Arthur Koestler - The Act of Creation
Arthur Koestler - The Act of Creation
Arthur Koestler - The Act of Creation
"tnger"
../
"<«~~s---- $1i0JlTCUT
-Yl,l;:dioS
I
I
A.i,tobiography
DIALOGUE WITH DEATH
SCUM OF THE EARTH
.Alm.OW IN THE BLUE
THE INVISIBLE WRITING
nm GOD TH.AT FAILED (with others)
Essays
nm YOGI AND THE COMMISSAR
INSIGHT AND OUTLOOK
PB.OMISE AND FULPILMENT
THE TRAIL OF THE DINOSAUR.
REFLECTIONS ON HANGING
nm SLEEPWALKERS
THE LOTUS AND THB ROBOT
SUICIDE OP A NATION? (edit.)
Theatre
TWJI.IGHT BAR •
~RTHUR KOESTLER
~UTCHINSON OF LONDON
HUTCHINSON & CO. (Publishers) LTD
1.78-202 Great Portland Streer. London~ W-1.
First
*
published 1964
71iis book has been set in Bembo type face. II. ha«
been printed ln CreM Bri&ain b}' The A11.:hor Press.
Lzd .• in Tip:tree. Esse;c. on A.luiqlU! Wove pRpn.
•
CONTENTS
*
Foreword by Professor Sir Cyril Burt 13
Author's Preface 21
BOOK ONE
*
PART ONE
THE JESTER
PART TWO
THE SAGE
PART THREE
THE A,RTIST
A. THE PARTICIPATORY EMOTIONS
XII THE LOGIC OF THE MOIST EYE 27r
Laughter and Weeping-Why do we Weep?-Raptness
-Mouming-Relief-Pity-Self-Pity-Siimmary
XIII PAR TNESS AND WHOLENESS 285
Stepchildren of Psychology-The Conceptof Hierarchy
XIV ON ISLANDS AND WATERWAYS 292
B. VERBAL CREATION
XV ILLUSION 3or
The Power of fllusion-The Value of Illusion-The
Dynamicsof Illusion-Escape and Catharsis-Identification
and Magic-The Dawn of Literature
XVI RHYTHM AND RHYME 311
Pulsation-Measure and Meaning-Repetition and Affinity
-Compulsive Punning-Coaxing the Unconscious
XVII IMAGE
The Hidden Analogy-Emotive Potentials-The Picture- 320
strip-On Law and Order-On Truth and Beauty
XVIII INFOLDING 333
Originality and Emphasis-Economy-The Last Veil-
Summary
XIX CHARACTER AND PLOT 34.5
Identification-Phantoms and Images-Conflict-Integra-
tions and Confrontations-Archetypes-Catalogi1ing
P/04-
Puppets and Strings
XX THE BELLY OF THE WHALE 358
The Night Journey-The Guilt ofJonah-The Root and
tlie Flower-The Tightrope
IO CONTJ!NTS
c. VISUAL CREATION
XXI MOTIF AND MEDIUM 366
Looking at Nat11re-Pigment and Meaning-The Two En-
vironments-Visual I1iferences-Codes of Perception-Con-
vention and Creation
BOOK TWO
Introduction * 413
I PRENATAL SKILLS 415
Structure and Function-The Cell-Matrix-Nucleus and
Cytoplasm-R7uiative and Mosaic Development=-
Organizers an Inducers-Summary
APPENDIX I
ON LOADSTONES AND AMBER 661
APPENDIX II
SOME FEATURES OF GENIUS 674
I. THB S.ENSB OP WOND.ER 674
Aristotle on Motivation-The Leaders of the Revolution-
-Newton, Monster and Saint-The Mysticism of Franklin
-The Fundamentalism of Faraday-The Metaphysics of
Maxwell-s-The Atheism of Darwin-The Faith of Pasteur
2. INNOCBNCB AND BXPBll.IBNCB 703
Precociousness-Scepticism and Credulity-.Al:Jstraction
and Practicality-Multiple Potentials
References 709
Works Mentioned in this Book 7I7
Acknowledgements 729
Index 73I
I
FOREWORD
BY PROFESSOR SIR CYRIL BURT
I
I
AUTHOR'S PREFACE
I
I
BOOK ONE
THE ART OF DISCOVERY
AND THE DISCOVERIES OF ART
PART ONE
THE JESTER
I
•
I
THE LOGIC OF LAUGHTER
The Triptych
But these do not concern us yet. The point to retain is the con-
tinuity of the scale leading from the faint smile to Homeric laughter,
confirmed by laboratory experiments. Electrical stimulation of the
zygomatic major, the main lifting muscle of the upper lip, with currents
of varying intensity, produces expressions ranging from smile to
broad grin to the facial contortions typical of loud laughter. 2 Other
researchers made films of tickled babies and of hysterics to whom
tickling was conveyed by suggestion. They again showed the reflex
swiftly increasing from the first faint facial contraction to paroxysms
of shaking and choking-as the quicksilver in a thermometer, dipped
into hot water, rapidly mounts to the red mark.
These gradations of intensity not only demonstrate the reflex
character of laughter but at the same time provide an explanation for
the rich variety of its forms-from Rabelaisian laughter at a spicy joke
to the rarefied smile of courtesy. But there are additional reasons to
account for this confusing variety. Reflexes do not operate in a vacuum;
they are to a greater or lesser extent interfered with by higher nervous
centres; thus civilized laughter is rarely quite spontaneous. Amusement
can be feigned or suppressed; to a faint involuntary response we may
add at will a discreet chuckle or a leonine roar; and habit-formation
soon crystallizes these reflex-plus-pretence amalgams into characteris-
tic properties of a person.
Furthermore, the same muscle contractions produce different
effects according to whether they expose a set of pearly teeth or a
toothless gap-producing a smile, a simper, or smirk. Mood also super-
imposes its own facial pattern-hence gay laughter, melancholy smile,
lascivious grin. Lastly, contrived laughter and smiling can be used as a
conventional signal-language to convey pleasure or embarrassment,
friendliness or derision. We are concerned, however, only with
spontaneous laughter as a specific response to the comic; regarding
which we can conclude with Dr. Johnson that 'men have been wise
in very different modes; but they have always laughed in the same
way'.
I have taken pains to show that laughter is, in the sense indicated above,
a-true reflex, because here a paradox arises which is the starting point
of our 'inquiry. Motor reflexes, usually exemplified in textbooks by
THE LOGIC OF LAUGHTER 3I
knee:jerk or pupillary contraction, are relatively simple, direct res-
ponses to equally simple stimuli which, under normal circumstances,
function autonomously, without requiring the intervention of higher
mental processes; by enabling the organism to counter disturbances of
a :frequently met type with standardized reactions, they represent
eminently practical arrangements in the service of survival. But what
is the survival value of the involuntary, simultaneous contraction of
fifteen facial muscles associated with certain noises which are often
irrepressible? Laughter is a reflex, but unique in that it serves no
apparent biological purpose; one might call it a luxury reflex. Its only
utilitarian function, as far as one can see, is to provide temporary
relief :from utilitarian pressures. On the evolutionary level where
laughter arises, an element of frivolity seems to creep into a humour-
1ess·iiniv"erse governed by-the laws of thermodynamics and the survival
of the fittest.
The paradox can be put in a dilferent way. It strikes us as a reasonable
arrangement that a sharp light shone into the eye makes the pupil
contract, or that a pin stuck into one's foot causes its instant with-
drawal-because both the 'stimulus' and the 'response' are on the same
physiological level. But that a complicated mental activity like the
reading of a page by Thurber should cause a specific motor response
on the reflex level is a lopsided phenomenon which has puzzled philoso-
phers since antiquity.
There are, ofcourse, other complex intellectual and emotional activi-
ties which also provoke bodily reactions-frowning, yawning, sweat-
ing, shivering, what have you. But the effects on the nervous system
of reading a Shakespeare sonnet, working on a mathematical problem,
or listening to Mozart are diffuse and .indefinable. There is no clear-
cut predictable response to tell me whether a picture in the art gallery
strikes another visitor as 'beautiful'; but there is a predictable facial
contraction which tells me whether a caricature strikes him as 'comic'.
Humour is the only domain of creative activity where a stimulus 012 a high
level of complexity produces a massive and sharply defined response on the
level of physiological reflexes. This paradox enables us to use the res-
ponse as an indicator for the presence of that elusive quality, the
comic, which we are seeking to define-as the tell-tale clicking of the
geiger-counter indicates the presence of radioactivity. And since the
comic is related to other, more exalted, forms of creativity, the back-
door approach promises to yield some positive results. We all know
that there is only one step from the sublime to the ridiculous; the more
32 TB:S ACT OF CREATION
surprising that Psychology has not considered the possible gains which
could result from the reversal. of that step.
Some of the stories that follow, including the first, I owe to my late
friend John von Neumann, who had all the makings of a humorist:
he was a mathematical genius and he came from Budapest.
FIGU:R.E 2
'l'B:13 ACT OP CREATION
more than one plane. The former may be called single-minded, the
latter a double-minded, transitory state of unstable equilibrium where
the balance of both emotion and thought is disturbed. The forms which
this creative instability takes in science and art will be discussed later;
fust we must test the validity of these generalizations in other :fields of
the comic.
At the time when John Wilkes was the hero of the poor and
lonely, an ill-wisher informed him gleefully: 'It seems that some of
your faithful supporters have turned their coats.' 'Impossible,'
Wilkes answered. 'Not one of them has a coat to tum.'
'.F._h_: !~Ples discussedso far all belo~_g_ ~~ the ~-ss _ ?f j?k<:5 and
anecdotes with a single point of culmination. The liiglier forms of
sustainedhumour, such as the satire or comic poem, do not rely on
a singleeffectbut on a seriesof minor explosionsor a continuous state
~of mild
....~ amusement.
.
Fig."3 is meant to indicate what happens when a
FIGURE 3
l'HE ACT OP CREATION
I must now try the reader's patience with a few pages (seven, to be
exact) of psychological speculation in order to introduce a pair of
related concepts which play a central role in this book and are indis-
pensable to all that follows. I have variously referred to the two planes
in Figs. 2 and 3 as 'frames of reference', 'associative contexts', 'types of
logic', 'codes of behaviour', and 'universes of discourse'. Henceforth I
shall use the expression 'matrices of thought' (and 'matrices of be-
haviour') as a unifying formula. I shall use the word 'matrix' to denote
any ability, habit, or skill, any pattern of ordered behaviour governed
by a 'code' of fixed rules. Let me illustrate this by a few examples on
different levels.
The common spider will suspend its web on three, four, and up to
twelve handy points of attachment, depending on the lie of the land,
but the radial threads will always intersect the laterals at equal angles,
according to a fixed code of rules built into the spider's nervous system;
and the centre of the web will always be at its centre of gravity. The
matrix-the web-building skill-is flexible: it can be adapted to en-
vironmental conditions; but the rules of the code must be observed
and set a limit to flexibility. The spider's choice of suitable points of
attachment for the web are a matter of strategy, depending on the en-
vironment, but the form of the completed web will always be poly-
gonal, determined by the code. The exercise of a skill is always under
the dual control (a) of a fixed code of rules (which may be innate or ac-
quired by learning) and (b) of a flexible strategy, guided by environ-
mental pointers-the 'lie of the land'.
As the next example let me take, for the sake of contrast, a matrix
on the lofty level of verbal thought. There is a parlour game where
each contestant must write down on a piece of paper the names of all
towns he can think of starting with a given letter-say, the letter 'L'.
Here the code of the matrix is defined by the rule of the game; and the
members of the matrix are the names of all towns beginning with 'L'
which the participant in question has ever learned, regard:less whether
at the moment he remembers them or not. The task before him is to
£sh these names out of his memory. There are various strategies for
THE LOGIC OF LAUGHTER 39
doing this. One person will imagine a geographicalmap, and then scan
this imaginary map for towns with 'L', proceedingin a given direction
-say west to east. Another person will repeat sub-vocallythe syllables
Li, La, Lo, as if striking a tuning fork, hoping that his memory circuits
(Lincoln,Lisbon, etc.) will start to 'vibrate' in response. His strategy
determineswhich member of the matrix will be called on to perform,
and in which order. In the spider's case the 'members' of the matrix
were the various sub-skillswhich enter into the web-building skill:
the operations of secreting the thread, attaching its ends,judging the
angles. Again, the order and manner in which these enter into action
is determined by strategy, subject to the 'rules of the game' laid down
by the web-building code.
_All coherent thinking is equivalentto playing a game accordingto a
set oI rules. It may, of course,happen that in the course of the parlour
game f have arrived via Lagos in Lisbon, and feel suddenly tempted to
dwell on the pleasant memories of an evening spent at the night-club
La Cucarachain that town. But that would be 'not playing the game',
and I must regretfully proceed to Leeds.Drifting from one matrix to
another characterizesthe dream and related states; in the routines of
disciplinedthinking only one matrix.is active at a time.
In word-associationtests the code consistsof a single command, for
instance 'name opposites'.The subject is then given a stimulusword-
say, 'large'-and out pops the answer: 'small'. If the code had been
'synonyms', the responsewould have been 'big' or 'tall', etc. Associa-
tion tests are artificialsimplificationsof the thinking process;in actual
reasoning the codes consist of more or less complex sets of rules and
sub-rules. In mathematicalthinking, for instance,there is a great array
of specialcodes, which govern different types of operations; some of
these are hierarchically ordered, e.g. addition-multiplication-ex-
ponential function. Yet the rules of these very complex games can
be represented in 'coded' symbols: x + y, or x.y or x7 or xJy, the
sight of which will 'trigger off' the appropriate operation-as
reading a line in a piano score will trigger off a whole series of very
complicated finger-movements. Mental skills such as arithmetical
operations, motor skills such as piano-playing or touch-typing, tend
to become with practice more or less automatized, pre-set routines,
which are triggered off by 'coded signals' in the nervous system-
as the trainer's whistle puts a performing animal through its paces.
This is perhapsthe placeto explainwhy I have chosenthe ambiguous
word 'code' for a key-concept in the present theory. The reason is
TBB .A.CT OF CREATION
precisely its nice ambiguity. It signifies on the one hand a set of rules
which must be obeyed-like the Highway Code or Penal Code; and
it indicates at the same time that it operates in the nervous system
through 'coded signals'-like the Morse alphabet-which transmit
orders in a kind of compressed 'secret language'. We know that not
only th~ nervous system but all controls in the organism operate in
this fashion (starting with the fertilized egg, whose 'genetic code'
contains the blue-print of the future individual. But that blue-print in
the cell nucleus does not show the microscopic image of a little man;
it is 'coded' in a kind of four-letter alphabet, where each letter is
represented by a different type of chemical molecule in a long chain;
see Book Two, I).*
Let us return to reasoning skills. Mathematical reasoning is governed
by specific rules of the game-multiplication, differentiation, integra-
tion, etc. Verbal reasoning, too, is subject to a variety of specific codes:
we can discuss Napoleon's defeat at Waterloo 'in terms of' (a) historic
significance, (b) military strategy, (c) the condition of his liver, (d) the
constellation of the planets. We can call these 'frames of reference' or
'universes of discourse' or 'associative contexts'-expressions which I
shall frequently use to avoid monotonous repetitions of the word
'matrix'. The jokes in the previous section can all be described as
universes of discourse colliding, frames getting entangled, or contexts
getting confused. But we must remember that each of these ex-
pressions refers to specific patterns of activity which, though flexible,
are governed by sets of fixed rules.
A chess player looking at an empty board with a single bishop on it
does not see the board as a uniform mosaic of black and white squares,
but as a kind of magnetic field with lines of force indicating the bishops'
possible moves: the board has become patterned, as in Fig. 4 a; Fig. 4 b
shows the pattern of the rook.
When one thinks of'matrices' and 'codes' it is sometimes helpful to
bear these figures in mind. The matrix is the pattern before you, rep-
resenting the ensemble of permissible moves. The cede which governs
the matrix can be put into simple mathematical equations which con-
tain the essence of the pattem in a compressed, 'coded' form; or it can
be expressed by the word 'diagonals'. The code is the fixed, invariable
factor in a skill or habit; the matrix its variable aspect. The two words
do not refer to different entities, they refer to different aspects of the
same activity. When you sit in front of the chessboard your code is
the rule of the game determining which moves are permitted, your
THE ACT OF CREATION
matrix is the total of possible choices before you. Lastly, the choice of
the actual move among the variety of permissible moves is a matter
of strategy, guided by the lie of the land-the 'environment' of other
chessmen on the board. We have seen that comic effects are produced
by the sudden clash of incompatible matrices: to the experienced chess
player a rook moving bishopwise is decidedly 'funny'.
Consider a pianist playing a set-piece which he has learned by heart.
He has incomparably more scope for 'strategy' (tempo, rhythm,
phrasing) than the spider spinning its web. A musician transposing a
tune into a different key, or improvising variations of it, enjoys even
greater freedom; but he too is still bound by the codes of the diatonic
or chromatic scale. Matrices vary in flexibility from reflexes and more
or less automatized routines which allow but a few strategic choices,
to skills of almost unlimited variety; but all coherent thinking and
behaviour is subject to some specifiable code of rules to which its
character of coherence is due-even though the code functions partly
or entirely on unconscious levels of the mind, as it generally does. A
bar-pianist can perform in his sleep or while conversing with the
barmaid; he has handed over control to the automatic pilot, as it were.
Hidden Persuaders
Everybody can ride a bicycle, but nobody knows how it is done. Not
even engineers and bicycle manufacturers know the formula for the
correct method of counteracting the tendency to fall by turning the
handlebars so that 'for a given angle of unbalance the curvature of
each winding is inversely proportional to the square of the speed at
which the cyclist is proceeding'. 6 The cyclist obeys a code of rules
which is specifiable, but which he cannot specify; he could write on
his number-plate Pascal's motto: 'Le cceut a ses raisons que la raison 11e
connalt point.' Or, to put it in a more abstract way:
The controls of a skilled activity generally function below the level
of consciousness on which that activity takes place. The code is a
hidden persuader.
This applies not only to our visceral activities and muscular skills,
but also to the skill of perceiving the world around us in a coherent
and 'meaningful manner. Hold your left hand six inches, the other
twelve inches, away from your eyes; they will look about the same
size, although the retinal image of the left is twice the size of the right.
THE LOGIC -OF LAUGHTER 43
Trace the contours of your face with a soapy finger on the bathroom
mirror (it is easily done by closing one eye). There is a shock waiting:
the image which looked life-size has shrunk to half-size, like a head-
hunter's trophy. A person walking away does not seem to become a
dwarf-as he should; a black glove looks just as black m the sunlight
as in shadow-though it should not; when a coin is held before the eyes
in a tilted position its retinal projection will be a more or less flattened
ellipse; yet we see it as a circle, because we know it to be a circle; and it
takes some effort to see it actually as a squashed oval shape. Seemg is
believing, as the saying goes, but the reverse is also true: knowing is
seeing. 'Even the most elementary perceptions', wrote Bartlett, 7 'have
the character of inferential constructions.' But the inferential process,
which controls perception, again works unconsciously. Seeing is a
skill, part innate, part acquired in early infancy.* The selective codes
in this case operate on the input, not on the output. The stimuli im-
pinging on the senses provide only the raw material of our conscious
expenence-the 'booming, buzzing confusion' of William James;
before reaching awareness the mput is filtered, processed, distorted,
interpreted, and reorganized in a series of relay-stations at various levels
of the nervous system; but the processing itself is not experienced by
the person, and the rules of the game according to which the controls
work are unknown to him. '
The examples I mentioned refer to the so-called 'visual constancies'
which enable us to recognize that the size, brightness, shape of objects
remain the same even though their retinal image changes all the time;
and to 'make sense' out of our sensations. They are shared by all people
with normal vision, and provide the basic structure on which more
personal 'frames of perception' can be built. An apple looks different to
Picasso and to the greengrocer because their visual matrices are different.
_ Let _me .rerurn once more to verbal thinking. When a person dis-
~e-~t.!~.Y, the problem of capital punishment he may do so 'in terms
.9f~social utility .or religious morality or psychopathology. Each of
~,~(?S~ universes of discourse is governed by a complex set of rules, some
~f }.Yhich operate on conscious, others on unconscious levels. The latter
are axiomatic beliefs and prejudices which are taken for granted and
implied in the code. Further implied, hidden in the space between the
words, are the rules of grammar and syntax. These have mostly been
learned not from textbooks but 'by ear', as a young gypsy learns to
fiddle without knowing musical notation. Thus when one is engaged
in ordinary conversation, not only do the codes of grammar and
THE ACT OF CREATION
To p. 44. The dual concepts of matrices and codes were designed with one
eye on psychology, the other on physiology. Their theoretical implications in
this wider context are discussed in Book Two.
The reader versed in experimental psychology will have been reminded by
now of such old friends from the Wurzburg School as Aufgabe, Einstellung,
Bewusstseinslage; and of their Anglo-Saxon relatives: 'determining tendency',
'expectancy', 'task', 'schema' and 'set'. He will probably also remember that
J.J. Gibson in a famous article (quoted by Humphrey, 1951, p. 105) listed some
forty different meanings in which the word 'set' was used. I hope to show that
'matrices' and 'codes' are concepts at the same time more precise, and of more
general validity, than Aufgaben or 'sets'.
50
•
II
LAUGHTER AND EMOTION
Among the theories of laughter that have been proposed since the
days of Aristotle, the 'theory of degradation' appears as the most
persistent. For Aristotlehimselflaughter was closelyrelated to ugliness
and debasement;for Cicero 'the province of the ridiculous... lies in
a certain basenessand deformity'; for Descartes laughter is a mani
festation ofjoy 'mixed with surpriseor hate or sometimeswith both';
in Francis Bacon's list of laughable objects, the first place is taken by
'deformity'. The essenceof the 'theory of degradation' is defined in
Hobbes's Leviathan:
that aggression and self-defence, rage and fear. hostility and appre-
hension, are as pairs of twins in their psychology and physiology. One
of the typical situations in which laughter occurs is the moment of the
sudden cessation of danger, real or imaginary; and rarely is the character
of laughter as a discharge-mechanism for redundant tensions more
strikingly manifested than in the sudden change of expression on the
small child's face from anxious apprehension to the happy laugh of
relief.
Whatever the composition of the emotional charge which a narra-
tive carries, it will produce a comic effect only if an aggressive-defensive
tendency, however sublimated, is present in it. You may be deeply
moved by a person's predicament, and yet unable to suppress a smile
at its ludicrous aspect; and the impression of the 'ludicrousness' of
another person's behaviour always implies an assertion-conscious
or unconscious-of your own superiority; you smile at his ex-
pense.
The emotions which dominate on the opposite side of the triptych
do not concern us as yet; but I must briefly mention them for the sake
of contrast. Listening to Mozart, watching a great actor's performance,
being in love or some other state of grace, may cause a welling up of
happy emotions which moisten the eye or overflow in tears. Com-
passion and bereavement may have the same physical effect. The
emotions of this class, whether joyous or sad, include sympathy,
identification, pity, admiration, awe, and wonder. The common
denominator of these heterogeneous emotions is a feeling of participa-
tion, identification, or bdonging;in other words, the self is experienced
as being a part of a larger whole, a higher unity-which may be Nature,
God, Mankind, Universal Order, or the Anima Mundi; it may be an
abstract idea, or a human bond with persons living, dead, or imagined.
I propose to call the common element in these emotions the partici-
patory or self-transcending tendencies. This is not meant in a mystical
sense (though mysticism certainly belongs to this class of emotion); the
term is merely intended to convey that in these emotional states the
need is felt to behave as a part of some real or imaginary entity which
transcends, as it were, the boundaries of the individual self; whereas
when governed by the self-assertive class of emotions the ego is ex-
perienced as a sdf-contained whole and the ultimate value.
As a rule our emotions are complex mixtures in which both ten-
dencies participate. Thus the emotion called 'love' -whether sexual
or matem.al-usually contains an aggressive or possessive, self-asserting
LAUGHTER AND EMOTION SS
component, and an identificatory or self-transcendingcomponent. If
emotions were representedby differentcolours, then the two opposite
tendencieswould appear as brightness values (black-white mixtures)
superimposedon them.
The subjectwill be discussedin more detail later (ChaptersXI-XV);
readers irritated by these repeated anticipatory excursions may find
some excuse for them in the considerationthat the painful vivisection
of the comic, in which they are asked to participate, is not an end in
itself, but a means to uncover the pattern which unites the apparently
so heterogeneouscreative activitiesin humour, art, and discovery.
NOTES
Top. 56. Criticizing a paper read by a neurologist to a learned society, he
remarked: 'The author spoke of emotions in very general terms.... There are
featureswhich he mentioned which I could recognizeas characteristicof major
emotions, as anger and rage; but after all, love is an emotion.... I think that
when we discuss emotion we ought to specify the sorts of emotion we have in
mind' {Cannon,19.29).
To p. 61. The article in which this list appeared is characteristicof the
behaviouristapproach; it ennumerated three 'basic principles' of laughter: (a)
'as an expressionofjoy', (b) 'laughter makesfor group cohesionthrough homo-
geneity of feeling within the group', (c) 'laughing can be used as a weapon in
competitivesituations'. The word 'humour' was not mentioned in the article;
laughing at 1okes,antics, etc.', was mentioned only in passing,as obviouslynot
a phenomenon worthy of the psychologists'attention.
Top. 63. Some domesticated animals-dogs, chimpanzees-seem to be
capableof a humorous expressionand to engagein teasingactivities.These may
be regardedas evolutionaryforerunnersof laughter,
•
III
VARIETIES OF HUMOUR
Our spacemen, Mrs. Lamport fears, are 'heading for the ''lunar
bin".' The ageing libertine, she tells us, 'feels his old Krafft Ebbing'.
The Reverend Spooner had a great affection, or so he said, for 'our
queer old dean'.
One swallow, the proverb says, does not make a sum.mer-nor
quench the thirst. Elijah's ravens, according to Milton, were 'though
ravenous taught to abstain from what they brought'. Not so Napoleon,
who, shortly after his coronation, confiscated the estates of the house
of Orleans, which caused a contemporary to remark: 'C' est le premier
vol de I' aigle.' Equally to the point was Mr. Paul Jenkin' s discovery re-
garding the pros and cons of Britain's entry into the Common Market:
'The Cons were pro, while Lab has tumed con.'
The pun is the bisociation of a single phonetic form with two
64,
VARIETIES OP HUMOUR
Impersonation
The various categories of the comic shade into each other: Disney's
animals acting like humans could as well be classifiedunder the
68 TBB ACT OP CREATION
The Child-Adult
the whereabouts of her departed husband's soul. She replied: 'Oh well,
I suppose he is enjoying eternal bliss, but I wish you wouldn't talk
about such unpleasant subjects.' I would call this an illustration of the
peaceful coexistence of the tragic and trivial planes in our humble
minds. Equally convincing is this statement made by a schoolboy to
his mathematics master:
'Infinity is where things happen which don't.'2
The Miefit
Both Cicero and Francis Bacon gave deformity a high place on their
lists of causes for laughter. The princes of the Renaissance collected
midgets, hunchbacks, monsters, and Blackamoors for their merriment.
We have become too civilized for that kind of thing, but children still
jeer and laugh at people with a limp or a stammer, at foreigners with a
funny pronunciation, at people oddly dressed-at any form of appear-
ance or behaviour which deviates from the familiar norm. The more
backwoodish a social group, juvenile or adult, the stricter its concep-
tion of the normal, and the readier it will ridicule any departure from it.
Consider for a moment the curious fact that to a civilized person a
stutterer causes sympathetic embarrassment, whereas a person of
normal speech giving an imitation of stuttering makes us laugh. So
does the youngster in love who stutters only under the effect of a
momentary surge of emotion. Again, a person with a foreign accent
is accepted with tolerance, but the imitation of a foreign accent is
comic. The explanation is that we know the imitator's stutter or mis-
prononunciation to be mere pretence; this makes sympathy bpth un
necessary and impossible, and enables us to be childishly cruel with a
clear conscience. We have met the same phenomenon (page 71) in
our attitude towards the bodily deformities imputed by the caricaturist
to his victim.
The tolerant acceptance of physical or mental malformations in
our fellow creatures, though of relatively recent origin, has become
deeply engrained in Western society; we are no longer aware of the
VARIETIES OF HUMOUR 75
fact that it requires a certain imagination and a good deal of empathy
to recognize in a dwarf, or a 'thick-lipped Blackamoor', a human
being which, though different in appearance, exists and feels as one-
self does. In the small child this kind of projective mechanism is
absent or rudimentary. Piaget, among others, has strikingly shown
how late the child accords to its fellow beings a conscious ego like its
own. The more a person deviates from the familiar norm of the
child's surroundings, the more difficult it is for the child to project into
him life and feelings, to grant him the faculty of having experiences
like his own. The same applies to the attitudes shown by tribal or
parochial societies to foreigners, slaves, members of the 'lower classes'
(almost inevitably treated as comic figures in literature up to and in
cluding Dickens); as well as to criminals, the mentally disordered and
physically deformed. The creature who does not 'belong' to the
tribe, clan, caste, or parish is not really human; he only aspires or
pretends to be 'like us'. To civilized man, a dwarf is comic only if he
struts about pretending to be tall, which is he not; in the primitive' s
eye the dwarf is comic because he pretends to be human, which he is
not. The Greek word 'barbarian' means both foreigner and stutterer
(bar-bar-ous); the uncouth, repetitive, barking sounds he uttered
were a grotesque imitation of true human speech. Bodily and func-
tional deformities are laughable to the uncouth mind for the same
reasons as impersonation and caricature.
However, an additional factor enters into the comic effect of some dis-
orders of behaviour such as stuttering, mispronunciation, misspelling:
one might call it the bisociation of structure and function, or of part
and whole. The stammering barbarian was a comic figure to the Greeks
for reasons just mentioned; but the comedian's stage-stutter is funny in
a different way. When he struggles with a consonant, trying to take
the same hurdle again and again, eyes bulging and face convulsed, we
become suddenly aware of the complicated motions of lips and tongue
required to produce the sound 'M'; our attention becomes focussed
on these physiological details tom from their functional context and
placed under a magnifying glass, as it were. Much the same happens
when the gramophone needle gets stuck in a groove, and the soprano's
voice keeps repeating the same word on the same quaver. The part has
THE ACT OP CREATION
Displacement
The broken heart has become such a cliche that its physicalimplica-
tions-splitting apart and creating a gap-are never thought of. Wilde
shifts our attention to that forgotten physical image; he lets salvation
enter through the aching gap, like a thief in the night. When the White
THE ACT OF CREATION
Coincidence
Nonsense
One type of comic verse lives on the bisociation of exalted form with
trivial content. Certain metric forms, such as hexameter and Alexan-
drine, arouse expectations of pathos, of the heroic and exalted; the
pouring ofhomdy, trivial contents into these epic moulds-'beautiful
soup, so rich and green' -creates a comic effect of the same type as the
parody. The rolling dactyls of the first line of the limerick, carrying,
instead of Hector and Achilles, a young lady from Stockton as their
passenger, make her already appear ridiculous, regardless of the calami-
ties which are sure to befall her. In this atmosphere of malicious ex-
pectation whatever witticism the text has to o.ffer will have a much
enhanced effect.
VARIETIES OF HUMOUR 79
Instead of an epic mould, a soft, lyrical one will equally do:
Tickling
A child fingers the pepper-pot, waves pepper into its nose, and
sneezes violently. Touch it under the arm-pits, or finger its waist,
and it wriggles vigorously. It sneezes to dislodge the pepper from its
nose, and its wriggle suggests a sneeze to relieve its whole body. The
violent squirm of the tickled child so obviously tries to avoid the
tickling hand that, when the truth is perceived, it is difficult to
understand how tickling and laughter could ever be identified or
confused.3
The Clown
I have discussed the logic of humour and its emotive dynamics, and
have tried to indicate how to analyse a joke. But nothing has been said
so far about the criteria which decide whether it is a good, bad, or
indifferent joke. These are, of course, partly a matter of personal taste,
partly dependent on the technique of the humorist; only the second is
our concern..
There are, I shall suggest, three main criteria of comic technique:
originality, emphasis, and economy. In the light of the previous
chapters we shall expect them to play also a significant part in the
techniques of scientific theorizing and artistic creation.
FIGURE 5
IV
FROM HUMOUR TO DISCOVERY
Explosion and Catharsis
FIGURB 6
on the triptych are meant to refer to these two modes of the discharge
PROM HUMOUR TO DISCOVERY
Summary
I
I
PART TWO
THE SAGE
I
•
v
MOMENTS OF TRUTH
The Chimpanzee and the Stick
the stick much sooner, and uses it with more skill; and at a third
repetition, the stick is used immediately, as on all subsequent
occasions.1
It is obvious that Nueva was not led to her discovery by any process
of conditioning, or trial and error. Her behaviour from the moment
when her eyes fell on the stick was, in Kohler's words, 'unwaveringly
purposeful': she seized the stick, carried it without hesitation to the bars,
stretched it out of the cage, and placed it behind the banana-a
smooth, integrated sequence of actions, quite different from the erratic,
hit-and-miss behaviour of rats trying to find their way through a maze,
or cats trying to get out of a puzzle-box. It was an original, self-taught
accomplishment, which had no precedent in the chimpanzee's past. The
process which led to her discovery can be described as a synthesis of two
previously unconnected skills, acquired in earlier life. In the first place,
Nueva had learned to get at bananas outside her cage by squeezing an
arm or foot through the bars; the ensemble of variations of this simple
skill constitutes matrix number one. She had also acquired the habit-
m.atrix number two-of scraping the earth with a stick and of pushing
objects about with it. But in this playful activity the stick was never
used for any utilitarian purpose; to throw, push, or roll things about is
a habit common to a variety of young animals. Nueva's discovery
consisted in applying this playful habit as an auxiliary matrix to get at
the banana. The moment of truth occurred when Nueva's glance fell
on the stick while her attention was set on the banana. At that moment
the two previously separate matrices fused into one, and the 'stick to
play with' became a 'rake to reach with' -an implement for obtaining
otherwise unobtainable objects.
Like many other discoveries, Nueva' s seems a simple and obvious
one-but only after the fact. A dog, for instance, will carry a stick
between his teeth, but he will never learn to use it as a rake. Moreover,
chimpanzees are not the only species which finds it difficult to apply a
'playful' technique to a utilitarian purpose with which it had not been
connected in previous experience; a number of discoveries in the
history of human science consisted in just that. Galileo astonished the
world when he tu.med the telescopic toys, invented by Dutch opticians,
to astronomic use; the invention of the steam engine as a mechanical
toy by Hero of Alexandria in the second century s,c, had to wait two
thousand years before it was put to practical use; the geometry of conic
sections which Apollonius of Perga had studied in the fourth century
MOMENTS OF TRUTH 103
B.C. just for the fun of it, gave Kepler, again two thousand years later,
his elliptical orbits of the planets; the passion for dice of the Chevalier
de Mere,made him approach Pascal for advice on a safe gambling
system, and thus was the theory of probability born, that indispensable
tool of modem physics and biology, not to mention the insurance
business. 'It is remarkable', wrote Laplace, 'that a science which began
with considerations of play has risen to the most important objects of
human knowledge.' Thus at the very start of our inquiry we hit on a
pattern-the discovery that a playful or l' art pour I' art technique
provides an unexpected clue to problems in a quite different field-
which is one of the leitmotifs in the history of science.
Nueva's discovery was the use of tools; the next one to be described
is the making of tools. Its hero is Sultan, the genius among Kohler's
chimpanzees:
eagerly picked off one leaf after the other, so that only the long, bare
stem was left . • . The pulling off of the leaves is both correct and
incorrect; incorrect because it does not make the stem any longer,
correct because it makes its length show up better and the stem thus
becomes optically more hke a stick .... There can be no doubt that
Koko did not pull off the leaves in play only; his look and his move-
ments prove distinctly that throughout the performance his attention
is wholly concentrated on the banana; he is merely concerned now
with preparing the implement. Play looks quite different; and I have
never seen a chimpanzee play while (like Koko in this case) he was
showing himself distinctly intent upon his ultimate purpose.'
Before the chimpanzee actually broke off the branch there must
have been a moment when he perceived it as a member of both matrices
at the same time-still a part of the tree but already a detached tool. Thus
one could say that Sultan had seen a visual pun: a single form (the
branch) attached to two different functions.
The act of discovery has a disruptive and a constructive aspect. It
must disrupt rigid patterns of mental organization to achieve the new .
synthesis. Sultan's habitual way of looking at the tree as a coherent, j
visual whole had to be shattered. Once he had discovered that branches ·
can be made into tools he never again forgot it, and we may assume
that a tree never again looked the same to him as before. He had lost
MOMENTS OP TRUTH IOS
the innocence of his vision, but from this loss he derived an immense
gain: the perception of'branches' and the manipulation of'tools' were
now combined into a single, sensory-motor skill; and when two
matrices have become integrated they cannot again be torn asunder.
This is why the discoveriesofyesterdayare the commonplacesof today,
and why yve always marvel h_?w st~p!d we were ~~t to see what pos1
(actum appears to be so obvious.
Archimedes
FIGURE 7
on the basin to the next as a result of the immersion of his body, and
it occurred to him in a flash that the volume of water displaced was
equal to the volume of the immersed parts of his own body-which
therefore could simply be measured by the pint. He had melted his
body down, as it were, without harming it, and he could do the same
with the crown.
Once more, as in the case of the chimpanzee, the matter is childishly
simple after the fact-but let us try to put ourselves in Archimedes's
place. He was in the habit of taking a daily bath, but the experiences
and ideas associated with it moved along habit-beaten tracks: the
sensations of hot and cold, of fatigue and relaxation, and a pretty slave-
girl to massage his limbs. Neither to Archimedes nor to anybody else
before him had it ever occurred to connect the sensuous and trivial
occupation of taking a hot bath with the scholarly pursuit of the
measurement of solids. No doubt he had observed many times that the
level of the water rose whenever he got into it; but this fact, and the
distance between the two levels, was totally irrelevant to him-until it
'suddenly became bisociated with his problem. At that instant he
realized that the amount of rise of the water-level was a simple measure
of the volume of bis own complicated body.
The discovery may now be schematized as follows (Figure 8):
M1is the same as in the preceding diagram, governed by the habitual
rules of the game, by means of which Archimedes originally tried to
solve the problem; M2 is the matrix of associations related to taking a
bath; ~ represents the actual train of thought which effects the
connection. The Link L may have been a verbal concept (for instance:
Io6
FIGURE 8
make or are made by history acquires a new twist in the more limited
field of the history of science. The twist is provided by the phenomenon
of multiple discoveries. Historical research into this curious subject is
of fairly recent origin; it came as a surprise when, in 1922, Ogburn and
Thomas published some hundred and fifty examples of discoveries and
inventions which were made independently by several persons; and,
more recently, Merton came to the seemingly paradoxical conclusion
that 'the pattern of independent multiple discoveries in science is .•.
the dominant pattern rather than a subsidiary one'. 5 He quotes as an
example Lord Kelvin, whose published papers contain 'at least thirty-
two discoveries of his own which he subsequently found had also been
made by others'. The 'others' include some men of genius such as
Cavendish and Helmholtz, but also some lesser lights.
The endless priority disputes which have poisoned the supposedly
serene atmosphere of scientific research throughout the ages, and the
unseemly haste of many scientists to establish priority by rushing into
print-or, at least, depositing manuscripts in sealed envelopes with
some learned society-point in the same direction. Some-among them
Galileo and Hooke-even went to the length of publishing half-
completed discoveries in the form of anagrams, to ensure priority
without letting rivals in on the idea. Kohler's chimpanzees were of a
more generous disposition.
Thus one should not underestimate ripeness as a factor facilitating
discoveries which, as the saying goes, are 'in the air'-meaning, that
the various components which will go into the new synthesis are all
lying around and only waiting for the trigger-action of chance, or the
catalysing action of an exceptional brain, to be assembled and welded
together. If one opponunity is missed, another will occur.
But, on the other hand, although the infinitesimal calculus was
developed independently by Leibniz and by Newton, and a long line
of precursors had paved the way for it, it still required a Newton or a
Leibniz to accomplish the feat; and the greatness of this accomplish-
ment is hardly diminished by the fact that two among millions, instead
of one among millions, had the exceptional genius to do it. We are
concerned with the question how they did it-the nature of creative
originality-and not with the undeniable, but trivial consideration that
if they had not lived somebody else would have done it some time; for
that leaves the same question to be answered, to wit, how that someone
else did it. Ishall not presume to guess whether outstanding individuals
such as Plato and Aristotle, Jesus of Nazareth and Paul of Tarsus,
MOMENTS OF TRUTH III
I shall briefly describe, for the sake of contrast, two celebrated discov-
eries of entirely different kinds: the first apparently due to conscious,
logical reasoning aided by chance; the second a classic case of the
intervention of the unconscious.
Eighteen hundred and seventy-nine was the birth-year of immun-
ology-the prevention of infectious diseases by inoculation. By that
time Louis Pasteur had already shown that cattle fever, rabies, silkworm
disease, and various other affiictions were caused by micro-organisms,
and had firmly established the germ theory of disease. In the spring of
1879-he was fifty-seven at that time-Pasteur was studying chicken
cholera. He had prepared cultures of the bacillus, but for some reason
this work was interrupted, and the cultures remained during the whole
summer unattended in the laboratory. In the early autumn, however,
he resumed his experiments. He injected a number of chickens with the
bacillus, but unexpectedly they became only slightly ill and recovered.
He concluded that the old cultures had been spoilt, and obtained a new
culture of virulent bacilli from chickens afflicted by a current outbreak
of cholera. He also bought a new batch of chickens from the market
and injected both lots, the old and the new, with the fresh culture. The
newly bought chicks all died in due time, but, to his great surprise the
old chicks, who had been injected once already with the ineffective
culture, all survived. An eye-witness in the lab described the scene
which took place when Pasteur was informed of this curious develop-
ment. He 'remained silent for a minute, then exclaimed as if he had
seen a vision: "Don't you see that these animals have been vaccinated!" '
Now I must explain that the word 'vaccination' was at that time
already a century old. It is derived from vaaa, cow. Some time in the
176os a young medical student, Edward Jenner, was consulted by a
Gloucester dairymaid who felt out of sorts. Jenner thought that she
might be suffering from smallpox, but she promptly replied: 'I cannot
take the smallpox because I have had the cow-pox.' After nearly
twenty years of struggle against the scepticism and indifference of the
medical profession,Jenner succeeded in proving the popular belief that
people who had once caught the cow-pox were immune against
smallpox. Thus originated 'vaccination' -the preventive inoculation of
human beings against the dreaded and murderous disease with material
taken from the skin sores of afflicted cattle. Although Jenner realized
that cow-pox and smallpox were essentially the same disease, which
II2
MOMENTS OF TRUTH 113
became somehow modified by the organism which carried it, he did
not draw any general conclusions from his discovery. 'Vaccination'
soon spread to America and became a more or less general practice in
a number of other countries, yet it remained limited to smallpox, and
the word itself retained its exclusively bovine connotations.
The vision which Pasteur had seen at that historic moment was, once
again, the discovery of a hidden analogy: the surviving chicles of the
:first batch were protected against cholera by their inoculation with the
'spoilt' culture as humans are protected against smallpox by inoculation
with pox bacilli in a modified, bovine form.
Now Pasteur was well acquainted with Jenner's work. To quote one
of his biographers, Dr. Dubos (himself an eminent biologist): 'Soon
after the beginning of his work on infectious diseases, Pasteur became
convinced that something similar to "vaccination" was the best ap-
proach to their control. It was this conviction that made him per-
ceive immediately the meaning of the accidental experiment with
chickens.'
In other words, he was 'ripe' for his discovery, and thus able to
pounce on the first favourable chance that offered itself As he himself
said:~foµune ~vours the prepared mind.' Put in this way, there seems
to be nothing very awe-inspiring in Pasteur's discovery. Yet for about
three-quarters of a century 'vaccination' had been a common practice
in Europe and America; why, then, did nobody before Pasteur hit on
the 'obvious' idea of extending vaccination from smallpox to other
diseases? Why did nobody before him put two and two together?
Because, to answer the question literally, the first 'two' and the second
'two' appertained to different frames of reference. The first was the
technique of vaccination; the second was the hitherto quite separate
and independent research into the world of micro-organisms: fowl-
parasites, silkworm-bacilli, yeasts fermenting in wine-barrels, invisible
viruses in the spittle of rabid dogs. Pasteur succeeded in combining
these two separate frames because he had an exceptional grasp of the
rules of both, and was thus prepared for the moment when chance
provided an appropriate link.
He knew-what Jenner knew not-that the active agent in Jenner's
'vaccine' was the microbe of the same disease against which the subject
was to be protected, but a microbe which in its bovine host had under-
gone some kind of 'attenuation'. And he further realized that the
cholera bacilli left to themselves in the test-tubes during the whole
summer had undergone the same kind of 'attenuation' or weakening,
Il4 THE ACT OF CREATION
as the pox bacilli in the cow's body. This led to the surprising, almost
poetic, conclusion, that life inside an abandoned glass tube can have
the same debilitating effect on a bug as life inside a cow. From here
on the implications of the Gloucestershire dairymaid's statement
became gloriously obvious: 'As attenuation of the bacillus had oc-
curred spontaneously in some of his cultures [just as it occurred
inside the cow], Pasteur became convinced that it should be possible
to produce vaccines at will in the laboratory. Instead of depending upon
the chance of naturally occurring immunizing agents, as cow-pox was
for smallpox, vaccination could then become a general technique
applicable to all infectious diseases.'9
One of the scourges of humanity had been eliminated-to be
replaced in due time by another. For the story has a sequel with an
ironic symbolism, which, though it does not strictly belong to the
subject, I cannot resist telling. The most famous and dramatic applica-
tion of Pasteur's discovery was his anti-rabies vaccine. It was tried for
the first time on a young Alsatian boy by name of Josef Meister, who
had been savagely bitten by a rabid dog on his hands, legs, and thighs.
Since the incubation period of rabies is a month or more, Pasteur hoped
to be able to immunize the boy against the deadly virus which was
already in his body. After twelve injections with rabies vaccine of
increasing strength the boy returned to his native village without
having suffered any ill effects from the bites. The end of the story is
told by Dubos: 'Josef Meister later became gatekeeper at the Pasteur
Institute in Paris. In 1940, fifty-five years after the accident that gave
him a lasting place in medical history, he committed suicide rather
than open Pasteur's burial crypt for the German invaders. •ea He was
evidently predestined to become a victim of one form of rabidness
or another.
For fifteen days I strove to prove that there could not be any
functions like those I have since called Fuchsian functions. I was
then very ignorant; every day I seated myself at my work table,
stayed an hour or two, tried a great number of combinations,and
reached no results. One evening, contrary to my custom, I drank
black coffeeand could not sleep. Ideas rose in crowds; I felt them
collide until pairs interlocked, so to speak, making a stable com-
bination. By the next morning I had establishedthe existenceof a
class of Fuchsian functions, those which come from the hypergeo-
metric series; I had only to write out the results,which took but a
few hours.
Then I wanted to representthesefunctions by the quotient of two
series;this idea was perfectly consciousand deliberate, the analogy
with elliptic functions guided me. I asked myself what properties
these series must have if they existed, and I succeededwithout diffi
culty in forming the series I have called theta-Fuchsian.
Just at this time I left Caen, where I was then living, to go on a
geologic excursion under the auspicesof the school of mines. The
changes of travel made me forget my mathematical work. Having
reached Coutances, we entered an omnibus to go some place or
other. At the moment when I put my foot on the step the idea came
to me, without anything in my former thoughts seeming to have
paved the way for it, that the transformationsI had used to define
the Fuchsian functions were identical with those of non-Euclidean
geometry. I did not verify the idea; I should not have had time, as,
upon taking my seat in the omnibus, I went on with a conversation
already commenced, but I felt a perfect certainty. On my return to
Caen, for conscience'sake Iverified the result at my leisure.
Then I turned my attention to the study of some arithmetical
questionsapparently without much success and without a suspicion
of any connectionwith my precedingresearches.Disgustedwith my
failure, I went to spend a few days at the seaside, and thought of
II6 THB ACT OF CREATION
something else. One morning, walking on the bluff, the idea came to
me, with just the same characteristicsof brevity, suddenness,and
immediate certainty, that the arithmetic transformationsof indeter-
minate ternary quadratic forms were identical with those of non-
Euclidean geometry.
Returned to Caen, I meditated on this result and deduced the
consequences.The exampleof quadratic forms showed me that there
were Fuchsiangroups other than those corresponding to the hyper-
geometric series; I saw that I could apply to them the theory of
theta-Fuchsian series and that consequently there existed Fuchsian
functions other than those from the hypergeometric series, the ones
I then knew. Naturally I set myselfto form all thesefunctions.I made
a systematicattack upon them and carried all the outworks, one after
another. There was one, however, that still held out, whose fall
would involve that of the whole place.But all my effortsonly served
at first the better to show me the difficulty, which indeed was
something. All this work was perfectly conscious.
Thereupon I left for Mont-Valerien, where I was to go through
my military service; so I was very differentlyoccupied. One day,
going along the street, the solution of the difficulty which had
stopped me suddenly appeared to me. I did not try to go deep into
it immediately, and only after my service did I again take up the
question. I had all the elements and had only to arrange them and
put them together. So I wrote out my final memoir at a singlestroke
and without difficulty.
Ishall limit myself to this single example; it is useless to multiply
them. In regard to my other researches I would have to say
analogoustirings ...
Most striking at first is this appearanceof sudden illumination, a
manifest sign of long, unconscious prior work. The role of this
unconscious work in mathematical invention appears to me
incontestable..•• 10
••. One phenomenon is certain and I can vouch for its absolute
certainty: the sudden and immediateappearanceof a solution at the
very moment of sudden awakening. On being very abruptly
MOMENTS OF TRUTH II7
awakened by an external noise, a solution long searched for appeared
to me at once without the slightest instant of reflection on my part-
the fact was remarkable enough to have struck me unforgettably-
and in a quite different direction from any of those which I had
previously tried to follow.
On April 27, 1802, he tells us, I gave a shout of joy ... It was seven
years ago I proposed to myself a problem which I have not been able
to solve directly, but for which I had found by chance a solution, and
knew that it was correct, without being able to prove it. The matter
often returned to my mind and Ihad sought twenty rimes unsuccess-
fully for this solution. For some days I had carried the idea about
with me continually. At last, I do not know how, Ifound it, together
with a large number of curious and new considerations concerning
the theory of probability. As I think there are very few math-
ematicians in France who could solve this problem in less time, I have
no doubt that its publication in a pamphlet of twenty pages is a good
method for obtaining a chair of mathematics in a college.19
At last two days ago I succeeded, not by dint of painful effort but
so to speak by the grace of God. As a sudden flash of light, the
enigma was solved. ... For my part I am unable to name the nature
of the thread which connected what I previously knew with that
which made my success possible. ls
The serpent biting its own tail gave Kekule the due to a discovery
which has been called 'the most brilliant piece of prediction to be
found in the whole range of organic chemistry' and which, in fact, is
one of the cornerstones of modem science. Put in a somewhat
simplifiedmanner, it consistedin the revolutionary proposal that the
molecules of certain important organic compounds are not open
structures but closed chains or 'rings' -like the snake swallowing its
tail.
Sitmmary
the old and is relevant in the new context; the discovery of hidden
analogies as a result of the former; the bringing into consciousness of
tacit axioms and habits of thought which were implied in the code and
taken for granted; the un-covering of what has always been there.
This leads to the paradox that the more original a discovery the more
obvious it seems afterwards. The creative act is not an act of creation
in the sense of the Old Testament. It does not create something out of
nothing; it uncovers, selects, re-shuffles, combines, synthesizes already
existing facts, ideas, faculties, skills. The more familiar the parts, the
more striking the new whole. Man's knowledge of the changes of the
tides and the phases of the moon is as old as his observation that apples
fall to earth in the ripeness of time. Yet the combination of these and
other equally familiar data in Newton's theory of gravity changed
mankind's outlook on the world.
'It is obvious', says Hadamard, 'that invention or discovery, be it in
mathematics or anywhere else, takes place by combining ideas. . . •
The Latin verb cogito for "to think" etymologically means "to shake
together". St. Augustine had already noticed that and also observed
that intelligo means "to select among".'
The 'ripeness' of a culture for a new synthesis is reflected in the
recurrent phenomenon of multiple discovery, and in the emergence
of similar forms of art, handicrafts, and social institutions in diverse
cultures. But when the situation is ripe for a given type of discovery
it still needs the intuitive power of an exceptional mind, and sometimes
a favourable .chance event, to bring it from potential into actual exist-
ence. On the other hand, some discoveries represent striking tours de
force by individuals who seem to be so far ahead of their time that their
contemporaries are unable to understand them.
Thus at one end of the scale we have discoveries which seem to be
due to more or less conscious, logical reasoning, and at the other end
sudden insights which seem to emerge spontaneously from the depth of
the unconscious. The same polarity oflogic and intuition will be found
to prevail in the methods and techniques of artistic creation. It is
summed up by two opposite pronouncements: Bernard Shaw's 'Ninety
per cent perspiration, ten per cent inspiration', on the one hand,
Picasso's 'I do not seek-Ifind' LJe ne cherche pas,je trouve), on the other.
I
•
VI
THREE ILLUSTRATIONS
B
fore proceeding further, let me return for a moment to the
basic, bisociative pattern of the creative synthesis: the sudden
interlocking of two previously unrelated skills, or matrices of
thought. I shall give three somewhat more detailed examples which
display this pattern from various angles: Gutenberg's invention of
printing with movable types; Kepler's synthesis of astronomy and
physics; Darwin's theory of evolution by natural selection.
Here, then, we have matrix or skill No. 1: the printing from wood-
blocks by means of rubbing.
In the letters which follow we see him desperately searching for a
simpler method to replace the laborious carving of letters in wood:
Every coin begins with a punch. The punch is a little rod of steel,
one end of which is engraved with the shape of one letter, several
letters, all the signs which are seen in relief on a coin. The punch is
moistened and driven into a piece of steel, which becomes the
THRBB ILLUSTRATIONS
I took part in the wine harvest. I watched the wine flowing, and
going back from the effect to the cause, I studied the power of this
press which nothing can resist ....
At this moment it occurs to him that the same, steady pressure might
be applied by a seal or coin-preferably oflead, which is easy to cast-
on paper, and that owing to the pressure, the lead would leave a trace
on the paper-Eureka!
One must strike, cast, make a form like the seal of your commun-
ity; a mould such as that used for casting your pewter cups; letters in
relief like those on your coins, and the punch for producing them
like your foot when it multiplies its print. There is the Bible!
'If I have been able to see farther than others,' said Newton, 'it was
because I stood on the shoulders of giants.' One of the giants was
Johannes Kepler (1471-1530) whose three laws of planetary motion
provided the foundation on which the Newtonian universe was built.
They were the first 'natural laws' in the modem sense: precise,
verifiable statements expressed in mathematical terms; at the same
time, they represent the first attempt at a synthesis of astronomy and
physics which, during the preceding two thousand years, had developed
on separate lines.
Astronomy before Kepler had been a purely descriptive geometry
of the skies. The motion of stars and planets had been represented by
the device of epicycles and eccentrics-an imaginary clockwork of
circles turning on circles turning on circles. Copernicus, for instance,
had used forty-eight wheels to represent the motion of the five known
planets around the sun. These wheels were purely fictitious, and meant
as such-they enabled astronomers to make more or less precise
predictions, but, above all, they satisfied the dogma that all heavenly
motion must be uniform and in perfect circles. Though the planets
moved neither uniformly nor in perfect circles, the imaginary cog-
wheels did, and thereby 'saved the appearances'.
Kepler's discoveries put an end to this state of affairs. He reconciled
astronomy with physics, and substituted for the fictitious clockwork a
universe of material bodies not unlike the earth, freely floating and
turning in space, moved by forces acting on them. His most important
book bears the provocative title: A New Astronomy Based 011 Causation
Or Physics ef the Sky (16o9). It contains the first and second of Kepler's
three laws. The first says that the planets move around the sun not in
circles but in elliptic orbits; the second says that a planet moves in its
orbit not at uniform speed but at a speed that varies according to its
THREE ILLUSTRATIONS 125
position, and is defined by a simple and beautiful law: the line connect-
ing planet and sun sweeps over equal areas in equal times. The
third law establishes an equally elegant mathematical correlation
between the length of a planet' s year and its mean distance from the
sun.
Kepler did not start his career as an astronomer, but as a student of
theology (at the Lutheran University ofThuebingen); yet already as a
student he was attracted by the Copernican idea of a sun-centred
universe. Now Canon Copernicus's book, On the Revolutions of the
Heavenly Spheres, had been published in the year of his death, 1543;
that is, fifty years before Kepler first heard of him; and during that half
century it had attracted very little attention. One of the reasons was its
supreme unreadability, which made it into an all-time worst-seller:
its first edition of a thousand copies was never sold out. Kepler was the
first Continental astronomer to embrace the Copernican theory. His
Mysterium Cosmographicum, published in 1597 (fifty-four years after
Copernicus's death), started the great controversy-Galileo entered the
scene fifteen years later.
The reason why the idea of a sun-centred universe appealed to Kepler
was repeatedly stated by himself: 'I often defended the opinions of
Copernicus in the disputations of the candidates and I composed a
careful disputation on the first motion which consists in the rotation of
the earth; then I was adding to this the motion of the earth around the
sun.for physical or, if you prefer, metaphysical reasons.'2 Ihave emphasized
the last words because they contain the leitmotif of Kepler's quest, and
because he used the same expression in various passages in his works.
Now what were those 'physical or, if you prefer, metaphysical
reasons' which made Kepler prefer to put the sun into the centre of the
universe instead of the earth?
Twenty-five years later, when he was over fifty, Kepler repeated his
credo: 'It is by no means permissible to treat this analogy as an empty
I.26 TBll ACT OF CREATION
The sun in the middle of the moving stars, himself at rest and yet the
source of motion, carries the image of God the Father and Creator,
He distributes his motive force through a medium which contains
the moving bodies, even as the Father creates through the Holy
Ghost.'
There exists only one moving soul in the centre of all the orbits;
that is the sun which drives the planetsthe more vigorously the closer
the planet is, but whose force is quasi-exhaustedwhen acting on the
outer planets becauseof the long distanceand the weakening of the
force which it entails.5
Tycho, was given the task of working out the orbit of Mars. He spent
six years on the task and covered nine thousand folio-sheets with
calculations in his small handwriting without getting anywhere. When
at last he believed he had succeeded he found to his dismay that certain
observed positions of Mars differed from those which his theory
demanded by magnitudes up to eight minutes arc. Eight minutes arc
is approximately one-quarter of the apparent diameter of the moon.
This was a catastrophe. Ptolemy, and even Copernicus, could afford
to neglect a difference of eight minutes, because their observations were
accurate only within a margin of ten minutes, anyway. 'But,' Kepler
wrote in the New Astronomy, 'but for us, who by divine kindness were
given an accurate observer such as Tycho Brahe, for us it is fitting that
we should acknowledge this divine gift and put it to use .... Henceforth
I shall lead the way towards that goal according to my ideas. For if I
had believed that we could ignore these eight minutes, I would have
patched up my hypothesis accordingly. But since it was not permissible
to ignore them., those eight minutes point the road to a complete
reformation of astronomy ..• ,'7
Thus a theory, built on years of labour and torment, was instantly
thrown away because of a discord of eight miserable minutes arc.
Instead of cursing those eight minutes as a stumbling block, he
transformed them into the cornerstone of a new science. For those
eight minutes arc had at last made him realize that the field of
astronomy in its traditional framework was well and truly blocked.
One of the recurrent frustrations and tragedies in the history of
thought is caused by the uncertainty whether it is possible to solve a
given problem by traditional methods previously applied to problems
which seem to be of the same nature. Who can say how many lives
were wasted and good minds destroyed in futile attempts to square the
circle, or to construct a perpetuum mobile? The proof that these problems
are insoluble was in each case an original discovery in itself (such as
Maxwell's second law of thermodynamics); and such proofs could only
be found by looking at the problem from a point of view outside its
traditional matrix. On the other hand, the mere knowledge that a
problem is soluble means that half the game is already won.
The episode of the eight minutes arc had convinced Kepler that his
problem-the orbit of Mars-was insoluble so long as he felt bound by
the traditional rules of sky-geometry. Implied in those rules was the
dogma of'uniform motion in perfect circles'. Uniform motion he had
already discarded before the crisis; now he felt that the even more
THREB ILLUSTRATIONS 129
The conclusion is quite simply that the planet's path is not a circle
-it curves inward on both sides and outward again at opposite ends.
Such a curve is called an oval. The orbit is not a circle but an oval
figure.8
This oval orbit was a wild, frightening new departure for him. To
be fed up with cycles and epicycles, to mock the slavish imitators of
Aristotle was one thing; to assign an entirely new, lopsided, implausible
path for the heavenly bodies was quite another. Why indeed an oval?
There is something in the perfect symmetry of spheres and circles
which has a deep, reassuring appeal to the unconscious mind-other-
wise it could not have survived two millennia. The oval lacks that
archetypal appeal. It has an arbitrary, distorted form. It destroyed the
dream of the 'harmony of the spheres', which lay at the origin of the
whole quest. At times he felt like a criminal, or worse: a fool. All he
had to say in his own defence was: 'I have cleared the Augean stables
of astronomy of cycles and spirals, and left behind me only a single
cartful of dung.'&
That cartful of dung-non-uniform motion in non-circular orbits
-could only be justified and explained by arguments derived not
from geometry, but from physics. A phrase kept humming in his ear
like a catchy tune, and crops up in his writings over and again: there
is a force in the sun which moves the planets, there is a force in the sun .
. . . And since there is a force in the sun, there must exist some simple
relationship between the planet's distance from the sun, and its speed.
A light shines the brighter the nearer one is to its source, and the same
must apply to the force of the sun: the closer the planet to it, the
quicker it will move. This had been his instinctive conviction; but now
he thought that he had found the proof for it. 'Ye physicists, prick your
ears, for now we are going to invade your territory.' The next six
chapters· in the Astronomia Nova are a report on that invasion into
celestial physics, which had been out of bounds for astronomy since
Plato. He had found the second matrix which would unblock his.
problem.
That excursion was something of a comedy of errors-which
130 THE ACT OF CREATION
quarto volumes, and took fifty years to publish. Linne, who laid down
the laws for defining genera and species, and whose system of
classification survives to this day, started as a believer in immutability;
but later in hfe he admitted that new species may arise as 'daughters of
Time'. Buffon attacked not only Linnaeus's classification, but the
principles underlying it; he denied the existence of rigid boundaries
between one speaes and another, between vegetable and animal,
between animal and man: species arose, transformed themselves, and
became extinct according to climatic and other changes in nature.
Judged by the form and organization of its body, he wrote, 'the
orangutang would approach nearer to man than to any other animal'.
A century later Darwin admitted that 'whole pages [in Buffon] are
laughably like mine'.
By the end of the eighteenth century the cumulative evidence from
'the general facts in the affinities, embryology, rudimentary organs,
geological history, and geographical distribution of organic beings'
(Darwin to Asa Gray)10 led to the simultaneous appearance of
evolutionary theories in a number of European countries. 'It is a rather
singular instance,' he remarked elsewhere, 'of the manner in which
similar views arise at about the same time, that Goethe in Germany,
Dr. [Erasmus] Darwin in England and Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire in France
• . . came to the same conclusion on the origin of the species, in the
years 1794-9 5'll-that is, fifteen years before Charles Darwin was born.
The second great public controversy between evolutionists and anti-
evolutionists originated in the fateful years 2 and 3-according to the
calendar of the French Revolution-when the three main protagonists
in the drama were all given chairs at the University of Paris by the
Revolutionary Government. They were Lamarck, Cuvier, Geoffroy
Saint-Hilaire. The climax came in 1830, when Geoffroy, the evolu-
tionist, and Cuvier, who denied evolution, confronted each other in
public debate before the French Academy of Sciences. Cuvier won the
debate-and rightly so because Geoffroy had tried to demonstrate a
good cause by a badly chosen example-but the outcome· mattered
less than the debate itself, which Goethe declared to be an event far
more memorable than the French Revolution. This was a quarter of a
century before Darwin submitted his first paper on evolution to the
Royal Society.
A further scandal broke in 1844-still fifteen years before the
publication of The Origin of Species-when Robert Chambers
published anonymously bis Vestiges of Creation, an impassionate if
THREE ILLUSTRATIONS 133
d.ilettanric plea for the evolutionary doctrine. Its impact may be
gathered from a scenein Disraeli's Tancred, in which the heroine sings
the book's praises: 'You know, all is development. The principle is
perpetually going on. First, there was nothing, then there was some-
thing; then-I forget the next-I think there were shells, then fishes;
then we came-let me see-chd we come next? Never mind that; we
came at last. And at the next change there will be something very
superior to us-something with wings. Ah! that's it: we were fishes,
and I believewe shallbe crows. But you must read it ... it is all proved.
... You understand, it is all science;it is not like those books in which
one says one thing and another the contrary, and both may be wrong.
Everything is proved .. .'
The passage has that particular flavour which we have come to
associatewith the Darwinian controversy.Even Tancred's rejoinder to
the enthusiasticlady: 'I do not believeIever was a fish,' has the familiar
ring of music-halljokes about 'my grandpa was an ape'. And yet, I
repeat, all this excitement pre-dates the publication of Darwin's .first
paper by more than ten years.
Thus Darwin originated neither the idea nor the controversy about
evolution, and in his early years was fully aware of this. When he
decided to write a book on the subject,hejotted down severalversions
of an apologetic disclaimerof originality for the preface of the future
work:
The remark that he had arrived at his ideas independently from his
predecessorsshould not perhaps be taken at face value, for Darwin's
own notebooks are conclusive proof that he had certainly read
Lamarck, the greatest among his precursors, and a number of other
works on evolution, before he arrived at formulating his own theory.
Even so, the intended apology never found its way into the book which
it was meant to preface. In his early notebooks, not intended for
134 THE ACT OP CREATION
If species generate other species, their race i$ not utterly cut off
otherwise all die. ·
If all men were dead, then monkeys may make men, men make
angels.
refused to accept such direct adaptations as the only, or even the main
cause of evolution, because the evidence seemed to speak against it.
Evidence showed that a great variety of species lived under identical
environmental conditions; and vice versa, that the same species could
be found under widely varymg conditions. If species evolved, as
Lamarck's theory proposed, by direct adaptations to the environment,
then their variety remained unexplained. Evolution was a fact; but
what caused it? What was the nature of the force which transformed
animals and plants into new shapes?
The second thread that he picked up was of almost as trivial a nature
for a country-bred English gentleman as Archimedes's daily bath:
domestic breeding. The improvement of domestic breeds is achieved
by the selective mating of favourable variations:
It seemed to me probable that a careful study of domesticated
animals and of cultivated plants would offer the best chance of
making out this complicated problem. Nor have I been disappointed;
in this and in all other perplexing cases I have invariably found that
our knowledge, imperfect though it he, of variation under
domestication, afforded the best and safest clue. I may venture to
express my conviction of the high value of such studies, although they
have been very commonly neglected by naturalists.18 (my italics)
The cat had its tail cut off at Shrewsbury and its kittens had all
short tails; but one a little longer than the rest; they all died. She had
kittens before and afterwards with tails.
Dr. Smith says he is certain that when white men and Hottentots
or Negroes cross at Cape of Good Hope, the children cannot be made
intermediate. The first children partake more of the mother, the later
ones of the father.
selection; but who or what selects the favourable variations for breed-
ing in the case of undomesticated animals or plants? 'How selection
could be applied to organisms living in a state of nature remained for
some time a mystery to me.'
The deadlock lasted a year and three months. He tried a number of
hypotheses, but none of them worked. He toyed with the idea of
some universal law, according to which speoes were born, matured, and
died.just as individuals do. 'There is nothing stranger in the death of a
species than m the death of individuals.' Then he assumed, by a
perverse analogy, chat since nothing is preserved of an individual who
dies without leaving offspring, so a species too will die out unless it
gives nse to another species. But they were wrong guesses, and his
thoughts kept running in circles in the blocked matrix-as Sultan's did
unnl his eyes fell on the stick.
In Darwin's case the stick was Malthus's An Essay on the Principle of
Population, rt had been published in 1797-more than forty years earlier.
When Darwin read the essay-among other books which he read 'for
amusement', as he said-he saw in a flash the 'natural selector', the
causative agent of evolution, for which he had been searching:
He had found the third thread. Now the pattern of the theory was
complete: what remained to be done was its elaboration-the weaving
of the huge carpet which took him most of the rest of his life.
The odd thing about the story is-as others have pointed out-that
Darwin had completely misunderstood Malthus. The struggle for
existence, in which Darwin discovered the causative mechanism of
evolutionary improvement, Malthus himself had regarded as a cause
of misery, frustration, and decline. The increase of population was for
Malthus an unmitigated evil and an obstacle to progress. The-essay had
actually been written as a polemic against Condorcet and Godwin, who
had argued the perfectability of the human species. Domestic breeding,
THR:SE ILLUSTRATIONS
years on the problem and had a 'distinct and tangible idea of its
solution'.
One year later the same 'distinct and tangible idea' came to Wallace.
In his autobiography Wallace described how he was 'lying muffled in
blankets in the cold fit of a severe attack of intermittent fever at
Ternate' (an island near New Guinea) when he suddenly remembered
Malthus's essay on population which he had read 'twelve or more years
earlier'. 26
The effect was analogous to that of friction upon the specially
prepared match, producing that Rash of insight which led immediately
to the simple but universal law of the 'survival of the fittest' ... 'It
suddenly flashed upon me that this self-action process [i.e. the struggle
for existence] would necessarily improve the race, because in every genera-
tion the inferior would inevitably be killed off and the superior would
remain-that is, the fittest would survive. The more I thought over it the
more I became convinced that I had at length found the long-sought-
for law of nature that solved the problem of the origin of the species.P?
In the course of the next two evenings, 'in a few feverish hours', he
put his theory into a paper of four thousand words and sent it off to
Darwin, in the pleasant belief that it would be a surprise to him-since
Darwin had not yet published his own theory, although he had put it
on paper years earlier in several versions and shown it to his friends.
'I never saw a more striking coincidence', Darwin wrote. 'IfW allace
had my manuscript sketch written out in 1842, he could not have made
a better short abstract.'
Luckily, both Wallace and Darwin acted with a generosity and
reasonableness rare in the annals of science; the result was the presenta-
tion on 1 July 1848 of a joint memoir by Darwin and Wallace to
the Linnean Society, under the title 'On the Tendency of Species to
form Varieties; and on the Perpetuation of Varieties and Species by
Natural Means of Selection'. Neither author was present; Wallace was
overseas, Darwin ill in bed. When the paper was read out there was
no discussion and no sign of interest. At the end of the year the
President of the Society said in his annual report: 'The year which has
passed .•. has not, indeed, been marked by any of those striking dis-
coveries which at once revolutionize, so to speak, the department of
science on which they bear.'28 In November next year The Origin of
Spedes was published, and only then did the storm break.
Though both men were constantly ailing from real and perhaps
also from imaginary diseases, Darwin lived to be seventy-three, and
THREE ILLUSTRATIONS 143
Wallace ninety. Though they differed on some points of theory and
though their opponents tried to play them out against each other, they
managed to remain life-long friends; towards the end of his life Darwin
obtained a pension for Wallace from Mr. Gladstone, and Wallace was
one of Darwin's pall-bearers. At the fiftieth anniversary, in r909,
commemorating the joint publication of the Darwin-Wallace papers,
Wallace modestly declared that their relative contributions 'could be
justly estimated as the proportion of twenty years to one week'29-
which was an exaggeration, as Wallace's later works, particularly the.
'Contributions' and 'Darwinism' were of considerable importance.
The psychologically fascinating aspect of the story is that the same
bisociative process was triggered off in Darwin's case by reading
Malthus, in Wallace's by the buried memory of Malthus, whom he
had read many years earlier, popping into consciousness at a feverish
moment. Thus Darwin's discovery strikes one as more rational,
Wallace's as more dramatic and bizarre, and this is in keeping with the
character of the two men. If Darwin had more patience and clarity of
mind, Wallace had more fantasy and perhaps even more depth. His
remark that selection through survival of the fittest was a 'self-acting
process' anticipated the concept of negative feed-back. His conviction
that the rise of organic life, the rise of consciousness, and the rise of man
represent Jumps' in the evolutionary series, due to some 'unknown
reality' which has to be added to the mechanical operation of natural
selection, had a religious flavour; yet his conclusion that 'man and his
rise now appear short in time-explosively short' has been confirmed
by contemporary anthropology. If Darwin had an 'amiable credulity',
Wallace believed, among other things, in phrenology and in the cruder
forms of mesmerism and spiritualism. No wonder he had to dive
into the depths of his unconscious mind to bring up the same trophy
which Darwin spied clrifting on the surface, and secured with a boat-
hook.
That both read Malthus is not much of a coincidence as his essay
was well known and d1SCUSsed at the time; and had it not been
Malthus, they could have extracted the same idea from other sources-
from Erasmus Darwin, for instance, or from certain passages in
Lamarck. The time was ripe; 'it was not the coincidence of discovery
that is surprising but rather the fact that the coincidence was so long
delayed'.30 This remark by one of Darwin's biographer's is not based
on hind-sight, but on the opinion of Darwin's friends and contem-
poraries:
THB ACT OF CREATION
I
•
VII
THINKING ASIDE
Limits of Logic
I
n an old Alchemist's Rosarium, whose author I have forgotten, I once
saw two pieces of advice for finding the Philosopher's Stone
printed side by side:
The Stone can only be found when the search lies heavily on the
searcher.-Thou seekest hard and findest not. Seek not and thou
wilst :find.
Only gradually did the reaction set in-the realization that 'if there
are two realms, physical and mental, awareness cannot be taken as the
criterion of mentality [because] the springs of human nature lie in the
unconscious .•. as the realm which links the moments of human
awareness with the background of organic processes within which they
emerge'.2
Among the first to take up the cudgels against Descartes's 'Cogito
ergo sum' was the Cambridge philosopher Cudworth:
We may have ideas of which we are not conscious .... There are
infinitely moreideas impressed on our minds than we can possibly
attend to or perceive. . . . There may be an impression of ideas
without any actual perception of them. 4
At about the same time, in 1868, Erich von Hartmann published his
Philosophy ofthe Unconscious, which became a best-seller. From a period
novel by the popular Spie1hagen we leam that in 1870 two main topics
dominated conversation in the intellectual salons of Berlin: Wagner
and the Unconscious. We are reminded of the scene in the London
salon of Disraeli's play, where the fashionable topic of Evolution is
discussed-fifteen years before anybody had heard the name of
Darwin. Whyte lists six philosophical works published within ten
years after von Hartmann's which carry the word 'unconscious' in
their titles. In the literature of the period Nietzsche was the towering
giant. He took over the unconscious Id from Lichtenberg (which
Groddeck then took over from Nietzsche, and Freud from Groddeck.);
it is one of the leitmotifs in Nietzsche's work:
Where are the new doctors of the soul? .•. Consciousness is the last
and latest development of the organic, and is consequently the most
unfinished and least powerful of these developments. Every extension
of knowledge arises from making conscious the unconsciousness. The
great basic activity is unconscious. For it is narrow, this room of
human consciousness.
I
Exploring the Shallows
and sink back again into twilight and darkness; how do they assist
mental creativity? The answers we have heard up to now were of
a general nature; they all asserted that such assistance was indispensable
and did in fact occur; but they had little to say regarding the concrete
mechanism or procedure through which it was rendered. Perhaps the
most lucid attempt in this direction was made by that versatile genius
Francis Galton in a famous analogy:
The italics are mine, and are meant to register protest. Assuming the
idea in the presence-chamber of my mind is, as it happens to be, Mr.
Galton himself, I can recall six distinct occasions in the last few months
when I thought of him. He helped to ease the gloom of my last birth-
day-because Galton lived to the age of eighty-nine; and the idea
'most nearly allied', which was summoned from the ante-chamber
'in a mechanically logical way', was 'Methuselah'. On another occasion
I read about the acquittal of a woman who had been tried for the
mercy-killing of her malformed baby; Galton was summoned because
he had invented the word 'eugenics'; next came, logically, the 'most
nearly allied' idea of Adolf Hitler, whose S.S. men practised eugenics
after their own fashion. On yet another occasion the closest association
was 'colour-blindness'-fust studied by Dalton which rhymes with
Galton; and so forth. Each summons into the presence-ch.amber had
its own 'mechanical logic', if you wish to call it that; and the choice of
the 'most nearly allied idea', the order of precedence in the ante-
chamber, depended on what sort oflogic, or rule of the game, was at
the time in control of the mind. Galton was a pioneer of the experimen-
, tal method in word-association tests; but as a follower of the English
THINKING A.SIDE 161
Thus the objects of the scanning process are ultimately the individual's
past experiences (including his pre-natal past) incorporated in one form
or another into his mental landscape. And the rules which control the
scanning process (the pattern of 'mental eye motions', as it were) are
also derived from past experiences by abstraction and generalization;
they are the results of learning compressed into the operational codes
of thinking skills.
As an example, take the parlour game 'Towns with M' (see page 38).
The moment I start playing it a fixed code takes control of my mental
processes, and their freedom is whittled down to strategic choices.
These may be based on exploring an imagined geographical map, or
on the 'tuning-fork' method. The mental map is a blurred, hazy, and
distorted replica of what I learned in school and on travels; but as I
proceed to scan it, from west to east with the mind's eye, name after
name emerges from the misty twilight: Manchester, Munich, Moscow,
Murmansk, Michigan, etc. If, on the other hand, I apply the tuning-
fork method, Manchester will call out Mannheim, Madrid, Madras,
and so forth. All of these names were learned in the past; all of them were
members of the 'M' matrix (otherwise they could not have been
summoned on the 'wavelength' of that particular code); all of them
were unconscious or pre-conscious the moment before the beam of
focal awareness alighted on them. The beam was guided .firstly by the
rule of the game ('find towns with M, not rivers with S'), and secondly
by strategy ('move from west to east'). The rule was fixed, the strategy
variable. A further point to note is (though it does not concern us yet)
that strategy operates by a kind of.feed-back from the lie of the land:
I was searching for towns with 'M' between Munich and Moscow,
but found none: so I moved on. Other factors enter: I might have
remembered Mannheim, but did not because of an unpleasant exper-
ience there: emotional disturbances interfering with 'mechanical logic'.
Incidentally, the forming of a sentence in ordinary conversation
follows a similar pattern. Instead of scanning a map for towns with 'M',
you must scan your vocabulary for words which will fit a given
meaning.
Take an even simpler practical example. I live in London and have
to spend a day in Paris some time next week to see my French publisher.
If this were a pleasure-trip the fringes of my consciousness would at
once be crowded with half-remembered, floating images of bistros,
streets, galleries, metro stations; but, as it is a business trip, a different
code enters into action and the matrix is cluttered with timetables,
THINKING ASIDE
But two objections come to his mind. Firstly, is not the number of
possible combinations infinite, and the chance of hitting on a favourable
one infinitesimal? No, he answers, because during the conscious
preparatory work which preceded the period of unconscious mcuba-
tion, a fust selection was already made of those atoms which are to be
unhooked from the wall; and although no satisfactory combination of
them was found, 'after this shaking up imposed upon them by our will,
these atoms do not return to their previous rest. They freely continue
to dance' until the one favourable collision in a million occurs. (This
is rather like saying that the chances of the monkey on the typewriter
hitting on a Shakespeare sonnet would be considerably improved by
building a typewriter which uses whole words as keys instead of
letters.)
The second objection which occurred to Poincare is as follows:
although countless combinations are formed 'in consequence of the
automatism of the subliminal self, only the interesting ones ... break
into the domain of consciousness'. But, if so, what is the nature of the
mysterious sieve which rejects the uselesscombinations and allows only
the lucky hits to pass into consciousness? Poincare's answer is that
the selection is done by 'the aesthetic sensibility of the real creator. The
useful combinations are precisely the most beautiful, I mean those best
able to charm this special sensibility'.
This is certainly a more attractive answer than Galton's, who sum-
mons ideas from the ante-chamber 'in a mechanically logical way'; yet
Poincare himself felt its unsatisfactoriness, For it combines a mechanistic
theory about the random collision of atomic ideas in the unconscious,
with an aesthetic sensibility which resides in the conscious, and plays
the part of a deus ex machlna. We do not doubt that this kind of
sensibility is present in the creative mind, and to inquire into its nature
is precisely what we are after; but Poincare lets the matter rest just
where the problem starts.
Particularly fascinating in this lecture, delivered in 1908, is the fact
that Poincare, after acknowledging his debt to the 'subliminal self' and
I66 'IRE ACT OF CREATION
singing its praises, confesses that he would 'hate to accept' that it might
in some respects be superior to the conscious self, and relegates it to the
role of an automatic mixing machine in the basement. He worked by
intuition, but for all his modesty and open-mindedness he was unable
to shake off the rationalist hubris of the nineteenth century.*
All we have gleaned from these excursions into the history of our
subject, from Ploti.nus to Poincare, is firstly, a negative insight into the
narrow limitations of conscious thinking; and on the positive side,
affirmations of the superiority of unconscious mentation at certain
stages of creative work. But regarding the reasons for this superiority,
and the process by which it manifests itself, we got merely a few vague
intimations, or else unsatisfactory mechanistic hypotheses such as
Galton's and Poincare's, Nor, I may add here, had Freud or Jung much
to say about the specific problem how unconscious processes lead to
new discoveries.
Let us at this stage follow the advice we have so often heard repeated,
and 'think aside'-by turning, for a moment, from scientists to poets.
If we were to apply Poincare' s hypothesis we would come to the
conclusion that the poet has a conscious mind endowed with aesthetic
sensibility, and an unconscious mind equipped with an automatic
rhyme-computer (built on the principle of rhyming lexicons), and also
with an image computer (a kind of magic lantern with an automatic
slide-changer}. Out of the hundreds of rhymes and similes produced
per minute the vast majority would, of course, be, valueless, and the
aesthetic censor in the conscious mind would have a :full-time job
rejecting them-until he went out of his mind.
It seems neither an economical nor an inspired procedure. Now let
us listen to Coleridge's celebrated description of the genesis of Kubla
Khan. He is speaking of himself in the third person singular:
In the summer of the year 1797, the Author, then in ill health, had
retired to a lonely farm-house between Porlock and Linton .•.• In
consequence of a slight indisposition, an anodyne had been
prescribed, from the dfects of which he fell asleep in his chair at the
moment that he was reading the following sentence, or words of the
same substance, in Purchals Pilgrimage:
THINKING ASIDE
The whole poem, with its rather striking allegory, grew out of a
hackneyed metaphor, which was meant to serve only as a visual
illustration to a verbal narrative. But all at once the servant becomes
master, the illustration takes over from the text; visual association, the
logic of the eye are in command, and the words must follow their
lead ....
We further note that the whole sequence of'not less than from two
to three hundred lines' of the Kubla Khan dream itself was triggered off
by a passage read in Purchas's Pilgrimage, as indifferent as the simile of
the stone cast into the stream: 'Here the Khan Kubla commanded a
palace to be built', etc. But at that point his imagination caught on, the
opium took effect, visual thinking took over, and images 'rose up as
thing s ' .
Thinking inpictures dominates the manifestations of the unconscious
-the dream, the hypnogogic half-dream, the psychotic' s hallucina-
tions, the artist's 'vision'. (The 'visionary' prophet seems to have been
a visualizer, and not a verbalizer; the highest compliment we pay to
those who trade in verbal currency is to call them 'visionary thinkers'.)
But, on the other band, pictorial thinking is a more primitive form.
of mentation than conceptual thinking, which it precedes in the
mental evolution of the individual and of the species. The language of
the primitive (and of the child) is, to borrow Kretschmer' s simile, 'like
the unfolding of a picture-strip: each word expresses a picture, a
pictorial image, regardless of whether it signifies an object or an
action'. In Golding's novel The Inheritors the Neanderthal men always
say 'I had a picture' when they mean 'I thought of something'; and
anthropologists agree that for once a. novelist got the picture right.
Thus the poet who reverts to the pictorial mode of thought is
regressing to an older and lower level of the mental hierarchy-as we do
every night when we dream, as mental patients do when they regress
to infantile fantasies. But the poet, unlike the dreamer in his sleep,
altemates between two different levels of the mental hierarchy; the
THINKING ASIDE 169
dreamer's awareness functions on one only. The poet thinks both in
images and verbal concepts, at the same time or in quick alternation;
each trouvaille, each original find, bisociates two matrices. The dreamer
floats among the phantom shapes of the hoary deep; the poet is a skin-
diver with a breathing tube.
Similar considerations apply-and will be discussed in Part ill
-to rhythm, metre, alliteration, assonance, rhyme. The rhythmic beat,
echoing the shaman's tom-tom, awakens archaic resonances and 'lulls
the mind into a waking trance' (Yeats). The rhyme appeals to the
tendency to vocal repetition in the language of primitives and children
(kala-kala, ma-ma), and to the equally deep-rooted tendency to
associate by sound-punning. To conclude this anticipatory excursion:
the creative activity of the artist involves momentary regressions to
earlier stages in mental evolution, bringing forms of mentation into
play which otherwise manifest them.selves only in the dream or dream-
like states.
'One fine summer evening,' he relates, 'I was returning by the last
omnibus, '' outside" as usual, through the deserted streets of the
170 THE ACT OF CREATION
The necessity for this retreat derives from the fact that words are a
blessing which can turn into a curse. They crystallize thought; they
give articulation and precision to vague images and hazy intuitions.
But a crystal is no longer a fluid. 'Language is not only the foundation
for the whole faculty of thinking, but the central point also from which
proceed the misunderstandings of reason by hersel£'B8 This was written
by Hamman, a German philosopher of the eighteenth century, who
had a great influence on Goethe. Roman Jakobson, a contemporary
linguist-to quote one among many-voices the same ancient doubt:
174 THE ACT OF CREATION
Top. 166. Less understandable is the case of Spearman, who wrote a. book
on the Creative Mind (1930) with only passing mention of unconscious processes,
the main reference being a sneer at Freud's preoccupation with 'subconscious
bestiality'. This was written when Spearman was Professor of Psychology at the
University of London.
Top. 1.7z. The exceptions were G.D. Birkhoff, Norbert Wiener (who said
that 'he happens to think with or without words'), and G. Poly.l.
I
•
VIII
UNDERGROUND GAMES
The Importanceof Dreaming
cerned with the creative aspect only; but I should mention in passing
that the underground layers of the mental hierarchy must not be con-
fused with 'repressed complexes'. The latter form a special category
within the much broader realm of subconscious phenomena. Com-
plexes originate in traumatic experiences; the underground games of
the mind reflect the facts of mental evolution.
The levels of mental organization have been compared to the
archaeological strata of ancient and prehistoric civilizations, buried,
but not irretrievably, under our contemporary towns. The analogy is
Freud's1 but I would like to carry it one step further. Imagine for a
moment that all important written records and monuments pre-dating
the Industrial Revolution have been destroyed by some catastrophe
like the burning down of the library in Alexandria; and that know-
ledge of the past could be obtained only by archaeological excavations.
Without digging into the undergound strata, modem society, ig-
norant of the culture of the Renaissance, of Antiquity, Prehistory, and
the Age of the Dinosaurs, would be reduced to an unimaginably super-
ficial, two-dimensional existence: a species without a past and probably
-for lack of comparative values-without much future. An individual
deprived of his dreams, of irrational impulses, of any form of ideation
except articulate verbal thought, would be in much the same position.
Dreaming, in the literal and metaphorical sense, seems to be an essen-
tial part of psychic metabolism-as essential as its counterpart, the
formation and automatization of habits. Without this daily dip into
the ancient sources of mental life we would probably all become
desiccated automata. And without the more spectacular exploratory
dives of the creative individual, there would be no science and no art.
each case the creative act consisted in a new synthesis of previously un-
connected matrices of thought; a synthesis arrived at by 'thinking
aside', a temporary relinquishing of the rational controls in favour of
the codes which govern the underground games of the mind. We
have seen that the dream operates with a type of logic which is in-
admissible in the waking state, and which, for precisely that reason,
proved useful in critical situations where the matrices of conscious
thought are blocked. Thus the illogicality and apparent naivete of
visual associations, or the indifference of the dreaming mind to con-
vention and common sense, turned out to be of great value in forging
new combinations out of seemingly incompatible contexts. All the
bisociative mechanisms of the comic we found in the dream free-
wheeling as it were, without being harnessed to any obvious rational
purpose. But when the whole personality, on all its levels, becomes
saturated with the problem in hand during the period of incubation,
then the freewheding machinery too is 'engaged' in its service and
goes into action-not necessarily in the dream, but mostly on some
intermediary, part-conscious level.
The examples in previous chapters had been meant to illustrate
various aspects of unconscious discovery. In the sections which follow
Ishall try to show, a little more systematically, how the peculiarities of
subconscious ideation, reflected in the dream, facilitate the bisociative
click.
I tried this and that, until I got fed up with the whole thing, but
the image of that monk in his saffron robe walking up the hill kept
persisting in my mind. Then a moment came when, super-imposed
on this image, I saw another, more transparent one, of the monk
walking down the hill, and I realized in a flash that the two figures
must meet at some point some time-regardless at what speed they
walk and how often each of them stops. Then I reasoned out what I
already knew: whether the monk descends two days or three days
later comes to the same; so I was quite justified in letting him
descend on the same day, in duplicate so to speak.
simple facts of the matter, and to give due credit in his paper to Y's
paternity.
On one level of his mind X had, of course, known all this; discovery
in this case, as in many others, consisted in uncovering what had always
been there. But his knowledge had been buried under the rigid crust
of a conventional matrix, which made his conscious thoughts turn in a
vicious circle.
Charles Lamb once remarked in a letter that he wished 'to draw his
last breath through a pipe and exhale it in a pun'.
The benefits which the humorist and the poet derive from two
meanings linked together by one sound are evident/ in the natural
sciences they are non-existent, for the simple reason that verbal formula-
tion, the choice of the particular words in which a theory is expressed,
is to a large extent irrelevant to its content. But in the sciences con-
cerned with language and meaning, the relations between sense and
sound play an important part. Homonyms and homophones, sound
affinities and transformations, are essential pointers in etymology and
comparative philology, in the study of the structure and development
of language. I have mentioned the 'divine pun' by which adam, man,
was created out of adamiih, earth. Eve's Hebrew name is Havvdh, life;
while ahavvah is love; esh, a synonym for man, has the same root as
ish, fire; and milkhamah, war, is derived from lekhem, bread; so is the
village of Beth-lehem: the House of Bread.
Affinities of sound provide the threads which lead from contem-
porary words and concepts back to the Greek and Sanskrit womb.The
deciphering of the scripts of ancient languages is often aided by clues
such as the frequency with which a certain sign occurs, and other
'links' between sign, symbol, sound, and sense. Thus the links which,
in 1821, enabled Champollion to break into the secret of hieroglyphics,
were the proper names Ptolemy, Cleopatra, and Alexander, which
appeared on the Rosetta Stone (and on various other documents}
bearing parallel inscriptions in Greek and in two different Egyptian
scripts. The three names, inscribed in conspicuous cartouches, pro-
vided Champollion with altogether fourteen alphabetic signs of as
certained value-certainly the greatest service which any Cleopatra
bas rendered to history.
In the infantile and primitive imagination, the ties between sound
UNDERGROUND GAMES
and meaning are still very intimate; name and object form an almost
indivisible unity, shown in the universal practices of word magic,
incantations, and verbal spells. Related to this is the belief that the
letters contained in a word form secret connections according to cer-
tain hermeneutical rules-a belief, shared by Judaism, several other
Oriental religions, and adopted by the Christian Fathers. It was thought,
for instance, that to extract their hidden meaning, certain texts in
Hebrew Scriptures should be arranged in vertical columns and read
downwards; or that the first and last letter in each word should be used
to form new words; or that the letters should be reduced to their
numerical value, and the sums so obtained should then be manipu-
lated according to the rules of mystic numberlore. Here we have the
archaic origins of the pun, the crossword puzzle, the acrostic, anagram,
and cryptogram, which have always exerted such a curious fascina-
non in the most varied cultures-from Pythagoras and Lao-Tse to
Champollion and Freud. The humorist's joke, the linguist's dis-
covery, the poet's euphony, all derive from that source.
really have no intention of doing so,' then, says Freud, 'you can take it
for granted that he did have that intention. Or, the patient will say:
''You are asking me who that person in my dream could be. It is not
my mother." We then correct him: ''In other words, it's your mother."
..• At times one can obtain information about unconscious repressed
processes by a very easy method. One asks: ''What do you consider
to be the most unlikely aspect of that situation? What was it that you
least intended to do?" If the patient swallows the bait, and tells one
what he can believe least, then he has almost invariably conceded the
true answer.'10
Freud seemed to believe (following Bain and others) that the reason
for the unconscious tendency to unify opposites is the relativity of
all scales by which attributes are measured: a 'hot' summer-day in
London is 'cold' to the visitor from the Sudan, and Gulliver is a
'giant' or a 'dwarf' according to the country he visits. He further
refers to the fact that in some ancient languages pairs of opposites are
designated by the same word: thus altus means both 'high' and 'deep',
and sacer both 'holy' and 'accursed'.
For once, however, Freud did not seem to have probed deep enough;
he did not mention the rites of the Saturnalia and other ancient festi-
vals, in which the roles of slaves and masters are reversed; nor the
constant affirmation of the unity of opposites in most Oriental religions
and philosophies. It seems indeed that the tendency to stand things,
from ti.me to time, on their head, has its deep, unconscious roots,
which probably reach down into the physiological peculiarities of the
nervous system.* One of its striking manifestations is the reversi-
bility of 'figure' and 'background' in visual perception-about which
below.
I am not at all sure how far these considerations are relevant to a
certain pattern of discovery which recurs with curious insistence in the
biological sciences: we £nd, over and again, mishaps and minor
laboratory disasters which tum out to be blessings in disguise, and
spoilt experiments which perversely yield the solution-by brutally
shifting the experimenter's attention from a 'plus' to a 'minus' aspect
of the problem, as it were. One might call this pattern 'discovery by
misadventure'. A classic case is that of the Abbe Haily (1743-1822), a
humble teacher at the college at Lemoine, whose leisure hours were
devoted to collecting specimens of plants and minerals-until a small,
embarrassing accident suddenly changed the direction of his interests
and his whole life:
ONDBRGROUND GAMES 193
One day, when examining some minerals at the house of a
friend, he was clumsy enough to allow a beautiful cluster of prismatic
crystals of calcareous spar to fall on the ground. One of the prisms
broke in such a way as to show at the fracture faces which were no
less smooth than those elsewhere, but presented the appearance of a
new crystal altogether different in form from the prism. Haily picked
up this fragment and examined the faces with their inclinations and
angles. To his great surprise, he discovered that they are the same in
rhomboidal spar as in Iceland spar.
He wished to be able to generalize: he broke bis own little collec-
tion into pieces; crystals lent by his friends were broken; everywhere
he found a structure which depended upon the same laws.11
FIGURE 9
The great biologist Elie Mechrukoff felt rather lonely one a.fi:emoon
in 1890 'when the whole family had gone to the circus to see some
extraordinary performing apes, and I remained alone with my micro-
scope'. u The microscope was in a laboratory of the Ecole Normale
which Pasteur had given him; Mechnikoff was observing the life of the
mobile cells in the transparent larvae of starfish, and idly threw a few
rose-thorns among them. The thorns were promptly surrounded by
the larvae and dissolved inside their transparent bodies-they had been
gobbled up and digested. This reminded him of what happens when a
human finger is infected by a splinter: it will be surrounded by pus
which, like the starfish larvae, will attack and try to digest the intruder.
By this analogy Mechnikoff discovered the organisms' main defence
mechanism against invading microbes: the 'phagocytes', cell-eaters, a
population of mobile cells among the white blood corpuscles.
The starting point of Kepler's discoveries was a supposed analogy
between the role of the Father in the Trinity and the role of the Sun in
the Universe. Lord Kdvin hit on the idea of the mirror galvanometer
when he noticed a reflection oflight on bis monocle. Sultan saw that a
THB ACT OP CREATION
branch was like a stick; Newton saw that the moon behaved like an
apple. Pasteur saw the analogy between a spoilt culture and a cow-pox
vaccine; Fleming saw the analogy between the action of a mould and
the action of a drip from his nose. Freud, on his own account, conceived
the idea of the sublimation of instincts by looking at a funny cartoon in
the Fliegende Blatter-the one-time German equivalent of Punch. Inthe
first picture a little girl was herding a flock of goslings with a stick. In
the second she had grown into a governess herding a flock of young
ladies with a parasol1'
Some writers identify the creative act in its entirety with the unearth-
ing of hidden analogies. 'The discoveries of science, the works of art
are explorations-more, are explosions, of a hidden likeness', Bronow-
ski wrote.15 But where does the hidden likeness hide, and how is it
found? Sultan's branch could literally be seen as a stick-though even in
this case, a change of the perceptual frame was required to discover the
likeness. But in most truly original acts of discovery the 'seeing' is in
fa.ct imagining; it is done in the mind's, and mostly the unconscious
mind's eye. The analogy between the life of one kind of microbe inside
a cow and another kind of microbe in a forgotten culture tube was not
'hidden' anywhere; it was 'created' by the imagination; and once an
analogy has been created, it is of course there for all to see-just as a
poetic metaphor, once created, soon fades into a cliche.
Analogy, inlogic, means a process of'reasoning from parallel causes';
in common parlance it means that two situations or events are similar
insome respects, but not inall respects. The rub is in the words 'parallel'
and 'similar'; the latter, in particular, has bedevilled psychology ever
since the term 'association by similarity' was invented (by Bain, I
believe) as an explanation of how the mind works. A Chinaman who
collects stamps is 'similar' to a Negro in that both are males; he is
similar to a Chinese girl in th.at both are Chinese; and he is similar to
other stamp-colleaors of any nationality. Mathematics began, wrote
Bertrand Russell, when it was discovered that a brace of pheasants and
a couple of days have something in common: the number two.
'Similarity' is not a thing offered on a plate (or hidden in a cupboard};
it is a relation established in the mind by a process of selective emphasis
on those features which overlap ina certain respect-along one dimen-
sional gradient-and ignoring other features. Even such a seemingly
simple process as recognizing the similarity between two letters 'a'
written by different hands, involves processes of abstraction and.
generalization in the nervous system which are largdy unexplained.
UNDERGROUND GAMBS 20!
'optic puns' or visual symbols; but there is another type of vague and
cloudy analogy generated in the dream and half-dream, which dis-
integrates on awakening and cannot be put into words-except by
muttering 'something reminded me of something, but I don't know
what reminded me of what, and why'. Some dreams have a way of
dissolving in the wakening mind like solid crystals melting in a liquid:
and if we reverse the process we get at least a speculative pointer to the
manner in which those 'somethings' vaguely reminding me of other
'somethings' condense into a nascent analogy. This may be a hazy,
tentative affair-the dance of Poincare' s unhooked atoms; and its shape
may be changing from camel to weasel, as Hamlet's cloud. The un-
conscious regions of fertile minds must be pullulating with such nascent
analogies, hidden likenesses, and the cloudy forms of things unknown.
But most clouds form and dissolve again; only a few intuitions reach
the stage of' seeding the cloud' which results in the formation of verbal
drops; and cloud-bursts are a rarity.
Two final examples may serve to illustrate the actual process of
discovering hidden analogies. The first is related to clouds in a literal
sense-Franklin's invention of the lightning conductor.
Benjamin Franklin became interested in electricity in 1746 when he
was forty, and began playing about with Leyden jars-a kind of
electrified bottle which gave one fearful shocks. Within the next three
years he rediscovered by himself virtually everything that was known
about electricity to that date, and added several fundamental discoveries
of his own.
In 1749 he noted in his diary that he thought lightning and thunder
to be electrical phenomena.* He also found that when brought near to'
an electrified body, a pointed object, like a finger, will draw a much
stronger spark than a blunt one. 'To know this power of points', he
musingly wrote, 'may possibly be of some use to mankind, though we
should never be able to explain it.' He then drew an analogy between a
cloud and an dectrified body, and concluded that lightning was an
electrical discharge phenomenon. But if that was the case, mankind
could protect itself against this cosmic scourge:
I say, jf these things are so, may not the knowledge of this power of
points be of use to mankind. in preserving houses, churches, ships &
cont. from the stroke of lightning, by directing us to fix on the
highest parts of those edifices, upright rods of iron made sharp as a
needle, and gilt to prevent rusting, and from the foot of those rods a
UNDERGROUND GAMES .203
wire down one of the shrouds of a ship, and down her side till it
reaches the water? Would not these pointed rods probably draw
the electrical fue silently out of a cloud before it came nigh enough to
strike, and thereby secure us from that most sudden and terrible
mischief?l6
clouds' electric charge into a Leyden jar; 'by the electric fire thus
obtained spirits were inflamed and other experiments performed'.
Such was the excitement caused all over the world that one of
Franklin's imitators, a certain Monsieur Richmann, was killed in St.
Petersburg by the lightning discharge he drew from a cloud. He was
worshipped as a hero and found many would-be imitators; among
them the German inventor Herr Boze. Even Joseph Priestley, one of
the great British scientists of the century, rhapsodized about 'the
sentiments of the magnanimous Mr. Boze, who with a truly philo-
sophic heroism, worthy of the renowned Empedocles, said he wished he
might die by the electric shock, that the account of his death might
furnish an article for the memoirs of the French Academy of Sciences.
But it is not given to every electrician to die the death of the justly
envied Riehmann.'17
There are two successive Eureka processes involved in this story. In
the first, the bisociative lmk was what Franklin called 'the power of
points'; it gave rise to the analogy: pointed finger discharges Leyden
jar, pointed rod discharges cloud. It may have been attained by ideation
on a relatively conscious level, probably with the aid of visual imagina-
tion. The second stroke of genius was the use of the kite to reach the
thunderbolt. It illustrates the argument I have put forward earlier in this
chapter: one can hardly say that a hidden analogy was pre-existent in the
universe between a kite used as a sail by a boy floating on a lake, and a
lightning conductor. What actually happened was that Franklin was
desperately searching for a means to make contact with a thundercloud,
thinking in habitual terms of tall spires, long iron rods, and perhaps the
Tower of Babel. But all these approaches proved impracticable, and the
matrix was blocked-until in a moment of lassitude and day-dreaming
the previously unrelated memory-train of swimming, egg-retrieving,
and kite-sailing was brought to bear on it.
The last example that I shall quote in this section is a particularly
impressive illustration of the unconscious in the role of matchmaker. I
am referring to the discovery, in 1920, of the chemical transmission of
nerve-impulses by Otto Loewi. Since the matter is somewhat technical,
I shall give a simplified account of it.
Before Loewi's discovery it was generally believed that nervous
control of bodily functions was exercised by a direct transmission of
electrical impulses from nerve-terminal to muscle or gland. But this
theory failed to account for the fact that the same type of electric
impulse travelling down a nerve had an excitatory effect on some
UNDERGROUND GAMES 2.05
organs, an inhibitory effect on others. Now certain drugs were known
to have precisely the same effect. In a discussion with a friend in r903,
it occurred to Loewi that the chemical agents which were contained in
these drugs may also be present at the nerve-terminals; the electric
impulse would initiate chemical action, which in its tum would act on
the muscle or gland. But Loewi could not think of an experimental
method to test the idea-and forgot it for the next seventeen years.
Fifteen years later, for quite different purposes, he designed an
experiment. He made preparations of two frogs' hearts which were kept
beating in salt solutions to see whether their activities gave out any
chemical substance. In the sequel he forgot all about the experiment.
Another two years passed until the critical event:
The story of this discovery shows that an idea may sleep for
decades in the unconscious mind and then suddenly return. Further,
it indicates that we should sometimes trust a sudden intuition without
too much scepticism. If carefully considered in the daytime, I would
undoubtedly have rejected the kind of experiment I performed. It
would have seemed likely that any transmitting agent released by a
nervous impulse would be in an amount just sufficient to influence
the effector organ. It would seem improbable that an excess that could
be detected would escape into the fluid which :6.lled the heart. It
was good fortune that at that moment of the hunch I did not think
but acted immediately.
For many years this nocturnal emergence of the design of the
crucial experiment to check the validity of a. hypothesis uttered
seventeen years earlier was a complete mystery.18
Let me briefly recapitulate the three stages of this drama. The first is
the sudden emergence, during a conversation in r903, of the hunch that
his problem could be solved by switching from a 'spark theory' to a
'soup theory' (in neurological jargon, 'spark' refers to electrical, 'soup'
to chemical transmission of nerve impulses). But a hunch of this kind
as often as not turns out to be a fallacious over-simplification; so the
idea went into the incubator for the next seventeen years, till r920.
Act Two. In r918, fifteen years after the hunch, Loewi performs
certain experiments for which purpose he has to design a technique
for the detection of fluids secreted by the frog's heart. He then forgets
all about it.
UNDERGROUND GAMES 207
Summary
NOTES
Top. 192. Jung's emphasis on the mandala as the symbol of the coincidencia
oppositorum concerns the reconciliation ofopposites in the fully integrated penon-
which is an altogether different question.
Top. zoz. Half a century earlier, the era.ck.lings and sparks produced by
rubbing a piece of amber had been compared to lightning and thunder by Wall,
a friend of Boyle's; but as the context shows, the comparison was meant in a
purely metaphorical way.
Top. zio. ' ••• Einstein has reported that his profound generalization con-
necting space and time occurred to him while he was sick in bed. Descartes is
said to have made his discoveries while lying in bed in the morning and both
Cannon and Poincare report having got bright ideas when lying in bed unable to
sleep-the only good thing to be said for insomnia! It is said that James Brindley,
the great engineer, when up against a difficult problem, would go to bed for
several days till it was solved. Walter Scott wrote to a friend:
' "The half-hour between waking and rising has all my life proved propitious
to a.ny task which was exercising my invention. ••• It was always when I first
opened my eyes that the desired ideas thronged upon me." ' {Beveridge, W. r. B.,
1950, pp. 73-4).
I
IX
THE SPARK AND THE FLAME
False Inspirations
I
have discussed the genesis of the Eureka act-the sudden shaking
together of two previously unconnected matrices; let us now tum
to the aftermath of it.
If all goes well that single, explosive contact will lead to a lasting
:fusion of the two matrices-a new synthesis will emerge, a further
advance in mental evolution will have been achieved. On the other
hand. the inspiration may have been a mirage; or premature; or not
sufficiently impressive to be believed in.
A stimulating inquiry by the American chemists Platt and Barker
showed that among those scientists who answered their questionnaire
eighty-three per cent claimed frequent or occasional assistance from
unconscious intuitions. But at the same time only seven pep cent among
them asserted. that their intuitions were always correct; the remainder
estimated the percentage of their 'false intuitions' variously at ten to
ninety per cent.
A false inspiration is not an ordinary error committed in the course
of a routine operation, such as making a mistake in counting. It is a kind
of inspired blunder which presents itself in the guise of an original
synthesis, and carries the same subjective conviction as Archimedes's
cry did. Let me quote Poincare once more:
The previous chapters may have given the mistaken impression that
the genius need only listen to his Socratian demon and all will be well.
But the demon is a great hoaxer-precisely because he is not bound by
the codes of disciplined thought; and every original thinker who relies,
as he must, on his unconscious hunches, incurs much greater risks to his
career and sanity than his more pedestrian colleagues. 'The world little
knows', wrote Faraday, 'how many of the thoughts and theories which
have passed through the mind of a scientific investigator have been
crushed in silence and secrecy; that in the most successful instances not
a tenth of the suggestions, the hopes, the wishes, the preliminary
conclusions have been realized.'2 Darwin, Huxley, and Planck, among
many others, made similar confessions; Einstein lost 'two years of hard
work' owing to a false inspiration. 'The imagination', wrote Beveridge,
'merely enables us to wander into the darkness of the unknown where,
by the dim light of the knowledge that we carry, we may glimpse
something that seems of interest. But when we bring it out and
examine it more closely it usually proves to be only trash whose
glitter had caught our attention. Imagination is at once the source of
all hope and inspiration but also of frustration. To forget this is to court
despair.'3
All through his life Kepler hoped to prove that the motions of the
planets round the sun obeyed certain musical laws, the harmonies of the
spheres. When he was approaching fifty, he thought he had succeeded.
The following is one of the rare instances on record of a genius des-
cribing the heady effect of a false inspiration-Kepler never discovered
that he was the victim of a delusion:
T. H. Huxley has said that the tragedies.of science are the slayings of
beautiful hypotheses by ugly facts. Against this tragedy, at least, the
artist seems to be immune. On the other hand, it is generally believed
that the scientist can at least rely on the verification of his intuitions by
experiment, whereas the artist has no such objective tests to decide
whether or not he should bum his manuscript, or slash his canvas to
pieces.
In fact, however, 'verification by experiment' can never yield
absoulte certainty, and when it comes to controversial issues the data
can usually be interpreted in more than one way. The history of
medicine is full of obvious and distressing examples of this. In physics
and chemistry too, the best we can do by so-called 'crucial experiments'
is to confirm a prediction-but not the theory on which the prediction
is based (see below, pp 27o-6); and scientific controversies about the
interpretation of experimental results have been just as passionate and
subjective as controversies between theologians or art critics. If a hunch
is drastically contradicted by experiment, it will of course be aban-
doned. But, by and large, scientists are inclined to trust their intuitions;
and if confronted with experiments which give ambiguous or diver-
gent results, either to declare-as Einstein once did-that 'the facts are
wrong'; or-as Hobbes did-that 'the instance is so particular and
singular, that' tis scarce worth our observing'; or to resort to the standard
phrase that the unfavourable experimental result is due 'to unknown
sources of error'-hoping that some day, somehow, it will all work out.
Modem theoretical physics lives to a large extent on that hope. Thus
verifiability is a matter of degrees, and neither the artist, nor the
scientist who tries to break new ground, can hope ever to achieve
absolute certainty.
Premature Linkages
This is actually not true, for the resulting curve will be a cycloid
resembling an ellipse-but the odd fact is that Copernicus had hit on the
ellipse which is the form of all planetary orbits-had arrived at it for the
wrong reasons and by faulty deduction-and having done so, promptly
dropped it: the passage is crossed out in the manuscript, and is not
contained inthe printed edition of the Revolutions. The history ofhuman
thought is full of triumphant eurekas; but only rarely do we hear of the
anti-climaxes, the missed opportunities, which leave no trace.
Kepler, too, nearly threw away the elliptic orbits; for almost three
yea.rs he held the solution in his hands-without seeing it. His conscious
mind refused to accept the 'cartload of dung' which the underground
had cast up. When the battle was over, he confessed: 'Why should I
mince my words? The truth of Nature, which I had rejected and
chased away, returned by stealth through the backdoor, disguising
itself to be accepted. Ah, what a foolish bird I have been!'&
Poor Kepler, he was even more foolish than he thought: he actually
discovered universal gravity-then rejected it. In the Preface to the
New Astronomy he explains that the tides are due to the attraction of the
moon, and describes the working of gravity-even that the attracting
force is proportionate to mass; but in the text of that book, and of all
subsequent works, he has-incredible as it sounds-completely for-
gotten all about it. I have given elsewhere a detailed account of this
remarkable case of snowblindness. 7
Galileo revolutionized astronomy by the use of the telescope; but he
refused to believe in the reality of comets and declared them to be
optical illusions. For he too believed that heavenly bodies must move
in perfect circles; and since comets moved in very elongated elliptical
orbits, they could not be heavenly bodies.
Freud's revered master, Professor Brucke at the Vienna Medicine
Faculty, discovered., in r849, a technique to illuminate the retina of the
eye; but the idea of observing the illuminated retina through a lens did
not occur to him! It was his friend Helmholtz who hit on the idea-
218 THE ACT OF CREATION
l-9 14 II8
2--0 25 272
2-6 14 446
3--0 20 8g6
3-6 26 1222
4--0 26 1540
4-6 32 1870
5--0 20 2072
5-6 27 2289
6-o 9 2562
The integration of the matrices is indicated not only by the steep rise
of the learning curve after the eighteenth month, but by the fuct that
from now on the child, of its own initiative> will point at a thing and
ask to be told its name. Delighted with its discovery, it sometimes
develops a veritable 'naming mania': it indicates an object, calls out its
name, or, if it has forgotten it, invents a name ofits own; for henceforth
a person or thing is fdt to be incomplete if it has no name attached to it.
Thus the dawn of symbol-consciousness is a gradual, cumulative
2.22 THE ACT OF CREATION
event; a kind of diluted Eureka process, spread out in time, because the
final integration can take place only when the child's mental organiza-
tion has attained sufficient maturity. But the same process may occur in
a telescoped, highly dramatized form in rare cases such as Helen Keller's.
The blind, deaf, and mute little girl was nearly seven when Miss
Sullivan took charge of her and taught her the first few words, c-a-k-e,
d-o-1-1, etc., by means of the manual alphabet, a kind of morse spelt by
finger-play. Since Helen was 'overripe' for learning a language, she
covered, within less than a month, the same ground which takes a
normal child about two years, from the imitative acquisition of the
first word ('I did not know that I was spelling a word or even that
words existed; I was simply making my fingers go in monkey-like
imitation')-to the :final discovery:
empirical induction: 'some things have names ergo I assume that all things
have names'. (Needless to say, I do noc mean to impute any conscious
reasoning of this kind to the babe in its cradle.) The chicle episode, on the
other hand, which made Pasteur jump to his conclusion and establish
the general principle of immunization, could be called 'induction from
a single case'-a procedure usually illustrated in primers on logic by the
example 'all French waiters have red hair'. For a detailed discussion of
the relations of gradual learning to sudden discovery I must refer the
reader to Book Two.
Summary
x
THE EVOLUTION OF IDEAS
also the century of the fatal misalliance between Aristotelian physics and
the theology of St. Thomas Aquinas. Within a few generations this
'faulty synthesis' was to create a new orthodoxy, which led to another
three centuries of sterility and stagnation.
Then comes A.D. 16oo-a landmark second in importance only to
6oo B.c.-which inaugurates the second heroic age of science: the
century of Dr. Gilbert, Kepler, Galileo, Pascal, Descartes, Leibniz,
Huyghens, Harvey, and Newton. In the next century, the eighteenth,
the speed of the advance is considerably reduced: it is a period of
assimilation, consolidation, and stock-taking, the age of the popular-
izers, classifiers, and systematizers; of Fontanelle, Linnaeus, and Buffon,
of the Philosophes and Encyclopedistes. As Pledge has remarked: 'An.
observer born early in the century, and making the Grand Tour,
would have been an old man before he came across, in the Paris of
Lavoisier, anyone worthy ofNewton.'4
Finally,in the nineteenth century and in the first half of the twentieth.,
we have an explosive development of ever-increasing momentum. The
nineteenth century was the age of the most spectacular syntheses in the
history of thought-of royal marriages between previously unrelated
and often hostile dynasties. The science of electricity merged with that
of magnetism.* Then electro-magnetic radiations were discovered to
account for light, colour, radiant heat, Hertzian waves. Chemistry was
swallowed up by atomic physics. The control of the body by nerves and
glands was seen to rely on electro-chemical processes. The previously
independent 'effluvia' or 'powers of nature' which had been known as
'heat', 'light', 'electric fire', 'mechanical motion', 'magnetic Bux' were
recognized to be all convertible one into another, and to be merely
different forms of 'energy', whose total amount contained in the
universe always remained the same. Soon afterwards, the various
forms of matter, the 'elements' of chemistry, suffered the same fate,
as they were all found to be constructed out of the same building blocks
in different combinations. An.cl lastly, these building blocks themselves
seemed to be nothing but parcels of compressed energy, packed and
patterned according to certain mathematical formulae.
The Pythagorean aspiration, to reduce 'all things to numbers',
seemed. to be at last on the point of fulfilment. The advance of science
in the last century offers the panorama of a majestic river-delta, where
the various branches first separate and diverge, then follow more or less
parallel courses, in a complex pattern of cross-connections and re-
unifications, as they approach their ultimate confluence in the sea.
Creative Anarchy
Even this short and breathless gallop through the twenty-SL"< centuries
since the dawn of scientific thought, ought to be sufficient to show that
the progress of science is neither gradual nor continuous. Each basic
advance was effected by a more or less abrupt and dramatic change:
the breaking down of frontiers between related territories, the amal-
gamation of previously separate frames of reference or experimental
techniques; the sudden falling into pattern of previously disjointed
data. Let me illustrate this process by a few further examples-no
longer of individual discoveries, but of episodes in the evolution of
the collective matrices of science.
In the recurrent cycle described in the previous section I mentioned
periods of crisis and creative anarchy (corresponding to the individual's
'period of incubation'), which precede the new synthesis. The first such
crisis occurred at the very beginning of our story when the ritualized
worship of the Olympian gods and demi-gods could no longer provide
answers to the ultimate questions after the meaning of existence.
Mythology had become a. 'blocked matrix'; from the whims of Vulcan
and Poseidon man's interest turned to the nature of fire and water;
from the chariot of Helios to the motions of the sun along the ecliptic;
from the antics of Zeus and Athena to the natural causes of physical
events. The result was intoxicating. To quote Burnet: 'No sooner did
an Ionian philosopher learn half a dozen geometrical propositions and
hear that the phenomena of the heavens recur in cycles than he set to
work to look for law everywhere in nature and with an audacity
a.mounting to hubris to construct a system of the universe. '5
The same audacity and hubris characterized the early seventeenth cen-
tury, when the stranglehold of the Aristotelian Schoolmen was broken,
and the solid, walled-in universe of the Middle Ages lay in shambles,
exposed to the speculatiye depradations of hosts of Paracelsians, Gilbert-
ians, Copernicans, and Galileans. ' 'Tis all in pieces, all coherence gone',
lamented John Donne; it must have been an intoxicating age to live in.
Lastly, since the discoveries of the 192os, theoretical physics, and with
it our picture of sub-atomic and extra-galactic reality, of substance and
causality, have again reverted to a state of creative anarchy. And so the
cycle keeps repeat:ipg itself:
But alas:
It did not last: the Devil howlmg 'Ho!
Let Einstein be!' restored the status quo.s-
Those who refuse to go beyond fact rarely get as far as fact; and
anyone who has studied the history of science knows that almost
every step therein has been made by ... the invention of a hypothesis
which, though verifiable, often had little foundation to start with ....
Sir Lawrence Bragg is the only physicist who shared a Nobel Prize
with his own father-for their joint work on analysing crystal
234 THE ACT OF CREATION
Without the hard little bits of marble which are called 'facts' or
'data' one cannot compose a mosaic; what matters, however, are not
so much the individual bits, but the successivepatterns into which you
arrange them, then break them up and rearrange them. 'We shall
find', wrote Butterfield on the opening page of his history of the
ScientificRevolution. 'that in both celestial and terrestrial physics-
which hold the strategic place in the whole movement-change is
brought about, not by new observationsor additional evidencein the
first instance,but by transpositionsthat were taking place inside the
minds of the scientiststhemselves.... Of all forms of mental activity,
the most difficultto induce even in the minds of the young, who may
be presumed not to have lost their flexibility,is the art of handling the
same bundle of data as before, but placing them in a new system of
relations with one another by giving them a differentframework. all
of which virtually means putting on a different kind of thinking-cap
for the moment. It is easy to teach anybody a new fact about Richelieu,
but it needs light from heaven to enable a teacher to break the old
framework in which the student has been accustomed to seeing his
Richelieu.'10
Once more we are facingthe stubborn powers of habit, and the anti-
thesis of habit and originality. New facts alone do not make a new
theory; and new facts alone do not destroy an outlived theory. In both
cases it requirescreativeoriginalityto achieve the task. The facts which
proved that the planetary motions depended on the sun have been
staring into the face of astronomers throughout the ages-but they
preferred to look away.
... The moon has a security against falhng in her very motion and
the swing of her revolutions.just as objects put in slings are prevented
from falling by the circular whirl;for everythi11g is carried along by the
motion natural to it if it is not deflected by anything else. Thus the moon
is not carried down by her weight because her natural tendency is
frustrated by her revolution.P (my italics)
Limits of Confirmation
From the days of Greece to the present that history echoes with the
sound and fury of passionate controversies. This fact in itself is sufficient
proof that the same 'bundle of data', and even the same 'crucial experi-
ment', can be interpreted in more than one way.
To mention only a few of the more recent among these historic
controversies: the cosmology of Tycho de Brahe explained the facts, as
they were known at the time, just as well as the system of Copernicus.
In the dispute between Galileo and the Jesuit Father Sarsi on the nature
of comets we now know that both were wrong, and that Galileo was
more wrong than his forgotten opponent. Newton upheld a corpus-
culary, Huyghens a wave-theory of light. In certain types of experiment
the evidence favoured Newton, in other types Huyghens; at present
we tend to believe that both are true. Leibniz derided gravity and
accused Newton of introducting 'occult qualities and miracles' into
science. The theories of Kekule and Van' t Hoff on the structure of
organic molecules were denounced by leading authorities of the period
as a 'tissue of fancies.'1' Liebig and Wohler-who had synthesized
urea from anorganic materials-were among the greatest chemists of
the nineteenth century; but they poured scom on those of their
colleagues who maintained that the yeast which caused alcoholic
fermentation consisted ofliving cellular organisms. They even went so
far as to publish, in 1839, an elaborate skit in the Annalen der Chemie, in
which yeast was described 'with a considerable degree of anatomical
r~ as consisting of eggs which developed into minute animals
THE EVOLUTION OP IDE.AS
And in the second place, the famous experiment did not in fact confirm,
but contradicted Einstein's theory. The speed of light was not at all the
same in all directions. Light-signals sent 'ahead' along the earth's orbit
travelled slower than signals 'left behind'. It is true that the difference
amounted to only about one-fourth of the magnitude to be expected
on the assumption that the earth was drifting through a stationary
ether. But the 'ether-drift' still amounted to the respectable velocity of
about five miles per second. The same results were obtained by D. C.
Miller and his collaborators, who repeated the Michelson-Morley
experiments, with more precise instruments, in a series of experiments
extending over twenty-five years (1902 to 1926). The rest of the story
is best told by quoting Polanyi again:
Fashions in Science
Far from being hypnotized with the idea that micro-organisms are
the only factors of importance in medicine, Pasteur knew that men
as well a.s animals, in health or in disease, must always be considered
as a whole a.nd in relation to their environment .... In all bis public-
cations •.. he repeatedly stated the thesis-almost as an obsession-
. that the activities of micro-organisms can be controlled, not only by
acting on them directly, but also by modifying the environment in
which they operate.lD
Boundaries of Sdence
really but a handful.' wrote Francis Bacon, 'the invention of all causes
and all sciences would be a labour of but a few years.'
Within a generation after Haeckel had proclaimed that the Riddles
of the Universe had been solved, nearly all the solutions turned out
to be spurious. In 1925 Whitehead wrote that the physical theory of
matter 'got into a state which is strongly suggestive of the epicycles
of astronomy before Copernicus'; in the lifetime of the next genera-
tion it became a welter of paradoxa, compared to which the universe
of rotating crystal spheres had been a model of sanity.
I have written elsewhere about the great vanishing act which accom-
panied the process of unification in science. It started when Galileo
discarded colour, sound, smell, and taste as illusions of the senses which
could all be reduced to the 'primary qualities' of physics, to matter
and motion. But one after another these 'ultimate and irreducible'
entities vanished to the tune of the 'Ten Little Nigger Boys'. First the
indivisible atom went up in fireworks, then the atomic nucleus, then
the 'elementary particles' in the nucleus; matter evaporated in the
physicists' hands, and its ultimate constituents joined dectricity, mag-
netism, and gravity as manifestations of excited states of':6.dds' which
could be described only in mathematical terms. Theoretical physics is
no longer concerned with things, but with the mathematical relations
between abstractions which are the residue of the vanished things. To
quote Russell: 'Physics is mathematical not because we know so much
about the physical world, but because we know so little; it is only its
mathematical properties that we can discover.'
For three centuries the reduction of qualities to quantities bas been
spectacularly successful, and it was reasonable to hope that within a
generation or two the supreme synthesis which would enable us to
reduce all phenomena in the physical world to a few basic mathe-
matical formulae-something of the nature of the Unified Fidd
Theory on which Einstein worked, unsuccessfully, throughout the
second half of his life. It is still not unlikdy that this hope was well
founded, that in the foreseeable future subatomic physics will strike
rock bottom as it were, and obtain the answers to the questions it has
asked. But it is becoming increasingly evident that both the questions
and. the answers of contemporary physics are couched in an elusive
symbol-language which has only a very indirect bearing on reality,
and has little to offer to satisfy man's craving for glimpses of the ulti
mate truth. Eddington realized long ago that these symbols 'have as
much resemblance to the real qualities of the material world ••• as
THE ACT OF CREATION
He said, that new Systems of Nature were but new Fashions, which
would vary in every Age; and even those who pretend to demon-
strate them from Mathematical Principles, would flourish but a short
Period of Time, and be out of Vogue when that was determined.s?
Perhaps that saturation point is not far away, and perhaps science
will then start asking a new type of question. One branch after another
of chemistry, physics, and cosmology has merged in the majestic river
as it approaches the estuary-to be swallowed up by the ocean, lose
its identity, and evaporate into the clouds; the final act of the great
vanishing process, and the beginning, one hopes, of a new cycle. It
has been said that we know more and more about less and less. It
seems that the more universal the 'laws' which we discover, the more
elusive they become, and that the ultimate conswn.mation of all rivers
of knowledge is in the cloud of unknowing.
Thus, contrary to appearances and beliefs, science, like poetry or
architecture or painting, has its genres, 'movements', schools, theories
which it pursues with increasing perfection until the level of saturation
is reached where all is done and said-and then embarks on a new
approach, based on a different type of curiosity, a different scale of
values. Not only Newton, but Leonardo, Mozart, and Flaubert saw
further because they too stood on the shoulders of giants; and Ein
stein's space is no closer to reality than Van Gogh's sky. The glory of
science is not in a truth 'more absolute' than the truth of Bach or
Tolstoy, but in the act of creation itself The scientist's discoveries
impose his own order on chaos, as the composer or painter imposes
his; an order that always refers to limited aspects of reality, and is
biassed by the observer's frame of reference, which differs from period
to period, as a Rembr:mdt nude differs from a nude by Manet.
Summary
artistic statements .is a matter of degree (see also below, Chap. XVII).
Some scientific controversies are decided by cumulative weight of
evidence; others are resolved by a synthesis embracing both competing
theories; but still others are pseudo-controversies reflecting differences
in emphasis and fashions of thought-and the latter are often as sub-
jective and emotional as fashions in art.
Lastly, a distinction should be made between progress in the pre-
cision of scientific statements and their explanatory power. The latter
depends on the type of question the statement is meant to answer; and
history shows that the questions change with the changing values in
different periods and cultures.
NOTES
Top. aa8. See Appendix I.
Top. :z30. Bronowski (1961), p.27. Cf. also: 'The most fortunate moments
in the history of knowledge occur when facts which have been as yet no more
than special data arc suddenly referred to other apparently distant facts, and thus
appear in a new light' (Wolfgang Kohler, 1940, p.89).
XI
SCIENCE AND EMOTION
Three Character-Types
I must, before I die, £nd some means of saying the essential thing
which is in me, which I have not yet said, a thing which is neither
love nor hate nor pity nor scorn but the very breath of life, shining
and coming from afar, which will link into human life the immensity,
the frightening, wondrous an'cl implacable forces of the non-
human.10
The historical causes which led to the split between the two cultures
SCIENCE AND EMOTION
are outside the scope of this book; but I must mention one specific
factor which is largely responsible for turning science into a bore, and
providing the humanist with an excuse for turning his back on it. It
is the academic cant, of relatively recent origin, that a self-respecting
scientist must be a bore, that the more dehydrated the style of his
writing, and the more technical the jargon he uses, the more respect he
will command. I repeat, this is a recent fashion, less than a century old,
but its effect is devastating. The pre-Socratics frequently wrote their
treatises in verse; the ancient Peruvian language had a single word-
hamavec-for both poet and inventor. Galileo's Dialogues and polemical
writings were literary masterpieces which had a lasting influence on
the development of Italian didactic prose; Kepler's New Astronomy is
a baroque tale of suspense; Vesalius' Anatomy was illustrated by
a pupil of Titian. Even the abstract symbol language of the mathe-
maticians lent itself to works of art. As the great Boltzmann wrote:
'A mathematician will recognize Cauchy, Gauss, Jacobi, or Helm-
holtz, after reading a few pages, just as musicians recognize, from the
first few bars, Mozart, Beethoven, or Schubert.' And Jeans compared
Maxwell's physics with an enchanted fairyland where no one knew
what was coming next.
I have given samples of Pasteur's and Poincare's style; Franklin was
an accomplished stylist; Maxwell wrote commendably funny,* and
Erasmus Darwin unintentionally funny verse; as for William James, I
must confess that I find his style far more enjoyable than his brother
Henry's. In our present century Eddington, Jeans, Freud, Kretschmer,
Whitehead, Russell, Schrodinger, to mention only a few, gave con-
vincing proof that works on science can at the same time be works of
literary art. (One could also quote works by literary and art critics as
pedantic and desiccated as papers in a technical journal for applied
chemistry.) Needless to say, technical communications addressed to
specialists must employ technical language; but even here the over-
loading with jargon, the tortuous and cramped style, are largely a
matter of conforming to fashion.
The same inhuman-in fact anti-humanistic-trend pervades the
climate in which science is taught, the classrooms and the textbooks.
To derive pleasure from the art of discovery, as from the other arts,
the consumer-in this case the student-must be made to re-live, to
some extent, the creative process. In other words, he must be induced,
with proper aid and guidance, to make some of the fundamental dis
coveries of science by himself; to experience in his own mind some of
THE ACT OF CREATION
those flashes of insight which have lightened its path. This means that
the history of science ought to be made an essential part of the curricu-
lum, that science should be represented in its evolutionary context-
and not as a Minvera born fully armed. It further means that the
paradoxes, the 'blocked matrices' which confronted Archi.medes,
Copernicus, Galileo, Newton, Harvey, Darwin, Einstein should be
reconstructed in their historical setting and presented in the form of
riddles-with appropriate hints-to eager young minds. The most
productive form of learning is problem-solving (Book Two, XIlI-
XIX). The traditional method of confronting the student not with the
problem but with the finished solution, means depriving him of all
excitement, to shut off the creative impulse, to reduce the adventure of
mankind to a dusty heap of theorems.
Art is a form of communication which aims at eliciting a re-creative
echo. Education should be regarded as an art, and use the appropriate
techniques of art to call forth that echo. The novice, who has gone
through some of the main stages in the evolution of the race during his
pre-natal development, and of the evolution from savage to civilized
society by the time he reaches adolescence, should then be made to
continue his curriculum by re-capitulating some of the decisive episodes,
impasses, and turning points on the road to the conquest of knowledge.
Our textbooks and methods of teaching reflect a static, pre-evolu-
tionary concept of the world. For man cannot inherit the past; he has
to re-create it.
Summary
money or favours from the tyrant of Syracuse, his jubilant shout was
certainly not due to anticipation of the reward.
Ambition, greed, vanity can enter the service of creativity only
through indirect channels; and the self-transcending emotions must
undergo a similar process of sublimation from mystic immersion in
the harmony of the spheres to the scrupulous attention paid to eight
minutes arc. The process is reflected. in the gradual transformation of
magic into science.
The creative achievements of the scientist lack the 'audience appeal'
of the artist's for several reasons briefly mentioned-technical jargon,
antiquated. teaching methods, cultural prejudice. The boredom created
by these factors has accentuated the artificial frontiers between con-
tinuous domains of creativity.
NOTE
To page 26.5: Sec Appendix ll, p. 691.
I
PART THREE
THE ARTIST
A. THE PARTICIPATORY EMOTIONS
XII
THE LOGIC OF THE MOIST EYE
Laughter and Weeping
Why do we Weep?
Let me discuss a few typical situations which may cause the shedding
of tears.
A. Raptness. Listening to the organ in a cathedral, looking at a
majestic landscape from the top of a mountain. observing an infant
hesitantly returning a smile, being in love-any of these experiences
may cause a welling-up of emotions, a moistening or overflowing of
the eyes, while the body is becalmed and drained ofits tensions. A few
steps higher on the intensity-scale, and the 'I' seems no longer to exist,
to dissolve in the experience like a grain of salt in water; awareness
becomes de-personalized and expands into 'the oceanic feeling of
limitless extension and oneness with the universe',"
Here, then, we see the self-transcending emotions displayed in their
purest form. Once you start fond.ling the smiling baby and making a
fuss of it, an active, possessive element enters into the situation and the
spell is broken. The purely self-transce11ding emotions do not tend towards
action, but towards quiescence, tranquillity, and catharsis. Respiration and
pulse-rate are slowed down, muscle-tone is lowered; 'entrancement'
is a step towards the trance-like states induced by the contemplative
techniques of Eastern mysticism and by certain drugs. The experience
of'the blending of the finite with the infurlte' can become so intense
that it evokes Faust's prayer: 0 Augenblick verweile-kt this moment
last for eternity, let me die. But there is nothing morbid in this; it
is a yearning for an even more complete communion, the ultimate
catharsis or samadhi.
The reason for their passive, quietistic nature is that the self-trans--
cen.d.ing emotions cannot be consummated by any sped.fie volunttZT}' action.
You cannot take the mountain panorama home with you; the surest
method to break the charm is clicking your camera. You cannot merge
with the infuiite or dissolve in the universe by any exertion of the
body; and even in the most selBess forms oflove and communion each
individual remains an island. To be 'overwhelmed.' by love, wonder,
devotion, 'enraptured.' by a smile, 'entranced' by beautyeach verb
274 THE ACT OF CREATION
C. Relief. A woman whose son has been reported by the War Office
as missing suddenly sees him walking into her room, safe and sound.
Again the first reaction is shock and rigidity; then she flings herself
into his arms, alternately laughing and weeping.
Obviously there are two processes involved here. The first is the
sudden, dramatic relief from anxiety; the other an overwhelm.ingjoy,
love, tendemess. Some writers on the subject are apt to confuse these
two reactions-to regard all joyous emotion as due to relief from
anxious tension. But clearly a tender reaction would be expected in
any case from the mother on her son's return-even if he were merely
returning from a day at school, and there had been no previous
amciety. Vice versa. relief from anxiety in itse1£ though always
pleasant, does not create tender feelings overflowing in tears. What
happened in the present case is that the agony the woman endured. had
· increased the intensity of her yearning and love; and that relief from
amdety had increased. out of all proportion the gratification she
THE I.OGIC OF THE MOIST EYE 277
would have felt on his return after an absence under normal circum-
stances.
Let me be a little more explicit-for the situation has, as we shall
see, a direct bearing on the emotional reactions induced by works of
dramatic art. The mother's sudden relief from anxiety could be ver-
balized as 'thank God you are not dead'. Up to that moment she had
tried to control her fears, to banish from consciousness the terrible
images of what may have been happening to her boy. Now she can
let herself go, allow her emotions a free outlet. Hence the manic dis-
play of hugging, bustling, laughing, calling in the neighbours, and
upsetting the tea kettle: she is working off the adrenalin of all that
pent-up and suddenly released anxiety. But in the middle of these
hectic activities there are moments when she glances at the embarrassed
prodigal with a kind of incredulous, rapt expression and her eyes again
overflow with soothing, peaceful tears. The alternation and over-
lapping of the two patterns-one eruptive and agitated. the other
gradual and cathartic-indicate the now familiar two processes and
the nature of the emotions acted out.
These become even more evident in exclamations such as 'How silly
of me to cry', followed by more bustling and merriment. The unex-
pected return of the boy was like a the 'bolt out of the blue' which cut
short the tense narrative of her anxious fantasies; the tension has sud-
denly become redundant, and is disowned by reason. At other moments
she is still unable 'to believe her eyes' and emotion wells up again. This
may even include some unconscious resentment against the cause of so
much needless worry, who stands in her room, sunbumt and grinning,
unaware of the suffering he has caused: 'What a fool I have been to
worry so much' may betral.tSlatedas 'What a fool you have made ofme'.
'Laughing through one's tears' is caused by quickly oscillating mental
states, where reason and emotion are altematdy united and c1issociatcd.
A sudden shock which demands a major emotional readjustment is
often followed by such oscilatory phases in which the subject alr.cr-
nately believes and disbelieves her eyes, until a full grasp of reality is
reached on all levels. If instead of the happy ending, there had been a
tragic one-a telegram informing the woman ofher boy's death-th~
instead of disbelieving her eyes, she would have been tempted to dis-
believe the news; and while the happy mother behaves at moments as
if the boy were still in danger, the bereaved mother may beha.vc at
times as ifhe were still alive. Inthe former case, the successive flashes of
reality which disrupt the web of illusion bring happy relief; in the
THE ACT OP CREATION
'Great pain', wrote Darwin, 'urges all animals, and has urged them
during endless generations, to make the most violent and diversi-
fied efforts to escape from the cause of sufferings. Even when a limb
or other separate part of the body is hurt, we often see a tendency to
shake it as if to shake off the cause, though this obviously be im
possible. Thus a habit of exerting with the utmost force all the
muscles will have been. established whenever great suffering is
experienced.'3
Cannon has shown that the Bodily Changes in Pain, Hunger, Fear, and
Rage (the title of his classic work) all follow the same basic pattern,
that they are emergency responses of the sympathico-adrenal system.
Violent pain seems to be experienced by the unconscious mind as an
aggression, whether it is inflicted by an outside agent or not. When
the aggressor is a tooth or a cramp in the stomach we are apt to say 'it
hurts', as if the offending organ were not part of oneself and we try
to shake the aggressor off; as animals do, by writhing, or pressing
against i~. Only when the pain has abated to a tolerably steady, 'dull'
level do we accept it as part of ourselves-we 'have' a headache or 'are'
wider the weather-at the same time admitting that nothing can be
done about it; writhing and struggling cease in the admission of defeat,
THE LOGIC OF THE MOIST EYE 281
'All the viscera can. be infiuenced simultaneously in one direction or the other
by varying, up or down., the ••• tonic activity of the sympathetic division. And
any special viscw can be sq,arately i.nfiuenced ••• by varying ••• the tonic
activity of the special nerve of the opposed cranial or sacral [parasympathetic J
division. .•. The sympathetic is like the loud and soft pedals, modulating all the
notes together; the cranial and sacral [parasympathetic] innervations arc like the
separate keys.' (Cannon, 19.29, zad, ed.)
In the years since this has been written the significance for psychology of the
anatomical and physiological contrast between the two branches of the auto-
nomic nervous system has become more evident, to the extent that 'rage is
called the most adrenergic, and love the most cholinergic reaction' (Cobb, 1950).
A further correspondence between patterns of emotive behaviour and modes of
interaction between the two branches of the autonomic nervous system emerged
when it was shown that the vagoinsulin system may act, in different circum-
stances, as an inhibitory or a catalytic agent in the glucose-utilization process
and may also produce overcompensatory after effects (Gellhom, 1943, and 1957).
Hebb (1949) suggested that a distinction should be made between two categories
of emotions, 'those in which the tendency is to maintain or increase the original
stimulating conditions (pleasmable or integrative emotions)' and 'those in which
the tendency is to abolish or decrease the stimulus (rage, fear, disgust)". Whcxcas
the latter have a disruptive effect on cortical behaviour, the former have not. A
few years later, Olds (1959 and 1960) and othen demonstrated the existence of
'positive' and '.negative' emotive systems by electric stimulation, and further
showed that they were activated respectively by the parasympathetic and sym-
pathetic centres in the hypothalamus.
These hints all seem to point in the same direction, but in fairness to the
general reader I ought to point out that, while there is ample experimental
proof that the hunger-rage-fear emotions are mediated by the sympathieo,-
adrenal division, there is no direct evidence for the symmetrical correlation pro-
posed here. Such proof can be forthcoming only when emotions outside the
hunger-rage-fear class will be recognizec:l as a worthwhile object of study by a·
perimental psychology-which at present is not the case:
283
THB ACT OF CREATION
•
XIII
PARTNESS AND WHOLENESS
Stepchildren of Psychology
NOT.ES
Top. 285. I am using 'self-transcending emotions' as a short-hand expres-
sion for 'emotion.al states in which the self--tta!l.SCCncling tendencies dominate'.
Top. 290. In the only excursion into science fiction of which I am guilty. I
made a visiting maiden from an alien planet explain the basic doctrine of its
quasi-Kcplerian religion:
• •.. We worship gravitation. It is the only force which does not travel
thtough. space in a rush; it is everywhere in repose. It keeps the stars in their
orbits and our feet on our catth. It is Nature's fear of loneliness, the earth's
longing for the moon; it is love in its pare. inorganic form.' ( Twilight Bar, 1945.)
•
XIV
ON ISLANDS AND WATERWAYS
I
n the chapter on the 'Logic of the Moist Eye' I have discussed
weeping as a manifestation of frustrated participatory emotions.
Let me now briefly consider the normal manifestations of this
class of emotions in childhood and adult life.
As Freud, Piaget, and others have shown, the very young child does
not differentiate between ego and environment. The mother's breast
seems to it a more intimate possession than the toes on its own body.
It is aware of events, but not for a long time of itself as a separate
entity. It lives in a state of mental symbiosis with the outer world, a
continuation of the biological symbiosis in the womb, a state which
Piaget calls 'protoplasmic consciousness'.1 The universe is focussed
on the self, and the self is the universe; the outer environment is only
a kind of second womb.
From this original state of protoplasmic or symbiotic consciousness,
the development towards autonomous individuation is slow, gradual,
and will never be entirely completed. The initial state of consciousness
may be likened to a liquid, fluid universe traversed by dynamic currents,
by the rhythmic rise and fall of physiological needs, causing minor
storms which come and go without leaving any solid traces. Gradually
the floods recede and the first islands of objective reality emerge; their
contours grow firmer and sharper and are set off against the undifferen-
tiated flux. The islands are followed by continents, the dry territories
of reality are mapped out; but side by side with them the liquid world
co-exists, surrounding it, interpen.etrating it by canals and inland
lakes, the relics of the erstwhile oceanic communion. In the words of
Freud:
the handle bas struck your palm, but that its head has struck the nail,
as if the hammer bad become part of your body.' These are not in
ventions of psychologists to make the simple appear as complicated,
but examples of our tendency to confuse what happens in the self
with what happens outside it-a kind of'perceptual symbiosis' between
ego and environment.
Projective empathy-again.in a technical sense-is based on a similar
confusion: an arrow drawn on paper is fdt to manifest a dynamic
tendency to move (probably a consequence of our own unconscious
eye-movements); a church spire seems to 'soar' upwards, a picture has
'movement' and 'balance', and so on. Not only motions, but emotions
too are projected from the self into lifeless objects; my car, climbing a
bill, 'groans' and 'pants' under its 'effort'; the weeping willow weeps,
the thunder growls. The tendency to animism, to project unconsciously
life and feeling into inanimate bodies, is well-nigh irresistible-witness
the two millennia of Aristotelian physics; we can only conclude that
it is a basic feature of our psychic make-up.
Equally inveterate is the tendency to project our own emotions into
other living beings-animals and people. The first leads to anthro-
pomorphism-ascribing to our pet dogs, horses, and canaries reasoning
processes modelled on our own; the second to what one might call
'egomorphism' -the illusion that others must fed on any subject
exactly as I do. A more complicated projective transaction is trans-
ference-where A projects his feelings, originally aimed at B, on to a
substitute, C: a father figure, sister figure, or what have you, each
further transferable to D, E, etc. The Who's Who of the subconscious
seems to be printed with coloured inks on blotting paper.
lntrojection is meant to signify the reverse of projection, though the
two phenomena are often indistinguishable from each other.* When
somebody bangs his head on the doorpost, I wince; when a forward
in a soccer game has a favourable opportunity to shoot, I kick my
neighbour's shin. Adolescents unconsciously ape their hero's man-
nerisms; our super-egos were supposedly moulded by our parents at a
time when the self was still in a fluid state. Throughout bis life, the
individual keeps introjecting chunks and patterns of other people's
existence into bis own; he suffers and enjoys vicariously the emotions
of those with whom be becomes entangled in identificatory rapports.
Some of these personality-transactions have lasting effects; others are
,nore transitory, but at the same time more dramatic. Laughter and
yawning have an instantly infectious effect; so have cruelty, hysteria,
ON ISLANDS AND WATERWAYS
Summary
infancy, with its fluid ego boundaries, is partly relegated to the sub-
conscious strata-from which the artist and the mystic draw their
inspirations; partly superseded by the phenomena of projection and
introjection, empathy and identification, transference and hypnosis.
Similarly, the participatory bonds of primitive magic are gradually
transformed into symbolic rituals, mythological epics, and mystery
plays: into the magic of illusion. The shadows in Plato's cave are
symbols of man's loneliness; the paintings in the Lascaux caves are
symbols of his magic powers.
The participatory emotions, like their opposites, can be accom-
panied by feelings of pleasure or un-pleasure which form a con-
tinuous scale, and add a third dimension to emotional experience.
Lastly, identification, in itself a self-transcending experience, can serve
as a vehicle (or trigger) for vicarious emotions of anger and fear.
NOTES
Top. z94. The point has been succinctly made by Walter de la Mare:
It's a very odd thing
As odd as can be-
That whatever Miss T. eats
Turns into Miss T.
Top. 296. 'In relation to the dissclution of the ego complex, identification
can receive a somewhat di1ferent interpretation according as ego-components are
projected into the outside world or as clements from the outside world arc in
corporated into the personality. In very fluid dream processes such a distinction
cannot usually be very accurately drawn; but in schizophrenia. for example. both
possibilities can be most clearly experienced.' (Kretschmer, I954, p. 93.)
Top. 297. The expression 'lowest common denominator• h mathematically
nonsensica1; it should, of course, be 'highest'. But the 'highest common deno-
minator• in a crowd of large numbers is still pretty low; thus the faulty idiom
conveys the tight idea, and the correct expression would only create confusion.
•
B. VERBAL CREATION
xv
ILLUSION
The Power of Illusion
person, knowing all the time that he faces a screen onto which shadows
are projected by a machine, and knowing furthermore quite well what
is going to happen at the end-for instance, that the police will arrive
just in the nick of time to save the hero-should nevertheless go through
agonies of suspense, and display the corresponding bodily symptoms.
It is even more remarkable that this capacity for living intwo universes
at once, one real, one imaginary, should be accepted without wonder
as a. commonplace phenomenon. The following extract from a London
newspaper report may help to restore our sense of wonder: 1
Moreover, when one of the seven houses on the set became 'vacant'
because its owner was said to have moved-in fact because the actor
in question had been dropped from the programme-there were several
applications for renting the house; and when at a dramatic moment of
the serial the barmaid in the 'Rover's Return' smashed an ornamental
plate, several viewers sent in replacements to comfort her.
Of course, these people know that they are watching actors. Do they
nevertheless believe that the characters are real? The answer is neither
yes nor no, but yes and no. The so-cal1ed law of contradiction in
logic-that a thing is either A or not-A but cannot be both-is a late
acquisition in the growth of individuals and cultures (Book Two,
XV). The unconscious mind, the mind of the child and the primi-
tive, are indifferent to it. So are the Eastern philosophies which teach
the unity of opposites, as well as Westem theologians and quantum
physicists. The addicts of Coronation Street who insist on believing in
the reality of Ena Sharples have merely carried one step further the
momentary split-mindedness experienced by a sophisticated movie-
audience at the climax of a Hitchcock thriller; they live in a more or
less permanently bisociated world.
But where does beauty, aesthetic value, or 'art' enter into the process?
The answer requires several steps. The first is to recognize the in-
trinsic value of illusion in itself It derives from the transfer of attention
from the 'Now and Here' to the 'Then and There' -that is, to a
plane remote from self-interest. Self-assertive behaviour is focussed. on
the Here and Now; the transfer of interest and emotion to a different
time and location is in itself an act of self-transcendence in the literal
sense. It is achieved through the lure of heroes and victims on the
stage who attract the spectator's sympathy, with whom he partially
identifies himself, and for whose sake he temporarily renounces his
preoccupations with his own worries and desires. Thus the act of
participating in an illusion has an inhibiting effect on the self-asserting
tendencies, and facilitates the unfolding of the self-transcending ten-
dencies. In other words illusion has a cathartic effect-as all ancient and
modern civilizations recognized by incorporating various forms of
magic into their purification-rites and abreaction therapies.
It is true that illusion, from Greek tragedy to horror comics, is also
THE ACT OF CREATION
rain-god, and yet remained the shaman at the same time. From the
stag dances of the Huichol Indians or the serpent dances of the Zuni,
there is only one step to the goat dance of the Achaeans, the precursor
of Greek drama. 'Tragedy' means 'goat-song' (tragos-he goat, oide-
song); it probably originated in the ceremonial rites in honour of
Dyonysius, where the performers were disguised in goat-skins as
satyrs, and in the related ceremonies in honour of Apollo and Demeter.
Indian and Chinese stage craft have similarly religious origins. Etruscan
drama derived from funeral rites; modem European drama evolved
from the medieval mystery plays performed on the occasion of the
main church festivals. But though the modem theatre hardly betrays
its religious ancestry, the magic of illusion still serves essentially the
same emotional needs: it enables the spectator to transcend the narrow
confines of his personal identity, and to participate in other forms of
existence. For-to quote for a last ti.me the unfashionable Levy-Brohl,
to whom Freud, Jung, and others owe so much:
•
I
XVI
RHYTHM AND RHYA1E
Pulsation
However, unlike the beat of the tom-tom, or the rattle of the car-
riage wheels, a strophe of verse does not consist in a simple repetitive
rhythm, but in complex patterns of short and long, stressed and light
syllab~ further complicated by super-imposed patterns of assonance
or rhyme. As music has evolved a long way from the simple, repetitive
314 THE ACT OF CREATION
Compulsive Punning
operator ask for a Tupfer [tampon] he burst into uTupfer ... Tupfer,
Hupfer, Hupfer, hupfen Sie mal ••. " On hearing the word Messer, he
burst into "Messer, messer, Metzer, Sie sind ein Metzel, das ist ja ein
Gemetxel, metzeln Sie doch nicht so messen Sie doch Sie messen ja nicht
Herr Professor, profiteor, professus sum, profiteri." These manic responses
were dependent on manipulation of the tumour and could be elicited
only from the Boor of the third ventricle. '3
Forster's patient opened up a curious insight into the processes in
the poet's brain-in an unexpectedly literal sense of the word. The
first Bight of ideas, Tupfer, Hi1pfer, etc.-'tampon, jumper, go and
jump into the air'-has a gruesome kind of humour coming from a
man tied face down to the operating table with his skull open. The
second flight, translated, runs as follows: Messer, Metzer, etc.-'Knife,
butcher, you are a butcher in a butchery; truly this is a massacre
[Gemetzel]; don't go on butchering [metzeln], take measurements
[messen]; why don't you measure, Herr Professor, profiteor, professus sum,'
and so on.
Thus the patient's apparently delirious punning and babbling con-
vey a meaningfulmessage to the surgeon-his fear of being butchered,
and his entreaty that the surgeon should proceed by careft.il measure-
ments, that is, in a more cautious, circumspect way. His train of
thought seems to move under dual control. It is controlled by allitera-
tion and assonance-for he has regressed to the level of sound-associa-
tion and must abide by its rules. But it is also controlled by his inter-
mittent, rational awareness of his situation on the operating table.
Without this, his Bight of words would become meaningless (and does
so at times). Without the tyranny of the other code, he would address
the surgeon in simple, sensible prose. As it is, he must serve both masters
at the same time.*
Let us take a blasphemous short-cut from patient to poet. We have
seen that the creative act always involves a regression to earlier, more
primitive levels inthe mental hierarchy, while other processes continue
simultaneously on the rational surface-a condition that reminds one
of a skin-diver with a breathing-tube. (Needless to say, the exercise
has its dangers: skin-divers are prone to fall victims to the 'rapture of
the deep' and tear their breathing-tubes off-the reculer sans sauter of
William Blake and so many others. A less fatal professional disease
is the Bends, a punishment for attempting to live on two different
levels at once.)
Coaxing the Unconscious
..• I could no more define poetry than a terrier can define a rat,
but we both recognize the object by the symptoms which it pro-
vokes in us. One of these symptoms was described in connection
with another object by Eliphazthe Temanite: 'A spirit passedbefore
my face: the hair of my flesh stood up.' Experience has taught me,
when I am shaving of a morning, to keep watch over my thoughts,
because,if a line of poetry strays into my memory, my skin bristles
so that the razor ceases to act. This particular symptom is accom-
panied by a shiver down the spine..•. I think that the production
of poetry, in its first stage,is less an activethan a passiveand involun-
tary process;and ifl were obliged, not to definepoetry, but to name
the class of things to which it belongs, I should call it a secretion;
whether a natural secretion, like turpentine in the fir, or a morbid
secretion,like the pearl in the oyster. I have seldom written poetry
unlessI was rather out of health, and the experience,though pleasur-
able, was generally agitating and exhausting.'
The sceptical reader may object that all these metaphors about the
blindfold poet thinking in his marrow-bones while secreting pearls
like an oyster, reflect a too romantic view of the profession; and that
I have put altogether too much emphasis on the role of the uncon-
scious. The answer is partly to be found in the chapter on 'Thinking
Aside', which shows that the unconscious is neither a romantic nor a
mystic &ncy, but a working concept in the absence of which nearly
every event of mental life would have to be regarded as a miracle.
There is nothing very romantic about the wheels of the railway carriage
screaming 'I told you so'; it is simply an observed fact.
In the second place, though unconscious processes cannot be
governed by conscious volition, they can at least be coaxed into
activity by certain tricks acquired at the price of a little patience.
Friedrich Schiller learned to get himself into a creative frame of mind
by smelling rotten apples, Turgenev by keeping his feet in a bucket
of hot water, Balzac by drinking poisonous quantities of black coffee;
for lesser mortals even a pipe or pacing up and down in the study
might do.
And lastly, there is the long process of conscious elaboration-of
cutting, grinding, polishing the rough stone which inspiration has un-
earthed. Here the range of variations from one writer to another-
and from one work to another by the same writer-is as enormous
as with the daboration and formulation of a 'nuclear discovery in
science. An excellent account of this process is to be fotm.d in an essay,
far too little known, by A. E. Housman from which I have already
quoted:
NOTE
To. p. 316. Less dramatic than Forster's syndrome but equally convincing
were experiments by Luria and Vinagradova, which demonstrated that subjects
who normally associated words by their meaning regressed to association by
sound when they were made drowsy by chloral hydrate (Br. ]. of Psychol.,
May, I9S9),
I
XVII
IMAGE
The Hidden Analogy
I
n Chapters VII-VITI I have spoken at length of the close related-
ness between the scientist seeing an analogy where nobody saw one
before, and the poet's discovery of an original metaphor or simile.
Both rely on the mediation of unconscious processes to provide the
analogy. In the scientist's Eureka process two previously unconnected
frames of reference are made to intersect, but the same description may
be applied to the poet's trouvaille-the discovery of a felicitous poetic
comparison. The difference between them is in the character of the
'frames of reference', which in the first case are of a more abstract, in
the second of a more sensuous nature; and the criteria of their validity
clift"er accordingly. But the difference, as we have seen, is a matter of
degrees; and oft.en the two overlap. The discovery of perspective and
fore-shortening, for instance, belongs to both geometrical science and
representative art; it establishes formal analogies between two-dimen-
sional and three-dimensional space, but at the same time has a direct
sensory impact.
Here is another example which I have already mentioned-the
account, by one of Freud's earlier biographers, of how the master
suddenly hit upon the idea of the sublimation of instinct:
The two cartoons provided the hidden (though not all to deeply
bidden) analogy for the Eureka process. But vice versa, the two
320
IMA GB 32I
Emotive Potentials
'where', he comments, 'I feel the rain on my hands and hair rather
than see it.' He goes on to say that he always liked Keats and dis
liked Shelley because 'the characteristic of Keats is, I find, his constant
appeal to the sense of touch, while Shelley's appeal is as constantly to
the sense of movement'. Graves's stimulating essay (published in I925)
ended with the suggestion that psychologists should engage in 'intense
research' on this question; it is a pity th.at it has not been followed up.
(My guess would be that more people than one suspects can smell
322 THE ACT OF CREATION
The Picture-strip
Much the same could be said of the emotive power of some visual
imagery-including Blake's own. We have seen (Chapter VII) that
'thinking in pictures' dominates the manifestations of the unconscious
in the dream, in hallucinatory states, but also in the creative work of
scientists. In fact, the majority of mathematicians and physicists turned
out to be 'visionaries' in the literal sense-that is, visual, not verbal
thinkers.
But we have also seen that pictorial thinking is an earlier and more
primitive form of mentation than conceptual thinkingin the evolu-
tion of the individual as in that of the species. The language of children
is 'picturesque'-again in the literal sense of the word; and the lan
gauge of primitives is 'like the unfolding of a picture strip, where each
word expresses a pictorial image, regardless as to whether the picture
signifies an object, an action, or a quality. Thus "to strike" and "a
blow" are expressed by the same word. These languages are not merely
· deficient in the more abstract type of imagery, but in practically all
higher grammatical construction' (Kretsehmer). 8
Let me give a concrete example from Kretschmer' s textbook,
followed by the comments of that excellent German psychiatrist-
whosc work, comparable in importance to Jung's, is far too little
known to the English-speaking public. The example is a simple story
told in the Bushman language. It is about a Bushman who worked as
IMA.GE 323
a shepherd for a. white man until the latter ill-treated him; whereupon
the Bushman ran away, and the white man engaged another Bushman,
to whom the same thing happened. Translated into Bushman language,
this story is picturized as follows:
Kretschmer comments:
I returned, and saw under the sun, that the race is not to the swift,
nor the battle to the strong, neither yet bread to the wise, nor yet
riches to men of understanding, nor yet favour to men of skill; but
time and chance happeneth to th.em all (Ecclesiastes.)
might serve as a motto for all appeals to the emotions which are ex-
plained and justified by reference to divine law-the Voice Without
R.eply.
The Will of God, or the Laws of Nature, as the organizing and har-
monizing principle of the universe is one of the most powerful arche-
types of human experience. No doubt it originates to a large part in
feelings of insecurity, of cosmic anxiety, the need for protection-
hence the reassurance and relief which are felt whenever a threatening
or merely puzzling phenomenon can be 'explained' as a manifestation
of some universal law or divine order. For the opposite of order is
chaoswhich means unpredictability of events, absence of protection.
IMAGE 327
exposure to the whims of incomprehensible forces. The emergence or
order from chaos is a leitmotif of all mythologies; even the blood-
thirsty goddesses of the Hindus and the choleric deities of the Pantheon
provided a measure of reassurance, because they were moved by
hum.an passions which could be comprehended by the mind; so that
everything that befell one was satisfactorily explained.
Thus virtually any expla.na.tion-valid or not-which commands
belief has a calming and cathartic effect. It can be observed on every
level: from the sudden, smiling relief of the small child when some
startling appearance is shown to be related to something familiar, and
recognized as part of the general order of things-to the euphoria of
the scientist, who has solved his problem. Even painful experiences
are tempered with relief once they are recognized as particular in-
stances of a general law. To lose a relative by a 'stupid accident' is more
painful than to lose one 'lawfully', through old age or incurable illness.
The only effective consolation in the face of death is that it is part of
the cosmic order; if chimneysweepers were exempted from it, we
should resent it very much indeed. The idea of 'blind chance' deciding
our fate is intolerable; the mind abhors gaps in the lawful order as
nature abhors the vacuum.
However, the reduction of the uncanny and vexing to the orderly and
funi.liar, of the rustling of leaves in the dark forest to the whisper of
fairies or the vibrations of compressed air-both equally reassuring-
is merdy the negative aspect of the power of explanation: relief from
anxiety. Its positive aspect is epitomized in the Pythagorean belief
that musical harmonies govern the motion of the stars. The myth of
creation appeals not only to man's abhorrence of chaos, but also to his
sense of wonder at the cosmic order: light is more than the absence of
darkness, and law more than the absence of disorder. I have spoken
repeatedly of that sense of' oceanic wonder' -the most sublimated ex-
pression of the self-transcendingemotions-which is at the root of the
scientist's quest for ultimate Causes, and the artist's quest for the ulti-
mate realities of experience. The sensation of 'marvellous clarity' which
enraptured Kepler when he discovered his second law is shared by
every artist when a strophe suddenly falls into what seems to be its
predestined pattern, or when the felicitous image unfolds in the mind
328 THE ACT OP CREATION
-the only one which can 'explain' by symbols the rationally unex-
plainable-and express the inexpressible.
Experiences of this kind, when something previously turbid be-
comes suddenly transparent and permeated by light, are always.
accompanied by the sudden expansion and subsequent catharsis of the
self-transcending emotions. Ihave called this the 'earthing' of emotion,
on the analogy of earthing (or 'grounding') an electrically charged
body, so that its tensions are drained by the immense current-absorb-
ing capacity of 'mother earth'. The scientist attains catharsis through
the reduction of phenomena to their primary causes; a disturbing par-
ticular problem is mentally 'earthed' into the universal order. The
same description applies to the artist, except that his 'primary causes'
and 'laws of order' are differently constituted. They derive from
mythology and magic, from the compulsive powers of rhythm and
form, from archetypal symbols which arouse unconscious resonances.
But their 'explanatory power', though not of a rational order, is
emotionally as satisfying as that of the scientist's explanations; both
mediate the 'earthing' of particular experiences into a universal frame;
and the catharsis which follows scientific discovery or artistic trou-
vaille has the same 'oceanic' quality. The melancholy charm of the
golden lads who come to dust because that is the condition of man, is
due to the 'earthing' of our personal predicaments in a universal
predicament. Art, like religion, is a school of self-transcendence; it
expands individual awareness into cosmic awareness, as science teaches.
us to reduce any particular puzzle to the great universal puzzle.
When Rembrandt had the audacity to paint the carcass of a flayed
ox, he taught his public to see and accept behind the repulsive par-
ticular object the timeless patterns of light, shadow, and colour. We
have seen that the discoveries of art derive from the sudden transfer
of attention from one matrix to another with a higher emotive poten-
tial. The intelledual aspect of this Eureka process is closely akin to the
scicntist'&-<>r the mystic's-'spontaneous illumination': the percep-
tion of a familiar object or event in a new, significant, light; its emotive
aspect is the rapt stillness of oceanic wonder. The two togcther-intellec-
toal illumination and emotional catharsis-are the essence of the
aesthetic experience. The first constitutes the moment of truth; the
second provides the experience of beauty. The two are complemen-
tary aspects of an indivisible process-that 'earthing' process where
'the innnite is made to blend itself with the finite, to stand visible, as it
were, attainable there' (Carlyle).
IMAGE
NOTES
FIGURE IO
\CiumistrJ
\Bio~
\Bw1.o&J
\"Mtdicine
···-.1'SJCMW'5!J
.....~royof.oe
-. -. ~
···· ..~1,y
··· .. J(cml
··. ··-~--,::.,,;,. 111 •
·····":'j.71,C,
······•·•••••·····• su1,· •
--~~~--~~~~~~~~~-(~
From antiquity until well into the Renaissance artists thought, or pro-
fessed to think, that they were copying nature; even Leonardo wrote
into his notebook 'that painting is most praiseworthy which is most
like the thing represented.'. Of course, they were doing nothing of the
sort. They were creating, as Plato had reproached them, 'man-made
dreams for those who are awake'. The thing represented had to pass
through two distorting lenses: the artist's mind, and his medium of
expression, before it emerged as a man-made dream-the two, of
course, being intimately connected and interacting with each other.
To start with the medium: the space of the painter's canvas is smaller
than the landscape to be copied, and his pigment is different from the
colours he sees; the writer's ink cannot render a voice nor exhale the
smell of a rose. The nature of the medium always excludes direct
imitation. Some aspects of experience cannot be reproduced at all;
some only by gross oversimplification or distortion; and some only at
the price of sacrificing others. The limitations and peculiarities of his
medium force the artist at each step to make choices, consciously or un-
consciously; to select for representation those features or aspects which.
he considers to be relevant, and to discard those which. he considers
irrelevant. Thus we meet again the trinity of selection, exaggeration,
and simplification which I have discussed before (pp. 82-6; 263 f.). Even
333
334 THE ACT OF CREATION
Economy
Summary
•
XIX
CHARACTER AND PLOT
Identification
I n his monologue in Act II, after the First Player's dramatic recital,
Hamlet asks a pertinent question:
In the first place, the evidence shows that there arc people endowed
'With the fu:olty of so-called eidetic imagery-that is, of really seeing
mental images with dream-like, hallucinatory vividness; but this
faculty, though relatively frequent in children. is rare in adults. The
avenge a~ does not really see anything appro~ a complete and
CHARACTER AND PLOT 347
sharp image when he recalls a memory-for instance, the &c.c of a
friend-though he may deceive himself into believing that he does.
How do we know that he is deceiving himself? Herc is one way of
proving it-among many others. The experimenter lets the subject
look at a square of: say, four rows of four letters (which do not form
any meaningful sequences) until the subject thinks he cm sec them in
his mind's eye. He can, in fact, fluently 'read' them out after the square
has been ta.ken away-or so he believes. For when he is asked to read
the square backwards, or diagonally, his fluency is gone. He has, in
fact, learned the sequence by rote without realizing it-which is quite
a different matter from forming a visual image. If he could really see
the square, he could read it in all directions with the same ease and
speed.
The ordinary citizen, who does not happen to be a painter, or a
policeman, or of a particularly observant type, would be at a. loss to
give an exact visual description even of people whom he knows quite
well. What we do remember of a person is a combination of (a}
certain vivid details, and (b) what we call 'general impressions'. The
'vivid detail' may be a gesture, an intonation, an outstanding visual
feature-the mole on Granny's chin-which, for one reason or an-
other, has stuck in one's memory, like a fragment from a picture-
strip, and which functionspars pro toto-as a part, or sign deputizing
for the whole.
The 'general impression' on the other hand, is based on the opposite
method of memory-formation: it is a schematized, sketchy, quasi
'skeletonized' outline of a whole configuration, regardless of detail.
A woman may say to a man, 'I haven't seen you wearing that tie
bcfore'-though she has not the faintest recollection of any of the
ties he has worn in the past. She recognizes a deviation from memories
which she is unable to recall. The explanation of the paradox is that
although she cannot remember the colour or pattern of any single tic
which that man wore in the past, she docs remember that they were
generally subdued and discreet, which the new tie is not. It deviates not
from any particular past experience, but .&om the general code, from
an abstracted visual quality that these past experiences had in common.
Such perceptual codes function as selective filters, as it were; the filter
rejects as 'wrong' anything which does not fit its 'mesh'; and accepts
or 'recognizes' anything that fits it, i.e. which gives the same 'general
impression'. The gentleman with the new tie, for instance, can get his
own back with the remark, 'You have done something to your lwr~
TBl! ACT OP CREATION
haven't you?' He has never noticed her previous hair-dos at all, but he
docs notice that the present one just doesn't go with her mousy appear-
ance. Here the code is 'mousiness' which, like all visual schematizations,
is difficult to describe in words, but instantly recognized by the eye.
We ta1k of an 'innocent' or 'lascivious' expression, of 'sensitive' or
'brutal' features-characteristics which defy verbal description, but
which can be sketched with a few lines-as emotions can be indi
cated by a few basic strokes indicating the slant of mouth and eyes.
Other codes of recognition may combine form and motion, or
vision and hearing: a characteristic gait, the timbre of a voice.
Thus recognizing a person does not mean matching a retinal image
against a memory image of photographic likeness. My memory of
John Brown is not a photographic record; it consists of several, simpli-
fied and schematized 'general impressions' whose combination, plus a
few 'vivid details', enable me to recognize him when we meet, or to
remember him in his absence. But that remembrance is only partly of
a pictorial nature, and much less so than I believe it to be-see the
experiment with the letter-square. The reason for this self-deception is
that the process of combining those simplified visual and other schemata
and adorning them with a few genuine 'photographic' fragments, is
unconscious and instantaneous. The perceptual codes function below
the level of awareness; we are playing a game without being aware
of the rules. We overestimate the precision of our imagery, as we
overestimate the precision of our verbal thinking (quite often we think
that we have understood the meaning of a difficult text and discover
later that we haven't really) because we are unaware of the gaps
between the words and between the sketchy contours of the schemata.
All inttospectivc 'visual' thinkers, from Einstein downward, em-
phasized the vagueness, haziness, and abstract character of their con-
scious visual imagery. True picture-strip thinking is confined to the
dream, and other manifestations of the subconscious.
The point of this apparent digression was to show that if the above
is trUe regarding our mental images of real people whom we know, it
must be all the more true regarding our images of fictional characters
which lack any sensory basis. A character may indeed be 'alive' with
the utmost vividness in the reader's mind, but this vividness need not
be of a visual nature. The reader may fall in love with Karenina,
despair when she throws hetself under the train, mourn her death-
=and yet be unable to vismlizc her in his mind's eye or give a detailec:l
description of her appearmcc. Her 'living image' in the reader is not
CHARACTER .A.ND PLOT 349
a photographic image, but a multi-dimension.al construct of a variety
of aspects of her general appearance, her gestures and voice, her pat-
terns of thinking and behaving. It is a combination of various 'general
impressions' and 'vivid details'-that is, construded on much the same
principles as images of real people.
In fact, there is no sharp dividing line between our images of people
whom we have met in the flesh, and those whom we know only from
descriptions-whether fuctua1 or fictional (or a combination of both).
The dream knows no distinction between factual and £ctitious charac-
ters, and children as well as primitives are apt to confuse the two.
Thus the phantoms of Bovary and Karenina which float around
us are not so very different from our apparently solid memories of Joe
Smith and Peter .Brown; both varieties are made of the same stuff.
In one of Muriel Spark's novels, a wise old bird asks his woman friend:
'Do you think:, Jean, th.at other people exist? ... I mean, do you
consider th.at people-the people around us-are real or illusory?
Surely you see that here is a respectable question. Given that yon
believe in your own existence as self-evident, do you believe in that of
others? Do you believe that I for instance, at this moment ex:ist?'1
The only certainty that other people exist, not merdy as physical
shapes, but as sentient beings, is derived from partly conscious, but
mostly unconscious, inference, i.e. empathy. We automatically infer
from minute pointers in a person's face or gestures-which we mostly
do not even register consciously-his character, mood, how he will
behave in an emergency, and a lot of other things. Without this
faculty of projecting part of one's own sentient personality into the
other person's shell, which enables us to say 'I know how you feel',
the pointers would be meaningless. Lorenz has shown that the various
postures and flexions of the wolf's tail are indicative of at least ten
different moods. As we have lost our tails we cannot empathize with
these moods-but since our labial muscles are not very different, we
feel at once the significance of bared teeth.
The semi-abstract schematizations which we call 'general impres-
sions' of appearance, character, and personality, are intuitive pointer-
readings based on empathy. It is by this means that we assign reality
and sentience to other people. Once more, the process differs from
bringing a fictional character alive in our minds mainly by the nature
of the pointers. A bland face at a cocktail party uttering the conven-
tional type of remark may provide less pointers for empathy and imagi
nation than the cunningly planted hints of the novelist, spccia1ly
TBB ACT OP CREATION
Drama striv.es on conflict, and so does the novel, The nature of the
conflict may be explicitly stated or merely implied; but an element of
it must be present, otherwise the characters would be gliding through
a frictionless universe.
The conflict may be fought in the divided heart of a single charac-
ter; or between two or more persons; or between man and his destiny.
The conflict between personalities may be due to a clash of ideas or
temperaments, to incompatible codes of behaviour or scales of value.
But whatever its motif, a quarrel will assume the dignity of drama only
if the audience is lead to accept the attitude of both sides as valid, each
within its own frame of reference. If the author succeeds in this, the
confiict will be projected into the spectator's or reader's mind, and
experienced as a dash between two simultaneous and incompatible
identifications. 'We make out of our quarrels with others rhetoric,
but of our quarrels with ourselves poetry/ said Yeats.
Dramatic conflict thus always reveals some paradox which is latent
in the mind. It reflects both sides of the medal whereas in our practical
pursuits we see only one at a time. The paradox may be seemingly
superficial. as when our sympathies arc divided between Hamlet and
Laertes, two equally worthy contestants, with the resulting desire to
hdp both, that is to harm both. But at least the double complicity in
the double slaughter is prompted not by hate but love, and we are
made to realize that it was destiny, not their own volition, which made
them destroy each other; the paradox is 'earthed' in the human
condition.
Thus the artist compels his audience to live on several planes at
once. He identifies himself with several characters in tum-Caesar,
Brutus, Antony, projecting some aspect of himself into each of them,
and speaking through their mouths; or introjecting them, if you like,
and lcndiug them his voice. He presents Brutus and Caesar alternately
m situations where they command sympathy and impose their patterns
of reasoning, their scales of value, until each bas established his own
CHARACTER AND PLOT 3SI
independent matrix in the spectator's mind. Having acquired these
multiple identities, the spectator is led to a powerful climax, where he
is both murderer and victim; and thence to catharsis. In the Blzagavid
Gita the Lord Krishna appears on the battlefidd in the role of charioteer
to his disciple Arjuna, whom he cures of his pacifist scruples by ex-
plaining that the slayer and the slain are One, because both are em-
bodiments of the indestructible Atma; therefore 'the truly wise mourn
neither for the living nor for the dead.' I doubt whether this doctrine,
taken literally, had a beneficial effect on the ethics of Hinduism,* but
to be both Caesar and Brutus in one's imagination has a profound
cathartic effect, and is one way of approaching Nirvana.
Brutus is an honourable man; so is Caesar; but what about Iago?
Through pitying Desdemona, and sharing Othello's despair, we are
compelled to hate Iago; but we can hate Iago only if he has come to
life for us and in us; and he has come to life in us because he too com-
m.ands our understanding and, at moments, our sympathy-the
resonance of our own frustrated ambitions and jealousies. Without
this unavowed feeling of complicity, he would be a mere stage-prop,
and we could hate him no more than a piece of cardboard. Iago,
Richard III, Stavrogin, the great villains of literature, have an irresist-
ible appeal to some common, repressed villainousness in ourselves,
and give us a wonderfully purifying opportunity to discover what it
feels like to be frankly a villain.
But true-black villains are limit cases; the more evenly our sym-
pathies are distributed among the antagonists, the more successfully
the work will actualize latent aspects of our personalities. Caliban and
Prospero, Faust and Mephisto, Don Quixote and Sancho Panza, Christ
and the Great Inquisitor-each pair is locked in an everlasting dud in
which we act as seconds for both. In each of these conflicts two self-.
contained frames of reference, two sets of values, two universes of
discourse collide. All great works of literature contain variations and
combinations, overt or implied, of such archetypal conflicts inherent
in the condition ofman, which first occur in the symbols of mythology.
and are restated in the particular idiom of each culture and period. All
literature, wrote Gerhart Hauptmann, is 'the distant echo of the primi-
tive word behind the veil of words'; and the action of a drama or
novel is always the distant echo of some ancestral action behind the
veil of the period's costumes and conventions. There are no new
themes in literature, as there are no new human instincts; but every age
provides new variations and sublimations, new settings and a different
352 THE ACT OP CllBATION
set of rules for fighting the old battles all over again. To quote G. W.
Brandt: 'There is basically only a limited number of plots; they can be
seen, in different guises, recurring down the ages. The reason is in life
itsel£ Human relationships, whilst in.finitely varied in detail, reveal-
stripped down to fundamentals-a number of repetitive patterns.
Writers straining to invent a plot entirely fresh have known this for a
long time. Goethe quoted Gozzi' s opinion that there were only thirty
six tragic situations-and he added that Scbiller, who believed that
there were more, had not even succeeded in finding as many as that.'•
Archetypes
and fair.jDust hath closed Helen's eye.JI am sick, I must die.fLord have
mercy upon us.'
'If death did not exist', wrote Schopenhauer, 'there would be no
philosophy-nor would there be poetry.' That does not mean that
either philosophy, or art, must be obsessivdy preoccupied with death;
merely, that great works of art are always transparent to some dim
outline of the ultimate experience, the archetypal image. It need not
have a tragic shape, and it may be no more than the indirect reflection
of a reflection, the echo of an echo. But metaphor and imagery yield
aesthetic value only if the two contexts which are involved in the com-
parison form an ascending gradient-if one of them is felt to be
nearer to the source of the stream. Mutatis mutandum, a scientific
theory need not be directly concerned with the ultimate secret of the
universe, but it must point towards it by bringing order and harmony
into some obscure comer. To clinch the argument, I must quote once
more Housman's essay on The Name and Nature of Poetry:
Cataloguing Plots
malevolent powers who trap the King into performing his disastrous
deeds apparently out of his own free will. In all plots of the Appoint-
ment in Samara type, apparent coincidences are the means by which
destiny defeats the will of man (cf. coincidence in comedy, p. 78). In
Christian theology, the ways of God become less arbitrary, but more
inscrutable; man proposes, God disposes; original sin chokes his
designs. In the .Eastern religions he is tied to the wheel of rebirth; in
Islam he carries his fate fastened round his neck. The great theological
disputes between Calvinists and Lutherans, Jansenites and Jesuits
turned mainly on the question of predestination, or more precisely, on
the length of the rope left to man to hang himse1£
With the rise of Natural Philosophy, a change in the character of
destiny began to take shape. Romeo and Juliet still die as a result of
fatal misunderstandings ('One writ with me in sour misfortune's
book'). But in Shakespeare's later works, destiny acts no longer only
from outside but also from inside the personae; they are victims not
so much ofblind fate, but of their blind passions: 'the fault, dear Brutus,
is not in our stars, but in ourselves'. These are great, brave words; but
they did not solve the dilemma, they merely polished its horns. Divine
predestination was transformed into scientific determinism, which left
man even less scope than before for exercising his will and making free
choices. The hairshirt of the penitent had allowed him some freedom
of movement, but the laws of heredity and environment wove a
strait-jacket so tight that it became indistinguishable from his living
skin. Even the word 'volition' was banned from psychology as empty
of meaning. Chromosomes and glandular secretions took over from
the gods indeciding a man's fate. He remained a marionette on strings,
with the only difference that he was now suspended on the nucleic
acid chains determining his heredity, and the conditioned-reflex
chains forged by the environment.
The most explicit adoption of this schema for literary uses is found
in the naturalist movement of the nineteenth century. Its programme
was formulated in Zola's Le Roman Experimental, inspired by the
a
Introduction l' ltude de la medicine experimentale by the great Claude
Bernard (who discovered the vaso-motor system of nerves, and the
glucose-producing function of the liver). Zola urged his fellow writers
to take a 'physiological view' of man as a product of nature devoid of
free will and subject to the laws of heredity and environment. For-
tunately, in spite of the naturalist vogue in Germany, R~ and
Scandinavia, writers accepted his views in theory only-as they are
CHA.RACTBI. A.ND PLOT 357
wont to do. The creative mind knows how to draw on archetypal
symbols without degrading them by misplaced concreteness.
You can make an X-ray photograph of a fuce, but you cannot make
a face from an X-ray photograph. You can show that underlying the
subtle and complex action of a novel there is a primitive skeleton,
without committing Iese majeste, or foolishly assuming that the plot
makes the novel. There is only a limited number of plots, recurring
down the ages, derived from an even more limited number of basic
patterns-the conflicts, paradoxes, and predicaments inherent in man's
condition. And if we continue the stripping game, we find that all
these paradoxes and. predicaments arise from conflicts between in
compatible frames of experience or scales of value, illuminated in con-
sciousness by the bisociative act. In this final illumination Aristotle
saw 'the highest form of lea.ming' because it shows us that we are 'men,
not gods'; and he called tragedy 'the noblest form. ofliterature' because
it purges suffering from its pettiness by showing that its causes lie in
the inescapable predicaments of existence.*
NOTES
Top. 351. Hindu apologists would have us take Krishna's exhortations to
belligerence as allegorical references to wars fought inside the human soul. The
argument is as far-fetched as the- Christian apologists' attempts to represent the
Song of Songs as an allegory of Christ's love for His Church.
Top. 35z. Eric Newton (An Introdudion to European Painting) actually uses
the same metaphor.
Top. 357. At least this seems the most plausible explanation of the cryptic
remark in the Poetics that we take pleasure in tragedy because learning is pleasur-
able, and tragedy involves learning.
xx
THE BELLY OF THE WHALE
The Night Journey
I went down to the bottoms of the mountains: the earth with her
bars was about me for ever.
The craving for the womb, for the dissolution of the self in a lost,
vegetative oneness-Freud's Nirvana principle-is further symbolized
in the image of mother ocean in whose calm depths all life originates.
Mythology is full of these symbols-the metaphors of the collective
unconscious. However bewildering they may appear to the waking
mind, they are familiar to the dreamer, and recur constantly in the
THB ACT OF CREATION
sleep of people who have nothing else in common. The Night Journey
is the antipode of Promethean striving. One endeavours to steal the
bright fire from the gods; the other is a sliding back towards the pulsa-
ting darkness, one and undivided, of which we were part before our
separate egos were formed.
Thus the Night Journey is a regression of the participatory tendencies,
a crisis in which consciousness becomes unhom=-to become reborn in
a higher form of synthesis. It is once more the process of reculer pour
mieux sauter; the creative impulse, having lost its bearing in trivial
entanglements, must effect a retreat to recover its vigour.
Without our regular, minor night journeys in sleep we would soon
become victims of mental desiccation. Dreaming is for the aesthetically
underprivileged the equivalent of artistic experience, his only means of
self-transcendence, of breaking away from the trivial plane and creating
his own mythology.
Woe to him who seeks to pour oil upon the waters when God has
brewed them into a gale! Woe to him who seeks to please rather
than to appal! Woe to him whose good name is more to him than
goodness! Woe to him who, in this world, courts not dishonour!
And the author of the Jonah story himself must have been aware of
its vast implications, of the impossibility of treating all men who
lead an ordinary life as harshly as Jonah-for the story ends with an
unusual act of clemency by the otherwise so vengeful desert-god,
which comes as a curious anticlimax full of ironical tolerance for the
inadequacy of man:
Then said the Lord. •.. And should I not spare Nineveh. that great
city, wherein are more than six score thousand persons that cannot
discern between their right hand and their left hand: and also much
cattle?
The Root and the Flower
The refrain, recurring after each of the three stanzas of the poem,
. connects (as the context clearly indicates) Cleopatra's meditations
362
THE BELLY OP TBE WHALE
during her childish dance with the monumental archetype of the spirit
of God moving upon the face of the waters.
A flower, even if it is only a daisy, must have a root; and a work of
art, however gay, precious, or serene, is in the last instance fed, how-
ever indirectly, invisibly, through delicate capillary tubes, from the
ancient substrata of experience. If it has a humorous message, it pro-
duces a smile-a subdued laugh or sous-tire; if it is tragic, it produces a
sous-pleurer, that rapt stillness and overflowing of emotion where, to
quote Donne again, with a strong, sober thirst, my soule attends.
The Tightrope
The ordinary mortal in our urban civilization moves virtually all his
life on the Trivial Plane; only on a few dramatic occasions-during
the storms of puberty, when he is in love or in the presence of death-
does he fall suddenly through the manhole, and is transferred to the
Tragic Plane. Then all at once the pursuits of his daily routines appear
as shallow, trifling vanities; but once safdy back on the Trivial Plane,
he dismisses the realities of the other as the products of overstrung
nerves or adolescent effusions. Sudden catastrophes-famines, wars, and
plagues-may shift a whole population from the Trivial to the Tragic
Plane; but they soon succeed in banalizing even tragedy itse1£ and
carry on business as usual among the shambles. During the Spanish
Civil War, one of my fellow prisoners, a youth condemned to death
by shooting, and suffering from appendicitis, was put on a milk diet
two days before his execution.
The force of habit, the grip of convention, hold. us down on the
Trivial Plane; we are unaware of our bondage because the bonds are
invisible, their restraints acting below the level of awareness. They are
the collective standards of value, codes of behaviour, matrices with
built-in axioms, which determine the rules of the game, and make most
of us run, most of the time, in the grooves of habit-reducing us to
the status of skilled automata which Behaviourism proclaims to be the
only condition of man. What Bergson called 'the mechanical encrusted
on the living' is the result of protracted confinement to the Trivial
Plane.
But, glory be, man is not a flat-earth dweller all the timeonly
most of the time. Like the universe in which he lives, he is in a state
of continuous creation. The exploratory drive is as fundamental to his
TB! .ACT OP CllB.ATION
•
C. VISUAL CREATION
XXI
MOTIF AND MEDIUM
Looking at Nature
K
epler, contemplating a snow-crystal melting on his always
sweaty palm, saw in it the harmony of the spheres reflected
in miniature. Let a less romantically disposed person look for
the first time at a snowflake under a microscope: he will catch his
breath and wax equally lyrical: 'How strange-how beautiful-how
clever is nature', et cetera. Yet the symmetrical pattem of hexagons
thus marvellously revealed, loses all its magic when drawn on a
drawing-board. It becomes aesthetically neutral for lack of a second
context-the familiar sight of the feathery snowflake. It is the super-
imposition of the two matrices-the trivial object revealing the mathe-
matical regularity of its micro-cosmic architecture-which creates the
impact, and gives rise to the aesthetic experience.
Whether Odysseus saw in the sky at dawn 'rosy-fingered Athene
lift her golden ray. or whether you share the sorrow of the weeping
willow, there is inevitably a second frame of reference superimposed
on the picture. Man always looks at nature through coloured glasses
-through mythological, anthropomorphic, or conceptual matrices-
even when he is not conscious of it and believes that he is engaged in
'pure vision', unsullied by any meaning. The 'innocent eye' is a fiction,
based on the absurd notion that what we perceive in the present can be
isolated in the mind from the influence of past experience. There is no
perception of 'pure form' but meaning seeps in; and settles on the
image (though the meaning need not be expressed in verbal language,
about which more later).
The idea that looking at nature is self-rewarding, and that land-
scapes devoid of action can give rise to aesthetic experiences, is of
relatively recent origin; so is landscape painting.* Dr. Johnson regarded
mountains as 'rather uncouth objects'; in the literature ofthe eighteenth
366
MOTIP AND MEDIUM
What is happening is, put into our jargon, a series of bisociative pro-
cesses involving the participatory emotions.
At the base ofthe series we again find illusion-the magic transforma-
tion of the carved tree into a god. The painted mask, the carved
372 THE ACT OP CREATION
idol, are perceived at the same time as what they are and what they
represent. The witch-doctor works his evil spell by sticking a needle
into the rag-doll representing the victim; the cave-artist of Alta.mira
made sure of a plentiful supply of meat by populating the rock with
painted bison and wild horses.
To those with naive tastes, illusion in itself is sufficientto evoke
aesthetic experience, and 'life-likeness' is regarded as the supreme
criterion of art. As mentioned before, even Leonardo wrote 'that
painting is most praiseworthywhich is most like the thing represented'.
However, the 'most like' has an infinite number of interpretations-
and that for two solid reasons: the limitations of the medium and the
prejudices of vision. The range of luminosity in the painter's pigment
is only a fraction of that of natural colours; the area on the canvasonly
a fraction of the visual field; its coarse grain can accommodate only
a fraction of fine detail; it lacks the dimension of depth in space, and
motion in time. (Even a photograph is far from being a true likeness;
apart from its obvious limitations of colour and light = sensitivity,
it increasesthe ratio of focal to peripheral vision about a hundredfold
-which may be one of the reasonswhy nature is so much prettified
on picture postcards.}Hence the painter is forced to cheat, to invent
tricks, to exaggerate,simplify,and distort in order to correct the dis
torting effects of the medium. The way he cheats, the tricks he uses,
are partly determined by the requirements of the medium itself-he
must think 'in terms of' stone, wood, pigment, or gouache-but
mainly by the idiosyncrasiesof his vision: the codeswhich govern the
ma.trices of his perception. Whether Manet's impressionof'The Races
ofLongchamp' looks more 'life-like' than Frith's academicallymeticu-
lous' 'Derby Day' depends entirdy on the beholder's spectacles.An
artist can copy in plaster, up to a point, a Roman copy of a Greek
bronze head; he cannot 'copy' on canvasa running horse. He can only
createan appearancewhich, seenin a certainlight, at a certain distance,
in a certain mood, will suddenly acquire a life of its own. It is not a
copy, but a metaphor. The horse was not a model, but a motif for his
creation-in the sense in which the landscape painter looks for a
romantic or pastoralmoti.£
In the terminology of behaviouristpsychology we would have to
say that looking at the modd constitutesthe 'stimulus', and putting
a dab of paint on the canvasthe 'response'-and that is all there is to
it. But the two activities take place OD; two diffei:en.t planes. The
stimuluscomesfrom one environment-the outer world: the response
MOTIF AND MEDIUM 373
acts on a different environment: a square surface. The two environ-
ments obey two different sets of laws. An isolated brush-stroke does
not represent an isolated detail. There are no point-to-point corres-
pondences between the two planes of the motif and the medium;
they are bisociated as wholes in the artist's mind.
Visual Inferences
Once the artist has acquired sufficient technical skill to clo with his
material more or Jess what he likes, the question what he likes, i.e.
what aspects of reality he considers relevant, becomes all-important.
In other words. of the two variables I mentioned-the limitations of
the medium. and the prejudiced eye beholding the motif, the first can
be regarded, within a given school, as relatively stable, and we can
concentrate our attention on the second. There can be no unprejudiced
eye for the simple reason that vision is full of ambiguities, and all per-
ception. as we saw, is an inferential construction which proceeds on
various levels, and most of it unconsciously (c£ pp. 38-44). The visual
constancies (p. 43) which enable us to perceive objects as stable in shape,
size, colour, etc., in spite of their unstable, ever-changing appearances
are a first step in the interpretation of our confusing, ambiguous retinal
images. They are automatic skills, partly innate, mostly learned in
early childhood. The process is reversed in some of the so-called optical
illusions where the unconscious code governing preception draws the
wrong inferences in an unusual situation. But even these primitive
mechanisms, which norm.ally function below the level of awareness,
can suddenly become a problem in interpretation for the painter, I
have mentioned {p. 43) that owing to the mechanism. of brightness-
constancy a black glove looks as black in sunlight as in the shade-
until you look at it through a reduction screen in the experimental
laboratory or through the impressionist painter's crooked index-finger.
The various constancies are unconscious inferences we draw to make
sense of our sensations, to lend stability to the unstable flux of appear-
ances. They transform what the eye sees so as to suit the requirements
of reason, of what we know about the external world. Between the
retina and the higher centres of the cortex the innocence of vision is
irretrievably lost-it has succumbed to the suggestion of a whole series
of hidden persuaders.
Perceptual projection, which I have already mentioned (p. -295), is
374 THB ACT OP CREATION
Codes of Perception
This leads us to the most powerful single fu:tor among the many
factors which enter into the processing of the visual input: the power
of convention as a hidden persuader (p. 42 f.). Perception is a part-
innate, part-acquired skill of transforming the raw-material of vision
MOTIF AND MBDIUM 377
into the 'finished product'; and every petiod has its conventional
formulae and methods of interpretation for doing this. The ordinary
mortal thinks most of the time in cliches-and sees most of the time in
cliches. His visual schemata are prefabricated for him; he looks at the
word through contact-lenses without being aware of it.
The extreme example is ancient Egypt-but merely because it
lasted so long; contemporary Zen painting and calligraphy, as already
said, obeys almost as rigid rules of the game. The Egyptian painter
unvaryingly represented the human figure with head in profile, eye
frontally, legs in profile, chest frontally, and so on, showing each part
in its most characteristic aspect. Whether the ordinary Egyptian per-
ceived his fellow creatures this way we cannot tell, and-remembering
that we perceive a tilted coin still as a circle, and not foreshortened
into an ellipse-he probably could not tell either. But we do know that
the moment he translated motif into medium, his vision became
stereotyped. It is highly improbable that conformity was enforced on
artists against their will for a full three thousand years. There exist
exceptions to the rule, relief figures dating as far back as 2400 B.c.,11
which show foreshortening and dynamic motion; if there had been a
taboo on such innovations, they would hardly have been preserved.
But the exceptions became less, not more frequent as time went by;
for reasons beyond our understanding, Egyptian art, as Egyptian
society, remained static, and habit prevailed over originality.
Greek art, between the sixth and fourth century B.c. was, compared
with Egypt, in a state of permanent revolution, which carried it within
no more than six or seven generations from the archaic style to the
trompe l' ail: Yet, although originality and innovation were valued as
never before, it could not avoid developing its own cliches, 'After all,'
wrote Gombrich, 'Greek art of the classical period concentrated on the
image of man almost to the exclusion of other motifs, and even in the
portrayal of man it remained wedded to types. This does not apply
only to the idealized type of physique which we all associate with
Greek art. Even in the rendering of movement and drapery the reper-
toire of Greek sculpture and painting has turned out to be strangely
limited. There are a restricted number of formulas for the rendering of
ngures standing, running, fighting, or falling, which Greek artists
repeated with relatively slight variations over a long period of time.
Perhaps if a census of such motifs were taken, the Greek vocabulary
would be found to be not much larger than the Egyptian.'12
That vocabulary-and its Euclidean grammar of proportion-
THE ACT OF CREATION
For it is a certain maxim, no man sees what things are, that knows
not what they ought to be. That this maxim is true, will appear by
an academy figure drawn by one ignorant in the .structure, and
knitting of the bones, and anatomy, compared with another who
understands these thoroughly . • • both see the same life, but with
different eyes.19
NOTES
only among lovers; the texture of silk or polished stone also provides.
minor pleasures. The brocade fineries of Van Eyck's figures have a.
strong tactile appeal; the impact of the gangrened flesh of Christ in
Griinewald's Isenheim. altar is one of horror redeemed by pity. It is
perhaps only matched in power by Flaubert's rendering of the legend
of St. Julian sharing his bed with the leper.
are more pleasing to the ear than a-periodic noises; and some screeching
noises-rubbing a blackboard with a dry sponge for instance-are
so offensive that they give gooseflesh to some people. Again, among
musical chords, the octave, fifth, and major third are more agreeable
to the European ear than others; and some dissonances, heard in
isolation, can put one on edge. But the flattery or offensiveness of
individual chords has only an indirect bearing on the emotional
effect of a string quartet as a whole. There is no numerical relation
between the number of consonances and our aesthetic appreciation.
The pattern of alternation between sweet and bitter sounds is merely
one among several relevant patterns interacting with each other in
the multi-dimensional experience.
Sensory preferences-the discrimination between ,;ensory stimula-
tions which 'agree', and those which 'disagree' with our innate or
acquired dispositions-do not provide the clue to the nature of aesthetic
experience, but they provide one of the dues: particularly those pre-
ferences which are part of the human heritage, and shared by all. The
Chinese taste for music differs from ours considerably; but all men
arc subject to the pull of gravity and prefer keeping their balance to
losing it. A leaning tower, or a big head on a thin neck give rise to dis
agreeable sensations mediated by projective empathy (p. 296). But
this again is only part of the story. Inverted, top-heavy, disturbing
forms may combine in the picture with forms in repose, creating a
total pattern with a balance of a higher order-in which the parts
with positive and negative balance play the same role as con-
sonant and dissonant chords, or beats and missed beats in a metric
stanza.
One of the most haunting pictures in this particular respect is
Pollaiulo's 'Martyrdom of St. Sebastian' (in the London National
Gallery). The saint stands with his naked feet on the sawn-off stumps
of two branches of a dead tree, his hands tied behind his back, looking
as if he were bound to topple over any moment. He is held up by
another, hardly visible, branch of a tree which rises behind him, and
to which his hands are presumably tied; but even so he is bound to
fall. What prevents him, in the beholder's eye, from falling is a trick
in the composition of the picture: the figure of the saint forms the
apex of a solid, well-balanced triangle. The sides of the triangle are
six figures in symmetrical poses, performing symmetrical gestures.
The imbalance of the part is redeemed by the balance of the whole,
by the triangle which lends unity to diversity. The fact that the
IMAGE AND EMOTION
sible to our bodies represent a tiny segment.'1 But it has now become
possible to decipher these signals and bring their message into visible
focus by instruments which expand and compress events in time.
penetrate space near to the border where granules of matter are revealed
as patterns of concentrated energy, and enable the eye to see 'in terms
of' ultra-violet and infra-red radiations. All of us have seen an occa-
sional photograph of a spiral nebula or a snow-crystal, but these are like
early daguerreotypes compared with the new landscapes seen through
the electron-microscope, They show the ultra-structure of the world
-electric discharges in a high voltage arc which look like the most
elaborate Brussels lace, smoke molecules of magnesium. oxide like a
composition by Mondrian, nerve-synapses inside a muscle suspended
like algae, phantom-figures of swirling heated air, ink molecules
travdling through water, crystals like Persian carpets, and ghostly
mountains inside the micro-structure of pure Hafnium, like an illus-
tration to Dante's Purgatorio. What strikes one is that these land-
scapes, drawn as it were in invisible ink, possess great intrinsic beauty
of form. The aesthetic experience derived from them seems to be
directly related to what Emerson called the first and second secrets of
nature: 'Motion or change, and identity or rest'-and also to the
fact that the universe is made of only one stuff with a finite set
of basic geometrical patterns in an infutlte number of dynamic
variations.
Ascending Gradients
Summary
•
XX III
ART AND PROGRESS
Cumulative Periods
there is a surprising passage: 'I have often imagined that this un-
finished manner contributed even to that striking resemblance for
which his portraits are so remarkable. Though this opinion may be
considered as fanciful, yet I think a plausible reason may be given, why
such a mode of painting should have such an effect. It is presupposed
that in this undetermined manner there is the general effect; enough
to remind the spectator of the original; the imagination supplies the
rest, and perhaps more satisfactorily to himself, if not more exactly,
than the artist, with all his care, could possibly have done.'
From the middle of the nineteenth century onwards, the trend to-
wards the implicit, the oblique hint, the statement disguised as a riddle
kept gathering speed and momentum-so much so that it sometimes
gave the impression of art not merely 'folding in' but folding up. In im-
pressionist painting, Gombrich remarked, 'the direction of the brush-
stroke is no longer an aid to the reading of forms. It is without any
support from structure that the beholder must mobilize his memory of
the visible world and project it into the mosaic of strokes and dabs on
the canvas before him. The image, it might be said, has no firm anchor-
age left on the canvas-it is only "conjured up' in our minds" .'5 From
here it was only a step to cutting the anchor and doing away with
illusion as something altogether too obvious. Picasso's women shown
part en face and part in profile, sometimes with a third eye or limbs
shuffled around, rely on the beholder's knowledge of the female form
and on his willingness to participate in the master's experiments with
it; like Leonardo's experiments with his chimeras, they are a challenge
and an invitation to explore the possible worlds implied in the visible
world. At the opposite extreme of the scale we find the meticulous
realism of a series of great portrait painters-from Holbein to, say,
Fantin Latour. From a purely optical point of view they seem to be
completely explicit statements; and yet they contain a mystery in
another dimension-the mystery of character and personality summed
up in a single expression, breathing through the pigment of the canvas.
A photograph can convey the truth of a moment; a portrait can inti
mate the truth of a whole life.
Thus there exist various dimensions of infolding-various direc-
tions in which the beholder must exert his imagination and complete
the hint. One is reflected in the development which started with the
veiled sfumato and the loose, evocative brush-with Eastlake' s judicious
unfinish of the consummate workman'-and ends, for the time being,
with the bafBing challenges offered by contemporary art. Another is
A.RT AND PROGRESS 399
the avoidance of any too overt appeal to the emotions-whether in a
hum.an face or in a Neopolitan sunset. The less there is left to divine,
the quicker the process of saturation sets in, which rejects any further
offer of the mixture as before as sentimental, melodramatic, porno-
graphic, or just slushy kitsch. Rembrandt's famous warning to the
spectator to keep his distance-' don't poke your nose into my pictures,
the smell of paint will poison you' -could be reversed: 'don't tum your
canvas into .flypaper to catch my emotions, I can't bear the feel of it.'
Even patterns of unity-in-diversity, for all their archetypal echoes,
become boring if they are too obvious-as rhythm becomes monotonous
unless its pulsation is perceived beneath the surface only of a complex
musical or metric pattern.
The Japanese have a word for it: shibuyi. The colour-scheme of a
.kimono so discreet, subdued, and apparently dull that there seems to be
no scheme at all, is shibuyi. A statue whose grace is hidden by a rough,
unpolished, seemingly unfinished surface, is shibuyi. So is the delicious
taste of raw fish, once the acrid tang which hides it is overcome. The
Chinese, however, discovered the law ofinfold.ing much earlier on. A
seventeenth-century manual of painting advocates the technique of
'leaving out', illustrated by drawings.of the familiar .kind where the
simple outline of a face, minus features, serves as a surprisingly ex-
pressive formula: 'Figures, even though painted without eyes, must
seem to look; without ears, must seem to listen. There are things which
ten hundred brushstrokes cannot depict but which can be captured by
a few simple strokes if they are right. That is truly giving expression
to the invisible.'6
But economy of means and avoidance of the obvious should not be
misinterpreted as lack of spontaneity or a tendency towards modera-
tion. Sesshu, perhaps the greatest of Japanese painters (a contemporary
of Leonardo's), was a master of the leaving-out technique; yet he used
not only his brush, but fistfuls of straw dipped in ink to impart to his
landscapes their p.owerful and violent sense of motion. Goya's 'Disasters'
combine a maximum of economy with a maximum of horror. On
the other hand, Royal Academy portraits in the approved tradition
display all the virtues of moderation, yet in their pedestrian explicit-
ness 'deprive the mind', to quote Mallarme once more, 'of that
delicious joy of imagining that it creates'.
The artist's aim, we saw at the beginning of this book, is to tum his
audience into his accomplices. Complicity does not exclude violence-
but it must be based on a shared secret.
XXIV
CONFUSION AND STERILITY
The Aesthetics of Snobbery1
I
n 1948, a German art restorer named Dietrich Fey, engaged in
reconstruction work on Lubeck' s ancient St. Marien Church,
stated that his workmen had discovered traces of Gothic wall-
paintings dating back to the thirteenth century, under a coating of
chalk on the church walls. The restoration of the paintings was en-
trusted to Fey's- assistant, Lothar Malskat, who finished the job two
years later. In 1950 Chancellor Adenauer presided over the ceremonies
marking the completion of the restoration work, in the presence of
art experts from all parts of Europe. Their unanimous opinion, voiced
by Chancellor Adenauer, was that the twenty-one thirteenth-century
Gothic saints on the church walls were 'a valuable treasure and a
fabulous discovery oflost masterpieces'.
None of the experts on that or any later occasion expressed doubt as
to the authenticity of the frescoes. It was Herr Malskat himself who,
two years later, disclosed the fraud. He presented himself on his own
initiative at Lubeck police headquarters, where he stated that the
frescoes were entirely his own work undertaken by order of his boss,
Herr Fey; and he asked to be tried for forgery. The leading Germ.an
art experts, however, stuck to their opinion; the frescoes, they said,
were without doubt genuine, and Herr Malskat was merely seeking
cheap publicity. An official Board of Investigation was appointed,
and came to the conclusion that the restoration of the wall-paintings
was a hoax-but only after Herr Malsbt had confessed that he had
also manufactured hundreds of Rembrandts, Watteaus, Toulouse-
Lautrecs, Picassos, Henri Rousseaus, Corots, Chagalls, Vlamincks,
and other masters, and sold them as originals-some of which were
actually found by the police in Herr Fey's house. Without this corpus
delicti, it is doubtful whether the German experts would ever have
admitted having been fooled.
400
CONFUSION AND STERILITY 401
merit between the true and the false Picasso, Caracci, or Vermeer, is
conclusive proof that no such difference can be registered by the lay
man's eye. Are we, then, all snobs to whom a signature, an expert
testimony based on X-ray photography, or the postmark of a period
is more important than the intrinsic beauty of the object itself? And
what about the contested works of Shakespeare and Johann Sebastian
Bach? Are their dramatic and poetic and harmonic qualities dependent
on the technical controversies between specialists?
The answer, I believe, can be summed up in a single sentence: our
appraisal of a work of art or literature is hardly ever a unitary act,
and mostly the result of two or more independent and simultaneous
processes which interfere with and tend to distort each other. Let me
illustrate this by a story which I have told elsewhere at greater length.&
A friend of mine, whom I shall call Catherine, was given as a present
by an unobtrusive admirer a drawing from Picasso's classical period;
she took it to be a reproduction and hung it in her staircase. On my
next visit to her house, it was hanging over the mantelpiece in the
drawing-room: the supposed reproduction had turned out to be an
original. But as it was a line-drawing in ink, black contour on white
paper, it needed an expert, or at least a good magnifying lens, to show
that it was the original and not a lithograph or reproduction. Neither
Catherine, nor any of her friends, could tell the difference. Yet her
appreciation of it had completely changed, as the promotion from
staircase to drawing-room showed. I asked her to explain the reason
for her change of attitude to the thing on the wall which in itself had
not changed at all; she answered, surprised at my stupidity, that of
course the thing had not changed, but that she saw it differently since
she knew th.at it was done by Picasso himself and 'not just a repro-
duction'. I then asked what considerations determined her attitude to
pictures in general, and she replied with equal sincerity that they were,
of course, considerations of aesthetic quality-'composition, colour,
harmony, power, what have you'. She honestly believed to be guided
by purdy aesthetic value-judgements based on those qualities; but if
that was the case, since the qualities ofthe picture had not changed, how
could her attitude to it have changed?
I was labouring a seemingly obvious point, yet she was unable to
see that she was contradicting hersel£ It proved quite useless repeating
to her that the origin and rarity-value of the object did not alter its
qualities-and, accordingly, should not have altered her appreciation
of it, if it had really been based on purdy aesthetic criteria as she
THE ACT OF CREATION
Let me now present the case for the defence. The appraisal of a work
of art is generally the result of two or more independent processes
CONFUSION AND STERILITY 405
which interact with each other. One complex process constitutes the
aesthetic experience as such, which has been discussed inprevious chap-
ters; it implies a system of values, and certain criteria of excellence, on
which we believe our judgement to be based. But other processes
interfere with it, with their different systems of values, and distort our
judgements. I shall mention two types of such interfering systems.
The first is summed up in the statement of a little girl of twelve,
the daughter of a friend, who was taken to the Greenwich Museum,
and when asked to name the most beautiful thing she had seen there,
declared without hesitation: 'Nelson's shirt.' When asked what was
so beautiful about it, she explained: 'That shirt with blood on it was
j oily nice. Fancy real blood on a real shirt which belonged to somebody
really historic.'
Her sense of values, unlike Catherine's, was still unspoilt. The
emotion that she had experienced was derived from the same kind of
magic that emanates from Napoleon's inkpot, the relic of the saint
carried in the annual procession, the rope by which a famous
murderer was hanged, the galley-proof corrected by Tolstoy's hand.
Our forbears believed that an object which had been in the possession
of a person became imbued with his emanations, and in turn emanated
something of his substance. 'There is, I am sure,' a columnist wrote in
the Daily Express, 'for most of us a special pleasure in sinking your
teeth into a peach produced on the estate of an Earl who is related to
the Royal Family.'' You might even come to fed that you are a
member of the family if you persist long enough in this somewhat
indirect method of transubstantiation.
We can no more escape the pull of magic inside us than the pull of
gravity. Its manifestations may talce a more or less dignified form; but
the value we set on the peach from the Earl's estate or the splinter from
the saint's bone, on Dickens's quill or Galileo's telescope, is derived
from the same source of sympathetic magic. It is, as the little girl said,
jolly nice to behold a fragment of a marble by Praxiteles-although it
has been battered out of hum.an shape, with a leper's nose and broken.
ears. The contact with the master's hand has imbued it with a kind
of effluvium which has lingered on, and emanates the same thrill
as the real blood on Nelson's shirt-or the real ink from Picasso's
pen.
The inordinate importance that we attribute to the original and
authenticated, even in those borderline cases where only the expert
can decide on questions of authenticity, has its unconscious roots in
4o6 l'HE ACT OF CREATION
hole in space; and the period-frame in our minds which creates for it
a hole in time, and assigns its place on the stage of history. Each time
we think we are making a purely aesthetic judgement according to our
lights, the stage-lights interfere. When we contemplate the Gothic
wall-paintings on the church in Liibeck for the first time, believing
them to be authentic, and then -a second time, knowing that they were
made by Herr Malskat, our experience will indeed be completely
changed, although the frescoes are the same as at the time when they
were hailed as masterpieces. The period-frame has been changed, and
with it the stage-lights.
Apart from being unavoidable, this relativism. of aesthetic judgement
has its positive sides: by entering into the spirit and climate of the
period, we automatically make allowances for its crudities of tech-
nique, for its conventions and blind spots; we bend over the past with
a tender antiquarian stoop. But this gesture degenerates into anti-
quarian snobbery at the point where the period-frame becomes more
important than the picture, and perverts our scale of values. The
symptoms are all too familiar: indiscriminate reverence for any-
thing classified as Italian Primitive or Austrian Baroque (including its
mass-produced puffy, chubby, winged little horrors); collective shifts
of period-consciousness (from anti-Victorian to pro-Victorian in
recent years); the inanities of fashion (Fra Angelico is 'in', Botticelli is
'out').
S
o far I have discussedcreativity in scienceand art, that is to say,
the highest forms of mental activity, with only occasional
referencesto the humbler routines of existence.I started at the
roof, as it were-what remainsto be done is to build up the wallswhich
support it.
The main purpose of this somewhat perverse procedure was to deal
:first with those subjectswhich are of primary interest to the general
reader and to establisha wider theoretical framework afterwards.But
there exist additional considerationsto justify this reversal of order.
At the Hixon Symposiumin 1948 K. S. Lashleyquoted with approval
a French author writing in 1887. 'The study of comparativegrammar,'
Lashleysaid, 'is not the most direct approach to the physiology of the
cerebral cortex, yet Fournie has written, "Speech is the only window
through which the physiologistcan view the cerebrallife." '1The word
'only' is, of course,an unwarranted exaggeration,but perhapsno more
unwarrantedthan the oppositeclaim, that the 'only' legitimatewindow
is that through which we watch the workings of the salivaryreflex in
dogs or the behaviour of rats in mazes. To repeat an argument from
the Preface to Book One: in the history of most scienceswe find
alternationsbetween the downward approach from roof to basement,
from the complex to the elementary, and the upward approach from
the elementary to the complex; until the two £nally merge. It was the
study of complex electro-magnetic phenomena which provided the
clue to sub-atomic structures.Tom out of the larger context in which
the 'elementary part' functions, it ceases to be a true elementary part
-whether we speakofelectrons,tissue-cells,or 'elementsofbehaviour'.
Geneticsstarted with morphologicalclassificationsand comparisonsof
whole organisms long before anything was known about chromo-
somes,genes, and nucleic acids. The use of undefined, 'dirty' concepts
as black boxes in theory-making has led into many cul-de-sacsin the
history of science,but was neverthelessindispensablefor its progress.
413
THE .ACT OP CREATION
•
PRENATAL SKILLS
O
rganic life, in all its manifestations,from embryonic develop-
ment to symbolic thought, is governed by 'rules of the
game' which lend it coherence,stability, and an appearance
of p~ose (or 'goal-directedness' if you prefer that term). These
rules or codes, whether phylogeneticallyor ontogeneticallyacquired,
function on all levels of the hierarchy, from the chromosomes to the
neuron-circuits responsiblefor verbal thinking. Each code represents
the fixed, invariant aspectof an adaptableskill or matrix of behaviour.
I shall take the stylistic licence of using the word 'skill' in a broad
sense,as a synonym for 'matrix', and shall speak of the morphogenetic
skills which enable the egg to grow into a hen, of the vegetative
skills of maintaining homeostasis, of perceptual, locomotive, and
verbal skills.
We shall find as a fundamental characteristicof codes on all levels
that they function on the trigger-releaseprinciple, so that a relatively
simple signal releasespre-set, complex action patterns. The signalmay
be mechanical,as in artificialparthenogenesisinduced by a pin-prick;
chemical (e.g. inducers and evocator substances); or neural (Tin-
bergen and Lorenz's Internal Rdeasive Mechanisms).But the pre-set
action pattern activated by the code is generally an elasticpattern, not
a rigid automatism (such as suggested, for instance, in Tinbergen's
schema). Skills have varying degreesof flexibility.The restraints im
posed by the code do not exhaustthe degreesof freedom possessedby
the matrix; there are usuallyvarious alternativechoicesleft to provide
for a 8.exiblestrategy according to the 'lie of the land'-i.e. guided by
feedback from the environment. Matrices thus function under the
dual control of an invariant code and a variable environment. These
two factors jointly determine which members of the matrix should
enter into action and in what order.
415
416 THE ACT OP CREATION
The Cell-Matrix
frog. Moreover, if the tissue of, say, the kidney area is (by centri-
fuging) completely disintegrated into freely floating separate cells dis
tributed at random, these cells, suspended in a proper medium, will in
due time produce rudimentary kidneys-just as the dissociated cells
of a living sponge, which has been broken up by straining through a
filter, will start to form new cell aggregates and end up by forming a
complete, normal sponge. 7
Thus a morphogentic field behaves 'as a unit or a whole and not
merely the sum of the cellular materials of which it is composed. The
field with its organizing capacities remains undisturbed if the cellular
material which it controls under normal circumstances is diminished
or en1arged. The unit character of the field finds its clearest manifesta-
tion in these regulative properties.' {Hamburger.8)
The various fields of the future organs and limbs form a mosaic in
the embryo as a whole; at the same time they display remarkable
regulative properties towards their own parts;-they are again Janus-
faced entities. Each organ primordium is, when 'looking upward', a
member of the total matrix; when 'looking downward', a self-
governing, autonomous sub-whole. Although the future of the field
in its entirety is clearly predetermined on the mosaic principle, the
future of its parts is still dependent on regulative factors. The cell-
populations which constitute an organ-primordiwn have lost their
genetic totipotentiality, but they still possess a sufficient amount of
multi-potentiality to keep the matrix of the field flexible. The shape of
the future organ is fixed, but the part which a given cell-group or
single cell will. play in it is again dependent on biochemical gradients
and inducers in the environment, which will trigger off the appro-
priate genes in the cells' genetic code.
The differentiation of organ systems, organ parts, etc., is a stepwise
affair which has been compared to the way a sculptor carves a statue out
of a block of wood. With each step in development the functions
assigned to each group of cells become more precise, and more of its
genetic potential is suppressed-until in the end most cells lose even
their basic freedom to divide. By the time the fertilized ovum has
developed into an adult organism, the individual cell has been re-
duced from totipotentiality to almost nullipotentiality. It still carries
the coded blue-print of the whole organism in its chromosomes, but all,
except that tiny fraction of the code which regulates its specialized
activities, has been permanently switched off.
Organizers and Inducers
the surface, but at the same time remain attached to the brain by the
optic stalks (which will develop into the optic nerves). In the process,
the vesicles assume the shape of concave saucers, the optic cups.
When these make contact with the surface, the skin areas overlaying
the contact areas fold neatly into the hollow cups, thicken, detach
themselves from the surface, and eventually become the transparent
lenses. It can be shown that it is the optic cup which induces the skin
to make a lens, for if the cup of a frog embryo is removed, no lens will
form; and vice versa, if the eye vesicle is grafted under the embryo's
belly, the belly skin will form a lens.
However, the docility of embryonic tissue has its limits. The tissue
must be 'competent'9 to react to the inductor; and 'competence' is
determined by the degree of differentiation the tissue has reached-or,
put in another way, by the amount of genetic multi.potential which it
still retains. An inductor 'cannot make any cell produce any specific
response unless the cell is intrinsically prepared to do so' •10 A given
region of the ectoderm. at a given stage of differentiation may retain
enough genetic flexibility to become either a lens or skin-tissue; it
will not be prepared to form. a kidney. In the experimental laboratory,
a transplanted eye-vesicle can be wed to induce a lens on the sala-
mander's belly. But under normal conditions the inductor's function
is to catalyze or 'evocate' the actualization of the genetic potentials
present in the appropriate tissue. Hence the term 'evocator-sub-
stance' for the chemical agent responsible for induction.
A curious fact about inductors is that they seem to be organ-specific
but not species-specific. The optic cup of a frog transplanted under a
salamander embryo's skin will cause it to produce a lens; the primary
organizer of the salamander will induce brain structures not only in
frogs but even in fuh;11 and the organizer of a frog, even of a fish, can
induce secondary embryos in the obliging salamander. But the in
duced embryo will be a salamander, not a frog or a fish; and the frog-
skin transplanted on to the salamander's head will form a frog-mouth,
not a salamander-mouth. In this respect, too the evocator seems to
act merely as a trigger-releaser on the genetic potential of the cell
This assumption was confirmed when Holtfreter, J. Needham, and
others discovered that rudimentary nervous systems could be in
ducted in salamander embryos by a great variety of Iiving or dead
organizers. These include most tissues of the adult salamander itself;
mouse-liver and insect organs, molluscs, acidified salt solutions,
sterols, and dye stuffs. Moreover, it was found that some tissues (such
PRENATAL SXILLS
To p. 418. This is, of course, not meant to belittle the enormous advantages
of sexual over asexual reproduction.
Top. 422. In some, probably extreme cases, the nuclear changes are even
more drastic. The nucleus of the fertilized egg of the gall-midge contains forty
chromosomes, and in the course of the first few divisions these are faithfully
duplicated. But in the ££th division, only eight sets of chromosomes in the soma
cells duplicate in the orthodox manner; the other thirty-two fail to do so and
gradually dissolve in the cytoplasm. The future germ cells, however, which have
previously been segregated from the rest of the eggs, do not participate in the
fateful fifth division and preserve their chromosome complement intact. Thus
the nuclei of all specialized body cells have only eight chromosomes, whereas
the germ cells have forty. C£ Fischberg, M. and Bladder, A. W. (x961).
Top. 435. During maturation in the higher species, the two types of control
overlap; and pre-set biological time-clocks seem to exercise some influence
throughout adult life.
II
Locomotor Hierarchies
FIGURE II
Let me enlarge on some of these points and add a few facts which
have emerged since.
In the first place it has been found that intrinsic, rhythmic activity
of an autonomous character is not confined to motor nerves, but that
'receptors also are spontaneously active even in the absence of stimula-
tion from environm.en.t.'8 This spontaneous receptor activity, while
modified by environmental events, is under efferent control from the
central nervous system. The central control (both of the spontaneous
receptor activity and of the input) is, as we shall see, primarily of a
restraining, inhibitory nature. But for the time being let us confine
ourselves to motor organization.
In an earlier paper (1941 a, p. 23) Weiss distinguished the following
levels of the hierarchy:
'1. The level of the individual motor unit.
'2. All ~e motor units belonging to one muscle.
'3. Co-ordinated functions of muscular complexes relating to a
single joint.
'4. Co-ordinated movements of a limb as a whole.
'5. Co-ordinated movements of a number of locomotor organs
resulting in locomotion.
'6."The highest level common to all animals'\ the movements of
"the animal as a whole" .'
THB ACT OF CREATION
Getting back to earth, that is, to the medium levels of the hierarchy-
the levels 3, 4, ands in Weiss's schema-we find, fortunatdy, more
precise indications about its manner of working.
Von Holst's study of the swimming motions of fish revealed a
distinct three-step hierarchy: (a) the motions of the rays within a
single fin, due to the alternative contractions of two antagonistic
pairs of muscles; (b) the motions of the fin as a whole; and {c) the co-
ordination of the motions of all the fins. In the anaesthetized goldfish,
the swinging motions of each individual ray remain perfectly regular,
but their co-ordination within the fin is disturbed: they Butter in dis-
order. The anaesthesia evidently does not affect the integrative centres
on the lowest (a) level, but puts the higher nervous centres on the (b)
level out of action. On the next higher, (c) level, the pectoral fin acts
as a kind ofpacemaker by imposing, or superimposing, its own rhythm
on the caudal fins-the so-called 'magnet effect'. This whole loco-
motor hierarchy is relatively independent of sensory stimuli, for
fishes and tadpoles go on swimming in perfect co-ordination if they
have been disafferentatecl, i.e. if all the main sensory connections have
been severed. Von Holst concludes that the stimulus-response schema
does not apply to the autonomous locomotive hierarchy, and that 'the
reflex is not the primary element of behaviour but a device for adapt-
ing the primary automatism to changing peripheral conditions' .11
Higher up on the evolutionary ladder we find increasing flexibility
THE UBIQUITOUS HIERARCHY 439
of motor skills. In a series of famous experiments, von Buddenbrook
and Bethe have shown that the removal cf one or several legs from
centipedes, spiders, and other insects does not lead to disorganization,
but to a spontaneous rearrangement of the whole pattern of loco-
motion which is instantaneous and not preceded by trial-and-error
learning. The normal progress of an insect or crab is the so-called
'cross-amble'. If 'L' and 'R' stand for left and right, and the index
numbers stand for the order of legs from front to rear, the crab's
locomotive code is as follows: R1, L2, Ra, L4, R5, etc., are stepping
simultaneously; then Li, R2, La, R4, Ls-are stepping simultaneowly;
and so on. If, now, the left front leg is removed, the pattern changes
instantaneously to: R1, L3, Rs, L5, etc.; followed by ~. R2, 14, R4, L6, etc.
The crab's progress before and after loss of the left front leg:
Before: 7 6 5 3 2 1
L ____.
After: J 6 3 2, i
)(1..--+
lt+
FIGURE I2
A
0
B0 C0 D0 E0
FIGURE I3
although both, being connected with the same nerve cell, receive
excitation equally .... The nature of every muscle is such that it does
not react to every excitation from the centre, but only to excitation of a
quite de.finiteform which is characteristic for it. '12
To account for the specific selectivity of muscle response, Weiss
uses the analogy of selective resonance in a broad sense. The acoustic
analysers of the ear each respond to one particular pitch and to one
only, thus analysing a complex clang into its harmonic elements.
Mutatis mutandis, Weiss assumes that:
' ... the total impulse flowing towards a particular peripheral
region from the central nervous system can, metaphorically speaking,
forthwith be designated as an "excitation clang". The "excitation
clang" is composed of "excitation tones" for the varying muscles
which are to be activated at a given moment, and hence is constantly
fluctuating in its composition .... The process now is as follows: at
the very same ti.me, the same "excitation clang" Bows through all
the motor root fibres (at least all those supplying a given functional
area of considerable extent) towards the periphery. It flows equally
through all the fibres as if it had been indiscriminately poured into a
canal system and were flooding all the channels. Thus it arrives at all
the muscles which are in any way whatever connected with the centre.
But when it gets to this point it is analysed. Every muscle, in accordance
with its constitution, selects the components appropriate to it from
those eventually arriving; and acts as if these components alone had
arrived, And thus, although the very same impulse streams to all the
muscles and across every available route, only that combination of
muscles comes into action-as is now intelligible-which the central
nervous system has provided for.'18
He then proceeds to show that the theory of selective response is
not contradicted by the indiscriminate responses of muscles to electro-
galvanic stimulation. The latter is an artificial, gross stimulation which
compares to natural stimulation like a violent a-periodic blast to a
specific clang. 'Just as, both with the clang and with the blast. the sub-
stratum carrying the movement is always the same, i.e. the air; so
obviously the medium in which both the organized and the un-
organized nerve impulse run their course is always the same. i.e. the
conductive substance of the nerve fibre. But just as the clang sets a
definite selection of resonators vibrating, whereas a noise or blast
causes them to resound all at once and without an exception; so also
on:J.y the organized impulse, built up of specific impulse-tones, is
THE UBIQUITOUS HIERARCHY 443
capable of bringing the co-ordinated selection of muscles into activity,
while the artificially induced, unorganized impulse, by contrast,
forces every muscle whatsoever which it reaches into functi.on.'1'
Let me translate the picture that emerges from the experimental
evidence into the terms of the present theory. The locomotor matrix
on level 4 of the hierarchy (p. 435) is represented by the muscular
structure of the limb, plus the 'canal-system' of nervous pathways
leading into it, and includes the apparatus-whatever its nature--
which accounts for the sdecti.vity of the response by enabling muscles
to analyse incoming impulses. The coae is the sequence of excitation-
clangs which calls forth one complete motion-say, one step of the
limb. Members of the matrix are the several joints on the next-lower
level No. 3, which are triggered off in a pre-set order by their sub-
codes, i.e. by the appropriate components of the excitation-dang.
We may remember by way of analogy, how part-sequences of the
genetic code are triggered into action in a pre-set order.
The 'motor unit' at the bottom of the hierarchy responds according
to the all-or-nothing rule, but the musculature of a joint is capable of
graded responses, and the motions of the whole limb follow a :Be:xible
strategy-shorter or longer step, swift or groping-dependent on the
input from the environment. Weiss accounted for these variations by
proposing that the excitation-clang 'is constantly :fluctuating in its
composition', and thus determines which single muscle should be
activated at any given moment. But this conception does not seem to
agree well with the basic principle that centres on high levels do not
deal directly with units on low levels of the hierarchy. A way out of
this difficulty is to be found in suggestions by Ruch (1951) and Miller
ct al. (x960 ), according to which pre-set patterns of skilled movements
arc triggered off as units by the brain; but the signal-i.e. the' excitation
clang'-would merely 'rough in' the sequence of movements 'and thus
reduce the troublesome transients involved in the correction of move-
ment by output-informed feedbacks' .15 Since feedback circuits must
be assumed to operate on every level, down to the single cell, the
adjustment of the details of the 'roughed-in' movement could be
handed over to lower levels. Miller et al. have made the further sugges-
tion that this handing-down procedure may be the equivalent of
converting an order coded in a 'digital' language, into a graded,
'analogue' output. The excitation-clang could thus consist in a series
of 'on', 'off' signals like the dots and dashes of the Morse code; but
each sub-unit could respond to its specific 'on' signal by a 'more' or
THE .ACT OP CREATION
Limits of Control
NOTES
•
III
DYNAMIC EQUILIBRIUM AND
REGENERATIVE POTENTIAL
Acting and ReactinJ
What is Equilibrium?
An organism can be said to function normally so long as the stresses
between internal and external milieu do not exceed a certain standard
range. To simplify the argument, let the term 'internal milieu' em-
DYNAMIC EQUILIBRIUM AND REGBNERATIVB POTENTIAL 449
brace all processes within the organism, and let us lump together the
nature, intensity, and duration of environmental excitations in a single
variable. We shall then be able to distinguish between (a) 'normal',
(b) 'paranormal' or 'traumatic', and (c) destructive environmental
conditions-though, needless to say, the boundaries between them
cannot be sharply defined.
The term 'dynamic equilibrium' shall apply only to a normal
organism functioning under 'normal' conditions. Under these con-
ditions the organ-systems, organs, and organ-parts of the animal per-
form their specific, autonomous functions as sub-wholes, at the same
time submitting to the regulative control imposed by the higher
centres. The control is exercised by excitatory and inhibitory pro-
cesses, but the latter play a vastly greater part. From the moment of
conception, the genetic potentials of the individual cell are further
restrained with every step in differentiation; and on every level of the
growing and mature organism inhibitory blocks, negative feedbacks,
growth-inhibiting hormones are at work. In the nervous system,
in particular, there is censorship at every step-to prevent overloading
of the information channels and overshooting of responses. Without
this hierarchy of restraints, the organism would instantly blow its
fuses in a kind of delirium agitans and then collapse.
Under normal conditions the part will not tend to escape the res-
training influence of the whole. Under paranormal conditions the
balance is upset. Thus the term 'balance' or 'equilibrium' takes on a
special meaning in the context of an organic hierarchy: it is not meant
to refer to relations between parts on the same level of the hierarchy,
but to the relation of a part to its controlling centre on the next higher level.
The stresses arise not between inputs 'competing for the final common
path,' as the expression goes, not between 'antagonistic drives' or
'conflicting impulses' (which do not directly communicate with each
other and cannot 'fight it out among th.emselves')-but between the
excited part and the whole, whose attention it is trying to monopolize:
in other words, between the self-assertive tendencies of the part and the
restraints imposed by the controlling centre. Equilibrium is maintained in
the organism by rules comparable to the procedure in a law court
where the opposing parties address themselves not to each other, but
to the judge.
This interpretation of equilibrium in a hierarchy was suggested in
my Insight and Outlook (p. 139 seq.), and independently proposed by
Tinbergen. In discussing the competition between various 'fi.'Ced
THE ACT OF CREATION
Physiological Isolation
These genetic potentials are the residues of the cell's erstwhile toti-
potentiality before differentiationset in-its original power to create
a whole new organism. Some of that power is reactivated when the
regeneration tissue-the part designed to replace the lost organ or
limb-is releasedfrom the controls which under normal conditions
keep it under restraint. For this partial or total secessionof the part
from the whole, C. M. Child coined the useful concept of 'physio-
logical isolation'.5
Physiologicalisolation may be regarded as a drastic form of dis-
equilibriumbetween the part and the whole. Its consequencesmay be
beneficial or deleterious. Child distinguishesfour causes for it. (a)
Growth of the whole beyond a critical limit may make it ungovern-
able so that parts of it find themselvesoutside the range of central
dominance and control. This may lead in lower organisms to re-
production by fusion or budding: the isolatedpart is either shed (as,
for instance,the planarian's tail) to form a new organism, or it may
de-differentiateand reintegrateinto a complete organism by budding.
(b) Decline of the organism'spowers of control (through senescence,
metabolic or hormonal disorders) may, in combination with other
causes,lead to a pathologicalregressionof cells and tissues with un-
tramelled proliferationand without reintegration, resulting in malig-
nant growths. (c) Partial obstructionor total blockageof (nervousand
DYNAMIC EQUILIBRIUM AND REGENERATIVE POTENTIAL 453
chemical) communications, and (d) persistent local excitation beyond
a critical limit, may release the part from its normal controls and
activate, for better or worse, its latent potentialities.
We shall see that Child's 'isolation' concept has a wide range of
applicability. In all cases, isolation of the part from the whole leads to
de-differentiation or other forms of regression; in some cases this is
followed by re-differentiation and reintegration. Isolation leading to
regression of an irreversible kind plays a considerable part in pathology,
psycho-pathology, and social pathology.* On the other hand, re-
gression followed by a progressive rebound releases creative potentials
which are normally under restraint. Its magic can be observed on every
level: from asexual reproduction to the repair of structural damage
and functional disorder, and further up to psychotherapy, scientific
discovery, and artistic creation. In the chapter which follows I shall
briefly discuss the manifestations of 'super-flexibility' of reculer pour
mieux sauter-on these various levels.
NOTE
To p. 453. Thus, for instance, Smithers in A Clinical Prospect of the Cancer
Problem (1960) stresses the decisive influence which Child's Physiological Foundtr
tions of Behaviour had on the development of his ideas.
IV
RECULER POUR MIEUX SAUTER
Structural Regenerations
I
n primitive organisms such as the flatworm, and in the early em-
bryonic stages of higher organisms, a physiologically isolated part
tends in general 'to lose its characteristics as a part and to become or
approach the condition of a new whole individual' .1Liberation of the
part's previously restrained genetic potential 'involves a change in
behaviour and structure from that of a part towards that of a whole
organism'.2 Such organisms could be said to live not only in dynamic
equilibrium. with their environment, but in a kind of 'regenerative
equilibrium.' which enables them to rise to virtually any challenge by
means of these secondary adaptations.
Some higher animals are still capable of regenerating lost organs or
limbs. Let us have a closer look how it is done. When a salamander's
leg has been amputated, the tissues near the wound surface de-differen-
tiate and the cells acquire an embryonic appearance. This is the regres-
sive or 'catabolic' phase. Around the fourth day begins the formation
of the blastema-the regeneration bud; and from here on throughout
the 'anabolic' or synthetic phase the process follows closely the forma-
tion of limbs in normal embryonic development.* The blastema
elongates into a cone and develops axially, the toes at its tip appearing
first, and the rest of the limb gradually taking shape as it grows in
length. When the organ is completed, central control is taken over
by the nervous system. just as in the case of the embryo. The nervous
system, however, also plays an indispensable part in initiating the first,
catabolic phase. If no peripheral nerves are present in the amputation
stump, regeneration does not occur.**
The 'isolated part' in this case is the amputation stump. The blastema
has in the beginning the multi-potential characteristics of the organ
primord.ia, and its re-differentiation again proceeds stepwise: if the
454
R.BCUL.BR POUR MIEVX SAUTER 455
field is split in half, each half gives rise to a whole organ; if one half is
removed, the remaining half will still develop into a complete limb.
Although the isolated part, transformed into a new organ primor-
dium (or its close equivalent), enjoys a high degree of independence
and controls the formation of the new limb, its ties with the higher
levels of the hierarchy are not completely severed. Its function in the
whole has changed; its normal controls (through the nervous system
and local chemical gradients) are out of action or even reversed; but
the organism as a whole nevertheless assists the regenerating part by
certain emergency measures-a 'general alarm reaction' followed by a
'general adaptation syndrome', each stage indicated by metabolic
changes and by the appearance of specific proteins and hormones in the
circulatory system.
Thus the isolation of the part is only temporary and relative; and
when the process is completed, the regenerated limb assumes its
normal function in the whole. The entire regressive-progressive
sequence is the means by which the animal's 'regenerative equilibrium'
enables it to adjust to traumatic experiences from the environment.
Looked at from a different angle, one might say that the whole
process is designed to prevent or correct malformations, i.e, faulty
integrations. Without the initial nerve supply, the regressing am-
putation stump would be resorbed, the scar tissue would close over
it, and the animal would achieve a modus vivendi as a cripple-a faulty
integration. On the other hand, a frog which will not normally re-
generate a lost limb will do so if the nerve supply to the stump is
a.rti.ficially augmented, providing the initial stimulus to start the pro-
cess. Traumatic challenges can only be met by the liberation of the
organism's latent powers-a temporary return to a more youthful or
primitive condition.
Reversed Gradients
'Routine Regenerations'
The last sentence that I have quoted leads into the borderland between
regenerative and 'norm.al' processes: namely routine replacements.
They range from the periodic moulting of feathers and shedding of the
antlers, to the replacement of the whole human epidermis about once
a month owing to wear and tear, and the replacement of red blood
cells at the rate of 3 X 1011 per day; not to mention the metabolic turn-
over on the molecular level which consumes about thirty per cent of
our total protein intake. This type of routine (or so-called 'physio-
logical') regeneration which goes on all the time is sometimes described
as a constant 'renewal' or 'rejuvenation' of the body. It is often im
possible to make a clear distinction between 'wear' and 'tear'-for
instance in minor abrasions of the skin. The differential factor is
obviously the degree of stress, which, past a critical threshold, will
bring general alarm reactions and 'adaptations of the second order'
into play.
Reorganizations of Function
fol ways. The results are all too familiar: personalities whose whole
outlook is dominated by prejudice and biassed values; the compulsive
rituals of neurotics; the devouring obsession of the crank; and so on
to the major psychoses in which large chunks of the personality have
been 'split off' and become permanently isolated from the rest. The
intrusion of magic causation; inability to distinguish between fact and
fantasy; delusions of grandeur, or persecution by invisible powers, are
symptoms of regression to earlier levels, of the de-differentiation of
thought-matrices-of reculer sans sauter.
Less extreme cases are neurotics who react to their traumatic experiences
by elaborating defence systems which enable them to find some kind of
modus vivendi with the world. One may call such behaviour-patterns
'faulty integrations'-like the newt's whose forelegs move back-
wards. Psychotherapy aims at undoing faulty integrations by inducing
a temporary regression of the patient to an earlier level, in the hope
that he will eventually reintegrate into a more stable pattern. Neuro-
surgery, shock-therapy, and related methods aim at releasing philo-
genetically older centres of the brain from cortical restraints. In a less
drastic form, Freudians, Jungians, etc., try to make the patient revert
to unconscious and infantile planes of experience, and to regenerate,
as it were, into a more or less new-born person.
Thus psychotherapy may be called an experiment in artificially in-
duced regeneration. It relies on the same basic process of reculer pour
mieux sauter, which we see operating on every level: from the flatworm
which replaces a lost head, through the crab which adjusts its gait to
the loss of a leg, to the rat which, unable to turn to the right, makes a.
three-quarter turn to the left. We found the same pattern repeated on
the level of human creativity: the scientist, faced by a perplexing situa-
tion-Kepler's discrepant eight minutes' arc, Einstein's light-traveller
paradox-must plunge into a 'dark night: of the soul' before he can re-
emerge into the light. The history of the sciences and arts is a tale of
recurrent crises, of traumatic challenges, which entail a temporary
disintegration of the traditional forms of reasoning and perception: a
de-differentiation of thought-matrices, a dismantling of its axioms, a
new innocence of the eye; followed by the liberation from restraint
of creative potentials, and their reintegration in a new synthesis,
The RoHtine of Dreaming
There is also a mental equivalent for the less spectacular routine re-
generation of tissues, designed to compensate for wear and tear. The
analogue process is the maintenance of 'mental tissues' exposed to the
wear and tear of diurnal stresses, by the regenerative effect of nocturnal
regressions to the primitive levels of the dream. Experimental evidence
seems to indicate that the restorative powers of sleep are primarily
derived from the process of dreaming. Experimental subjects who were
woken up each time their EEG waves indicated the onset of dreaming,
displayed symptoms of fatigue and nervous disorder; long periods of
dreamless sleep could not compensate for dream-deprivation. 'Man
cannot persist long in a conscious state,' wrote Goethe, 'he must throw
himself back into the unconscious, for his root lives there.'
We have seen (Book One, VII, Vill) that these periodic plunges
into the unconscious are accompanied by the temporary disintegra-
tion of matrices of logical thought. But they also entail a partial loss
of identity, a de-differentiation of the personality-as indicated by the
remarkable degree of uniformity in the contents of dreams shared by
people of very different character, and by the relatedness of these
contents to mythological themes and symbols. These shared patterns
led Jung to postulate a 'collective'-that is, individually undifferen-
tiated-level of the unconscious. On that level, members of the same
culture seem to share some degree of psychic equipotentiality ex-
pressed in 'archetypal symbols'. These are supposed to be condensa-
tions of basic experiences of the race in the distant past; hence their
great emotion-rousing potential.
To recapitulate: the fact that art and discovery draw on uncon-
scious sources indicates that one aspect of all creative activity is a
regression to ontogenetically or philogenetically earlier levels, an
escape from the restraints of the conscious mind, with the subsequent
release of creative potentials-a process paralleled on lower levels by
the liberation from restraint of genetic potentials or neural equi-
potentiality in the regeneration of structures and functions. The
scientist, traumatized by discordant facts, the artist by the pressures of
sensibility, and the rat by surgical intervention, share, on different
levels, the same super-flexibility enabling them to perform 'adapta-
tions of a second order', rarely found in the ordinary routines of life.
Regeneration and Creativity
"'i
l
l
These rather fancy diagrams are solely meant to indicate in a crude way
the complementary factors in the reculer pour mieux sauter phenomenon.
In A, increase in tissue-differentiation entails a reciprocal decrease of
genetic multi.potentiality. In B, an analogous reciprocity prevails
between unconscious intuitions and automatized routines-or, if you
like, between fluid imagery and 'misplaced concreteness'. R indicates
the 'regenerative span'. (The curve in A should of course have breaks
and a series of discrete steps.)
It could be objected that structural regenerations merdy restore the
status quo ante whereas mental reorganization leads to an advance. But
in the fust place this is not always the case. Psychotherapy aims at
correcting 'faulty integrations' caused by traumatic experiences-at
restoring normality. In the second place the biological evolution of
'the species with which we are concerned has to all intents and purposes
come to a standstill, whereas mental evolution continues, and its
vehicle is precisely the creative individual. The Eureka process is a
mental mutation, perpetuated by social inheritance. Its biological
equivalent are the genetic mutations which carried the existing species
up the evolutionary ladder. Now a mutation-whatever its unknown
THE ACT OF CREATION
NOTES
To p. 454. It is still an open question, however, whether or how much
undifferentiated 'reserve cells' (as in lower animals) contribute material to the
blastema.
Top. 454. It seems that the initial role of the nervous system is to determine
the main axis of the regenerate-that it acts, not as an inductor, but as a trophic
agent. At the later, anabolic stages of the process no nerve supply is needed-as
denervation experiments show.
Top. 456. This, actually, is the only clearly demonstrated case of metaplasia
among higher animals.
Top. 459. About the ways how this is achieved, cf. McCulloch in the
ffixon Symposium, p. 56.
v
PRINCIPLES OF ORGANIZATION
B
efore we tum to adult behaviour, a pause for stocktaking may
be in order. _
In a four-dimensional continuum, embryonic devdopment
would be represented by an ascending hierarchy of spatial levds per-
pendicular to the time axis. In spite of the perplexing diversity of
phenomena on different levels-cleavage, gastrulation, induction,
neuro-genesis-certain basic principles were seen to operate on every
level throughout the hierarchy. Principles (or 'laws of nature') can
only be described in symbolic language of one kind or another. The
language used in the present theory is based on four key-concepts:
motivation, code, matrix, and environment. Since these are assumed to
operate in a hierarchic framework, the dichotomy of sdf-asserting and
participatory tendencies of behaviour on all levels need not be separately
postulated, but derives logically, as it were, from the dual character
of every sub-whole as a sub-ordinate and supra-ordinate entity.
Let me now recapitulate some of the main points which have
emerged from the previous chapters, taken in conjunction with
Book One:
I. Motivation in embryonic development is a subject for the meta-
physician. J. Needham's tongue-in-the-cheek phrase about 'the
striving of the blastula to grow into a chicken' indicates the directive-
ness of the morphogenetic process and its equifinal, regulative proper-
ties, which become particularly evident under adverse conditions.
These properties represent the genetic precursors of the motivational
drives, needs, and goal-directedness of the adult animal; during matura-
tion, the former shade into the latter, and there is no sharp dividing line
between them.
2. 'A part is a whole is a part'. Each sub-whole is both a ·sub' and a
467
THE ACT OP CREATION
codes; and they in tum activate their members as units through their
sub-codes.
To put it in a different way: each part-process is a pattern of relations;
but it is manipulated from the next-higher level as a unit-a relatum.
We shall see that as a general rule, when we ascend in any hierarchy,
relations turn into relata, which enter into new relations, and so on.
The code can be said to represent the invariant pattern of a relation;
the matrix the ensemble of the relata. But one step up, and the code
itself becomes a relatum; one step down, and the members of the
matrix are seen as complex relations. We may thus add one more pair of
complementary terms to characterize the Janus-faced entities in the de-
vdopmental hierarchy: part<--> whole; structure<--> func-
tion, regulative <-- > mosaic, autonomous <-- > dependent,
relation <-- > relatum, matrix <-- > code.
8. The stresses set up between the organism's inner and outer en-
vironment are matched by active adaptations on various scales. The
term 'dynamic equilibrium' indicates adaptative processes which do
not entail major changes in the pattern of the whole; 'regenerative
span' refers to the organism's capacity for 'adaptations of the second
order' to challenges which can be met only by a reshaping of structures
or a reorganization of functions; while 'routine regenerations' occupy
an intermediary position, and overlap with both.
'Equilibrium' in this context refers not to relations between parts,
but between the excited part and the controls which represent the
whole. Under conditions of dynamic equilibrium, the stresses between
the self-assertive tendencies of the excited part and its integrative
controls are of a transitory character. Paranormal challenges may lead
to the phenomenon of' physiological isolation', owing to over-stimula-
tion of the part or blockage of communication with its normal con-
trols. In lower organisms, the isolated part tends to develop into a
new whole. If it was segregated ab ovo, as sex cells and regeneration
cells are, this development follows a straight course; if isolation occurs
at later stages, as in :fissure, budding, and organ-regeneration, it in-
volves a temporary regression of the part to an embryonic or more
juvenile phase of development, and the liberation of genetic potentials
which are normally under restraint. It is a safety device which enables
the organism to cope with traumatic challenges, and correct faulty
integrations; it furthermore confers on it a super-flexibility which
plays an important part in biological and mental evolution.
On higher levels of the evolutionary scale, regenerative processes
PRINCIPLES OP ORGANIZATION 473
are predominantly reorganizationsoffunctions. These range from the
repair of neuro-muscular co-ordination to the compensation of cor-
tical damages, and to the re-structuring of perceptual and conceptual
patterns in the reculer pour mieux sautet of the creative process.
During the regressive,catabolic phase, the part tends to dominate
the whole through the reversal of axial gradients and hierarchic con-
trols. This may lead to irreversible changes of a pathological nature
(malignant growths, idle fixe ). To avoid snapping of the loosenedties,
the isolation of the part must be temporary and not complete: after
the routine-controls have gone out of action, the organism as a whole
must assistthe regenerativeprocess.
'Routine repairs" were seen to range from the regeneration of tissues
lost through wear and tear, to the restorativee.ffects of sleep.Dreaming
could be described as a de-differentiationof reasoning-matricesand
even, up to a point, of personal identity.
9. These periodic 8.uctuationsfrom the highest level of integration
down to earlier or more primitive levels and up again to a new,
modified pattern, seem to play a major part in biologicaland mental
evolution. Their universalityis reflectedin the myths of death and re-
birth, the 'dark night of the soul', etc. The 'magic' of organ-regenera-
tions, and of unconscious guidance in creativity, both owe their
striking character to the sudden re-activation of (morphogenetic or
psychogenetic) potentials which are normally under restraint in the
adult individual. The period of incubation may be compared to the
cata.bolicphase in organ-regeneration: the former releasespre-con-
ceptual, intuitive modes of ideation from the censorshipimposed by
the consciousmind; the latter triggers off embryonic growth-processes
equally inhibited by the mature organism. The contact-guidance of
nerves towards their end-organs and the revival of other pre-natal
skills, provide enticingparallelsto the unconsciousgradients and ancient
'waterways' which mediate the underground rendezvousof ideas.
Summary
were seen to operate on all levels, such as: {a) the dichotomy of self-
assertive and participatory tendencies derived from the dual character
of each part as a 'sub' and a 'whole'; and the related complementarity
of regulative and mosaic development, of equipotentiality and fixed
pathway, of rdati.ons and relata, (b) Control within the organic hier-
archy is exercised by 'regulation channels', i.e. high centres do not
normally have direct dealings with lowly ones, and vice versa. (c)
Trigger-rdeaser devices seem to be the general rule in the activation of
pre-set, autonomous patterns. (d) The releaser signals (excitation-
clangs, frequency-modulation sequences?) from higher echelons were
found to be of a more implicit, generalized order than the actual per-
formance 'spelled out' by the addressee. (e) The pattern of the per-
formance :is determined by its invariant code, but sub-wholes have
varying degrees of freedom for adaptable strategies (equipotential
variations) dependent on feedback from their local environment.
(f) Under normal conditions these flexible strategies are sufficient to
restore dynamic equilibrium between the whole and its excited parts.
(g) Traumatic experiences may cause irreversible, degenerative changes
in the exposed part, but under favourable conditions may initiate
supedicxiblc adaptations of a second order-regenerations of structure
or reorganieations of function, which are capable of redressing faulty
integration, and also play an important part in biological and mental
dcvdopment.
The reader may consider some of these conclusions trivial, others
perhaps as rash generalizations. In the following chapters their validity
willbe tested in the light of instinct-behaviour, learning. and problem-
solving.
NOTE
To p. 470. 'Feedback' is used here in a broad sense, to include all exeero-
ceptive and proprioceptive inputs relevant to the ongoing activity.
VI
CODES OF INSTINCT BEHAVIOUR
The Genetics of Behaviour
inclined to call this a rather risky attitude; and what is the individual
survival value of not hitting (or biting, goring) below the belt? Or if
it com.es to that, of the digger-wasps' nerve-racking maternal activities?
'A female of this species, when about to lay an egg, digs a hole,
kills or paralyses a caterpillar, and carries it to the hole, where she
stows it away after having deposited an egg on it (phase a). This done,
she digs another hole, in which an egg is laid on a new caterpillar. In
the meantime, the first egg has hatched and the larva has begun to
consume its store of food. The mother wasp now turns her attention
again to the first hole (phase b ), to which she brings some more moth
larvae; then she does the same in the second hole. She returns to the
first hole for the third time to bring a final batch of six or seven cater-
pillars (phase c), after which she doses the hole and leaves it for ever.
In this way she works in turn at two or even three holes, each in a
different phase of development. Baerends investigated the means by
which the wasp brought the right amount of food to each hole. He
found that the ~wasp visited all the holes each morning before leaving
for the hunting grounds. By changing the contents of the hole and
watching the subsequent behaviour of the wasp, he found that (1)
by robbing a hole he could force the-wasp to bring far more food than
usual; and (2) by adding larvae to the hole's contents he could force
her to bring less food than usual.'4
Let me repeat: the reason why 'a genetics of behaviour still has to be
developed' seems to be that it cannot be developed with the existing
theoretical tools without reducing the whole attempt to absurdity.
It may still be possible, and even respectable today for a geneticist to
state that: 'The hoary objection of the improbability of an eye or a
hand or a brain being evolved "by blind chance" has lost its force.'$
But are we also to assume that the behaviour-patterns of the digger-
wasp, or of the courtship and fighting rituals of various species have
all evolved 'by pure chance'? This assumption is implied in the doctrine
of contemporary genetics-though rardy stated in explicit form.
Similar assumptions have been made by extreme behaviourists in the
:field of leaming theory; there is, in fact, a direct continuity between
the doctrine of natural selection operating on random mutations, and
reinforcement operating on random trials. Both grew out of the same
philosophical climate. But while learning theory is in full retreat from
that extreme position, and has a variety of alternative suggestions to
offer, nothing the like is in sight in the genetics of instinct-behaviour.
Instinct and Learning
Tinberge11 s Hierarchy
1
FIGURE I5
In spring the lengthening of days triggers off the small fish's 'migra
ting code', while hormonal activities provide the drive or motivation.
The fish then migrates into shallow water and swims around until a
certain environmental configuration (rise of temperature, combined
with green vegetation, etc.) strikes the 'right note', i.e. releases an
efferent impulse, which in tum triggers off the sub-code of the nest-
building activity. This activity is again subdivided into digging, glue-
ing, etc., each of these skills governed by its autonomous sub-code.
The latter are activated by trigger releasers; the order of operations is
determined· by inputs from the environment and proprioceptive
feedbacks. The hierarchy of mating behaviour remains blocked until
nest-building is complete; but the 'fighting' hierarchy (with its :five
different sub-codes) may be called at any moment into action by a
trigger mechanism sensitive to a specific sign-Gestalt input: 'red male
enterll!&!erritory'. In this case the fighting code dominates the animal's
THE ACT OP CREATION
... Lorenz has pointed out ... that purposiveness, the striving towards
an end, is typical only of appetitive behaviour and not of consumma-
tory actions.... Whereas the consummatory act seems to be dependent
on the centres of the lowest level of instinctive behaviour, appetitive
behaviour may be activated by centres of all the levels above that of
the consummatory act.... 21 The centres of the higher levels do control
purposive behaviour which is adaptive with regard to the mechanisms
it employs to attain the end. The lower levels, however, give rise to
increasingly simple and more stereotyped movements, until at the
level of the consummatory act we have to do with an entirely rigid
component, the taxis, the variability of which, however, is entirely
dependent on changes in the outer world. This seems to settle the
controversy; the consummatory act is rigid, the higher patterns are
purposive and adaptive:22
But what exactly, one might ask, constitutes a 'consummatory act'?
A glance at Tinbergen' s diagram on page 4 79, for instance, will show
that all actual manifestations of the reproductive instinct are classified
as 'consummatory acts', whereas 'building', 'fighting', etc., are merely
abstract, classificatory terms in which longer sequences of consum-
matory acts are bracketed together. Where, then, is the 'appetitive
behaviour'? In the stickleback's spring migration in search of a nesting
site? But that action-pattern was, judged by its dependence on specific
releasers (temperature, verdant vegetation, etc.) on the same 'con-
summatory' level as, for instance, 'testing of materials'. The nearest
Tinbergen gets to a definition of the consummatory act is in the
following passage:
'The activation of a centre of the lowest level usually, perhaps always,
results in a relatively simple motor response: biting, chasing, threaten-
ing, etc., in the case of fighting actual eating, actual escape, actual
coiti.on, etc., in other instincts These relatively simple responses
are, usually, the end of a bout of prolonged activity, and their per-
formance seems to "satisfy" the animal, that is to say, to bring about a
sudden drop of motivation. This means that such an end-response
consumes the specific impulses responsible for its activation. Fighting,
eating, mating, "playing the broken wing" etc., are, as a rule, "self-
exhausting" .'23
However, neither 'digging' nor 'leading female to nest' is an end-
response, or self-exhausting, or leads to a 'drop in motivation'. 'Testing
of materials' is not a consummation, but a part-activity in the flexible,
i.e. 'appetitive', pattern of(i,uilding. And the building activity is not a
CODES OF INSTINCT BEHAVIOUR
are both 'appetitive' and 'consummatory', but that some are more
appetitive and some more consummatory than others.
What really matters in our context is the continuous scale of grada-
tions between rigid and flexible action-patterns. Somewhere near the
middle of the scale we find the common spider, whose web-making I
have already used as a paradigm for an invariant yet adaptable built-in
code (Book One, p. 38). It will suspend its familiar net from three,
four, or more points of attachment, according to the lie of the land;
yet the centre of the polygonal web will always coincide with its
centre of gravity and the radial threads will always intersect the lateral
threads at equal angles. We thus have a simple fixed code, yet a highly
flexible strategy. Moreover, if some of the garden spider's legs and
claws are amputated, it will still construct a more or less normal net-
the code remains unaffected by the elimination of some members of
the matrix.
Towards the 'rigid' end of the scale we find reflex-like matrices, exem-
plified in the so-called Leerla,if activities. This term, too, was coined
by Lorenz; the current English translation is 'vacuum activity' -but
•freewheeling' would perhaps be more appropriate. Seagulls, reared
in isolation, will perform on the stone floor of the laboratory their
characteristic 'tap-dance' which, under normal circumstances, would
serve to bring small animals to the surface of the tidal mud. Cats will
go through the motion of burying their faeces on the kitchen tiles; and
hand-reared young flying-squirrels 'when given nuts, would go through
all the motions of burying them in the bottom of the wire-cage, and
then go away contented, even though the nuts were exposed to full
view'. 26 The same author describes the behaviour of hand-reared
tawny owls 'which, after being fed, would act as if pouncing upon
living prey though it had never had the experience of dealing with a
living mouse'. 27
Such examples of 'stupid', automaton-like behaviour are the stron-
gest evidence for innate codes of action. At the same time they are
also additional evidence against the chain-reflex theory of instinct-
". behaviour: the owl, which has never seen a mouse, pounces after being
fed, and with.out any visual stimulus; in the gull's case, the hard floor
of the laboratory is a stimulus quite different from the sofi: mud-hence
the •chain-reaction' ought never to start, or to break off after the .first
CODES OP INSTINCT BEHAVIOUR
NOTES
Top. 481. The equivalent of the term 'appetitive behaviour' in American
behaviourist theory are Hull's drive-stimulus (Sn); and his 'fractional ante-
dating goal-stimuliand responses'(SG Ro}.
Top. 481. Out of this grew the theory that the fixed pattern of the con-
summatory act-and not the 'appeted stimulus'-is the goal of the animal's
strivingand the source of the 'action-specificenergy' of the drive; but the subject
is outside the scope of this book.
VII
IMPRINTING AND IMITATION
S
o far we have discussedthe codes of morphogenesisand innate
behaviour, which emerge ready-made from the black boxes of
evolution-like Ali Baba's thieves, popping out of the urns in
which they were hiding.
In the chapters which follow we shall discuss the ontogenesis of
behavioural codes-the acquisitionof habits, knowledge, skills, by the
processesof learning from experience.
The 'Following-response'
advances. Many other birds, and possibly also some fish and insects,
show the phenomena of imprinting in varying degrees.
Here, then, we have a pregnant example of the genesis of a matrix
through the integration of innate and acquired behaviour-patterns.
The built-in 'following response' has the characteristic autonomy of
motor-patterns which we have met before: it is triggered off and modi-
fied, but not created by the environmental input. The first step in the
development of the matrix is the act of imprinting itself; it must occur,
as already mentioned, during the critical phase when the young bird
is susceptible for it (in ducks, for instance, between eleven and eighteen
hours after birth, with a pointed peak in the susceptibility curve at
sixteen hours).1 The input which triggers off the following-response
is at this stage an undifferentiated and primitive sign-releaser: 'Large
moving object' -much simpler in character than the more specific
Gestalt stimuli which release the :fighting or mating instinct in the
sticlcleback ('red belly', 'swollen belly') or the begging response of the
herring-gull chick ('red spot on beak').
The next stage is one of perceptiial learning. After a few hours, even a
few minutes, of following a human being, the gosling will follow only
human beings-it has somehow learned to 'abstract', or 'encode' in its
memory some specific Gestalt-characteristics of homo saplens which
distinguish it from other 'shapes that move'. On the other hand, at
this stage all human beings are still 'equipotential' members of the
emergent perceptual matrix. At a still later stage, the goose may
become attached to one or more single individuals, that is to say, it
learns to discriminate individuals within the species-as, vice versa,
animal breeders learn to sharpen their perception and to distinguish
one sheep or goose from another.
We thus meet, already on this level, the twin phenomena involved
in all learning processes: generalization ('transfer', 'abstraction') and
discrimination (segregation of pattern, selective inhibition of responses
to non-specific stimuli). These basic processes will be discussed later
(Chapter X}; in the meantime, let us note that the innate, primitive
'rule of the game' which made the new-born animal respond to 'things-
that-move', has been sharpened and elaborated into a more complex
set of rules by a series of steps. Each of these steps involved a re-
structuring of the perceptual matrix by successive generalizations and
discriminations-which we may regard as quasi-extensions of func-
tional integration and structural differentiation into the learning pro-
cess. Morphogenesis and learning form continuous series which over-
IMPRINTING .AND IMITATION 491
lap during maturation; and the matrices of innate and acquired be-
haviour form an equally continuous hierarchy.
Untapped Resources
NOTES
Top. 491. The chaffinch song consists of three distinct and well-articulated
phrases. Hand-reared chaffinches produce a much simplified, rudimentary variant
of the song, where the first and second phrase are often inseparable, and the third
partly or wholly missing. But-and this is the elegant point of the experiment-
if the young bird is left to be reared by its parents, then taken away and isolated
in September, that is to say, long before it starts singing, it will nevertheless burst
into normal song next spring. Apparently 'these birds have by their first Septem-
ber learned that the song "should" be in three phrases and that the terminal phrase
should contain a more or less elaborate flourish'. Thus 'on the perceptory side
the process of recognizing and accepting the specific song as henceforth the
"normal" for the individual (as distinct from the acquisition of the new motor
habits involved in performing the song) seems to resemble the original examples
of imprinting [the following response I sufficiently close to warrant considering
them together' (Thorpe, 1956, p. 375).
Top. 491. In the human child, processes analogous to Priigung may perhaps
be responsible for producing infantile fixations and fetishistic rituals. The cases
of boot-fetishism, for instance, frequently reported in works on sexual pathology
remind one of imprinting by inanimate objects-such as a gander's seven-year
fixation on an oildrum, reported by Thorpe (p. 365). A further analogy may be
found between Gestalt-sign releasers, based on the vital statistics of film-stars, and
Tinbergen's simplified laboratory models of the pregnant stickleback.
Top. 493. Thorpe continues: 'However, the answer may be that the nature
ofsensory nervous mechanisms is such that to achieve full efficiency at the normal
level of stimulation, the threshold must be much lower.' (Thorpe, 1956 p. 283).
1
But other passages which I have quoted show that he does not regard this ex-
planation as satisfactory.
VIII
MOTIVATION
Retrospect
momentary peep into the upright bag, at the dreadful object lying
quietly at the bottom.'29
This was written half a century before Kohler's Mentality of Apes
was translated into English-with a delay of eight years after the
appearanceof the German original.30 It had the effect of something
like a bombshell on American psychology, in which Pavlov and
Watson were all the rage. Yet even Kohler, though he attacked
Thorndike, remained essentiallyconservative as far as motivation is
concerned; it took another quarter-century for a new crop of experi-
mentalists to discover, in the 1950s, that the exploration of novelty,
the manipulation of objects, the dismantling and reassembling of
complex manual puzzles,and even scribblingand drawing were self-
rewarding and self-arousingactivities.
'Those who have had opportunitiesto observe monkeys and apes at
close hand for prolonged periods invariably dwell on their addiction
to looking, mauling, prodding, licking, and ~nerally squeezingevery
drop of possible entertainment from whatever crosses their path.'31
Particularlyrevealingis the fact that Rhesusmonkeyswho have learned
to dismantlea complex manual puzzleofinterlockingpiecesperformed
better when there was no food reward put inside the puzzle than when
they knew that there was one. In the second case they got impatient
and tried short-cuts; in the first case they practised disinterestedly,
'l' art pour l' art'. 82
while kittens, puppies, and young chimps seem to spend a major portion
of their time in 'locomotive exploration'. Lastly, we come to 'investi-
gatory' or 'inquisitive' behaviour, ranging from Darwin's monkey who
cannot refrain from peeping into the snake-infested Pandora's box, to
the 'insatiable curiosity' of the artist and explorer.
Thus neuro-physiological considerations, laboratory work with
animals, and the observations of ethologists of the Lorenz-Tinbergen
school, all seem to converge in the same direction. Even the embryo-
logical studies of Coghill (pp. 430££) and Weiss (p. 434 seq.), with their
emphasis on spontaneous, intrinsic activities on all levels of the organic
hierarchy, lend indirect support to the primacy of the exploratory
drive. The lesson of fifty years of rats-in-mazes has been summed up,
e.g. by Thacker in the statement that 'motivation for learning is
central and neural ••. organized and proliferated cognitive structure
itself is the goal towards which learning moves'.s9 In other words,
the motivat{on for learning is to learn.
Thorpe, for all his habitual caution, has gone even further. He
starts with a rhetorical question: 'And so it becomes important to
consider how far th.ere is evidence of learning motivated by a general
drive quite independent of the motivation of particular instincts' ;40
and he concludes that 'th.ere is now substantial and precise evidence for
a general drive in a number of animals, and this can be looked upon
as an indication of a primary motivation which to some extent, how-
ever slight, is superior to the governing centres of any of the instincts
or of their combinations, and finds its most characteristic expression
in exploratory behaviour in all its various forms'. ,1
In his monograph on The Nature of Explanation (1943), which has
inspired a great many neurologists and computer-theorists, the
Cambridge psychologist K. J. Craik: put forward the idea that the
function of the organism's nervous system. is to set up a symbolic
model of the external world: 'The brain • • . imitates or models
external processes. The function of such symbolization is plain. If the
organism carries a "small-scale model" of external reality and of its
own possible actions within its head, it is able to try out various alter-
natives, conclude which is the best of th.em, react to future situations
before they arise, utilize the knowledge of past events in dealing with
the present and future, and every way to 'react in a. much fuller, safer,
and more competent manner to the emergencies which face it.'42
To extract information from the chaotic environment is as vital
to the organism as it is essential for it to extract specific forms of
MOTIVATION
NOTES
Top. 496. Ernest Jones says in his biography: 'Freud partook in much of the
prudishness of bis time, when allusions to lower limbs were improper'. He then
gives several examples-such as Freud 'sternly forbidding' his fianeee to stay
'with an old friend, recently married, who, as she delicately put it, "had married
before her wedding,,' Gones, I9S3, Vol. I, p. 142).
Top. soo. 'His thinking was particular, not general. When he thought of
secondary drive, he thought of ••. fear or anxiety. When he thought of secon-
dary reinforcement, he thought of such things as •.• tokens substituting for food'
(Hilgarcl. 19ss, p. 177).
British Welfare State. Its rudiments can be found even in the rat and pigeon-as
Skinner himself pointed out-when rewards are given rarely and irregularly;
this treatment induces the creature to go on trying for an astonishingly long time
without a single reward-just as Britons will fill in week after week their foot-
ball coupons.
IX
PLAYING AND PRETENDING
L
ogically every book on learning theory ought to have between
the sections on 'innate behaviour' and 'acquired behaviour' a
chapter on 'learning through play'-or, at least, on 'ludic
behaviour' (from ludere, to play)-a term coined by Berlyne, pre-
sumably to make the subject sound more respectable. The role of play
in the learning and practice of skills is too obvious to naturalists and
pedagogues to need stressing; yet play was another stepchild of the
Psychology of the Dark Ages. Its connotations of curiosity, explora-
tion, frivolousness and joie de vivre did not appeal to the spirit of the
times; its unpredictability did not fit the S.-R. schema; above all, its
self-reinforcing motivation, dissociated from the primary physio-
logical needs, stood in flagrant contradiction to any drive-reducing
theory. Thus the concept of 'ludic behaviour' was objectionable on
the same grounds as the concept of the exploratory drive; the former
appears in fact to be the purest manifestation of the latter.
Difficulties of Definition
A further reason for this neglect may have been the difficulty of de-
fining 'play'* without making the definition circular. By way of
elimination, let us try to distinguish between true play and vacuum
activities during maturation. A young bird toys with straws and
feathers 'aimlessly' before the other action-patterns of the nest-
building instinct have matured; displays of fragmentary mating be-
haviour before sexual maturity fall into the same category. Some of
these activities look playful in the sense of serving no apparent pur-
pose (although in fact they may be weful as 'practice runs' in develop-
ing a skill); yet they can hardly be regarded as true play because they
509
,SIO THB ACT OP CREATION
It follows from the above that play can only arise at an evolutionary
level or in such special situations, where the organism has been partially
liberated from the tyranny of 'primary needs' in the traditional sense,
and can afford to 'take time off' to play. This happens among animals
where the young mature slowly and enjoy prolonged parental pro-
tection and care; under the sheltered conditions of domestication and
captivity; and in human history, of course, with the increase of security
against the hazards of the natural and social environment. To quote
Thorpe again: 'The prolonged childhood of the human species [has]
been of prime importance in the process of freeing appetitive behaviour
from the primary needs. This and man's growing mastery of his
environment have been the essential first steps not only for play but
for all those activities which transcend mere maintenance and which
underlie the mental and spiritual development of man; activities
which, though originating in "play", have produced real advantages
in knowledge and comprehension, of the scheme of things ... .'3
A related process of emancipation, namely the detachment of reason-
ing from emotion, gave rise, as we saw, to humour. Man's emergent
ability to perceive a thing or event simultaneously in two incompatible
mental contexts enabled him to take the step from the 'ludic' to the
'ludicrous'. The historic link between the two is probably reflected in
the word 'ludicrum'-stage play. The actor's or bard's pretence of
being himself and somebody else at the same time was at the origin of
tragedy and epic; a similar act of magic-carving or painting a thing
which is meant to be something else-was the origin of representational
art. These, of course, are activities on an incomparably higher level
than the play of kittens and birds; yet as Lorenz has pointed out, both
imitation and pretence occur already on the animal level. When
puppies fight in play, they do not hurt each other or their masters;
they conform to certain 'rules of the game'. Whether these have their
phylogenetical origin in the ritualized fights of their wild ancestors or
whether they are acquired by social learning, the fact remains that such
fights are 'not in earnest' and necessitate 'bringing in the "higher" or
more psychological concept of''pretence'' '·'
Equally suggestive is the so-called 'sub-song' of birds. As distinct
from the true or full song which is fixed and species-specific, the sub-
song is 'a somewhat amorphous, rambling utterance'. 0 Birds indulge
in it when their 'primary needs' are not pressing-before the mating
SII
SI2 THE ACT OF CREATION
NOTE
To p. 509. The Concise Oxford Dictionary gives no less than thirty-four
meanings of the word.
x
PERCEPTION AND MEMORY
I
must now switch from animal to man, and later back again. The
manner in which animals learn holds important lessonsfor man;
but in order to interpret the data the experimenter must make
certain minimum assumptionsregarding the animals' experiences;and,
whether he is aware of it or not, these assumptionsare based on his
own human experience. We talk about the animal's pain-reaction or
fear-reactionbecausewe have experiencedpain and fear; we interpret
certain signsas meaning that the animal is alert or apprehensiveby in-
ferences which are often unconscious and contain an unavoidably
anthropomorphicelement. Even Lloyd Morgan's canon acknowledged
this; it merely said that one shouldnot be more anthropomorphic than
one could help.*
Now, learning involvesperceptionand memory; and sincewe know
incomparably more about both in man than in cats or rats, we must
discuss some aspects of man's perceptual and sensory-motor skills.
before we turn to learning in animals. Instead of the over-worked
province of visual perception. I shall start, for a change, on hearing.
the cat's auditory nerve was tapped and wired to an amplifier, so that
impulses passing from ear to brain were directly recorded. The im-
pulses were caused by the clicking of a metronome. But the moment
a mouse in a glass jar was shown to the cat the firings in the auditory
nerve were diminished or ceased altogether: the cat was turning a
'deaf ear' on the metronome. The point of the experiment was to
show that the process of stimulus-selection is centrally controlled, but
sets in at the periphery-the outer gate of the Kremlin compound.
Attitude and expectation-the pattern of the behavioural matrix to
which the organism is attuned at the time-determine what shall con-
stitute a stimulus and what shall not. On a happy family evening, when
people are talking while the radio is playing, junior is crying, and the
dog is begging to be let out, each of these simultaneous inputs may be
perceived as 'signal' and the rest as 'noise'. In audition, at least, the
'figure-background relation' seems to be more complicated than the
Gestalt school suggests; it is not something innate in perceptual organi-
zation, but dependent on past experience and present state of mind.
Women were known to sleep soundly through an air-raid but to
awake at the slightest cry of their babies; people deeply asleep show
sharp EEG reactions when their own name, or the name of a girl-
friend, is read out in a list of other 'background' names.s
The point has also an indirect bearing on the controversy whether
discrimination is based on the 'absolute' or relational properties of
stimuli.3 The answer seems to be, briefly, th.at absolute stimuli do not
exist-short of sticking a knife into somebody. Yet even on the
primitive level of pain, the matrix influences perception-as wit-
nessed by the General in the American Civil War who, in the heat of
battle, did not notice that his middle finger was shot away; not to
mention anaesthesia by hypnosis in dentistry and child-birth-or the
even more remarkable phenomena of hysterical conversion blindness.
Thus the higher centres exercise a selective influence on sensation and
perception; those aspects of the input which are irrelevant will be treated
as noise, and forgotten 'without leaving a trace'. But the criteria of rele-
vance depend on the 'rules of the game' which the organism is playing
at the time.
Selective control of the input is the first stage in the process of ex-
tracting information from the chaotic noises and other sensations which
PERCEPTION .AND MBMORY SIS
bombard the organism's receptors; without it, the mind would be in
a kind of Brownian motion. This first stage is followed by the proces-
sing of the input in a series of relaying operations, each of them designed
to strip the input of what appears to be irrelevant=-according to the
criteria of relevance which operate along that input-channel. One
might call this a process of de-panicularization. It is a clumsy word, but
it conveys what is really implied in the terms 'generalization' or 'ab-
straction', with their multiple connotations.
The most familiar examples of 'de-particularization' are, of course,
the visual constancies. The triangle, or the letter 'W', is stripped of the
irrelevancies of retinal position, size, etc. Thanks to colour constancy
the accidents of light and shadow are discarded; than.ks to size con-
stancy, my moving hand does not seem to shrink or grow-changes in
perspective size are 'dis-regarded' by the regard. Yet the criteria of
relevance and irrelevance depend, even in these cases of apparently
spontaneous perception, to a considerable degree on interpretative
frames-on perceptual matrices acquired by past experience. When
an object of the appearance of a tennis ball is inflated against a homo-
geneous background, it will be seen as if it were retaining its size and
approaching the observer.' This is different from size constancy be-
cause in this case the observer has to accommodate his eyes and make
them converge at a closer range so that the ball gets out of focus and
should be seen as a blurred double image. Yet the knowledge that
tennis balls behave reasonably and do not grow into footballs some-
how manages to compensate for this, and to discard the anomalies in
the situation as irrdevant noise. To quote Bartlett once more: 'Even
the most elementary perceptions have the character of inferential
constructions.' The-, Baconian ideal of observation without theorizing
is undermined by the mechanism of observation itsel£ Perception is.
polluted by implied hypotheses. To look, to listen, to taste, means to
ask questions; and mostly they are leading questions.
To obtain a more detached view of the living organism's methods.
of coding and storing its experiences, let me make a naive comparison
with a typical engineering procedure. Examining a modern gramo-
phone record with a magnifying glass, you see a spiral curve with
lateral oscillations of varying amplitude and spacing-a curve where
the abscissa represents time, and the ordinate the amplitude of the
needle's oscillations. And yet this two-dimensional curve, with a
single independent variable, can reproduce any sequence of sounds,
from the Sermon on the Mount to the Ninth Symphony performed by
516 THE ACT OF CREATION
orchestra and choir, including the buzzing of a fly and a cough in the
audience. In fact the entire range of human knowledge and experience
could be expressed by the function of this one independent variable, so
that one is tempted to ask why the nervous system does not produce
engrams in this simple type of code, instead of the incomparably more
complicated methods it uses. The answer is, that a 'linear' memory
trace of this type would be completely useless for the purposes of
analysing, recognizing, and matching new inputs, and for working
out the appropriate responses. It would merely represent the 'blooming,
buzzing confusion of pure sensation sans organization' which, in the
words of William James, is the new-born infant's world. Before it
can be more or less permanently stored, the input must be processed,
dismantled, and reassembled in various ways, which the following
examples may serve to illustrate.
Let the input be fifty instruments and fifty voices performing a choral
part of Beethoven's Ninth. On the gramophone record, and in the air
waves which make the ear-drum vibrate, the pitch, timbre, and loudness
of the individual voices and instruments have all been superimposed
on each other-scrambled together into a single variable pulse. The
individuality of soprano, flute, viola, is lost in the process; it requires
a human nervous system to reconstitute it.
The pulse is transmitted and amplified by the bones of the middle
ear and enters through the oval window into the cochlea. Here the
basilar membrane, based in viscous fluid, starts the process of un-
scrambling the acoustic omelette. This is done, partly at least, by a
kind of Fourrier-analysis of the oscillatory curve, which breaks it down
into its spectrum of basic frequencies.* The parallel fibres of the basilar
membrane form a kind of spiral harp; each fibre responds to a specific
frequency. This analysing mechanism operates over a range of twenty
to twenty thousand cycles per second, and auditory discrimination
varies from about 0.05 at low frequencies to 0.025 at 2,000 c/s (Piccolo
flute). Each frequency has its separate 'place' on the spiral membrane.
Each "place' is presumed to be connected by a separate group of fibres,
running through several relay stations, to a presumably fixed location
in the primary reception area in the auditory cortex-area 22.
But this mechanism of transmission by fixed pathways and non-
PERCEPTION AND MEMORY 517
specific impulses is only half of the story; the other half is transmission
of the lower frequencies by 'volleys' in a bundle of fibres firing in turn
at the specific frequency of the input.5 The details of both theories are
still controversial, but the available evidence indicates that they com-
plement each other. We have, then, here one more instance of the
complementary character of two types of nervous function: conduction
by specific pathways, and conduction by specific signals over equi-
potential pathways.
We now have our fifty singers and :fifty instruments decomposed
into a constantly changing mosaic pattern of excitations in area 22
where each point (or region or circuit)6 represents the frequency of
one pure tone, and in some form also its intensity-regardless of the
instrument or voice in which it originated. This state of affairs bears no
resemblance to any conceivable neural model based on S.-R. theory
-or on the Gestalt physiology of Kohler and Kaffka.* In fact the
whole physiological theory of Gestalt, and many of its psychological
postulates, break down when we come to audition. This is not sur-
prising since Kohler concentrated entirely on visual perception; and
in the seven hundred-odd pages of Kaffka' s Principles of Gestalt Psy-
chology exactly one page (p. 200) is devoted to 'other (than visual)
senses'. Even on this one page, the only reference to audition is the
statement that 'sound' and 'stillness' have a reversible figure-back-
ground relation.
At the auditory projection area we must assume the dismantling
process to end and the reassembling to start. When we listen to the
symphony we do not hear an ensemble of the pure tones into which
it has been broken up in the cochlea, but an ensemble of individual
instruments and voices: that is, of organized sub-wholes. The individual
timbre of an instrument is determined by its overtones-the series of
partials which accompany the fundamental, and the energy-distribu-
tion of them. By superimposition of the sine curves of the partials, we
obtain the periodic curve characteristic for each instrument. When we
identify the sound of a violin or flute by picking out and bracketing
together its partials-which were 'drowned' among thousands of other
partials in the air-pressure wave-we have achieved 'timbre constancy',
comparable to visual figure constancy. This, of course, is based on past
experience and involves an act of recognition by the 'trained ear' of
instruments previously heard in isolation.
'Coloured Filters'
Since all but the most elementary perceptions interact with past ex-
perience, it seems a rather unsound procedure to discuss perception
divorced from the problem of memory. The question, then, is how
the 'trace' was originally acquired which enables me to recognize an
instrument or voice on subsequent occasions. Let us assume that I am
hearing an exotic instrument for the first time, and that I am interested
at the moment only in its timbre, not in the melody played on it
(which, in the case of a Japanese koto or samisen, would be above my
head anyway). As I am listening, the mathematical relations between
the partials remain constant and enduring, whereas their pitch and
loudness are changing all the time. This stable and enduring relation-
pattem (the fixed ratios between the part-frequencies) will be treated
by my nervous system, which is processing the input, as relevant,
whereas the changes in the relata (the absolute frequencies) are dis
carded as irrelevant. When this filtering-out process is completed, the
input will have been finally stripped of all irrelevant detail, according
to the demands of parsimony, and reduced to its invariant pattem-
to 'information' purified of 'noise'. If an input has undergone these
transformations and was permitted to progress this far without being
blocked somewhere on its way (as, for instance, the voices of irrelevant
strangers at a cocktail party are) then it will tend to leave a lasting
'trace' which will enable the nervous system to recognize in future the
same voice or instrument.
We have witnessed, as it were, the formation of the code of a new
perceptual skill. The organism feeds on negative entropy; in com-
munication theory, 'entropy' becomes 'noise'. The sensorium ab-
stracts information from the chaotic environment as the mitochondria
extract, by a series of dismantling and reassembling processes, a specific
form of energy from food. The abstracting and recording of informa-
tion involves, as we have just seen, the sacrifice of details which are
filtered out as irrelevant in a given context. But what is considered as
irrelevant in one context, may be relevant in another; and vice versa.
We can recognize an instrument regardless of the tune played 011 it;
but we can also recognize a tune regardless of the instrument on which
it is played. The tune is abstracted and recorded in a memory-trace
de-particularized of timbre; timbre is recorded de-particularized of
tune. Thus the filtering-out of redundancies as the input is relayed
from periphery to centre does not proceed along a single channel, but
518
PERCEPTION AND MEMORY
along several channels, each with its series of filters of different colour,
as it were. The different colours represent the criteria of relevance in
different perceptual hierarchies. Each hierarchy analyses the input
according to its own criteria of relevance; but the loss of detail in
curred in the process of memory-formation along a single channel is
partly counteracted by the fact that information rejected as irrelevant
by its coloured filters may be admitted as relevant by another channel
belonging to a difterent hierarchy. We shall see that this principle of
multi-dimensional analysis is of basic importance in the phenomena of
recognition and recall.
A Digression on Engrams
Tracing a Melody
becomes a relatum which enters into relations with other tonal pat-
terns; or with itself in symmetrical reversal; or contrapuntally with
other themes.
Most people are capable ofleanring and recognizing simple melodies,
and equally capable of recognizing the sound of various instruments
-but few mortals share the privilege of 'absolute pitch', of being
able to identify single notes. In other words, retention of a pattern of
stimuli is the rule, retention of an isolated stimulus the exception. If
the pattern is relatively simple, it is 'take in at a glance', as a whole:
as a rule, listening to the fust two transients is sufficient to identify an
instrument. 9 But the more complex the pattern, the more difficult it
becomes to 'take the whole in at a glance', and it can be retained only
by dint of a certain amount of rote learning.
Once more, however, the items memorized are not discrete bits, but
organized sub-wholes; and they are not summated in an open chain
but interrelated in a closed figure. Thus the first movement of a sonata
will fall into three sub-wholes: statement of themes, development,
recapitulation; and the first of these is usually subdivided into the ex-
position of two themes in the order ABA; while in the rondo we
usually have A B A C A.
Similar considerations apply, for instance, to the learning of a
poem. Rhythm, rhyme, grammar, and meaning provide patterns or
'grids' superimposed on each other-matrices governed by already
established codes; and the memorizing that remains to be done is not
so much a 'stamping in' but a 'filling of gaps'. This is shown by the
typical way of'getting stuck' in reciting a poem; e.g.;
' ••. Cannon to left of them / Cannon in front of them / (- -)
and thundered'. A word has fallen out like a piece from a jigsaw
puzzle-but it merely leaves a gap; it does not break the 'chain'. The
old-fashioned method of teaching history by reigns and battles is an
obvious example of stamping in. .Even so, the data often show some
rudimentary organization into rhythmic or visual patterns, acquired
spontaneously or by some memorizing trick such as rhyming jingles.
Calculating prodigies memorize long series of numbers, not by chain-
ing but by ordering them into familiar sub-groups. Nonsense syllables
are easier retained by twisting them into a semblance of words, and
522 THE ACT OF CREATION
all that it found worth retaining, to a formula such as: isoscele marriage
triangle with pet-dog at centre of gravity, or: whodunit with five in
dependent variables (suspects).
Let us assume that at each stage of this serial abstractive process, the
input activates some particular scanning- or filtering-device which is
'attuned' to that particular input. The receiving end of that device
corresponds to its 'matrix' aspect: it is potentially responsive to a great
many inputs which have one specific feature or pattern in common,
and are thus equipotential in that respect. When an input is 'recognized'
by the matrix as conforming to that pattern, it will emit a code-
signal to the higher echelons. But while the matrix is 'attuned' to a
great number of variations in the input pattern, the code merely signals
the invariant aspect ofit, e.g. 'a triangle', 'an octave', 'a fly', 'a denial'.
The size and position of the triangle, the particulars of the fly, the
wording of the denial are lost in the coding, and cannot be retrieved by
reversing the process within that particular hierarchy (though it may
have been preserved by another).
Thus the analysing-devices behave like analogue-to-digital com-
puters, and in other respects, too, the order of events is the exact re-
verse-as one would expect-of the processes we have observed in
motor-hierarchies. When an animal engages in some skilled action,
the co-ordinating centre activates a matrix of equi-fi.nal motor patterns;
which particular sub-skill will be called into activity depends on cir-
cumstances. Thus the 'roughed-in' action-programme becomes more
an2 more particularized in the course of its descent to the periphery-
while contrariwise, the peripheral input is more and more de-particu-
larized or 'skeletonized' in its ascent towards the centre. The first is a
process of progressively spelling out implicit orders; the second an
equally stepwise process of abstracting the meaning implied in the
mosaic of sensations. Both processes are irreversible: the exact words
of the actors in the play cannot be retrieved.
It can also happen, however, that one has quite forgotten what that
play, seen years ago, was about-except for one particular detail, an
inflection of voice, an imploring gesture of the heroine which, tom
from its context, remains engraved. on one's memory. There exists,
indeed, a method of retention which seems to be the direct opposite
of memory-formation in abstractive hierarchies. It is characterized by
the preservation of vivid details, which, from a purely logical point ,
of view, are often quite irrelevant; and. yet these quasi-cinemato-
graphic details or 'close-ups', which seem to contradict the demands
PERCEPTION AND MEMORY 525
of parsimony, are both enduring, strikingly sharp, and add texture and
flavour to memory.
Bartlett, in a classic experiment, made his subjects read an Indian
legend and then reproduce it on repeated occasions at intervals of in-
creasing length-ranging from fifteen minutes after the first reading
to several months or years. The story was about thirty lines long; it
concerned a young Indian who got involved in the 'War of the Ghosts',
and was wounded in the process. The last paragraph read:
He told it all, and then became quiet. When the sun rose he fell
down. Something black came out of his mouth. His face became
contorted. The people jumped up and cried. He was dead.10
Learning to See
Let us tum to vision.
Innate perceptual organization provides no more than the primitive
foundation on which learning can build. The long controversy be-
tween Behaviourists and the iµtivistically inclined Gestalt school
whether perceptual organization is innate or learned has finally been
superseded by the more realistic question how much is innate and how
much acquired by early learning. The consensus seems to be that
colour and brightness constancy, and the recognition of line, angle, and
texture are innate inrats as well as mcn.11 So is 'primitive unity' (Hebb)
-the segregation of simple figures as coherent entities from the back-
ground (for instance, a black splash on a white card). But when it
comes to more complex figures where the contrast is less marked, even
the figure-ground relation is strongly influenced by learning and ex-
pectancy. I have quoted examples from the neglected field of auditory
perception where the relativity of :figural unity is obvious. The radio-
logist whom experience has taught to see a peptic ulcer or a lesion of
the lung, treats the much sharper contours of the ribs as 'background'.
When you hunt for a collar-stud in a drawerful of miscellaneous ob-
jects, that small, insipid form, poor in Gestalt Priignanz, will 'stick out
a mile'; the remaining contents of the drawer are 'background'.
PERCEPTION AND MEMORY
The best-known among these are the matrices responsible for the
visual constancies and illusions which are found in every elemen-
tary textbook. Less attention has been paid to the modification of
THE ACT OF CREATION
a b
'(~)~< a=b
Levels of Memory
Image.and Meaning
A further step upward in the hierarchy leads to what I have called the
'picture-strip' kind of memory with emotive significance; and lastly
we arrive at the phenomena referred to as 'memory images' in ordinary
parlance.
An image is defined in Drever's Dictionary as 'a revived sense ex-
perience, in the absence of the sensory stimulation'. But since most of
the sensory stimulation has been irretrievably lost in the filtering-
processes of memory formation, only some exceptionally sharp,
vivid details are perhaps capable of being 'revived' or 'reproduced';
the remainder of the experience must be 'reconstructed'. It has been
known for a long time that introspective reports on 'visual memory
images' are largely based on self-deception. Visual recall-as Semon
once wrote-'renders only the strongest lights and shadows' ;29 but
strictly speaking, even shadows are absent from visual images-as they
532 THE ACT OF CREATION
are from Chinese paintings; and so are, as a rule, all but the crudest
shades of colour. The normal adult's memory-images are much vaguer,
sketchier in outline than he is wont to believe; in most cases when he
believes that he possesses a visual image of a thing, he is really referring
to aggregates of simplified perceptual schemata, held together by
conceptual licks.
This has been amply demonstrated (cf. Book One, pp. 346 seq) . In the
Binet-Mueller test30 the subject is directed to memorize a letter square
(comprising sixteen or twenty-five letters in random distribution) until
he thinks that he has formed a visual image of it, and can 'see' it in his
mind's eye. But when he is asked to read the letters in his image in
backward order or diagonally, he will take up to ten times longer than
when reciting them in their proper serial order from left to right.
Another classic test is the drawing of elephants by patients suffering
from a form of aphasia which impairs symbolic thought but leaves
perceptual faculties intact-a test first used by Pierre Marie, and later
by Henry Head:31
doubt that birds have a 'prelinguistic number sense'; that they 'are
able to abstract the "concept" of numerical identity from groups of up
to seven objects of totally different and unfamiliar appearance',42
Among mammals, squirrels have been shown to have the same
ability.a The evidence suggests 'that men and animals may have a pre-
linguistic "counting" ability of about the same degree, but that man's
superiority in dealing with numbers lies in his ability to use, as symbols
for numbers, words and figures which have not the same, or indeed
any, numerical attributes.'44 The symbolic coding of 'number Ges-
talten' seems indeed. a decisive step towards the formation of cardinal
numbers; I shall return to the subject later (Chapter XV}.
Sound-pictures, printed letters of the alphabet, number-configura-
tions, are all complex perceptual wholes, and at the same time ele-
mentary parts of symbolic thought: one might call them (to change
the metaphor) 'amphibian' entities. They signal the transition, in
mental evolution, from the 'aquatic' world of perception which keeps
the organism submerged in a fl.uid environment of sounds, shapes, and
smells, to the dry land of conceptualized thinking. The highest forms
of purely perceptualabstraction on the pre-verbal level are like bubbles
of air which aquatic creatures extract from the water; conceptualized
thought is dry and inexhaustible, like the atmosphere.
This is not meant of course to belittle the formidable powers of
perceptual abstraction found in some animals. The innate (or im
printed) releasive mechanisms, for instance, may be regarded as
phylogenetically acquired skills which enable the animal to combine
the colour, shape, and movement of the stimulus-patterninto a single
'constancy', The rat learns to make a 'mental map' of the maze in its
head (Chapter XII); and it has always been a mystery to me how my
dog recognizes another dog on the opposite sidewalk at sight without
using his sense of smell-for the typical reactions of staring, straining
at the leash, whining, occurs at the very instant of catching sight. The
other dog may be a miniature Peke, a dolled-up Poodle, or a Great
Dane; how does my dog identify that apparition as a kinsman-how
did he abstract the universal 'Dog'? Perhaps at a distance he merely
reacts to four legs and one or two other Gestalt characteristics common
to all canines, which account for their 'dogginess' -though we would
be at a loss to define them.
Generalization, Discrimination, and Association
While new matrices are formed by learning, others may decay through
disuse like old waterways overgrown by weeds. Apart from genera-
tion and decay, the traces left by past events in the nervous system also
undergo dynamic changes-simplification, condensation, distortion
on the one hand; elaboration and enrichment through the addition of
extraneous material on the other. The 'schemata' of memory, as
Bartlett called them, are 'living, constantly developing, aH"ected by
every bit of incoming sensational experience of a given kind'." In
other words, the past is constantly being re-made by the present.*
To quote Bartlett again:
'Remembering is not re-excitation of innumerable, fixed, lifeless
and fragmentary traces. It is an imaginative reconstruction, or con..
struction, built out of the relation of our attitude towards a whole
active mass of organized past reactions or experience, and to a little
outstanding detail which commonly appears in image or in language
form. It is thus hardly ever really exact, even in the most rudimentary
cases of rote-recapitulation, and it is not at all important that it should
be so.'48
True recall by imagery would be possible only if the de-particu-
larized memory could be re-particularized, the · irreversible process
reversed. One may be-able to 'hear'-wbile shaving, for instance
the faint, pale ghost of a voice from the past singing a simple song. To
540 THE ACT OF CREATION
make this possible, at least three different systems of' coloured filters',
concerned with melody, timbre, and wording, must each have pre-
served one aspect of the original experience. One may also recall,
more or less distinctly, characteristic combinations of form and
motion: the stride of a person, the roll of a boat, the waddle of a
tortoise. But the average person's abilities of perceptual imaging are
limited to this kind of production. Hence the paradox of what one
might call 'negative recognition': I visit a friend whom I have not seen
for some time, look round and say: 'Something is changed in this
room' -without being able to say what has been changed. I can only
assume that my memory of the room was determined by several
complementary matrices-sketchy, part verbal, part visual schemata,
such as 'Regency furniture', 'L-shaped plan', 'subdued colour scheme',
etc.-plus one or two 'vivid details': a picture, a flower-vase. A good
many changes could be made in the room which I would not notice
so long as they satisfy these criteria as 'equipotential variations'; only
changes which offend against one of the codes will make me register
that 'something is wrong'. My inability to name that 'something'
indicates that the code was functioning below the level of conscious
awareness (Cf. Book One, XIX).*
The adjectives used to describe a face-'soft', 'bony', 'pinched',
'humorous', etc.-refer to part visual, part verbal schemata, some of
which may be as. simplified as the surprisingly few linear elements
which suffice to indicate emotional expression by the posture and slant
of mouth and eyes. The caricaturist can evoke a face by a few strokes
which schematize a total impression (Hitler's moustache and lock), or
he can pick out a detail which acts as a 'sign-releaser' (Churchill's
-cigar). It is often easier to remember a face known only from illus-
trations-Napoleon or Mona Lisa-than faces of living persons; per-
haps because half of the compressing and coding of the visual infor-
mation has already been done by the artist. Equally revealing is the
police method of reconstructing the likeness of a criminal by the
Identi.-Kit method. This is based on 'a slide-file of five hundred and
ffiy facial characteristics containing, among other things, a hundred
ind two sets of eyes ranging from pop to squinting, thirty-three sets
of lips from thin to sensuous, fifty-two chins, from weak to jutting,
, and even twenty-five sets of wrinkles. Witnesses pick the individual
· features that most closdy resemble their idea of the criminal's look.
From their selections a composite picture of all the features is then
assembled.''9
PERCEPTION AND MEMORY S4I
If in the process of memory-formation the input is stripped down to
bare essentials, recall requires dressing it up again. This seems to be
done by some summary drapings, patched out with surviving frag-
ments of picture-strip, plus some fitting garments borrowed from
elsewhere-we all know how often 'vivid details' are incorporated
into the recall of experiences to which they do not belong. Imaging
involves imagining, which is a flexible skill. It is triggered-off by an
impulse of central origin-a kind of 'excitation-clang' which unlocks
'memory releasers' and sets off the feedback-circuits of 'inferential
reconstruction'; as with other plastic skills, two performances are never
quite the same.
Summary
as units into the symbolic hierarchy. We muse assume chat there are
analysing devices of this kind active in the nervous system, 'resonators'
which are 'attuned' to a certain configuration in the perceptual input,
and respond to it by signals in symbolic coding addressed to the higher
echelons. All inputs which are equipotential with respect to that con-
:6.guration-e.g. 'triangularity' -are regarded by the analyser as 'the
same thing', and reported by the same signal. The process is thus the
reverse of the 'spelling out' activites of the motor hierarchy-which is
in some respects comparable to the unlocking of memory-releasers in
recall.
'Generalization' and 'discrimination' are complementary aspects of
the same process, and will be discussed, together with the ambiguities
of'spreading' and 'transfer', in later chapters.
NOTES
To p. 513. Cf. Polanyi, 1958, p. 364: 'Behaviourists teach that in observing
an animal we must refrain above all from tr:ying to imagine what we would do
if placed in the animal's position. I suggest, on the contrary, that nothing at all
could be known about an animal that would be of the slightest interest to physi-
ology, and still less to psychology, except by following the opposite maxim .... '
Top. 517. The latter assumes that in visual perception a spatial 'picture' is
projected on to the primary optical cortex, which reproduces the retinal image.
Bur the excitation-pattern in the auditory cortex has no 'contours' separating
· :figure and background, and it would be difficult to imagine .6.dd currents'
1
created by them.
Top. 533. There are strong arguments against the segmentadon of language
according to the letters of the written alphabet (cf. e.g, Paget 1930; Ladefoged
in Mechanizatian of Thought Processes, 1959).
To p. 537. There exist of course both innate and acquired preferences for
choosing one syst~ of 'coloured filters' rather than another as a criterion of
equipotentiality. Two notes an octave apart sound more 'similar' to man and
rat than two notes close together. Evidently the nervous system finds it for its
own 'intents and purposes' more convenient to r:egard two frequencies of the
ratio 2p : pas more similar than two frequencies of the tatio p : (p-r).
I
n the process of becoming an expert typist, the student must go
through the whole range of learning processes variously classified
as instrumental conditioning, sign-learning, trial and error, rote and
place learning, insight. He is, of course, quite unaware of these cate-
gories-which, in fact, overlap at almost every stage. The essence of
the process is the step-wise integration of relatively simple codes of
behaviour into complex and flexible codes with a hierarchic structure.
This conclusion was actually reached (although expressed in different
words) in the r89os by Bryan and Harter1-then buried and forgotten
for nearly halfa century. Woodworth was one of the few experimental
psychologists who kept harking back to the subject. The following is
taken from his summary of Bryan and Harter' s Studies on the Tele-
graphic Language. The Acquisition of a Hierarchy of Habits.2
'The beginner first learns the alphabet of dots and dashes. Each letter
is a little pattem of finger movements in sending, a little pattern of
clicks in receiving. It is something of an achievement to master these
motor and auditory letter habits. At this stage the learner spells the words
in sending or receiving. With further practice he becomes familiar
with word-patterns and does not spell out the common words. The
transition from the letter habit to the word-habit stage extends over a
long period of practice, and before this stage is fully reached a. still
more synthetic form of reaction begins to appear. "The fair operator
is not held so closely to words. He can take in several words at a
mouthful, a phrase or even a short sentence." In sending he antici-
pates, as in other motor performances; but in receiving, he learns to
"copy behind.", letting two or three words come from the sounder
before he starts to copy. Keeping a few words behind the sounder
allows time for getting the sense of the message.'
S44
MOTOR SKILLS 545
Let us call these three stages of habit-formation the 'letter', 'word',
and 'context' levels. The letter habit is acquired by 'serial learning'.
But no chain-response theory can account even for this first step in
acquiring the skill-for the simple reason that the homogeneous dots
and the homogeneous dashes of the Morse sequence offer no distin-
guishable characteristics for the forming of specific S.-R. connections.
The letter 'u' is transmitted by dot-dot-dash; the letter 'w' by dot-
dash-dash. In terms of S.-R. theory, the finger-movement made in
sending the first dot is the initial part-response which triggers the chain,
its kinaesthetic sensation acting as a stimulus which calls out the next
response. But the correct response to the same stimulus will be either
dot or dash; nothing in the nature of the stimulus itself indicates what
the next response should be; the response is determined at this and each
following step not by the preceding stimulus but by the total pattern. The
habit cannot be represented by a linear series: • - - > - - - > · •
it can only be represented as a two-tired hierarchic structure:
/~~
II~~
.... +
FIGURE 17
.....
'maze' with variable target positions. But when, after a certain amount
of hit and miss, the letter habit had been mastered:
Yet even phrases ending with a full stop did not prove to be the
highest units. The records showed 'no pauses between phrases' but
an even flow; and here, too, 'the eyes [on the text to be copied] were
well ahead of the hands' -to enable the typist to take in the meaning.
As a third example let us consider learning to play the piano (though
I could find no textbook references to this not altogether unusual human
occupation). The 'letter habit' here becomes a 'note habit'-hitting
the intended black or white key; for 'word' read 'bar' or 'musical
phrase'; and so on to more complex integrated patterns. In this case,
however, even the lowest unit of the skill-hitting the right key-
displays considerable flexibility. There is no longer, as on the type-
writer, a rigid attribution of each key to one finger; on the piano
keyboard almost any finger can be used, according to circumstances,
to hit any key; several keys may be hit and held at the same time; and
a hard or soft touch makes all the difference to musical quality. (Need-
less to say, even the typist's motion-patterns must be adaptable to small
portables and large office machines, and the starting position of the
finger varies according to the preceding stroke. Flexibility is a matter
of degrees; a completely fixed response is, like the reflex arc, an
abstraction.)
The skill of hitting the correct piano-key is not acquired by es-
tablishing pcine-to-point correspondences, but primarily by practising
the various scales; these superimpose, as it were, structured motions
on to the keyboard, sub-structured into triads, septims, etc. At an
advanced stage, when improvization has become possible, the left
hand will learn to accompany the right, which acts as a 'pace-maker' -
a glorified form of the magnet effect in the gold-fish (p. 438}; but the
MOTOR SKILLS 547
left can also act in relative independence, according to the commands
of the score. At this level we have approximately the following state of
affairs: the visual input consists in two groups of parallel rows (staves)
of coded signals, of which the upper series must be referred to the
right, the lower to the left hand. In the course of this procedure both
rows of signals must be de-coded and re-coded. The symbols on the
two rows are usually in different parallel codes ('violin clef' for the
right, 'bass clef' for the left). Moreover, there are 'key signatures'-
sharp and flat signs-at the beginning of a section, which modify the
'face value' of the notes; there are symbols which indicate the timing
and duration of notes; and overall instructions regarding loudness,
tempo and mood. All these part-dependent, part-independent de- and
re-coding operations for both hands must proceed simultaneously, in
the psychological present, and more or less automatically.
On an ever higher level, the concert pianist develops a repertory of
ceuvres that he can 'trigger off' as units and play by heart-though
some of these units may be an hour long. Once again we must assume
that this is done by a combination of several interlocking hierarchies,
each articulated into sub-wholes and the sub-wholes thereof
Then there is improvisation. It need not be creative; the bar-
pianist who, half asleep, syncopates Chopin and trails off into some
variation of his own, is not a composer; but he has gained additional
flexibility-more degrees of freedom-in the practice of his skill. And
finally there is the creative act: the composer who weaves his threads
into new patterns, and the interpreter who sheds new light on existing
patterns.
The learning process is, somewhat paradoxically, easiest to visualize
as a reversal of the hierarchic sequence of operations which will
characterize performance when learning is completed. When the
typist copies a document, the sequence of operations is initiated on the
semantic level, then branches down into successive lower levels with
increasingly specific 'fixed action-patterns' -'word-habits' and 'letter-
habits'; terminating in the 'consummatory act' of the :finger muscles.
The impulses arborize downwards and outwards, whereas learning
proceeds in the reverse direction: the tips of the twigs of the future
tree are the :first to come into existence; the twigs then grow together
centripetally into branches, the branches merge into the trunk. It
strikes one as a very artificial procedure; but the type of mechanical
learning we have discussed, where the discrete base-units must be
stamped in bit by bit, is indeed an artificial procedure. The difference
THE ACT OF CREATION
between this method of learning through trial and error and learning
'by insight' becomes glaringly obvious if you compare what happens
during an elementary violin lesson and an equally elementary singing
lesson. The choir boy can rely on his innate, multiple auditory-vocal
feedbacks-operating through the air, through his bones, and through
proprioceptive sensations from his vocal tract-to control his voice.
But there exist no innate feedbacks between the violin student's cochlea
and finger-muscles, to control their motions. No amount of theoretical
insight into the working of the instrument can replace this handicap;
it can only be overcome by supplementing insight with trial and
error. In other words, human beings are biologically less 'ripe' for
learning the violin than for learning to sing. If evolution were to
produce a super-cricket or cicada sapiens, the opposite may be true.
To put it in a different way: the built-in feedbacks of the auditory-
vocal apparatus provide a direct insight into the rightness or wrong-
ness (singing out of tune) of the response; they permit an immediate
'perception of relations'-which is Thorpe's definition of insight. But
once more, this insight is far from absolute: when it comes to pro-
fessional singing, a heart-breaking amount of drill is required. The
pupil is often taught the proper techniques of breathing with his hand
on the teacher's stomach-because his insight into, and control of,
his own physiological functions is limited. Verbal instructions are of
little help, and are sometimes a hindrance, in the acquisition of muscle
skills; to become clever with one's hands, or one's feet in dancing,
requires a kind of muscle training which defies classification as either
insightful or trial-and-error learning.
I have repeatedly mentioned the mysteries of riding a bicycle:
nobody quite knows how it is done, and any competent physicist
would be inclinded to deny a priori that it can be done. However, as a
two-legged primate, man has an innate 'ripeness' for the acquisition
of all kinds of postural and balancing skills such as skating, rock-
climbing, or walking the tight-rope; accordingly, the hierarchy of
learning processes in the case of the cyclist starts on a higher level of
already integrated sub-skills, than in the examples previously dis-
cussed. Broadly speaking, the pupil must turn the handle-bar in the
direction he is falling, which will make him tend to fall in the opposite
direction, and so forth, until he gradually 'gets the feel' of the amount
of correction required. This is certainly trial-and-error learning in the
sense th.at errors are punished by a fall; but the trials are by no means
random, and the errors are all in the right direction-they merely over-
MOTOR SKILLS 549
or under-shoot the mark. The code which is formed by successive
adjustments of the neural 'servo-mechanism' is presumably of the
analogue-computer type-and the same appliesprobably to dancing,
skating, or tennis-playing.
But once the skill has been mastered and formed into a habit, its
integrated pattern is representedas a unit on the next-higher level in
the hierarchy, and can be triggered off by a single (verbal or non..
verbal) command. To take a more complicated example: the soccer-
player must acquire a variety of basic routines of taking command of
the ball-'stopping' it with foot, thigh, chest, or head; volleying it in
flight without stopping; kicking it with the instep, the inner or outer
side-wall of the boot; dribbling, passing,and shooting at the goal, etc.
When these elementary, yet very complex, techniques have been
mastered, each of them will become a self-containedsub-skill in his
repertory, and he will be able to decide, in a split second, which of
them to employ according to the layout of the field. The decision
whether to shoot or pass is based on discreteyes-no alternativesof the
digital type; but the execution of the actual move-shooting, passing,
etc.-seems to require an analogue-computertype of code. A further
step down the 'analogue' process of :flexing the leg-musclesfor a pass
of appropriate length is again converted into the digital on-off pro-
cesses in individual motor units; while on the top level a fluid strategy
is converted into discrete tacticaldecisions.
It would seem that behavioural matrices on every level of a given
hierarchy are triggered off by digital-type all-or-nothing impulses;
if the matrix is flexible it will function as a digital-to-analoguecon-
verter; and will in its turn trigger off sub-codes at certain critical
limits as analogue-to-digital converters. But theorizing about the
nervous system in terms of computer models is a risky affair,and may
yet lure psychology into a cul-de-sac-as the telephone-exchange
model did half a century ago."
the task; or, to put it the other way round, depending on the 'natural-
ness' of the task relative to the organism's existing skills. Learning to
type requires more stamping-in than learning to ride a bicycle; the
former is comparable to the blindfold memorizing of a maze, the
latter to the gradual adjustment of various interlocking servo-
mechanisms. In both cases the learning process consists in the integra-
tion of elementary skills-the members of the nascent matrix-into
a single pattern which can be activated as a unit. But even in acquiring
a mechanical skill like typing, bit-by-bit learning plays in fact a lesser
part than seems to be the case. The typist's mental map of the key-
board is not simply a rote-learned aggregation of twenty-six letters
(plus numbers and signs) distributed at random; it is a 'coded' map,
structured by a system of co-ordinates-the resting position of the
£ngers-and by the frequency-rating of letters, syllables, etc. These
patterns, superimposed on the keyboard map, could be compared to
the mnemonic aids used in the learning of nonsense syllables. Whole-
learning invades bit-learning at every opportunity; if the meaningless
is to be retained, the mind must smuggle meaning into it.
Once a skill has been mastered so that it can be activated as a unit it
functions more or less autonomously and automatically. This applies
to both perceptual and motor skills, from the perceptual constancies
and motor reflexes upwards. Learning to find the right key on the
keyboard -requires concentration, focal awareness; but when the
letter-habit has been acquired it becomes 'instinctive', unconscious;
attention is freed to concentrate on meaning, and can 'let the fingers
take care of themselves'; their control is relegated to lower levels of
awareness and, in all likelihood, to lower levels in the nervous system.
Thus the work of Gastaut and Beck clearly suggests that 'once we
have learned something we no longer rely so much on our cortex
and reticular formation. Those things we do "without thinking" ...
may depend more on the older primitive parts of the nervous system
such as the limbic structures, thus releasing higher centres such as the
cortex for other tasks.••• Common sense indicates such a possibility;
electro-physiology suggests it ..•. 's*
The same skilled action-driving a motor-car or playing a nocturne
by heart-can be performed automatically, or in semi-conscious
absent-mindedness, or with full concentration. But the motorist who
concentrates on driving fast along a crowded road has his attention,
focussed on matters of general strategy-e.g. whether it is safe to over-
take or not, whereas the actual manipulation of the wheel and pedals
MOTOR SKILLS 551
are still carried out automatically; and the pianist trying to give his
best, still finds the keys automatically. We again find confirmed that
the code which controls skilled behaviour always operates through
sub-codes which function on lower levels of awareness. Shifting the
focus of attention to these sub-codes produces the familiar 'paradox
of the centipede', Its equivalent in perception is the loss of meaning
which results when a word is repeated monotonously and attention
becomes focussed on the Klangbild (c£ 'ce-du, ce-du, ce-du', Book
One, p. 75 £; even more painful is the semantic paralysis which some-
times befalls a writer while correcting the proofs of a forthcoming
book.
The lower we descend in the hierarchy the more stereotyped, re-
flex-like activities we find; and vice versa, flexibility increases with each
step upward. The more complex the skill, the more alternative varia-
+
tions it offers for adaptable strategies: a matrix on the n r level has
more degrees of freedom than a matrix on the n level. But whether
they will be utilized and produce varied performance, depends on the
environment. Monotonous environments induce repetitive, stereo-
. typed habits; the degrees of freedom in the matrix freeze up. 'Over-
learning' is the fixation, through repetition in unvarying conditions,
of one among many possible variations in the exercise of a skill at the
expense of all others. Thus habits become automatized (a) because
they operate on the lower strata of the hierarchy with few degrees of
freedom, like hitting a typewriter key or depressing the accelerator
pedal; (b) when a complex skill is reduced through environmental
monotony to a single-track habit. 'Monotony' is of course a subjective
term referring to lack of change in those features of the environment
which are relevant to the subject's interests. For all we know the
streets of Koenigsberg through which Emmanuel Kant took his fixed
walk at a fixed hour for forty years might have been wildly exciting
to another person.
The integration of motor-patterns into larger and more complex
skills in the process of learning is paralleled by a similar progression
on the perceptual side. The telegraphist who has advanced from 'letter-
habits' through 'word-habits' to 'phrase-habits' in his sending tech-
nique, has at the same time learned to take in several words and even
phrases 'at a mouthful'. The pianist takes in a whole musical phrase
from the score at a glance; both input and output are no longer
measured in bits but in chunks.* The more complex the skill, the
bigger the chunks in space or time which must be taken into account.
.S.S2 THE ACT OF CREATION
The skilled soccer player keeps his eye on the ball, but is at the same
time aware of the positionsand peculiaritiesof the other players on the
field. The motorist, driving to his office, chooses the least congested
road among several alternativesby consulting the mental map in his
head. The typist, who deliberately lags a phrase or two behind dic-
tation, expands the duration of the psychologicalpresent to take in a
bigger chunk of meaning. While listening to speech or music we do
the same; while talking we trigger off long sequences of muscular
patterns as a whole. As we become more proficient in any skilled
activity, we learn 'to put feedback loops around larger and larger
segmentsof our behaviour'.s
Though motor learning proceeds, generally speaking, from lower
to higher levels, and performance in the reverse direction, this does
not mean that in performing we run through the whole gamut of the
learning process in reverse gear. As one learns to play a sonata by
heart, one needs less and less often to consult the score, and in the end
the visual feedback which was indispensable during iearning can
be dispensedwith entirely; the habit now functions autonomously.
The skilledpianist can play blindfold, a man can knot his tie without
looking into the mirror, the physician can tell the patient's pulse
without looking at his watch, the adult reads without spelling out the
letters. When the skill has been mastered, the props which served the
learning process are kicked away-as Maxwell kicked away the
scaffoldingof his mechanicalmodel when he arrived at his equations
(see AppendixI). Inthis respect,too, the learningprocessis irreversible.
The autonomy of the codeswhich pattern behaviour is a phenomenon
which we have met on all levels-from the self-regulatory activities
of the morphogenetic field, through the fixed action-patterns of
instinct behaviour, to the perceptual frames responsiblefor constan-
cies, illusions, and our ways of seeing the world through coloured
filters,as it were. But on the level of complex skills, the 'self-assertive'
tendencies of acquired motor-patterns are particularly striking. To
repeat an obvious example, one cannot disguise one's handwriting
sufficientlyto fool the expert; even the skilled burglar has his indi
vidual style in safe-breakingwhich gives him away. Autonomy and
self-governmentarc basicprinciplesin the hierarchy of skills.Thus 'the
performance of very quick movements', Lashley observed, 'indicates
their independenceof current control. "Whip-snapping" movements
of the hand can be regulated in extent, yet the entire movement, from
initiation to completion requires less than the reaction time for a
MOTOR SJCILLS 553
tactile or kinaesthetic stimulation of the arm, which is about one-
eighth of a second, even when no discrimination is involved .... The
finger-strokes of a musician may reach sixteen per second in passages
which call for a definite and changing order of successive finger-
movements. The succession of movements is too quick even for visual
reaction time ..•. Sensory control of movement seems to be ruled
out in such acts.'7
Similar conclusions were reached, as already mentioned, by Ruch,
concerning voluntary movement in general. In view of the rapidity
of skilled movements which are too fast to leave room for visual or
proprioceptive feedback control, Ruch, like Lashley, assumed the
operation of pre-set time-tension patterns of muscle contraction in the
nervous system: 'The cerebral-cerebellar circuit may represent not so
much an error-correcting device as a part of a mechanism by which an
instantaneous order can be extended in time •.. and thus reduce the
troublesome transients involved in the correction of movement by
output-informed feedbacks.'B
The tendency to reduce those 'troublesome' feedbacks to a minimum
is the essence of habit-formation and automatization. It follows the
principle of parsimony; if we had to concentrate on each movement
we made, there would be no room for thought. On the other hand,
this inherent tendency to form neural organizations which, one might
say, jealously defend their autonomy against interference from a
changing outside world, makes us all, in varying degrees, the slaves of
habit. We may reduce the degree of enslavement, but the basic pre-
dicament is inherent in the hierarchic structure or nervous organiza-
tion, where 'the structure of the input does not produce the structure
of the output, but merely modifies intrinsic nervous activities that
have a structural organization of their own'. The quotation (repeated
from p. 434) referred to instinct behaviour and the lower motor
functions, but it is equally applicable, as we have seen, to complex,
acquired skills. These may have a high degree of flexibility, but they
nevertheless operate through automatized sub-skills on the lower
ranges of the hierarchy, which manifest themselves in the individual
'touch' of the pianist, the 'style' of the tennis-player, the fixed man-
nerisms, quirks, idiosyncrasies, and unconscious rituals which are our
personal hallmarks.
· How much of his potential freedom a person puts to active use
depends partly on environmental factors-the novelty, intensity,
vexatiousness, etc., of the stimuli to which he is exposed. But the
554 THE ACT OF CREATION
To. p. 551. Cf. also: 'inrapid sight reading it is impossible to read the individual
notes of an arpeggio. The notes must be seen in groups, and it is actually easier
to read chords seen simultaneously and to translate them into temporal sequence
than to read successive notes in the arpeggio as usually written' (Lashley in the
Hixon Symposium, p. 123).
555
XII
THE PITFALLS OF LEARNING THEORY
A Glance in Retrospect
I
n the course of the past fifty years, learning theory has been one
of the central battlefields of psychology. 'One may say broadly',
Bertrand Russell wrote in 1927, 'that all the animals that have been
carefully observed have behaved so as to confirm the philosophy in
which the observer believed before his observations began. Nay, more,
they have all displayed the national characteristics of the observer.
Animals studied by Americans rush about frantically, with an incredible
display of hustle and pep, and at last achieve the desired result by
chance. Animals observed by Germans sit still and think, and at last
evolve the situation out of their inner consciousness. To the plain man,
such as the present writer, this situation is discouraging. I observe,
however, that the type of problem which a man naturally sets to an
animal depends upon his own philosophy, and that this probably
accounts for the differences in the results.'1
Russell's rem.arks remain true, even though some eminent psycho-
logists deny that they have a philosophy at all and hold all theory-
making to be 'wasteful and misleading')! Not only the choice of
problem, but also the choice of animals is characteristic of the ex-
perim.enter' s bias. Kohler, desirous to prove insight and intelligence,
concentrated mainly on chimpanzees. Skinner's best-known books
are called The Behaviour of Organisms (r938) and Science and Human
Behaviour (r953); but-as Hilgard said-'neither title betrays that the
precise data were derived largely from experiments on rats and pigeons.
It is somewhat anomalous that a systematist who refuses to predict
what a rat or pigeon will do-because such prediction does not belong
in a scientific study of behaviour-is willing to make confident
assertions about the most complex forms of human behaviour, eco-
nomic; political, religious'. a
THE PITFALLS OP LEARNING THEORY 557
Hull's attempt to create an all-embracing theory of behaviour
was almost entirely based on the bar-pressing activities of rats. This
was considered by Hull and his school as a sufficiently solid basis to
derive from them 'the basic laws of behaviour .•. including the social
behaviour of man'.'
Lastly, the German school of ethologists-Loren:z, Tinbergen, etc.
--concentrated mainly on highly ritualized forms of animal life in
birds and insects. Thus each school developed its special universe of
discourse, moving in a closed system, concentrating on their favourite
animals in their favourite experimental situations-dogs dripping
saliva through fistulae, cats raging in puzzle-boxes, rats running
through mazes, geese being 'imprinted' by Dr. Lorenz ambling on
all-fours.
But the data from these highly specialized, experimental trends did
not add up to a coherent picture, and each school had a tendency to
ignore what the others were doing. Thus, for instance, in Skinner's
Science and Human Behaviour, which was intended as a textbook, the
index contains neither the word 'insight', nor the names of Kohler,
Koffka, Lewin, Tolman, Hull, Lashley, or Lorenz; only Thorndike
and Pavlov are mentioned by name as theorists of learning with some
merit. And vice versa, I have searched in vain for the name of Pavlov
in the indices of Kohler's and Koffka' s books. 5 Thus much of the
controversies in learning theory resembled less a battle than a game of
blind man's buff.
How, just at a time when the mechanistic conceptions of the nine-
teenth century had been abandoned in all branches of science, from
physics to embryology; how just at that time, in the 1920s, the concept
of man as a rigid mechanism of chained reflexes could become fashion-
able in cultures as different as the United States and the Soviet Union
is a fascinating problem for the historian of science. The Pavlovian
school in Russia, and the Watsonian brand of Behaviourism in
America, were the twentieth-century postscript to the nineteenth
century's mechanistic materialism, its belated and most consistent
attempt to describe living organisms in terms of machine theory.
How the new comes into beiug: One natural question often raised is:
How do we ever get new verbal creations such as a poem or a
brilliant essay? The answer is that we get them by manipulating words,
shifting them about until a new pattern is hit upon .... It will help us to
go to manual behaviour. How do you suppose Patou builds a new
gown? Has he any 'picture in his mind' of what the gown is to look
like when it is finished? He has not .... He calls his model in, picks up
a new piece of silk, throws it around her; he pulls it in here, he pulls
it out there, makes it tight or loose at the waist, high or low, he makes
the skirt short or long. He manipulates the material until it takes on
the semblance of a dress .... The painter plies his trade in the same
way, nor can the poet boast of any other method.s
This schema follows (except for the last two points) by and large
Hilgard's classification of 'issues on which learning theories divide'.17
Only a few prominent psychologists would subscribe to all the
principles listed in either of the two columns; but a majority of them
would probably subscribe to the majority of the principles in a single
column.
The core of the controversy could be summed up in shorthand as
'drill' versus 'insight'. The answer, already suggested, seems to be
that the various methods of learning form a continuum extending
from classical conditioning at one end to spontaneous, intelligent
problem-solving at the other, while in the intermediary ranges we
find various combinations between drilled-in and insightful learning,
depending on the animal's ripeness for the task to be learned. This
approach, which aims at synthesis, not compromise, is of course by no
means original; it is shared-though for somewhat different reasons-
by 'functionalists' like Woodworth, behaviourists like Hebb, and
ethologists like Thorpe. Thus Hilgard wrote on the 'functionalist
outlook': 'Learning is not blind on the one hand and insightful on the
other; there are degrees of understanding involved from a minimum
at one extreme to a maximum at the other, with most cases fa1ling
between these extremes.'18 However, the definitions of 'insight' and
'understanding' vary, which leaves us with the same problem, only in
a different formulation. Let us try to get closer to it by considering
some typical examples of animal learning.
NOTES
To p. 559. Hilgard calls Hull's system 'the most influentialof the theories
between 1930 and 1950, judging from the experimentaland theoretical studies
engenderedbyit, whether in its defence,itsamendmentor its refutation' (Hilgard,
1958, p. 192).
Top. 559. The objection to this is not that Hull postulated a continuous
serieslinking rat to man, but that his 'primary laws' are epitomized by the bar-
pressingact of the rat, which he regarded as the atomic unit of behaviour. The
fallacy of this reasoning seems to be derived from Hull's implied notion of
mental progressfrom rat to man as a linear gradient. Theories of this kind fail to
take into account the hierarchicprinciple in mental evolution-reflected in the
572 THB ACT OF CREATION
hierarchy oflevels in the nervous system. Ifinstead of linear gradients, we think
in terms of levels of increasing complexity, then a difference in degrees does
become a difference in kind. Since the basic mechanisms of sexual reproduction
are common to all mammalian species, Hull's postulate seems to imply that
detailed study of sexual behaviour in the rat would eventually yield the 'primary
laws' underlying the Kinsey reports on the sexual behaviour of the American
male and female. Homologue principles (such· as the part-whole relation, or
control by feedback) do operate on all levels, but they are general principles,
not specific 'units' or 'atoms' of behaviour.
Top. 565. Coding is an irreversible act, and once the code is established, it
will be relatively permanent-until it decays. If. however, the dog is fooled
repeatedly and in quick succession ('massed practice'), i.e, food is withheld after
the buzzer has sounded, a negative code will superimpose itself on the previous
one. The first few times the response will stop at salivation short of chewing; but
soon it will stop short of salivation. After a few hours' rest, however, salivation
is restored by 'spontaneous recovery'-a paradox which has bedevilled learning
theory for a long time. Perhaps the explanation may be sought on the following
lines. The whole attitude of the dog, as it has become adapted to the laboratory
situation, is based on the expectation that all stimuli are events relevant to food; and
that the negative code (buzzer--> no food), ifit has been quickly superimposed
on the positive one (buzzer-- >food), is of a more temporary and brittle nature
than its opponent. If, however, the unrewarded signals arc spaced out over a
greater length of time, i.e, if the extinction-drill approximates in thoroughness
the original drill, extinction becomes final (Cf. e.g. Hebb, 1958, pp. 134-5, 147).
xm
THE PITFALLS OF GESTALT
More about Chimpanzees
from the wall, three or four yards away from the wooden box (the
italics are Kohler's: by 'objective' he means banana):
Koko ... first jumped straight upwards several times towards the
objective, then took his rope in his hand, and tried to lasso the prize
with a loop of it, could not reach so far, and then turned away from
the wall, after a variety of such attempts, but without noticing the
box. He appeared to have given up his efforts, but always returned
to them from time to time. After some time, on turning away from
the wall, his eye fell on the box: he approached it, looked straight
towards the objective, and gave the box a slight push, which did not,
however, move it; his movements had grown much slower; he left
the box, took a few paces away from it, but at once returned, and
pushed. it again and again with his eyes on the objective, but quite gently,
and. not as though he really intended to alter its position. He turned
away again, turned back at once, and gave the box a third. tentative
shove, after which he again moved slowly about. The box had
now been moved IO centimetres in the direction of the fruit. The
objective was rendered more tempting by the addition of a piece of
orange (the non plus ultra of delight!), and in a few seconds Koko was
once more at the box, seized it, dragged it in one movement up to a
point almost directly beneath the objective (that is, he moved it a
distance of at least three metres), mounted it and tore down the fruit.
A bare quarter of an hour had elapsed since the beginning of the
test.8
All's well that ends well. But it does not. A few minutes later the
experiment was repeated-after the banana had been moved about
three yards from its former position, while the box was left standing
where Koko had dragged it. When Koko was led back onto the stage:
he sprang at the new banana in the same manner as before, but with
somewhat less eagerness; at first he ignored the box. After a time he
suddenly approached it, seized and dragged it the greater part of the
distance towards the new banana, but at a distance of a quarter of a
metre he stopped, gazed at the banana, and stood as if quite puzzled
and. confused. And now began a tale of woe for both Koko and the
box. When he again set himself in motion it was with every sign of
rage, as he knocked the box this way and that, but came no nearer to
the objective. After waiting a little the experiment was broken of£9
THE PITPALLS OF GESTALT 579
This tale of woe continued for nineteen days during which the
experiment was repeated at varying intervals; and even afterwards,
when the new skill was firmly established at last, its performance still
alternated for a while with random trials.
Does Koko's behaviour satisfy the descriptive criteria of insight
learning?
(a) Suddenness. Yes, it does-because at the climactic moment of the
fust experiment, the solution did appear suddenly and all of a piece.
No, it does not-because prior to it Koko had made several half
hearted attempts at the correct solution and yet abandoned th.em.
(b) 'Complete solution with reference to the whole layout to the field'.
The answer is, No. (c) 'Smooth, unhesitating, direct and definitive'-
on one occasion, Yes, on the others, No. (d) 'Solution precedes exe-
cution of solution'-yes and no. (e) 'Solution retained after a single
performance'-definitely No. (f) Novelty-yes.
Kohler's own comments on this experiment are revealing. Although
of
in The Mentality Apes he stresses that the gulf between Trial-and-
Error and Insight is unbridgeable ('the contrast is absolute'lO), his
comment on Koko' s initial hesitations and fumblings with the box is:
'there is only one expression that really fits his behaviour at that
juncture: it's beginning to dawn on him!'ll Let us note that for about
ten days after that first success, Koko kept manipulating the box,
sometimes aimlessly, sometimes angrily, and during this whole
period 'no trace of a solution appeared, except an equivalent of the
words: "there's something about that box".'12 In another passage
Kohler says (italics Kohler's): 'It may happen that the animal will
attempt a solution which, while it may not result in success, yet has
some meaning in regard to the situation. "Trying around" then
consists in attempts at solution in the half-understood situation.'13
Preconditions of Insight
No more need be said to prove that if we apply the descriptive criteria
which I have ennumerated, we find a graded series from 'trying
around', through the 'dawning' of the solution, to the limit case of
the sudden solution. But limit cases at the end of a graded series do
not require a separate set of postulates to explain them. The break in
actual behaviour, the discrete and unitary character of the solution in
these cases can be explained in terms which are also applicable to other
580 THE ACT OP CREATION
forms of learning. Thus with regard to criterion (a) we can say that
the suddenness of the solution is due to the trigger action of chance in
a situation which was ripe for solution-that is to say, where the
animal's repertory comprises all the requisite single skills, and where
all that is needed is a link to combine them into a complex skill-e.g.
Sultan accidentally pushing one rod into the opening of the other. In
other cases-Sultan turning round to pick up the. remembered stick
-where chance plays no part, memory provides the link; but memory
enters into all forms of learning. Regarding (c) and (d) {smooth,
unitary execution of the act, indicating that it has been thought out
before being acted out), we may say that the animal has formed a
hypothesis, or carried out an implicit try, followed by explicit per-
formances of the act. Rats, cats, and dogs also show this brief suspension
of activity, this 'attitude of concentrated attention'U before they act
out a hypothesis-which may or may not be the correct one. (e)
Retention after a single performance can be interpreted as 'induction
based on a single case'-as the chick, from a single experience, draws
the correct empirical inference that all cinnabar caterpillars are to be
avoided. Lastly, (f), novelty is of course also achieved when the cat
learns the open-sesame trick in the puzzle-box. To argue that the cat's
novel response was acquired by Trial and Error, the chimp's by
Insight, is to argue in a circle, since novelty itself is supposed to serve
as a dilferential criterion.
Thus Sultan's Eureka processes, once we have got rid of thinking iii
S.-R. schemata, are interpretable in terms of the same theory which
covers all lower forms oflearning. They make a spectacular impression,
because (since the separate skills which had to be integrated into the
new skill were well-exercised items in his repertory of habits), the
problem to be solved was just one step beyond the limits of that
repertory, and all was set for a single spark to trigger off the
fusion.
At the opposite end of the learning scale, the dog in Pavlov's
laboratory is not equipped with pre-existent rules of the game which
could be combined with each other; it must construct a new code of rules,
starting more or less from scratch. Therein lies the main difference.
The dog must start with an agonized reappraisal of which environ-
mental events are relevant and which are not; then extract and codify
the recurrent invariant features from the stimuli promoted to signi-
ficance; then discriminate between finer features within those features.
The rat must piece together, bit by bit, his cognitive map of the maze;
THE PITFALLS OF GESTALT 581
the cat must gradually extract, by empirical induction, the rules of
Thorndike's game from a surrealistic universe.
The 'missing link' in between the cat and Sultan is provided by
Koko. He does not have to start from scratch; he has already played
with the box; he has sat on it and pushed it about. Was his first success-
ful solution of the problem a random try? Certainly not. It had all the
'dramatic suddenness, smoothness, directness and definiteness' that one
can wish for. It was more than a 'provisional try', rather like a hypo-
thesis which carried implicit conviction; yet on the other hand, it had
been preceded by hesitant action along the correct lines which was
abandoned; and it was succeeded by forgetting all but a fragment of
the successful solution-the fragment 'there is something about that
box'.
The reason for this paradoxical behaviour is evident. Koko had to
combine two skills; the reaching-jumping-climbing skill M1, and dis-
placing the box to serve as a platform, M2• But M2 is not part of the
chimp's habit-repertory; in all Kohler's experiments with manipu-
lating boxes and putting them on top of each other, his chimps proved
surprisingly stupid.* Thus the skill of manipulating boxes is not a well-
exercised, 'ready-made' item in Koko's repertory; and Koko is not
really ripe for the task set for him, because M2 is still too tentative and
unstable to become firmly attached to M1; linking did occur in a lucky
moment, but the link broke again. This description presupposes that
the box-manipulating skill was developing independently from banana-
collecting, as a purely playful occupation-as it did in fact when
Koko was made to play with the box before the experiment started.
And it further presupposes that if Koko had been given sufficient ti.me
to become proficient in that playful skill, then he would have ·become
ripe for a true bisociative act. Instead of this, however, he was led to
form a 'premature linkage' between boxes and bananas (cf. Book
One, IX).
This interpretation differs from Kohler's 'appearance of a complete
solution with reference to the whole layout of the field': or rather, it
specifies the condition under which such a 'complete solution' has a
chance to occur. But our interpretation is borne out by later experiments
by others, in which chimpanzees were given the same raking task as
set by Kohler. One chimpanzee out of six had previously used sticks
in play; this animal was the only one which had the 'insight' to rake in
the food placed outside the cage; the other five failed, although the
stick was lying in plain view. For the next three days all six chimps
THE ACT OF CREATION
were given sticks to play with. They used the sticks, as usual, to push
and poke, but never as a rake. Then the experiment was repeated-and
all six sticks turned into rakes instantly.15 Experiments with dogs reared
in isolation and then set 'insight situation' tasks, gave similar results.16
It may seem pedantic to lay so much stress on the independent
primary development of skills which are later combined in the
'moment of truth'. But the point does become relevant on higher
levels. The experimental sciences of electricity and magnetism de-
veloped independently, and the discovery of electro-magnetic in
duction was a truly bisociative act; in comparison to it the subsequent
improvements of electromagnets were a pedestrian procedure. The
previous independence of the cognitive structures which are made to
fuse in the creative act is, as we saw before, one of the criteria of
originality; I shall return to the subject in the £nal chapter.
'between a disease and its germ'.20 Again: 'Here not only the result is
experienced, but also very much of its "why" and "how" is felt in
just the actual context. Wherever this is the case we apply the term
insight.' But 'very much' is a relative term, and its use as an all-or-none
criterion-'wherever this is the case'-again confuses the issue. Turn-
ing to Koffka, we find that he explains the difficulties confronting the
cat in the problem-box by the fact that the actions which it must per-
form to gain release are to the cat 'objectively meaningless', that they
have 'no sort of internal connection with release', that they have no
'material relation' or 'intrinsic relation' with the opening of doors,
and so on.
It should be clear by now that all these somewhat obscure terms
are shamefaced references to physical causality, and that the position of
the Gestalt school boils down to the tautology that the animal's be-
haviour is the more intelligent the more insight it has into causal
relations. Nobody will quarrel with this statement; but it entirely
begs the central question of learning theory: namely, by what pro-
cesses and methods that insight into causal relations is acquired. The
loop in the puzzle-box, at the beginning of its training, means nothing
to the cat; at the end of its training it means escape. How is this mean-
ing acquired? Through trial-and-error learning, hypotheses, etc. The
problem can now be re-formulated as follows: can learning by trial
and error result in 'genuine' solutions, can it provide a correct, or true,
or meaningful representation of the causal connection between loop
and door? We can even go one step further and ask the same question
with regard to classical conditioning. If the dog could express itself
in Kohler's terminology, it would no doubt answer that the sound
of the gong 'signals' or 'means' food, that an 'objectively meaningful
connection', an 'intrinsic connection' or sachlicher Zusammenhang,
exists between the two. And this statement would entirely correspond
to fact, because in the laboratory universe this sequence is natural law.
Of course some connecting links are missing in the dog's inner model
of that law: the intentions of God Pavlov who has decreed it are un-
known to the dog. But such gaps occur on all levels of cognitive pro-
cesses. When the average citizen turns on his radio he has about as
much insight into the 'intrinsic connections'· between the knob and
the sound, the 'whys' and 'hows', the 'interconnections based on the
properties of the things themselves', the 'total layout of the field' as
Pavlov's dogs have.
Understanding is a matter of approximation. If we hold, with
THE PITFALLS OF GESTALT
NOTES
Top. 581. Kohler made a distinction between one-box experiments and
the building of two or three-storey structures. In the latter additional difficulties
arise from what he called the chimp's 'lack of a feeling for statics'. This handi-
cap no doubt adds to the animal's perplexity; but Koko's and Sultan's behaviour
in expcr.imcnts of this kind (c£ pp. 47, XIS, 122 ff) indicates that not only the
problem of balance, but the whole box-building business goes against the
chimpanzee's grain.
P
reparing to say something, whether it is a single sentence or a
public lecture, is to set a hierarchy in motion.
' ... And hasehe readernever askedhimself', WilliamJameswrote
in 1890, 'what kind of a mental fact is his intention of saying a thing before
he has said it? It is an entirely definite intention, distinct from all other
intentions, an absolutely distinct state of consciousness,therefore; and
yet how much of it consistsof definitesensorialimages,either of words
or of things? Hardly anything! Linger, and the words and things
come into the mind; the anticipatory intention, the divination is there
no more . . . [The intention] has therefore a nature of its own of the
most positive sort, and yet what can we say about it without using
words that belong to the later mental factsthat replaceit? The intention
to say so and so is the only name it can receive. One may admit that a
good third of our psychiclife consistsin these rapid premonitory per-
spectiveviews of schemesof thought not yet articulate.'1
In other words, before the verbal hierarchy is set into motion,
there is an ideationalprocessof a highly consciouscharacter, an inten-
tion or active expectation,which itself is not yet verbalized. Consider
what is involved in preparing an ex-tempore lecture. The first step is
to jot down the principal arguments or themes in key-words-in
'symbols of the secondremove' so to speak.Each theme is then treated
as a sub-whole, a flexible matrix of ideas with an invariant code: the
logic of the argument to be conveyed. But the ways of putting it
across are many: factually, whimsically, by concrete examples. My
strategicalchoice is governed by the lie of the land: the character of
the audience; and by feedback from implicit tries: their anticipated
reactions.If I have decided on. concrete examples, I must search for
592
LBARNING TO SPEAK 593
them in my memory, and then again make strategical choices. The
next question is where to start, to decide on the sequential order, and
the approximate time allotted to each of the various subjectsso as to
make a balanced whole. In this quasi-architecturalplanning, the argu-
ments are still treated as sub-wholes or building blocks, whose 'con-
tents are known but are present without adequate verbal designation'.2
All this is still a long way from the choice of actual words; in fact the
hazy intentional situation described by James repeats itself on several
levels.
But as we approach the actual formation of sentences,automatisms
begin to intrude, indicating that we are nearing the bottom of the
hierarchy-the consummatory acts of language which terminate the
appetitive behaviour of thought. The sub-codes of grammar and
syntax, which now enter into action, are almost wholly automatized;
and when we finally arrive at the formation of syntactic units-indi-
vidual words patterned into phrases-there is a good chancethat these
will be 'fixed action-patterns'-verbal formulae, cliches, mannerisms,
stereotyped turns of phrase, which remind one of the fighting rituals
of the stickleback(e.g. 'the evidence tends to show', 'as we have seen
before', 'we must bear in mind, however', etc}, Technicalpapers and
bureaucraticutterancesare conspicuousby their narrownessofvocabu-
lary and rigidity of phrasing. Fortunately, there exist non-abstractive
hierarchies whose criteria of relevance are aesthetic or emotional,
which co-determine the tactics of verbal choices and counteract the
tendency towards automatization.
Having gone through all these implicit motions, we end up by
spelling out the actual sounds or ink marks, vocal patterns or type
written letters. Yet even on this automatizedlevel, hierarchicorganiza-
tion prevails; the phonetic sequencesor manual patterns are triggered
off as wholes and perceivedas wholes; nowhere, in the course of our
descent through the hierarchy, do we strike rock-bottom, made of
hard 'atoms of behaviour'.
Thus 'verbal behaviour' is initiated by unverbalized intentions at
the top of the language hierarchy, and terminates. in deverbalized
sensory-motor activities; at each level it is governed by rules which
dude verbal definition, and modified by extraneous factors acting on
the plastic matrices of language. Each time we slice behaviour 'ver-
tically'-instead of horizontally on a single level-we arrive at a series
which at the top recedesinto an elusiveblur and at its base vanishesin
the twilight of awareness.
594 THE ACT OF CREATION
utilized both as labels, and as levers which make things happen, that
they serve both the progressive socialization and internalization of
behaviour-communication and inner discourse. This is well-covered
ground which needs no further labouring. But another phenomenon
of early language behaviour is rarely emphasized: the appearance of
the naming question or 'naming mania'. The child points at anything
it sees, asks 'This-?' or 'What that?', and is visibly satisfied to learn
the answer, without any utilitarian reward. Alternatively, it points at
things, calls out their name or, if it has forgotten it, invents a new one.
Here is a true paradigm oflatent learning, of the exploratory drive, or
of l'art pour l'art behaviour-whatever one wants to call it. To quote
Piaget: 'It is ••• no exaggeration to say that sensory-motor intelligence
is limited to desiring success or practical adaptation, whereas the func-
tion of verbal or conceptual thought is to know and state truth.'4
But there is another aspect to the 'name-expectation': henceforth
the child's concept of a thing or event will be experienced by it as
incomplete if there is no verbal label attached to it. The concept will
behave like a molecule with a free valency, as it were. We can perhaps
recapture an echo of this when we hunt for the forgotten name of a
person. Also, when we learn a new language, we suddenly have a
whole class of free valencies: we feel actually frustrated when we dis-
cover that the French have no word for 'snobbery' or 'understate-
ment', and are tempted to exclaim like a child: 'But surely they must
have a name for it?'
The behaviour of the rat exploring a maze or of the monkey fear-
fully peeping into the box with the snake, could be described as inter-
rogatory, and the same description could be applied to the puzzled
expressions and actions of a small child before it has learned to speak.
But its first explicit, verbal questions refer to the names of things, promp-
ted by the need to 'saturate' the free valencies in its pre-verbal object-
concepts. Is it too speculative to assume that this origin of the question-
ing habit must influence the whole later development of thought? The
fact that each naming question can be readily answered by adults, may
implant the implicit belief into the child that all questions are both
meaningful and answerable; that the nature of explanation is based on
the same kind of simple and direct connections as that between 'thing'
and 'name'. This implicit belief seems to have been one of the factors
responsible for the aberrations of human thought.
Concepts and Labels
When 'He' emits the operant, 'What time is it?', the muscular activity, of course,
produces a sound, which also serves as a stimulus for 'She'. On the receipt of this
stimulus, she emits an operant herself: 'Twelve o'clock', which in turn produces
a stimulus to 'He'. And so on .•..
In such a complex activity, then, we can see that what we really have is a
series ofS.-R. connections. The phenomenon of connecting a series of such S.-R.
writs is known as chaining, a process that should be apparent in any complex
activity. We might note that there are a number of sources of reinforcement
throughout the chaining process, in this example the most obvious being the
reinforcement of'She' by receiving an invitation for lunch and of'He' by having
the invitation accepted. In addition, as Keller and Schoenfeld point out, there
are such sources of reinforcement as the hearer 'encouraging' the speaker to
continue, the use that the conversationalists make of the information received
(he finds out what time it is), etc.
This example of the analysis of a complex activity is but one of numerous
possibilities that we could discuss. You should continue to think of others your-
self and try to diagram the chaining process for them ... (p. 375).
During its first years the child does not discriminate between nominal,
attributive, and causal predications-as earlier it did not differentiate
words according to grammatical categories.
When children between five and six are asked: 'Why does the sun
not fall down?', they will answer: 'Because it is hot', 'Because the sun
stops there', 'Because it is yellow'.15 And the moon does not fall down
'Because it is very high up', 'Because the sun is not there', etc. The sig-
nificant aspects of an experience are connected as 'going together'
in an undifferentiated 'feeling of relation'.16 Goethe's 'Connect, always
connect' seems to be the motto of the child as, out of the fluid raw
material of its experiences, it selects and shapes patterns and relations
-relations which will be re-classed and re-grouped later on according
to shifts in motivation and interest leading to the emergence of new
criteria of relevance-until the final, more rigid but not always more
perfect adult relation-categories emerge. The urge to connect, to
aggregate matrices of experience into more comprehensive ones; the
fumbling for hypotheses about the way things are held together, the
tentative formulation of rules of the game-in all these fertile activities
we see the participatory tendencies at work: intimations of the funda-
mental unity of all things. Later on they will crystallize in magic
causality, with its correlates: animism and 'mystic participation' (to
use an expression coined by Levy-Bruh! for the mentality of primi-
tives, and applied by Piaget to the mentality of the child). Needless
to say, the self-asserting tendencies too play their obvious part both
in the child's overt behaviour and its fantasy world.
It seems that the first relational patterns which arc discriminated arc
relatively static forms of attribution (of names and other properties),
and of dynamic changes-in-time. The latter give rise to a vague 'feeling
of causal relations'P? derived from the cumulative experience that
'things make other things do things'. At this stage, word-classes begin
to emerge which roughly correspond to substantive-nouns, adjective-
attributes, and action-words or verbs. But these classes, and the types
of relations implied in them, remain for a long time fluid. The child's
progress towards grammatically more correct forms of speech is
mainly due to imitation and conventional training-which mask the
fact that behind the increasingly adult forms of expression, magic
ways of thought survive. They survive, of course, even in the adult,
and never vanish completely. Thus the stabilization of the codes of
6I5
616 THE ACT OP CREATION
To quote Russell's famous dictum once more, 'it must have required
many ages to discover that a brace of pheasants and a couple of days
were both instances of the number two'. In fact, evidence indicates
that the discovery was not made in one fell swoop, but in several hesi-
tant steps; and when it was achieved, some cultures were quite content
622 TBB ACT OF CREATION
to stop there and rest on their glories: Australian aborigines have only
three number-words in their vocabulary: one, two, and many.11>
Most European languages show the traces of this stage of development:
the Latin ter means both 'three times' and 'many' (c£ 'thrice blest').
At the earliest stage the number concept is not yet abstracted from
the objects which are numbered: 'two-ness' is a feature situated in
particular twosome objects, not a general relation. Language bears
witness to this 'embeddedness': a 'brace' of pheasants is not a 'pride'
oflions; a 'pair', when married, is a 'couple', when engaged in singing,
a 'duo'. In some primitive languages not only the number two but all
numerals adhere to the type of object counted; in the Timshian tongue
of New Guinea there are seven different classes of number-words
referring, respectively, to Bat objects, round objects, long objects,
people, canoes, and measures; the seventh, used for counting in general,
was the latest to develop.20
Children go through a similar stage; Koffka mentions several three-
year-olds who understood and used the words 'two apples', but did
not understand 'two eyes', 'two ears'. One child, over four, when
asked by his grandfather, 'How many fingers have I?', replied, 'I
don't know; I can only count my own fingers.' There is an old joke
about the new arithmetic teacher who, when he asked the class, 'How
many oranges would Johnnie have if ... etc.', received the indignant
reply, 'Please, sir, we have only learned to count in apples'. The num-
ber-matrix, once adherent to the object-matrix, has gained such
lofty independence, that their re-union is experienced as a bisociation
of incompatibles.
The next step is the abstraction of individual numbers, which are not
yet regarded as parts of a continuous series. The first 'personalized'
number-concept abstracted by primitive and child alike is almost in-
variably the number two. Next follow the concepts 'one' and 'many'.
Some cultures, as mentioned, stop there; others retain traces of this
stage in their languages; Hebrew and Greek have retained separate
grammatical forms for the singular, the dual, and the plural. Koffka
mentions a child who played with combinations of 'two and one',
'two and two', etc., until early into its fifth year; only then did the
number-word 'three' become firmly established.
These first individual number-concepts are only semi-abstract;
they emerge as it were reluctantly from the womb, and retain for a
long time the umbilical cord which attaches them to concrete objects
or favourite symbols. In some primitive languages the word for five
LEARNING TO THINK
is 'hand', for ten 'two hands'. Each number primarily refers to some
such 'model collection' of practical or mystical significance: the four
cardinal points, the Holy Trinity, the magic Pentagram. Each number
has its preferential connotation, its personality and individual profile;
it is as yet unrelated to other numbers and does not form a continuous
series with them. The number sense of Otto Koehler' s birds who
can identify at a glance object-collections up to seven, and the same
faculty of human subjects (to whom heterogeneous objects are shown
on a screen for a time too short for counting) give us some idea of the
character of our own earliest number-concepts. They could. be des-
cribed as qualities rather than as quantities in a graded series; the identi-
fication of numbers in experiments where counting is excluded, con-
sists apparently in recognizing the quasi-Gestalt quality of 'fiveness'
(I say 'quasi' because the objects are distributed at random and do not
provide coherent figural unity]. In other words, each of the first
individual numbers up to perhaps seven or eight, is represented by
a separate matrix-its associative connotations-and a perceptual
analyser-code which enables us to recognize 'fivencss' directly, at a
glance. The analyser probably works by scanning, as in the perception
of triangles and squares; but this process is automatic and unconscious,
as opposed to conscious counting.
Thus the first 'personalized' number-concepts 'do not constitute a
homogeneous series, and are quite unsuited to the simplest logical or
mathematical operation'.21 Those first operations are, apparently,
carried out not by counting, but by matching the collection of objects
to be counted against 'model collections' of pebbles, notches cut into
a stick, knots made in a string, and above all the fingers and toes. The
'model collections' are usually those to which the individual number-
concept originally referred. The earliest model collections seem to have
been pebbles; 'to calculate' is derived from calculus, meaning pebble;
to tally, from talea, cutting. Relics of other model-collections abound
in our weights and measures: feet, yards, furlongs, chains, bushels,
rods. The Ayepones in Australia hunt wild horses; when they return
from an excursion nobody asks them how many horses they have
caught but 'How much space will they occupy?'. Even Xerxes counted
his army by this method-at least, if we are to believe Herodotus:
All the fleet, being now arrived at Doriscus, was brought by its
captains at Xerxes' command to the beach near Doriscus ... and
hauled up for rest. In the meanwhile, Xerxes numbered his army at
THE ACT OF CREATION
Doriscus. What the number of each part ofit was I cannot with exact-
ness say, for there is no one who tells us that; but the count of the
whole land army showed it to be a million and seven hundred
thousand. The numbering was done as follows: a myriad [ 10,000]
men were collected in one place, and when they were packed
together as closely as might be, a line was drawn round them; this
being drawn, the myriad was sent away, and a wall of stone built on
the line reaching up to a man's navel; which done, others were
brought into the walled space, till in this way all were counted.22
NOTE
To p. 613. Once upon a time Lashley and Wade (1946) tried to make a
distinction 'between the "so-called generalization" which means only a failure to
observe differences and the generalization which involves perception of both
similarities and differences. The amorphous figure, lacking in identity, is genera-
lized in the first sense only.' The quotation is from Hebb (1949, p. 27), who
seemed to share Lashley's view, although Lashley himself later dropped the
distinction. The 'amorphous figure' in the quotation refers to 'an irregular mass
of colour or a pattern ofintersecting Imes drawn at random'. Being amorphous
it does per de.finitionemlack identity, i.e., the prerequisites for the formation of an
object-concept; but it is nevertheless seen as some kind of figure on a background
that is discriminated. In fact, abstraction without discrimination is a contradiction
in terms. The abstracted quality-whether 'nose', 'dolly', or 'sound of the tuning
fork' is always differentiated from non-nose and non-dolly and no-sound. (If
the sound of the tuning fork is very weak, it will approach the limcn of no-sound;
about the effect of simple gradients of intensity, sec Hebb (1958), p. 189; about
pitch and octave gradients, sec Osgood, op. cit., p. 361. Since perception of in
tensity, pitch, etc. is part of the animal's perceptual organization, they must
inB.ucnce the functioning of the analyser-codes.)
XVI
I
n the preceding chapter we have discussed the processes by which
the rules of the game of symbolic thought are acquired; let us
now turn to adult thinking and problem-solving.
Thinking is a multi-dimensional affair. The Sterns recorded all the
questions asked by their little daughter in the course of four days;
but the record gives us only the scantiest pointers to what went on in
the child's head. Perhaps one day a super-EEG will be constructed,
which will record all the thoughts-or at least all verbalized thoughts
-which the stream of consciousness carries through the subject's
wired skull; yet even such a record, far more complete than anything
James Joyce could dream of, would be but a poor pointer to the multi-
dimensional patterns underlying the linear stream. The oscillating
curve on the gramophone record needs a human auditory system to
yield all the information it contains. The super-EEG would record
larger units of information-entire words; but it would still need a
psychoanalyst or a Joyce-interpreter to divine the meaning behind the
meaning: the connotations of individual words, their unconscious
echoes, the motivation behind it all, the rules of the patient's game,
hidden to himself, and the memories which crop up as landmarks in
his internal, mental environment.
We must nevertheless try to sort out some of the dimerrsional
variables in this immensely complex, multi-dimensional activity;
these variables will then yield gradients of different kinds; for instance:
Degrees of Self-Awareness
convergent series. One may call this the paradox of the dog at dinner.
The dog is eating his dinner; the wagging of his tail indicates that he is
enjoying himself; but does he know that he is enjoying himself? ...
A little boy is watching a Western on the TV screen. He is enjoying
himself. He knows perhaps that he is enjoying himself. Does he know
that he knows? ... The philosopher is thinking of a problem. He is
aware that he is thinking of this problem. Is he aware that he is aware,
etc .... ? The known is always one step ahead of the knower, and they
chase each other up a spiral staircase, as it were. In Craik' s terminology
one might say that the model can never make a complete model of
itsel£* Regarding verbal models in particular, we have seen (pp. 592 ff.)
that verbal statements are initiated by unverbalized intentions on higher
levels, so that we again arrive at a receding series. This seems to indi-
cate that the mind-body problem is not amenable to any solution in
explicit, verbal terms.
On the other hand, the fact that the subject who is aware can never-
theless become, to some extent, the object of his own awareness, is of
course of outstanding importance in mental life. Animals, apparently
from planaria onwards, display attention and expectancy which indicate
varying degrees of 'linear' awareness; primates, as well as domestic
pets, may also have some rudiments of self-awareness. But the many-
layered hierarchies of man, and particularly his symbolic hierarchies,
place him on a lonely peak, and impose on him the impossible com-
mand to 'know thyself'. Awareness of awareness is a tantalizing gift;
and 'I think therefore I exist' is a hopeful beginning. But the end, the
identification of the knower and the known, which alone would
constitute complete consciousness of existence, though always in
sight, is never achieved. The successive forms of self-identification,
starting from the child's fluid. world of experience which knows as yet
no firm boundary between self and not-self, can be likened to a mathe-
matical series converging towards unity, or to a spiral curve converg-
ing towards a centre which it will only reach after an infinite number
of involutions.
The aim of certain mystic practices-such as Hatha Yoga-is to
permeate the self with awareness of itself by gaining voluntary control
over visceral processes and isolated muscles. It would seem that this
focussing of consciousness on the self, the inward core of the contrac-
ting spiral, is the direct opposite of the self-transcending aspirations of
other schools of mysticism-the expansion of consciousness in an un-
, folding spiral, and its :final dissolution in the 'oceanic feeling'. In fact,
SOME ASPECTS OF THINKING 635
however, the Yogi's effort to gain consciousmastery of the body is
considered as merely a detour towards attaining 'pure consciousness'
-that is, 'consciousnesswithout object or content other than conscious-
ness itself'.'Thus turned upon itself, pure consciousnessis supposedto
penetrate the Real Self-which, unlike the transient self, is part and
parcel of the Atman, the universal spirit.1 Both methods, therefore,
each with a long historical ancestry, share the same ultimate aim-
situated at the point where oppositesmeet; after all, as the bright little
boy said, 'the infinite is where things happen which don't'.
'Self-awareness',in the sense of the preceding paragraphs, has of
course nothing to do with 'self-consciousness'in the senseof gauchery,
stage-fright. The latter is our old friend, the paradox of the centipede
-the disorganizationof behaviour which results when higher centres
interfere with the autonomous functioning of parts on lower levels.
'Self-consciousness',used in this sense, is a typically English coinage;
it provides an amusing and rather revealing contrast to the equally
malapropos German coinage 'Selbstbewusstsein'-meaning self-con-
fident, conscious of one's own value. As for the French, faithful to
the Cartesian spirit, they use conscience to designate both conscious-
ness and moral conscience.
x1, s= -p/2± Jp2/4--q. For the next few days or weeks, every
time he has to use the formula, he must look it up in his textbook (or,
ifhe is very brilliant, derive it afresh). At this stage of the learning pro-
cess the formula is not yet an automatically functioning rule of the
game; it is not yet a 'code' impressedon his nervous system. But after
some practice, a single glance at an expressionof the form x2+px+
q =o will tell him that it is a member of the matrix of quadratic equa-
tions and trigger off the rule-by now an automatized code-for
solving it.
Thus rules which at first have to be looked up, or reconstructed by
a consciouseffort, become codified and automatized by routine. It is
irrelevant in this particular context whether the student has by now
forgotten the derivation of the formula and merely uses it as a mechani-
cal gimmick; or whether he is aware of its binomial ancestry. This
makes a vast differencein terms of understanding, but need not affect
the processof automatization.
I have emphasizedbefore that the term 'code' is used in this book
not in the metaphorical way in which Freud, for instance, used the
word 'censor', but to refer to concrete processesor patterns of organi-
zation in the central nervous system. However, it sounds somehow
more plausible to attribute physiological reality to codes on lower
levelsof the organic hierarchy-the genetic code, the codesof instinct-
behaviour and sensory-motor skills-than to claim that the rules of
such esotericgamesas non-Euclidiangeometry or quantum mechanics
are physiologicallyrepresented,by appropriate coding methods, in the
nervous system, and can be triggered off by simple releasers (such as
the command 'let's talk shop'). I must therefore underline once more
that the term 'code' is meant to apply only to those rules of behaviour
which govern establishedroutines and function automatically with-
out consciouseffort.In the initial stagesof learning a complex symbolic
skill, the rules of the game (laws,theorems, mathematicalor chemical
formulae) must be constantly memorized, looked up, or consciously
recalled;so long as this is the case they are not yet incorporated.into
the physico-mental organization and are not to be called 'codes'.
Codes are only those fixed stable rules which, once switched on,
automaticallygovern the thinking routine. The problem in problem-
solving consistsfirstly in discovering which routine is appropriate to
the problem-what type of game is to be played; and secondly,how to
play it-i.e. which strategy to follow, which members of the flexible
matrix are to be brought into play according to the lie of the land.
SOME ASPECTS OF THINKING 639
We learn, or discover, with strenuous effort, a new method of
thinking; after a while, with practice, the novelty changes into semi-
automatized routine, based on an invariant code with an adaptable
matrix, and is incorporated into our repertory of habits. It is astonish-
ing how soon, once a new railroad is built across desert and mountains,
the passenger-trains start running on schedule.
But the process of habit-formation does not stop-there: not only the
rules of the newly learnt game become soon automatized to such an
extent that it becomes increasingly difficult to go against them, but
strategy, too, tends to become stereotyped and incorporated into the
code. Take progress in chess, an example I have mentioned before. The
beginner is uncertain about the rules; then the rules become automatic
codes and it becomes almost impossible for him to move his men in
impermissible ways; after protracted practice certain tactical prin-
ciples, which are no longer 'rules' in the formal sense, also begin to
operate automatically in his mind-e.g. to avoid pins, to seek open
rook-files. But this reification of tactical pseudo-rules into auto-
matized sub-codes contains a mortal danger, because considerations
of strategy on a higher level demand that each of these tactical rules
should be broken if the occasion warrants it. Sacrifices in material,
and moves which look cockeyed {that is: positionally unsound), are
signs of combinative power, i.e. originality; the mediocre player
always remains a slave of habit and cautious orthodoxy.
At this point the argument merges into that of Book One (IX-XI),
concerning the pitfalls of orthodoxy, over-specialization, and one-
sided development in the history of science and philosophy. In biology
or theoretical physics there are no clean-cut distinctions between
canonical rules of the game and heuristic rules of strategy and tactics.
We are inclined to believe, as popular books on science tell us, that the
'permissible moves' are laid down for ever by the laws of formal
logic and the criteria for judging evidence; and that strategy is deter-
mined only by the lie of the land, that is, the data of observation. In
fact, however, the rules tum out to be infiltrated with implicit assump-
tions and 'self-evident axioms' which as often as not are specious contra-
band; and the empirical strategies are often weighted by a stubborn
adherence to methods of interpretation and biassed techniques, pro-
moted to canonical status. Habit is heir to originality; without the
hierarchies of organized habits life would be chaos; creativity means
breaking up habits and joining the fragments into a new synthesis.
Matrix Categories
learns to write with the left, his signature, before long, recovers its
true character. 'Even the suspiciousbank clerk will cash his cheque
because the old form of signature returns,' wrote Penfield,3 who had
severalsuch patients. 'The pattern of the signature and of the writing
is in the brain, not in the hand.'
This applies, to a considerableextent, even to the style of writing.
Hemingway or Proust can be identified-and parodied-afterreading
a few lines-as you identify the timbre of a drum or violin after a few
transients. Even the language of conunon mortals whose style is
undistinguishedand seeminglyindistinguishable,appearsto have fixed
characteristicratios-.e.g. between the number of adjectivesto verbs.
The total matrix, which comprisesall theseframesof behaviour, con-
stitutesthe personalitystructure.But even here, the codecan apparently
be triggered on and off by some super-master-switch-as the spec-
tacular cases of multiple personalitiesindicate. Once more the hier-
archy fades into a receding series.
NOTES
Top. 634. Cyberneticists have discussed at length models which are supposed
to be capable of this feat. But they have no bearing on the question of awareness.
ASSOCIATION
'Multiple Auunements'
the matrices to which it belongs (for instance 'Civil War'); and vice
versa, that any of these matrices can be activated by it. If we assign to
each matrix, metaphorically speaking, a specific 'wave-length' then
the concept may be represented as an aggregate of several oscillation-
circuits, each of which will receive and emit on the specific 'wave-
length' of its matrix. We may call this the 'multiple attunement' of the
concept to the various matrices of which it is a member.*
Now the aggregate of circuits, which is the concept, may receive
on one wave-length and emit on another. 'Madrid' was evoked by the
phonetic matrix 'initial M', and in its turn activated a different matrix,
'Civil War', which functions on a different wave-length. If the matrix
of the incoming signal is of a complex or abstract character, the
aggregate may tend to switch over to a circuit functioning on the wave-
length of an emotionally more appealing matrix. Thus a concept is a
member of several clubs, but it likes some clubs more than others.
Its 'multiple attunements' may be represented as a line-spectrum of
frequencies with a relatively stable energy-distribution. The fre-
quencies of maximum energy-like the dominant partials in a sound-
spectrum-would represent the concept's 'most-preferred' associative
contexts. As the years go by, new lines would be added to the spectrum,
while others would fade away, and the energy-distribution of associa-
tive preferences would change-getting mellower perhaps, like an
old Stradivarius, or croaking, like an un-tuned piano. The effort to
'concentrate' on an abstract problem is probably proportionate to the
energy required to inhibit preferential associative contexts of high
energy-potential-Le. 'habit strength'.
The preceding paragraphs may have given an exaggerated impres-
sion of the subjectivity of concepts-rather on the lines of Humpty
Dumpty's 'a word means what I intend it to mean'. The connotations of
concepts referring to individuals or places are of course largely per-
sonal; but on the other hand, there is experimental evidence to show
that the associative priorities and the connotative 'aura' of concepts
of a general character are surprisingly stable and standardized in indi-
viduals of the same culture. 'Marbe's Law' demonstrated the existence
of a logarithmic relation between an individual's reaction-time in giv-
ing a certain response to a stimulus-word in an association test, and
the frequency of the same response occurring in a group of people.**
Osgood has invented an ingenious method of measuring 'semantic
differentials'. The subjects were asked to assess the ratings of a concept
, -e.g. POLITE-on ten different graded scales: e.g. 'angular-rounded',
ASSOCIATION
Types of Association
NOTES
To p. 644. 'Wave-length' is of course used metaphoricallyfor much more
complex processes,including both structural and functional characteristicsof
nervous tissue. 'Excitation-clang' or 'frequency-modulationsignals' or Hebb's
'phase-sequencesin cell assemblies'would be closerapproximations.
THE ACT OF CREATION
Top. 644. For a summary see Woodworth (1939) pp. 360 seq., Osgood
(1900) pp. 722 et seq. Osgood (p. 72.2), discussingthe relative frequencies and
reaction times of verbal responsesin associationtests, speaks of a 'hierarchical
structure of associations; but he uses the word 'hierarchy' to refer to a linear
scale of gradations.
XVIII
HABIT AND ORIGINALITY
The process of bridging the gap between the perceived problem and
its solution is describedin an oft-quoted passageby Karl Mach:
Searchingfor a Code
Degrees of Originality
the water each time back into the river. This leavesyou with one pint
which you can keep in the bigger or put into the smallercontainer-but
that does not help because now you cannot isolate the five pints to
which the single pint must be added. The solution is simply to switch
from addition to subtraction: you keep your pint in the smaller con-
tainer, and fill it up from the larger one-it will now only take 4- I = 3
pints, leaving 9-3 =6 pints in the large jug. Different people solve
this problem by different methods. Polya gives an analytical ex-
planation; personally I found that with most people the click occurs
through the reversalof the direction of thought from addition to sub-
traction-from figure to background-a phenomenon we frequently
met in discovery.
At a certain level of problem-solving even a healthy kind of illo-
gicality, of disregardingapparent contradictions, makes its appearance
-as in the image of the monk meeting his alter-ego. But enough has
been said to show that as the challengebecomes more provoking, the
nature of the guidance which directs the search for the right type of
matrix to bear on the problem, becomes more intuitive, more re-
mote from the normal routine of thinking, and that extra-conscious
processesplay an increasinglyimportant part. And thus, having started
from the base of the hierarchy,we arrive at last at the roof, which we
have surveyedin the first volume but had left hanging in the air: the
act of discovery.
a jiffy by substituting for it the time taken by the trains until they
crash (t= rno/40=2i). Both the formula, and the process of sub-
stitution, are familiar sub-skillsin the subject's repertory of habits,
and should function as members of the matrix. However, owing to
the unusual lie of the land-i.e. the way the data are presented-his
strategy breaks down, the matrix goes to pieces, and its members.
function as independent entities. Once this has occurred it would
require a certain originality to combine them again. We might even
be generous and say, that to re-combine them would be a minor bi-
sociativeact.
Thus the degree of independence of the matrices or submatrices
which combine in the solution of a problem, can only be judged with
reference to the subject's mental organization. Any boy of the sixth
form can derive the Pythagorean theorem, which he has previously
learned, as a matter of routine; but to discover it for him.selfwould.
require a high degree of originality.
I hope I have laid sufficientemphasis on the fact that originality
must be measured on subjectivescales and that any self-taughtnovelty
is a minor bisociativeact. This taken for granted, let me recapitulate
the criteria which distinguishbisociative originality from associative
routine.
Habit Originality
Association within the confines Bisoci.ation of independent
of a given matrix matrices
Habit Originality
Dynamic equilibrium Activation of regenerative
potentials
Repetitiveness Novelty
Conservative Destructive-Constructive
And thus we are back where we left off in the first book; the circle
is closed.
APPENDIX I: ON LOADSTONES
AND AMBER
I
have compared (Book One, X) the constructive periods in the
evolution of science to river-estuaries in which previously separate
branches of knowledge merge in a series of bisociative acts. The
present appendix is meant to illustrate the process by a few salient
episodes from the history of magnetism and electricity-two fields of
study which, until the beginning of the nineteenth century, had
developed on independent lines, and seemed to be in no way related.
Their merging was due to the discovery of unitary laws of a previously
unsuspected kind underlying the variety of phenomena, and took
physics a decisive step forward towards a universal synthesis.
belief that the source of the 'virtue' which attracted the compass needle
was located in the sky-in the Polar Star or the Great Bear.
During the next three hundred years no further progress seems to
have been made-except for some improvements of the compass and
attempts to measure magnetic declination, caused by the puzzling dis-
covery that the direction of the needle deviated at different places to
different degrees from the direction of the Polar Star.
The next landmark is Dr. William Gilbert of Colchester, court
physician to Queen Elizabeth, the first great English experimentalist.
Gilbert put both magnetism and electricity on the map-or rather, on
two separate maps; his influence on his younger contemporaries,
Kepler and Galileo, was enormous. Gilbert's fundamental discovery-
in fact the only important discovery made in the whole history of
magnetism as an independent science-is again one of those which, in
retrospect, appear deceptively simple. He found that the power which
attracted the magnetic needle was not in the skies but in the earth: that
the earth itself was a huge spherical loadstone. He arrived at this con-
clusion by making, as Peregrine had done, a spherical magnet, and
exploring the behaviour of a minute compass-needle on its surface.
As he moved the needle over his globe, he saw that it behaved exactly
as the needle of the mariner's compass behaved on a sea journey-both
with regard to its north-south alignment and to its 'dip', which in
creased the closer the needle approached either of the poles. He con-
cluded that his spherical loadstone was a model of the earth which
therefore must be a magnet.*
So the secret of the compass-needle was solved by ascribing magnetic
properties to the earth-there remained only the secret of the nature of
magnetism itsel£ Gilbert's book, De Magnete, was published A.D.
16oo-the same year in which Kepler joined forces with Tycho de
Brahe to lay the foundations of the new astronomy; the symbolic
year which, like a watershed, divides medieval from modem philo-
sophy. Gilbert, born in 1544, stood, like Kepler, astride the water-
shed: with one foot in the brave new world of experimental science,
the other stuck in Aristotelian animism. His descriptions of how
magnetism works are modem; his explanations of its causes are
medieval: he regards the magnetic force as a living emanation from
the spirit or soul of the loadstone. The earth, being a giant loadstone,
also'has a soul-its magnetic virtue-and so have the heavenly bodies.
'Magnetic force is animate, or imitates the soul; and in many things
surpasses the human soul while this is bound up in the organic body.'1
.APPENDIX I
The actions of the magnetic virtue are 'without error ... quick.
definite, constant, directive, motive, imperant, harmonious ... it
reaches out like an arm clasping round the attracted body and drawing
it to itself.... It must needs be light and spiritual so as to enter the
iron'-but it must also be a material, subtle vapour, an ether or
effluvium. Even the earth's rotation is somehow connected with
magnetism: 'In order that the Earth may not perish in various ways,
and be brought from confusion, she turns herself about by magnetic
and primary virtue.' 2
Thus Gilbert's book, which enjoyed uncontested authority for the
next two hundred years, postulated on the one hand action at a dis-
tance, but asserted on the other the existence of an effluvium or ether
which passes 'like a breath' between the attracting bodies. It was also
a major factor in creating semantic confusion: the word 'magnetism',
which originally referred to the properties of a type of ore mined in
Magnesia, a province of Thessaly, came soon to be applied to any kind
of attraction or affinity, physical, psychological, or metaphorical
('animal magnetism', 'Mesmerism', etc.). But as long as the study of
the behaviour of magnets remained an isolated field of research, no
further progress could be made. In 1621 van Helmont, and in 1641
Athanasius Kircher, published books on the subject which added
nothing new to it, but dwelt at length on the alleged wound-healing
properties of magnets; Kircher's book carried a whole section on the
'magnetism' of love, and ended with the dictum that the Lord is the
magnet of the universe. Newton took no interest in magnetism except
for some remarks in the third book of the PrincipiaS to the effect that
the magnetic force seemed to vary approximately with the inverse
cube of the distance; while Descartes extended his theory of cosmic
vortices to cover both magnetic and electric phenomena. The main
subjects of interest were the variations in the positions of the earth's
magnetic poles which, to the navigators' distress, were found to wander
around like floating kidneys. This led to the kind of controversy
characteristic of most periods of stagnation in the history of science;
thus one Henry Bond of London town, a 'Teacher of Navigation',
published in 1676 a book, The Lon,gitude Found, based on the theory
that the magnetic poles lagged behind the earth's daily rotation. This
thesis was tom to pieces in another book, The Longitude Not Found, by
Peter Blackborough.
Even the great Halley went haywire where magnetism was con-
cerned: he proposed that the earth was a kind of solar system in
THE ACT OF CREATION
miniature, with an inner core and an outer shell, both of them mag-
netized, and a luminous fluid between them to provide light for the
people living on the surfaceof the inner core; this luminous effluvium
escaping through the earth's pores gave rise to the aurora borealis.
Halley was the grc;atestastronomer and one of the leading scientific
minds of the age, who had published the first modern magnetic chart
in Mercator's projection, based on his own patient observations; but
his wild speculationsindicate that the element of the fantastic was
firmly embedded in the concept of magnetism-as it still is in our day.
Children are still fascinatedby compassesand magnets, governed by a
force more mysterious than gravity-because the latter is taken for
granted from earliestexperiencewhereas magnetism cannot be sensed,
and not only attracts but also repels. No wonder that this unique
phenomenon,while consideredin isolation,had led those who studied
it round in circlesin a blocked matrix.
But although, for nearly two centuries,the study of magnetismmade
no progress,Gilbert's work had a fertile influenceon other branchesof
science.The loadstone became the archetype of action-at-a-distance,
and paved the way for the recognition of universal gravity. Without
the demonstrable phenomena of magnetic attraction, people would
have been even more reluctant to exchange the traditional view that
heavy bodies tended towards the centre of the universe, for the im
plausiblesuggestionthat all heavenly and earthly bodies were tugging
at each other 'with ghostly fingers' acrossempty space.Even the magic
properties attributed to magnetism, and the very ambiguity of its
concept, proved to be unexpectedly stimulating to the tortuous line
of advance which led via Mesmerismand hypnosis to contemporary
forms of psychiatry.
The next turning point is Coulomb's discovery, in r785. that the
inverse square law applied to magnetism too, as it applied to gravity.
It must have looked at the time as if these two kinds of action-at-a-
distancewould soon tum out to be based on the same principle-as
Keplerand Descartesthought they were; as if a great merger of sciences
were in the offing. But that synthesisis still a matter of the future;
instead of merging with gravity, magnetism entered into a much less
obvious union with electricity.
Leyden Jar had been able to do. It taught them not only that the
chemical interaction of metals produced electricity; but also that an
electric current sent through certain chemicals led to their decom-
position. In 1806 Davy tentatively suggested that chemical affinity
had an electrical basis. But nearly a century had to pass until, in 1897,
Thompson discovered that a certain type of electrical discharge-the
so-called cathode rays-consisted of particles smaller than atoms;
and that in these particles 'matter derived from different sources such
as hydrogen, oxygen, etc.-is one and the same kind, this matter being
the substance from which the chemical elements are built up'.5
Thompson's 'elementary corpuscles' were later named 'electrons'.
But let me return for a moment to the Voltaic battery. The abun-
dant flow of current which it produced was so startling that it was at
fust doubted whether this 'electric fluid' was the same kind of thing
which came in sparks out of the older contraptions. Comparison of
their etfects led to the realization that the discharges of static electricity
from a Leyden Jar had a higher potential or tension, whereas the flow
from the battery had a low potential but carried a greater quantity of
current. Thus the distinction was made between the potential (vol-
tage), roughly comparable to the gradient of a river-bed, and the
quantity of liquid (amperage) that passed through it. But only fifty
years later did Faraday realize that the spark from a Leyden Jar could
be regarded as a short-lived current; then came Maxwell, who treated
currents as moving charges, thus finally unifying the two kinds of
electricity: 'frictional' and 'Voltaic'. ~
In the meantime, however, that other grand synthesis got underway:
the unification of electricity and magnetism. There were several steps.
The first link was established in 1820 by the observation of Hans
Christian Oersted in Copenhagen that if an electric current flowed
through a wire in the vicinity of a magnetic compass, the needle was
deflected and turned into a position at right angles to the wire. The
news created an immediate sensation in Paris, where Ampere's ex-
citable brain gave off a spark bigger than any Leyden Jar: he realized
in a single flash that if an electric current produced a magnetic field,
as the reaction of the needle indicated, then all magnetic fields may be
due to electric currents-that magnetism was a by-product of elec-
tricity. He let a current run through a spiral coil inside of which he
placed a steel needle: it became magnetized, and the :first electro-
magnet was born.*
But how, then, was the 'narural magnetism' of loadstones to be
APPENDIX I
freely suspended in the air. Gone were the tubes, the vortices, the
ether; all that remained were 'fields' of an abstract, non-substantial
nature, and the mathematical formalism which described the propa-
gation of real waves in an apparentlynon-existent medium. It was the
great turning point in physical science, when the aspiration to arrive
at intelligible, mechanical models was abandoned. This renuncia-
tion, born of necessity,soon hardened into dogma-a secular version
of the Commandment 'Thou shalt not make unto thee any graven
image'--of gods or atoms.*
The transition from model-making to mathematical abstraction is
strikingly illustrated by the fact that Maxwell himself left it to others
(to Heinrich Rudolph Herz, as it came to pass) to give empiricalproof
of his electro-magneticwaves. As Crowther wrote:
Yet even Maxwell had his blind spots. The electron as a basic,
quasi-atomic unit of electricity was clearly implied in his model of
ether-vortices, and in his theory of electrolysis.Yet he rejected the
concept of 'particles' of electricity as Faraday before had rejected it.
Thus, as already mentioned, it was left, to J. J. Thompson to take the
next decisivestep: the identificationof the electron as an elementary
unit of electricity, and at the same time an elementary particle of
matter. Some fifteen years later Rutherford discoveredthat the atom
had a positively charged nucleus; Moseleydiscoveredthat the number
of electrons in an atom determined its place in the periodic system;
and Bohr made his famous model of electrons circling round the
nucleus like planets round the sun. Matter and electricityhad merged
into a single matrix.
We have followed, though only in the scantest outline, the suc-
cessive confluencesinto a vast river-delta, of electricity, magnetism,
light, heat, and other electro-magneticradiations; of chemistry, bio-
chemistry,and atomic physics.This developmentwas, as we have seen
THE ACT OF CREATION
NOTES
To p._ 670. Vortices had already appeared in Kepler's and Descartes' ex-
planations; and Helmholz, too, had compared the dynamics of fluids with
electric currents and magnetic fields; but Maxwell's electro-hydro-dynamics
were of an incomparably more refined order.
APPENDIX I
Top. 671. Maxwell himself was less dogmatic about it. 'For the sake of
persons of different types of mind, scientific truth should be presented in different
forms and should be regarded as equally scientific whether it appears in the
robust form. and vivid colouring of a physical illustration or in the tenuity and
paleness of a symbolical expression.'
APPENDIX II: SOME FEA,TURES OF
GENIUS
I
n one of his essays-The Cutting of an Agate-William Butler
Yeats voiced one of the silliestpopular fallaciesof our times:
Aristotle on Motivation
After the long dark interlude which came to an end with the Pytha-
gorean Renaissance in Italy around A.D. 1500, four men stand high-
lighted on the stage of history: Copernicus, Tycho, Galileo, Kepler.
They were the pioneers of the Scientific Revolution, the men on whose
shoulders Newton stood: what do we know about their personal
motives-which ultimately changed the face of th.is planet?
We know least about Copernicus (1473-1543); as a person, he
seems to have been a pale, insignificant figure, a timid Canon in the
God-forsaken Prussian province of Varmia; his main ambition, as far
as one can tell, was· to be left alone and not to incur derision or dis-
favour. As a student in Italy, he had become acquainted with the
Pythagorean idea of a sun-centred universe, and for the next thirty
or forty years he elaborated his system in secret. Only in the last year
before his death, at the age of seventy, did he agree, under pressure of
his friends and superiors, to publish it; the first printed copy of his
book On the Revolutions of the Heavenly Spheres reached him on the
day of his death. It is one of the dreariest and. most unreadable books
that made history, and remained practically unnoticed for the next
fifty years, until Kepler took the idea up (the Church turned against
it only eighty years after Copernicus's death).
Copernicus was neither an original nor even a progressive thinker;
he was, as Kepler later remarked, 'interpreting Ptolemy rather than
nature'. He clung fanatically to the Aristotelian dogma that all planets
must move in perfect circles at uniform speeds; the first impulse of his
long labours originated in his discontent with the fact that in the
Ptolemaic system they moved in perfect circles but not at uniform
speed. It was the grievance of a perfectionist-in keeping with his
crabbed, secretive, stingy character (which every Freudian would
gleefully identify as the perfect 'anal' type). Once he had taken the
Ptolemaic clockwork to pieces, he began to search for a useful hint
how to put it together again; he found it in Aristarchus's heliocentric
idea which at that time was much in the air.* It was not so much a
new departure as a last attempt to patch up an outdated machinery
by reversing the arrangement of its wheels. As a modem historian has
said, the fact that the earth moves is 'almost an incidental matter in the
system of Copernicus which. viewed geometrically, is just the old
Ptolemaic pattern of the skies, with one or two wheels interchanged
and one or two of them taken out.''
677
THB ACT OF CltEATION
sprout, grow up, and bring forth goodly leaves, fragrant flowers,
and delicate fruit.... These men who so extol inconuptibility,
inalterabiliry,etc., speak thus, I believe, out of the great desire they
have to live long and for fear of death, not considering that, if men
had been immortal, they would not have had to come into the
world. These people deserve to meet with a Medusa's head that
would transform them into statues of diamond and jade that so
they might become more perfect than they are.lo
Once upon a time, in a very lonely place, there lived a man en-
dowed by nature with extraordinary curiosity and a very pene-
trating mind. For a pastime he raised birds, whose songs he much
enjoyed; and he observed with great admiration the happy contri-
vance by which they could transform at will the very air they
breathed into a variety of sweet songs.
One night this man chanced to hear a delicate song close to his
house, and being unable to connect it with anything but some small
bird he set out to capture it. When he arrived at a road he found a.
shepheredboy who was blowing into a kind of hollow stick while
moving his fingers about on the wood, thus drawing from it a
variety of notes similarto those of a bird, though by a quite different
method. Puzzled, but impelled by his natural curiosity, he gave the
boy a calf in exchange for this flute and returned to solitude. But
realizingthat if he had not chancedto meet the boy he would never
have learned of the existenceof a new method of forming musical
notes and the sweetest songs, he decided to travel to distant places
in the hope of meeting with some new adventure.
Well, after this man had come to believe that no more ways of
forming tones could possiblyexist ... when, I say, this man believed
he had seen everything, he suddenly found himself once more
plunged deeper into ignorance and bafflementthan ever. For having
captured in his hands a cicada,he failed to diminishits strident noise
either by closing its mouth or stopping its win.gs, yet he could not
see it move the scales that covered its body, or any other thing. At
last he lifted up the armour of its chest and there he saw some thin
hard ligaments beneath; thinking the sound might come from their
vibration, he decided to break them in order to silence it. But
nothing happened until his need.le drove too deep, and transfixing
the creature he took away its life with its voice, so that he was still
unable to determine whether the song had originated in those liga-
ments. And by this experience his knowledge was reduced to
diffidence,so that when asked how sounds were created he used to
answer tolerantly that although he knew a few ways, he was sure
that many more existed which were not only unknown but un-
Imaginable.P
Here we have the perfect union of the two drives: the vain-glorious
ego purged by cosmic awareness-ekstasis followed by katharsis.
From the end of the seventeenth century onward the scene becomes
too crowded for a systematic inquiry into individual motivations;
however, I have said enough to suggest the basic pattern-s-and though
the character of the times changed, that pattern remained essentially
the same.
Look at Newton, for instance: he has been idolized and his character
.APPENDIX II 685
bowdlerized to such an extent (above all in the Victorian standard
biography by Brewster) that the phenomenal mixture of monster and
saint out of which it was compounded was all but lost from sight. On
the one hand he was deeply religious and believed-with Kepler and
Bishop Usher-that the world had been created in 404 B.C.; that the
convenient design of the solar system-for instance, all planetary orbits
lying in a single plane-was proof of the existence of God, who not
only created the universe but also kept it in order by correcting from
time to time the irregularities which crept into the heavenly motions
-and by preventing the universe from collapsing altogether under the
pressure of gravity. On the other hand, he fulminated at any criticism
of his work, whether justified or not, displayed symptoms of persecu-
tion mania, and in his priority fight with Leibniz over the invention
of the calculus he used the perfidious means of carefully drafting in his
own hand the findings, in his own favour, of the 'impartial' committee
set up by the Royal Society. To quote M. Hoskin:
The Body
Of
BENJAMIN PRANK LIN
Printer
(Likethe Cover of an Old Book
Its Contents Tom Out
And Stript of its Lettering and Gilding)
Lies Here, Food for Worms.
But the Work ShallNot Be Lost
For It Will (As He Believed)Appear Once More
In a New and More Elegant Edition
Revisedand Corrected
By
The Author
His conviction that souls are immortal, that they cannot be des-
troyed and are merely transformed in their migrations led him, by
way of analogy, to one of the first clearformulationsof the law of the
conservation of matter, The following quotations will make the
connectionclear:
APPENDIX II
The argument seemsto indicate that what one might call the prin-
ciple of the 'conservation of souls' was derived from that of the 'con-
servation of matter'. But in fact it was the other way round. As
Kepler had transformed the Holy Trinity into the trinity of Sun-
Force-Planets, so in Franklin's case, too, a mystical conviction gave
birth, by analogy, to a scientifictheory. And could there be a more
charming combination of man's vanity with his transcendental
aspirations than to pray for a 'more elegant, revised, and corrected
edition' of one's proud and humble self?
human outlets except religion and science. This was probably the cause
of the protracted episode of mental disorder, comparable to Newton's,
which began when he was forty-nine. Characteristic of the coyness of
science historians is the Encyclopaedia Britannica's reference to Faraday's
clinical insanity: 'In 1841 he found that he required rest, and it
was not till 1845 that he entered on his second great period of
research.'
At thirty, shortly after his marriage-which remained childless-
Faraday joined an extreme fundamentalist, ascetic sect, the 'Sande-
ma.nia.ns', to which his father and his young wife belonged, and
whose services he had attended since infancy. The Sandemanians con-
sidered practically every human activity as a sin-including even the
Victorian virtue of saving money; they washed each other's feet,
intermarried, and refused to proselytize; on one occasion they sus-
pended Faraday's membership because he had to dine, by royal
command, with the Queen at Windsor, and thus had to miss the con-
gregation's Sunday service. It took many years before he was forgiven
and re-elected an Elder of the sect.
In his later years Faraday with.drew almost completely from social
contacts, refusing even the presidency of the Royal Academy because
of its too worldly disposition. The inhuman se1f-denials imposed by
his creed made Faraday canalize his ferocious vitality into the pursuit of
science, which he regarded as the only other permissible form of
divine worship.
his views on sociology and religion were antique, they were superior
to those of nearly all his scientific, contemporaries. He at least thought
about these problems, and if he was unable to find modem answers
to them, he learned enough of them to avoid the intellectual phili-
stinism of his time.'
It was the time when Berthelot proclaimed: 'The world today has
no longer any mystery for us'; when Haeckel had solved all his
Weltriitsel and A. R. Wallace, in his book on The Wonderful Century,
declared that the nineteenth century had produced 'twenty-four
fundamental advances, as against only fifteen for all the rest of recorded
history'. The Philistines everywhere were 'dizzy with success'-to
quote once more Stalin's famous phrase of r932, when factories and
power dams were going up at great speed while some seven million
peasants were dying of starvation. It had indeed been a wonderful
century for natural philosophy, but a.t its end moral philosophy had
reached one of its lowest ebbs in history-and Maxwell was well
aware of this. He was aware of the limitations of a rigidly deterministic
outlook; it was he who, in his revolutionary treatment of the dy-
namics of gases, replaced mechanical causation by a statistical approach
based on the theory of probability-a decisive step towards quantum
physics and the principle of indeterminism. Moreover, he was fully
aware of the far-reaching implications of this approach, not only for
physics but also for philosophy: 'It is probable that important results
will be obtained by the application of this the statistical method, which
is as yet little known and is not familiar to our minds. If the actual
history of Science had been different, and if the scientific doctrines
most familiar to us had been those which must be expressed in this
way, it is possible that we might have considered the existence of a
certain kind of contingency a self-evident truth, and treated the
doctrine of philosophical necessity as a mere sophism.'15
Already at the age of twenty-four he had realized the limitations of
materialist philosophy: 'The only laws of matter are those which our
minds must fabricate, and the only laws of mind are fabricated for it
by matter.'16 Twenty years later, at the height of his fame, he gave full
rein to his hobby, satirical verse, to ridicule the shallow materialism
of the Philistines. The occasion was the famous presidential address by
John Tyndall to the British Association meeting in Belfast. Tyndall,
a generous soul but a narrow-minded philosopher, attacked the
'theologians' and extolled the virtues of the brave new materialist
creed. Ma.-v:well's satire is still valid today:
APPENDIX II ()9I
In the very beginning of science,
the parsons, who managed things then,
Being handy with hammer and chisel,
made gods in the likeness of men;
Till Commerce arose, and at length
some men of exceptional power
Supplanted both demons and gods by
the atoms, which last to this hour.
Dr. Robert Darwin was an atheist who chose for his son Charles the
career of a country clergyman-simply because this seemed to be the
most gentlemanly occupation for a youth so obviously devoid of any
particular ambition and intellectual excellence. Charles himself fully
agreed with this choice. As a student at Cambridge he had read Pearson
on the Creeds, and had come to the conclusion that he did not 'in the
least doubt the strict and literal truth of every word in the Bible'.17
Even during the voyage of the Beagle he amused the officers by his
naive orthodoxy, and he was deeply shocked when one of his ship-
mates expressed doubts concerning the biblical account of the Flood.
Such a rigid fundamentalist belief could not be reconciled with specu-
lations about the origin of species; his loss of faith coincided with his
conversion to the evolutionary theory. For a while he fought a rear-
guard action against his doubts by day-dreaming about the discovery
of old manuscript texts which would confirm the historical truth of
the Gospels; but this did not help much. In the months following his
return from the voyage the new theory was born and his faith in
religion was dead.
Darwin's arguments against religion were as crude and literal-
minded as his belief had been: 'the miracles were not credible to any
sane man'; the Old Testament gave a 'manifestly false history of the
world, with the· Tower of Babe1, the rainbow as a sign, etc., etc.'18
He took strong exception to the 'damnable doctrine' that non-believers,
'and this would include my Father, Brother and almost all my best
friends', will be everlastingly punished. As for Hinduism or Buddhism,
and the persistence of religious aspirations throughout human history,
he explained them-in an oddly Lamarckian argument-as the result
of 'inherited experience'.
beliefin God, as for a monkey to throw off its instinctive fear and
hatred of a snake.
Before the great turning point in his life, 'the nuclear discovery' of
his theory, he had not only been an orthodox believer, but at least on
one occasion, in the grandeur of the Brazilian forest, he had also fdt
that quasi-mystical, 'deep inward experience' that there must be more
in man than 'the mere breath of his body.'19 But after the turning
point such experiences did not recur-and he himself wondered some-
times whether he was not like a man who had become colour-blind.
At the same decisive period, when he was about thirty, Darwin suffered,
inhis own words, a 'curious and lamentable loss of the higher aesthetic
tastes'. An attempt to re-read Shakespeare bored him 'to the point of
physical nausea'. 20 He preferred popular novels of the sentimental
kind-so long as they had a happy ending. In his autobiography he
complained:
But now for many years I cannot endure to read a line of poetry.
My mind seems to have become a kind of machine for grinding
general laws out of a large collection of facts, but why this should
have caused the atrophy of that part of the brain on which the higher
tastes depend, I cannot conceive. The loss of these tastes is a loss of
happiness, and may possibly be injurious to the intellect, and more
probably to the moral character, by enfeebling the emotional part
of our ?iature.
Man m.a.y be excused for feeling some pride at having risen, though
not through his own exertions, to the very summit of the organic
scale; and the fact of his having thus risen, instead of having been
aboriginally placed there, may give him hope for a still higher
destiny in the distant future. But we are not here concerned with
hopes or fears, only with the truth as far as our reason permits us to
discover it; and I have given the evidence to the best of my ability.
We must, however, acknowledge, as it seems to me, that man with
all his noble qualities, with sympathy which feels for the most
debased, with benevolence which extends not only to other men but
to the humblest living creature, with his god-like intellect which has
penetrated into the movements and constitution of the solar system
-with all these exalted powers-Man still bears in his bodily frame
the indelible stamp of his lowly origin.23
For the next two pages M. Boillot is shown what's what. He has to
taste the treated and untreated wines of a score of vintages and vine
yards, until he capitulates and admits the superior quality of the
698 THB ACT OF CREATION
At the age of forty-six Pasteur suffered a stroke which left his left
arm and leg permanently paralysed. Yet his greatest work was done
during the following two decades, when he was an invalid and had to
use his assistants' hands to carry out his experiments. In old age he
would often browse in his earlier publications. 'Turning the pages of
his writings, he would marvel at the lands that he had revealed by dis
pelling the fogs of ignorance and by overcoming stubbornness. He
would live again his exciting voyages, as he told Loir ina dreamy voice:
"How beau~ how beautiful! And to~ I did it all. I had forgotten
it." 't'1
2. INNOCENCE AND EXPERIENCE
Precociousness
In the first place, such data as we possess confirm the popular belief
that scientists reach their peak of creativity at an earlier age than
artists. Most scientists made their basic discoveries when they were
under forty-exceptions like Faraday or Pasteur always granted. In a
valuable study on Nobel Prize winners by L. Moulin2S we £nd the
average ~ge at which a person is awarded the prize to be fifty-one; but
for physicists it is forty-five. (The award. of course, often lags by a
number of years behind the discovery.) It is interesting to note that
the stupendous increase, over the last half-century, in the volume of
knowledge to be mastered had no significant influence on the age
at which the award is received: between 1901 and 1930 the average,
for physicists, was forty-five years, between 193 I and 1900, forty-six
years. The average for chemists was fifty years for the first, fifty-one
for the second period; for the award-winner in medicine it fell from
fifty-five in the fust, to fifty-three in the second period-presumably
as an effect of increasing team-work. The figures also indicate an agc-
gradient from the more 'theoretical' to the more 'empirical' or' applied'
sciences. This is in keeping with the well-known fact of the pre-
cociousness of mathematicians-the most 'theoretical' among scien-
tists (unfortunately there is no Nobel Prize for mathematics).
A related phenomenon is the dazzling multitude of infant prodigies
among scientists: for every Mozart there are about three Pascals,
Maxwclls, Edisons. To quote only a few examples: the greatest
703
THE ACT OF CREATION
The reasons for this peculiarity have already been discussed: scepticism
towards the conventional answers, the refusal to take anything for
granted, the freshness of vision of the unblinkered mind. Taken
together, tbcsc create an.acuity af perception,. a. gut.for seeing the banal
706 THE ACT OF CREATION
Multiple Potentials
NOTE
Top. 677. The Artistarchian system and the motion of the earth had been
discussed or taught by Copernicus's forerunners, the astronomers Peurba.ch and
Regiomontanus, by his teachers Brujewski and Novara, and by his colleagues
at the University of Bologna, Calcagnini, Ziegler, etc. (cf. The Sleepwalkers
pp. 205-10).
REFERENCES
BOOK ONE
B. Verbal Creation
XV. ILLUSION
I, Compressed from The Obsm,er, London, 2.12.1962. 2, Uvy-Bruhl (1926),
p. 76. 3, Ibid., p. 385. 4, Fitzmaurice Kelly,]., article on 'Literature' in Ene. Brit.,
13th ed.
XVII, IMAGE
I, Sachs, H. (1946). 2, (1925), p. 270 ff. 3, Kretschmer (1934).
XVIII. INPOI.DlNG
I, W/rdtis Art? 2, Richards, I. A. (1924), l, Cohen,J. (1958}.
XIX. CHARACTER AND P:tOT
I, Memmt.o Mori. 2, Brandt, G. W., in Cassell's Ene. of Literature (1953), Vol. I.
P· 422. 3, (1910), pp. 25 seq.
712, THE ACT OF CREATION
BOOK TWO
Habit and Originality
INTRODUCTION
1,Jeffress, A., ed. (1951), p. n3.
I. PRE-NATAL SKILLS
1, Woodger (1929), p. 327. 2, Hyden (1900), p. 307. 2A, Hyden (1962).
3, Bertalanffy (1952), p. 134. 4, Scbrodinger (1944), p. 71. S, Cf. e.g. Buttin, G.
1962. 6, Fischberg, M. and Blackler. A. W. (1961). 7, Willier, Weiss, and
Hamburger (1955), p. 338. 8, Hamburger (1955A),p. 67. 9, Waddingtcm (1932).
quoted from Polanyi (1958), p. 356. 10, Weiss (1939), p. 290. II, Hamburger
(~955B),p. 978. 12, Brachet (1955), pp. 389 ff. 13, Hamburger, loc. cit. 14, Bert-
alanfty (1952), p. 47.
V. PRINCIPLES OP ORGANIZATION
I, Pribram {196o).
VIII. MOTIVATION
1, Mowrer, 0. H. (1952). 2, Freud (1920), pp. 3-5. 3, Hilgard (1958), p. 428.
4, Hebb (l949), pp. 178-80. 5, Cf. i.a., Zener (1957); Loucks (1935, 1938};
Hovland (1937); Hilgard and Marquis (1940); and for a concise summary Hebb
(1949), pp. 174-6. 6, For a review of the literature, cf. e.g. Pribram (1960).
7, Miller et al., op. cit., p. 30. 8, Pribram (196o), p. 3. 9, Skinner (1938), p. 9.
IO, Ibid., pp. 40. II, Miller et al., op. cit., p. 22. 12, Hilgard (1958), p. 105.
13, Hwnphreys, L. G. (1939). 14, Hull (195.2),p. 350. IS, Hilgard (1958), p. 177.
16, Berlyne, D. E. (196o), p. 225. 17, Allport, G.W. (1957). 18, Goldstein, K.
(1939). 19, C£ e.g.,Jencks B. and Potter, P. B.,]ournal of Psychology, Vol. 49,
THE ACT OF CREATION
p. r39. 20, Nissen, H. W. (r954). ar, Berlyne, op. cit., p. us . .22, Ibid., p. u6.
23, Ibid., p. r27. 24, Ibid., p. rr7. 25, Ibid., p. II7. 26, Ibid., P· II9. 27, Ibid.,
pp. r33-4. 28, Lorenz (1956). 29, Compressed from The DescentofMan (r913 ed.),
pp. 108-10; and The Expression of the Emotions (1872), p. 43. 30, Berlin, 1917;
London and New York 1925. 31, Berlyne, op. cit., p. 148. 32, Harlow et al. (1950).
33, Harlow (1953), p. 25. 34, Woodworth (1947), p. 123. 35, Berlyne, op. cit.,
p. 170. 36, Loe. cit. 37, Pavlov (1927). 38, Darchen, R. (1952, I954, and 1957),
quoted by Berlyne, op. cit., p. 104. 39, Thacker, L.A. (1950). 40, Thorpe (1956),
p. 9. 41, Ibid., p. 12. 42, Craik, K.J. W. (r943), p. 61. 43, Allport, G. W. (1955),
p. 67.
IX, PLAYING AND PRETENDING
r, Thorpe (1956). .2, Berlyne, op. cit., p. 5. 3, Thorpe (1956), p. 87. 4, Loe. cit.
5, Ibid. p. 355.
B. Physiology
MNOLD, M. B., Emotion and Personality, Vol. 2, Neurological and Physio-
logical Aspects, Cassell, London, 1960;
Weeping in thalamic disease, 12, r 3 ;
Weeping and eeg, 162.
CHOROBSKI, S., 'The Syndrome of Crocodile Tears', Arch. Neur. and Psy-
chiatry, 1951.
FORD, 'Paroxysmal lacrimation etc.', Arch. Neurol. Psychiat. Chicago, 29,
1933.
GEOFFREY WALSH, E., Physiology of the Nervous System, Longmans Green,
London, 1957.
Crocodile tears, 408.
Kl.ING, C., 'The Role of the Parasympathetic in Emotions', Psycho!. Rev.,
1933.
MUTCH, T. R., 'The lacrimation reflex', Brit.]. Ophthal. 28, 317-36, 1944,
ROWBOTHAM, G. F., 'Observations on the effect oftrigeminal denervation',
Brain, 62, 364-80, 1939.
WHITB,J. C. and SMITHWICK, R. H. et al (3rd ed.), The Autonomic Nervous
System, 40, 41, 250, 1952
C. Weeping and PersonalityDevelopment
Hum,J. Mc. V. (ed.), Personality and the Behaviour Disorders, Vol. 1, Ronald
Press, Chap. 3, Mowrer, 0. H., Dynamic theory of personality, 89, 1944.
Rtvmu!, Interntl. ]. of Psychoanal. 17, 395-422 (Psychological development
in infancy.) r936.
SULI.IVAN, H. S., Conceptions of Modem Psychiatry,Tavistock Pbns., London,
I5, I7, 89, I9:S3,
SYMONDS, P. M., Dynamic Psychology, Appleton Century Crofts, New York,
48, 280, 1949.
SYMONDS, P. M., The Ego and the Self, Appleton Century Crofts, New York,
13, 1951.
D. Ontogeneticsof Weeping
AM:es, L.B., 'Motor correlates of infant crying',]. Genet, Psychol., 59, 239-
47, 1941.
BAYLEY, N., 'A study of crying in infants etc!,]. Genet. Psychol, 40, 3o6-29,
1932.
BORGQUIST, A., 'Crying', Am.], of Psycl1ol., 19o6.
CLARICE, HUNT and HUNT,]. G,.,,. Psychol. 17, 398-402 {Weeping and startle
pattern.), 1917.
GOODENOUGH, F. L., Anger iti Young Children, 66-9, 244-9, 1931.
GOODENOUGH. F. L, ]. Abn. Soc. Psychol. 27, 328-33 (Weeping in blind and
deaf children.), 1932.
GQooENOUGK,F. L., DevelopmentalPsychology (znd ed.), Appleton Century.
201, 2S7; Individual differences, 273, 1945
11.BPBRENCES
The author and publishers wish to thank the following for permission to quote
from various works: Basic Books, Inc., New York (The Uneonscious Before
Freud, by L. L. Whyte); Doubleday & Co., Inc., New York (Pasteur and Modem
Science, by Rene Dubos, © I960, by Educational Services, Inc. (Anchor Science
Study Series), and Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution, by Gertrude Himmelfarb,
© 1959, 1962, by Gertrude Kristel); the Clarendon Press, Oxford (The Study of
Instina, by Dr. N. Tinbergen); John Wiley & Sons, Inc., New York (Cerebral
Mechanisms in Behaviour-The Hixon Symposium, ed. L. A.Jeffress); Little, Brown
& Co., Boston (Louis Pasteur, by Rene Dubas,© 1950, by Rene Dubos); George
Allen & Unwin, Ltd., London (Thinking, by Sir Frederick Bartlett); Europa
Verlag, Zurich (Albert Einstein, by Carl Seelig); Cambridge University Press,
New York (The Name and Nature of Poetry, by A. E. Housman); G. Bell, London
(Gestalt Psychology, by W. Kobler); Allyn & Bacon, Boston (Psychology, ed.
A. D. Calvin,© I96I, by Allyn & Bacon); Methuen & Co., London (Learning
and Instinct in Animals, by W. H. Thorpe); Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd., London
(Personal Knowledge, by Michael Polanyi, Mentality of Apes, by W. Kohler, Tht
Symbolic Process, by J. F. Markey, The Growth of Reason, by F. Lorimer, and
Invention and the Unconscious, by J.-M. Montmasson).
2A*
INDEX
Scanning Selection, 3 3 3
objects and mies of the process, I62 Selective emphasis, 397
visual and mental, 158 et seq. Self-amputation in animals, 451
Schelling, ISI Self-assertive tendencies, 255, 257, 259,
Schiller, F., 257, 3 IS 305
Schizophrenic symbols, 324 in humour, 52, 56, 57, 95
Schopenhauer, 36, 3S4 in organic hierarchy, 449
Schrodinger, Erwin, 245, 26.5 of part-behaviour, 468
Science sublimation of, 259
boredom of, 263-6 Self-awareness, degrees of. 633-5
boundaries of, 248-52 Self-pity as reason for weeping, 280
emotion and, 255 et seq. Self-transcendence, 303
fashions in, 246-8 voluntary, 294
history of, see Science, History of Self-transcending emotions, S4, 258, 263,
hypnotism and, 239 28s, 298, 305, 328
Law of Infolding and, 342-3 in weeping, 273-4
martyrology of, 239 subhmation of, 261
orthodoxy and, 238, 239 Semantic differentials, 644
progress towards universal laws, 352 Semon, R., 531
rehtionship with art, 27, 28 Sense of wonder, 674 et seq.
religion and, 261-2 Sensory granficaticn, ditference from
religious mysticism and, 26o-I aesthetic satisfaction, 385
'river-delta' pattern of progress, 352 Seurat, 174, 329
words as tools and traps for, I76 Sex-drive, 496
Science, history of, 224 et seq. Sexual tension, 496
controversies, 240 Shaftesbury, Earl of, 150
impact of religion and politics, 238, 239 Shakespeare, 148
neither continuous, nor cumulative, 253 Shaw, G. B., 47, 120
twenty-six centuries of, 227-8 Shelley, P. B., 32I
Science "ml Hum4n Beha11iour, 17, 556, SS7 Sherrington, Sir Charles, 28, 432, 498
Scientific evidence, 242 Sign-learning theory, 497
Scientific Revolution, 260 Simplification, 333
leaders of, 677-84 Skill
Scientists autonomous and automatic functioning,
abstraction and practicality, 705-6 550-1
and the in.finite, 26z-3 balancing, 548
bisociation and, 72 complex, assertive tendencies of, 552
catharsis of problems, 328 dual control in exercise of, 38
destruction of the self-evident, 176-7 hierarchic structure of complex, 288-9
discovery and, 190 (s« also Discovery} morphogenic, 41 S
intellectual characteristics of, 703-8 motor, S44 et seq.
irrationality in, 146 perceptual, 489 et seq.
motivational drive, 675 hearing, 513 et seq.
multiple potential, 7o6--8 prenatal, 4IS ct seq.
precociousness of, 703-4 vegetative, 415
religion and, 26o-3 Skinner, B. F., 157, 496, 499, soo, S56,
the Benevolent Magicians, 255-6 SS7, 559
the creative and his audience, 263-6 Skinner Box, 248
the Mad Professors, 256 Sleepwal/urs, The, II
the uninspired Pedant, 256-7 Smiling, facial changes in, 29
the White Magician, 257-8 Smithers, D. W., 456
visual imagery and,, I®'-73 Smoke micrographs, 389, 390
~cott, Sir W., 2u: Snobbery, the aesthetics of, 400 ct seq.
Screening activity in hearing, SI3 et seq. 'Snowblindness' of thinkers, 216-20
INDEX 749
Soccer, 552. Tanaed, 133
techniques of playing, 549 Taste, 385-7
Sound affiDity, association by, 314-15 Taton, R., 234
Souriau, 145 Technical communications, 265
Space and Time, 174-5 Telegraphy, 5SI
Speak, learmng to, 592 ct seq. learning processes in, 544-S
Spearman, C., 177 Telepathy, 188
Speech Tension, unplcasurable, 496 et seq.
action-words of children, 6o6-7 Thacker, L. A., 5o6
childhood aspects of, 594-6 Theophrastus, 664
concepts and labels in, 597-9 Theorizing, derivation of term, 26o
dawn of symbol consciousness, 594-6 Thinking
direct, in illusion, 3 IO abstraction of pre-verbal concepts,
ideation and verbahzation in, 6oo-3 6o7-10
memory and, 533-5 apphcation of the term 'code', 638
motor activity precedes sensory control, associanve, 635
594 causality, 615-18
preparation before, 592-3 concretization of relation between
verbal behaviour in, 593-4 words and things, 613-14
Spencer, Herbert, SS, 69, 432 dimensional variables, 630-1
Spider, code of rules in building web, 38 directive, 635
Spinoza, 650, 651 discrimination in, 610-u
Sponges, 451 explanation, nature of, _618
Spontaneous activities, 468 in pictures, 168, 322-s
S-R Theories, 561-2 logic, 625-9
Stamping-in, 521, 522, 549-.SO magical. 261
Steam engine, 102, 109 master-switches and releasers, 635-7
Stein, Gertrude, 433 mathematical, 39, 40, 621-5
Stickleback, reproductive behaviour of, 479 multi-dimensional, 63er2
Stimuli, 499 not a linear process, 1S9
Strategy, related to skill, 3 8 physiological aspect of, S7-8
Structural differentiation, .p6, 417 pictorial, 167, 168
Studies on the TelegraphicLanguage, 544 recognition and transfer, 6II-I3
Stutterers, bisociation of, 74 rules and codes, 637-41
Style, artistic, 334-5, 33~ single plane, 3S, 36
Style codes, 640-I some aspects of, 630 et seq
Sublimation, magic and, 258-63 steps m purposive, 163
Subliminal self, 164 underground, 178 ct seq.
Subsidiary awareness, IS9 verbal, 38-9, 43
Sullivan, Miss, 222 visual, 347-8
Sully,]., 29 Thinking-an experimentaland Social Study,
Super-ego, 65
quoted, 231
Suzuki, D. T., note on, 177
Thinking aside, I4S et seq., 182
Swift, Dean, 73, 252, 257
Thompson, d'Arcy, 466
Swinburne, 322
Sylvester II, 255 Thompson, J. ).. 671
Symbolism, concretization and, 182-6 Thompson, W.R. so2
Symbohst movement, 337 Thorndike, E. L., 495, 504, 557, 568, 569,
Sympathico-adrenal system, 57, 59, 62, 88, 570, 586
280, 305 Thorpe, W. H., 450, 477, 478, 483, 49I,
Sympathy as reason for weeping, 278-9 492, 493, .soo, .su, 548, s62, ses. s61
Syntheses, premature Thought
Keplerian cosmology, 215 abdication of conceptual, 170
things and numbers. :zxs hooked atoms of, 164-6
750 IND BX