Brown, P. - St. Thomas' Doctrine of Necessary Being
Brown, P. - St. Thomas' Doctrine of Necessary Being
Brown, P. - St. Thomas' Doctrine of Necessary Being
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Duke University Press and Philosophical Review are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to The Philosophical Review.
http://www.jstor.org
76
77
to say that it is possible that God should not exist. But, surely, we can
understand what it would be like for God not to exist. What we can
understand is a possibility.5
As a final example, we may note that Father Copleston has
ascribed to the Angelic Doctor the view that "there can be but
one necessary being."6
A large number of commentators have, like Smart, interpreted
the first part of Aquinas' Third Way according to the following
schema:
(i) If anything exists, then there must exist a logically
necessary being.
(2) Something exists.
(3) Therefore: there must exist a logically necessary being.
St. Thomas would have to have been rather artless to defend such
an argument. For the most obvious point about it is that the two
premises are entirely superfluous. That is to say, if God's existence
is supposed to be logically necessary, then surely the conclusion
will stand on its own. Step (3), in short, itself constitutes the
rationalistic version of the ontological argument. So, if this
interpretation of Aquinas' demonstration were correct, the Third
Way would really be an a prior proof merely masquerading as
a posterior (cf. n. 42, infra).
The foregoing shows a complete misunderstanding of St.
Thomas' thought, however. For, to begin with, he writes about
necessary beings other than God so often in his works that it is
hard to imagine how anyone who bothered to check could over-
look the point. The most obvious passage on this matter is in the
last part of the Third Way itself:
Therefore, not all beings are merely possible, but there must exist
something the existence of which is necessary. But every necessary
thing either has its necessity caused by another or not. Now it is
impossible to go on to infinity in necessary things which have their
necessity caused by another. ... Therefore we cannot but admit the
existence of some being having of itself its own necessity, and not
receiving it from another. This all men speak of as God.7
5 ReligiousBelief (Ithaca, N. Y., 1959), pp. 151-152.
6 A Historyof Philosophy(London, I959), ii, 363.
7 SummaTheologica(hereafter S. T.), I, Q. 2, Art. 3.
78
This, the very passage which Smart and the others are claiming
to expound and discuss, both admits the possibility of a plurality
of necessary beings, and also explicitly states that a being's
necessity can be causedby another being. This latter point, one
would have thought, conclusively rules out the possibility that by
"necessary being" Aquinas meant "being whose existence is
logically necessary." For it would be naive to think that there
could be an efficient cause for what is logically necessary. And
St. Thomas' admission that there might in principle be many
necessary beings should lead one to doubt whether he thought
that "x exists necessarily" entails "x is an infinitely perfect being;
that is, God"-Kant to the contrary notwithstanding.
Now we find the following, rather unambiguous, assertion
in the Summa Theologica:"there are many necessary things in
existence."8 Again, Aquinas speaks of "those necessary things
that are created."9 Further, he mentions "all that is in things
created by God, whether it be contingent or necessary. "10 Nor
does St. Thomas fail to particularize: "heavenly bodies, with
their movements and dispositions, are necessary beings";" ; "in
the heavenly bodies, the substantial being ... is unchangeable" ;12
"the heavenly bodies ... are incorruptible."113 Further: "the
intellectual principle which we call the human soul is incor-
ruptible" ;14 "of all creatures, the rational creature chiefly is
ordained for the good of the universe, being per se incorruptible."'5
Further: "matter ... is incorruptible, since it is the subject of
generation and corruption."16 And lastly: "it must necessarily
be maintained that the angels are incorruptible of their own
8 S. T., I,
Q.44, Art. i, Obj. 2 (although the passage quoted actually occurs
in an Objection, St. Thomas' Reply implicitly accepts its truth); see also
Q. ig, Art. 8 and Q. 22, Art. 4.
9 S. i., I-II, Q. 93, Art. 4, Reply Obj. 3.
10 S. T., I-II, Q. 93, Art. 4.
1 S. T., I, Q. I15, Art. 6, Obj. i (again, the Reply does not dispute the
quoted statement).
12 S.T., I, Q. io, Art. 5; cf. also Q. 66, Art. 2.
13 S. T., I,
QI 75, Art. 6.
14 Ibid.
15 S.T., I, Q. 23, Art. 7.
16 S.T., I, Q. 104, Art. 4.
79
80
8I
We must conclude, then, that Aquinas did not hold either that
everything in the natural world is contingent, or that a necessary
being is one which cannot possibly not-exist, or that any being
which is necessary must be the ens realissimumor perfectissimum.
If it be demonstrated that St. Thomas did not understand
by "necessary existence" what he is commonly thought to have
understood, then it is incumbent upon me to explain what he did
mean by that phrase. And our previous quotations suggest that
Aquinas meant by the term "necessary," as applied to beings,
that they be neither generable nor corruptible.28 That is to say,
a necessary being is defined as one which cannot come into
existence via conglomeration, construction, or reformationo, and
which cannot pass out of existence via deterioration, destruction,
or deformation. This notion is obviously derived from Aristotle
(see De Caelo, Bk. I, Chs. 9-I2; De Generationeet Corruptione,Bk. II,
Ch. i i; Metaphysica,Bk. II, Ch. 2, Bk. V, Ch. 5, Bk. VI, Chs. I-4,
and Bk. XII, Chs. i-io). In short, for both Aristotle and Aquinas,
a necessarybeing is one which cannotundergoany essentialchangein any
of the ways permitted by the Aristotelian theories of matter and
form, potentiality and actuality, and simplicity and complexity.
So, as we have already seen (notes 23 and 26), Aristotle thought
that a necessary being can have a cause but nonetheless cannot
possibly come into or pass out of existence, since to do either
would involve a change in the above-mentioned sense. And St.
Thomas followed Aristotle in holding that a necessary being
could not begin or cease existing by any "natural" process allowed
by the Aristotelian physics; but Aquinas added that such beings
can come into existence via creation ex nihilo, as well as pass out
of existence via total annihilation.29 A necessary being, then,
is one which cannot undergo any essential alteration-though
all of them but God can undergo accidental change (cf. n. 33).
With regard to the angels, for instance, St. Thomas says the
following:
28 It must be borne in mind that "necessary" was for St. Thomas an alethic
modality de re, not de dicto; by "x necessarily exists" he did not mean "N(x
exists)." Cf. G. H. von Wright, An Essay in Modal Logic (Amsterdam, I951).
29 See nn. 24 and 27, and S. T., I, Qs. 44-46, 65-66, and 104, as well as
Q.s o, Art. 5, Q. 6i, Art. i, and Q. go, Art. 2.
82
83
84
85
86
38 De Caelo,bk. I, ch. I 2.
39 Cf. S.T., I, Q. 46, passim.
87
40 S.T., I, Q. 2, Art 3.
88
89
90