TByrd PHI210 Essay 3.0
TByrd PHI210 Essay 3.0
TByrd PHI210 Essay 3.0
Tyron E. Byrd-Dubail
Essay on the Problem of Evil, what it means about God, and the Rationalist Defenses
PHL-210
I : Introduction
The problem of evil lies as follows: If God is all good/ loving, all knowing, and all
powerful, then why does evil exist? If evil exists and He can do nothing about it, then we must
conclude that he is not all powerful. If evil exists and He can do something about it (=all
powerful) but does not, then we must conclude that He is not all loving. If evil exists and he can
do something about it and he is all good / loving, then He must not know, and thusly not be all
The problem of evil has been a topic since Greek antiquity. The first formal modern
exploration of this issue is generally attributed to David Hume, a Scottish philosopher, historian,
and essayist who lived from 1711-1776. “His major philosophical works- A Treatise of Human
Natural Religion (1779) remain deeply and widely influential. (Morris & Brown, 2019) The
oldest formulation of the problem of evil is ascribed to Epicurus, by proxy of Hume, who
attributes to him the following quotation, “Is [God] willing to prevent evil, but not able? Then He
is impotent. Is He able, but not willing? Then He is malevolent. Is He both able and willing?
In Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, first published in 1779 (Morris & Brown,
2019) Hume utilizes a dialogue format to explore a conversation between two characters,
Cleanthes and Demea, personifications of the prevailing philosophical thoughts at the time,
through whose conversations he introduces the problem of evil. Cleanthes represents the
“Dominant, progressive strain, consisting primarily of theologians in the British Royal Society,
3
who were fascinated by probability and the previous century’s impressive successes in
experimental natural philosophy (Morris & Brown, 2019).” Demea plays antagonist, suggesting
to Cleanthes that any attempt to quantify God is inherently reductive, “demeaning God’s mystery
and majesty (Morris & Brown, 2019)”. Demea accuses Cleanthes of “anthropomorphism,” while
Cleanthes dubs Demea “a mystic,” (Morris & Brown, 2019). At the end of the dialogue, there is
a statement, “the idea of God, as meaning an infinitely intelligent, wise, and good Being, arises
from reflecting on the operations of our own mind, and augmenting, without limit, those qualities
Scholars have later interpreted this as Demea being “The champion of these conservative
traditionalists,” since he argues parallels from a cosmological argument of God, first proposed by
St. Thomas Aquinas in his proof Five Ways, a series of rational approaches to religion expanding
off of concepts introduced by Aristotle. (Solomon et al., 2017) The Cosmological argument
summarized is that “Everything has to be cause by or created from something else (Solomon et
al., 2017),” which Aristotle called “a prime mover,” in reference to God. Deists have argued over
whether God plays an active part in the management of the universe post creation, to which St.
Thomas Aquinas stipulated that he thinks of God as a first cause in the creation of the universe
and also its day to day management/ the safeguarding of its existence. “We see that things which
lack intelligence, such as natural bodies, act for an end, and this is evident from their acting
always, or nearly always, in the same way, so as to obtain the best result. Hence it is plain that
they achieve their end, not fortuitously, but designedly. Now whatever lacks intelligence cannot
move towards an end, unless it be directed by some being endowed with knowledge and
intelligence; as the arrow is shot to its mark by the archer. Therefore, some intelligent being
exists by whom all natural things are directed to their end; and this being we call God.15
4
(Solomon et al., 2017)”. St. Thomas Aquinas’s Summa Theologica (1266-1273) would go on to
partially inspire Hume’s response via Dialogues on Natural Religion. (Solomon et al., 2017)
II : Thesis
their respective defenses against the problem of evil and what it infers about God; followed by
my position that the problem of evil does not mean that God does not exist, that if God exists, he
created the universe or just is the universe, and he doesn’t care about human beings. God doesn’t
have emotions and is unknowable to us. I did start to find new belief in God while crafting this
essay but I am now ambivalent about whether or not God exists. Any inference due to the
problem of evil is one that, in my utilitarian viewpoint that parallels Camus (who thought that
there is “no guarantee that justice will ever be realized, that life is ‘absurd’, and that any meaning
to be found in life must come from our struggling against the unfairness and irrationality we find
is known as, “the father of modern philosophy,” and one of the greatest writers of the
Renaissance. He was the first of the Rationalists. “Descartes was a radical voluntarist who
thought that all truth, including what we take to be necessary truth, depends on the will of God.
Care needs to be taken in how this view is expressed, for Descartes did not hold simply that what
we take to be necessary in fact is contingent. He held that actually necessary truth depends on
5
God’s unconstrained will, such that even propositions that are logically contradictory might have
been simultaneously true. Reason itself thus seems no longer reliable, and experience would
seem to be the only way of determining which of the worlds even beyond logic such a powerful
Descartes believed that rational, intuitive reflection on the nature of reality could be
utilized to derive further truths about reality. “Rationalists generally develop their view in two
steps. First, they argue that there are cases where the content of our concepts or knowledge
outstrips the information that sense experience can provide. Second, they construct accounts of
how reason, in some form or other, provides that additional information about the external world.
… One view, generally associated with Descartes (Rules, Rule II and Rule III, pp. 1–4), is that
what we know by intuition is certain, beyond even the slightest doubt, while what we believe, or
even know, on the basis of sense experience is at least somewhat uncertain. (Markie & Folescu,
2021)”.
Descartes basically argued that the human intellect is weaker than we assume, possessing
a limited power that can not extend to the greater boundaries of reality outside of our very
narrow perspective. While he accredited much ability to intellect, he did not extend this
confidence to the problem of evil and what it meant about God. “From all this, I perceive that the
cause of my errors is neither the God-given power of willing, considered in itself, for it is
extremely extensive and perfect of its kind; nor the power of understanding, for whatever I
understand, since my understanding is a gift of God, most certainly I understand it correctly, nor
is there any possibility of my being deceived in this. So what is the origin of my errors? It can
only be this: that, since the range of the will is greater than that of the intellect, I do not confine it
within the same limits, but extend it even to matters I do not understand; and since it is
6
indifferent to these, it easily falls away from the true and the good, and this is both how I come to
be deceived and how I come to sin. (Descartes, 2008: 42) (Rivis-Tipei, 2020).” Furthermore,
Descartes argues for “Cartesian Dualism,” that is that there are “two kinds of substance [sic.] :
thinking things, or minds, and extended things, or bodies.” (Dea et al., 2017) He thought that the
mind and body formed a composite, laying ground to the mind-body problem and creating an
intersectionality to the problem of evil and God. Notably, he thought God was a differing
substance from mind or body. “In the Principles, Descartes defined “substance” as a thing that
exists such that its existence does not depend on any other thing. He immediately added that,
strictly speaking, the term applies only to God, who, as uncreated, alone depends on nothing else
While he does not specifically address the problem of evil, it is considered by Brian
Calvert that “The Fourth Meditation can be regarded, without undue distortion, as dealing with a
limited version of the problem of evil is not, it seems to me, a contentious proposition (Calvert
1972).” Calvert asserts that Descartes selects one feature of the triad mentioned by Hume
(“error”), and discusses “whether this particular feature is consistent with the existence of an all-
powerful, perfect, non-deceiving deity. (Calvert 1972). Calvert also stipulates that Descartes
again addresses error in Synopsis of the Meditations, where Descartes says, “Error committed in
the pursuit of good and evil- but only of that which occurs in the judgement and discernment of
the true and false; and that I do not intend to speak of beliefs which belong to faith or to the
conduct of life, but of those which pertain to speculative truth. … (Descartes, 1960).” Descartes
argues more directly that “man misuses the faculties which God has given him, and so the
responsibility for the occurrence of error is attributable to man and not to God, (Descartes,
1960)” an argument implementing the ‘free will solution,’ which is that “God creates us with
7
free will, the ability to do what we want to do. Accordingly, we have created the evil and
suffering in the world ourselves, and it is no reflection of God’s goodness.” (Solomon et al.,
2017) One of the difficulties of quantifying Descartes’ views on the problem of evil is that on the
surface level, the free will argument alludes to moral evil, but Descartes answers this by saying,
“If we make a judgement (use our free will) in the absence of clear and distinct ideas (that is, an
inability to extend our perspective to the realm of God), we misuse our freedom; errors are liable
to occur, and often do (Calvert, 1972).” Descartes’ conclusion to the problem of evil, including
natural evil, would appear to thusly be that humans are incapable of truly perceiving evil, due to
limitations placed upon them by the gift of free will. Descartes’ ideas gave birth to rationalism,
the idea that knowledge is acquired through reason, and directly inspire Spinoza and Leibniz.
Benedict Spinoza (1632-1677) was a Dutch rationalist born to refugees of the Spanish
Inquisition in the Jewish diaspora of Amsterdam. “He was thoroughly educated in both Jewish
and medieval Christian philosophy, but his unconventional opinions cause him to be banished
from his native Amsterdam. His books were banned, and he spent much of his life working as a
lens grinder (Solomon et al., 2017).” One of the trademarks of Spinoza is his consideration of
substance, which he termed “Deus sive Natura” (God, in other words, nature) (Dea et al., 2017).
“Spinoza’s philosophy is first and foremost a philosophy of necessity. In the context of this
philosophy, good and evil are relative notions, devoid of rational meaning. They can only exist
by reference to a purpose. Good and evil are defined by their relation to the exigencies of reason.
Good is what promotes knowledge. It is a superior form of knowledge, the philosophical one, the
knowledge of substance, identical with God or Nature. In Spinoza’s system, evil is an “illusion”
8
that results from ignorance (Ricoeur, 1974: 311-312). In particular, Spinoza completely
abandons the “suspect argumentation of theodicy” (Ibidem: 312). Benefits and catastrophes, he
points out, happen without discrimination to both the good and the bad, both believers and
Like Descartes, Spinoza concludes that evil is an illusion that rises from our limited
perspective. Unlike Descartes, Spinoza did not believe that there two substances which compose
the subjective reality (body and mind) and a third undescribed (or perhaps, substanceless-ness)
that composes God, positing instead that God is everything, and everything is God. Thusly, there
is one substance and its modes, a monist idea that infers the inter-connectedness of everything
and was rejected by many of his peers who “saw that it eliminated any and all distinction
between creator, God, and His Creation (Dea et al., 2017).” Spinoza further detailed “substance”
exists because it does, which is an ontological argument, that is a “philosophical argument for
rational belief in God posited by 11th century monk Saint Anselm (Solomon et al., 2017).”
Ontological arguments rest on an axis that: 1) We can not conceive of God except as infinite and
perfect; 2) A being who had all perfections except for the perfection of existence, would not be
perfect; and 3) Therefore the most perfect being necessarily exists.” Phrased more simply, “to
prove by logic alone that, from the very idea we have of God, it is necessary that God exists.”
Thusly, Descartes and Spinoza, despite their disagreement on the nature of substance,
predominantly overlap in agreeance that humans can not perceive evil, but diverge upon God as
an actor. Spinoza suggests God is an actor “creating the universe from the outside through an act
of will,” (Dea et al., 2017) but perceived him as immanent (not outside of us or distinct from the
Universe), unlike Descartes who viewed God as transcendent (beyond the ordinary world of
human experience.) (Solomon et al., 2017). Thusly, while the two both conclude that humans can
9
not understand evil, there is a difference: To Descartes, humans are failing to understand
something beyond the world of human experience (God lies outside), while to Spinoza, humans
are failing to understand something that they are a piece of the overall organism inside of (You
are a piece of God, and vice versa). Spinoza’s idea built off the foundation established by
Descartes and he would in turn inspire Leibniz, directly an intentional meeting and indirectly as a
contemporary.
and mathematician from Leipzig. He is one of the most gifted polymaths to have ever lived,
much to the frustration of many of his peers. “When one compares the talents one has with those
of a Leibniz, one is tempted to throw away one's books and go die quietly in the dark of some
forgotten corner (Oeuvres complètes, vol. 7, p. 678) (Look, 2013).” His education was “chiefly
scholastic in nature, though he was also exposed to elements of Renaissance humanism.” When
he was a student, the philosophies of Descartes had not yet had significant impact on syllabus,
and Leibniz would be an emergent thinker in a new discipline (Look, 2013). “Unlike most of the
great philosophers of the period, Leibniz did not write a magnum opus; there is no single work
that can be said to contain the core of his thought. While he did produce two books, Theodicy
(1710) and the New Essays Concerning Human Understanding (finished in 1704 but not
published until 1765), prospective students of Leibniz's philosophy must piece together his ideas
from his myriad writings: essays published in scholarly and popular journals, unpublished works
left abandoned by their author, and his many letters. (Look, 2013).
10
Leibniz was critical of Descartes, due to the principles of Cartesian duality specifically
pertaining to the corporeal substance. Leibniz was attracted to the “mechanical philosophy”
(Look, 2013) of Descartes, but perceived two major issues with the rectification of this idea.
Problem 1: If the essence of body is “extension” (Look, 2013) [sic.? of matter], then Descartes is
“endorsing the view that matter is infinitely divisible.” If this were the case, he posits, then that
would mean that there is “in its nature, no source of activity (Look, 2013),” which means that the
bodily objects of the world cannot count as substances. Basically, Leibniz assumed if matter was
infinitely divisible, that, having no quality of inherent one-ness, an ability to be something other
Leibniz argues directly and overtly for the existence of God in his Discourse on
Metaphysics, which presents his argument as thus: “God is perfect. Power and knowledge are
perfections, and insofar as they belong to God, they do not have limits; When it follows that
God, possessing supreme and infinite wisdom, acts in the most perfect manner, not only
metaphysically, but also morally speaking (Look, 2013).” As a result, one can directly conclude
that Leibniz argues on an axiom of “least of all evils,” based upon his accreditation of the triad to
God and resultant reality, including what humans perceive as evil. “Indeed, when it comes to the
creation of the world, the “sufficient reason” for God's choice of this world is that this world is
the “best” of all possible worlds; in other words, in this case the Principle of Sufficient Reason is
essentially the Principle of the Best (Look, 2013).” Based on notions of truth and metaphysics
which originate in Aristotle’s Organon (cf. Posterior Analytics I.4), Leibniz concludes “in every
true affirmative proposition, whether necessary or contingent, universal or particular, the notion
of the predicate is in some way included in that of the subject. Praedicatum inest subjecto;
otherwise I do not know what truth is” (G II 56/L 337) (Look, 2013).” Leibniz goes on to state
11
principles of identity and contradiction that he uses as axioms for his reason: “a proposition
cannot be true and false at the same time, and that therefore A is A and cannot be A.” He
(1) No two substances can resemble each other completely and be distinct. (PII)
(5) The number of substances does not naturally increase and decrease.
(6) Every substance is like a complete world and like a mirror of God or of the whole universe,
At this point, it gets very difficult to derive exactly what Leibniz means when he is not
speaking directly. “Leibniz is not as clear as one would like him to be, for at this point in his
career it is possible to read him as seeing that something is a substance so long as it has a soul or
a substantial form, whereas later in his career it seems more clearly to be the case that the only
substances are souls or soul-like entities, the monads. In other words, Leibniz can be interpreted
are composites of matter and form. This has been the subject of debate in the field, but this entry
cannot adjudicate the matter (For more on this dispute, see Look 2010.) (Look, 2013).”
Thusly, Leibniz’s views were subject to change based upon his relative experience
throughout life, and his former ardency in multiple substances progresses towards monism,
which he accredits to “soul like entities,” his vague description of his rationalization of monads
(Look, 2013), settling on the concept of indivisibility as his underlying belief for what constitutes
12
renders it impossible for a body, or matter alone, to be a substance. Thus, Cartesian corporeal
substance, the essence of which is simply extension, cannot exist as substance. Put differently,
Leibniz's argument is that nothing that is divisible is a substance; a Cartesian chunk of matter is
Leibniz writes, “I hold that philosophy cannot be better reestablished and reduced to
something precise, than by recognizing only substances or complete beings endowed with a true
unity, together with the different states that succeed one another; everything else is only
phenomena, abstractions, or relations” (G II 101/AG 89). If this is the case, then aggregates of
simple substances are merely phenomena and fail to have the reality of the underlying simples.
Further, the bodies of natural philosophy, the bodies of the world we observe around us, would
seem to be in some sense mere phenomena (Look, 2013).” One can not help but be reminded of
the search in Cosmological fields for the grand unifying theory, which seems adjacent to
“Leibniz sets out a series of distinctions for human knowledge or cognition (cognitio):
knowledge is either obscure or clear; clear knowledge is either confused or distinct; distinct
intuitive. Now, according to Leibniz, clear knowledge means being able to recognize something
that is represented to us, for example, a rose; and knowledge is both clear and distinct when one
can enumerate marks sufficient to distinguish a rose from other things. When one can give such
an enumeration, one possesses a distinct notion or concept and is thus able to give a nominal
definition of the thing. Further, if all the marks that form part of a distinct notion are themselves
13
distinctly known, then the cognition is adequate. And, finally, if a notion is complex and we are
able to consider all its component notions simultaneously, then our knowledge of it is intuitive.
Ultimately, Leibniz holds that human beings have intuitive knowledge only of primary notions
and propositions, whereas God, of course, has intuitive knowledge of all things.” One is
reminded of an old Buddhist kaon, that, roughly paraphrased suggests: “When I began studying
Buddhism, I thought that a mountain was a mountain, then I learned that a mountain was the sum
of all the qualities that makes a mountain: trees, birds, animals, rocks, the sky, and so on. Once I
had studied Buddhism for a long time and no longer was a novice, I realized that all there is to a
mountain, is to be a mountain.” Leibniz wrote so much that it becomes difficult to “resolve all of
his writings and simpler truths until we reach the primitives (G VI 612/AG 217) (Look, 2013),”
before his time. He upholds to “the principle of sufficient reasons,” and accepts “innate ideas and
denies that the mind is at birth a tabula rasa, or blank slate (Look, 2013)”. He was a believer of
platonic knowledge, that is that knowledge can be derived the existence of innate ideas, and
directly cites such ideas, referring explicitly to Plato’s “fundamental questioning of the origin of
ideas (A VI vi 48/RB 48) (Look, 2013).” Leibniz remains firm throughout his life that the human
mind and soul is immateria. Leibniz also posited that “perception can not be explained in
mechanical or materialistic terms,” and directly argues against machine intelligence, a few
Like Spinoza, Leibniz based his ideas on the existence of God on the ontological
argument. Leibniz and Spinoza were contemporaries and discussed such ideas; having met once
14
in the 1670’s while Leibniz was on the way to Hanover (Look, 2013). Put most simply, Leibniz
argues that because the status quo exists (Quod ens perfectissimum existit) that it exists and is the
most perfect order. “Leibniz is then able to claim that there can be no inconsistency among
perfections, since a perfection, in being simple and positive, is unanalyzable and incapable of
being enclosed by limits. That is, if A and B are perfections, then the proposition “A and B are
incompatible” cannot be demonstrated because A and B are simples, nor can the proposition be
known per se. Therefore, it is possible that any and all perfections are in fact compatible. And,
possible (Look, 2013). If one is understanding correctly, his posit is basically, “Because only one
watch exists, and there is no other watch to compare it to, that watch is a (most) perfect watch.”
(5) If it is possible for a necessary being to exist, then a necessary being does
exist.
Unlike Spinoza, Leibniz also appeals to the cosmological argument, that is that
everything was caused by or made by something else, that there must have been a first cause,
which Aristotle referred to as, “the prime mover,” and St. Thomas Aquinas stipulated was God.
15
(Solomon et al., 2017) He touches on this in Theodicy, one of his best known works for the
phrase coined eponymously (Theodicy/ theodicies: an attempt to justify or defend God in the
face of evil by answering the triad: God is all good, powerful, and knowledgeable.) In a separate
“(1) God is omnipotent and omniscient and benevolent and the free creator of
(2) Things could have been otherwise–i.e., there are other possible worlds.
(Premise)
(3) Suppose this world is not the best of all possible worlds. (I.e., “The world
could be better.”)
(4) If this world is not the best of all possible worlds, then at least one of the
God did not know how this world would develop after his creation of it (i.e.
there were no other possible worlds from which God could choose.
(5) But, any one or more of the disjuncts of (4) contradicts (1) or (2).
(6) Therefore, this world is the best of all possible worlds. (Look, 2013)”
“He [Sic. Leibniz] tells us in the Discourse on Metaphysics, first, that “…the happiness
of minds is the principal aim of God…” (A VI iv 1537/AG 38) and, second, that “God has
16
chosen the most perfect world, that is, the one which is at the same time the simplest in
hypotheses and the richest in phenomena” (A VI iv 1538/AG 39). So, is this world of genocide
and natural disaster better than a world containing only onemultifoliate rose? Yes, because the
former is a world in which an infinity of minds perceive and reflect on the diversity of
phenomena caused by a modest number of simple laws. To the more difficult question whether
there is a better world with perhaps a little less genocide and natural disaster Leibniz can only
respond that, if so, God would have brought it into actuality. And this, of course, is to say that
question of evil are ontological, cosmological, rationalist, monist, and based in the least of all
VI : My Views
My beliefs in the question of evil and God are complicated and have changed many times
since starting this. If one had asked me two years ago what I think about the problem of evil and
what it infers about God, I would have told you that I don’t believe in any God and doubt that
God exists.
I grew up believing in God, until my parents divorced and my mother remarried someone
in an Christian Cult that warped any concept of God to manipulate others, and who told me
frequently that I was going to hell; while they pretended to speak in tongues and have seizures. I
tried to find a healthy application of religion during this time and many people told me I was
going to hell because I wasn’t their religion. One could conclude that I encountered moral evil
and concluded from it that God does not exist in any way that I recognize.
17
spare me from my degrading future and was denied out of spite the FAFSA classification that
covered my homelessness, so I went into the military. The superintendent that mocked me for
being the son of a drunk, who he accused of trying to fraud the state, was another encounter with
moral evil that in my naivety and failure to adequate protect myself, further eroded any belief in
God due to the question of moral evil. In the military, I had an abusive and toxic command to a
degree of severity that it broke many people and embroiled me deeply into an NCIS investigation
fighting structural power embedded into the upper rank structures, which was a pyrrhic victory
that cost my career but saved lives. I was right by 2016. More moral evil.
I also during this time witnessed multitudinous examples of what life for people is like in
the poorest countries in the world: children pickpocketing and robbing each other if they are
larger; beggars sitting on the roadside, desperation personified without arms, legs, or having
disfigured bodies. I responded to typhoons, tsunamis, and earthquakes and have witnessed the
scale of devastation unleashed from natural evil, and how it affects the poorest people in the
world; and this further reinforced in me that God doesn’t exist. I have been homeless after I
crashed and burned trying to move to Honolulu with friends because I had no family and had to
make it with no contacts and rebuilt a life from that. While in this position, I found out that for
every homeless person that just abuses drugs, there is also an old Chinese woman whose husband
died and she didn’t have a sound financial position afterwards, or a kind old man who got into a
car wreck with his wife, who died; and his TBI prevents him from understanding the value of
money and he can’t keep a job not because of temperament issues but orientation issues. I have
found through the story of my father that you can save lives thirteen years and the second you
don’t, you will be abandoned if you no longer do that and not a single person will check on you.
18
My experiences at 24, losing my job without any person willing to help me pivot in the same
employer to IT, or to help me access a network that would allow me placement anywhere else
echoed this, after serving my community for years. Community is about convenience, man is a
In the United States, people with too much medical debt don’t get to rent apartments that
have livable conditions, and you can wind up homeless. I know this from experience. It can be so
bad that a plane ride to another country changes your entire fate and causes your native country
to perceive you entirely differently based upon their old metrics, because they are no longer
parameters that bind you but assess you differently out of different context, while the sum is
unchanged. It doesn’t matter if you served your country, nobody cares, nobody can do anything,
If God knows, and is all powerful, he doesn’t care. If He knows, and is good; then he is
not all powerful. If he is all powerful and all good, then maybe he has never heard my father’s
story or those of some of the individuals I have met who honestly just deserved better. It doesn’t
really matter which possibility it is because the end sum is the same, and from the programmatic/
functional viewpoint; this means that the modulation in-between is just not at all anything
cognizant or powerful. It’s just causal Boolean gates through which we pass.
When I was younger, people used to invest in me more, but the older I get, the amount of
people willing to stop and take time to interact with me constructively without fiscal payment
has diminished pretty much to 0 and I believe that people expect you to, by the age of 30; be
already polished, even if you are simply a formerly homeless teenager who is trying to hide the
gaping holes in their education. Even if you lack of any access to structural resources, lost any
positive relationship with your body at a square knee at twenty four years old, and have spent the
19
rest of time since then being increasingly harassed by people when formerly you had always
experienced validation. Over and over my life has proven to be mostly random, without cause,
full of moral and natural evil despite the amount of work in the opposite direction you do (if
anything people who can not refrain from helping are taken advantage of the most frequently),
and there is little apparent benefit to caring about other people, investing in them, or sparing
them from finite amounts of suffering if able to do so. I think that the only meaning comes from
what you give to it, based upon what you feel like giving, and why. “To believe in God simply as
an initial creative force is to believe much less than most would take to be required, even for
what many of us would consider the most rudimentary theistic belief. A God who is conceived of
worshipped, not a God who gives meaning to our lives. In many people’s opinion (both theists
and atheists), such a force is not worthy of the name “God” at all. (Solomon et al., 2017)”
If you asked me a week ago, I would have said that after my experiences in the war (no
Atheists in foxholes), writing this and trying to formulate counter arguments against God, and
after starting to question my faith everything in my life started working out as if there was a deity
overhead finally un-punishing me for losing my belief; that I am starting to believe and feel some
sense of energy inside me that I have not perceived in decades. But if you ask me now, I simply
do not care, I am indeterminate, I don’t see the point one way or another and it is a moot question
for someone like me. The problem of moral and natural evil is too great to overcome, and there
are no deterministic statements one can make about substance, because even though we know
certain types of matter are divisible, and that right now we perceive a lowest subatomic level
somewhere around quarks; the other perspective is that this is subject to change and any
supposition is based on one’s personal understanding, not actual truth; just assumed truth. This
20
contradicts Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibniz; who thought that from this you could infer greater
I have been completely blind and paralyzed and regained much of my sight and motor
ability. During this time I thought of the parable of Saul/ Paul, how I had lost my faith, the small
mistakes that had accrued in my life the less good influences that I had; for the first time in a
long time I prayed to any and all gods, on all radio channels so to speak; but when I was spared
from my condition the suffering of life on the other end was so great that I found no respite, no
cause to belief, and I hung up the phone. After the past year, witnessing events at scales
incomprehensible and the first healthy expression of faith that I had been exposed to in a long
time, and being confronted with this question in class, I reformulated all of that. Then everything
began to crash and now, I am questioning if my emergent faith was just the unjustified reaches of
someone with no healthy authority present in their life for fifteen years formulating counter
arguments against faith while things so large as to be perceived as divine providence began to
manifest themselves, and in that I fell into delusion. At this moment, my belief is a coin flipping
through the air but my interest to where it will land is completely removed. We will see a week
from now, a year from now, five years from now. If things go well, which right now I am
bleeding conviction, I could wind up a deist. If not, it is just another cruel joke. I have suffered
too much in life to care. I can believe, not believe, what I do believe is that none of it matters.
I don’t deny evil. I think it’s the least of all evils only in the way that standing neck deep
in water while it goes up is “standing in the least water” that you could be standing in at that
time, provided the room was infinitely large and without boundary, devoid of anything to climb
to. There could certainly be more evil, that’s for sure, everyone could express their negative
freedom right now and punch someone else in the nose, but they don’t; at least most of the time,
21
so there is some conclusion of ‘the least,’ but that doesn’t mean it will stay a static quality, just
that the present, inherently a static quality that generates movement, like the peak of a wave
carrying a surfer. I don’t think it’s absurd to conclude that we have free will, I’ve seen TBI’s
change many people in ways that destroyed their entire lives. Maybe we have some, but that
doesn’t mean that a brick to the face can’t take it away (Solomon et al., 2017).
Like Camus, I think life is absurd. There is no guarantee of justice. I think some people
are bad people but born in the right places and accomplish great damage to others for many
innate reasons. Some people are good people but are crushed by the absolute cruelty of life until
they have no position with which to leverage goodness to any meaningful result. Moral evil and
natural evil is everywhere. While what you do sometimes has connection to what happens to you
the truth is that many things occur without reason, and you could just as likely tomorrow have a
stroke and wake up a rather changed person. My belief is closer to Voltaire, than the rationalists;
who I think spend far too much time attributing one thing or another to a derivative property of
the divisibility or indivisibility of something. Voltaire suggested that God is just a hypothesis for
physics, and that it is “as absurd to say of God that God is just or unjust as to say that God is blue
accounts. The rationalists agreed that you could infer posits about God from “rational, intuitive
reflection” (Dea et Al., 2017). This is contrary to my perception and that of theologians like Karl
Rahner, who despite their belief in God compared to my lack, says that God is an absolute
mystery that we can’t understand and that we can not understand God as a person in our finite
sense.” (Solomon et al., 2017) Rationalists like Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibniz are worried
about if things are 1 or 0 and what this infers about god and evil. I am more concerned that from
22
1 and 0; you can derive all real numbers and through constructs derived from these describe all
things in perfect language if one was sufficiently capable, but that nobody is. If God is 1 and not
0, this denies God omnipotency, and vice versa for if God is 0; but not if God is all numbers.
VII : Conclusion
Hume, in extension of an old Epicuran philosophical question on the nature of God; as addressed
by three rationalist writers: Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibniz. René Descartes was the father of
philosophical rationalism, not a monist, and separated man’s ability to perceive and the
substance of reality. He severed truth and perception in his attempt to answer the problem of evil,
concluding that man can not know evil and thusly not judge it; a conclusion he attributes to free
will, which both is the root of moral and natural evil, by allowing us to ‘incorrectly’ perceive
‘natural evil’ as ‘evil,’ instead of a process belonging to God which we are incapable of judging,
invoking the free will argument. Spinoza was a monist and utilized ontological arguments,
favoring tautology to reckon that the set of all sets is the most perfect set and that a subset can
not judge the perfection of a set above it due to the impossibility of a piece of a corpus to
perceive itself within the whole that it is a part of (amongst many other arguments too
multitudinous to address in a single portion of essay). Leibniz argued both for and against
monism at different parts of his life, made arguments ontological and cosmological, and built
intense metaphysical frameworks in math to found his arguments. All three writers discussed the
nature of substance at great lengths and the implications it had upon the nature of reality, the
problem of evil, and God. While they disagreed about the nature of such substances, all three
agreed on concepts of rational reflection to derive greater truths about the problem of evil, God,
23
and what it means about reality. They all defied formerly empiricist ideas such as the idea that
people are born tabula rasa, and all believed that truths can be known a priori.
god, that the indivisibility or divisibility of substance to infer things about god denies him
omnipotency, a major part of the triad (if he exists); which I rectify by suggesting that by
denying either system and proposing a system modelled after of computers, which were invented
so far after the lives of the Rationalists that I doubt they ever considered such a stance, not
having seen the ability of recursive iteration expressed within; which hypothetically resolves
God’s omnipotency, as well as infers that God is perhaps neither transcendent or immanent, but
that you can choose which of these filters you apply based on utensil purpose. Perhaps Descartes
would surmise that this is “misuses the faculties which God has given… and so responsibility for
The ongoing discussion of the problem of evil is one that can never be meaningfully
solved except for individual notion during the course of one’s life as they settle into frameworks
of argument and synthesize belief. One’s belief in a construct addressing the problem of evil may
be unsolved as readily one day to the next, if an individual is confronted with drastic enough
stimuli to spark conflict and reflection upon their beliefs. As for society, until every human and
and for that reason has driven conversation since antiquity. Its relevance today is just as
legitimate as it was during the time of Epicurus or John Hume, and possibly more so as we find
sometimes in the image of man, manifest; recalling arguments Leibniz made about the
24
indivisibility of experience (he posited that no machine, however intelligent, can have
In final summation: The debate of what ‘substance’ is played a far greater role in the
discussion of the problem of evil and what it means about God and reality than one might
References
Morris, W. E., & Brown, C. R. (2019, April 17). David Hume. Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy. Retrieved February 17, 2023, from
25
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2022/entries/hume/
Rivis-Tipei, I. (2020). The Problem of Natural Evil Part One: Evil in Philosophical
Discourse. Journal of Humanistic and Social Studies, 11(2), 151–163.
Dea, S., Walsh, J., & Lennon, T. M. (2017, November 6). Continental rationalism. Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved February 17, 2023, from
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/continental-rationalism/
Look, B. C. (2013, July 24). Gottfried Wilhelm leibniz. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Retrieved February 17, 2023, from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/leibniz/
Solomon, R. C., & Higgins, K. M. (2017). 3: God. In The big questions: A short
introduction to philosophy (pp. 80–94). essay, Cengage.
Markie, P., & Folescu, M. (2021, September 2). Rationalism vs. empiricism. Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved February 17, 2023, from
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rationalism-empiricism/
Calvert, B. (1972). Descartes and the Problem of Evil. JSTOR. Retrieved February 15, 2023,
from https://www-jstor-org.ezproxy.snhu.edu/stable/40230379