Is Inheritance Justified?
Is Inheritance Justified?
Is Inheritance Justified?
Author(s): D. W. Haslett
Source: Philosophy & Public Affairs, Vol. 15, No. 2 (Spring, 1986), pp. 122-155
Published by: Wiley
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2265382
Accessed: 20-12-2016 20:00 UTC
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
Wiley is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy & Public Affairs
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
D. W. HASLETT Is Inheritance
Justified?
Old ways die hard. A social practice may be taken for granted for centuries
before humanity finally comes to realize it cannot be justified. Take, for
example, slavery. Another example is the inheritance of political power.
For many centuries, throughout most of the world, the suggestion that
political power should be determined by democratic vote rather than
heredity would have been met with scorn; today we realize just how
unjustified determining political power by heredity really is.
Although we no longer believe in the inheritance of political power,
most of us still believe in the inheritance of wealth, of economic power.
But might not the inheritance of economic power be equally unjustified?
This is the question to be examined here. Inheritance involves property
rights; so another way of putting this question is: Should property rights
incorporate the practice of inheritance as it exists today?
I shall not address the question of whether individuals may justifiably
continue to take advantage of this practice as long as it exists, by con-
tinuing to bequeath and inherit property. (As far as I am concerned, they
may.) I address only the justifiability of the practice (or institution) itself.
Finally, in asking whether the practice of inheritance is justified, I focus
specifically upon whether it is justified in the United States, today. Any
conclusions I reach, however, will be applicable, no doubt, beyond this
limited frame of reference, one chosen mainly for convenience. And, for
convenience also, I shall be using the word "inheritance" throughout to
refer to any large amount one is given (as opposed to earns, or wins),
whether it be, technically, a bequest, or a gift.
This investigation is divided into three sections. Section I presents some
facts about wealth distribution and inheritance in the United States today,
I wish to thank Edgar Page for many helpful comments on an earlier draft of this article.
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
123 Is Inheritance
Justified?
facts that provide a useful background for the discussion which follows.
Many people support inheritance because they believe it to be essential
to capitalism. In Section II I try to show that, far from being essential,
inheritance is actually inconsistent with capitalism. Or, to be more exact,
I try to show that it is inconsistent with fundamental values that underlie
capitalism. For those, such as myself, who share these values, its incon-
sistency with them is prima facie reason for abolishing inheritance. But
prima facie reasons for doing something can be overridden if the objec-
tions to doing it are strong enough. So, in Section III, I examine what I
take to be the most important objections to abolishing inheritance. I
conclude that the practice of inheritance, as it exists today, should indeed
be abolished.
I. BACKGROUND INFORMATION
Family income in the United States today is not distributed very evenly.
The top fifth of American families receives 57.3 percent of all family
income, while the bottom fifth receives only 7.2 percent.I
But, for obvious reasons, a family's financial well-being does not depend
upon its income nearly as much as it does upon its wealth, just as the
strength of an army does not depend upon how many people joined it
during the year as much as it does upon how many people are in it
altogether. So if we really want to know how unevenly economic well-
being is distributed in the United States today, we must look at the
distribution not of income, but of wealth.
Although-quite surprisingly-the government does not regularly col-
lect information on the distribution of wealth, it has occasionally done
so. The results are startling. One to two percent of American families
own from around 20 to 30 percent of the (net) family wealth in the United
States; 5 to io percent own from around 40 to 6o percent.2 The top fifth
i. Lester C. Thurow, "Tax Wealth, Not Income," New York Times Magazine, i i April
1976, p. 33. These figures do not represent "income," as defined by the census bureau,
but "income" as defined more broadly so as to include also any income received from wealth.
Somewhat more recent figures are, of course, readily available. I am, however, using the
figures set out by Thurow for two reasons. First, figures representing the distribution of
income (as opposed to the amount of income) have varied little over the past twenty-five
years. Second, these figures are compared by Thurow directly to figures representing the
distribution of wealth in the United States, figures which are set out below.
2. The latest governmental study of the distribution of wealth, carried out in I983,
estimates the amount of net wealth held by the top 2 percent to be 28 percent, and that
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
124 Philosophy & Public Affairs
owns almost 8o percent of the wealth, while the bottom fifth owns only
0.2 percent.3 So while the top fifth has, as we saw, about eight times the
income of the bottom fifth, it has about 400 times the wealth. Whether
deliberately or not, by regularly gathering monumental amounts of in-
formation on the distribution of income, but not on the distribution of
wealth, the government succeeds in directing attention away from how
enormously unequal the distribution of wealth is, and directing it instead
upon the less unequal distribution of income. But two things are clear:
wealth is distributed far more unequally in the United States today than
is income, and this inequality in the distribution of wealth is enormous.
These are the first two things to keep in mind throughout our discussion
of inheritance.
The next thing to keep in mind is that, although estate and gift taxes
in the United States are supposed to redistribute wealth, and thereby
lessen this inequality, they do not do so. Before I98I estates were taxed,
on an average, at a rate of only o.2 percent-o.8 percent for estates over
$500,ooo-hardly an amount sufficient to cause any significant redistri-
bution of wealth.4 And, incredibly, the Economic Recovery Act of I98I
lowered estate and gift taxes.
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
125 Is Inheritance
Justified?
Of course the top rate at which estates and gifts are allegedly taxed is
far greater than the o.2 percent rate, on the average, at which they are
really taxed. Prior to I98I, the top rate was 70 percent, which in 198I
was lowered to 5o percent. Because of this relatively high top rate, the
average person is led to believe that estate and gift taxes succeed in
breaking up the huge financial empires of the very rich, thereby distrib-
uting wealth more evenly. What the average person fails to realize is that
what the government takes with one hand, through high nominal rates,
it gives back with the other hand, through loopholes in the law. Lester
Thurow writes, ". . . it is hard to understand why we go through the
fiction of legislating high nominal rates and then nullifying them with
generous loopholes-unless someone is to be fooled. The most obvious
purpose of high nominal rates and low effective rates is to use the high
nominal rates as a smokescreen to hide the transfer of wealth from gen-
eration to generation."5 I do not know if the government deliberately
intends the law on estate and gift taxation to be deceptive but, due to
the complications, exceptions, and qualifications built into this law, it is
deceptive and, more seriously still, it is ineffective as a means of distrib-
uting wealth more evenly. Indeed, as George Cooper shows, estate and
gift taxes can, with the help of a good attorney, be avoided so easily they
amount to little more than "voluntary" taxes.6 As such, it is not surprising
that, contrary to popular opinion, these taxes do virtually nothing to re-
duce the vast inequality in the distribution of wealth that exists today.
Once we know that estate and gift taxes do virtually nothing to reduce
this vast inequality, what I am about to say next should come as no
surprise. This vast inequality in the distribution of wealth is (according
to the best estimates) due at least as much to inheritance as to any other
factor. Once again, because of the surprising lack of information about
these matters, the extent to which this inequality is due to inheritance
is not known exactly. One estimate, based upon a series of articles ap-
pearing in Fortune magazine, is that 5o percent of the large fortunes in
the United States were derived basically from inheritance.7 But by far
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
126 Philosophy & Public Affairs
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
127 Is Inheritance
Justified?
Ii. Milton Friedman, Capitalism & Freedom (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
I962), pp. I6I-I62.
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I28 Philosophy & Public Affairs
Equal Opportunity
I 2. For a useful analysis of the concept of "equal opportunity," see Douglas Rae, Equalities
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, I98i), ch. 4. Using Rae's terminology, the
ideal of equal opportunity being discussed here is "means-regarding," rather than "prospect-
regarding."
In spite of the usefulness of Rae's analysis, it is, I think, mistaken in one crucial respect.
According to Rae, means-regarding equal opportunity receives whatever ideological, or
moral, credibility it has only by being confused with prospect-regarding equal opportunity
(pp. 67, 73). If what I say below about the value of (means-regarding) equal opportunity
is correct, this is a serious mistake.
13. Milton & Rose Friedman, Freedom to Choose (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich,
I979), pp. I3I-40. Friedman also talks favorably of another ideal of equality, which he
calls "equality before God." But equality before God turns out to be a restatement of the
ideal of liberty, which is discussed below.
14. See, for example, Bernard Williams, "The Idea of Equality," Philosophy, Politics and
Society, ser. 2, ed. Peter Laslett and W. G. Runciman (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, I962).
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
129 Is Inheritance
Justified?
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
130 Philosophy & Public Affairs
15. I say this fully aware of the criticism of equal opportunity, and meritocracy in general,
made by Michael Young in The Rise of Meritocracy (Harmondsworth, England: Penguin
Books, I96I). The problem with these criticisms is that they are based upon taking equal
opportunity (along with productivity) to be, not merely a prima facie value as it should be,
but absolute. Any legitimate prima facie value can easily be reduced to absurdity if it is
wrongly viewed as being absolute.
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
131 Is Inheritance
Justified?
Freedom
But so far I have not mentioned what many, including no doubt Friedman
himself, consider to be the most important ideal underlying capitalism:
that of liberty or, in other words, freedom. This ideal, however, takes
different forms. One form it takes for Friedman is that of being able to
engage in economic transactions free from governmental or other types
of human coercion. The rationale for this conception of freedom-let us
call it freedom in the "narrow" sense-is clear. As Friedman explains it,
assuming only that people are informed about what is good for them, this
form of freedom guarantees that ". .. no exchange will take place unless
both parties benefit from it."17 If at least the parties themselves benefit
from the transaction, and it does not harm anyone, then, it is fair to say,
the transaction has been socially valuable. So people with freedom of
exchange will, in doing what is in their own best interests, generally be
doing what is socially valuable as well. In other words, with this form of
freedom, the fabled "invisible hand" actually works.
All of this is a great oversimplification. For one thing, a transaction
i6. Although abolishing inheritance would, I should think, do more to increase equal
opportunity than any single other (feasible) reform, it is by no means the only reform that
is needed for this purpose. If we are serious about achieving significantly more equality of
opportunity within a capitalistic framework-and I think we certainly should be-we should
combine inheritance reform with, among other things, the following two additional reforms:
a program that guarantees access to higher education for all who are qualified, and a program
to bring about equal access to medical care for all. This latter reform would remove the
financial obstacle preventing children of the very poor from receiving prompt and reliable
medical care; prompt and reliable medical care is, in turn, necessary for preventing their
medical needs from progressing to the point where they have suffered irreversible damage
that could handicap them for the rest of their lives. One way of achieving equal access to
medical care for all is through a program of "socialized" medicine, but this is not the only
way.
17. Friedman, Capitalism & Freedom, p. I3.
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I32 Philosophy & Public Affairs
that benefits both parties may have side effects, such as pollution, which
harm others and, therefore, the transaction may not be socially valuable
after all. So freedom, in the narrow sense, should certainly not be absolute.
But the fact that freedom, in this sense, should not be absolute does not
prevent it from serving as a useful ideal.
Next, those, such as Friedman, who oppose governmental coercion in
the realm of economic exchanges often oppose governmental coercion
of another sort as well: paternalism. In other words, they oppose govern-
mental coercion designed to force us to do what is, supposedly, in our
own best interests. Examples of governmental paternalism would be a
law prohibiting the drinking of alcoholic beverages, on the grounds that
doing so is unhealthy, or a law requiring everyone to wear seat belts. But,
provided that it does not significantly affect freedom of exchange (that
is, freedom in the narrow sense), paternalism has little to do with capi-
talism; therefore, "antipaternalistic" freedom does not, it seems to me,
deserve to be included among the ideals that underlie capitalism. More
to the point, neither inheritance, nor its abolishment (at least not for the
reasons put forth here), could be correctly viewed as paternalistic anyway.
So we need not give this conception of freedom further consideration
here.
There are others whose conception of freedom is that of not being
subject to any governmental coercion (or other forms of human coercion)
for any purposes whatsoever-a conception sometimes referred to as
"negative" freedom. It is true that governmental (or other) coercion for
purposes of enforcing the abolition of inheritance violates this ideal, but
then, of course, so does any such coercion for purposes of maintaining
inheritance. So this "anticoercion" ideal, just like the antipaternalistic
ideal, neither supports nor opposes the practice of inheritance, and there-
fore this conception of freedom need not concern us further here either.
A very popular variation of the anticoercion conception of freedom is
one where freedom is, once again, the absence of all governmental (or
other human) coercion, except for any coercion necessary for enforcing
our fundamental rights. Prominent among our fundamental rights, most
of those who espouse such a conception of freedom will tell us, is our
right to property. So whether this conception of freedom supports the
practice of inheritance depends entirely upon whether our "right to prop-
erty" should be viewed as incorporating the practice of inheritance. But
whether our right to property should be viewed as incorporating the
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I33 Is Inheritance
Justified?
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I34 Philosophy & Public Affairs
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I35 Is Inheritance
Justified?
consistent: the truth is, I suggest, that all great concentrations of eco-
nomic power are suspicious, whether emanating from government, cor-
porations, or individuals.
So we may conclude that, at best, inheritance receives no support from
freedom in the narrow sense. But it remains for us to consider whether
inheritance receives any support from the other relevant ideal of freedom,
an ideal many, including myself, would consider to be the more funda-
mental of the two: freedom in the broad sense-being able to do, or having
the opportunity to do, what one wants. So we must now ask whether,
everything considered, there is more overall opportunity throughout the
country for people to do what they want with inheritance, or without it.
On the one hand, without inheritance people are no longer free to leave
their fortunes to whomever they want and, of course, those who otherwise
would have received these fortunes are, without them, less free to do
what they want also.
But to offset these losses in freedom are at least the following gains in
freedom. First, as is well known, wealth has, generally speaking, a di-
minishing marginal utility. What this means is that, generally speaking,
the more wealth one already has, the less urgent are the needs which
any given increment of wealth will go to satisfy and, therefore, the less
utility the additional wealth will have for one. This, in turn, means that
the more evenly wealth is distributed, the more overall utility it will have. 8
And since we may assume that, generally speaking, the more utility some
amount of wealth has for someone, the more freedom in the broad sense
it allows that person to enjoy, we may conclude that the more evenly
wealth is distributed, the more overall freedom to which it will give rise.
Now assuming that abolishing inheritance would not lessen overall
wealth (an assumption I shall try to show in Section III to be warranted),
and that it would indeed distribute wealth more evenly, it follows that,
by abolishing inheritance, there would be some gain in freedom in the
broad sense attributable to the diminishing marginal utility of wealth.
Next, abolishing inheritance would also increase freedom by increasing
equality of opportunity. Certainly those who do not start life having in-
herited significant funds (through either gift or bequest) start life, relative
i8. The more evenly wealth is distributed, the more overall utility it will have since any
wealth that "goes" from the rich to the poor, thereby making the distribution more even,
will (given the diminishing marginal utility of wealth) have more utility for these poor than
it would have had for the rich, thus increasing overall utility.
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I36 Philosophy & Public Affairs
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
137 Is Inheritance
Justified?
inheritance that are strong enough to override its inconsistency with these
ideals (or to show that my conclusion about its inconsistency with the
ideal of freedom to be premature). So, before we can make any final
judgment about the justifiability of inheritance, we must examine the
most significant of these objections.
III. OBJECTIONS
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I38 Philosophy & Public Affairs
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I39 Is Inheritance
Justified?
prohibited from leaving their children. And at a certain age, say twenty-
one (if the child's formal education has been completed), or upon removal
of whatever disability has caused dependency, the funds should cease.
This exception eliminates another objection to abolishing inheritance-
the objection that it would leave orphaned children, and other depend-
ents, without the support they needed.20
The third and final exception to be built into this proposal is one for
charitable organizations-ones created not for purposes of making a
profit, but for charitable, religious, scientific, or educational purposes.
And, in order to prevent these organizations from eventually controlling
the economy, they must, generally, be under the same constraint as is
the government with respect to any real property they are given, such
as an operating factory: they must, generally, sell it on the open market
within a year.
A limit of some sort could be placed upon the amount a person would
be entitled to give to charitable organizations; I am inclined, however, to
oppose any limit. Allowing unlimited contributions would, to be sure,
weaken one of the advantages of abolishing inheritance, that of providing
government with a major, new source of revenue, one that would serve
to lessen the burden of income taxes. For rather than allowing their
estates to pass to the government, most people would probably choose to
leave their estates to charitable organizations. But even if they did, the
advantage of lessening our tax burden would not be lost, for if vast
amounts were given to charitable organizations, these organizations could
be expected to fund much of the welfare, medical research, scholarships
for the poor, aid to education, and so on, that must (or should) now be
funded by the government, thereby lessening our tax burden not by
increasing governmental revenues, but by decreasing governmental ex-
penses. And charitable organizations would become, even more than they
20. Society must not, of course, forget about orphans, and other dependents, of the
relatively poor either; they should be adequately provided for somehow by the state. Yet it
might be prohibitively expensive for the state to care for orphans of the poor at the level
of luxury at which this exception to the abolishment of inheritance would allow orphans
of the rich to be cared for, thus raising a question of fairness. But if we accept the proposition
that (since we do not want to abolish the family) it is justified for the children of the rich
to live in more luxury than those of the poor while their parents are alive, then it is reasonable
for us to allow this higher standard to continue even if these parents happen to die. It is
usually traumatic enough for a child to have to adapt to the death of both parents without,
at the same time, having to adapt to an altogether different standard of living as well.
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
140 Philosophy & Public Affairs
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I4I Is Inheritance
Justified?
2i. Friedman, Capitalism & Freedom, pp. I63-64; and Freedom to Choose, p. 136.
22. Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), pp. 237-
38; F. A. Hayek, The Constitution of Liberty (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1960),
pp. 9o-91. Cf. John Rawls, A Theory ofJustice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
1971), p. 278.
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I42 Philosophy & Public Affairs
a careful and patient investigation into what the pros and cons actually
are. We must not be dissuaded from this task by the above quick, but
fallacious argument with which Friedman and others tempt us.
(3) Let us turn now to some objections of a more practical nature. The
first of these is that, regardless of whether abolishing inheritance is jus-
tified or not, the simple truth is that Americans are solidly against doing
so; therefore our discussion is a waste of time. The reply, of course, is
that, unless popular opinions are sometimes challenged, how, after all,
can we ever make any progress? What if, for example, just because the
public was against it, no one in the South a century ago had been willing
to consider whether abolishing slavery was justified? If abolishing in-
heritance really is justified, chances are the public will eventually come
to favor it; but the first order of business, clearly, is to decide if it really
is justified.
But we must not dismiss this practical objection too quickly; this ob-
jection is related to still another practical objection, one that does deserve
to be taken seriously: the objection that a ban on inheritance could never
be adequately enforced. Some would argue that, by secret Swiss bank
accounts, bogus exchanges, fake salaries, and simply by passing money
under the table, large gifts could be made at any time in spite of a law
abolishing them. Therefore, it would be concluded, no matter how jus-
tified the abolishment of inheritance might be, any law to that effect
would be a futile gesture; as the sophomore is fond of saying, it might
be good in theory, but would never work in practice.
Yet would a ban on inheritance actually be unenforceable? The pos-
sibility of gain through illegal gifts exists with current American estate
and gift tax law. Nevertheless, governmental investigators do succeed in
uncovering such gifts often enough for successful enforcement. The
reports of courts that handle tax litigation are filled with such cases.
Successful enforcement of this law suggests the government could, sim-
ilarly, enforce a law abolishing inheritance.
But, it may be replied, current estate and gift tax law provides the
wealthy with so many legal means of avoidance that (provided only that
they are willing to hire a clever attorney) illegal means are not even
necessary. A law abolishing inheritance, one not so easily avoided through
legal means, would be an entirely different matter. With it, the "need"
to resort to illegal means would be far greater and, therefore, so would
the difficulties of enforcement.
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I43 Is Inheritance
Justified?
There is, no doubt, some truth in this reply. But so far we have over-
looked an important factor: enforcement through informal social pres-
sure, as opposed to fonnal governmental pressure. And by "informal"
social pressure, I mean more than just the pressure that potential social
disapproval and ostracism exert upon us; I mean also the pressure our
early training and social conditioning exert on us, a pressure so great
that most of us would not violate most laws even without any govern-
mental enforcement of them. I doubt if governmental enforcement would
be adequate enforcement for many laws without social pressure to go
along with it. Take, for example, the legal prohibition upon alcoholic
beverages in America which, in spite of intensive governmental enforce-
ment, failed, and did so primarily because of a lack of popular support
or, in other words, a lack of informal social pressure for compliance with
the law. On the other hand, with the help of informal social pressure, I
doubt if there are many laws the government could not enforce ade-
quately, even if the government's role amounted to mere tokenism. Take,
for example, current income tax law; in spite of possibilities for cheating
that rival those of a law abolishing inheritance, this law does, for the most
part, work; and it works because, although few agree with the details of
the law, most believe that, in principle, an income tax is justified. And
if most people believed a law abolishing inheritance was justified then,
through a combination of government pressure and informal social pres-
sure, this law likewise would, I think, work well enough.
This, however, is where the fact that most people currently do not
think such a law would be justified becomes relevant. Since most people
currently do not think such a law would be justified, that such a law
could be adequately enforced at the present time is indeed doubtful. And
if it could not be adequately enforced, I must conclude that, currently,
no such law should be passed. Except where absolutely necessary in
order to protect minority rights, the imposition of extremely unpopular
laws upon an unwilling public has no place in a democracy.
None of this, however, must be allowed to obscure an equally important
point: the strength of a democracy depends upon there being the freedom
and willingness to question the status quo, to constantly seek a better
way. Although currently a law abolishing inheritance appears to have
little public support, if such a law really is justified, except for currently
having little public support, I believe the necessary public support will
eventually come-provided we remain willing to question the status quo.
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I44 Philosophy & Public Affairs
23. See, for example, D. C. McClelland, The Achieving Society (Princeton: Van Nostrand,
I96I), pp. 234-35; and Seymour Fiekowsky, On the Economic Effects of Death Taxation
in the United States (unpublished doctoral dissertation, Harvard University, I959), pp.
370-7I.
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
145 Is Inheritance
Justified?
(5) We come now to the most technical and, potentially, the most
serious objection to abolishing inheritance: the objection that this would
24. Gordon Tullock claims that a better way to redistribute income and wealth than
abolishing inheritance would be a direct tax on either income or wealth. See Tullock,
"Inheritance Justified," The Journal of Law and Economics (October I97I). But, if I am
right, abolishing inheritance would not, in general, decrease people's incentive to be pro-
ductive (on the contrary, it would probably increase incentive); whereas the same cannot
be said of Tullock's method of still greater income taxes, or of a substantial tax upon wealth.
In any case, Tullock fails to realize that by no means is redistribution the only, or even the
main, goal of abolishing inheritance; another goal, for example, is greater equality of op-
portunity (i.e., "starting places" that are more equal). Any tax upon income or wealth which
still permitted vast sums to be inherited from various sources would not be as successful
as abolishing inheritance, or as a modest quota (see below), in accomplishing this goal.
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I46 Philosophy & Public Affairs
25. Gordon Tullock says that, for economists, this has been, traditionally, the "principle"
objection to abolishing inheritance (yet it is not an objection Tullock himself makes).
Although it is what he calls the principle objection, he says the point has not been made
as strongly in the literature as one might expect. Ibid., p. 465, n. i. Nevertheless, Tullock
goes on to say, it is discussed in G. E. Hoover, "The Economic Effects of Inheritance Taxes,"
American Economic Review 17 (1927): 38-49; and Alvin H. Johnson, "Public Capitalization
of the Inheritance Tax," Journal of Political Economy 22 (I914): i60-8o.
26. Of the respondents to a study carried out in I964, around 97 percent with incomes
under $io,ooo did not mention bequest as a motive for saving, 8o percent with incomes
over $io,ooo did not mention it, and, even among those with incomes over $300,000, about
50 percent did not mention it. Robin Barlow et al., Economic Behavior of the Affluent
(Washington, D.C.: Brookings Institution, I966), pp. 3I-33. From this study, we see that
most people, even most of those with very high incomes, do indeed have motives for saving
other than that of leaving money to others.
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I47 Is Inheritance
Justified?
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I48 Philosophy & Public Affairs
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I49 Is Inheritance
Justified?
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
150 Philosophy & Public Affairs
members would have a chance to buy any family heirlooms before they
went on the open market and, except for the most expensive heirlooms,
they would normally have the means to do so. If the decedent had provided
for it, a son or daughter would be given the same chance to buy a family
business or farm. But even with the rather liberal credit terms built into
this proposal for sales to those specified by the decedent (io percent
down, and 30 years to pay the rest) probably most sons and daughters
would not be in a strong enough financial position to take advantage of
this opportunity.
Yet it is important to realize that even the family business/farm problem
is, today, rather limited in scope. There was a period in American history
when disrupting occupational continuity from parent to child by abolish-
ing inheritance would have had grave consequences for the nation as a
whole. Higher education, and other occupational training, were not read-
ily available for most people; more often than not, children learned their
occupation from their parents so as to carry on with the family business
or farm after their parents died. To disrupt this continuity by abolishing
inheritance, thereby depriving vast numbers of people of the only job for
which they were adequately prepared, might well have been a national
economic disaster. Inheritance, in those days, might well have been one
of society's main devices for achieving continuity from one generation to
the next in the production of goods and services.
But those days have long since passed-and, incidentally, I see little
reason for trying to resurrect them. Today higher education and other
forms of occupational training are readily available; people are far more
mobile than before; children do not, for the most part, follow in the exact
footsteps of their parents anymore; and continuity from one generation
to the next in the production of goods and services is now achieved instead
largely through the separation of ownership from management that is
found in today's large corporations. Disrupting occupational continuity
from parent to child by abolishing inheritance might have serious con-
sequences for the limited number of children who would like to carry on
from their parents, but the number is indeed limited.
It might be pointed out, however, that the objection to depriving chil-
dren of family businesses or farms goes beyond just the bad consequences
of doing so. This objection, so it might be said, also involves a matter of
justice; after a child has already built his or her life around a family
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I51 Is Inheritance
Justified?
29. The best way would be to abolish inheritance gradually over a number of years so
as to avoid any frantic rush to have children before the "deadline," and so as to avoid the
injustice of one child being able to inherit without restriction, while his younger sibling,
born after the "deadline," can inherit nothing.
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I52 Philosophy & Public Affairs
30. In the case of family farms, there is a further rationale: by preventing people from
inheriting them, the farms will, in being sold, be fragmented into a number of small,
inefficient units. The problem of fragmentation, however, does not appear to be very serious;
if significant fragmentation did occur, and did prove to be inefficient, it could easily be
remedied by some sort of legislation requiring that any farms sold by the government in
settling a person's estate be (normally) sold only as a whole, and requiring (perhaps) that
any resale within a period of, say, five years also be only as a whole.
31. A quota would be far superior to a lifetime accessions tax: it is, first of all, simpler-
a not insignificant advantage! -but, even more importantly, a quota would indeed place a
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I53 Is Inheritance
Justified?
ceiling, as a tax would not, upon how much any one person could receive from all sources-
the lack of any definite ceiling being perhaps the most insidious loophole of all.
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
154 Philosophy & Public Affairs
their salaries to the point where they might well be able to handle the
monthly payments. Furthermore, the government could, and I think
should, encourage joint purchases by employees with "supportive leg-
islation" designed to make such purchases easier by granting emnployees
very favorable purchasing terms. (In return for these favorable terms the
government could require that allfuture, full-time employees be required
to purchase an equal share as well, so that the establishment would then
never have "second class citizens.") As joint owners, workers would have
some control over their own destiny; they would periodically elect man-
agement; they would share in profits and losses; they would, in short,
enjoy what may be referred to as "workers' democracy." This democracy
would not, of course, be a "direct," but rather a "representative" one,
where the elected managers-normaRly highly trained, and highly paid,
professionals-would be in full charge of everyday affairs (just as in a
political democracy), yet answerable, ultimately, to the workers. I am
inclined to think most workers' democracies would be highly desirable.
The potential gains from such arrangements are considerable: they in-
clude a decrease in worker alienation, an increase in the tolerability of
working conditions, and a greater share for workers in the profits from
their own work.32 In general, the gains to be realized in going from a
"totalitarian" business establishment to a workers' democracy parallel
those in going from a totalitarian state to a political democracy. If either
abolishing inheritance altogether or establishing a modest quota, com-
bined with the right kind of supportive legislation, did succeed in creating
a gradual, and voluntary, evolution toward workers' democracies, this
would, I suggest, be a significant bonus.33
Throughout the world today, capitalism is on the defensive. Its many
enemies point to the extreme inequalities of wealth it generates, to the
shameless inequalities of opportunity, and they ask if such a system
32. For more on the potential gains, see David Schweickart, Capitalism or Worker Control?
(New York: Praeger, I980).
33. Ronald Chester believes that any reform in inheritance law that would greatly reduce
the vast inequalities of opportunity attributable to inheritance today might provide yet
another bonus. Chester writes that "numerous observers, including J. B. Mays (who is
British) and Americans such as E. H. Sutherland and Daniel Bell believe that preaching
equal opportunity without its fulfillment has made American social structure powerfully
criminogenic." Chester, Inheritance, Wealth and Society (Bloomington: Indiana University
Press, I982), p. I6I. So greatly reducing these vast inequalities of opportunity may, he
argues, pave the way toward significant reductions in property crime.
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
155 Is Inheritance
Justified?
34. On the relationship between capitalism and certain freedoms see, for example, Fried-
man, Capitalism & Freedom, especially chap. i.
This content downloaded from 200.130.19.155 on Tue, 20 Dec 2016 20:00:22 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms