the intellect that
is operative in that human person is S's and not H's. In that case, what the
will operative in H wills might be voluntary, but it would count as S's will,
not H's, since the intellect that informs the willing is S's. In this case, there
can be an extrinsic principle S which operates on the intellect of some
other agent H, but the operation of the extrinsic principle won't give us an
act of will that can count as H's.
On the other hand, if we were to imagine Satan (or the evil neuro-
surgeon) invading H's intellect only partially, for example, by producing
a thought or a train of thoughts, H's intellect will then examine that
thought or set of thoughts and evaluate it, retaining or rejecting it according
as it seems right to H to do so. In that case, however, the voluntary acts of
will which may result will stem from the reflections of H's intellect, not
586 ELEONORE STUMP
S's. Here again, then, we will not have a case in which a voluntary act of
will on H's part is causally determined by an extrinsic principle S,
operating through H's intellect.
So, worries about grace aside, it should by now be clear that Aquinas
is not a compatibilist. The causal chain resulting in any voluntary act on
an agent's part has to originate in the system of the agent's own intellect
and will. If it originates in some cause external to the agent which acts
with efficient causation on the agent's will, what results will not be an act
of will at all. And if it takes over the agent's intellect which in turn deter-
mines the content of the agent's will, what results will not be an act of the
agent's will. So while extrinsic principles may influence human volition,
as, for example, we sometimes do when we persuade one another by
arguments, causes external to an agent cannot effect a voluntary act of will
on that agent's part, either directly or indirectly.
If Aquinas isn't a compatibilist, what sort of incompatibilist is he? It
seems clear that he must be a libertarian. And yet, although the outlines of
Aquinas's theory of human freedom are now somewhat clearer, it still
isn't obvious in what sense the will—or the system of will and intellect—
is supposed to be free. No doubt, part of what gives rise to this perplexity
is the presupposition, common enough in discussions of free will, that lib-
ertarian free will includes or even just consists in the ability to do
otherwise.47 But in what sense is it possible for the will, or the will-and-
intellect, to do otherwise on Aquinas's view?
liberum arbitrium should be considered on the basis of electio. But both the
cognitive power and the appetitive power contribute something to electio.
From the cognitive power we need counsel, by which we determine what is
to be preferred to what, andfromthe appetitive power we need the desire to
accept what counsel has determined.56
That is why, he goes on to say, Aristotle supposed we ought to assign
electio either to the "appetitive intellect" or to the "intellective appetite,"
phrases meant to indicate the intertwining of intellect and will in liberum
arbitrium. (Of this pair, Aquinas opts for "intellective appetite"—the will
understood as preceded by certain acts of intellect—as the more appro-
priate candidate for the faculty to which liberum arbitrium is to be
assigned.) Although he thinks that if we take liberum arbitrium to be a
faculty rather than one of the powers of a faculty, then it is just the will
itself, he emphasizes that liberum arbitrium is the will understood as in-
terwoven with and dependent on intellect.57
Finally, that will has the ability to do otherwise even in acts of electio
does not stem from the fact that the will may simply choose not to follow
intellect,58 or may act in some other way as a homunculus independent of
intellect. It concerns instead the relations between intellect and will.
Insofar as the will has control over itself, this is mediated by the intellect.
It is also limited, since there are intellective apprehensions which are not
preceded by or dependent upon acts of will. Will may not always succeed,
for example, in getting intellect to stop thinking about something, because
something in the environment causes the thought to recur repeatedly in the
intellect, as in the case described above of the prisoner who wants not to
think about what his hearing keeps calling to his mind, namely, the torture
of his fellow prisoners. But, within a limited range, will can be effective
at controlling intellect, for example, by being able in some circumstances
to redirect the attention of the intellect, and in that way the will can also
have indirect control over itself.
Of course, the will's directing intellect in any of these ways will
depend on intellect's presenting will's doing so as good in these circum-
stances. That is why a human agent's control over her own actions is a
function of intellect and will and is an emergent power or property,
resulting from the dynamic interaction between intellect and will, rather
than a static power localized in the structure of one particular faculty.
Given the nature of Aquinas's account of freedom, it makes more sense to
attribute freedom to a human being with regard to willing or acting than
AQUINAS'S ACCOUNT OF FREEDOM 589
(PAP) A person has free will with regard to (or is morally responsible for)
doing an action A only if he could have done otherwise than A.67
Aquinas would reject this principle not only for bodily actions but even
for acts of will.
Many contemporary philosophers also suppose that PAP is false. A
standard strategy for showing that PAP isn't necessary for free will is what
has come to be known as a Frankfurt-style counterexample.68 In such an
example, a person P does an action A in circumstances that incline most
people to conclude that P is doing A freely, but (in the example) there is
some mechanism that would have operated to bring it about that P would
have done A if P had not done A by himself. In the actual sequence of
events presented in the counterexample, however, the mechanism does
not operate, and P does do A by himself. So the counterexample is
designed to make us think that P does A freely in the actual sequence of
events although it is not the case that P could have done otherwise than
A.69 Frankfurt-style counterexamples can be constructed either for bodily
actions such as leaving a room or for mental actions such as deciding to
leave a room.
592 ELEONORE STUMP
Sam) has within himself not only his own consciousness but the master's
as well. Since it is crucial to the alien plan that their taking over human
beings be undetected in the early stages of the invasion, they are careful
to make the behavior of people like Sam correspond to the behavior Sam
would normally have engaged in had he not been infected with the alien.
So when, under the control of the alien, Sam does some action A, it is also
true that if there had been some reason sufficient for Sam in his uninfect-
ed state to do not-A, the alien would have brought it about that Sam in his
infected state did not-A. In that case, then, there is a possible world in
which Sam does otherwise than A. Sam has the ability to do otherwise,
then; nonetheless, Sam isn't free with respect to his doing A.
In the standard Frankfurt-style counterexamples, the absence of al-
ternative possibilities doesn't preclude an agent's acting on his own
unimpeded intellect and will in the actual sequence of events. In the
analogue counterexamples, the presence of an alternative possibility
doesn't stem from any ability that the agent's own intellect and will have
in the actual sequence. What the standard and analogue counterexamples
together show, I think, is the correctness of Aquinas's position. In order to
determine whether or not an agent is free, it is important to determine
whether the intellect and will on which he acts are his own, not whether
alternative possibilities are present or absent for him. For Aquinas, human
freedom depends on human cognitive capacities and on the connection of
the will to those capacities. Consequently, as long as human acts of will
originate in those faculties, those acts count as voluntary and free, even if
the agent couldn't have done otherwise in the circumstances or the act of
will is necessitated by natural inclinations of intellect and will.
So Aquinas holds a view which is libertarian in some sense. It
maintains that human beings have free will and that free will is incom-
patible with causal determinism. Nonetheless, this is a position that will
strike some libertarians as highly unsatisfactory. For some medieval lib-
ertarians (and for some contemporaries), an act of will is free only in case
the agent could have performed a different act of will in exactly the same
set of circumstances with exactly the same set of beliefs and desires.71 For
such libertarians, the alternative possibilities available to the will need to
be available to the will simultaneously, with the agent in the same state of
mind. On this way of thinking about free will, to be free, the will needs to
be unconstrained not only by causal influences outside the agent; it needs
to be unconstrained even by the agent's intellect. On Aquinas's view,
594 ELEONORE STUMP
Eleonore Stump
Saint Louis University
St. Louis, MO
NOTES
1. See, for example, Klaus Riesenhuber, "The Bases and Meaning of Freedom in
Thomas Aquinas," Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 48
(1974), 99-111, esp. p. 101.
2. Cf. J. Korolec, "Free Will and Free Choice" in the Cambridge History of Later
Medieval Philosophy (ed. Norman Kretzmann, Anthony Kenny, Jan Pinborg, associate
editor Eleonore Stump, [Cambridge University Press, 1981]), p. 630; David Gallagher,
"Thomas Aquinas on the Will as Rational Appetite," Journal of the History of Philosophy
29 (1991), p. 570, n.26; and Daniel Westberg, "Did Aquinas Change His Mind About the
Will?", The Thomist 58 (1994), 41-60.
3. Cf. David Burrell, Freedom and Creation in Three Traditions, (Notre Dame, IN:
University of Notre Dame Press, 1993), and Brian Davies, The Thought of Thomas Aquinas,
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), pp. 174-78.
AQUINAS'S ACCOUNT OF FREEDOM 595
33. See, for example, ST I—II q.6 a.4, and QDV q.24 a. 1 ad 1. Cf. also QDM q.6 a. 1 ad
22, where Aquinas says, "he who does what he does not want [to do] does not have free
action, but he can have free will."
34. STI-riq.lOa.3.
35. 5TI-IIq.17a.lad2.
36. Aquinas's position here is like his position as regards perception and intellection.
The proper sense organ for sight is the eye, and yet, Aquinas thinks, it is a human being
who sees, not the eye, and a similar point could be made about intellective cognition. See,
for example, ST I q.75 a.2 ad 2.
37. 5TI-Hq.6a.2andq.l7a.5.
38. 5TI-IIq.6a.3ad3.
39. 5TI-IIq.6a.lsc.
40. ST I—II q.6 proemium.
41. 5TI-IIq.6a.7ad3.
42. 5TI-IIq.6a.l corpus.
43. 5TI-IIq.6a.2.
44. ST I—II q.9 a.6. The exception to this claim about extrinsic principles is God, who
can be an extrinsic cause without removing voluntariness since he is the extrinsic cause
creating the will with its inclinations and its connections to the intellect. (See, for example,
5TIq.105a.4ad2.)
45. 5TI-IIq.6a.4.
46. ST I—II q.80 a.3. See also, for example, QDV q.24 a.2 where he says, "If the
judgment of the cognitive [faculty] is not in a person's power but is determined extrinsi-
cally (aliunde), then the appetite will not be in his power either, and consequently neither
will [his] motion or activity."
47. I discuss the relationship of libertarianism and the ability to do otherwise at some
length in "Libertarianism and the Principle of Alternate Possibilities," ed. Jeff Jordan and
Daniel Howard-Snyder. Faith, Freedom, and Rationality: Philosophy of Religion Today
(Rowman & Littlefield, 1996), pp. 73-88.
48. ST I q.83 a. 1 Obj.2. See also 5TI q.83 a.3, where Aquinas says, "we are said to have
liberum arbitrium when we can receive one and reject another."
49. 5TI q.83 a.3 sc.
50. 5TI q.83 a.4.
51. QDV q.24 a.6.
52. See, for example, ST I—II q. 13.
53. See, for example, 5TI-II q. 15 a.3 ad 3.
54. See also In NE III.v [434] where Aquinas says that the genus of electio is the
voluntary; on his view, although "every [act of] electio is something voluntary, electio and
the voluntary are not altogether the same, but the voluntary is in more [acts than electio
is]." One reason for insisting that electio is not identical to the voluntary is this: [436]
"Those things which we do quickly we say are voluntary, because their source is in us, but
they are not said [to be done] with electio, because they don't arise from deliberation."
55. 5TIq.l9a.l0obj.2.
56. 5TI q.83 a.3.
57. 5TI q.83 a.4.
58. Cf. QDM q. 16 a.2 where Aquinas says, "evil cannot arise in an appetite in virtue of
appetite's being discordant with the apprehension it follows."
59. QDV q.24 a. 12.
AQUINAS'S ACCOUNT OF FREEDOM 597