Philosophical Solitude David Hume Versus Jean-Jacq
Philosophical Solitude David Hume Versus Jean-Jacq
Philosophical Solitude David Hume Versus Jean-Jacq
History Workshop Journal Issue 89 Advance Access Publication 22 January 2020 doi:10.1093/hwj/dbz048
C The Author(s) 2020. Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of History Workshop Journal.
V
This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (http://creative-
commons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted reuse, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the
original work is properly cited.
2 History Workshop Journal
some people unbearably lonely: ‘Solitude’, John Donne wrote after a period
of confinement with illness, ‘is a torment which is not threatened in hell
itselfe’.7 For other people – especially but not exclusively religious solitaries
– solitude is experienced as a privileged site of intimate connection, an always-
accompanied condition. ‘Never less alone than when alone’; ‘nothing so com-
inspiration, and artistic creativity; for the common herd it spelled vice and
debility.12
In the case of scholarly recluses, the negative valuation gained ground
from the late Renaissance onward as intellectual modernizers produced a
steady stream of writings deprecating ‘the obscureness. . .of contemplative
men’.13 The principal targets of these strictures were the scholastics or
. . .wits being shut up in the cells of a few authors (chiefly Aristotle their
dictator) as their persons were shut up in the cells of monasteries and
colleges. . .did out of no great quantity of matter and infinite agitation of
wit spin out unto us those laborious webs of learning. . . admirable for the
fineness of thread and work, but of no substance or profit.15
own mind’: a method ‘which can by no means stand with a practical and
universal Inquiry’.21
Yet throughout the learned world there remained an alternative version of
the philosophical life which legitimated solitude. Descartes’s discovery of the
cogito while ‘shut up alone in a stove-heated room’ became emblematic of
heroic truth-seeking.22 ‘It occurred to me’, he later wrote of his epiphany,
‘[T]hose women which restrain themselves from the company and use of
men, are damned.’33 A century later Hume wrote to a friend about a Mrs
Mallett who ‘seems to be going upon a strange Project of living alone in a
Hermitage, in the midst of the Forrest [sic] of Fountainebleau’. ‘The Woman
is Wrong in the Head’, was his correspondent’s verdict.34
the more sociable men become: nor is it possible, that, when enriched
with science, and possessed of a fund of conversation, they should be
contented to remain in solitude, or live with their fellow-citizens in that
distant manner, which is peculiar to ignorant and barbarous nations.39
For Hume it was these sociable men and women – the ‘conversible world’,
as he dubbed polite society – that philosophy had now to address. Echoing
the Spectator’s promise to bring philosophy ‘out of Closets and Libraries,
Schools and Colleges’ onto the ‘tea-tables’ of the nation, Hume called for a
‘League betwixt the learned and conversible Worlds’ and offered himself as
an emissary from the world of learned men who, if cut off from ‘good
Company’, as in the case of the Scholastics, became ‘barbarous’ in their
manners and ‘Chimerical’ in their reasoning. ‘And indeed’, as he opined,
‘what cou’d be expected from Men who never consulted Experience in any of
their Reasonings, or who never search’d for that Experience, where alone it
is to be found, in common Life and Conversation?’40
6 History Workshop Journal
Hume’s tone here was light; but the point about true philosophy emerging
out of ‘common life and conversation’ was a serious one, echoed by many
Enlightenment savants. ‘Meditating by one’s self is like digging in a mine’,
Locke wrote: ‘it often, perhaps, brings up maiden earth, . . .but whether it
contains any mettle in it, is never so well tryed as in conversation.’41 Social
former Spring & Vigor, so as to endure the Fatigue of deep & abstruse
thinking? . . .[Have I] taken a right way to recover?’49
We don’t know whether the unnamed physician replied to this letter. But
if he did, either he did not advise against further solitary study or Hume
ignored his advice, since within a year – after a brief attempt to refashion
Such a strange outpouring, with its awkward blend of anguish and conceit,
helplessness and heroics. All the long-rehearsed perils of philosophical soli-
tude – melancholy, grandiosity, indolence, paranoia, dogmatism, an
‘inflamed imagination’ – are present, along with an account of the remedies
Hume famously employs:
Hume’s biographer James Harris portrays it?54 Hume himself attributes the
catastrophe to his relentless scepticism which, by exposing the limitations of
human reason, has led him to the insupportable recognition that ‘we have no
choice. . .but betwixt a false reason and none at all’.55 Hume scholars have
generally followed him, although their readings of this ‘sceptical malady’
***
Hume and Rousseau met in Paris in the mid 1760s. By then Rousseau was a
confirmed recluse, having hidden away from real or imagined persecutors for
nearly a decade.60 By modern standards, this solitariness was far from soli-
tary. In whatever haven Rousseau found himself – country houses large and
small, foreign boltholes – he was accompanied by others; sometimes he was
so surrounded by people that he ran away to avoid them. And – like most
male solitaries – even at his most reclusive Rousseau was serviced by a
woman, in his case the one-time chambermaid and mother of his five chil-
dren, Thérèse Levasseur. Nevertheless, Rousseau’s self-image as a loner (‘a
hermit’, ‘a bear’, as he described himself) was very powerful, and in the final
decades of his life he became a veritable apostle of solitude, limning its joys
to all who would listen.61 Many heard him admiringly, among them James
Boswell who after a 1764 visit to Rousseau in his ‘romantick retirement’ in
Switzerland came away carolling his praises.62 Others were less impressed. In
Philosophical Solitude 9
England the Critical Review cast him as a modern Diogenes, ‘a recluse of the
gloomy, misanthropic type’, while in France his enemies accused him of
fleeing criticism.63 But the sharpest reactions came from Rousseau’s own
intellectual circle in Paris, where attitudes to intellectual solitude were at
least as equivocal as in Enlightenment Britain.
Who does not see. . .that it is not possible for the wicked man to love
living alone and with himself? He would feel himself in company that is
too bad, he would be too ill at ease, he would not be able to bear it for
very long. . .Amour-propre, the principle of all wickedness. . .thrives in
society, which caused it to be born and where one is forced to compare
oneself at each instant. It languishes and dies for want of nourishment in
solitude. Whoever suffices to himself does not want to harm anyone at all.68
Rousseau then went on, with his usual grandiosity, to blame Diderot’s
misrepresentation of him for a general revolution in attitudes to solitude.
‘Until that time, the love of seclusion had been regarded as one of the least
ambiguous signs of a peaceful and healthy soul’, he wrote; but then, with a
‘stroke of the pen’, Diderot had transformed solitude from a ‘peaceful and
gentle taste’ into ‘an infernal rage’, thereby defaming not just Jean-Jacques
but all intellectual solitaries:
10 History Workshop Journal
Many respected wise men and Descartes himself were thereby trans-
formed in an instant into so many awful misanthropes and scoundrels.
The Philosopher Diderot may have been alone when he wrote that sen-
tence, but I doubt he was alone when he thought of it, and he took great
care to circulate it widely in society. Would that it pleased God that the
wicked man were always alone!69
seems likely that his relationship with Rousseau awoke memories of this, as
he struggled to find somewhere in England sufficiently remote to satisfy his
famous charge (he eventually settled him in the wilds of Staffordshire).87 It
seems likely too that the pathological aloneness Hume discovered in both the
Marquess and Rousseau played on his own ambivalence about solitude: his
***
What are we doing, when we think? Or to put the question rather differently:
who are we with, when we are thinking? There is a long tradition, inaugu-
rated by Plato, which depicts thinking as inner dialogue, ‘a talk the soul
carries on with itself’ as Socrates famously described it.89 For Saint
Augustine and many Christian contemplatives after him, the dialogic rela-
tionship was with God, while for Enlightenment Platonists such as Lord
Shaftesbury, echoing Socrates, it was with the self as colloquist, one-half
of a ‘doubled soul’, as Shaftesbury wrote; a two-in-one as Hannah Arendt
much later described it, such that the thinking self is always, as Arendt put it,
‘in company. . .solitary but not lonely’; or as Shaftesbury said, quoting
Scipio, ‘never less alone than when I am by myself’.90
Rousseau’s lone meditations display a powerful sense of this inner com-
panionship, of a solitude shared with an alter-ego whose presence he often
found deeply enriching but also, all too often, darkly persecutory. As Grimm
said of Rousseau, ‘he takes with him a companion who will not suffer him to
rest in peace’.91 In his Rousseau: Judge of Jean-Jacques, mentioned above,
Rousseau gave this tormenting companion a voice as the ‘Frenchman’, an
interlocutor who repeats every vicious criticism that has ever been lobbed at
Rousseau which his hapless target, dubbed ‘Rousseau’, attempts to rebut.
Yet in his final work, Reveries of a Solitary Walker, this other self (‘my
expansive soul’ as Rousseau describes it in this text) appears as serene or
joyful, even at times euphoric with sublime joy, ‘a stupefying ecstasy. . .-
which. . .made me cry out in the agitation of my raptures, “Oh great being!
Oh great being. . .”’.92 Before their falling-out Hume had noted this mystical
element in Rousseau, his feeling of being in ‘immediate communication with
Philosophical Solitude 13
For the young Hume then, philosophical solitude was morbid, conjuring
up doubts and fears from which everyday sociality, ‘the common life’, res-
cued him; or so he claimed.102 Did this change in the course of his life? We
do not know. From his contretemps with Rousseau it’s clear that solitariness
went on being an issue for Hume, but how exigent an issue cannot be dis-
cerned.103 In a period when personal letters were often far from private,
Earlier versions of this article were presented to audiences at the University of St Andrews,
University College London and Queen Mary University of London; my thanks to my listeners
on these occasions for their perceptive questions which I hope I have at least partially answered;
special thanks to Marybeth Hamilton, Thomas Laqueur, Jinty Nelson, Lyndal Roper, and
Silvia Sebastiani for helpful comments on the penultimate version. In 2017–18 I held a
23 Descartes, Discourse, p. 77. But see below (n. 56) for a different version of Descartes’s
philosophical solitude.
24 Shapin, ‘The Mind is Its Own Place’, p. 204, 205; Steven Shapin, A Social History of
Truth: Civility and Science in Seventeenth-Century England, Chicago, 1994, p. 164.
25 John Evelyn to Robert Boyle, 3 Sept 1659: The Letterbooks of John Evelyn, eds.
Douglas Chambers and David Galbraith, Toronto, 2014, vol 1, p 254. See also Gillian
Darley, John Evelyn: Living for Ingenuity, New Haven, 2007, p. 157.
210–47; Tzvetan Todorov, Imperfect Garden: the Legacy of Humanism, Princeton, 2002; Leo
Damrosch, Jean-Jacques Rousseau: Restless Genius, New York, 2005; Antoine Lilti, The
Invention of Celebrity (2015), Malden MA, 2017, chap. 5. Anne Vila, in Suffering Scholars,
discusses the contemporary medical view of Rousseau as a prototype of the melancholic intel-
lectual solitary (pp. 130–40).
62 R. A. Leigh, ‘Boswell and Rousseau’, The Modern Language Review 47: 3 (1952), pp.
290–318.
Yet despite this he made secret enquiries about the state of Rousseau’s finances (Edmonds and
Eidinow, Rousseau’s Dog, pp. 160–1), entered into secret dealings over his living arrangements,
all seemingly with the most benign intentions but covert nonetheless (Edmonds and Eidinow,
Rousseau’s Dog, pp. 183–91), disguised his knowledge about the authorship of an unpleasant
spoof directed at Rousseau which acquired wide currency (Edmonds and Eidinow, Rousseau’s
Dog, pp. 192–204), and most astonishingly, opened some of Rousseau’s letters (Zaretsky and
Scott, Philosophers’ Quarrel, pp. 159–60).
93 Hume, letter to Rev. Hugh Blair, 28 Dec. 1765, in Letters, ed. Greig, vol. 1, p. 530.
94 Hume, ‘Of Personal Identity’, Treatise, pp. 299–311. An ‘idea of ourselves is always
present to us’, Hume writes (Treatise, p. 403) but it’s an idea with no substantive or spiritual
correlate. For Hume’s religious scepticism see his Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (1779).
Hume’s sympathy with Rousseau as a victim of persecution probably owed something to the
hostility he himself faced as an ‘infidel’ thinker.
The solitariness of the religious sceptic is a theme with a long history: looking back to