Tony Honore-Responsibility and Fault (1999) - Ch2,5
Tony Honore-Responsibility and Fault (1999) - Ch2,5
Tony Honore-Responsibility and Fault (1999) - Ch2,5
2"
RESPONSIBILITY AND LUCK
THE MORAL BASIS OF STRICT LIABILITY
This essay1 touches on both civil and common law, but its central
theme is a very broad one: that being responsible in law and in ordi-
nary life is not the same thing as being at fault or to blame. It starts
from the well-known rule of the tort of negligence that requires
everyone to attain an objective standard of care and competence; and
then moves towards a theory of responsibility in which the contrast
between fault and strict liability, though not obliterated, is blunted.
The argument is in three sections. As it is a little complicated, I
summarise it at the start. The first section argues that the objective
standard of competence, though purporting to be based wholly on
fault, really imposes a form of strict liability on those who suffer from
unavoidable shortcomings. In the absence of a moral justification for
strict liability it cannot be supported.
To justify strict liability we must first show why people should
sometimes bear the risk of bad luck, including in bad luck such mis-
fortunes as being stupid or clumsy. The second section argues that to
bear the risk of bad luck is inherent in the basic form of responsibil-
ity in any society, which I term outcome responsibility. Outcome
responsibility means being responsible for the good and harm we
bring about by what we do. By allocating credit for the good out-
comes of actions and discredit for bad ones, society imposes outcome
responsibility; though often the rewards it attaches and, outside the
law, the sanctions it imposes are informal and vague. Under a system
of outcome responsibility we are forced, if we want to keep our social
account in balance, to make what amounts to a series of bets on our
choices and their outcomes. Provided we have a minimum capacity
1. A version of the 13th Blackstone lecture delivered in Oxford under the auspices of
Pembroke College on 8 May 1988. First published in 104 Law Quarterly Review
(1988) pp.530–53.
14
RESPONSIBILITY AND LUCK
for choosing and acting, we win the bets and get credit for good out-
comes more than we lose them and incur discredit for bad ones. We
have to take the risk of harmful outcomes that may be sheer bad luck
and not our fault; but that does not make the system unfair to people
who are likely to be winners overall.
Seen in this light civil liability in law, whether strict or based on
fault, can be defended on the ground that it specifies an extra sanc-
tion to be imposed on a person who has anyhow lost a bet and will in
consequence incur discredit. The main role of legal liability is to rein-
force our basic outcome responsibility with formal sanctions such as
compensation or punishment. One ground for legal liability, fault, is
present when the person’s conduct not only has a bad outcome but
displays a bad disposition. Another, which leads to strict liability, is
present when the activity that has a bad outcome is specially danger-
ous to others. In practice these grounds often overlap.
Can the system of outcome responsibility itself be justified or
shown to be inescapable? Outcome responsibility is, I contend,
inescapable because it is the counterpart and at the same time a con-
stituent of our personal identity and character. We could not dispense
with outcome responsibility without ceasing to be persons.
The third section deals with capacity and freedom. Outcome
responsibility, though inescapable, can fairly be imposed only on
those who possess a sufficient general capacity for decision and
action. Capacity can for this purpose be tested by asking what a given
person normally achieves when he tries. It has, however, often been
thought that responsibility for a particular action requires something
further; a capacity on the part of the person to have acted differently
given all the factors, external and internal, that were present on the
occasion in question. But this sort of anti-deterministic capacity can-
not exist. So my theory of responsibility, though it does not require
determinism to be true, is compatible with it. The difference between
fault and strict liability in this respect is merely that a person guilty of
fault must have, besides a general capacity for decision and action, the
ability to succeed most of the time in doing the sort of thing that
would on this occasion have averted the harm. A person held strictly
liable must have the same general capacity but need not have this spe-
cial ability.
15
RESPONSIBILITY AND FAULT
The starting point of the argument is one that at first sight has noth-
ing to do with strict liability. It is the familiar rule of the law of neg-
ligence that everyone is bound to reach an objective standard of care
and competence. One corollary is that a person is liable for sub-
standard conduct, or is prejudiced by it, even if he acts as he does
because of a shortcoming that he cannot help. A stupid lorry-driver
fails to slow down in the fog and has an accident. One of normal
intelligence would have slowed down and avoided it. An impetuous
pedestrian dashes across the street and is run over. A more equable
person would have waited and walked across safely. An inexperienced
surgeon cuts an artery that with greater experience he would have
known how to avoid. In view of the objective theory of negligence,
their respective shortcomings (stupidity, impetuousness, perhaps also
inexperience) make them legally liable or reduce their claims.2
Some explanation of the terms employed may be useful.
“Negligence” refers to civil liability, in whatever system, for unin-
tended harm, where this is caused by someone’s failure to meet the
required standard of competence. The liability may be in tort or
delict, for breach of contract, under a special statute or under more
than one of these at once. Negligence, the common law term, is here
used in a transsystematic way, as equivalent to Roman culpa, German
Fahrlässigkeit, and French faute de négligence. Lack of competence
may stem from a number of factors. The person concerned, for
whom the term “shortcomer” is to hand, may not have the qualities,
physical, intellectual or emotional, needed to attain the standard set
for the task in question. He may lack the proper makeup. He may
suffer from a defect of character, temperament or physique, limited
intelligence, accident proneness, bad co-ordination, slow reactions.
On the other hand he may possess the physical and mental equip-
ment but lack education or training. Or he may have had all these
but, as a child, lack maturity, or, as a novice, experience. The short-
comer’s lack of competence may thus stem from a defect of physique
2. For inexperience the issue is debated: Nettleship v. Weston [1971] 2 QB 691; Wilsher
v. Essex Health Authority [1987] QB 730.
16
RESPONSIBILITY AND LUCK
3. E.g. F.V. Harper, F.I. James and O.S. Gray, The Law of Torts (2nd ed. 1986) vol. III
p.103f.; A. Weill and F. Terré, Droit Civil des Obligations (4th ed. 1986) s.628;
E. Deutsch, Haftungsrecht: Allgemeine Lehre (1976) p.268f. In Germany the objective
theory is statutory. BGB s.276 lays down that a person subject to a duty acts negli-
gently is he fails to take account of the care required by (social) intercourse: die im
Verkehr erforderliche Sorgfalt ausser acht lässt.
4. As French lawyers put it.
5. The German formulation.
6. Viz. an ordinary air pilot, not a pilot “having the same training and experience as Fred
Heath”: Heath v. Swift Wings Inc. 40 NC App. 158, 252 SE 2d 526, 529 (1979).
7. This is the answer to Nipperdey’s objection that the class selected might equally be that
of the phlegmatic, cholerics, alcoholics, etc. Staudinger, BGB s.276 no.18. The class
test is not alien to English law: The Lady Gwendolen [1965] P. 294 (reasonable
shipowner); Philips v. Whiteley [1938] 1 All ER 566 (reasonable jeweller); Wilsher v.
Essex Health Authority [1987] QB 730 (duty of doctor relates to post which he occu-
pies, not his own qualifications and experience).
8. Some have argued that the incapable should, in protecting themselves, be judged by a
more subjective standard (Harper, James and Gray, above n.3, vol. III pp.462–4);
H.H. Terry, 29 Harvard Law Rev. (1914–5) 47; Dellwo v. Pearson 259 Minn. 452,
107 NW 2d 859, 862–3 (1961), rejected in Dunn v. Teti 280 Pa. Super 399, 421 Atl.
2d 782, 784 (1980).
17
RESPONSIBILITY AND FAULT
9. Some cases allow mental subnormality to reduce the standard expected: e.g. Miller v.
Trinity Medical Center 260 NW 2d 4, 6–7 (1977).
10. Elderly plaintiff: e.g. Johnson v. St Paul City R Co 67 Minn. 260, 69 NW 900,901
(1897).
11. E.g. because he is confronted with a situation that is not of his choosing, like a fire
which through no fault of his breaks out on his land: Goldman v. Hargrave [1967] 1
AC 645. This duty to do what you can (eigenmögliche Sorgfalt: Deutsch, above n.3,
at p.280), which in German law applies to matters such as the award of a solatium
for death, injury or loss of liberty (BGB s.847 Schmerzengeld) is to be distinguished
from the degree of care which the agent, who may have fallen into a slack routine,
normally gives to his own affairs (below n.12).
12. The civil law diligentia quam in suis rebus, which applied to transactions like gratu-
itous deposit, where it seemed unreasonable to demand that the depositee should take
greater care of his friend’s property than his own. BGB s.277 and commentaries pro-
vide modern examples.
13. E.g. A.J. Ayer, Philosophical Essays (1954) p.27.
14. Below pp.32–8.
18
RESPONSIBILITY AND LUCK
15. Harper, James and Gray, above n.3, vol. III p.104; H. and L. Mazeaud and A. Tunc,
Responsabilité Civile (6th ed. 1965) vol. I ss.418f, distinguish social and moral from
legal fault, the latter including cases that I would regard as coming within strict lia-
bility, since the mark of fault is that it reflects adversely on the character or disposi-
tion of the agent.
16. There are of course those who deny that to treat the guilty as means in this way is
morally permissible, or who advance (unconvincing) arguments to the effect that
punishment does not involve this.
19
RESPONSIBILITY AND FAULT
know his driving very well, find it almost impossible to fix the stan-
dard of which a particular motorist is capable.
It is true that the objective standard makes proof easier and so saves
trouble and cost. In applying any normative standard it is convenient
to be guided by conventional practices, though these are clearly not
immune from criticism. Practice may be slack, as in the case of those
pilots who allegedly navigate car ferries without verifying that the
doors are closed. But often practice serves to settle, at least provision-
ally, the content of the objective standard.17
The difficulty of proof has some weight in support of the objective
standard, but by itself hardly provides a compelling reason for it.
Moreover, in criminal law the difficulty of proving intention, often
considerable, does not let in proof of a standard or model intention
instead of the actual intention of the defendant.
Another argument for objective liability is that any unfairness there
may be in holding the shortcomer to an objective standard is minor
in extent. Civil liability is often covered by third-party insurance, for
example, motor insurance. A person who is insured suffers less than
if he had to pay from his own pocket. So, it is said, in these cases the
objective standard does not impose much hardship. But the objective
standard existed in the ancient world and continued in force for
many centuries before third-party insurance became a widespread,
though certainly not universal, practice. Has the justification for it
sprung into being in the industrial age? Moreover, the insurance argu-
ment, which applies only to those walks of life in which insurance is
the standard or required practice, merely displaces the question. Why
should a person who commits no fault be burdened with insurance
premiums?
The various consequentialist arguments of social and legal policy
so far adduced seem not to provide an adequate reason for imposing
objective liability in the absence of a moral justification of a non-con-
sequentialist sort. The arguments they provide are supplementary
rather than basic. What is in issue is the justice of objective liability,
not merely its expediency. Is it fair to the individuals concerned to
hold them responsible for their shortcomings? The good conse-
quences may be necessary, but hardly sufficient reasons for doing so.
17. For a similar point in regard to the standard for children, see the good discussion in
Tyler v. Weed 285 Mich. 460, 280 NW 827 (1938).
20
RESPONSIBILITY AND LUCK
not fault but bad luck, which in this context includes, besides ordi-
nary accidents, the bad luck of being saddled with shortcomings.25
The objective standard of liability in negligence has a like dual effect.
Often it merely makes it easy to prove negligence on the part of some-
one who is in fact at fault. But sometimes it penalizes the bad luck of
those who suffer from shortcomings. The principle involved in
imposing ordinary strict liability, say for storing explosives, and in
applying the objective standard of negligence is at bottom the same.
Most of those held liable will be at fault but a minority will not. Thus
in Britain a motorist who has an accident because, though he scraped
through the test, he is too clumsy or stupid to drive properly can suf-
fer, directly or through his insurer, for his bad luck. So under a dif-
ferent legal theory can his opposite number in France or Germany
who is held liable for a road accident even though no fault on his part
can be proved.
Holmes, in a classic passage of The Common Law, points to this
combination of bad luck and blame. He says,
“If a man is born hasty and awkward, is always having accidents and hurt-
ing himself or his neighbours, no doubt his congenital defects will be
allowed for in the courts of Heaven, but his slips are no less troublesome
to his neighbours than if they sprang from guilty neglect.”
Hence
“the law considers . . . what would be blameworthy in the average man,
the man of ordinary intelligence and prudence, and determines liability
by that. If we fall below the level in those gifts, it is our misfortune.”
Holmes gives no morally convincing reason for holding the acci-
dent-prone man liable for his bad luck. The member of the awkward
squad is not to blame for his defect. In the courts of Heaven, accord-
ingly, he goes scot-free, but on earth his neighbours insist that he be
held liable. True, but by what right? It is certainly bad luck to fall
below a decent level in the gifts needed for social intercourse, but why
should this misfortune entail legal liability?
Any principle that can justify responsibility for bad luck must be
fair. If it is to be fair, it must entail that when we bear the risk of bad
luck we also benefit if our luck is good. Allocation according to luck
25. Including “faults” of character and other shortcomings, which, viewed from a certain
point of view, are the outcome of a cosmic lottery.
24
RESPONSIBILITY AND LUCK
must cut both ways. So the system will be fair only if there are situa-
tions in which we implicitly bet on the outcomes of our actions.
Do such situations exist? Imagine that when we reach a decision to
do X rather than Y – let us say to attempt a U-turn rather than to go
on to the next roundabout – we are choosing to put our money on X
and its outcome rather than Y and its outcome. When we opt for the
U-turn rather than the roundabout, we implicitly bet that we will get
to our destination quicker by making the U-turn. Our decision for
U-turn rather than roundabout will be like a decision to put money
on L’Escargot rather than Red Rum to win the Grand National. But
we will not be like ordinary punters but rather jockeys who, contrary
to existing practice, are allowed to back a horse and ride on it so that
they can influence the result of their bet. Thus, when we choose X
(say the U-turn), the bet we make is to be analysed as follows. We bet
we can do X (the U-turn) and that X will have the more favourable
outcome (getting there quicker). In calculating the odds for achiev-
ing the favourable outcome we have to discount the chance that we
may not be able to do X or that the outcome of X, if we do it, will not
be what we predict. Thus, we may not manage the U-turn; we may
instead cause an accident. Or, we may manage it but find we were
misinformed about the route, so that it would have been quicker to
go on to the roundabout anyhow.
One difference between an implicit bet on outcomes and an ordi-
nary wager concerns the stake and the winnings. In an ordinary bet
we know the amount of the stake and often the potential winnings in
advance. In implicit bets on the outcome of our actions, on the other
hand, we do not precisely know the stake and winnings in advance;
only that they will be proportionate to the outcome. The terms of the
bets we make with other members of our community (and indirectly
with ourselves) when we choose X rather than Y is that if we succeed
and have guessed the outcome right we receive credit for it. If we
manage the U-turn and get to our destination quicker we get credit
for that success. But if we botch it, have an accident, or mistake the
route, that is chalked up against us. This remains true even if the
botch or miscalculation is not our fault, though of course it generally
is. How much responsibility in terms of credit or debit accrues to us
– how big the stake and winnings are – depends on how important
the successful or botched outcome is in the eyes of others. We cannot
tell the precise amounts in advance, but usually have a rough idea
25
RESPONSIBILITY AND FAULT
what they are likely to be. But whether the outcome is foreseeable or
not, we can of course easily miscalculate. Despite the uncertainties,
over a span of time more outcomes are likely to redound to our credit
than to our debit, so that we are not permanently saddled with a los-
ing ticket. Risk and benefit go hand in hand. Ubi emolumentum ibi
onus.26
The betting system that I have outlined seems to me to correspond
to our experience of everyday life. Our actions impinge on others,
who resent it if the effects on them are harmful. So we are, unless
indifferent to the reaction of others, forced to gamble in order to
acquire credit and esteem and avoid exposure to discredit and resent-
ment. Even by opting for inaction we cannot avoid putting out
money on the table, because, as members of a community, we know
that we will be held responsible for whatever good or ill we cause,
including whatever harm our inaction produces in those cases where
omissions count as causes. To choose and execute a course of conduct
is to bet on your skill and judgement of the probabilities. Choosing
is inescapably betting.
If this suggestion is correct, we live under a system by which a com-
munity allocates responsibility according to outcomes, and we are
consequently forced to make bets on those outcomes. It is, I believe,
no exaggeration to say that this dual system colours, often uncon-
sciously, everything we do. Not only are actions and outcomes con-
ventionally allocated to people but we and others are entitled to insist
that they should be so allocated. Any moral or legal theory must
therefore be condemned as inadequate unless it justifies the allocation
of responsibility according to outcomes or shows that the system rests
on a mistake.
Given certain conditions outcome allocation can be defended as fair.
The necessary conditions are that the system must in its operation be
impartial, reciprocal and over a period, beneficial. It must apply impar-
tially to all those who possess a minimum capacity for reasoned choice
and action. It must be reciprocal in that each such person is entitled to
apply it to others and they to him. It must work so as to entitle each
person to potential benefits that are likely on the whole to outweigh the
detriments to which it subjects him. This makes it unfair to apply the
system to the incapable, for whom there is no likely surplus of benefit
over detriment. But for the capable the three conditions are normally
satisfied. All those who possess a minimum capacity stand to profit
from the system of outcome allocation most of the time and, if there is
a minority of permanent losers, they teeter on the edge of incapacity.27
The system of outcome allocation and outcome responsibility,
which it entails, can therefore in certain conditions be defended as
fair. Outcome responsibility automatically settles the bets made by
people who by choosing a course of action implicitly put their money
on the result. In any event outcome responsibility is, I contend, the
basic type of responsibility in a community: more fundamental than
either moral responsibility as generally understood, which requires
fault, or legal responsibility, which requires either fault or special
danger.
The analogy with a form of gambling in which we mostly win but
sometime lose helps to explain and in part to justify not merely out-
come responsibility but strict liability. In certain areas of life where
there is a special risk that what we do will have a harmful outcome,
society insists on pressing our responsibility for outcomes to its lim-
its. Our fellow citizens insist that we pay up in terms of compensa-
tion rather than just apologise or ring for the ambulance or comfort
the injured.
The justification of strict liability therefore depends in part on the
fairness of outcome responsibility. Strict liability is one species of
enhanced responsibility for outcomes. This does not entail that
whenever a harmful outcome is properly allocated to someone, this
justifies imposing on him a strict liability to compensate for that out-
come. Contrary to what Epstein28 and possibly Fletcher29 at times
seem to suggest, responsibility for a harmful outcome should not
automatically involve a legal duty to compensate. An extra element is
needed to ground the legal sanction. Sometimes the extra element is
fault. Fault discloses a hostile or uncooperative disposition on the
part of the harm doer, who either positively intends harm or disre-
gards a known risk of it. For strict liability, the extra element is usu-
ally that the conduct of the harm doer carries with it a special risk of
harm of the sort that has in fact come about. In that event, a conse-
27. We need to rethink the way in which to apply notions of responsibility to them, tak-
ing due account of their need to be seen as genuine persons.
28. R. Epstein, “A theory of strict liability”: 2 Journal of Legal Studies (1973) 151.
29. G.P. Fletcher, “Fairness and utility in tort theory”, 85 Harvard Law Rev. (1972) 537.
27
RESPONSIBILITY AND FAULT
Strict liability and fault liability run parallel in this respect. Those
who do not understand outcome allocation and the difference
between right and wrong (or lawful and unlawful) are generally held
incapable of fault, but in order to be guilty of fault they need not
know that a particular action is wrongful. On this analysis, virtually
everyone who possesses the general capacity needed for outcome
responsibility also possesses the capacity to be legally responsible both
on the basis of fault and strict liability.
A further point that bears on the fairness of outcome allocation,
and so of strict liability, is that neither is something that the person
subject to them has chosen. Does that make these institutions
morally dubious? We have never made a social contract providing for
outcome allocation, still less for strict liability. They bind us willy-
nilly.
It is true that we have no choice in the matter. But outcome allo-
cation can be defended on grounds deeper than the overall balance of
benefit over burden; and so, in its wake, can strict liability. For out-
come allocation is crucial to our identity as persons; and, unless we
were persons who possessed an identity, the question of whether it
was fair to subject us to responsibility could not arise. If actions and
outcomes were not ascribed to us on the basis of our bodily move-
ments and their mental accompaniments, we could have no continu-
ing history or character.30 There would indeed be bodies and,
associated with them, minds. Each would posses a certain continuity.
They could be labelled A, B, C. But having decided nothing and
done nothing these entities would hardly be people.
In the real world, fortunately, human bodily movements and their
mental accompaniments are with some exceptions interpreted as
actions and decisions. They are ascribed to authors, who accordingly
count as persons; and it is by virtue of these ascriptions that each of
us has a history, an identity and a character. But there is a price to be
paid for being a person. As the counterpart of this status we are
responsible for our actions and their consequences, and sometimes
this responsibility exposes us to legal sanctions. To ascribe person-
hood and responsibility to people in this way is to apply normative
principles. It is not merely that others attribute to us an identity and
a character, but that we are entitled to claim them for ourselves and
30. H.L.A. Hart and T. Honoré, Causation in the Law (2nd ed. 1985) lxxx–lxxxi.
29
RESPONSIBILITY AND FAULT
31. Cf. P. Strawson, 48 Proceedings of the British Academy (1962) 1, 24 (on induction).
32. “Forgive us our sins both voluntary and involuntary” (Orthodox liturgy).
30
RESPONSIBILITY AND LUCK
your fault in darting out into the road I run you over, I must stop,
send for the ambulance and give you what help I can in the mean-
time. My responsibility is not as great as if I had been at fault. It may
not be legal: that depends on the applicable system of law. It may not
be moral in the sense that I am morally responsible for the accident
itself. But, just because I have hurt you, I am responsible, and by
virtue of that responsibility bound to take certain steps. Indeed,
unless I am wholly insensitive, I shall feel and express regret for the
harm I have done. For it is a myth that fault and desert are essential
to responsibility. They serve rather to increase the credit or discredit
for the outcome of our behaviour that we incur in any event.
It is only this primary outcome responsibility that can explain why
we (rightly) judge murder more severely than attempted murder and
causing death by dangerous driving more severely than dangerous
driving. It is said that morally the harmful outcome makes no differ-
ence; and indeed the difference between causing death by dangerous
driving and mere dangerous driving, like the difference between aim-
ing a good shot at goal and scoring a goal, is causal, a matter of out-
comes. On a narrow view of morality the cases are not morally
distinguishable. For allocation according to outcomes is not alloca-
tion to according to effort, talent or disposition. A good outcome can
sometimes be achieved with less effort than a bad outcome, and by a
person with less talent and a worse character. Outcome allocation is
allocation according to results, whether they constitute achievements
or botches. But it does not follow that the system of allocation
according to result, in contrast with its application to individual
instances, lacks a moral or pre-moral basis. The person concerned,
though he cannot be sure what the outcome of his action will be, has
chosen to act in the knowledge that he will be credited or debited
with whatever it turns out to be. Moreover, we cannot opt out of the
system by which we obtain credit for favourable outcomes; and so we
cannot slough off the burden of discredit either. Finally, it is out-
comes that in the long run make us what we are.
31
RESPONSIBILITY AND FAULT
33. E.g. B. Aune, 27 Analysis (1967) pp.191–5; K. Lehrer, 29 Analysis (1968) pp.29–32.
34. The oscillation is forcefully brought out by T. Nagel, The View from Nowhere (1986)
ch.7.
35. E.g. Mack v. Davis 76 Ill. App 2d 88, 221 NE 2d 121,126 (1966): age, experience
and intelligence.
33
RESPONSIBILITY AND FAULT
36. Esser-Schmidt, Schuldrecht (6th ed. 1984) vol. I p.377: the object of the law of oblig-
ations is to divide zones of risk from one another.
34
RESPONSIBILITY AND LUCK
within the preceding five years commits on average, in five minutes of driving, at least
nine errors of different kinds.”
37
RESPONSIBILITY AND FAULT
43. “Can and Can’t”, 73 Mind (1964) 463–479, reprinted, below p.144. Endorsed by
D. Dennett, Elbow Room (1984) pp.147–8.
38
RESPONSIBILITY AND LUCK
39
RESPONSIBILITY AND FAULT
4. C ONCLUSION
The argument has been complex but its core is simple. Our respon-
sibility for what we do and for its outcome is inseparable from our
status as persons. We cannot disclaim outcome responsibility without
undermining that status; and outcome responsibility is therefore
more fundamental than moral and legal responsibility, which are
species of it. But the fairness of holding someone responsible outside
or inside the law depends on their possessing a general capacity for
decision and action such that, under the system of bets into which
society forces them, they stand over a span of time to win more than
they lose. The system is not a fair one to apply to those whose limited
capacities make them consistent losers. Given a sufficient general
capacity, however, it involves no great extension of principle for the
law to impose strict liability for risky activities alongside fault liabil-
ity for conduct that discloses an uncooperative disposition. To bear
the risk of bad luck is inseparable from being a choosing person.
40
!5"
NECESSARY AND SUFFICIENT
CONDITIONS IN TORT LAW 1
Argument about causation inside and outside the law is often con-
cerned with the question: must a cause be a necessary condition, or a
sufficient condition of a result, or must it be a necessary element in a set
of conditions jointly sufficient to produce the result? This essay sup-
ports the third view both outside the law and inside it, whenever a
sequence of physical events is in issue. A different but related idea can
be used to explain reasons for human action, “causing” or inducing
people to act rather than causing things to happen. There is, I con-
tend, no special legal meaning of causation and the related concepts
such as inducement.
On the other hand, law alone determines when causal connection
must be proved and when it can be dispensed with in legal contexts.
When causal connection must be proved, law also settles what must
be shown to have caused what. This is specially important in tort law.
Tort law generally imposes fault liability on people who by their
wrongful conduct cause harm to others; but sometimes it imposes
strict liability on people who engage in activities which, though not
wrongful, cause others harm. The causal inquiry takes a different
form according as fault or strict liability is in issue.
Tort lawyers have traditionally held the view that, whatever the
meaning of causal connection, the way to test whether it exists in a
given case is to ask whether in the circumstances the harmful result
would have occurred in the absence of the wrongful act. This is to
adopt the but-for test, by which causal connection exists between
condition and consequence whenever, but for the condition, the con-
sequence would not in the circumstances have occurred. The but-for
1. First published in Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law (ed. David G. Owen, Oxford 1995)
pp.363–85.
94
NECESSARY AND SUFFICIENT CONDITIONS IN TORT LAW
test is also called the test of strong necessity.2 It often gives what is
intuitively the right answer, but sometimes fails to do so. This test is
meant to exclude those factors that had no impact on a particular
course of events. But sometimes it cuts out factors that did have an
impact. It serves to exclude many irrelevant conditions, but also
excludes others that are relevant.3 Thus in some cases of over deter-
mination – cases where two or more independent wrongful acts alone
would have sufficed to bring about the harm – the but-for test leads
to the dubious conclusion that neither act caused the harm. So, if the
but-for test were applied to such a case, the victim could recover from
neither wrongdoer. As a way around this and other difficulties, courts
have developed an alternative test of causal connection, for use in tort
cases when the but-for test seems to give the wrong answer. This alter-
native test asks whether the condition in question was a “substantial”
factor in producing the result. But this device, which allows judges
and juries to follow their intuitions, is purely pragmatic4 and leaves
the theoretical problem untouched. The substantial factor notion is
indefinite, if not indeterminate, and it is difficult to see how it might
be fitted into a coherent theory of causation.
2. On strong and weak necessity and sufficiency see John L. Mackie, The Cement of the
Universe: A Study of Causation pp.39–40, 60–6, 126–7 (1974); Richard W. Wright,
“Causation, Responsibility, Risk, Probability, Naked Statistics and Proof: Pruning the
Bramble Bush by Clarifying the Concepts” [hereafter Pruning] 73 Iowa Law Rev. 1001,
1020 (1988).
3. Wright, Pruning, above n.2, at p.1022.
4. Id. at pp.1018–19.
5. H.L.A. Hart and A.M. Honoré, Causation in the Law (1959).
95
RESPONSIBILITY AND FAULT
6. Id. at p.106. A different, though related account was needed for interpersonal transactions.
7. H.L.A. Hart and Tony Honoré, Causation in the Law (2nd ed. 1985) pp.51–61, 125. See
below, nn.59–61 and accompanying text.
8. This is to apply the reverse but-for test. Wright, Pruning, above n.2, at p.1021 n.108.
Richard Wright termed a condition of this sort, necessary in a weak sense but sufficient in
a strong sense, a “NESS” condition. He derived it from the NESS test, which is meant to
replace the but-for test: id. at 1019. See below, nn.16 and 17 and accompanying text.
9. Mackie, above n.2, at pp.59–63 (building to some extent on Konrad Marc-Wogau, “On
Historical Explanation”, 28 Theoria 213–33 (1962)).
10. Mackie says insufficient (on its own), which is obvious, but also non-redundant, i.e. nec-
essary as an element in that particular jointly sufficient set of conditions: id. p.62.
11. I have modified his terminology so far as the use of “factor” and “condition” are concerned.
96
NECESSARY AND SUFFICIENT CONDITIONS IN TORT LAW
16. Mackie, above n.2, at pp. 77–8, effectively criticized by Wright, Pruning, above n.2, at
pp.1031–4.
17. Richard Wright, “Causation in Tort Law” 73 Cal. Law Rev. 1735 (1985) (especially
pp.1788–1813) [hereafter Causation]; Wright, Pruning, above n.2, at pp.1018–44.
18. Wright, Pruning, above n.2, at p.1019 n.98.
19. See Wright, id. p.1019 n.98. For a criminal law example see Ingeborg Puppe, “Der Erfolg
und seine kausale Erklärung im Strafrecht”, 92 ZStW 863, 867f (1980); “Die Beziehung
zwischen Sorgfaltswidrigkeit und Erfolg bei den Fahrlässigkeitsdelikten” 99 ZStW 595–6
(1987).
20. F. Toepel, Kausalität und Pflichtwidrigkeitszusammenhang beim fahrlässigen Erfolgsdelikt
(1992).
98
NECESSARY AND SUFFICIENT CONDITIONS IN TORT LAW
apply outside the law, and how far it reflects normative considera-
tions, legal or moral.
Some points are, or should be, common ground between the NESS
and but-for theories. First, each of these theories embraces both a
search for the meaning of “causally relevant condition” and a test by
which we can tell whether a condition is causally relevant. That is,
they are both at times semantic and at times heuristic. The impor-
tance of the distinction is that we may believe that a condition was a
cause of a specific event because it was a member of a set of condi-
tions jointly sufficient to bring it about and yet not be able to say
exactly what those conditions were. We may therefore mean by cause
a condition of that sort, and yet be satisfied in a given instance that it
was a cause on the basis of the rough uniformities observed in every-
day life that lead us to think that the presence of the condition made
a difference to the outcome. We may do this though we could not
specify the INUS conditions that are exemplified in the case in
hand.21 No one will deny that the but-for test has in many instances
a heuristic value: it often provides a quick way of testing the existence
of causal connection. It is another matter whether it is part of the
meaning of “causally relevant condition” or “cause”.
Philosophers debate whether causal connection is a relation
between events or between facts.22 An event can be described in
many different ways but a fact is tied to a specific description. That
Brutus stabbed Caesar and that he betrayed Caesar describe the same
historical event but the fact that Brutus stabbed the dictator is not the
same fact as the fact that he betrayed him. This difference has a bear-
ing on what a plaintiff must prove in a lawsuit. In a wrongful death
action by Caesar’s widow, she would have to prove, first, the fact that
Brutus stabbed her husband and, second, the further fact that
Caesar’s death was caused by the first fact of Brutus’ stabbing; it
would not be enough to show that Brutus betrayed Caesar, even
though what Brutus did could be truthfully described as betrayal,
because not all forms of betrayal will found tort actions.
21. But see Mackie, above n.2, at pp.54–5, expressing the contrary view.
22. Mackie, above n.2, at pp.248–265.
99
RESPONSIBILITY AND FAULT
would not have resulted in a fire. But the position would be different
if we knew that, had John not dropped a match, David would have
done so anyway. In that case, though John will indeed have destroyed
the forest, he destroyed a forest that was anyhow doomed, and that
may affect the forest owner’s claim. However, there is usually no rea-
son to suppose any such alternative event and therefore no need
expressly to substitute anything for the condition eliminated.
But the notion that we do not substitute anything for the condi-
tion whose causal relevance we are testing is an illusion. Suppose we
want to test the assertion that Churchill kept Britain in the war in
1940. Was the fact that he was Prime Minister the cause of Britain
remaining in the war? Here we cannot eliminate Churchill without
substituting another Prime Minister whose hypothetical conduct of
affairs would have had a bearing on whether Britain remained in the
war. The contradictory of “Churchill was Prime Minister” viz.
“Churchill was not Prime Minister” would have implied in the world
of 1940 that someone else was Prime Minister (say Halifax); and we
must then ask whether that person would have wanted and been able
to convince Parliament and the British people to continue the war.
The causal statement about Churchill implicitly contrasts him with
this hypothetical substitute. It is true that logically “Churchill was
not Prime Minister in 1940” is compatible with there being no Prime
Minister at all. But it is the real world, not an imaginary world or a
logical calculus, that determines what is implied in the context by the
contradictory of the condition in question, and what should there-
fore be substituted for it in testing the counterfactual proposition. In
that real world, had Churchill not been Prime Minister, someone else
would have held that office. And that someone else might or might
not have kept Britain in the war.
In a legal context the same approach may be applied, except that
when the inquiry concerns the causal relevance of wrongful conduct, as
is usual in tort claims, we must substitute for the wrongful conduct of
the defendant rightful conduct on his part.30 When liability is based on
fault the comparison is not with what would have happened had the
defendant done nothing, but with what would have happened had he
acted properly. The reason for making this substitution is similar to that
30. Hart and Honoré (2nd ed.), above n.7, at pp.lviii–lx, 411–14; Toepel, above n.20, at
p.106.
104
NECESSARY AND SUFFICIENT CONDITIONS IN TORT LAW
31. This is not the case if the law provides that, if the defendant acts unlawfully, he acts at his
risk. Then, as in cases of strict liability, it has only to be shown that his action was causally
connected with the harm, not that the wrongful aspect of it was so connected. Hart and
Honoré, Causation (2nd ed.), above n.7, at lx–lxi. And of course there are torts, such as
trespass, in which harm need not be proved.
32. The dropped match incident might crop up in the context of negligence in tort law. In that
case the comparison would be between what the defendant did and his exercising due care
in regard to the match e.g. by putting it out before throwing it away.
105
RESPONSIBILITY AND FAULT
whether the plaintiff would have suffered injury had the defendant
not engaged in the activity (e.g. using explosives) that entails strict lia-
bility. There is normally no reason to suppose that, if the defendant
had not used explosives for blasting, he or someone else would then
and there have injured the plaintiff by some other means.
Both inside and outside the law, therefore, the purpose of the
inquiry determines how we should frame the hypothesis to be tested.
Tort law lays down what counts as wrongful conduct or conduct
entailing strict liability and so what the plaintiff has to prove. It aims
to protect people against wrongful infringement of their rights and
exposure to undue danger. So, to ascertain whether an infringement
has occurred, the wrongful conduct of the defendant must normally
be compared with the notional rightful conduct that the plaintiff was
entitled to expect in the circumstances. The question is, whether the
difference between the wrongful conduct that occurred in the real
world and the rightful conduct (together with its likely conse-
quences) that we imagine as occurring, would have led to a different
result in the hypothetical world that resembles the real world in all
other respects. In the strict liability context, where the law protects
against risks created by lawful conduct on the part of others, the
causal inquiry is adapted to that aim.
Does the fact that in tort law we normally compare wrongful with
rightful conduct show that the causal question is a normative ques-
tion in disguise? It does not, for the inquiry into what would have
occurred had the defendant obeyed a legal norm is no more norma-
tive than the question what would have occurred had the Prime
Minister been someone other than Churchill. The answer to these
causal inquires has no normative component. It remains the same,
even if we suppose that it would have been better for Britain to make
peace in 1940, or that it would be better, in order to combat over-
population, for those who drive automobiles to drive blindfold.
There are those who think that counterfactual propositions cannot
be true or false.33 The tort process however assumes, in my view
rightly, that they can be. We can often know what on a certain
hypothesis would happen in the real world. We know that if we strike
a match under certain conditions a flame will appear. The statement
“if a match is struck under conditions XYZ a flame will appear” can
be true or false and its truth value can be tested. Why not, also, “if a
match had been struck . . . a flame would have appeared”? The only
difference is that the proposition about the past can be verified only
indirectly, on the assumption that in similar conditions similar results
recur. This assumption cannot itself be verified, but unless it is well-
founded we cannot rely on causal regularities or scientific laws. Of
course we are often uncertain what would have happened on a given
occasion had the defendant acted lawfully. Here, though the coun-
terfactual statement “had X not done what he did Y would not have
happened” is in principle true or false, we cannot tell for certain
which it is. We must then have recourse to rules of law that instruct
the judge or jury to go by the probabilities and, if necessary, to fall
back on rules about the burden of proof.
Two similar causal processes may culminate in the same harm at the
same time. Two shots, negligently but independently fired by A and
B when out hunting, simultaneously hit C and destroy his left eye.
Each shot was sufficient to do this without the other, and the effects
107
RESPONSIBILITY AND FAULT
employed and that the nutshell be not too thick, but unnecessary that
the wind lie in a northerly direction or that the agent utter a blood-
curdling whoop. The recipe is general, built up over time as instances
accumulate and conditions are tested.
The discovery of conditions that are necessary members of a set
sufficient to produce some result can be used to explain events as well
as to bring them about. It can extend to events over which we have
no control. We seek to discover the conditions of these events, per-
haps in order to control similar events in future, or simply to under-
stand how the universe works. The knowledge thus acquired may
come in handy, but it may be pursued for its own sake. It can be used
to trace the effects of natural events and inanimate forces. It can also
be used to assign responsibility – social responsibility – to human
beings for the outcome of their conduct.
For all these purposes – making recipes, explaining events and
attributing responsibility – we can use the concept of the necessary
members of a set of conditions together sufficient to produce a result
of a given type, though we may not be able to specify or quantify all
the conditions. This limited ability to specify conditions does not
prevent our using causal ideas to explain events backwards in terms
of previous events and conditions, or to allot responsibility for con-
duct forwards in terms of outcomes. These are not normative func-
tions. It makes no difference whether the event to be explained, or the
conduct to be assessed, is judged good or bad. It is tort law, not the
concept of cause, that invites us to focus on the outcome of wrongful
conduct.
What bearing has this on the problem of over-determination? The
lesson is surely that the NESS test is not confined to the context of
responsibility in general or tort law in particular. To revert to the two
independent shots by A and B that put out C’s eye, the acts of A and
B each exemplify how to put C’s left eye out, if that was, perhaps, the
objective of snipers in a military campaign. Each also provides an
explanation of C’s loss of his left eye. Why, then, should not each pro-
vide a basis for assigning legal and moral responsibility to A and B?
No recourse to legal policy, or to normative considerations, is needed
to reach the conclusion that both A and B independently caused the
harm to C. None of the purposes for which causal concepts are used
requires us to adopt the but-for theory. There can be different recipes
for attaining a given type of result, more than one of which is available
109
RESPONSIBILITY AND FAULT
ditions. If not, A’s negligent shooting was a cause of C’s loss of eye-
sight. But suppose that careful investigation shows that A’s shot
missed. In that case A’s shot was not causally relevant to the outcome
and we must construct another set of conditions, including B’s shot,
and test whether B’s shot was a necessary member of that set of con-
ditions which together produced the loss of eyesight. Toepel objects
that this procedure involves deciding that A’s shot was causally rele-
vant before we test it for causal relevance.39 That is not so. All we have
decided before testing A’s shot for relevance while provisionally omit-
ting B’s is that, as we know some of the INUS conditions for loss of
eyesight, A’s shot may on this occasion have been a causally relevant
condition even in the absence of B’s shot. It is true that the testing
procedure is possible only if we know some causal regularities before
we start. But we need not assume from the start that the outcome of
the test will be positive.
A similar causal over-determination analysis may be applied to
other cases in which two similar processes appear responsible for an
event, for example, where two fires merge and jointly culminate in
harm40 or where the pollution created by a number of persons inde-
pendently pollutes a stream or lake.41
This requires that the victim, place and time be specified. She has also
to show that the defendant’s wrongful act caused the death, which
involves showing that some causal process initiated by the defendant
brought it about. In the water keg example, that B’s conduct (in emp-
tying the water keg) was a condition of C’s death by dehydration is
relevant because the process of dehydration connects B’s act by a
series of stages with C’s death. To establish that this process occurred
is relevant because, given the plurality of possible causes of death, it
is necessary for C’s widow to point to a specific causal process that
links the two, and dehydration is such a process.
49. Dillon v. Twin State Gas & Elec. Co., 163 Atl. 111 (1932).
50. The facts are suggested by Baker v. Willoughby [1970] AC 467. Cf. Jobling v. Associated
Dairies, [1982] AC 794.
113
RESPONSIBILITY AND FAULT
Yet A will plead that his liability is limited to the six months’ earnings
alone, since, as it turns out, C would not have been able to wrestle for
more than that period in any event. If both of these arguments are
accepted, C, having been wrongfully injured on two occasions,
obtains less than had he been injured only once, which is unsatisfac-
tory. Yet this is not like the case of simultaneous over-determination
where each agent can properly be said to have caused the same injury.
Someone who claims to have lost future opportunities of earning
money must show that he would have been able to take advantage of
those opportunities in the absence of the wrongful act of which he
complains. For example, if after six months C had died of a heart
attack, not brought on by the injury inflicted by A, his estate could
not claim loss of earnings for the period after he was dead. A dead
man cannot wrestle, and there is no reason to impose on A the risk
that C could die of natural causes unconnected with A’s wrongful act.
There are two possible ways round the difficulty, one of which is
consistent with causal principles while the other rests on a basis of
risk-allocation. The first solution is to hold that there is a cause of
action in tort law for depriving someone by a wrongful act of a tort
remedy that would otherwise have been available to him. In the
injured wrestler case, B has deprived C of a tort remedy against A for
his lost wrestling earnings following the second injury. This cause of
action, if it existed, would be like the suggested remedy, now much
discussed, against a defendant who wrongfully deprives a plaintiff of
a chance.51 The alternative way of solving the injured wrestler conun-
drum is to treat is to treat A as guaranteeing C that he will not be
deprived of his prospective remedy for loss of earnings by a later
wrongful act of someone else. To construct such a guarantee is to pro-
vide a non-causal basis of liability, an example of the familiar princi-
ple by which the risk of harm to C is sometimes placed on A. Here
the risk would be imposed on A as a result of A’s wrongdoing, just as
in the law of sale risk is sometimes transferred to the seller because of
his failure to deliver goods on time. The justification for putting the
risk on A would be that it is the function of the law to protect people
against wrongful invasions of their rights. Rather than let a person
51. Wright, Pruning, above n.2, at pp.1067–72. A “lost chance” case may arise, for example,
if a doctor negligently fails to diagnose a progressive disease such as cancer in a timely man-
ner, and so deprives the patient of, say, a twenty per cent chance of recovery. Causes of
action along these lines, whatever their intrinsic merits, do no violence to causal principles.
114
NECESSARY AND SUFFICIENT CONDITIONS IN TORT LAW
D. Indeterminacy
61. See Australian Steel & Mining Corp. v. Corben 1974 2 N.S.W.L.R. 202, 209; Hart and
Honoré, Causation (2nd ed.), above n.7, at p.193. Compare, for criminal law, judgement
of Feb. 24, 1959, BGH Gr. Sen. St., 13 Entscheidungen des Bundesgerichtshofes in
Strafsachen [BGHSt] 15 (F.R.G.); contra Toepel, above n.20, at p.93.
118
NECESSARY AND SUFFICIENT CONDITIONS IN TORT LAW
119
RESPONSIBILITY AND FAULT
4. C ONCLUSION
120