Friedrich Nietzsche
Friedrich Nietzsche
Friedrich Nietzsche
Nietzsche was a German philosopher, essayist, and cultural critic. His writings on truth, morality,
language, aesthetics, cultural theory, history, nihilism, power, consciousness, and the meaning of
existence have exerted an enormous influence on Western philosophy and intellectual history.
Aesthetics - a branch of philosophy that explores the nature of art, beauty, and taste, with the
creation and appreciation of beauty.
Nihilism - a philosophical doctrine that suggests the lack of belief in one or more reputedly
meaningful aspects of life. Most commonly, nihilism is presented in the form of existential nihilism,
which argues that life is without objective meaning, purpose, or intrinsic value
Introduction:
Nietzsche spoke of "the death of God," and foresaw the dissolution of traditional religion and
metaphysics. Some interpreters of Nietzsche believe he embraced nihilism, rejected philosophical
reasoning, and promoted a literary exploration of the human condition, while not being concerned
with gaining truth and knowledge in the traditional sense of those terms.
Nietzsche claimed the exemplary human being must craft his/her own identity through self-
realization and do so without relying on anything transcending that life—such as God or a soul.
This way of living should be affirmed even were one to adopt, most problematically, a radical
vision of eternity, one suggesting the "eternal recurrence" of all events. According to some
commentators, Nietzsche advanced a cosmological theory of “will to power.” But others interpret
him as not being overly concerned with working out a general cosmology. Questions regarding the
coherence of Nietzsche's views--questions such as whether these views could all be taken together
without contradiction, whether readers should discredit any particular view if proven incoherent or
incompatible with others, and the like--continue to draw the attention of contemporary intellectual
historians and philosophers.
Cosmology - study of the origin, evolution, and eventual fate of the universe.
Life:
Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche was born October 15, 1844, the son of Karl Ludwig and Franziska
Nietzsche. Karl Ludwig Nietzsche was a Lutheran Minister in the small Prussian town of Röcken,
near Leipzig. When young Friedrich was not quite five, his father died of a brain hemorrhage,
leaving Franziska, Friedrich, a three-year old daughter, Elisabeth, and an infant son. Friedrich’s
brother died unexpectedly shortly thereafter (reportedly, the legend says, fulfilling Friedrich’s
dream foretelling of the tragedy). These events left young Friedrich the only male in a household
that included his mother, sister, paternal grandmother and an aunt, although Friedrich drew upon
the paternal guidance of Franziska’s father. Young Friedrich also enjoyed the camaraderie of a few
male playmates.
Upon the loss of Karl Ludwig, the family took up residence in the relatively urban setting of
Naumburg, Saxony. Friedrich gained admittance to the prestigious Schulpforta, where he received
Prussia’s finest preparatory education in the Humanities, Theology, and Classical Languages. Outside
school, Nietzsche founded a literary and creative society with classmates including Paul Deussen
(who was later to become a prominent scholar of Sanskrit and Indic Studies). In addition, Nietzsche
played piano, composed music, and read the works of Emerson and the poet Friedrich Hölderlin,
who was relatively unknown at the time.
In 1864 Nietzsche entered the University of Bonn, spending the better part of that first year
unproductively, joining a fraternity and socializing with old and new acquaintances, most of whom
would fall out of his life once he regained his intellectual focus. By this time he had also given up
Theology, dashing his mother’s hopes of a career in the ministry for him. Instead, he choose the
more humanistic study of classical languages and a career in Philology. In 1865 he followed his major
professor, Friedrich Ritschl, from Bonn to the University of Leipzig and dedicated himself to the
studious life, establishing an extracurricular society there devoted to the study of ancient texts.
Nietzsche’s first contribution to this group was an essay on the Greek poet, Theognis, and it drew
the attention of Professor Ritschl, who was so impressed that he published the essay in his academic
journal, Rheinisches Museum. Other published writings by Nietzsche soon followed, and by 1868
(after a year of obligatory service in the Prussian military), young Friedrich was being promoted as
something of a “phenomenon” in classical scholarship by Ritschl, whose esteem and praise landed
Nietzsche a position as Professor of Greek Language and Literature at the University of Basel in
Switzerland, even though the candidate had not yet begun writing his doctoral dissertation. The year
was 1869 and Friedrich Nietzsche was 24 years old.
At this point in his life, however, Nietzsche was a far cry from the original thinker he would later
become, since neither he nor his work had matured. Swayed by public opinion and youthful
exuberance, he briefly interrupted teaching in 1870 to join the Prussian military, serving as a medical
orderly at the outbreak of the Franco-Prussian War. His service was cut short, however, by severe
bouts of dysentery and diphtheria. Back in Basel, his teaching responsibilities at the University and a
nearby Gymnasium consumed much of his intellectual and physical energy. He became acquainted
with the prominent cultural historian, Jacob Burkhardt, a well-established member of the university
faculty. But, the person exerting the most influence on Nietzsche at this point was the artist, Richard
Wagner, whom Nietzsche had met while studying in Leipzig. During the first half of the decade,
Wagner and his companion, Cosima von Bülow, frequently entertained Nietzsche at Triebschen,
their residence near Lake Lucerne, and then later at Bayreuth.
It is commonplace to say that at one time Nietzsche looked to Wagner with the admiration of a
dutiful son. This interpretation of their relationship is supported by the fact that Wagner would have
been the same age as Karl Ludwig, had the elder Nietzsche been alive. It is also commonplace to
note that Nietzsche was in awe of the artist’s excessive displays of a fiery temperament, bravado,
ambition, egoism, and loftiness— typical qualities demonstrating “genius” in the nineteenth century.
In short, Nietzsche was overwhelmed by Wagner’s personality. A more mature Nietzsche would later
look back on this relationship with some regret, although he never denied the significance of
Wagner’s influence on his emotional and intellectual path, Nietzsche’s estimation of Wagner’s work
would alter considerably over the course of his life. Nonetheless, in light of this relationship, one can
easily detect Wagner’s presence in much of Nietzsche’s early writings, particularly in the latter
chapters of The Birth of Tragedy and in the first and fourth essays of 1874’s Untimely Meditations.
Also, Wagner’s supervision exerted considerable editorial control over Nietzsche’s intellectual
projects, leading him to abandon, for example, 1873’s Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks,
which Wagner scorned because of its apparent irrelevance to his own work. Such pressures
continued to bridle Nietzsche throughout the so-called early period. He broke free of Wagner’s
dominance once and for all in 1877, after a series of emotionally charged episodes. Nietzsche’s
fallout with Wagner, who had moved to Bayreuth by this time, led to the publication of 1878’s
Human, All-Too Human, one of Nietzsche’s most pragmatic and un-romantic texts—the original title
page included a dedication to Voltaire and a quote from Descartes. If Nietzsche intended to use this
text as a way of alienating himself from the Wagnerian circle, he surely succeeded. Upon its arrival in
Bayreuth, the text ended this personal relationship with Wagner.
It would be an exaggeration to say that Nietzsche was not developing intellectually during the
period, prior to 1877. In fact, figures other than Wagner drew Nietzsche’s interest and admiration. In
addition to attending Burkhardt’s lectures at Basel, Nietzsche studied Greek thought from the Pre-
Socratics to Plato, and he learned much about the history of philosophy from Friedrich Albert
Lange’s massive History of Materialism, which Nietzsche once called “a treasure trove” of historical
and philosophical names, dates, and currents of thought. In addition, Nietzsche was taken by the
persona of the philosopher Arthur Schopenhauer, which Nietzsche claimed to have culled from close
readings of the two-volume magnum opus, The World as Will and Representation.
Nietzsche discovered Schopenhauer while studying in Leipzig. Because his training at Schulpforta
had elevated him far above most of his classmates, he frequently skipped lectures at Leipzig in order
to devote time to [CE1] Schopenhauer’s philosophy. For Nietzsche, the most important aspect of this
philosophy was the figure from which it emanated, representing for him the heroic ideal of a man in
the life of thought: a near-contemporary thinker participating in that great and noble “republic of
genius,” spanning the centuries of free thinking sages and creative personalities. That Nietzsche
could not countenance Schopenhauer’s “ethical pessimism” and its negation of the will was
recognized by the young man quite early during this encounter. Yet, even in Nietzsche’s attempts to
construct a counter-posed “pessimism of strength” affirming the will, much of Schopenhauer’s
thought remained embedded in Nietzsche’s philosophy, particularly during the early period.
Nietzsche’s philosophical reliance on “genius”, his cultural-political visions of rank and order through
merit, and his self-described (and later self-rebuked) “metaphysics of art” all had Schopenhauerian
underpinnings. Also, Birth of Tragedy’s well-known dualism between the cosmological/aesthetic
principles of Dionysus and Apollo, contesting and complimenting each other in the tragic play of
chaos and order, confusion and individuation, strikes a familiar chord to readers acquainted with
Schopenhauer’s description of the world as “will” and “representation.”
Despite these similarities, Nietzsche’s philosophical break with Schopenhauerian pessimism was as
real as his break with Wagner’s domineering presence was painful. Ultimately, however, such
triumphs were necessary to the development and liberation of Nietzsche as thinker, and they proved
to be instructive as Nietzsche later thematized the importance of “self-overcoming” for the project
of cultivating a free spirit.
The middle and latter part of the 1870s was a time of great upheaval in Nietzsche’s personal life. In
addition to the turmoil with Wagner and related troubles with friends in the artist’s circle of
admirers, Nietzsche suffered digestive problems, declining eyesight, migraines, and a variety of
physical aliments, rendering him unable to fulfill responsibilities at Basel for months at a time. After
publication of Birth of Tragedy, and despite its perceived success in Wagnerian circles for trumpeting
the master’s vision for Das Kunstwerk der Zukunft (“The Art Work of the Future”) Nietzsche’s
academic reputation as a philologist was effectively destroyed due in large part to the work’s
apparent disregard for scholarly expectations characteristic of nineteenth-century philology. Birth of
Tragedy was mocked as Zukunfts-Philologie (“Future Philology”) by Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, an up-
and-coming peer destined for an illustrious career in Classicism, and even Ritschl characterized it as a
work of “megalomania.” For these reasons, Nietzsche had difficulty attracting students. Even before
the publication of Birth of Tragedy, he had attempted to re-position himself at Basel in the
department of philosophy, but the University apparently never took such an endeavor seriously. By
1878, his circumstances at Basel deteriorated to the point that neither the University nor Nietzsche
was very much interested in seeing him continue as a professor there, so both agreed that he should
retire with a modest pension [CE2] . He was 34 years old and now apparently liberated, not only
from his teaching duties and the professional discipline he grew to despise, but also from the
emotional and intellectual ties that dominated him during his youth. His physical woes, however,
would continue to plague him for the remainder of his life.
After leaving Basel, Nietzsche enjoyed a period of great productivity. And, during this time, he was
never to stay in one place for long, moving with the seasons, in search of relief for his ailments,
solitude for his work, and reasonable living conditions, given his very modest budget. He often spent
summers in the Swiss Alps in Sils Maria, near St. Moritz, and winters in Genoa, Nice, or Rappollo on
the Mediterranean coast. Occasionally, he would visit family and friends in Naumburg or Basel, and
he spent a great deal of time in social discourse, exchanging letters with friends and associates.
In the latter part of the 1880s, Nietzsche’s health worsened, and in the midst of an amazing flourish
of intellectual activity which produced On the Genealogy of Morality, Twilight of the Idols, The Anti-
Christ, and several other works (including preparation for what was intended to be his magnum
opus, a work that editors later titled Will to Power) Nietzsche suffered a complete mental and
physical breakdown. The famed moment at which Nietzsche is said to have succumbed irrevocably
to his ailments occurred January 3, 1889 in Turin (Torino) Italy, reportedly outside Nietzsche’s
apartment in the Piazza Carlos Alberto while embracing a horse being flogged by its owner.
After spending time in psychiatric clinics in Basel and Jena, Nietzsche was first placed in the care of
his mother, and then later his sister (who had spent the latter half of the 1880’s attempting to
establish a “racially pure” German colony in Paraguay with her husband, the anti-Semitic political
opportunist Bernhard Foerster). By the early 1890s, Elisabeth had seized control of Nietzsche’s
literary remains, which included a vast amount of unpublished writings. She quickly began shaping
his image and the reception of his work, which by this time had already gained momentum among
academics such as Georg Brandes. Soon the Nietzsche legend would grow in spectacular fashion
among popular readers. From Villa Silberblick, the Nietzsche home in Weimar, Elisabeth and her
associates managed Friedrich’s estate, editing his works in accordance with her taste for a populist
decorum and occasionally with an ominous political intent that (later researchers agree) corrupted
the original thought[CE3] . Unfortunately, Friedrich experienced little of his fame, having never
recovered from the breakdown of late 1888 and early 1889. His final years were spent at Villa
Silberblick in grim mental and physical deterioration, ending mercifully August 25, 1900. He was
buried in Röcken, near Leipzig. Elisabeth spent one last year in Paraguay in 1892-93 before returning
to Germany, where she continued to exert influence over the perception of Nietzsche’s work and
reputation, particularly among general readers, until her death in 1935. Villa Silberblick stands today
as a monument, of sorts, to Friedrich and Elisabeth, while the bulk of Nietzsche’s literary remains is
held in the Goethe-Schiller Archiv, also in Weimar.
Pessimism - the tendency to see, anticipate, or emphasize only bad or undesirable outcomes, results,
conditions, problems.
PERIODIZATION OF WRITINGS
Nietzsche’s writings during this time reflect interests in philology, cultural criticism, and aesthetics.
His inaugural public lecture at Basel in May 1869, “Homer and Classical Philology” brought out
aesthetic and scientific aspects of his discipline, portending Nietzsche’s attitudes towards science,
art, philology and philosophy. He was influenced intellectually by the philosopher Arthur
Schopenhauer and emotionally by the artist Richard Wagner. Nietzsche’s first published book, The
Birth of Tragedy, appropriated Schopenhaurian categories of individuation and chaos in an
elucidation of primordial aesthetic drives represented by the Greek gods Apollo and Dionysus. This
text also included a Wagnerian precept for cultural flourishing: society must cultivate and promote
its most elevated and creative types—the artistic genius. In the Preface to a later edition of this
work, Nietzsche expresses regret for having attempted to elaborate a “metaphysics of art.” In
addition to these themes, Nietzsche’s interest during this period extended to Greek philosophy,
intellectual history, and the natural sciences, all of which were significant to the development of his
mature thought. Nietzsche’s second book-length project, The Untimely Meditations, contains four
essays written from 1873-1876. It is a work of acerbic cultural criticism, encomia to Schopenhauer
and Wagner, and an unexpectedly idiosyncratic analysis of the newly developing historical
consciousness. A fifth meditation on the discipline of philology is prepared but left unpublished.
Plagued by poor health, Nietzsche is released from teaching duties in February 1876 (his affiliation
with the university officially ends in 1878 and he is granted a small pension).
Schopenhauer - Ang kanyang mga solusyon sa pagdurusa ay katulad ng mga taga-isip na Vedantiko
at Budista (i.e. asetisismo) at ang kanyang pananampalataya sa "transendental na idealidad" ay
nagtulak sa kanyang tumanggap sa ateismo at nag-aral mula sa pilospiyang Kristiyano.
Individuation - describes the manner in which a thing is identified as distinguished from other things.
Chaos - the concept in classical creation myths; in Greek mythology, according to Hesiod, the first
thing to exist.
During this time Nietzsche liberated himself from the emotional grip of Wagner and the artist’s circle
of admirers, as well as from those ideas which (as he claims in Ecce Homo) “did not belong” to him in
his “nature” (“Human All Too Human: With Two Supplements” 1). Reworking earlier themes such as
tragedy in philosophy, art and truth, and the human exemplar, Nietzsche’s thinking now comes into
sharper focus, and he sets out on a philosophical path to be followed the remainder of his
productive life. In this period’s three published works Human, All-Too Human (1878-79), Dawn
(1881), and The Gay Science (1882), Nietzsche takes up writing in an aphoristic style, which permits
exploration of a variety of themes. Most importantly, Nietzsche lays out a plan for “becoming what
one is” through the cultivation of instincts and various cognitive faculties, a plan that requires
constant struggle with one’s psychological and intellectual inheritances. Nietzsche discovers that
“one thing is needful” for the exemplary human being: to craft an identity from otherwise
dissociated events bringing forth the horizons of one’s existence. Self-realization, as it is conceived in
these texts, demands the radicalization of critical inquiry with a historical consciousness and then a
“retrograde step” back (Human aphorism 20) from what is revealed in such examinations, insofar as
these revelations threaten to dissolve all metaphysical realities and leave nothing but the abysmal
comedy of existence. A peculiar kind of meaningfulness is thus gained by the retrograde step: it
yields a purpose for existence, but in an ironic form, perhaps esoterically and without ground; it is
transparently nihilistic to the man with insight, but suitable for most; susceptible to all sorts of
suspicion, it is nonetheless necessary and for that reason enforced by institutional powers. Nietzsche
calls the one who teaches the purpose of existence a “tragic hero” (GS 1), and the one who
understands the logic of the retrograde step a “free spirit.” Nietzsche’s account of this struggle for
self-realization and meaning leads him to consider problems related to metaphysics, religion,
knowledge, aesthetics, and morality.
Aphoristic - can be a terse saying, expressing a general truth or principle, or it can be an astute
observation.
Problems of Interpretation
Nietzsche’s work in the beginning was heavily influenced, either positively or negatively, by the
events of his young life. His early and on-going interest in the Greeks, for example, can be attributed
in part to his Classical education at Schulpforta, for which he was well-prepared as a result of his
family’s attempts to steer him into the ministry. Nietzsche’s intense association with Wagner no
doubt enhanced his orientation towards the philosophy of Schopenhauer, and it probably promoted
his work in aesthetics and cultural criticism. These biographical elements came to bear on
Nietzsche’s first major works, while the middle period amounts to a confrontation with many of
these influences. In Nietzsche’s later writings we find the development of concepts that seem less
tangibly related to the biographical events of his life.
Let's outline four of these concepts, but not before adding a word of caution regarding how this
outline should be received. Nietzsche asserts in the opening section of Twilight of the Idols that he
“mistrusts systematizers” (“Maxims and Arrows” 26), which is taken by some readers to be a
declaration of his fundamental stance towards philosophical systems, with the additional inference
that nothing resembling such a system must be permitted to stand in interpretations of his thought.
Although it would not be illogical to say that Nietzsche mistrusted philosophical systems, while
nevertheless building one of his own, some commentators point out two important qualifications.
First, the meaning of Nietzsche’s stated “mistrust” in this brief aphorism can and should be treated
with caution. In Beyond Good and Evil Nietzsche claims that philosophers today, after millennia of
dogmatizing about absolutes, now have a “duty to mistrust” philosophy’s dogmatizing tendencies
(BGE 34). Yet, earlier in that same text, Nietzsche claimed that all philosophical interpretations of
nature are acts of will power (BGE 9) and that his interpretations are subject to the same critique
(BGE 22). In Thus Spoke Zarathustra’s “Of Involuntary Bliss” we find Zarathustra speaking of his own
“mistrust,” when he describes the happiness that has come to him in the “blissful hour” of the third
part of that book. Zarathustra attempts to chase away this bliss while waiting for the arrival of his
unhappiness, but his happiness draws “nearer and nearer to him,” because he does not chase after
it. In the next scene we find Zarathustra dwelling in the “light abyss” of the pure open sky, “before
sunrise.” What then is the meaning of this “mistrust”? At the very least, we can say that Nietzsche
does not intend it to establish a strong and unmovable absolute, a negative-system, from which
dogma may be drawn. Nor, possibly, is Nietzsche’s mistrust of systematizers absolutely clear.
Perhaps it is a discredit to Nietzsche as a philosopher that he did not elaborate his position more
carefully within this tension; or, perhaps such uncertainty has its own ground. Commentators such
as Mueller-Lauter have noticed ambivalence in Nietzsche’s work on this very issue, and it seems
plausible that Nietzsche mistrusted systems while nevertheless constructing something like a system
countenancing this mistrust. He says something akin to this, after all, in Beyond Good and Evil,
where it is claimed that even science’s truths are matters of interpretation, while admitting that this
bold claim is also an interpretation and “so much the better” (aphorism 22). For a second cautionary
note, many commentators will argue along with Richard Schacht that, instead of building a system,
Nietzsche is concerned only with the exploration of problems, and that his kind of philosophy is
limited to the interpretation and evaluation of cultural inheritances (1995). Other commentators will
attempt to complement this sort of interpretation and, like Löwith, presume that the ground for
Nietzsche’s explorations may also be examined. Löwith and others argue that this ground concerns
Nietzsche’s encounter with historical nihilism. The following outline should be received, then, with
the understanding that Nietzsche’s own iconoclastic nature, his perspectivism, and his life-long
projects of genealogical critique and the revaluation of values, lend credence to those anti-
foundational readings which seek to emphasize only those exploratory aspects of Nietzsche’s work
while refuting even implicit submissions to an orthodox interpretation of “the one Nietzsche” and
his “one system of thought.” With this caution, the following outline is offered as one way of
grounding Nietzsche’s various explorations.
(i) Nihilism and the Revaluation of Values, which is embodied by a historical event, “the death of
God,” and which entails, somewhat problematically, the project of transvaluation;
(ii) The Human Exemplar, which takes many forms in Nietzsche’s thought, including the “tragic
artist”, the “sage”, the “free spirit”, the “philosopher of the future”, the Übermensch (variously
translated in English as “Superman,” “Overman,” “Overhuman,” and the like), and perhaps others
(the case could be made, for example, that in Nietzsche’s notoriously self-indulgent and self-
congratulatory Ecce Homo, the role of the human exemplar is played by “Mr. Nietzsche” himself);
(iii) Will to Power (Wille zur Macht), from a naturalized history of morals and truth developing
through subjective feelings of power to a cosmology;
(iv) Eternal Recurrence or Eternal Return (variously in Nietzsche’s work, “die ewige Wiederkunft”
or “die ewige Wiederkehr”) of the Same (des Gleich), a solution to the riddle of temporality
without purpose.
Although Michael Gillespie makes a strong case that Nietzsche misunderstood nihilism, and in any
event Nietzsche’s Dionysianism would be a better place to look for an anti-metaphysical
breakthrough in Nietzsche’s corpus (1995, 178), commentators as varied in philosophical
orientation as Heidegger and Danto have argued that nihilism is a central theme in Nietzsche’s
philosophy. Why is this so? The constellation of Nietzsche’s fundamental concepts moves within his
general understanding of modernity’s historical situation in the late nineteenth century. In this
respect, Nietzsche’s thought carries out the Kantian project of “critique” by applying the nineteenth
century’s developing historical awareness to problems concerning the possibilities of knowledge,
truth, and human consciousness. Unlike Kant’s critiques, Nietzsche’s examinations find no
transcendental ego, given that even the categories of experience are historically situated and
likewise determined. Unlike Hegel’s notion of historical consciousness, however, history for
Nietzsche has no inherent teleology. All beginnings and ends, for Nietzsche, are thus lost in a flood of
indeterminacy. As early as 1873, Nietzsche was arguing that human reason is only one of many
peculiar developments in the ebb and flow of time, and when there are no more rational animals
nothing of absolute value will have transpired (“On truth and lies in a non-moral sense”). Some
commentators would prefer to consider these sorts of remarks as belonging to Nietzsche’s
“juvenilia.” Nevertheless, as late as 1888’s “Reason in Philosophy” from Twilight of the Idols,
Nietzsche derides philosophers who would make a “fetish” out of reason and retreat into the illusion
of a “de-historicized” world. Such a philosopher is “decadent,” symptomatic of a “declining life”.
Opposed to this type, Nietzsche valorizes the “Dionysian” artist whose sense of history affirms “all
that is questionable and terrible in existence.”
Nietzsche’s philosophy contemplates the meaning of values and their significance to human
existence. Given that no absolute values exist, in Nietzsche’s worldview, the evolution of values on
earth must be measured by some other means. How then shall they be understood? The existence
of a value presupposes a value-positing perspective, and values are created by human beings (and
perhaps other value-positing agents) as aids for survival and growth. Because values are important
for the well being of the human animal, because belief in them is essential to our existence, we
oftentimes prefer to forget that values are our own creations and to live through them as if they
were absolute. For these reasons, social institutions enforcing adherence to inherited values are
permitted to create self-serving economies of power, so long as individuals living through them are
thereby made more secure and their possibilities for life enhanced. Nevertheless, from time to time
the values we inherit are deemed no longer suitable and the continued enforcement of them no
longer stands in the service of life. To maintain allegiance to such values, even when they no longer
seem practicable, turns what once served the advantage to individuals to a disadvantage, and what
was once the prudent deployment of values into a life denying abuse of power. When this happens
the human being must reactivate its creative, value-positing capacities and construct new values.
Commentators will differ on the question of whether nihilism for Nietzsche refers specifically to a
state of affairs characterizing specific historical moments, in which inherited values have been
exposed as superstition and have thus become outdated, or whether Nietzsche means something
more than this. It is, at the very least, accurate to say that for Nietzsche nihilism has become a
problem by the nineteenth century. The scientific, technological, and political revolutions of the
previous two hundred years put an enormous amount of pressure on the old world order. In this
environment, old value systems were being dismantled under the weight of newly discovered
grounds for doubt. The possibility arises, then, that nihilism for Nietzsche is merely a temporary
stage in the refinement of true belief. This view has the advantage of making Nietzsche’s remarks
on truth and morality seem coherent from a pragmatic standpoint, in that with this view the
problem of nihilism is met when false beliefs have been identified and corrected. Reason is not a
value, in this reading, but rather the means by which human beings examine their metaphysical
presuppositions and explore new avenues to truth.
Yet, another view will have it that by nihilism Nietzsche is pointing out something even more unruly
at work, systemically, in the Western world’s axiomatic orientation. Heidegger, for example, claims
that with the problem of nihilism Nietzsche is showing us the essence of Western metaphysics and
its system of values (“The Word of Nietzsche: ‘God is dead’”). According to this view, Nietzsche’s
philosophy of value, with its emphasis on the value-positing gesture, implies that even the concept
of truth in the Western worldview leads to arbitrary determinations of value and political order and
that this worldview is disintegrating under the weight of its own internal logic (or perhaps “illogic”).
In this reading, the history of truth in the occidental world is the “history of an error” (Twilight of
the Idols), harboring profoundly disruptive antinomies which lead, ultimately, to the undoing of the
Western philosophical framework. This kind of systemic flaw is exposed by the historical
consciousness of the nineteenth century, which makes the problem of nihilism seem all the more
acutely related to Nietzsche’s historical situation. But to relegate nihilism to that situation, according
to Heidegger, leaves our thinking of it incomplete.
Heidegger makes this stronger claim with the aid of Nietzsche’s Nachlass. Near the beginning of the
aphorisms collected under the title, Will To Power (aphorism 2), we find this note from 1887: “What
does nihilism mean? That the highest values devalue themselves. The aim is lacking; 'Why?' finds no
answer.” Here, Nietzsche’s answer regarding the meaning of nihilism has three parts.
(i) The first part makes a claim about the logic of values: ultimately, given the immense breadth of
time, even “the highest values devalue themselves.” What does this mean? According to Nietzsche,
the conceptual framework known as Western metaphysics was first articulated by Plato, who had
pieced together remnants of a declining worldview, borrowing elements from predecessors such as
Anaximander, Parmenides, and especially Socrates, in order to overturn a cosmology that had been
in play from the days of Homer and which found its fullest and last expression in the thought of
Heraclitus. Plato’s framework was popularized by Christianity, which added egalitarian elements
along with the virtue of pity. The maturation of Western metaphysics occurs during modernity’s
scientific and political revolutions, wherein the effects of its inconsistencies, malfunctions, and mal-
development become acute. At this point, according to Nietzsche, “the highest values devalue
themselves,” as modernity’s striving for honesty, probity, and courage in the search for truth, those
all-important virtues inhabiting the core of scientific progress, strike a fatal blow against the
foundational idea of absolutes. Values most responsible for the scientific revolution, however, are
also crucial to the metaphysical system that modern science is destroying. Such values are
threatening, then, to bring about the destruction of their own foundations. Thus, the highest values
are devaluing themselves at the core. Most importantly, the values of honesty, probity, and courage
in the search for truth no longer seem compatible with the guarantee, the bestowal, and the
bestowing agent of an absolute value. Even the truth of “truth” now falls prey to the workings of
nihilism, given that Western metaphysics now appears groundless in this logic.
For some commentators, this line of interpretation leaves Nietzsche’s revaluation of values lost in
contradiction. What philosophical ground, after all, could support revaluation if this interpretation
were accurate? For this reason, readers such as Clark work to establish a coherent theory of truth in
Nietzsche’s philosophy, which can apparently be done by emphasizing various parts of the corpus to
the exclusion of others. If, indeed, a workable epistemology may be derived from reading specific
passages, and good reasons can be given for prioritizing those passages, then consistent grounds
may exist for Nietzsche having leveled a critique of morality. Such readings, however, seem
incompatible with Nietzsche’s encounter with historical nihilism, unless nihilism is taken to represent
merely a temporary stage in the refinement of Western humanity’s acquisition of knowledge.
With the stronger claim, however, Nietzsche’s critique of the modern situation implies that the
“highest values [necessarily] devalue themselves.” Western metaphysics brings about its own
disintegration, in working out the implications of its inner logic. Nietzsche’s name for this great and
terrible event, capturing popular imagination with horror and disgust, is the “death of God.”
Nietzsche acknowledges that a widespread understanding of this event, the “great noon” at which
all “shadows of God” will be washed out, is still to come. In Nietzsche’s day, the God of the old
metaphysics is still worshiped, of course, and would be worshiped, he predicted, for years to come.
But, Nietzsche insisted, in an intellectual climate that demands honesty in the search for truth and
proof as a condition for belief, the absence of foundations has already been laid bare. The dawn of a
new day had broken, and shadows now cast, though long, were receding by the minute.
(ii) The second part of the answer to the question concerning nihilism states that “the aim is
lacking.” What does this mean? In Beyond Good and Evil Nietzsche claims that the logic of an
existence lacking inherent meaning demands, from an organizational standpoint, a value-creating
response, however weak this response might initially be in comparison to how its values are then
taken when enforced by social institutions (aphorisms 20-23). Surveys of various cultures show that
humanity’s most indispensable creation, the affirmation of meaning and purpose, lies at the heart of
all fundamental values. Nihilism stands not only for that apparently inevitable process by which the
highest values devalue themselves. It also stands for that moment of recognition in which human
existence appears, ultimately, to be in vain. Nietzsche’s surveys of cultures and their values, his
cultural anthropologies, are typically reductive in the extreme, attempting to reach the most
important sociopolitical questions as neatly and quickly as possible. Thus, when examining so-called
Jewish, Oriental, Roman, or Medieval European cultures Nietzsche asks, “how was meaning and
purpose proffered and secured here? How, and for how long, did the values here serve the living?
What form of redemption was sought here, and was this form indicative of a healthy life? What may
one learn about the creation of values by surveying such cultures?” This version of nihilism then
means that absolute aims are lacking and that cultures naturally attempt to compensate for this
absence with the creation of goals.
(iii) The third part of the answer to the question concerning nihilism states that “‘why?’ finds no
answer.” Who is posing the question here? Emphasis is laid on the one who faces the problem of
nihilism. The problem of value-positing concerns the one who posits values, and this one must be
examined, along with a corresponding evaluation of relative strengths and weaknesses. When,
indeed, “why?” finds no answer, nihilism is complete. The danger here is that the value-positing
agent might become paralyzed, leaving the call of life’s most dreadful question unanswered. In
regards to this danger, Nietzsche’s most important cultural anthropologies examined the Greeks
from Homer to the age of tragedy and the “pre-Platonic” philosophers. Here was evidence,
Nietzsche believed, that humanity could face the dreadful truth of existence without becoming
paralyzed. At every turn, the moment in which the Greek world’s highest values devalued
themselves, when an absolute aim was shown to be lacking, the question “why?" nevertheless called
forth an answer. The strength of Greek culture is evident in the gods, the tragic art, and the
philosophical concepts and personalities created by the Greeks themselves. Comparing the creativity
of the Greeks to the intellectual work of modernity, the tragic, affirmative thought of Heraclitus to
the pessimism of Schopenhauer, Nietzsche highlights a number of qualitative differences. Both types
are marked by the appearance of nihilism, having been drawn into the inevitable logic of value-
positing and what it would seem to indicate. The Greek type nevertheless demonstrates the
characteristics of strength by activating and re-intensifying the capacity to create, by overcoming
paralysis, by willing a new truth, and by affirming the will. The other type displays a pessimism of
weakness, passivity, and weariness—traits typified by Schopenhauer’s life-denying ethics of the will
turning against itself. In Nietzsche’s 1888 retrospection on the Birth of Tragedy in Ecce Homo, we
read that “Hellenism and Pessimism” would have made a more precise title for the first work,
because Nietzsche claims to have attempted to demonstrate how
the Greeks got rid of pessimism—with what they overcame it….Precisely tragedy is the proof that
the Greeks were no pessimists: Schopenhauer blundered in this as he blundered in everything (“The
Birth of Tragedy” in Ecce Homo section 1).
From Twilight of the Idols, also penned during that sublime year of 1888, Nietzsche writes that
tragedy “has to be considered the decisive repudiation” of pessimism as Schopenhauer understood
it:
affirmation of life, even in its strangest and sternest problems, the will to life rejoicing in its own
inexhaustibility through the sacrifice of its highest types—that is what I called Dionysian….beyond
[Aristotelian] pity and terror, to realize in oneself the eternal joy of becoming—that joy which also
encompasses joy in destruction (“What I Owe the Ancients” 5).
Nietzsche concludes the above passage by claiming to be the “last disciple of the philosopher
Dionysus” (which by this time in Nietzsche’s thought came to encompass the whole of that
movement which formerly distinguished between Apollo and Dionysus). Simultaneously, Nietzsche
declares himself, with great emphasis, to be the “teacher of the eternal recurrence.”
The work to overcome pessimism is tragic in a two-fold sense: it maintains a feeling for the absence
of ground, while responding to this absence with the creation of something meaningful. This work is
also unmodern, according to Nietzsche, since modernity either has yet to ask the question “why?,”
in any profound sense or, in those cases where the question has been posed, it has yet to come up
with a response. Hence, a pessimism of weakness and an incomplete form of nihilism prevail in the
modern epoch. Redemption in this life is denied, while an uncompleted form of nihilism remains the
fundamental condition of humanity. Although the logic of nihilism seems inevitable, given the
absence of absolute purpose and meaning, “actively” confronting nihilism and completing our
historical encounter with it will be a sign of good health and the “increased power of the spirit” (Will
to Power aphorism 22). Thus far, however, modernity’s attempts to “escape nihilism” (in turning
away) have only served to “make the problem more acute” (aphorism 28). Why, then, this failure?
What does modernity lack?
How and why do nihilism and the pessimism of weakness prevail in modernity? Again, from the
notebook of 1887 (Will to Power, aphorism 27), we find two conditions for this situation:
1. the higher species is lacking, i.e., those whose inexhaustible fertility and power keep up the faith
in man….[and] 2. the lower species (‘herd,’ ‘mass,’ ‘society,’) unlearns modesty and blows up its
needs into cosmic and metaphysical values. In this way the whole of existence is vulgarized: insofar
as the mass is dominant it bullies the exceptions, so they lose their faith in themselves and become
nihilists.
With the fulfillment of “European nihilism” (which is no doubt, for Nietzsche, endemic throughout
the Western world and anyplace touched by “modernity”), and the death of otherworldly hopes for
redemption, Nietzsche imagines two possible responses: the easy response, the way of the “herd”
and “the last man,” or the difficult response, the way of the “exception,” and the Übermensch.
Ancillary to any discussion of the exception, per se, the compatibility of the Übermensch concept
with other movements in Nietzsche’s thought, and even the significance that Nietzsche himself
placed upon it, has been the subject of intense debate among Nietzsche scholars. The term’s
appearance in Nietzsche’s corpus is limited primarily to Thus Spoke Zarathustra and works directly
related to this text. Even here, moreover, the Übermensch is only briefly and very early announced
in the narrative, albeit with a tremendous amount of fanfare, before fading from explicit
consideration. In addition to these problems, there are debates concerning the basic nature of the
Übermensch itself, whether “Über-” refers to a transitional movement or a transmogrified state of
being, and whether Nietzsche envisioned the possibility of a community of Übermenschen, as
opposed to a solitary figure among lesser types. So, what should be made of Nietzsche’s so-called
“overman” (or even “superman”) called upon to arrive after the “death of God”?
Whatever else may be said about the Übermensch, Nietzsche clearly had in mind an exemplary
figure and an exception among humans, one “whose inexhaustible fertility and power keep up the
faith in man.” For some commentators, Nietzsche’s distinction between overman and the last man
has political ramifications. The hope for an overman figure to appear would seem to be permissible
for one individual, many, or even a social ideal, depending on the culture within which it appears.
Modernity, in Nietzsche’s view, is in such a state of decadence that it would be fortunate, indeed, to
see the emergence of even one such type, given that modern sociopolitical arrangements are more
conducive to creating the egalitarian “last man” who “blinks” at expectations for rank, self-
overcoming, and striving for greatness. The last men are “ the most harmful to the species because
they preserve their existence as much at the expense of the truth as at the expense of the future”
(“Why I am a Destiny” in Ecce Homo 1). Although Nietzsche never lays out a precise political
program from these ideas, it is at least clear that theoretical justifications for complacency or
passivity are antithetical to his philosophy. What, then, may be said about Nietzsche as political
thinker? Nietzsche’s political sympathies are definitely not democratic in any ordinary way of
thinking about that sort of arrangement. Nor are they socialist or Marxist.
Nietzsche’s political sympathies have been called “aristocratic,” which is accurate enough only if one
does not confuse the term with European royalty, landed gentry, old money or the like and if one
keeps in mind the original Greek meaning of the term, “aristos,” which meant “the good man, the
man with power.” A certain ambiguity exists, for Nietzsche, in the term “good man.” On the one
hand, the modern, egalitarian “good man,” the “last man,” expresses hostility for those types willing
to impose measures of rank and who would dare to want greatness and to strive for it. Such
hostilities are born out of ressentiment and inherited from Judeo-Christian moral value systems.
(Beyond Good and Evil 257-260 and On the Genealogy of Morals essay 1). “Good” in this sense is
opposed to “evil,” and the “good man” is the one whose values support the “herd” and whose
condemnations are directed at those whose thoughts and actions might disrupt the complacent
normalcy of modern life. On the other hand, the kind of “good man” who might overcome the weak
pessimism of “herd morality,” the man of strength, a man to confront nihilism, and thus a true
benefactor to humanity, would be decidedly “unmodern” and “out of season.” Only such a figure
would “keep up the faith in man.” For these reasons, some commentators have found in Nietzsche
an existentialist program for the heroic individual dissociated in varying degrees from political
considerations. Such readings however ignore or discount Nietzsche’s interest in historical processes
and the unavoidable inference that although Nietzsche’s anti-egalitarianism might lead to
questionably “unmodern” political conclusions, hierarchy nevertheless implies association.
The distinction between the good man of active power and the other type also points to ambiguity
in the concept of freedom. For the hopeless, human freedom is conceived negatively in the
“freedom from” restraints, from higher expectations, measures of rank, and the striving for
greatness. While the higher type, on the other hand, understands freedom positively in the
“freedom for” achievement, for revaluations of values, overcoming nihilism, and self-mastery.
Nietzsche frequently points to such exceptions as they have appeared throughout history—
Napoleon is one of his favorite examples. In modernity, the emergence of such figures seems
possible only as an isolated event, as a flash of lightening from the dark cloud of humanity. Was
there ever a culture, in contrast to modernity, which saw these sorts of higher types emerge in
congress as a matter of expectation and design? Nietzsche’s early philological studies on the Greeks,
such as Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks, The Pre-Platonic Philosophers, “Homer on
Competition,” and “The Greek State,” concur that, indeed, the ancient world before Plato produced
many exemplary human beings, coming forth independently of each other but “hewn from the same
stone,” made possible by the fertile cultural milieu, the social expectation of greatness, and
opportunities to prove individual merit in various competitive arenas. Indeed, Greek athletic
contests, festivals of music and tragedy, and political life reflected, in Nietzsche’s view, a general
appreciation for competition, rank, ingenuity, and the dynamic variation of formal structures of all
sorts. Such institutions thereby promoted the elevation of human exemplars. Again, the point must
be stressed here that the historical accuracy of Nietzsche’s interpretation of the Greeks is no more
relevant to his philosophical schemata than, for example, the actual signing of a material document
is to a contractarian political theory. What is important for Nietzsche, throughout his career, is the
quick evaluation of social order and heirarchies, made possible for the first time in the nineteenth
century by the newly developed “historical sense” (BGE 224) through which Nietzsche draws
sweeping conclusions regarding, for example, the characteristics of various moral and religious
epochs (BGE 32 and 55), which are themselves pre-conditioned by the material origins of
consciousness, from which a pre-human animal acquires the capacity (even the “right”) to make
promises and develops into the “sovereign individual” who then bears responsibility for his or her
actions and thoughts (GM II.2).
Like these rather ambitious conclusions, Nietzsche’s valorization of the Greeks is partly derived from
empirical evidence and partly confected in myth, a methodological concoction that Nietzsche draws
from his philological training. If the Greeks, as a different interpretation would have them, bear little
resemblance to Nietzsche’s reading, such a difference would have little relevance to Nietzsche’s
fundamental thoughts. Later Nietzsche is also clear that his descriptions of the Greeks should not be
taken programmatically as a political vision for the future (see for example GS 340).
The “Greeks” are one of Nietzsche’s best exemplars of hope against a meaningless existence,
hence his emphasis on the Greek world’s response to the “wisdom of Silenus” in Birth of Tragedy.
(ch. 5). If the sovereign individual represents history’s “ripest fruit”, the most recent millennia have
created, through rituals of revenge and punishment, a “bad conscience.” The human animal thereby
internalizes material forces into feelings of guilt and duty, while externalizing a spirit thus created
with hostility towards existence itself (GM II.21). Compared to this typically Christian manner of
forming human experiences, the Greeks deified “the animal in man” and thereby kept “bad
conscience at bay” (GM II.23).
In addition to exemplifying the Greeks in the early works, Nietzsche lionizes the “artist-genius” and
the “sage;” during the middle period he writes confidently, at first, and then longingly about the
“scientist,” the “philosopher of the future,” and the “free spirit;” Zarathustra’s decidedly sententious
oratory heralds the coming of the Übermensch; the periods in which “revaluation” comes to the fore
finds value in the destructive influences of the “madman,” the “immoralist,” the “buffoon,” and even
the “criminal.” Finally, Nietzsche’s last works reflect upon his own image, as the “breaker of human
history into two,” upon “Mr. Nietzsche,” the “anti-Christian,” the self-anointed clever writer of great
books, the creator of Zarathustra, the embodiment of human destiny and humanity’s greatest
benefactor: “only after me,” Nietzsche claims in Ecce Homo, “is it possible to hope again” (“Why I am
a Destiny” 1). It should be cautioned that important differences exist in the way Nietzsche conceives
of each of these various figures, differences that reflect the development of Nietzsche’s
philosophical work throughout the periods of his life. For this reason, none of these exemplars
should be confused for the others. The bombastic “Mr. Nietzsche” of Ecce Homo is no more the
“Übermensch” of Thus Spoke Zarathustra, for example, than the “Zarathustra” character is a “pre-
Platonic philosopher” or the alienated, cool, sober, and contemptuous “scientist” is a “tragic artist,”
although these figures will frequently share characteristics. Yet, a survey of these exceptions shows
that Nietzsche’s philosophy, in his own estimation, needs the apotheosis of a human exemplar,
perhaps to keep the search for meaning and redemption from abdicating the earth in metaphysical
retreat, perhaps to avert the exhaustion of human creativity, to reawaken the instincts, to inspire
the striving for greatness, to remind us that “this has happened once and is therefore a possibility,”
or perhaps simply to bestow the “honey offering” of a very useful piece of folly. This need explains
the meaning of the parodic fourth book of Zarathustra, which opens with the title character
reflecting on the whole of his teachings: “I am he…who once bade himself, and not in vain: ‘Become
what you are!’” The subtitle of Nietzsche’s autobiographical Ecce Homo, “How One Becomes What
One Is,” strikes a similar chord.
6. Will to Power
The exemplar expresses hope not granted from metaphysical illusions. After sharpening the critique
of art and genius during the positivistic period, Nietzsche seems more cautious about heaping praise
upon specific historical figures and types, but even when he could no longer find an ideal exception,
he nevertheless deemed it requisite to fabricate one in myth. Whereas exceptional humans of the
past belong to an exalted “republic of genius,” those of the future, those belonging to human
destiny, embody humanity’s highest hopes. As a result of this development, some commentators will
emphasize the “philosophy of the future” as one of Nietzsche’s most important ideas. Work pursued
in service of the future constitutes for Nietzsche an earthly form of redemption. Yet, exemplars of
type, whether in the form of isolated individuals like Napoleon, or of whole cultures like the Greeks,
are not caught up in petty historical politics or similar mundane endeavors. According to Nietzsche in
Twilight of the Idols, their regenerative powers are necessary for the work of interpreting the
meaning and sequence of historical facts.
My Conception of the genius—Great men, like great epochs, are explosive material in whom
tremendous energy has been accumulated; their prerequisite has always been, historically and
psychologically, that a protracted assembling, accumulating, economizing and preserving has
preceded them—that there has been no explosion for a long time. If the tension in the mass has
grown too great the merest accidental stimulus suffices to call the “genius,” the “deed,” the great
destiny, into the world. Of what account then are circumstances, the epoch, the Zeitgeist, public
opinion!...Great human beings are necessary, the epoch in which they appear is accidental…
(“Expeditions of an Untimely Man,” 44).
It is with this understanding of the “great man” that Nietzsche, in Ecce Homo, proclaims even
himself a great man, “dynamite,”“breaking the history of humanity in two” (“Why I am a Destiny” 1
and 8). A human exemplar, interpreted affirmatively in service of a hopeful future, is a “great event”
denoting qualitative differences amidst the play of historical determinations. Thus, it belongs, in this
reading, to Nietzsche’s cosmological vision of an indifferent nature marked occasionally by the
boundary-stones of noble and sometimes violent uprisings.
To what extent is Nietzsche entitled to such a vision? Unlike nihilism, pessimism, and the death of
God, which are historically, scientifically, and sometimes logically derived, Nietzsche’s “yes-saying”
concepts seem to be derived from intuition, although Nietzsche will frequently support even these
great hopes with bits of inductive reasoning. Nietzsche attempts to describe the logical structure of
great events, as if a critical understanding of them pertains to their recurrence in modernity: great
men have a “historical and psychological prerequisite.” Historically, there must be a time of waiting
and gathering energy, as we find, for example, in the opening scene of Zarathustra. The great man
and the great deed belong to a human destiny, one that emerges in situations of crisis and severe
want. Psychologically, they are the effects of human energy stored and kept dormant for long
periods of time in dark clouds of indifference. Primal energy gathers to a point before a cataclysmic
event, like a chemical reaction with an electrical charge, unleashes some decisive, episodic force on
all humanity. From here, the logic unfolds categorically: all great events, having occurred, are
possibilities. All possibilities become necessities, given an infinite amount of time. Perhaps
understanding this logic marks a qualitative difference in the way existence is understood. Perhaps
this qualitative difference will spark the revaluation of values. When a momentous event takes
place, the exception bolts from the cloud of normalcy as a point of extreme difference. In such ways,
using this difference as a reference, as a “boundary-stone” on the river of eternal becoming, the
meaning of the past is once again determined and the course of the future is set for a while, at least
until a coming epoch unleashes the next great transvaluative event. Conditions for the occurrence of
such events, and for the event of grasping this logic itself, are conceptualized, cosmologically in this
reading, under the appellation “will to power.”
Before developing this reading further, it should be noted some commentators argue that the
cosmological interpretation of will to power makes too strong a claim and that the extent of will to
power’s domain ought to be limited to what the idea might explain as a theory of moral psychology,
as the principle of an anthropology regarding the natural history of morals, or as a response to
evolutionary theories placed in the service of utility. Such commentators will maintain that Nietzsche
either in no way intends to construct a new meta-theory, or if he does then such intentions are
mistaken and in conflict with his more prescient insights. Indeed, much evidence exists to support
each of these positions. As an enthusiastic reader of the French Moralists of the eighteenth century,
Nietzsche held the view that all human actions are motivated by the desire “to increase the feeling
of power” (GS 13). This view seems to make Nietzsche’s insights regarding moral psychology akin to
psychological egoism and would thus make doubtful the popular notion that Nietzsche advocated
something like an egoistic ethic. Nevertheless, with this bit of moral psychology, a debate exists
among commentators concerning whether Nietzsche intends to make dubious morality per se or
whether he merely endeavors to expose those life-denying ways of moralizing inherited from the
beginning of Western thought. Nietzsche, at the very least, is not concerned with divining origins. He
is interested, rather, in measuring the value of what is taken as true, if such a thing can be
measured. For Nietzsche, a long, murky, and thereby misunderstood history has conditioned the
human animal in response to physical, psychological, and social necessities (GM II) and in ways that
have created additional needs, including primarily the need to believe in a purpose for its very
existence (GS 1). This ultimate need may be uncritically engaged, as happens with the incomplete
nihilism of those who wish to remain in the shadow of metaphysics and with the laisser aller of the
last man who overcomes dogmatism by making humanity impotent (BGE 188). On the other hand, a
critical engagement with history is attempted in Nietzsche’s genealogies, which may enlighten the
historical consciousness with a sort of transparency regarding the drive for truth and its
consequences for determining the human condition. In the more critical engagement, Nietzsche
attempts to transform the need for truth and reconstitute the truth drive in ways that are already
incredulous towards the dogmatizing tendency of philosophy and thus able to withstand the new
suspicions (BGE 22 and 34). Thus, the philosophical exemplar of the future stands in contrast, once
again, to the uncritical man of the nineteenth century whose hidden metaphysical principles of
utility and comfort fail to complete the overcoming of nihilism (Ecce Homo, “Why I am a Destiny” 4).
The question of whether Nietzsche’s transformation of physical and psychological need with a
doctrine of the will to power, in making an affirmative principle out of one that has dissolved the
highest principles hitherto, simply replaces one metaphysical doctrine with another, or even
expresses completely all that has been implicit in metaphysics per se since its inception continues to
draw the interest of Nietzsche commentators today. Perhaps the radicalization of will to power in
this way amounts to no more than an account of this world to the exclusion of any other. At any
rate, the exemplary type, the philosophy of the future, and will to power comprise aspects of
Nietzsche’s affirmative thinking. When the egoist’s “I will” becomes transparent to itself a new
beginning is thereby made possible. Nietzsche thus attempts to bring forward precisely that kind of
affirmation which exists in and through its own essence, insofar as will to power as a principle of
affirmation is made possible by its own destructive modalities which pulls back the curtain on
metaphysical illusions and dogma founded on them.
The historical situation that conditions Nietzsche’s will to power involves not only the death of
God and the reappearance of pessimism, but also the nineteenth century’s increased historical
awareness, and with it the return of the ancient philosophical problem of emergence. How does
the exceptional, for example, begin to take shape in the ordinary, or truth in untruth, reason in un-
reason, social order and law in violence, a being in becoming? The variation and formal emergence
of each of these states must, according to Nietzsche, be understood as a possibility only within a
presumed sphere of associated events. One could thus also speak of the “emergence,” as part of this
sphere, of a given form’s disintegration. Indeed, the new cosmology must account for such a fate.
Most importantly, the new cosmology must grant meaning to this eternal recurrence of emergence
and disintegration without, however, taking vengeance upon it. This is to say that in the teaching of
such a worldview, the “innocence of becoming” must be restored. The problem of emergence
attracted Nietzsche’s interest in the earliest writings, but he apparently began to conceptualize it in
published texts during the middle period, when his work freed itself from the early period’s
“metaphysics of aesthetics.” The opening passage from 1878’s Human, All Too Human gives some
indication of how Nietzsche’s thinking on this ancient problem begins to take shape:
Chemistry of concepts and feelings. In almost all respects, philosophical problems today are again
formulated as they were two thousand years ago: how can something arise from its opposite….?
Until now, metaphysical philosophy has overcome this difficulty by denying the origin of the one
from the other, and by assuming for the more highly valued things some miraculous origin….
Historical philosophy, on the other hand, the very youngest of all philosophical methods, which can
no longer be even conceived of as separate from the natural sciences, has determined in isolated
cases (and will probably conclude in all of them) that they are not opposites, only exaggerated to be
so by the metaphysical view….As historical philosophy explains it, there exists, strictly considered,
neither a selfless act nor a completely disinterested observation: both are merely sublimations. In
them the basic element appears to be virtually dispersed and proves to be present only to the most
careful observer. (Human, All Too Human, 1)
It is telling that Human begins by alluding to the problem of “emergence” as it is brought to light
again by the “historical philosophical method.” A decidedly un-scientific “metaphysical view,” by
comparison, looks rather for miraculous origins in support of the highest values. Next, in an
unexpected move, Nietzsche relates the general problem of emergence to two specific issues, one
concerning morals (“selfless acts”) and the other, knowledge—which is taken to include judgment
(“disinterested observations”): “in them the basic element appears to be virtually dispersed” and
discernable “only to the most careful observer.”
The logical structure of emergence, here, appears to have been borrowed from Hegel and, to be
sure, one could point to many Hegelian traces in Nietzsche’s thought. But previously in 1874’s “On
the Uses and Disadvantages of History for Life,” from Untimely Meditations, Nietzsche had
steadfastly refuted the dialectical logic of a “world historical process,” the Absolute Idea, and
cunning reason. What, then, is “the basic element”, dispersed in morals and knowledge? How is it
dispersed so that only the careful observer can detect it? The most decisive moment in Nietzsche’s
development of a cosmology seems to have occurred when Nietzsche plumbed the surface of his
early studies on the pathos and social construction of truth to discover a more prevalent feeling, one
animating all socially relevant acts. In Book One of the The Gay Science (certainly one of the greatest
works in whole corpus) Nietzsche, in the role of “careful observer,” identifies, with a bit of moral
psychology, the one motive spurring all such acts:
On the doctrine of the feeling of power. Benefiting and hurting others are ways of exercising one’s
power upon others: that is all one desires in such cases…. Whether benefiting or hurting others
involves sacrifices for us does not affect the ultimate value of our actions. Even if we offer our lives,
as martyrs do for their church, this is a sacrifice that is offered for our desire for power or for the
purpose of preserving our feeling of power. Those who feel “I possess Truth”—how many
possessions would they not abandon in order to save this feeling!...Certainly the state in which we
hurt others is rarely as agreeable, in an unadulterated way, as that in which we benefit others; it is a
sign that we are still lacking power, or it shows a sense of frustration in the face of this poverty….
(aphorism 13).
The “ultimate value” of our actions, even concerning those intended to pursue or preserve
“truth,” are not measured by the goodness we bring others, notwithstanding the fact that
intentionally harmful acts will be indicative of a desperate want of power. Nietzsche, here, asserts
the significance of enhancing the feeling of power, and with this aphorism from 1882 we are on the
way to seeing how “the feeling of power” will replace, for Nietzsche, otherworldly measures of
value, as we read in finalized form in the second aphorism of 1888’s The Anti-Christ:
What is good?—All that heightens the feeling of power, the will to power, power itself in man. What
is bad?—All that proceeds from weakness. What is happiness?—The feeling that power increases—
that a resistance is overcome.
No otherworldly measures exist, for Nietzsche. Yet, one should not conclude from this absence of a
transcendental measure that all expressions of power are qualitatively the same. Certainly, the
possession of a Machiavellian virtù will find many natural advantages in this world, but Nietzsche
locates the most important aspect of “overcoming resistance” in self-mastery and self-commanding.
In Zarathustra’s chapter, “Of Self-Overcoming,” all living creatures are said to be obeying something,
while “he who cannot obey himself will be commanded. That is the nature of living creatures.” It is
important to note the disjunction: one may obey oneself or one may not. Either way, one will be
commanded, but the difference is qualitative. Moreover, “commanding is more difficult than
obeying” (BGE 188 repeats this theme). Hence, one will take the easier path, if unable to command,
choosing instead to obey the directions of another. The exception, however, will command and obey
the healthy and self-mastering demands of a willing self. But why, we might ask, are all living things
beholden to such commanding and obeying? Where is the proof of necessity here? Zarathustra
answers:
Listen to my teaching, you wisest men! Test in earnest whether I have crept into the heart of life
itself and down to the roots of its heart! Where I found a living creature, there I found will to power;
and even in the will of the servant, I found the will to be master (Z “Of the Self-Overcoming”).
Here, apparently, Nietzsche’s doctrine of the feeling of power has become more than an observation
on the natural history and psychology of morals. The “teaching” reaches into the heart of life, and it
says something absolute about obeying and commanding. But what is being obeyed, on the
cosmological level, and what is being commanded? At this point, Zarathustra passes on a secret told
to him by life itself: “behold [life says], I am that which must overcome itself again and again…And
you too, enlightened man, are only a path and a footstep of my will: truly, my will to power walks
with the feet of your will to truth.” We see here that a principle, will to power, is embodied by the
human being’s will to truth, and we may imagine it taking other forms as well. Reflecting on this
insight, for example, Zarathustra claims to have solved “the riddle of the hearts” of the creator of
values: “you exert power with your values and doctrines of good and evil, you assessors of
values….but a mightier power and a new overcoming grow from out of your values…” That mightier
power growing in and through the embodiment and expression of human values is will to power.
It is important not to disassociate will to power, as a cosmology, from the human being’s drive to
create values. To be sure, Nietzsche is still saying that the creation of values expresses a desire for
power, and the first essay of 1887’s On the Genealogy of Morality returns to this simple formula.
Here, Nietzsche appropriates a well-known element of Hegel’s Phenomenology, the structural
movement of thought between basic types called “masters and slaves.” This appropriation has the
affect of emphasizing the difference between Nietzsche’s own historical “genealogies” and that of
Hegel’s “dialectic” (as is worked out in Deleuze’s study of Nietzsche). Master and slave moralities,
the truths of which are confirmed independently by feelings that power has been increased, are
expressions of the human being’s will to power in qualitatively different states of health. The former
is a consequence of strength, cheerful optimism and naiveté, while the latter stems from impotency,
pessimism, cunning and, most famously, ressentiment, the creative reaction of a “bad conscience”
coming to form as it turns against itself in hatred. The venom of slave morality is thus directed
outwardly in ressentiment and inwardly in bad conscience. Differing concepts of “good,” moreover,
belong to master and slave value systems. Master morality complements its good with the
designation, “bad,” understood to be associated with the one who is inferior, weak, and cowardly.
For slave morality, on the other hand, the designation, “good” is itself the complement of “evil,” the
primary understanding of value in this scheme, associated with the one possessing superior
strength. Thus, the “good man” in the unalloyed form of “master morality” will be the “evil man,”
the man against whom ressentiment is directed, in the purest form of “slave morality.” Nietzsche is
careful to add, at least in Beyond Good and Evil, that all modern value systems are constituted by
compounding, in varying degrees, these two basic elements. Only a “genealogical” study of how
these modern systems came to form will uncover the qualitative strengths and weaknesses of any
normative judgment.
The language and method of The Genealogy hearken back to The Gay Science’s “doctrine of the
feeling of power.” But, as we have seen, in the period between 1882 and 1887, and from out of the
psychological-historical description of morality, truth, and the feeling of power, Nietzsche has given
agency to the willing as such that lives in and through the embrace of power, and he generalizes the
willing agent in order to include “life” and “the world” and the principle therein by which entities
emerge embodied. The ancient philosophical problem of emergence is resolved, in part, with the
cosmology of a creative, self-grounding, self-generating, sustaining and enhancing will to power.
Such willing, most importantly, commands, which at the same time is an obeying: difference
emerges from out of indifference and overcomes it, at least for a while. Life, in this view, is
essentially self-overcoming, a self-empowering power accomplishing more power to no other end. In
a notebook entry from 1885, Will to Power’s aphorism 1067, Nietzsche’s cosmological intuitions take
flight:
And do you know what “the world” is to me? Shall I show it to you in my mirror? This world: a
monster of energy, without beginning, without end…as force throughout, as a play of forces and
waves of forces…a sea of forces flowing and rushing together, eternally changing and eternally
flooding back with tremendous years of recurrence…out of the play of contradictions back to the joy
of concord, still blessing itself as that which must return eternally, as a becoming that knows no
satiety, no disgust, no weariness; this my Dionysian world of the eternally self-creating, the eternally
self-destroying, this mystery world of the two-fold voluptuous delight, my “beyond good and evil,”
without goal, unless the joy of the circle is itself a goal….This world is the will to power—and nothing
besides! And you yourselves are also this will to power—and nothing besides!
Nietzsche discovers, here, the words to articulate one of his most ambitious concepts. The will to
power is now described in terms of eternal and world-encompassing creativity and destructiveness,
thought over the expanse of “tremendous years” and in terms of “recurrence,” what Foucault has
described as the “play of domination” (1971). In some respects Nietzsche has indeed rediscovered
the temporal structure of Heraclitus’ child at play, arranging toys in fanciful constructions of what
merely seems like everything great and noble, before tearing down this structure and building again
on the precipice of a new mishap. To live in this manner, according to Nietzsche in The Gay Science,
to affirm this kind of cosmology and its form of eternity, is to “live dangerously” and to “love fate”
(amor fati).
In spite of the positivistic methodology of The Genealogy, beneath the surface of this natural history
of morals, will to power pumps life into the heart of both master and slave conceptual frameworks.
Moreover, will to power stands as a necessary condition for all value judgments. How, one might
ask, are these cosmological intuitions derived? How is knowledge of both will to power and its
eternally recurring play of creation and destruction grounded? If they are to be understood
poetically, then the question “why?” is misplaced (Zarathustra, “Of Poets”). Logically, with respect to
knowledge, Nietzsche insists that principles of perception and judgment evolve co-dependently with
consciousness, in response to physical necessities. The self is organized and brought to stand within
the body and by the stimuli received there. This means that all principles are transformations of
stimuli and interpretations thereupon: truth is “a mobile army of metaphors” which the body forms
before the mind begins to grasp. Let us beware, Nietzsche cautions, of saying that the world
possesses any sort of order or coherence without these interpretations (GS 109), even to the extent
that Nietzsche himself conceives will to power as the way of all things. If all principles are
interpretive gestures, by the logic of Nietzsche’s new cosmology, the will to power must also be
interpretive (BGE 22). One aspect of the absence of absolute order is that interpretive gestures are
necessarily called-forth for the establishment of meaning. A critical requirement of this interpretive
gesture becoming transparent is that the new interpretation must knowingly affirm that all
principles are grounded in interpretation. According to Nietzsche, such reflexivity does not discredit
his cosmology: “so much the better,” since will to power, through Nietzsche’s articulation, emerges
as the thought that now dances playfully and lingers for a while in the midst of what Vattimo might
call a “weakened” (and weakening) “ontology” of indifference. The human being is thereby “an
experimental animal” (GM II). Its truths have the seductive power of the feminine (BGE 1); while
Nietzsche’s grandest visions are oriented by the “experimental” or “tempter” god, the one later
Nietzsche comes to identify with the name Dionysus (BGE 295).
The philosopher of the future will posses a level of critical awareness hitherto unimagined, given
that his interpretive gestures will be recognized as such. Yet, a flourishing life will still demand, one
might imagine, being able to suspend, hide, or forget—at the right moments—the creation of values,
especially the highest values. Perhaps the cartoonish, bombastic language of The Genealogy’s
master and slave morality, to point to an example, which was much more soberly discussed in the
previous year’s Beyond Good and Evil, is employed esoterically by Nietzsche for the rhetorical effect
of producing a grand and spectacular diversion, hiding the all-important creative gesture that
brought forth the new cosmology as a supreme value: “This world is the will to power and nothing
besides!—And you yourselves are also this will to power--and nothing besides!” With this teaching,
Nietzsche leaves underdeveloped many obvious themes, such as how the world’s non-animate
matter may (or may not) be involved with will to power or whether non-human life-forms take part
fully and equally in the world’s movement of forces. To have a perspective, for Nietzsche, seems
sufficient for participating in will to power, but does this mean that non-human animals, which
certainly seem to have perspectives, and without question participate in the living of life, have the
human being’s capacity (or any capacity for that matter) to command themselves? Or, do trees and
other forms of vegetation? Apparently, they do not. Such problems involve, again, the question of
freedom, which interests Nietzsche primarily in the positive form. Of more importance to Nietzsche
is that which pertains solely to the human being’s marshalling of forces but, even here (or perhaps
especially here), a hierarchy of differences may be discerned. Some human forms of participation in
will to power are noble, others ignoble. But, concerning these sorts of activities, Nietzsche stresses in
Beyond Good and Evil (aphorism 9) the difference between his own cosmology, which at times
seems to re-establish the place of nobility in nature, and the “stoic” view, which asserts the oneness
of humanity with divine nature:
“According to nature” you want to live? Oh you noble Stoics, what deceptive words these are!
Imagine a being like nature, wasteful beyond measure, indifferent beyond measure, without
purposes and consideration, without mercy and justice, fertile and desolate and uncertain at the
same time; imagine indifference itself as a power—how could you live according to this indifference?
Living—is that not precisely wanting to be other than this nature? Is not living—estimating,
preferring, being unjust, being limited, wanting to be different? ….But this is an ancient, eternal
story: what formerly happened with the Stoics still happens today, too, as soon as any philosophy
begins to believe in itself. It always creates the world in its own image; it cannot do otherwise.
Philosophy is this tyrannical drive itself; the most spiritual will to power, to the “creation of the
world,” to the causa prima.
Strauss claims that here Nietzsche is replacing “divine nature” and its egalitarian coherence with
“noble nature” and its expression of hierarchies, the condition for which is difference, per se,
emerging in nature from indifference (1983). Other commentators have suggested that Nietzsche,
here, betrays all of philosophy, lacking any sense of decency with this daring expose—that what is
left after the expression of such a forbidden truth is no recourse to meaning.
The most generalized form of the philosophical problem of emergence and disintegration, of the
living, valuing, wanting to be different, willing power, is described here in terms of the difference-
creating gesture embodied by the human being’s essential work, its “creation of the world” and first
causes. Within nature, one might say, energy disperses and accumulates in various force-points:
nature’s power to create these force-points is radically indifferent, and this indifference towards
what has been created also characterizes its power. Periodically, something exceptional is thrust out
from its opposite, given that radical indifference is indifferent even towards itself (if one could speak
of ontological conditions in such a representative tone, which Nietzsche certainly does from time to
time). Nature is disturbed, and the human being, having thus become aware of its own identity and
of others, works towards preserving itself by tying things down with definitions; enhancing itself,
occasionally, by loosening the fetters of old, worn-out forms; creating and destroying in such
patterns, so as to make humanity and even nature appear to conform to some bit of tyranny. From
within the logic of will to power, narrowly construed, human meaning is thus affirmed. “But to what
end?” one might ask. To no end, Nietzsche would answer. Here, the more circumspect view could be
taken, as is found in Twilight of the Idol’s “The Four Great Errors”: “One is a piece of fate, one
belongs to the whole, one is in the whole, there exist nothing which could judge, measure, compare,
condemn our being, for that would be to judge, measure, compare, condemn the whole….But
nothing exists apart from the whole!” Nietzsche conceptualizes human fate, then, in his most
extreme vision of will to power, as being fitted to a whole, “the world,” which is itself “nothing
besides” a “monster of energy, without beginning, without end…eternally changing and eternally
flooding back with tremendous years of recurrence.” In such manner, will to power expresses itself
not only through the embodiment of humanity, its exemplars, and the constant revaluation of
values, but also in time. Dasein, for Nietzsche, is suspended on the cross between these ontological
movements—between an in/different playing of destruction/creation—and time. But, what
temporal model yields the possibility for these expressions? How does Nietzsche’s experimental
philosophy conceptualize time?
7. Eternal Recurrence
The world’s eternally self-creating, self-destroying play is conditioned by time. Yet, Nietzsche’s
skepticism concerning what can be known of telos, indeed his refutation of an absolute telos
independent of human fabrication, demands a view of time that differs from those that place willing,
purposiveness, and efficient causes in the service of goals, sufficient reason, and causa prima.
Another formulation of this problem might ask, “what is the history of willing, if not the
demonstration of progress and/or decay?”
Nietzsche’s solution to the riddle of time, nevertheless, radicalizes the Christian concept of
eternity, combining a bit of simple observation and sure reasoning with an intuition that produces
curious, but innovative results. The solution takes shape as Nietzsche fills the temporal horizons of
past and future with events whose denotations have no permanent tether. Will to power, the
Heraclitean cosmic-child, plays-on without preference to outcomes. Within the two-fold limit of this
horizon, disturbances emerge from their opposites, but one cannot evaluate them, absolutely,
because judgment implicates participation in will to power, in the ebb and flow of events
constituting time. The objective perspective is not possible, since the whole consumes all
possibilities, giving form to and destroying all that has come to fulfillment. Whatever stands in this
flux, does so in the midst of the whole, but only for a while. It disturbs the whole, but does so as part
of the whole. As such, whatever stands is measured, on the one hand, by the context its emergence
creates. On the other hand, whatever stands is immeasurable, by virtue of the whole, the logic of
which would determine this moment to have occurred in the never-ending flux of creation and
destruction. Even to say that particular events seem better or worse suited to the functionality of
the whole, or to its stability, or its health, or that an event may be measured absolutely by its fitted-
ness in some other way, presupposes a standpoint that Nietzsche’s cosmology will not allow. One is
left only to describe material occurrences and to intuit the passing of time.
The second part of Nietzsche’s solution to the riddle of time reasons that the mere observation of an
occurrence, whether thought to be a simple thing or a more complex event, is enough to
demonstrate the occurrence’s possibility. If “something” has happened, then its happening,
naturally, must have been possible. Each simple thing or complex event is linked, inextricably, to a
near infinite number of others, also demonstrating the possibilities of their happenings. If all of these
possibilities could be presented in such a way as to account for their relationships and probabilities,
as for example on a marvelously complex set of dice, then it could be shown that each of these
possibilities will necessarily occur, and re-occur, given that the game of dice continues a sufficient
length of time.
Next, Nietzsche considers the nature of temporal limits and duration. He proposes that no beginning
or end of time can be determined, absolutely, in thought. No matter what sort of temporal limits are
set by the imagination, questions concerning what lies beyond these limits never demonstrably
cease. The question, “what precedes or follows the imagined limits of past and future?” never
contradicts our understanding of time, which is thus shown to be more culturally and historically
determined than otherwise admitted.
Finally, rather than to imagine a past and future extended infinitely on a plane of sequential
moments, or to imagine a time in which nothing happens or will happen, Nietzsche envisions
connecting what lies beyond the imagination’s two temporal horizons, so that time is represented in
the image of a circle, through which a colossal, but definitive number of possibilities are expressed.
Time is infinite with this model, but filled by a finite number of material possibilities, recurring
eternally in the never-ending play of the great cosmic game of chance.
What intuition led Nietzsche to interpret the cosmos as having no inherent meaning, as if it were
playing itself out and repeating itself in eternally recurring cycles, in the endless creation and
destruction of force-points without purpose? How does this curious temporal model relate to the
living of life? In his philosophical autobiography, Ecce Homo, Nietzsche grounds eternal recurrence
in his own experiences by relating an anecdote regarding, supposedly, its first appearance to him in
thought. One day, Nietzsche writes, while hiking around Lake Silvaplana near Sils Maria, he came
upon a giant boulder, took out a piece of paper and scribbled, “6000 Fuss jenseits von Mensch und
Zeit.” From here, Nietzsche goes on to articulate “the eternal recurrence of the same,” which he
then characterizes as “a doctrine” or “a teaching” of the “highest form of affirmation that can
possibly be attained.”
It is important to note that at the time of this discovery, Nietzsche was bringing his work on The Gay
Science to a close and beginning to sketch out a plan for Zarathustra. The conceptualization of
eternal recurrence emerges at the threshold of Nietzsche’s most acute positivistic inquiry and his
most poetic creation. The transition between the two texts is made explicit when Nietzsche repeats
the final aphorism of The Gay Science’s Book IV in the opening scene of Zarathustra’s prelude. The
repetition of this scene will prove to be no coincidence, given the importance Nietzsche places upon
the theme of recurrence in Zarathustra’s climactic chapters. Moreover, in the penultimate aphorism
of The Gay Science, as a sort of introduction to that text’s Zarathustra scene (which itself would
seem quite odd apart from the later work), Nietzsche first lays out Zarathustra’s central teaching, the
idea of eternal recurrence.
The greatest weight.—What, if some day or night a demon were to steal after you into your loneliest
loneliness and say to you: “This life as you now live it and have lived it, you will have to live once
more and innumerable times more; and there will be nothing new in it, but every pain and every joy
and every thought and sigh and everything unutterably small or great in your life will have to return
to you, all in the same succession and sequence—even this spider and this moonlight between the
trees, and even this moment and I myself. The eternal hourglass of existence is turned upside down
again and again, and you with it, speck of dust!” (GS 341).
“What if,” wonders Nietzsche, the thought took hold of us? Here, the conceptualization of eternal
recurrence, thus, coincides with questions regarding its impact: “how well disposed would you have
to become to yourself and to life to crave nothing more fervently than this ultimate eternal
confirmation and seal?”
How would the logic of this new temporal model alter our experiences of factual life? Would such a
thought diminish the willfulness of those who grasp it? Would it diminish our willingness to make
normative decisions? Would willing cease under the pessimistic suspicion that the course for
everything has already been determined, that all intentions are “in vain”? What would we lose by
accepting the doctrine of this teaching? What would we gain? It seems strange that Nietzsche would
place so much dramatic emphasis on this temporal form of determinism. If all of our worldly
strivings and cravings were revealed, in the logic of eternal recurrence, to be no more than illusions,
if every contingent fact of creation and destruction were understood to have merely repeated itself
without end, if everything that happens, as it happens, both re-inscribes and anticipates its own
eternal recurrence, what would be the affect on our dispositions, on our capacities to strive and
create? Would we be crushed by this eternal comedy? Or, could we somehow find it liberating?
Even though Nietzsche has envisioned a temporal model of existence seemingly depriving us of the
freedom to act in unique ways, we should not fail to catch sight of the qualitative differences the
doctrine nevertheless leaves open for the living. The logic of eternity determines every contingent
fact in each cycle of recurrence. That is, each recurrence is quantitatively the same. The quality of
that recurrence, however, seems to remain an open question. What if the thought took hold of us? If
we indeed understood ourselves to be bound by fate and thus having no freedom from the eternal
logic of things, could we yet summon love for that fate, to embrace a kind of freedom for becoming
that person we are? This is the strange confluence of possibility and necessity that Nietzsche
announces in the beginning of Gay Science’s Book IV, with the concept of Amor fati: “I want to learn
more and more to see as beautiful what is necessary in things; then I shall be one of those who make
things beautiful. Amor fati: let that be my love henceforth!”
Responses to this “doctrine” have been varied. Even some of the most enthusiastic Nietzsche
commentators have, like Kaufmann, deemed it unworthy of serious reflection. Nietzsche, however,
appears to stress its significance in Twilight of the Idols and Ecce Homo by emphasizing Zarathustra’s
importance in the “history of humanity” and by dramatically staging in Thus Spoke Zarathustra the
idea of eternal recurrence as the fundamental teaching of the main character. The presentation of
this idea, however, leaves room for much doubt concerning the literal meaning of these claims, as
does the paucity of direct references to the doctrine in other works intended for publication. In
Nietzsche’s Nachlass, we discover attempts to work out rational proofs supporting the theory, but
they seem to present no serious challenge to a linear conception of time. Among commentators
taking the doctrine seriously, Löwith takes it as a supplement to Nietzsche’s historical nihilism, as a
way of placing emphasis on the problem of meaning in history after the shadows of God have been
dissolved. For Löwith’s Nietzsche, nihilism is more than an historical moment giving rise to a crisis of
confidence or faith. Rather, nihilism is the essence of Nietzsche’s thought, and it poses the sorts of
problems that lead Nietzsche into formulating eternal return as a way of restoring meaning in
history. For Löwith, then, eternal return is inextricably linked to historical nihilism and offers both
cosmological and anthropological grounds for accepting imperatives of self-overcoming. Yet, this
grand attempt fails to restore meaning after the death of God, according to Löwith, because of
eternal return’s logical contradictions.
The reception of Nietzsche’s work, on all levels of engagement, has been complicated by historical
contingencies that are related only by accident to the thought itself. The first of these complications
pertains to the editorial control gained by Elizabeth in the aftermath of her brother’s mental and
physical collapse. Elisabeth’s overall impact on her brother’s reputation is generally thought to be
very problematic. Her husband, Bernhard Förster, whom Friedrich detested, was a leader of the late
nineteenth-century German anti-Semitic political movement, which Friedrich often ridiculed and
unambiguously condemned, both in his published works and in private correspondences. On this
issue, Yovel demonstrates persuasively, with a contextual analysis of letters, materials from the
Nachlass, and published works, that Nietzsche developed an attitude of “anti-anti-Semitism” after
overcoming the culture of prejudice that formed him in his youth (Yovel, 1998). In the mid-1880s,
Förster and wife led a small group of colonists to Paraguay in hopes of establishing an idyllic, racially
pure, German settlement. The colony foundered, Bernhard committed suicide, and Elisabeth
returned home, just in time to find her brother’s health failing and his literary career ready to soar.
Upon her return, Elisabeth devised a way to keep alive the memory of both husband and brother,
legally changing her last name to “Förster-Nietzsche,” a gesture indicative of designs to associate the
philosopher with a political ideology he loathed. The stain of Elisabeth’s editorial imprint can be seen
on the many ill-informed and haphazard interpretations of Nietzsche produced in the early part of
the twentieth century, the unfortunate traces of which remain in some readings today. During the
1930s, in the midst of intense activity by National Socialist academic propagandists such as Alfred
Bäumler, even typically insightful thinkers such as Emmanuel Levinas confused the public image of
Nietzsche for the philosopher’s stated beliefs. Counter-efforts in the 1930s to refute such
propaganda, and the popular misconceptions it was fomenting at the time, can be found both inside
and outside Germany, in seminars, for example, led by Karl Jaspers and Karl Löwith, and in Georges
Bataille’s essay “Nietzsche and the Fascists.” Of course, the ad hominem argument that “Nietzsche
must be a Fascist philosopher because the Fascists venerated him as one of their own,” may be
ignored. (No one should find Kant’s moral philosophy reprehensible, by comparison, simply on the
grounds that Eichmann attempted to exploit it in a Jerusalem court). Apart from the fallacy, here,
even the premise itself regarding Nietzsche and the Fascists is not entirely above reproach, since
some Fascists were skeptical of the commensurability of Nietzsche’s thought with their political
aims. The stronger claim that Nietzsche’s thought leads to National Socialism is even more
problematic. Nevertheless, intellectual histories pursuing the question of how Nietzsche has been
placed into the service of all sorts of political interests are an important part of Nietzsche
scholarship.
Since the middle part of the last century, Nietzsche scholars have come to grips with the role played
by Elisabeth and her associates in obscuring Nietzsche’s anti-Nationalistic, anti-Socialist, anti-German
views, his pan-European advocacy of race mixing, as well as his hatred for anti-Semitism and its place
in the late-nineteenth-century politics of exploitation. The work Elisabeth performed as her
brother’s publicist, however, undoubtedly fulfilled all of her own fantasies: in the early 1930’s,
decades after Friedrich’s death, the Nietzsche-Archiv was visited, ceremoniously, by Adolf Hitler,
who was greeted and entertained by Elisabeth (in perhaps the most symbolic gesture of her
association with the Nietzsche image) with a public reading of the work of her late husband,
Bernhard, the anti-Semite. Hitler later attended Elisabeth’s funeral as Chancellor of Germany.
In a matter related to Elizabeth’s impact on the reception of her brother’s thought, the relevance of
Nietzsche’s biography to his philosophical work has long been a point of contention among
Nietzsche commentators. While an exhaustive survey of the way this key issue has been addressed
in the scholarship would be difficult in this context, a few influential readings may be briefly
mentioned. Among notable German readers, Heidegger and Fink dismiss the idea that Nietzsche’s
thought can be elucidated with the details of his life, while Jaspers affirms the “exceptional” nature
of Nietzsche’s life and identifies the exception as a key aspect of his philosophy. French readers such
as Bataille, Deleuze, Klossowski, Foucault, and Derrida assert the relevance of various biographical
details to specific movements within Nietzsche’s writings. In the United States, the influential
reading of Walter Kaufman follows Heidegger, for the most part, in denying relevance, while his
student, Alexander Nehamas, tends the other way, linking Nietzsche’s various literary styles to his
“perspectivism” and ultimately to living, per se, as an self-interpretive gesture. However difficult it
might be to see the philosophical relevance of various biographical curiosities, such as Nietzsche’s
psychological development as a child without a living father, his fascination and then fallout with
Wagner, his professional ostracism, his thwarted love life, the excruciating physical ailments that
tormented him, and so on, it would also seem capricious and otherwise inconsistent with Nietzsche’s
work to radically severe his thought from these and other biographical details, and persuasive
interpretations have argued that such experiences, and Nietzsche’s well-considered views of them,
are inseparable from the multiple trajectories of his intellectual work.
Attempts to isolate Nietzsche’s philosophy from the twists and turns of a frequently problematic life
may be explained, in part, as a reaction to several early, and rather detrimental, popular-
psychological studies attempting to explain the work in a reductive and decidedly un-philosophical
manner. Such was the reading proffered, for example, by Lou Salomè, a woman with whom
Nietzsche briefly had an unconventional and famously complex romantic relationship, and who later
befriended Sigmund Freud among other leaders of European culture at the fin-de-siècle. Salomè’s
Friedrich Nietzsche in His Works (1894) helped cast the image of Nietzsche as a lonely, miserable,
self-immolating, recluse whose “external intellectual work…and inner life coalesce completely.” In
some commentaries, this image prevails yet today, but its accuracy is also a matter of debate.
Nietzsche had many casual associates and a few close friends while in school and as a professor in
Basel. Even during the period of his most intense intellectual activity, after withdrawing from the
professional world of the academy and, like Marx and others before him in the nineteenth century,
taking up the wandering life of a “good European,” the many written correspondences between
Nietzsche and life-long friends, along with what is known about the minor details of his daily habits,
his days spent in the company of fellow lodgers and travelers, taking meals regularly (in spite of a
very closely regulated diet), and similar anecdotes, all put forward a different image. No doubt the
affair with Salomè and their mutual friend, the philosopher Paul Rée, left Nietzsche embittered
towards the two of them, and it seems likely that this bitterness clouded Salomè’s interpretation of
Nietzsche and his works. Elisabeth, who had always loathed Salomè for her immoderation and
perceived influence over Friedrich, attempted to correct her rival’s account by writing her own
biography of Friedrich, which was effusive in its praise but did little to advance the understanding of
Nietzsche’s thought. Perhaps these kinds of problems, then, provide the best argument for resisting
the lure to reduce interpretations of Nietzsche’s thought to gossipy biographical anecdotes and
clumsy, amateurish speculation, even if the other extreme has also been excessive at times.
Another key issue in the reception of Nietzsche’s work involves determining its relationship to the
thoughts of other philosophers and, indeed, to the philosophical tradition itself. On both levels of
this complex issue, the work of Martin Heidegger looms paramount. Heidegger began working
closely with Nietzsche’s thought in the 1930s, a time rife with political opportunism in Germany,
even among scholars and intellectuals. In the midst of a struggle over the official Nazi interpretation
of Nietzsche, Heidegger’s views began to coalesce, and after a series of lectures on Nietzsche’s
thought in the late 1930’s and 1940, Heidegger produces in 1943 the seminal essay, “Nietzsche’s
Word: “God is Dead””. Nietzsche, for Heidegger, brought “the consummation of metaphysics” in the
age of subject-centered reasoning, industrialization, technological power, and the “enframing” (Ge-
stell) of humans and all other beings as a “standing reserve.” Combining Nietzsche’s self-described
“inversion of Platonism” with the emphasis Nietzsche had undoubtedly placed upon the value-
positing act and its relatedness to subjective or inter-subjective human perspectives, Heidegger
dubbed Nietzsche “the last metaphysician” and tied him to the logic of a historical narrative
highlighted by the appearances of Plato, Aristotle, Roman Antiquity, Christendom, Luther, Descartes,
Leibniz, Schopenhauer, and others. The “one thought” common to each of these movements and
thinkers, according to Heidegger, and the path Nietzsche thus thinks through to its “consummation,”
is the “metaphysical” determination of being (Sein) as no more than something static and constantly
present. Although Nietzsche appears to reject the concept of being as an “empty fiction” (claiming,
in Twilight of the Idols, to concur with Heraclitus in this regard), Heidegger nevertheless reads in
Nietzsche’s Platonic inversion the most insidious form of the metaphysics of presence, in which the
destruction and re-establishment of value is taken to be the only possible occasion for philosophical
labor whereby the very question of being is completely obliterated. Within this diminution of
thought, the Nietzschean “Superman” emerges supremely powerful and triumphant, taking
dominion over the earth and all of its beings, measured only by the mundane search for advantages
in the ubiquitous struggle for preservation and enhancement.
As is typically the case with Heidegger’s interpretations of the history of philosophy, many aspects of
this reading are truly remarkable—Heidegger’s scholarship, for example, his feel for what is
important to Nietzsche, and his elaboration of Nietzsche’s work in a way that seems compatible with
a narrative of the concealing and revealing destiny of being. However, the plausibility of this reading
has come into question almost from the moment the full extent of it was made known in the 1950s
and 60s. In Germany, for example, Eugen Fink concludes his 1960 study of Nietzsche by casting
doubt upon Heidegger’s claim that Nietzsche’s thought can be reduced to a metaphysics:
Heidegger’s Nietzsche interpretation is essentially based upon Heidegger’s summary and insight into
the history of being and in particular on his interpretation of the metaphysics of modernity.
Nevertheless, the question remains open whether Nietzsche does not already leave the
metaphysical dimensions of any problems essentially and intentionally behind in his conception of
the cosmos. There is a non-metaphysical originality in his cosmological philosophy of “play.” Even
the early writings indicate the mysterious dimension of play….
Fink’s reluctance to take a stronger position against the reading of his renowned teacher seems
rather coy, given that Fink’s study, throughout, has stressed the meaning and importance of
“cosmological play” in Nietzsche’s work. Other commentators have much more explicitly challenged
Heidegger’s grand narrative and specifically its place for Nietzsche in the Western tradition,
concurring with Fink that Nietzsche’s conceptualization of play frees his thought from the tradition
of metaphysics, or that Nietzsche, purposively or not, offered conflicting views of himself, eluding
the kind of summary treatment presented by Heidegger and much less-gifted readers (who consider
Nietzsche to be no more than a late-Romantic, a social-Darwinist, or the like). In this sort of
commentary, Nietzsche’s work itself is at play in deconstructing the all-too-rigid kinds of
explanations.
While such a reading has proven to be popular, partly because it seems to make room for various
points of entry into Nietzsche’s thought, it has understandably stirred a backlash of sorts among less
charitable commentators who find pragmatic or neo-Kantian strains in Nietzsche’s critique of
metaphysics and who wish to separate Nietzsche’s level-headed philosophy from his poorly-
developed musings. Notable works by Schacht, Clark, Conway, and Leiter fall into this category. In a
loosely related movement, many commentators bring Nietzsche into dialogue with the tradition by
concentrating on aspects of his work relevant to particular philosophical issues, such as the problem
of truth, the development of a natural history of morals, a philosophical consideration of moral
psychology, problems concerning subjectivity and logo-centrism, theories of language, and many
others. Finally, much work continues to be done on Nietzsche in the history of ideas, regarding, for
example, Nietzsche’s philology, his intellectual encounters with nineteenth-century science; the neo-
Kantians; the pre-Socratics (or “pre-Platonics,” as he called them); the work of his friend, Paul Rée;
their shared affinity for the wit and style of La Rochefoucauld; historical affinities and influences such
as those pertaining to Hölderlin, Goethe, Emerson, and Lange, detailed studies of what Nietzsche
was reading and when he was reading it, and a host of other themes. Works by Habermas, Porter,
Gillespie, Brobjer, Ansell-Pearson, Conway, and Strong are notable for historicizing Nietzsche in a
variety of contexts.
In most cases, interpretations of Nietzsche’s thought, and what is taken to be most significant about
it, when not directed solely by external considerations, will be determined by the texts in Nietzsche’s
corpus given priority and by a decision regarding Nietzsche’s overall coherence, as concerns any
given issue, throughout the trajectory of his intellectual development.