Jung - Lamarckianism
Jung - Lamarckianism
Jung - Lamarckianism
Abstract: Whether Jung was a Lamarckian or not has always been a hotly debated
topic, both within the post-Jungian community and amongst scholars with an interest
in Jung in the wider academic community. Yet surprisingly few substantial pieces of work
have been dedicated to it and, to my mind, no one has yet managed to do justice to all the
subtleties involved. The scholars who have claimed that Jung is a Lamarckian have, for
the most part, oversimplified the debate by failing to discuss the passages in which Jung
appears to be defending himself against Lamarckism; the scholars who have defended
Jung against Lamarckism, however, have as a rule not adequately dealt with the question
of whether these passages actually get Jung off the hook. This paper will attempt to correct
this imbalance by putting forward four key passages spanning Jung’s career that all
represent conclusive evidence that Jung was indeed a Lamarckian. After discussing these,
it will then deal in detail with the passages in which Jung appears to be defending himself
against Lamarckism, making the case that they do not represent a defence against
Lamarckism at all and have therefore generally been misinterpreted by many scholars.
Introduction
In his controversial book The Jung Cult, Richard Noll has the following to say
about Jung’s theories:
Jung and his theories have remained well outside the established institutional worlds
of science and medicine, as they have been regarded, with justification, as inconsistent
with the greater scientific paradigms of the twentieth century.
(Noll 1994, p. 6)
A very common perception of Jung’s work which, if true, would certainly prove
Noll’s point, is the notion that Jung was a Lamarckian. Lamarckism is a theory
Genes [. . .] indirectly control the manufacture of bodies, and the influence is strictly
one way: acquired characteristics are not inherited. No matter how much knowledge
and wisdom you acquire during your life, not one jot will be passed on to your chil-
dren by genetic means. Each new generation starts from scratch. A body is the genes’
way of preserving the genes unaltered.
(Dawkins 1989, p. 23)
Jung frequently claimed that the innate structures of the mind which all of
us inherit are related to certain highly typical experiences which are common
in every human life, for example having a mother, a father, or relating to
the opposite sex. Making such a claim is not necessarily a Lamarckian
position–many neo-Darwinian evolutionary psychologists have also concluded
that such innate structures exist. What Jung also claimed, however, was
that the frequent repetition throughout our ancestral history of these experi-
ences has somehow ‘engraved’ or ‘imprinted’ (both terms are used by Jung
in various texts present in the Collected Works) them on to the innate base
of our unconscious. Such statements, which seem to hint at a belief in the
inheritance of acquired characteristics, at the very least have a Lamarckian
‘ring’ to them.
These passages represent a dimension of Jung’s work which scholars who
are critical of Jung’s ideas have drawn on to make the same point that Noll
makes in the opening quote of this article, namely that Jung’s ideas are
flawed and out of touch with current scientific developments. Because evolu-
tionary theories which rely on the inheritance of acquired characteristics are
out of date, Jung’s entire body of work is out of date, too. Examples of
scholars who have made such claims are Percival (1993) and Pietikainen
(2003). The fact that Jung believed in the inheritance of acquired character-
istics and was therefore a Lamarckian, however, has also been posited as
fact by scholars favourable to Jung: examples are McDowell (2001) and
Haule (2010).
But was Jung really a Lamarckian? Answering this question is not as
straightforward as it may appear, as there are also a number of passages in
260 Ritske Rensma
[The archetypes] are in a sense the deposits of all our ancestral experiences, but they
are not the experiences themselves. So at least it seems to us, in the present limited state
of our knowledge.
(Jung, 1916 / 1928 / 1935, para. 300)
according to many writers who know his work well. The eminent Harvard
paleontologist Stephen Jay Gould wrote with admiration about Lamarck,
describing him as a ‘fine scientist’ (1992); the science journalist Michael
Balter has called him ‘one of the great scientists of his age’ (Balter 2000).
Darwin himself also recognized the importance of Lamarck, writing the
following about him in On the Origin of Species:
Lamarck was the first man whose conclusions on the subject excited much attention.
This justly celebrated naturalist first published his views in 1801. [. . .] He first did
the eminent service of arousing attention to the probability of all changes in the
organic, as well as in the inorganic world, being the result of law, and not of miraculous
interposition.
(Darwin 1897 [1859], p. xv)
Few people seem to have read Lamarck’s original works, which is perhaps the
reason why there are some common misperceptions about his ideas. One of the
most widely spread misperceptions is that Lamarck believed in a direct cause of
hereditary changes in organisms by the environment. As Mayr (1972) has
pointed out, however, Lamarck never claimed anything to this effect. Although
the environment does play an important role in Lamarck’s view of how
evolution occurred, it only produces changes in organisms in an indirect way.
This is perhaps best explained by one of the most famous examples of how
Lamarck explained the way evolution worked: that of the giraffe’s long neck.
Giraffes, as the by now somewhat clichéd way of illustrating Lamarck’s ideas
goes, have long necks because during their lives their ancestors stretched
their necks to reach high leaves, making them slightly longer because of
the repeated stretching. This longer neck was passed on to their offspring,
who then also stretched their necks, subsequently passing on their even longer
necks to their offspring. Therefore, giraffes nowadays have very long necks–the
result of a long, cumulative process of inheriting acquired characteristics from
previous generations.
Needless to say, this process of passing on acquired characteristics can only
begin when the giraffe finds itself in an environment where eating leaves from
high branches is a necessity. This feature of the environment produces in the
organism a certain need (besoin in Lamarck’s own words), namely to reach
the leaves. It is in response to this need that the acquired characteristic of a
longer neck is produced, which is then passed on to the next generation. It is
therefore not a matter of the environment producing changes in a passive
organism. Instead, Lamarck stated that use or disuse caused certain parts of
an organism’s body to enlarge or shrink. This principle, that of use or disuse,
he called ‘The first law’ in his book Philosophie Zoologique. The second law
was that such changes are inherited.
Another common misconception about Lamarck’s ideas is that they are a
kind of polar opposite to Darwin’s ideas, with which they are completely
incommensurable. This, too, is inaccurate. Darwin himself, as a matter of fact,
262 Ritske Rensma
because the experiences which they relate to have been intensely experienced. From
a Darwinian perspective, such a statement does not make sense at all. It is certainly
true that many Darwinian evolutionary psychologists have stated that innate
structures for dealing with common experiences like finding a mate or nurturing
children exist2; however, whether such an experience was intense or not is irrelevant
from a Darwinian point of view. Only the fact that the innate structure related to
dealing with the experience gave our ancestors an adaptive advantage is relevant,
not the intensity of the experience. Only from a Lamarckian perspective does such
a statement make sense: an experience which has been experienced as intense could
be seen as leaving a larger or more dominant ‘imprint’, which in turn gets inherited.
Jung also writes in this passage from Psychological Types that in the archetypes
‘all experiences [my italics, RR] are represented which have happened on this
planet since primeval times’. This statement is also incompatible with modern ways
of thinking about evolution. From a Darwinian perspective, namely, only some
experiences leave their mark on the innate structure of the psyche (albeit in an
indirect way, because the innate structure for dealing with the experience has become
a general trait through natural selection); only by subscribing to a Lamarckian
perspective can one make the case that all experiences have left their mark.
This evidence that Jung thought along Lamarckian lines in Psychological
Types is further strengthened by the fact that Jung aligns himself in this book
with a thinker who is notorious for having been a Lamarckian: the German
biologist Richard Semon. Jung refers to Semon in the first passage from
Psychological Types quoted above, in which he states the following: ‘[The
archetype] can be conceived as a mnemic deposit, an imprint or engram
(Semon)’. Semon’s concept of the engram comes from his book The Mneme
(1921), in which he put forward his ideas about how memory works in human
beings. In this book, Semon argued that stimuli which are remembered leave a
physical trace behind in the nerve tissue of the organism’s brain. Semon then went
on to claim that such memory traces–or engrams, as he called them–were inher-
itable, which is very clearly a Lamarckian position. Perhaps because of this explicit
Lamarckism, Semon is somewhat of a forgotten figure by now, but he seems to have
had somewhat of an influence on Jung, especially in the early stages of his career.
The fact that this line of influence exists, needless to say, can’t be taken as direct
evidence that Jung was a Lamarckian too. The possibility exists that Jung was
simply unfortunate in aligning himself with a thinker who was soon to be
discredited for his Lamarckian ideas, without fully believing in all of the ideas
which Semon subscribed to himself. Given the evidence stated above, however,
2
I don’t mean to claim here that evolutionary psychology is a homogenous whole, with every
scholar subscribing to the same point of view. I’m aware of the fact that there are differing theories
within the field, as well as of the fact that the field as a whole has been criticized. If, in the following
pages, I contrast Jung’s statements with what a hypothetical ‘Darwinian evolutionary psychologist’
might say, I do so only to illustrate that Jung’s statements do not make sense from a Darwinian
perspective–but do make sense from a Lamarckian perspective.
266 Ritske Rensma
I don’t think that is the right conclusion at all. Jung most definitely thought
along Lamarckian lines in this period of his career, and although the fact that
he references Semon doesn’t fully prove this hypothesis, it does certainly lend
strong support to it.
The second text which I would like to offer as evidence that Jung thought along
Lamarckian lines is related to his ideas about race and stems from the 1930s. In
this period Jung for some time defended the position that there exists not only a
collective unconscious, which is present in all human beings, but also a racial
unconscious, which is different for each race. Jung made statements about this
topic primarily in the 1930s–I have found no such statements from the 1940s
or later. Some of the statements which Jung makes when discussing this idea of a
racial unconscious have distinct Lamarckian overtones. The passage which I would
like to offer as evidence for this comes from his Visions seminar from 1933, in
which he says the following about the German racial unconscious:
The remains of ancestral life which are found in the [German] unconscious consist in
what the ancestors have done; there are memories of riding in carts, of using weapons,
so one must necessarily do something similar, in order to put those ancestral memories
into practice.
(Jung 1998 [1930–1934], p. 977)
contains is for me evidence that Jung was still a Lamarckian in 1943. The
passage in question reads as follows:
One of the commonest and at the same time most impressive experiences is the apparent
movement of the sun every day. We certainly cannot discover anything of the kind in the
unconscious, so far as the known physical process is concerned. What we do find, on the
other hand, is the myth of the sun-hero in all its countless variations. It is this myth, and
not the physical process, that forms the sun archetype. The same can be said of the phases
of the moon. The archetype is a kind of readiness to produce over and over again the same
or similar mythical ideas. Hence it seems as though what is impressed upon the
unconscious were exclusively the subjective fantasy-ideas aroused by the physical process
[my italics, RR]. We may therefore assume that the archetypes are recurrent impressions
made by subjective reactions.
(Jung, 1916 / 1918 / 1926 / 1936 / 1943, para. 109)
The key sentence here is the penultimate one: ‘Hence it seems as though what is
impressed upon the unconscious were exclusively the subjective fantasy-ideas
aroused by the physical process’. What Jung is claiming here goes directly
against the current Darwinian way of thinking, in that he states that what he
calls ‘subjective fantasy-ideas’ have left an impression on the innate structure
of the unconscious. This is a claim which does not hold up if one thinks along
neo-Darwinian lines. A Darwinian evolutionary psychologist could claim that
we inherit innate structures which give rise to similar fantasy-ideas as our
forebears (in fact, this is what Darwinian post-Jungians like Anthony Stevens
argue is the case). What is not possible, however, is that fantasy-ideas leave
an ‘imprint’ which is then inherited: that is only possible if one believes that
acquired characteristics can be inherited, and Jung makes it very clear indeed
that he believes this in this passage, calling the archetypes ‘recurrent impressions
made [my italics, RR] by subjective reactions’. The line of causality which Jung
puts forward in this last sentence is distinctly Lamarckian: subjective reactions
make an impression on the unconscious, which in turn gets inherited. Jung,
then, was rather clearly a Lamarckian in the early 1940s as well.
The last piece of evidence which I want to deal with in this section comes
from a letter Jung wrote to the British Jungian analyst Michael Fordham in June
1958. Fordham had written to Jung on May 30, 1958 to ask him what his views
were on heredity, indicating that he was concerned that Jung’s views on the
subject didn’t appear to match the by then commonly accepted neo-Darwinian
theories. Jung wrote back on the 14th of June 1958 and indicated that he shared
what he called ‘the ordinary view about it’, and that he therefore believed that
‘individual acquisitions under experimental conditions are not inherited’ (Jung
1973, p. 450). He added, however, that he thought this could not possibly be
true in general, ‘since changes in individual cases must have been inherited,
otherwise no change would have come about in phylogenesis’. It is clear from
this statement that Jung still had a distinctly un-Darwinian understanding of
how heredity worked at that time. In the Darwinian account of evolution,
268 Ritske Rensma
change occurs even though no individual changes are passed on, through the
natural selection of character traits brought about by random gene mutations.
The position which Jung takes in the letter, despite his claim that he shares ‘the
ordinary view’ of inheritance, still relies on the notion of the inheritance of acquired
characteristics, in that he claims that ‘changes in individual cases must have been
inherited, otherwise no change would have come about in phylogenesis’. The letter
to Fordham, then, makes it blatantly clear that Jung had no problem at all with
putting forward such Lamarckian notions of inheritance as late as June 1958. As
Jung died only three years later, it seems to me highly unlikely that he still changed
his mind after that. This leaves us with only one possible conclusion: Jung relied on
a Lamarckian understanding of how evolution works throughout his career.
[It] was not until the publication of his essay ‘The Spirit of Psychology’ [. . .] that he
finally freed himself of the Lamarckian taint, making a distinction between the deeply
unconscious and therefore unknowable and irrepresentable archetype-as-such (similar
to Kant’s das Ding-an-sich) and archetypal images, ideas and behaviours that the
archetype-as-such gives rise to. It is the archetype-as-such (the predisposition to have
certain experience) that is inherited, not the experience itself. This proposition is fully
in accord with modern biological usage and is no more Lamarckian than the statement
that children are innately disposed to acquire speech or to run on two legs.
(Stevens 2006, p. 77)
3
To this list I should add myself as well, as in my book The Innateness of Myth (2009) I also
defended this particular interpretation of the concept of the archetype. After doing a lot more research
on the topic, however, I have come to the conclusion that it does not hold up to scrutiny. This
change of mind does not affect any of the major arguments of the book, though, as the section about
Jung’s Lamarckism represents only a very small part (the book’s main topic is Joseph Campbell’s
reception of Jung’s theoretical framework, arguing that Campbell underwent several drastic shifts
of opinion regarding Jung’s overall merit).
Analytical psychology and the ghost of Lamarck 269
Again and again I encounter the mistaken notion that an archetype is determined in
regard to its content, in other words that it is a kind of unconscious idea (if such an
expression be admissible). It is necessary to point out once more that archetypes are
not determined as regards their content, but only as regards their form and then only
to a very limited degree.
(Jung 1938 / 1954, para. 155)
According to Stevens and the other ‘anti-Lamarck scholars’ (my term for the
group of scholars mentioned above, who have all defended Jung against
Lamarckism in a highly similar way), passages like this one prove that Jung
was not Lamarckian. The argument which they provide for this rests on an
important presupposition: that there is only one possible way of accounting
for the evolution of the psyche in a Lamarckian way. According to this
presupposition, a Lamarckian would never claim that what we inherit from our
forebears is merely an abstract ‘form’ which makes it likely that we have
similar–but not identical–experiences to our forebears; instead, a Lamarckian
would–as Freud did–claim that we inherit the memory of their actual experi-
ences. A Lamarckian, according to these scholars, would therefore hold that what
is inherited from our forebears is already determined in regard to its content, to use
Jung’s phrase from the quote above: since we inherit the actual memory of their
experiences, what we inherit are specific images and ideas, and not an abstract
form or blueprint which can give rise to similar images and ideas. Since Jung made
it clear that he believed in the inheritance of exactly such an abstract form, and not
of a mirror image of a specific ancestral memory, he cannot be a Lamarckian. As
Stevens puts it:
4
Published in CW 8 as ‘On the nature of the psyche’.
270 Ritske Rensma
At first glance, this argument may seem convincing, which goes a long way
towards explaining why it is so prevalent. If we examine this argument in the
light of what has been discussed in this article so far, however, we can come
to see that it is not a valid argument at all. Although the ‘anti-Lamarck’ scholars
are correct when they claim that Jung did not subscribe to the kind of psycho-
logical Lamarckism which Freud defended, in which an actual memory of an
ancestral experience is passed on, they are incorrect when they claim that this
proves that Jung is not Lamarckian. What they have proven is that Jung was
not a psychological Lamarckian in the same sense that Freud was; however,
since this is not the only ‘psychological Lamarckian’ position, they have not
given conclusive evidence that Jung was not a Lamarckian. As Jung’s own writings
clearly show, it is perfectly possible to claim that we do not inherit specific
ancestral memories, while at the same time also subscribing to an evolutionary
mechanism which involves the inheritance of acquired characteristics. Jung
indeed subscribed to both these ideas, sometimes even referring to both in the
very same passage:
Endless repetition has engraved these experiences into our psychic constitution, not in the
form of images filled with content, but at first only as forms without content, representing
merely the possibility of a certain type of perception and action.
(Jung 1936 / 1959, para. 99)
This passage makes it very clear indeed that a different kind of Lamarckism
exists than the one the ‘anti-Lamarck’ scholars have in mind when they try to
defend Jung against the Lamarckian accusation: a Lamarckism which at the
same time subscribes to inheriting acquired characteristics and to the belief that
what we inherit are not actual ‘memory images’ (Jung’s term) but instead what
Jung calls ‘forms without content’. What Stevens and the other ‘anti-Lamarck’
scholars have completely overlooked is that it is not the nature of what is
claimed to be inheritable which establishes whether a thinker is a Lamarckian
or not (in the case of Freud and Jung, an actual ancestral memory versus merely
an innate disposition to have the same experience), but whether the evolutionary
mechanism the thinker in question subscribes to relies on the inheritance of
acquired characteristics or not. Only by pointing out that Jung did not
subscribe to such a mechanism can the ‘anti-Lamarck’ scholars acquit Jung
of Lamarckism. This should be the focal point of the debate, not whether
Jung believed in innate ideas and images or not.
As I hope to have made clear, however, Jung most certainly believed in a
mechanism of evolution which relies on the inheritance of acquired characteristics.
This fact does not rule out the possibility, of course, that Jung didn’t only think
along Lamarckian lines, but that he combined Lamarckian and Darwinian ideas.
This was once a common position, which we find not only in Darwin’s own work
but also in the work of such staunch defenders of Darwinism as Ernst Haeckel. If
this were true in Jung’s case, then we would expect to find evidence in his writings
that he sometimes thought in terms of adaptation, of certain characteristics offering
Analytical psychology and the ghost of Lamarck 271
an organism an environmental advantage, which in turn explains the fact that these
characteristics are now prevalent. I believe that such passages can indeed be found
in the Collected Works, for example when Jung claims that consciousness arose
because it gave our ancestors an evolutionary advantage (Jung 1927 / 1931, para.
695). This leads me to think that Jung was not anti-Darwinian as such, but drew on
both Lamarckian and Darwinian ideas depending on the context. The Lamarckian
passages, however, do seem to form the majority.
Such an approach would have been typical for Jung, who was notoriously
eclectic in his interests and in the thinkers he drew inspiration from.5 Although
Jung does not appear to have been influenced by Lamarck himself, it is certainly
obvious that he drew inspiration from thinkers who subscribed to Lamarckian
ideas. I have already mentioned Richard Semon, but the above mentioned
Haeckel also appears to have influenced him.6 Given the fact that there are also
Darwinian passages in the Collected Works, it should come as no surprise that
Jung also took inspiration from Darwinian thinkers. As Hogenson (2001) has
pointed out in this Journal, for example, Jung was also strongly influenced by
James Mark Baldwin and Conway Lloyd Morgan. Unlike Hogenson’s claim,
however, I do not think that the fact that Jung took inspiration from these
Darwinian thinkers strengthens the supposition that he was radically opposed
to Lamarckian ideas. For instance, Jung draws on the work of Baldwin in
Psychological Types (Jung 1921 / 1960, para. 518)–the exact same text in which
he also compares his concept of the archetype to the ideas of the neo-Lamarckian
thinker Richard Semon.7
As I already indicated above, many people nowadays think of Darwinism
and Lamarckism as two completely incompatible systems of thought. In the
early stages of Jung’s career, however, this distinction was by no means clear-
cut. The currently accepted paradigm of neo-Darwinism–otherwise known
as the ‘modern synthesis’–was only established in the twenties and thirties, by
which time Jung had already developed many of his core ideas. The real
acceptance of neo-Darwinism on a large scale only took place in the fifties
5
For a good overview of Jung’s many different influences see Sonu Shamdasani’s excellent Jung
and the Making of Modern Psychology (2003).
6
The most important area where I see Haeckel’s influence in Jung’s work is the former’s so-called
‘biogenetic law’, which can be summarized as ‘ontogeny recapitulates phylogeny’. Even though it is
now largely discredited, examples of Jung putting it forward as fact can be found throughout the
Collected Works.
7
Hogenson’s second argument against Jung being a Lamarckian is that Jung does not subscribe to
the Freudian notion that individually acquired instincts or memories can be passed on completely
intact to the next generation. As the section on Stevens and the other ‘anti-Lamarck’ scholars has
made clear, however, this is not the only possible Lamarckian position. Hogenson is correct in argu-
ing that Jung did not subscribe to the Freudian type of Lamarckism; however, as there are other
possible positions, this finding does not logically lead to the conclusion that Jung was not Lamarckian.
As I hope to have shown in this paper, there is more than enough evidence that Jung was Lamarckian,
even though he definitely wasn’t in the same camp as Freud in this regard.
272 Ritske Rensma
and sixties, and by then it was too late for it to have any really lasting influence
on Jung. Jung’s focus by then was on completely other areas of investigation
(for example alchemy and synchronicity), and when people in his inner circle
who were more up to speed with developments in biology tried to broach the
topic of Lamarckism, Jung appears to have been rather dismissive of their
concerns. The biologist Adolf Portmann, for example, was highly concerned
about the passages in Jung’s work which sounded Lamarckian in tone, saying
the following in an interview:
I was under the strong impression that not many of the biological and physical
chemical experiences of our modern time entered into his thinking . . . He had come
from the first great adventure of Darwinism; he had turned, as I see it, away from
the extreme forms of Darwinism to a more Lamarckian way of thinking, and this
was, I think, a more or less ever-present background he never discussed . . . A discus-
sion about a notion like “archetype” is impossible when you do not consider the
new biological facts of hereditary connections with the environment, or of the instinc-
tive life of animals, and of the instinctive residuums in man. To find out exactly what
the thinking of Jung was in this respect seems to me of a very great importance, but the
work has not yet been done.
(Shamdasani 2003, p. 266)
When Portmann dealt with this topic in a paper, however, Jung was highly
critical of it, going so far as to say that ‘it was hopeless trying to explain
archetypes to people who had no direct experience of the material, and that
he wished scientists would sometimes ask him before plunging in blithely in
fields they didn’t know anything about’ (ibid.). Even though Jung had admitted
to Portmann a few years earlier that he ‘was no longer at home in modern
biology’(ibid.), it appears that he had no motivation to inform himself about
new developments in the field, and that he remained committed to the outdated
evolutionary ideas to which he had subscribed throughout his career.
Conclusion
Needless to say, I am not the first scholar to come to the conclusion that there
are Lamarckian passages in Jung’s work. Other scholars before me have made
similar claims, but in my opinion no one has as yet argued the case for it in a
satisfactory way. Scholars who classify Jung as a Lamarckian tend either to
make the offhand comment that this is the case without giving any kind of
evidence at all, or focus only on one or two passages without dealing with the
possibility that Jung could have changed his mind somewhere along the way.
As Jung, by his own admission, changed his mind a lot, this seems to me to
be a serious shortcoming. For the most part, other scholars have also failed to
show why the passages which appear to be a defence against Lamarckism are
not, in fact, what they appear to be. Since so many scholars have drawn on
these passages to argue that Jung was not a Lamarckian, it seems to me that
Analytical psychology and the ghost of Lamarck 273
these cannot be overlooked. Here I must give credit to Percival (1993), who is
the only scholar I’m aware of who has pointed out before me that the
passages in which Jung claims that the abstract archetype-as-such is not
‘filled in with content’ and not a re-echo of an ancestral memory do not
prove that he was not a Lamarckian. What Percival has failed to do, however,
is to offer substantial evidence that Jung remained committed to this position
throughout his life. Where he also falls short, for me, is in the conclusions he
attaches to his findings. Percival’s article about Jung’s Lamarckian bent is
called ‘Is Jung’s theory of archetypes compatible with neo-Darwinism and
sociobiology’, and it is highly critical of Jung. Percival makes the case in it
that Jung’s Lamarckism disqualifies him from being of any relevance today:
now that neo-Darwinism has become the dominant paradigm, a thinker
who believed in the inheritance of acquired characteristics can only be of
historical interest.
For myself, I think that that conclusion is rather premature. It hinges on the
hidden presupposition that a theory can only be of use if it is unblemished in
its entirety. If any of its constituting parts are discredited, the whole should be
discredited too. The example of Darwin himself relying on Lamarckian ideas,
however, shows that that particular understanding of scientific progress is not
a correct one. No one these days would claim that Darwin’s ideas are of no
value because of the Lamarckian passages some of his books contain; therefore,
Lamarckian passages in Jung’s work do not by necessity lead to the conclusion
that all his other ideas are useless too. Problems with Darwin’s own ideas do not
disqualify the neo-Darwinian project; by the same token, problems with some
of Jung’s ideas do not disqualify the possibility of a post-Jungian position.
If Jung had subscribed to Freud’s version of Lamarckism, which holds that
it is possible to inherit an actual memory from one’s ancestors, then yes,
analytical psychology would have been in big trouble indeed, for it is impossible
to account for such an inheritance using modern scientific theories. Jung’s
archetypes, however–which he was at pains to point out are ‘forms without
content’, and not individual memories–can be accounted for in terms of
modern scientific ideas, as the work of a great many post-Jungian scholars has
shown (quite often in the pages of this Journal).8 This project, then–to relate the
8
Books relevant to this topic have been written by Stevens (2002), Knox (2003) and Haule (2010).
Important articles have been written by–amongst others–Tresan (1996), McDowell (2001), Knox
(2002, 2009), Hogenson (2005), Merchant (2009) and Goodwyn (2010). There is as yet no consen-
sus amongst these scholars as to how Jung’s concept of the archetype should be related to contem-
porary scientific models, with some focusing on a model of the archetype which puts emphasis on its
innateness (for example Stevens) and others focusing on what has been called an ‘emergent/develop-
mental’ model of the archetype (for example Knox). All these scholars share my opinion, however,
that Jung’s ideas are still relevant, and worthy of being brought into the twenty-first century (for a
good overview of the different positions within the debate, see Merchant (2009)). Needless to say,
there have also been scholars who have argued that Jung’s ideas cannot be related to contemporary
ideas. Examples of this position are Percival (1993) and Pietikainen (2003).
274 Ritske Rensma
TRANSLATIONS OF ABSTRACT
Que Jung soit Lamarckien ou non a toujours été un sujet de vifs débats, autant dans
la communauté post-Jungienne que chez les chercheurs s’intéressant à Jung dans la
communauté académique en général. On peut s’étonner du fait que, jusqu’à présent,
peu de travaux aient été consacrés à ce sujet, et à ma connaissance personne n’a
encore réussi à faire honneur à toutes les subtilités que cela implique. Les chercheurs
qui ont prétendu que Jung était Lamarckien ont, en grande partie, simplifié le débat à
l’extrême, en omettant de discuter des extraits dans lesquels Jung semble se défendre
de Lamarckisme; cependant, les chercheurs qui ont défendu Jung de Lamarckisme, ne
se sont en règle générale pas confrontés à la question de savoir si ces extraits tirent
vraiment Jung d’affaire. Cet article va tenter de corriger ce déséquilibre en mettant en
avant quatre extraits clés recouvrant la carrière de Jung, qui concluent tous à l’évidence
que Jung était en effet un Lamarckien. Après avoir discuté de ces extraits, il examinera
dans le détail les extraits dans lesquels Jung semble se défendre de Lamarckisme, en
expliquant pourquoi ces extraits ne représentent pas du tout une défense contre du
Lamarckisme, et ont par conséquent été en général mal interprétés par de nombreux
chercheurs.
Analytical psychology and the ghost of Lamarck 275
Die Frage, ob Jung Lamarckist war oder nicht, stellte, sowohl innerhalb der post-
jungianischen Gemeinde wie auch unter Wissenschaftlern der weiteren akademischen
Gemeinschaft mit einem Interesse an Jung, immer einen heiß debattierten Punkt dar. Doch
überraschenderweise wurde dem nur wenig substantielle Arbeit gewidmet und aus meiner
Sicht hat es bis jetzt noch niemand vollbracht, all den hierin enthaltenen Feinheiten
Gerechtigkeit widerfahren zu lassen. Diejenigen Wissenschaftler, die behauptet haben, Jung
sei Lamarckist, haben zum größten Teil die Debatte dadurch übervereinfacht, daß sie es
unterließen, jene Passagen zu berücksichtigen, in denen sich Jung selbst gegen den Vorwurf
des Lamarckismus’ verwahrte; Jene Wissenschaftler dagegen, die Jung gegen den Vorwurf
des Lamarckismus’ verteidigten, haben regelmäßig verabsäumt sich adäquat mit der Frage
zu beschäftigen, ob diese Textstellen Jung wirklich aus der Klemme bringen. Dieser Beitrag
wird versuchen, dieses Ungleichgewicht dadurch zu korrigieren, daß vier Schlüsselstellen
aus Jungs Karriere angeführt werden, die allesamt schlüssige Belege dafür liefern, daß Jung
in der Tat Lamarckist war. Im Anschluß an die Diskussion dieser Passagen wird im Detail
auf jene Stellen eingegangen, in denen sich Jung selbst gegen den Vorwurf des Lamarckismus’
wehrt und dabei nachgewiesen, daß diese Textteile keineswegs eine Verteidigung gegen den
Lamarckismusvorwurf darstellen und folglich generell von vielen Wissenschaftlern fehlinter-
pretiert wurden.
Se Jung fosse lamarckiano o no è sempre stato uno scottante argomento di dibattito, sia
all’interno della comunità post-junghiana che fra gli allievi interessati a Jung nella comu-
nità accademica più ampia. Eppure sorprendentemente pochi lavori sostanziali sono stati
dedicati all’argomento, e secondo me nessuno è finora riuscito a rendere giustizia a tutte
le sottigliezze implicate. Gli allievi che hanno dichiarato che Jung è lamarckiano hanno
per lo più ipersemplificato il dibattito, mancando nel discutere i passaggi in cui Jung sem-
bra difendere se stesso contro il Lamarckismo; tuttavia gli allievi che hanno difeso Jung
contro il Lamarckismo non si sono adeguatamente confrontati con la questione se questi
passaggi abbiano realmente liberato Jung dalla trappola. In questo articolo si tenterà di
correggere tale squilibrio presentando quattro passaggi chiave che attraversano la car-
riera di Jung e che rappresentano tutti la conclusiva evidenza che Jung fosse Lamarck-
iano. Dopo aver discusso tali passaggi si tratteranno dettagliatamente i passaggi nei quali
Jung sembra stia difendendosi contro il Lamarckismo, provando che tali passaggi non
rappresentano affatto una difesa contro il Lamarckismo, e sono stati quindi general-
mente mal interpretati dagli allievi.
Был или не был Юнг ламаркианцем – этот вопрос всегда оставался горячей
темой для дискуссий, как внутри пост-юнгианского сообщества, так и среди
исследователей из более широкого академического круга, интересующихся
Юнгом. Однако на удивление мало солидных работ были посвящены этой
теме, и, на мой взгляд, никому еще не удалось отдать должное внимание всем
присущим этой теме тонкостям. Те специалисты, которые утверждали, что
Юнг ламаркианец, по большей части чересчур упрощали спорный вопрос,
не будучи способными обсудить те пассажи, в которых Юнг защищался от
попыток приписать ему ламаркизм; те же исследователи, которые защищали
точку зрения о том, что Юнг не имеет отношения к ламаркизму, как правило,
276 Ritske Rensma
Siempre ha sido un tema ardientemente debatido si Jung era o no Lamackiano, tanto por
la comunidad postjunguiana y entre los estudiosos de Jung dentro de una más amplia
comunidad académica. Sin embargo, sorprendentemente, se han realizados pocos traba-
jos substanciales se han dedicado a este tópico, y en mi criterio ninguno ha hecho justicia
para manejar las sutilezas involucradas. Los estudiosos que sostienen que Jung es
Lamarckiano han, en su mayoría, sobre-simplificado el debate, por evitar los escritos
donde Jung parece defenderse contra el Lamarckismo; los estudiosos que defienden a
Jung del Lamarckismo, sin embargo, tienen como regla no lidiar adecuadamente con
la pregunta de si estos párrafos realmente liberan a Jung de su enganche. Este trabajo tra-
tará de corregir este desbalance trayendo al frente cuatro escritos definitorios que
demuestran en forma concluyente que Jung era de hecho Lamarckiano. Después de
discutir estos escritos, trabajaremos aquellos escritos con los cuales Jung aparenta
defenderse del Lamarckismo, evidenciando que ellos no representan una defensa contra
el Lamarckismo, y que han sido malinterpretados por los estudiosos.
References
Balter, M. (2000). ‘Was Lamarck just a little bit right?’. Science, 288, 5463, 38.
Clarke, J. J. (1992). In Search of Jung. New York: Routledge.
Darwin, C. (1897 [1859]). On the Origin of Species (6th edn). London: John Murray.
——— (1921 [1868]). The Variation of Animals and Plants Under Domestication.
London: John Murray, 2nd edn.
Dawkins, R. (1989). The Selfish Gene. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2nd edn.
Freud, S. (1967). Moses and Monotheism. New York: Vintage Books.
Goodwyn, E. (2010). ‘Approaching archetypes: reconsidering innateness’. Journal of
Analytical Psychology, 55, 4, 502–21.
Gould, S. J. (1992). The Panda’s Thumb: More Reflections in Natural History. London,
New York: W.W. Norton.
Haule, J. R. (2010). Jung in the 21st Century. Vol. 1. London & New York: Routledge.
Hogenson, G. B. (2001). ‘The Baldwin effect: a neglected influence on CG Jung’s evolu-
tionary thinking’. Journal of Analytical Psychology, 46, 4, 591–611.
——— (2005). ‘The Self, the symbolic and synchronicity: virtual realities and the emer-
gence of the psyche’. Journal of Analytical Psychology, 50, 3, 271–84.
Jacobi, J. (1959). Complex, Archetype, Symbol. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Jung, C. G. (1916 / 1918 / 1926 / 1936 / 1943). ‘On the psychology of the unconscious’.
CW 7.
Analytical psychology and the ghost of Lamarck 277
——— (1916 / 1928 / 1935). ‘The relations between the ego and the unconscious’. CW 7.
——— (1921 / 1960). ‘Psychological types’. CW 6.
——— (1927 / 1931). ‘Analytical psychology and “Weltanschauung”’. CW 8.
——— (1936 / 1959). ‘The concept of the collective unconscious’. CW 9i.
——— (1938 / 1954). ‘Psychological aspects of the mother archetype’. CW 9i.
——— (1946 / 1954). ‘On the nature of the psyche’. CW 8.
——— (1973). Letters 2: 1951–1961. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
——— (1998 [1930–1934]). Visions: Notes of the Seminar Given in 1930–1934.
London: Routledge.
Knox, J. (2002). ‘Memories, fantasies, archetypes: an exploration of some connections
between cognitive science and analytical psychology’. Journal of Analytical Psychology,
46, 4, 613–35.
——— (2003). Archetype, Attachment, Analysis: Jungian Psychology and the Emergent
Mind. Hove: Brunner-Routledge.
——— (2009). ‘Mirror neurons and embodied simulation in the development of
archetypes and self-agency’. Journal of Analytical Psychology, 54, 3, 307–23.
Mayr, E. (1972). ‘Lamarck revisited’. Journal of the History of Biology, 5, 1, 55–94.
McDowell, M. J. (2001). ‘Principle of organization: a dynamic-systems view of the
archetype-as-such’. Journal of Analytical Psychology, 46, 4, 637–54.
Merchant, J. (2009). ‘A reappraisal of classical archetype theory and its implications for
theory and practice’. Journal of Analytical Psychology, 54, 3, 339–58.
Noll, R. (1994). The Jung Cult: Origins of a Charismatic Movement. Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Palmer, M. (1997). Freud and Jung on Religion. London: Routledge.
Percival, R. S. (1993). ‘Is Jung’s theory of archetypes compatible with neo-Darwinism
and sociobiology?’ Journal of Social and Evolutionary Systems, 16, 4, 459–87.
Pietikainen, P. (2003). ‘Soul man meets the blind watchmaker: CG Jung and Neo-
Darwinism’. Psychoanalysis and History, 5, 2, 195–212.
Rensma, R. (2009). The Innateness of Myth: A New Interpretation of Joseph Campbell’s
Reception of C.G. Jung. London: Continuum.
Samuels, A. (1985). Jung and the post-Jungians. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Semon, R. (1921). The Mneme. London: George Allen & Unwin.
Shamdasani, S. (2003). Jung and the Making of Modern Psychology: The Dream of a
Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Stevens, A. (2002). Archetype Revisited - An Updated Natural History of the Self.
London: Brunner-Routledge, 2nd edn.
——— (2006). ‘The archetypes’. In The Handbook of Jungian Psychology, ed. R. K.
Papadopoulos. New York/London: Routledge.
Storr, A. (1973). Jung. London: Fontana.
Tresan, D. I. (1996). ‘Jungian metapsychology and neurobiological theory’. Journal of
Analytical Psychology, 41, 3, 399–436. doi: 10.1111/j.1465-5922.1996.00399.x