CPR Kant-208-476
CPR Kant-208-476
CPR Kant-208-476
NOTHING AS
1
As Empty Conception without object, ens rationis
2 3
Empty object of Empty intuition
a conception, without object,
nihil privativum ens imaginarium
4
Empty object without conception, nihil negativum
We see that the ens rationis is distinguished from the nihil negativum or
pure nothing by the consideration that the former must not be reckoned
among possibilities, because it is a mere fiction-though not self-contradic-
tory, while the latter is completely opposed to all possibility, inasmuch as
the conception annihilates itself. Both, however, are empty conceptions.
On the other hand, the nihil privativum and ens imaginarium are empty
data for conceptions. If light be not given to the senses, we cannot repre-
sent to ourselves darkness, and if extended objects are not perceived, we
cannot represent space. Neither the negation, nor the mere form of intu-
ition can, without something real, be an object.
208
Immanuel Kant
*Sensibility, subjected to the understanding, as the object upon which the under-
standing employs its functions, is the source of real cognitions. But, in so far as it
exercises an influence upon the action of the understanding and determines it to
judgement, sensibility is itself the cause of error.
209
The Critique of Pure Reason
210
Immanuel Kant
211
The Critique of Pure Reason
A. OF REASON IN GENERAL.
212
Immanuel Kant
213
The Critique of Pure Reason
214
Immanuel Kant
215
The Critique of Pure Reason
216
Immanuel Kant
cally, the conditioned certainly relates to some condition, but not to the
unconditioned. From this principle also there must originate different
synthetical propositions, of which the pure understanding is perfectly ig-
norant, for it has to do only with objects of a possible experience, the
cognition and synthesis of which is always conditioned. The uncondi-
tioned, if it does really exist, must be especially considered in regard to the
determinations which distinguish it from whatever is conditioned, and
will thus afford us material for many a priori synthetical propositions.
The principles resulting from this highest principle of pure reason will,
however, be transcendent in relation to phenomena, that is to say, it will
be impossible to make any adequate empirical use of this principle. It is
therefore completely different from all principles of the understanding,
the use made of which is entirely immanent, their object and purpose
being merely the possibility of experience. Now our duty in the transcen-
dental dialectic is as follows. To discover whether the principle that the
series of conditions (in the synthesis of phenomena, or of thought in gen-
eral) extends to the unconditioned is objectively true, or not; what conse-
quences result therefrom affecting the empirical use of the understanding,
or rather whether there exists any such objectively valid proposition of
reason, and whether it is not, on the contrary, a merely logical precept
which directs us to ascend perpetually to still higher conditions, to ap-
proach completeness in the series of them, and thus to introduce into our
cognition the highest possible unity of reason. We must ascertain, I say,
whether this requirement of reason has not been regarded, by a misunder-
standing, as a transcendental principle of pure reason, which postulates a
thorough completeness in the series of conditions in objects themselves.
We must show, moreover, the misconceptions and illusions that intrude
into syllogisms, the major proposition of which pure reason has supplied—
a proposition which has perhaps more of the character of a petitio than of
a postulatum—and that proceed from experience upwards to its condi-
tions. The solution of these problems is our task in transcendental dialec-
tic, which we are about to expose even at its source, that lies deep in
human reason. We shall divide it into two parts, the first of which will
treat of the transcendent conceptions of pure reason, the second of tran-
scendent and dialectical syllogisms.
217
The Critique of Pure Reason
BOOK I.
Despite the great wealth of words which European languages possess, the
thinker finds himself often at a loss for an expression exactly suited to his
conception, for want of which he is unable to make himself intelligible
either to others or to himself. To coin new words is a pretension to legisla-
tion in language which is seldom successful; and, before recourse is taken
to so desperate an expedient, it is advisable to examine the dead and learned
languages, with the hope and the probability that we may there meet with
some adequate expression of the notion we have in our minds. In this
case, even if the original meaning of the word has become somewhat un-
certain, from carelessness or want of caution on the part of the authors of
it, it is always better to adhere to and confirm its proper meaning—even
although it may be doubtful whether it was formerly used in exactly this
sense—than to make our labour vain by want of sufficient care to render
ourselves intelligible.
For this reason, when it happens that there exists only a single word to
express a certain conception, and this word, in its usual acceptation, is
thoroughly adequate to the conception, the accurate distinction of which
from related conceptions is of great importance, we ought not to employ
the expression improvidently, or, for the sake of variety and elegance of
style, use it as a synonym for other cognate words. It is our duty, on the
contrary, carefully to preserve its peculiar signification, as otherwise it eas-
ily happens that when the attention of the reader is no longer particularly
attracted to the expression, and it is lost amid the multitude of other words
of very different import, the thought which it conveyed, and which it
alone conveyed, is lost with it.
Plato employed the expression idea in a way that plainly showed he meant
by it something which is never derived from the senses, but which far tran-
scends even the conceptions of the understanding (with which Aristotle
occupied himself), inasmuch as in experience nothing perfectly correspond-
ing to them could be found. Ideas are, according to him, archetypes of
things themselves, and not merely keys to possible experiences, like the cat-
219
The Critique of Pure Reason
egories. In his view they flow from the highest reason, by which they have
been imparted to human reason, which, however, exists no longer in its
original state, but is obliged with great labour to recall by reminiscence—
which is called philosophy—the old but now sadly obscured ideas. I will
not here enter upon any literary investigation of the sense which this sub-
lime philosopher attached to this expression. I shall content myself with
remarking that it is nothing unusual, in common conversation as well as in
written works, by comparing the thoughts which an author has delivered
upon a subject, to understand him better than he understood himself inas-
much as he may not have sufficiently determined his conception, and thus
have sometimes spoken, nay even thought, in opposition to his own opin-
ions.
Plato perceived very clearly that our faculty of cognition has the feeling
of a much higher vocation than that of merely spelling out phenomena
according to synthetical unity, for the purpose of being able to read them
as experience, and that our reason naturally raises itself to cognitions far
too elevated to admit of the possibility of an object given by experience
corresponding to them-cognitions which are nevertheless real, and are not
mere phantoms of the brain.
This philosopher found his ideas especially in all that is practical,* that
is, which rests upon freedom, which in its turn ranks under cognitions
that are the peculiar product of reason. He who would derive from expe-
rience the conceptions of virtue, who would make (as many have really
done) that, which at best can but serve as an imperfectly illustrative ex-
ample, a model for or the formation of a perfectly adequate idea on the
subject, would in fact transform virtue into a nonentity changeable ac-
cording to time and circumstance and utterly incapable of being employed
as a rule. On the contrary, every one is conscious that, when any one is
held up to him as a model of virtue, he compares this so-called model
with the true original which he possesses in his own mind and values him
according to this standard. But this standard is the idea of virtue, in rela-
tion to which all possible objects of experience are indeed serviceable as
221
The Critique of Pure Reason
222
Immanuel Kant
heart—and their number is but small—if they shall find themselves con-
vinced by the considerations following as well as by those above, to exert
themselves to preserve to the expression idea its original signification, and
to take care that it be not lost among those other expressions by which all
sorts of representations are loosely designated—that the interests of sci-
ence may not thereby suffer. We are in no want of words to denominate
adequately every mode of representation, without the necessity of encroach-
ing upon terms which are proper to others. The following is a graduated
list of them. The genus is representation in general (representatio). Under
it stands representation with consciousness (perceptio). A perception which
relates solely to the subject as a modification of its state, is a sensation
(sensatio), an objective perception is a cognition (cognitio). A cognition is
either an intuition or a conception (intuitus vel conceptus). The former
has an immediate relation to the object and is singular and individual; the
latter has but a mediate relation, by means of a characteristic mark which
may be common to several things. A conception is either empirical or
pure. A pure conception, in so far as it has its origin in the understanding
alone, and is not the conception of a pure sensuous image, is called notio.
A conception formed from notions, which transcends the possibility of
experience, is an idea, or a conception of reason. To one who has accus-
tomed himself to these distinctions, it must be quite intolerable to hear
the representation of the colour red called an idea. It ought not even to be
called a notion or conception of understanding.
Transcendental analytic showed us how the mere logical form of our cog-
nition can contain the origin of pure conceptions a priori, conceptions
which represent objects antecedently to all experience, or rather, indicate
the synthetical unity which alone renders possible an empirical cognition
of objects. The form of judgements—converted into a conception of the
synthesis of intuitions—produced the categories which direct the employ-
ment of the understanding in experience. This consideration warrants us
to expect that the form of syllogisms, when applied to synthetical unity of
intuitions, following the rule of the categories, will contain the origin of
particular a priori conceptions, which we may call pure conceptions of
reason or transcendental ideas, and which will determine the use of the
understanding in the totality of experience according to principles.
The function of reason in arguments consists in the universality of a cog-
223
The Critique of Pure Reason
224
Immanuel Kant
tioned as the common title of all conceptions of reason, we again light upon
an expression which we find it impossible to dispense with, and which nev-
ertheless, owing to the ambiguity attaching to it from long abuse, we cannot
employ with safety. The word absolute is one of the few words which, in its
original signification, was perfectly adequate to the conception it was in-
tended to convey—a conception which no other word in the same language
exactly suits, and the loss—or, which is the same thing, the incautious and
loose employment—of which must be followed by the loss of the concep-
tion itself. And, as it is a conception which occupies much of the attention
of reason, its loss would be greatly to the detriment of all transcendental
philosophy. The word absolute is at present frequently used to denote that
something can be predicated of a thing considered in itself and intrinsically.
In this sense absolutely possible would signify that which is possible in itself
(interne)-which is, in fact, the least that one can predicate of an object. On
the other hand, it is sometimes employed to indicate that a thing is valid in
all respects—for example, absolute sovereignty. Absolutely possible would
in this sense signify that which is possible in all relations and in every re-
spect; and this is the most that can be predicated of the possibility of a thing.
Now these significations do in truth frequently coincide. Thus, for example,
that which is intrinsically impossible, is also impossible in all relations, that
is, absolutely impossible. But in most cases they differ from each other toto
caelo, and I can by no means conclude that, because a thing is in itself
possible, it is also possible in all relations, and therefore absolutely. Nay,
more, I shall in the sequel show that absolute necessity does not by any
means depend on internal necessity, and that, therefore, it must not be con-
sidered as synonymous with it. Of an opposite which is intrinsically impos-
sible, we may affirm that it is in all respects impossible, and that, conse-
quently, the thing itself, of which this is the opposite, is absolutely neces-
sary; but I cannot reason conversely and say, the opposite of that which is
absolutely necessary is intrinsically impossible, that is, that the absolute ne-
cessity of things is an internal necessity. For this internal necessity is in cer-
tain cases a mere empty word with which the least conception cannot be
connected, while the conception of the necessity of a thing in all relations
possesses very peculiar determinations. Now as the loss of a conception of
great utility in speculative science cannot be a matter of indifference to the
philosopher, I trust that the proper determination and careful preservation
of the expression on which the conception depends will likewise be not
indifferent to him.
In this enlarged signification, then, shall I employ the word absolute, in
opposition to that which is valid only in some particular respect; for the
225
The Critique of Pure Reason
226
Immanuel Kant
227
The Critique of Pure Reason
228
Immanuel Kant
We are not at present engaged with a logical dialectic, which makes com-
plete abstraction of the content of cognition and aims only at unveiling
the illusory appearance in the form of syllogisms. Our subject is transcen-
dental dialectic, which must contain, completely a priori, the origin of
certain cognitions drawn from pure reason, and the origin of certain de-
duced conceptions, the object of which cannot be given empirically and
which therefore lie beyond the sphere of the faculty of understanding. We
have observed, from the natural relation which the transcendental use of
our cognition, in syllogisms as well as in judgements, must have to the
logical, that there are three kinds of dialectical arguments, corresponding
to the three modes of conclusion, by which reason attains to cognitions
on principles; and that in all it is the business of reason to ascend from the
conditioned synthesis, beyond which the understanding never proceeds,
to the unconditioned which the understanding never can reach.
Now the most general relations which can exist in our representations
are: 1st, the relation to the subject; 2nd, the relation to objects, either as
phenomena, or as objects of thought in general. If we connect this subdi-
vision with the main division, all the relations of our representations, of
229
The Critique of Pure Reason
230
Immanuel Kant
nature of our reason is possible, and has been given in the present chapter.
It is easy to perceive that the sole aim of pure reason is the absolute totality
of the synthesis on the side of the conditions, and that it does not concern
itself with the absolute completeness on the Part of the conditioned. For of
the former alone does she stand in need, in order to preposit the whole series
of conditions, and thus present them to the understanding a priori. But if
we once have a completely (and unconditionally) given condition, there is
no further necessity, in proceeding with the series, for a conception of rea-
son; for the understanding takes of itself every step downward, from the
condition to the conditioned. Thus the transcendental ideas are available
only for ascending in the series of conditions, till we reach the uncondi-
tioned, that is, principles. As regards descending to the conditioned, on the
other hand, we find that there is a widely extensive logical use which reason
makes of the laws of the understanding, but that a transcendental use thereof
is impossible; and that when we form an idea of the absolute totality of such
a synthesis, for example, of the whole series of all future changes in the
world, this idea is a mere ens rationis, an arbitrary fiction of thought, and
not a necessary presupposition of reason. For the possibility of the condi-
tioned presupposes the totality of its conditions, but not of its consequences.
Consequently, this conception is not a transcendental idea—and it is with
these alone that we are at present occupied.
Finally, it is obvious that there exists among the transcendental ideas a
certain connection and unity, and that pure reason, by means of them,
collects all its cognitions into one system. From the cognition of self to the
cognition of the world, and through these to the supreme being, the pro-
gression is so natural, that it seems to resemble the logical march of reason
from the premisses to the conclusion.* Now whether there lies unobserved
*The science of Metaphysics has for the proper object of its inquiries only three
grand ideas: GOD, FREEDOM, and IMMORTALITY, and it aims at showing,
that the second conception, conjoined with the first, must lead to the third, as a
necessary conclusion. All the other subjects with which it occupies itself, are merely
means for the attainment and realization of these ideas. It does not require these
ideas for the construction of a science of nature, but, on the contrary, for the pur-
pose of passing beyond the sphere of nature. A complete insight into and compre-
hension of them would render Theology, Ethics, and, through the conjunction of
both, Religion, solely dependent on the speculative faculty of reason. In a system-
atic representation of these ideas the above-mentioned arrangement—the syntheti-
cal one—would be the most suitable; but in the investigation which must necessar-
ily precede it, the analytical, which reverses this arrangement, would be better adapted
to our purpose, as in it we should proceed from that which experience immediately
presents to us—psychology, to cosmology, and thence to theology.
231
The Critique of Pure Reason
232
Immanuel Kant
BOOK II.
enon, and I conclude, from the fact that I have always a self-contradictory
conception of the unconditioned synthetical unity of the series upon one
side, the truth of the opposite unity, of which I have nevertheless no con-
ception. The condition of reason in these dialectical arguments, I shall
term the antinomy of pure reason. Finally, according to the third kind of
sophistical argument, I conclude, from the totality of the conditions of
thinking objects in general, in so far as they can be given, the absolute
synthetical unity of all conditions of the possibility of things in general;
that is, from things which I do not know in their mere transcendental
conception, I conclude a being of all beings which I know still less by
means of a transcendental conception, and of whose unconditioned ne-
cessity I can form no conception whatever. This dialectical argument I
shall call the ideal of pure reason.
234
Immanuel Kant
235
The Critique of Pure Reason
1 2
The Soul is As regards its quality
SUBSTANCE it is SIMPLE
3
As regards the different
times in which it exists,
it is numerically identical,
that is UNITY, not Plurality.
4
It is in relation to possible objects in space.*
*The reader, who may not so easily perceive the psychological sense of these
expressions, taken here in their transcendental abstraction, and cannot guess why
the latter attribute of the soul belongs to the category of existence, will find the
expressions sufficiently explained and justified in the sequel. I have, moreover, to
apologize for the Latin terms which have been employed, instead of their Ger-
man synonyms, contrary to the rules of correct writing. But I judged it better to
sacrifice elegance to perspicuity.
236
Immanuel Kant
thoughts that are its predicates, and of which, apart from these, we cannot
form the least conception. Hence in a perpetual circle, inasmuch as we
must always employ it, in order to frame any judgement respecting it.
And this inconvenience we find it impossible to rid ourselves of, because
consciousness in itself is not so much a representation distinguishing a
particular object, as a form of representation in general, in so far as it may
be termed cognition; for in and by cognition alone do I think anything.
It must, however, appear extraordinary at first sight that the condition
under which I think, and which is consequently a property of my subject,
should be held to be likewise valid for every existence which thinks, and that
we can presume to base upon a seemingly empirical proposition a judge-
ment which is apodeictic and universal, to wit, that everything which thinks
is constituted as the voice of my consciousness declares it to be, that is, as a
self-conscious being. The cause of this belief is to be found in the fact that
we necessarily attribute to things a priori all the properties which constitute
conditions under which alone we can cogitate them. Now I cannot obtain
the least representation of a thinking being by means of external experience,
but solely through self-consciousness. Such objects are consequently noth-
ing more than the transference of this consciousness of mine to other things
which can only thus be represented as thinking beings. The proposition, “I
think,” is, in the present case, understood in a problematical sense, not in so
far as it contains a perception of an existence (like the Cartesian “Cogito,
ergo sum”),* but in regard to its mere possibility—for the purpose of dis-
covering what properties may be inferred from so simple a proposition and
predicated of the subject of it.
If at the foundation of our pure rational cognition of thinking beings
there lay more than the mere Cogito—if we could likewise call in aid
observations on the play of our thoughts, and the thence derived natural
laws of the thinking self, there would arise an empirical psychology which
would be a kind of physiology of the internal sense and might possibly be
capable of explaining the phenomena of that sense. But it could never be
available for discovering those properties which do not belong to possible
experience (such as the quality of simplicity), nor could it make any
apodeictic enunciation on the nature of thinking beings: it would there-
fore not be a rational psychology.
Now, as the proposition “I think” (in the problematical sense) contains
the form of every judgement in general and is the constant accompani-
ment of all the categories, it is manifest that conclusions are drawn from it
only by a transcendental employment of the understanding. This use of
238
Immanuel Kant
239
The Critique of Pure Reason
is the subject of it, and adds to the mere notion of a thinking being the
mode of its existence, and in the second place annexes a predicate (that of
simplicity) to the latter conception—a predicate which it could not have
discovered in the sphere of experience. It would follow that a priori syn-
thetical propositions are possible and legitimate, not only, as we have
maintained, in relation to objects of possible experience, and as principles
of the possibility of this experience itself, but are applicable to things in
themselves—an inference which makes an end of the whole of this Cri-
tique, and obliges us to fall back on the old mode of metaphysical proce-
dure. But indeed the danger is not so great, if we look a little closer into
the question.
There lurks in the procedure of rational Psychology a paralogism, which
is represented in the following syllogism:
That which cannot be cogitated otherwise than as subject, does not
exist otherwise than as subject, and is therefore substance.
A thinking being, considered merely as such, cannot be cogitated other-
wise than as subject.
Therefore it exists also as such, that is, as substance.
In the major we speak of a being that can be cogitated generally and in
every relation, consequently as it may be given in intuition. But in the
minor we speak of the same being only in so far as it regards itself as
subject, relatively to thought and the unity of consciousness, but not in
relation to intuition, by which it is presented as an object to thought.
Thus the conclusion is here arrived at by a Sophisma figurae dictionis.*
That this famous argument is a mere paralogism, will be plain to any
one who will consider the general remark which precedes our exposition
of the principles of the pure understanding, and the section on noumena.
For it was there proved that the conception of a thing, which can exist per
se—only as a subject and never as a predicate, possesses no objective real-
*Thought is taken in the two premisses in two totally different senses. In the
major it is considered as relating and applying to objects in general, consequently
to objects of intuition also. In the minor, we understand it as relating merely to
self-consciousness. In this sense, we do not cogitate an object, but merely the
relation to the self-consciousness of the subject, as the form of thought. In the
former premiss we speak of things which cannot be cogitated otherwise than as
subjects. In the second, we do not speak of things, but of thought (all objects
being abstracted), in which the Ego is always the subject of consciousness. Hence
the conclusion cannot be, “I cannot exist otherwise than as subject”; but only “I
can, in cogitating my existence, employ my Ego only as the subject of the judge-
ment.” But this is an identical proposition, and throws no light on the mode of
my existence.
240
Immanuel Kant
ity; that is to say, we can never know whether there exists any object to
correspond to the conception; consequently, the conception is nothing
more than a conception, and from it we derive no proper knowledge. If
this conception is to indicate by the term substance, an object that can be
given, if it is to become a cognition, we must have at the foundation of the
cognition a permanent intuition, as the indispensable condition of its
objective reality. For through intuition alone can an object be given. But
in internal intuition there is nothing permanent, for the Ego is but the
consciousness of my thought. If then, we appeal merely to thought, we
cannot discover the necessary condition of the application of the concep-
tion of substance—that is, of a subject existing per se—to the subject as a
thinking being. And thus the conception of the simple nature of sub-
stance, which is connected with the objective reality of this conception, is
shown to be also invalid, and to be, in fact, nothing more than the logical
qualitative unity of self-consciousness in thought; whilst we remain per-
fectly ignorant whether the subject is composite or not.
241
The Critique of Pure Reason
242
Immanuel Kant
one, without anything being lost except the plurality of subsistence, inasmuch as
the one substance would contain the degree of reality of all the former substances.
Perhaps, indeed, the simple substances, which appear under the form of matter,
might (not indeed by a mechanical or chemical influence upon each other, but
by an unknown influence, of which the former would be but the phenomenal
appearance), by means of such a dynamical division of the parent-souls, as inten-
sive quantities, produce other souls, while the former repaired the loss thus sus-
tained with new matter of the same sort. I am far from allowing any value to such
chimeras; and the principles of our analytic have clearly proved that no other
than an empirical use of the categories—that of substance, for example—is pos-
sible. But if the rationalist is bold enough to construct, on the mere authority of
the faculty of thought—without any intuition, whereby an object is given—a
self-subsistent being, merely because the unity of apperception in thought can-
not allow him to believe it a composite being, instead of declaring, as he ought to
do, that he is unable to explain the possibility of a thinking nature; what ought to
hinder the materialist, with as complete an independence of experience, to em-
ploy the principle of the rationalist in a directly opposite manner—still preserv-
ing the formal unity required by his opponent?
243
The Critique of Pure Reason
1
I think,
2 3
as Subject, as simple Subject,
4
as identical Subject, in every state of my thought.
(our existence in this life); and to extend our cognition to the nature of all
thinking beings by means of the empirical—but in relation to every sort
of intuition, perfectly undetermined—proposition, “I think”?
There does not then exist any rational psychology as a doctrine furnish-
ing any addition to our knowledge of ourselves. It is nothing more than a
discipline, which sets impassable limits to speculative reason in this region
of thought, to prevent it, on the one hand, from throwing itself into the
arms of a soulless materialism, and, on the other, from losing itself in the
mazes of a baseless spiritualism. It teaches us to consider this refusal of our
reason to give any satisfactory answer to questions which reach beyond
the limits of this our human life, as a hint to abandon fruitless specula-
tion; and to direct, to a practical use, our knowledge of ourselves—which,
although applicable only to objects of experience, receives its principles
from a higher source, and regulates its procedure as if our destiny reached
far beyond the boundaries of experience and life.
From all this it is evident that rational psychology has its origin in a mere
misunderstanding. The unity of consciousness, which lies at the basis of the
categories, is considered to be an intuition of the subject as an object; and
the category of substance is applied to the intuition. But this unity is noth-
ing more than the unity in thought, by which no object is given; to which
therefore the category of substance—which always presupposes a given in-
tuition-cannot be applied. Consequently, the subject cannot be cognized.
The subject of the categories cannot, therefore, for the very reason that it
cogitates these, frame any conception of itself as an object of the categories;
for, to cogitate these, it must lay at the foundation its own pure self-con-
sciousness—the very thing that it wishes to explain and describe. In like
manner, the subject, in which the representation of time has its basis, can-
not determine, for this very reason, its own existence in time. Now, if the
latter is impossible, the former, as an attempt to determine itself by means of
the categories as a thinking being in general, is no less so.*
*The “I think” is, as has been already stated, an empirical proposition, and con-
tains the proposition, “I exist.” But I cannot say, “Everything, which thinks,
exists”; for in this case the property of thought would constitute all beings pos-
sessing it, necessary beings. Hence my existence cannot be considered as an infer-
ence from the proposition, “I think,” as Descartes maintained—because in this
case the major premiss, “Everything, which thinks, exists,” must precede—but
the two propositions are identical. The proposition, “I think,” expresses an unde-
termined empirical intuition, that perception (proving consequently that sensa-
tion, which must belong to sensibility, lies at the foundation of this proposition);
but it precedes experience, whose province it is to determine an object of percep-
245
The Critique of Pure Reason
tion by means of the categories in relation to time; and existence in this proposi-
tion is not a category, as it does not apply to an undetermined given object, but
only to one of which we have a conception, and about which we wish to know
whether it does or does not exist, out of, and apart from this conception. An
undetermined perception signifies here merely something real that has been given,
only, however, to thought in general—but not as a phenomenon, nor as a thing
in itself (noumenon), but only as something that really exists, and is designated
as such in the proposition, “I think.” For it must be remarked that, when I call
the proposition, “I think,” an empirical proposition, I do not thereby mean that
the Ego in the proposition is an empirical representation; on the contrary, it is
purely intellectual, because it belongs to thought in general. But without some
empirical representation, which presents to the mind material for thought, the
mental act, “I think,” would not take place; and the empirical is only the condi-
tion of the application or employment of the pure intellectual faculty.
246
Immanuel Kant
to the latter, it is justified in extending the former, and with it our own
existence, beyond the boundaries of experience and life. If we turn our
attention to the analogy of the nature of living beings in this world, in the
consideration of which reason is obliged to accept as a principle that no
organ, no faculty, no appetite is useless, and that nothing is superfluous,
nothing disproportionate to its use, nothing unsuited to its end; but that,
on the contrary, everything is perfectly conformed to its destination in
life—we shall find that man, who alone is the final end and aim of this
order, is still the only animal that seems to be excepted from it. For his
natural gifts—not merely as regards the talents and motives that may in-
cite him to employ them, but especially the moral law in him—stretch so
far beyond all mere earthly utility and advantage, that he feels himself
bound to prize the mere consciousness of probity, apart from all advanta-
geous consequences—even the shadowy gift of posthumous fame—above
everything; and he is conscious of an inward call to constitute himself, by
his conduct in this world—without regard to mere sublunary interests—
the citizen of a better. This mighty, irresistible proof—accompanied by an
ever-increasing knowledge of the conformability to a purpose in every-
thing we see around us, by the conviction of the boundless immensity of
creation, by the consciousness of a certain illimitableness in the possible
extension of our knowledge, and by a desire commensurate therewith—
remains to humanity, even after the theoretical cognition of ourselves has
failed to establish the necessity of an existence after death.
247
The Critique of Pure Reason
because it proposes to prove the personality of the soul apart from this
communion (after death), and is therefore transcendent in the proper sense
of the word, although occupying itself with an object of experience—only
in so far, however, as it ceases to be an object of experience. But a suffi-
cient answer may be found to the question in our system. The difficulty
which lies in the execution of this task consists, as is well known, in the
presupposed heterogeneity of the object of the internal sense (the soul)
and the objects of the external senses; inasmuch as the formal condition of
the intuition of the one is time, and of that of the other space also. But if
we consider that both kinds of objects do not differ internally, but only in
so far as the one appears externally to the other—consequently, that what
lies at the basis of phenomena, as a thing in itself, may not be heteroge-
neous; this difficulty disappears. There then remains no other difficulty
than is to be found in the question—how a community of substances is
possible; a question which lies out of the region of psychology, and which
the reader, after what in our analytic has been said of primitive forces and
faculties, will easily judge to be also beyond the region of human cogni-
tion.
248
Immanuel Kant
GENERAL REMARK
249
The Critique of Pure Reason
object in itself by means of the representation “I,” but also for the purpose
of determining the mode of its existence, that is, of cognizing itself as
noumenon. But this is impossible, for the internal empirical intuition is
sensuous, and presents us with nothing but phenomenal data, which do
not assist the object of pure consciousness in its attempt to cognize itself
as a separate existence, but are useful only as contributions to experience.
But, let it be granted that we could discover, not in experience, but in
certain firmly-established a priori laws of the use of pure reason—laws
relating to our existence, authority to consider ourselves as legislating a
priori in relation to our own existence and as determining this existence;
we should, on this supposition, find ourselves possessed of a spontaneity,
by which our actual existence would be determinable, without the aid of
the conditions of empirical intuition. We should also become aware that
in the consciousness of our existence there was an a priori content, which
would serve to determine our own existence—an existence only sensu-
ously determinable—relatively, however, to a certain internal faculty in
relation to an intelligible world.
But this would not give the least help to the attempts of rational psy-
chology. For this wonderful faculty, which the consciousness of the moral
law in me reveals, would present me with a principle of the determination
of my own existence which is purely intellectual—but by what predicates?
By none other than those which are given in sensuous intuition. Thus I
should find myself in the same position in rational psychology which I
formerly occupied, that is to say, I should find myself still in need of
sensuous intuitions, in order to give significance to my conceptions of
substance and cause, by means of which alone I can possess a knowledge
of myself: but these intuitions can never raise me above the sphere of
experience. I should be justified, however, in applying these conceptions,
in regard to their practical use, which is always directed to objects of expe-
rience—in conformity with their analogical significance when employed
theoretically—to freedom and its subject. At the same time, I should un-
derstand by them merely the logical functions of subject and predicate, of
principle and consequence, in conformity with which all actions are so
determined, that they are capable of being explained along with the laws
of nature, conformably to the categories of substance and cause, although
they originate from a very different principle. We have made these obser-
vations for the purpose of guarding against misunderstanding, to which
the doctrine of our intuition of self as a phenomenon is exposed. We shall
have occasion to perceive their utility in the sequel.
250
Immanuel Kant
We showed in the introduction to this part of our work, that all transcen-
dental illusion of pure reason arose from dialectical arguments, the schema
of which logic gives us in its three formal species of syllogisms—just as the
categories find their logical schema in the four functions of all judge-
ments. The first kind of these sophistical arguments related to the uncon-
ditioned unity of the subjective conditions of all representations in gen-
eral (of the subject or soul), in correspondence with the categorical syllo-
gisms, the major of which, as the principle, enounces the relation of a
predicate to a subject. The second kind of dialectical argument will there-
fore be concerned, following the analogy with hypothetical syllogisms,
with the unconditioned unity of the objective conditions in the phenom-
enon; and, in this way, the theme of the third kind to be treated of in the
following chapter will be the unconditioned unity of the objective condi-
tions of the possibility of objects in general.
But it is worthy of remark that the transcendental paralogism produced
in the mind only a one-third illusion, in regard to the idea of the subject
of our thought; and the conceptions of reason gave no ground to main-
tain the contrary proposition. The advantage is completely on the side of
Pneumatism; although this theory itself passes into naught, in the cru-
cible of pure reason.
Very different is the case when we apply reason to the objective synthe-
sis of phenomena. Here, certainly, reason establishes, with much plausi-
bility, its principle of unconditioned unity; but it very soon falls into such
contradictions that it is compelled, in relation to cosmology, to renounce
its pretensions.
For here a new phenomenon of human reason meets us—a perfectly
natural antithetic, which does not require to be sought for by subtle soph-
istry, but into which reason of itself unavoidably falls. It is thereby pre-
served, to be sure, from the slumber of a fancied conviction—which a
merely one-sided illusion produces; but it is at the same time compelled,
either, on the one hand, to abandon itself to a despairing scepticism, or,
on the other, to assume a dogmatical confidence and obstinate persistence
in certain assertions, without granting a fair hearing to the other side of
the question. Either is the death of a sound philosophy, although the former
might perhaps deserve the title of the euthanasia of pure reason.
Before entering this region of discord and confusion, which the conflict
251
The Critique of Pure Reason
of the laws of pure reason (antinomy) produces, we shall present the reader
with some considerations, in explanation and justification of the method
we intend to follow in our treatment of this subject. I term all transcen-
dental ideas, in so far as they relate to the absolute totality in the synthesis
of phenomena, cosmical conceptions; partly on account of this uncondi-
tioned totality, on which the conception of the world-whole is based—a
conception, which is itself an idea—partly because they relate solely to the
synthesis of phenomena—the empirical synthesis; while, on the other hand,
the absolute totality in the synthesis of the conditions of all possible things
gives rise to an ideal of pure reason, which is quite distinct from the cosmical
conception, although it stands in relation with it. Hence, as the paralogisms
of pure reason laid the foundation for a dialectical psychology, the anti-
nomy of pure reason will present us with the transcendental principles of
a pretended pure (rational) cosmology—not, however, to declare it valid
and to appropriate it, but—as the very term of a conflict of reason suffi-
ciently indicates, to present it as an idea which cannot be reconciled with
phenomena and experience.
252
Immanuel Kant
253
The Critique of Pure Reason
254
Immanuel Kant
255
The Critique of Pure Reason
1
The absolute Completeness of the
COMPOSITION
of the given totality of all phenomena.
2
The absolute Completeness of the
DIVISION
of given totality in a phenomenon.
3
The absolute Completeness of the
ORIGINATION
of a phenomenon.
4
The absolute Completeness of the
DEPENDENCE of the EXISTENCE
of what is changeable in a phenomenon.
We must here remark, in the first place, that the idea of absolute totality
relates to nothing but the exposition of phenomena, and therefore not to
the pure conception of a totality of things. Phenomena are here, therefore,
regarded as given, and reason requires the absolute completeness of the
conditions of their possibility, in so far as these conditions constitute a
series-consequently an absolutely (that is, in every respect) complete syn-
thesis, whereby a phenomenon can be explained according to the laws of
the understanding.
Secondly, it is properly the unconditioned alone that reason seeks in
this serially and regressively conducted synthesis of conditions. It wishes,
to speak in another way, to attain to completeness in the series of pre-
misses, so as to render it unnecessary to presuppose others. This un-
conditioned is always contained in the absolute totality of the series,
when we endeavour to form a representation of it in thought. But this
absolutely complete synthesis is itself but an idea; for it is impossible,
at least before hand, to know whether any such synthesis is possible in
the case of phenomena. When we represent all existence in thought by
means of pure conceptions of the understanding, without any condi-
256
Immanuel Kant
tions of sensuous intuition, we may say with justice that for a given
conditioned the whole series of conditions subordinated to each other
is also given; for the former is only given through the latter. But we
find in the case of phenomena a particular limitation of the mode in
which conditions are given, that is, through the successive synthesis of
the manifold of intuition, which must be complete in the regress. Now
whether this completeness is sensuously possible, is a problem. But
the idea of it lies in the reason—be it possible or impossible to connect
with the idea adequate empirical conceptions. Therefore, as in the ab-
solute totality of the regressive synthesis of the manifold in a phenom-
enon (following the guidance of the categories, which represent it as a
series of conditions to a given conditioned) the unconditioned is nec-
essarily contained—it being still left unascertained whether and how
this totality exists; reason sets out from the idea of totality, although
its proper and final aim is the unconditioned—of the whole series, or
of a part thereof.
This unconditioned may be cogitated—either as existing only in the
entire series, all the members of which therefore would be without ex-
ception conditioned and only the totality absolutely unconditioned—
and in this case the regressus is called infinite; or the absolutely uncon-
ditioned is only a part of the series, to which the other members are
subordinated, but which Is not itself submitted to any other condition.*
In the former case the series is a parte priori unlimited (without begin-
ning), that is, infinite, and nevertheless completely given. But the re-
gress in it is never completed, and can only be called potentially infinite.
In the second case there exists a first in the series. This first is called, in
relation to past time, the beginning of the world; in relation to space,
the limit of the world; in relation to the parts of a given limited whole,
the simple; in relation to causes, absolute spontaneity (liberty); and in
relation to the existence of changeable things, absolute physical neces-
sity.
We possess two expressions, world and nature, which are generally in-
terchanged. The first denotes the mathematical total of all phenomena
and the totality of their synthesis—in its progress by means of composi-
259
The Critique of Pure Reason
unity of reason, it is too great for the understanding, if according with the
understanding, it is too small for the reason. Hence arises a mutual oppo-
sition, which cannot be avoided, do what we will.
These sophistical assertions of dialectic open, as it were, a battle-field,
where that side obtains the victory which has been permitted to make the
attack, and he is compelled to yield who has been unfortunately obliged
to stand on the defensive. And hence, champions of ability, whether on
the right or on the wrong side, are certain to carry away the crown of
victory, if they only take care to have the right to make the last attack, and
are not obliged to sustain another onset from their opponent. We can
easily believe that this arena has been often trampled by the feet of com-
batants, that many victories have been obtained on both sides, but that
the last victory, decisive of the affair between the contending parties, was
won by him who fought for the right, only if his adversary was forbidden
to continue the tourney. As impartial umpires, we must lay aside entirely
the consideration whether the combatants are fighting for the right or for
the wrong side, for the true or for the false, and allow the combat to be
first decided. Perhaps, after they have wearied more than injured each
other, they will discover the nothingness of their cause of quarrel and part
good friends.
This method of watching, or rather of originating, a conflict of
assertions, not for the purpose of finally deciding in favour of either
side, but to discover whether the object of the struggle is not a mere
illusion, which each strives in vain to reach, but which would be no
gain even when reached—this procedure, I say, may be termed the
sceptical method. It is thoroughly distinct from scepticism—the prin-
ciple of a technical and scientific ignorance, which undermines the
foundations of all knowledge, in order, if possible, to destroy our be-
lief and confidence therein. For the sceptical method aims at cer-
tainty, by endeavouring to discover in a conflict of this kind, con-
ducted honestly and intelligently on both sides, the point of misun-
derstanding; just as wise legislators derive, from the embarrassment
of judges in lawsuits, information in regard to the defective and ill-
defined parts of their statutes. The antinomy which reveals itself in
the application of laws, is for our limited wisdom the best criterion of
legislation. For the attention of reason, which in abstract speculation
does not easily become conscious of its errors, is thus roused to the
momenta in the determination of its principles.
But this sceptical method is essentially peculiar to transcendental
260
Immanuel Kant
*The antinomies stand in the order of the four transcendental ideas above de-
tailed.
261
The Critique of Pure Reason
THESIS.
PROOF.
Granted that the world has no beginning in time; up to every given mo-
ment of time, an eternity must have elapsed, and therewith passed away
an infinite series of successive conditions or states of things in the world.
Now the infinity of a series consists in the fact that it never can be com-
pleted by means of a successive synthesis. It follows that an infinite series
already elapsed is impossible and that, consequently, a beginning of the
world is a necessary condition of its existence. And this was the first thing
to be proved.
As regards the second, let us take the opposite for granted. In this case,
the world must be an infinite given total of coexistent things. Now we
cannot cogitate the dimensions of a quantity, which is not given within
certain limits of an intuition,* in any other way than by means of the
synthesis of its parts, and the total of such a quantity only by means of a
completed synthesis, or the repeated addition of unity to itself. Accord-
ingly, to cogitate the world, which fills all spaces, as a whole, the successive
synthesis of the parts of an infinite world must be looked upon as com-
pleted, that is to say, an infinite time must be regarded as having elapsed
in the enumeration of all co-existing things; which is impossible. For this
reason an infinite aggregate of actual things cannot be considered as a
given whole, consequently, not as a contemporaneously given whole. The
world is consequently, as regards extension in space, not infinite, but en-
closed in limits. And this was the second thing to be proved.
ANTITHESIS.
The world has no beginning, and no limits in space, but is, in rela-
tion both to time and space, infinite.
PROOF.
*Space is merely the form of external intuition (formal intuition), and not a real
object which can be externally perceived. Space, prior to all things which determine it
(fill or limit it), or, rather, which present an empirical intuition conformable to it, is,
under the title of absolute space, nothing but the mere possibility of external phe-
nomena, in so far as they either exist in themselves, or can annex themselves to given
intuitions. Empirical intuition is therefore not a composition of phenomena and
space (of perception and empty intuition). The one is not the correlate of the other in
a synthesis, but they are vitally connected in the same empirical intuition, as matter
and form. If we wish to set one of these two apart from the other—space from phe-
nomena—there arise all sorts of empty determinations of external intuition, which
are very far from being possible perceptions. For example, motion or rest of the world
in an infinite empty space, or a determination of the mutual relation of both, cannot
possibly be perceived, and is therefore merely the predicate of a notional entity.
263
The Critique of Pure Reason
ON THE THESIS.
*The quantum in this sense contains a congeries of given units, which is greater
than any number—and this is the mathematical conception of the infinite.
264
Immanuel Kant
ON THE ANTITHESIS.
The proof in favour of the infinity of the cosmical succession and the
cosmical content is based upon the consideration that, in the opposite
case, a void time and a void space must constitute the limits of the world.
Now I am not unaware, that there are some ways of escaping this conclu-
sion. It may, for example, be alleged, that a limit to the world, as regards
both space and time, is quite possible, without at the same time holding
the existence of an absolute time before the beginning of the world, or an
absolute space extending beyond the actual world—which is impossible. I
am quite well satisfied with the latter part of this opinion of the philoso-
phers of the Leibnitzian school. Space is merely the form of external intu-
ition, but not a real object which can itself be externally intuited; it is not
a correlate of phenomena, it is the form of phenomena itself. Space, there-
fore, cannot be regarded as absolutely and in itself something determina-
tive of the existence of things, because it is not itself an object, but only
the form of possible objects. Consequently, things, as phenomena, deter-
mine space; that is to say, they render it possible that, of all the possible
predicates of space (size and relation), certain may belong to reality. But
we cannot affirm the converse, that space, as something self-subsistent,
can determine real things in regard to size or shape, for it is in itself not a
real thing. Space (filled or void)* may therefore be limited by phenomena,
*It is evident that what is meant here is, that empty space, in so far as it is limited
by phenomena—space, that is, within the world—does not at least contradict
transcendental principles, and may therefore, as regards them, be admitted, al-
though its possibility cannot on that account be affirmed.
265
The Critique of Pure Reason
266
Immanuel Kant
THESIS.
Every composite substance in the world consists of simple parts; and there
exists nothing that is not either itself simple, or composed of simple parts.
PROOF.
ANTITHESIS.
No composite thing in the world consists of simple parts; and there does
not exist in the world any simple substance.
267
The Critique of Pure Reason
PROOF.
268
Immanuel Kant
THESIS.
269
The Critique of Pure Reason
ANTITHESIS.
270
Immanuel Kant
271
The Critique of Pure Reason
THESIS.
Causality according to the laws of nature, is not the only causality operat-
ing to originate the phenomena of the world. A causality of freedom is
also necessary to account fully for these phenomena.
PROOF.
Let it be supposed, that there is no other kind of causality than that ac-
cording to the laws of nature. Consequently, everything that happens pre-
supposes a previous condition, which it follows with absolute certainty, in
conformity with a rule. But this previous condition must itself be some-
thing that has happened (that has arisen in time, as it did not exist before),
for, if it has always been in existence, its consequence or effect would not
thus originate for the first time, but would likewise have always existed.
The causality, therefore, of a cause, whereby something happens, is itself a
thing that has happened. Now this again presupposes, in conformity with
the law of nature, a previous condition and its causality, and this another
anterior to the former, and so on. If, then, everything happens solely in
accordance with the laws of nature, there cannot be any real first begin-
ning of things, but only a subaltern or comparative beginning. There can-
not, therefore, be a completeness of series on the side of the causes which
originate the one from the other. But the law of nature is that nothing can
happen without a sufficient a priori determined cause. The proposition
therefore—if all causality is possible only in accordance with the laws of
nature—is, when stated in this unlimited and general manner, self-con-
tradictory. It follows that this cannot be the only kind of causality.
From what has been said, it follows that a causality must be admitted,
by means of which something happens, without its cause being deter-
mined according to necessary laws by some other cause preceding. That is
to say, there must exist an absolute spontaneity of cause, which of itself
originates a series of phenomena which proceeds according to natural
laws—consequently transcendental freedom, without which even in the
course of nature the succession of phenomena on the side of causes is
never complete.
272
Immanuel Kant
ANTITHESIS.
PROOF.
273
The Critique of Pure Reason
ON THE THESIS.
274
Immanuel Kant
ON THE ANTITHESIS.
275
The Critique of Pure Reason
which you can just as little comprehend; and even the possibility of so
simple a conception as that of change must present to you insuperable
difficulties. For if experience did not teach you that it was real, you never
could conceive a priori the possibility of this ceaseless sequence of being
and non-being.
But if the existence of a transcendental faculty of freedom is granted—
a faculty of originating changes in the world—this faculty must at least
exist out of and apart from the world; although it is certainly a bold as-
sumption, that, over and above the complete content of all possible intui-
tions, there still exists an object which cannot be presented in any possible
perception. But, to attribute to substances in the world itself such a fac-
ulty, is quite inadmissible; for, in this case; the connection of phenomena
reciprocally determining and determined according to general laws, which
is termed nature, and along with it the criteria of empirical truth, which
enable us to distinguish experience from mere visionary dreaming, would
almost entirely disappear. In proximity with such a lawless faculty of free-
dom, a system of nature is hardly cogitable; for the laws of the latter would
be continually subject to the intrusive influences of the former, and the
course of phenomena, which would otherwise proceed regularly and uni-
formly, would become thereby confused and disconnected.
276
Immanuel Kant
THESIS.
PROOF.
The world of sense, as the sum total of all phenomena, contains a series of
changes. For, without such a series, the mental representation of the series
of time itself, as the condition of the possibility of the sensuous world,
could not be presented to us.* But every change stands under its condi-
tion, which precedes it in time and renders it necessary. Now the existence
of a given condition presupposes a complete series of conditions up to the
absolutely unconditioned, which alone is absolutely necessary. It follows
that something that is absolutely necessary must exist, if change exists as
its consequence. But this necessary thing itself belongs to the sensuous
world. For suppose it to exist out of and apart from it, the series of cosmical
changes would receive from it a beginning, and yet this necessary cause
would not itself belong to the world of sense. But this is impossible. For,
as the beginning of a series in time is determined only by that which
precedes it in time, the supreme condition of the beginning of a series of
changes must exist in the time in which this series itself did not exist; for
a beginning supposes a time preceding, in which the thing that begins to
be was not in existence. The causality of the necessary cause of changes,
and consequently the cause itself, must for these reasons belong to time—
and to phenomena, time being possible only as the form of phenomena.
Consequently, it cannot be cogitated as separated from the world of sense—
the sum total of all phenomena. There is, therefore, contained in the world,
something that is absolutely necessary—whether it be the whole cosmical
series itself, or only a part of it.
ANTITHESIS.
An absolutely necessary being does not exist, either in the world, or out of
it—as its cause.
PROOF.
Grant that either the world itself is necessary, or that there is contained in
it a necessary existence. Two cases are possible. First, there must either be
in the series of cosmical changes a beginning, which is unconditionally
necessary, and therefore uncaused-which is at variance with the dynamical
law of the determination of all phenomena in time; or, secondly, the series
itself is without beginning, and, although contingent and conditioned in
all its parts, is nevertheless absolutely necessary and unconditioned as a
whole—which is self-contradictory. For the existence of an aggregate can-
not be necessary, if no single part of it possesses necessary existence.
Grant, on the other band, that an absolutely necessary cause exists out
of and apart from the world. This cause, as the highest member in the
series of the causes of cosmical changes, must originate or begin* the exist-
ence of the latter and their series. In this case it must also begin to act, and
its causality would therefore belong to time, and consequently to the sum
total of phenomena, that is, to the world. It follows that the cause cannot
be out of the world; which is contradictory to the hypothesis. Therefore,
neither in the world, nor out of it (but in causal connection with it), does
there exist any absolutely necessary being.
*The word begin is taken in two senses. The first is active—the cause being
regarded as beginning a series of conditions as its effect (infit). The second is
passive—the causality in the cause itself beginning to operate (fit). I reason here
from the first to the second.
278
Immanuel Kant
ON THE THESIS.
279
The Critique of Pure Reason
ascending series of empirical conditions: and in this they are quite right.
But as they could not find in this series any primal beginning or any
highest member, they passed suddenly from the empirical conception of
contingency to the pure category, which presents us with a series—not
sensuous, but intellectual—whose completeness does certainly rest upon
the existence of an absolutely necessary cause. Nay, more, this intellectual
series is not tied to any sensuous conditions; and is therefore free from the
condition of time, which requires it spontaneously to begin its causality in
time. But such a procedure is perfectly inadmissible, as will be made plain
from what follows.
In the pure sense of the categories, that is contingent the contradictory
opposite of which is possible. Now we cannot reason from empirical con-
tingency to intellectual. The opposite of that which is changed—the op-
posite of its state—is actual at another time, and is therefore possible.
Consequently, it is not the contradictory opposite of the former state. To
be that, it is necessary that, in the same time in which the preceding state
existed, its opposite could have existed in its place; but such a cognition is
not given us in the mere phenomenon of change. A body that was in
motion = A, comes into a state of rest = non-A. Now it cannot be con-
cluded from the fact that a state opposite to the state A follows it, that the
contradictory opposite of A is possible; and that A is therefore contingent.
To prove this, we should require to know that the state of rest could have
existed in the very same time in which the motion took place. Now we
know nothing more than that the state of rest was actual in the time that
followed the state of motion; consequently, that it was also possible. But
motion at one time, and rest at another time, are not contradictorily op-
posed to each other. It follows from what has been said that the succession
of opposite determinations, that is, change, does not demonstrate the fact
of contingency as represented in the conceptions of the pure understand-
ing; and that it cannot, therefore, conduct us to the fact of the existence of
a necessary being. Change proves merely empirical contingency, that is to
say, that the new state could not have existed without a cause, which be-
longs to the preceding time. This cause—even although it is regarded as
absolutely necessary—must be presented to us in time, and must belong
to the series of phenomena.
ON THE ANTITHESIS.
The difficulties which meet us, in our attempt to rise through the series of
phenomena to the existence of an absolutely necessary supreme cause,
280
Immanuel Kant
must not originate from our inability to establish the truth of our mere
conceptions of the necessary existence of a thing. That is to say, our objec-
tions not be ontological, but must be directed against the causal connec-
tion with a series of phenomena of a condition which is itself uncondi-
tioned. In one word, they must be cosmological and relate to empirical
laws. We must show that the regress in the series of causes (in the world of
sense) cannot conclude with an empirically unconditioned condition, and
that the cosmological argument from the contingency of the cosmical
state—a contingency alleged to arise from change—does not justify us in
accepting a first cause, that is, a prime originator of the cosmical series.
The reader will observe in this antinomy a very remarkable contrast.
The very same grounds of proof which established in the thesis the exist-
ence of a supreme being, demonstrated in the antithesis—and with equal
strictness—the non-existence of such a being. We found, first, that a nec-
essary being exists, because the whole time past contains the series of all
conditions, and with it, therefore, the unconditioned (the necessary); sec-
ondly, that there does not exist any necessary being, for the same reason,
that the whole time past contains the series of all conditions—which are
themselves, therefore, in the aggregate, conditioned. The cause of this seem-
ing incongruity is as follows. We attend, in the first argument, solely to
the absolute totality of the series of conditions, the one of which deter-
mines the other in time, and thus arrive at a necessary unconditioned. In
the second, we consider, on the contrary, the contingency of everything
that is determined in the series of time-for every event is preceded by a
time, in which the condition itself must be determined as conditioned—
and thus everything that is unconditioned or absolutely necessary disap-
pears. In both, the mode of proof is quite in accordance with the common
procedure of human reason, which often falls into discord with itself,
from considering an object from two different points of view. Herr von
Mairan regarded the controversy between two celebrated astronomers,
which arose from a similar difficulty as to the choice of a proper stand-
point, as a phenomenon of sufficient importance to warrant a separate
treatise on the subject. The one concluded: the moon revolves on its own
axis, because it constantly presents the same side to the earth; the other
declared that the moon does not revolve on its own axis, for the same
reason. Both conclusions were perfectly correct, according to the point of
view from which the motions of the moon were considered.
281
The Critique of Pure Reason
282
Immanuel Kant
the highest aspirations and most ardent desires of humanity. Nay, it may
even be said that the true value of mathematics-that pride of human rea-
son—consists in this: that she guides reason to the knowledge of nature—
in her greater as well as in her less manifestations—in her beautiful order
and regularity—guides her, moreover, to an insight into the wonderful
unity of the moving forces in the operations of nature, far beyond the
expectations of a philosophy building only on experience; and that she
thus encourages philosophy to extend the province of reason beyond all
experience, and at the same time provides it with the most excellent mate-
rials for supporting its investigations, in so far as their nature admits, by
adequate and accordant intuitions.
Unfortunately for speculation—but perhaps fortunately for the practi-
cal interests of humanity—reason, in the midst of her highest anticipa-
tions, finds herself hemmed in by a press of opposite and contradictory
conclusions, from which neither her honour nor her safety will permit her
to draw back. Nor can she regard these conflicting trains of reasoning
with indifference as mere passages at arms, still less can she command
peace; for in the subject of the conflict she has a deep interest. There is no
other course left open to her than to reflect with herself upon the origin of
this disunion in reason—whether it may not arise from a mere misunder-
standing. After such an inquiry, arrogant claims would have to be given
up on both sides; but the sovereignty of reason over understanding and
sense would be based upon a sure foundation.
We shall at present defer this radical inquiry and, in the meantime,
consider for a little what side in the controversy we should most willingly
take, if we were obliged to become partisans at all. As, in this case, we
leave out of sight altogether the logical criterion of truth, and merely con-
sult our own interest in reference to the question, these considerations,
although inadequate to settle the question of right in either party, will
enable us to comprehend how those who have taken part in the struggle,
adopt the one view rather than the other—no special insight into the
subject, however, having influenced their choice. They will, at the same
time, explain to us many other things by the way—for example, the fiery
zeal on the one side and the cold maintenance of their cause on the other;
why the one party has met with the warmest approbations, and the other
has always been repulsed by irreconcilable prejudices.
There is one thing, however, that determines the proper point of view,
from which alone this preliminary inquiry can be instituted and carried
on with the proper completeness—and that is the comparison of the prin-
ciples from which both sides, thesis and antithesis, proceed. My readers
283
The Critique of Pure Reason
3. This side has also the advantage of popularity; and this constitutes no
small part of its claim to favour. The common understanding does not
find the least difficulty in the idea of the unconditioned beginning of all
284
Immanuel Kant
1. We cannot discover any such practical interest arising from pure prin-
ciples of reason as morality and religion present. On the contrary, pure
empiricism seems to empty them of all their power and influence. If there
does not exist a Supreme Being distinct from the world—if the world is
without beginning, consequently without a Creator—if our wills are not
free, and the soul is divisible and subject to corruption just like matter—
the ideas and principles of morality lose all validity and fall with the tran-
scendental ideas which constituted their theoretical support.
285
The Critique of Pure Reason
286
Immanuel Kant
*It is, however, still a matter of doubt whether Epicurus ever propounded these
principles as directions for the objective employment of the understanding. If,
indeed, they were nothing more than maxims for the speculative exercise of rea-
son, he gives evidence therein a more genuine philosophic spirit than any of the
philosophers of antiquity. That, in the explanation of phenomena, we must pro-
ceed as if the field of inquiry had neither limits in space nor commencement in
time; that we must be satisfied with the teaching of experience in reference to the
material of which the world is posed; that we must not look for any other mode
of the origination of events than that which is determined by the unalterable laws
of nature; and finally, that we not employ the hypothesis of a cause distinct from
the world to account for a phenomenon or for the world itself—are principles for
the extension of speculative philosophy, and the discovery of the true sources of
the principles of morals, which, however little conformed to in the present day,
are undoubtedly correct. At the same time, any one desirous of ignoring, in mere
speculation, these dogmatical propositions, need not for that reason be accused
of denying them.
287
The Critique of Pure Reason
288
Immanuel Kant
the confusion than to settle the truth of one or other of the conflicting
doctrines, would live in a state of continual hesitation. Today, he would
feel convinced that the human will is free; to-morrow, considering the
indissoluble chain of nature, he would look on freedom as a mere illusion
and declare nature to be all-in-all. But, if he were called to action, the play
of the merely speculative reason would disappear like the shapes of a dream,
and practical interest would dictate his choice of principles. But, as it well
befits a reflective and inquiring being to devote certain periods of time to
the examination of its own reason—to divest itself of all partiality, and
frankly to communicate its observations for the judgement and opinion
of others; so no one can be blamed for, much less prevented from, placing
both parties on their trial, with permission to end themselves, free from
intimidation, before intimidation, before a sworn jury of equal condition
with themselves—the condition of weak and fallible men.
To avow an ability to solve all problems and to answer all questions would
be a profession certain to convict any philosopher of extravagant boasting
and self-conceit, and at once to destroy the confidence that might other-
wise have been reposed in him. There are, however, sciences so consti-
tuted that every question arising within their sphere must necessarily be
capable of receiving an answer from the knowledge already possessed, for
the answer must be received from the same sources whence the question
arose. In such sciences it is not allowable to excuse ourselves on the plea of
necessary and unavoidable ignorance; a solution is absolutely requisite.
The rule of right and wrong must help us to the knowledge of what is
right or wrong in all possible cases; otherwise, the idea of obligation or
duty would be utterly null, for we cannot have any obligation to that
which we cannot know. On the other hand, in our investigations of the
phenomena of nature, much must remain uncertain, and many questions
continue insoluble; because what we know of nature is far from being
sufficient to explain all the phenomena that are presented to our observa-
tion. Now the question is: Whether there is in transcendental philosophy
any question, relating to an object presented to pure reason, which is un-
answerable by this reason; and whether we must regard the subject of the
question as quite uncertain, so far as our knowledge extends, and must
give it a place among those subjects, of which we have just so much con-
289
The Critique of Pure Reason
291
The Critique of Pure Reason
292
Immanuel Kant
293
The Critique of Pure Reason
294
Immanuel Kant
295
The Critique of Pure Reason
of a thing that in relation to some other thing it is too large or too small,
the former is considered as existing for the sake of the latter, and requiring
to be adapted to it. Among the trivial subjects of discussion in the old
schools of dialectics was this question: “If a ball cannot pass through a
hole, shall we say that the ball is too large or the hole too small?” In this
case it is indifferent what expression we employ; for we do not know which
exists for the sake of the other. On the other hand, we cannot say: “The
man is too long for his coat”; but: “The coat is too short for the man.”
We are thus led to the well-founded suspicion that the cosmological
ideas, and all the conflicting sophistical assertions connected with them,
are based upon a false and fictitious conception of the mode in which the
object of these ideas is presented to us; and this suspicion will probably
direct us how to expose the illusion that has so long led us astray from the
truth.
*I have elsewhere termed this theory formal idealism, to distinguish it from ma-
terial idealism, which doubts or denies the existence of external things. To avoid
ambiguity, it seems advisable in many cases to employ this term instead of that
mentioned in the text.
296
Immanuel Kant
nal sense, are real. For, as space is the form of that intuition which we call
external, and, without objects in space, no empirical representation could
be given us, we can and ought to regard extended bodies in it as real. The
case is the same with representations in time. But time and space, with all
phenomena therein, are not in themselves things. They are nothing but
representations and cannot exist out of and apart from the mind. Nay, the
sensuous internal intuition of the mind (as the object of consciousness),
the determination of which is represented by the succession of different
states in time, is not the real, proper self, as it exists in itself—not the
transcendental subject—but only a phenomenon, which is presented to
the sensibility of this, to us, unknown being. This internal phenomenon
cannot be admitted to be a self-subsisting thing; for its condition is time,
and time cannot be the condition of a thing in itself. But the empirical
truth of phenomena in space and time is guaranteed beyond the possibil-
ity of doubt, and sufficiently distinguished from the illusion of dreams or
fancy—although both have a proper and thorough connection in an ex-
perience according to empirical laws. The objects of experience then are
not things in themselves, but are given only in experience, and have no
existence apart from and independently of experience. That there may be
inhabitants in the moon, although no one has ever observed them, must
certainly be admitted; but this assertion means only, that we may in the
possible progress of experience discover them at some future time. For
that which stands in connection with a perception according to the laws
of the progress of experience is real. They are therefore really existent, if
they stand in empirical connection with my actual or real consciousness,
although they are not in themselves real, that is, apart from the progress of
experience.
There is nothing actually given—we can be conscious of nothing as
real, except a perception and the empirical progression from it to other
possible perceptions. For phenomena, as mere representations, are real
only in perception; and perception is, in fact, nothing but the reality of an
empirical representation, that is, a phenomenon. To call a phenomenon a
real thing prior to perception means either that we must meet with this
phenomenon in the progress of experience, or it means nothing at all. For
I can say only of a thing in itself that it exists without relation to the senses
and experience. But we are speaking here merely of phenomena in space
and time, both of which are determinations of sensibility, and not of things
in themselves. It follows that phenomena are not things in themselves, but
are mere representations, which if not given in us—in perception—are
non-existent.
297
The Critique of Pure Reason
298
Immanuel Kant
therein I must stop, and at what point in the regress I am to find this
member—is transcendental, and hence necessarily incognizable. But with
this we have not to do; our concern is only with the law of progression in
experience, in which objects, that is, phenomena, are given. It is a matter
of indifference, whether I say, “I may in the progress of experience dis-
cover stars, at a hundred times greater distance than the most distant of
those now visible,” or, “Stars at this distance may be met in space, al-
though no one has, or ever will discover them.” For, if they are given as
things in themselves, without any relation to possible experience, they are
for me non-existent, consequently, are not objects, for they are not con-
tained in the regressive series of experience. But, if these phenomena must
be employed in the construction or support of the cosmological idea of an
absolute whole, and when we are discussing a question that oversteps the
limits of possible experience, the proper distinction of the different theo-
ries of the reality of sensuous objects is of great importance, in order to
avoid the illusion which must necessarily arise from the misinterpretation
of our empirical conceptions.
The antinomy of pure reason is based upon the following dialectical argu-
ment: “If that which is conditioned is given, the whole series of its condi-
tions is also given; but sensuous objects are given as conditioned; conse-
quently...” This syllogism, the major of which seems so natural and evi-
dent, introduces as many cosmological ideas as there are different kinds of
conditions in the synthesis of phenomena, in so far as these conditions
constitute a series. These ideas require absolute totality in the series, and
thus place reason in inextricable embarrassment. Before proceeding to
expose the fallacy in this dialectical argument, it will be necessary to have
a correct understanding of certain conceptions that appear in it.
In the first place, the following proposition is evident, and indubitably
certain: “If the conditioned is given, a regress in the series of all its condi-
tions is thereby imperatively required.” For the very conception of a con-
ditioned is a conception of something related to a condition, and, if this
condition is itself conditioned, to another condition—and so on through
all the members of the series. This proposition is, therefore, analytical and
has nothing to fear from transcendental criticism. It is a logical postulate
of reason: to pursue, as far as possible, the connection of a conception
with its conditions.
299
The Critique of Pure Reason
If, in the second place, both the conditioned and the condition are things
in themselves, and if the former is given, not only is the regress to the
latter requisite, but the latter is really given with the former. Now, as this
is true of all the members of the series, the entire series of conditions, and
with them the unconditioned, is at the same time given in the very fact of
the conditioned, the existence of which is possible only in and through
that series, being given. In this case, the synthesis of the conditioned with
its condition, is a synthesis of the understanding merely, which represents
things as they are, without regarding whether and how we can cognize
them. But if I have to do with phenomena, which, in their character of
mere representations, are not given, if I do not attain to a cognition of
them (in other words, to themselves, for they are nothing more than em-
pirical cognitions), I am not entitled to say: “If the conditioned is given,
all its conditions (as phenomena) are also given.” I cannot, therefore, from
the fact of a conditioned being given, infer the absolute totality of the
series of its conditions. For phenomena are nothing but an empirical syn-
thesis in apprehension or perception, and are therefore given only in it.
Now, in speaking of phenomena it does not follow that, if the condi-
tioned is given, the synthesis which constitutes its empirical condition is
also thereby given and presupposed; such a synthesis can be established
only by an actual regress in the series of conditions. But we are entitled to
say in this case that a regress to the conditions of a conditioned, in other
words, that a continuous empirical synthesis is enjoined; that, if the con-
ditions are not given, they are at least required; and that we are certain to
discover the conditions in this regress.
We can now see that the major, in the above cosmological syllogism,
takes the conditioned in the transcendental signification which it has in
the pure category, while the minor speaks of it in the empirical significa-
tion which it has in the category as applied to phenomena. There is, there-
fore, a dialectical fallacy in the syllogism—a sophisma figurae dictionis.
But this fallacy is not a consciously devised one, but a perfectly natural
illusion of the common reason of man. For, when a thing is given as con-
ditioned, we presuppose in the major its conditions and their series, un-
perceived, as it were, and unseen; because this is nothing more than the
logical requirement of complete and satisfactory premisses for a given con-
clusion. In this case, time is altogether left out in the connection of the
conditioned with the condition; they are supposed to be given in them-
selves, and contemporaneously. It is, moreover, just as natural to regard
phenomena (in the minor) as things in themselves and as objects pre-
sented to the pure understanding, as in the major, in which complete
300
Immanuel Kant
301
The Critique of Pure Reason
absurd. But I cannot believe that there is any justice in this accusation.
The first of these propositions I shall presently consider in a more detailed
manner. With regard to the others, if by the word of God he understood
merely the Universe, his meaning must have been—that it cannot be per-
manently present in one place—that is, at rest—nor be capable of chang-
ing its place—that is, of moving-because all places are in the universe, and
the universe itself is, therefore, in no place. Again, if the universe contains
in itself everything that exists, it cannot be similar or dissimilar to any
other thing, because there is, in fact, no other thing with which it can be
compared. If two opposite judgements presuppose a contingent impos-
sible, or arbitrary condition, both—in spite of their opposition (which is,
however, not properly or really a contradiction)—fall away; because the
condition, which ensured the validity of both, has itself disappeared.
If we say: “Everybody has either a good or a bad smell,” we have omit-
ted a third possible judgement—it has no smell at all; and thus both con-
flicting statements may be false. If we say: “It is either good-smelling or
not good-smelling (vel suaveolens vel non-suaveolens),” both judgements
are contradictorily opposed; and the contradictory opposite of the former
judgement—some bodies are not good-smelling—embraces also those
bodies which have no smell at all. In the preceding pair of opposed judge-
ments (per disparata), the contingent condition of the conception of body
(smell) attached to both conflicting statements, instead of having been
omitted in the latter, which is consequently not the contradictory oppo-
site of the former.
If, accordingly, we say: “The world is either infinite in extension, or it is
not infinite (non est infinitus)”; and if the former proposition is false, its
contradictory opposite—the world is not infinite—must be true. And
thus I should deny the existence of an infinite, without, however affirm-
ing the existence of a finite world. But if we construct our proposition
thus: “The world is either infinite or finite (non-infinite),” both state-
ments may be false. For, in this case, we consider the world as per se
determined in regard to quantity, and while, in the one judgement, we
deny its infinite and consequently, perhaps, its independent existence; in
the other, we append to the world, regarded as a thing in itself, a certain
determination—that of finitude; and the latter may be false as well as the
former, if the world is not given as a thing in itself, and thus neither as
finite nor as infinite in quantity. This kind of opposition I may be allowed
to term dialectical; that of contradictories may be called analytical oppo-
sition. Thus then, of two dialectically opposed judgements both may be
false, from the fact, that the one is not a mere contradictory of the other,
302
Immanuel Kant
but actually enounces more than is requisite for a full and complete con-
tradiction.
When we regard the two propositions—“The world is infinite in quan-
tity,” and, “The world is finite in quantity,” as contradictory opposites, we
are assuming that the world—the complete series of phenomena—is a
thing in itself. For it remains as a permanent quantity, whether I deny the
infinite or the finite regress in the series of its phenomena. But if we dis-
miss this assumption—this transcendental illusion—and deny that it is a
thing in itself, the contradictory opposition is metamorphosed into a merely
dialectical one; and the world, as not existing in itself—independently of
the regressive series of my representations—exists in like manner neither
as a whole which is infinite nor as a whole which is finite in itself. The
universe exists for me only in the empirical regress of the series of phe-
nomena and not per se. If, then, it is always conditioned, it is never com-
pletely or as a whole; and it is, therefore, not an unconditioned whole and
does not exist as such, either with an infinite, or with a finite quantity.
What we have here said of the first cosmological idea—that of the abso-
lute totality of quantity in phenomena—applies also to the others. The
series of conditions is discoverable only in the regressive synthesis itself,
and not in the phenomenon considered as a thing in itself—given prior to
all regress. Hence I am compelled to say: “The aggregate of parts in a
given phenomenon is in itself neither finite nor infinite; and these parts
are given only in the regressive synthesis of decomposition—a synthesis
which is never given in absolute completeness, either as finite, or as infi-
nite.” The same is the case with the series of subordinated causes, or of the
conditioned up to the unconditioned and necessary existence, which can
never be regarded as in itself, ind in its totality, either as finite or as infi-
nite; because, as a series of subordinate representations, it subsists only in
the dynamical regress and cannot be regarded as existing previously to this
regress, or as a self-subsistent series of things.
Thus the antinomy of pure reason in its cosmological ideas disappears.
For the above demonstration has established the fact that it is merely the
product of a dialectical and illusory opposition, which arises from the
application of the idea of absolute totality—admissible only as a condi-
tion of things in themselves—to phenomena, which exist only in our rep-
resentations, and—when constituting a series—in a successive regress. This
antinomy of reason may, however, be really profitable to our speculative
interests, not in the way of contributing any dogmatical addition, but as
presenting to us another material support in our critical investigations.
For it furnishes us with an indirect proof of the transcendental ideality of
303
The Critique of Pure Reason
phenomena, if our minds were not completely satisfied with the direct
proof set forth in the Trancendental Aesthetic. The proof would proceed
in the following dilemma. If the world is a whole existing in itself, it must
be either finite or infinite. But it is neither finite nor infinite—as has been
shown, on the one side, by the thesis, on the other, by the antithesis.
Therefore the world—the content of all phenomena—is not a whole ex-
isting in itself. It follows that phenomena are nothing, apart from our
representations. And this is what we mean by transcendental ideality.
This remark is of some importance. It enables us to see that the proofs
of the fourfold antinomy are not mere sophistries—are not fallacious, but
grounded on the nature of reason, and valid—under the supposition that
phenomena are things in themselves. The opposition of the judgements
which follow makes it evident that a fallacy lay in the initial supposition,
and thus helps us to discover the true constitution of objects of sense. This
transcendental dialectic does not favour scepticism, although it presents
us with a triumphant demonstration of the advantages of the sceptical
method, the great utility of which is apparent in the antinomy, where the
arguments of reason were allowed to confront each other in undiminished
force. And although the result of these conflicts of reason is not what we
expected—although we have obtained no positive dogmatical addition to
metaphysical science—we have still reaped a great advantage in the cor-
rection of our judgements on these subjects of thought.
The cosmological principle of totality could not give us any certain knowl-
edge in regard to the maximum in the series of conditions in the world of
sense, considered as a thing in itself. The actual regress in the series is the
only means of approaching this maximum. This principle of pure reason,
therefore, may still be considered as valid—not as an axiom enabling us to
cogitate totality in the object as actual, but as a problem for the under-
standing, which requires it to institute and to continue, in conformity
with the idea of totality in the mind, the regress in the series of the condi-
tions of a given conditioned. For in the world of sense, that is, in space
and time, every condition which we discover in our investigation of phe-
nomena is itself conditioned; because sensuous objects are not things in
themselves (in which case an absolutely unconditioned might be reached
in the progress of cognition), but are merely empirical representations the
304
Immanuel Kant
305
The Critique of Pure Reason
guishable notions, although the ground of the distinction has never been
clearly exposed. The term employed by the mathematicians is progressus
in infinitum. The philosophers prefer the expression progressus in
indefinitum. Without detaining the reader with an examination of the
reasons for such a distinction, or with remarks on the right or wrong use
of the terms, I shall endeavour clearly to determine these conceptions, so
far as is necessary for the purpose in this Critique.
We may, with propriety, say of a straight line, that it may be produced
to infinity. In this case the distinction between a progressus in infinitum
and a progressus in indefinitum is a mere piece of subtlety. For, although
when we say, “Produce a straight line,” it is more correct to say in
indefinitum than in infinitum; because the former means, “Produce it as
far as you please,” the second, “You must not cease to produce it”; the
expression in infinitum is, when we are speaking of the power to do it,
perfectly correct, for we can always make it longer if we please—on to
infinity. And this remark holds good in all cases, when we speak of a
progressus, that is, an advancement from the condition to the conditioned;
this possible advancement always proceeds to infinity. We may proceed
from a given pair in the descending line of generation from father to son,
and cogitate a never-ending line of descendants from it. For in such a case
reason does not demand absolute totality in the series, because it does not
presuppose it as a condition and as given (datum), but merely as condi-
tioned, and as capable of being given (dabile).
Very different is the case with the problem: “How far the regress, which
ascends from the given conditioned to the conditions, must extend”; whether
I can say: “It is a regress in infinitum,” or only “in indefinitum”; and whether,
for example, setting out from the human beings at present alive in the world,
I may ascend in the series of their ancestors, in infinitum—mr whether all
that can be said is, that so far as I have proceeded, I have discovered no
empirical ground for considering the series limited, so that I am justified,
and indeed, compelled to search for ancestors still further back, although I
am not obliged by the idea of reason to presuppose them.
My answer to this question is: “If the series is given in empirical intu-
ition as a whole, the regress in the series of its internal conditions proceeds
in infinitum; but, if only one member of the series is given, from which
the regress is to proceed to absolute totality, the regress is possible only in
indefinitum.” For example, the division of a portion of matter given within
certain limits—of a body, that is—proceeds in infinitum. For, as the con-
dition of this whole is its part, and the condition of the part a part of the
part, and so on, and as in this regress of decomposition an unconditioned
306
Immanuel Kant
307
The Critique of Pure Reason
Here, as well as in the case of the other cosmological problems, the ground
308
Immanuel Kant
*The cosmical series can neither be greater nor smaller than the possible empirical
regress, upon which its conception is based. And as this regress cannot be a deter-
minate infinite regress, still less a determinate finite (absolutely limited), it is evi-
dent that we cannot regard the world as either finite or infinite, because the regress,
which gives us the representation of the world, is neither finite nor infinite.
309
The Critique of Pure Reason
*The reader will remark that the proof presented above is very different from the dog-
matical demonstration given in the antithesis of the first antinomy. In that demonstra-
tion, it was taken for granted that the world is a thing in itself—given in its totality prior
to all regress, and a determined position in space and time was denied to it—if it was not
considered as occupying all time and all space. Hence our conclusion differed from that
given above; for we inferred in the antithesis the actual infinity of the world.
310
Immanuel Kant
From this follows the affirmative answer: “The regress in the series of
phenomena—as a determination of the cosmical quantity, proceeds in
indefinitum.” This is equivalent to saying: “The world of sense has no
absolute quantity, but the empirical regress (through which alone the world
of sense is presented to us on the side of its conditions) rests upon a rule,
which requires it to proceed from every member of the series, as condi-
tioned, to one still more remote (whether through personal experience, or
by means of history, or the chain of cause and effect), and not to cease at
any point in this extension of the possible empirical employment of the
understanding.” And this is the proper and only use which reason can
make of its principles.
The above rule does not prescribe an unceasing regress in one kind of
phenomena. It does not, for example, forbid us, in our ascent from an
individual human being through the line of his ancestors, to expect that
we shall discover at some point of the regress a primeval pair, or to admit,
in the series of heavenly bodies, a sun at the farthest possible distance
from some centre. All that it demands is a perpetual progress from phe-
nomena to phenomena, even although an actual perception is not pre-
sented by them (as in the case of our perceptions being so weak as that we
are unable to become conscious of them), since they, nevertheless, belong
to possible experience.
Every beginning is in time, and all limits to extension are in space. But
space and time are in the world of sense. Consequently phenomena in the
world are conditionally limited, but the world itself is not limited, either
conditionally or unconditionally.
For this reason, and because neither the world nor the cosmical series of
conditions to a given conditioned can be completely given, our concep-
tion of the cosmical quantity is given only in and through the regress and
not prior to it—in a collective intuition. But the regress itself is really
nothing more than the determining of the cosmical quantity, and cannot
therefore give us any determined conception of it—still less a conception
of a quantity which is, in relation to a certain standard, infinite. The re-
gress does not, therefore, proceed to infinity (an infinity given), but only
to an indefinite extent, for or the of presenting to us a quantity—realized
only in and through the regress itself.
311
The Critique of Pure Reason
312
Immanuel Kant
For we may and ought to grant, in the case of space, that division or
decomposition, to any extent, never can utterly annihilate composition
(that is to say, the smallest part of space must still consist of spaces); oth-
erwise space would entirely cease to exist-which is impossible. But, the
assertion on the other band that when all composition in matter is annihi-
lated in thought, nothing remains, does not seem to harmonize with the
conception of substance, which must be properly the subject of all com-
position and must remain, even after the conjunction of its attributes in
space-which constituted a body—is annihilated in thought. But this is
not the case with substance in the phenomenal world, which is not a thing
in itself cogitated by the pure category. Phenomenal substance is not an
absolute subject; it is merely a permanent sensuous image, and nothing
more than an intuition, in which the unconditioned is not to be found.
But, although this rule of progress to infinity is legitimate and appli-
cable to the subdivision of a phenomenon, as a mere occupation or filling
of space, it is not applicable to a whole consisting of a number of distinct
parts and constituting a quantum discretum—that is to say, an organized
body. It cannot be admitted that every part in an organized whole is itself
organized, and that, in analysing it to infinity, we must always meet with
organized parts; although we may allow that the parts of the matter which
we decompose in infinitum, may be organized. For the infinity of the
division of a phenomenon in space rests altogether on the fact that the
divisibility of a phenomenon is given only in and through this infinity,
that is, an undetermined number of parts is given, while the parts them-
selves are given and determined only in and through the subdivision; in a
word, the infinity of the division necessarily presupposes that the whole is
not already divided in se. Hence our division determines a number of
parts in the whole—a number which extends just as far as the actual re-
gress in the division; while, on the other hand, the very notion of a body
organized to infinity represents the whole as already and in itself divided.
We expect, therefore, to find in it a determinate, but at the same time,
infinite, number of parts—which is self-contradictory. For we should thus
have a whole containing a series of members which could not be com-
pleted in any regress—which is infinite, and at the same time complete in
an organized composite. Infinite divisibility is applicable only to a quan-
tum continuum, and is based entirely on the infinite divisibility of space,
But in a quantum discretum the multitude of parts or units is always
determined, and hence always equal to some number. To what extent a
body may be organized, experience alone can inform us; and although, so
far as our experience of this or that body has extended, we may not have
313
The Critique of Pure Reason
discovered any inorganic part, such parts must exist in possible experi-
ence. But how far the transcendental division of a phenomenon must
extend, we cannot know from experience—it is a question which experi-
ence cannot answer; it is answered only by the principle of reason which
forbids us to consider the empirical regress, in the analysis of extended
body, as ever absolutely complete.
314
Immanuel Kant
316
Immanuel Kant
317
The Critique of Pure Reason
say: “Every effect must have its origin either in nature or in freedom,” or
whether both cannot exist together in the same event in different rela-
tions. The principle of an unbroken connection between all events in the
phenomenal world, in accordance with the unchangeable laws of nature,
is a well-established principle of transcendental analytic which admits of
no exception. The question, therefore, is: “Whether an effect, determined
according to the laws of nature, can at the same time be produced by a free
agent, or whether freedom and nature mutually exclude each other?” And
here, the common but fallacious hypothesis of the absolute reality of phe-
nomena manifests its injurious influence in embarrassing the procedure
of reason. For if phenomena are things in themselves, freedom is impos-
sible. In this case, nature is the complete and all-sufficient cause of every
event; and condition and conditioned, cause and effect are contained in the
same series, and necessitated by the same law. If, on the contrary, phenom-
ena are held to be, as they are in fact, nothing more than mere representa-
tions, connected with each other in accordance with empirical laws, they
must have a ground which is not phenomenal. But the causality of such an
intelligible cause is not determined or determinable by phenomena; although
its effects, as phenomena, must be determined by other phenomenal exist-
ences. This cause and its causality exist therefore out of and apart from the
series of phenomena; while its effects do exist and are discoverable in the
series of empirical conditions. Such an effect may therefore be considered to
be free in relation to its intelligible cause, and necessary in relation to the
phenomena from which it is a necessary consequence—a distinction which,
stated in this perfectly general and abstract manner, must appear in the
highest degree subtle and obscure. The sequel will explain. It is sufficient, at
present, to remark that, as the complete and unbroken connection of phe-
nomena is an unalterable law of nature, freedom is impossible—on the
supposition that phenomena are absolutely real. Hence those philosophers
who adhere to the common opinion on this subject can never succeed in
reconciling the ideas of nature and freedom.
318
Immanuel Kant
319
The Critique of Pure Reason
I have thought it advisable to lay before the reader at first merely a sketch
of the solution of this transcendental problem, in order to enable him to
form with greater ease a clear conception of the course which reason must
adopt in the solution. I shall now proceed to exhibit the several momenta
of this solution, and to consider them in their order.
The natural law that everything which happens must have a cause, that
320
Immanuel Kant
the causality of this cause, that is, the action of the cause (which cannot
always have existed, but must be itself an event, for it precedes in time
some effect which it has originated), must have itself a phenomenal cause,
by which it is determined and, and, consequently, all events are empiri-
cally determined in an order of nature—this law, I say, which lies at the
foundation of the possibility of experience, and of a connected system of
phenomena or nature is a law of the understanding, from which no de-
parture, and to which no exception, can be admitted. For to except even a
single phenomenon from its operation is to exclude it from the sphere of
possible experience and thus to admit it to be a mere fiction of thought or
phantom of the brain.
Thus we are obliged to acknowledge the existence of a chain of causes,
in which, however, absolute totality cannot be found. But we need not
detain ourselves with this question, for it has already been sufficiently
answered in our discussion of the antinomies into which reason falls, when
it attempts to reach the unconditioned in the series of phenomena. If we
permit ourselves to be deceived by the illusion of transcendental idealism,
we shall find that neither nature nor freedom exists. Now the question is:
“Whether, admitting the existence of natural necessity in the world of
phenomena, it is possible to consider an effect as at the same time an
effect of nature and an effect of freedom—or, whether these two modes of
causality are contradictory and incompatible?”
No phenomenal cause can absolutely and of itself begin a series. Every
action, in so far as it is productive of an event, is itself an event or occur-
rence, and presupposes another preceding state, in which its cause existed.
Thus everything that happens is but a continuation of a series, and an
absolute beginning is impossible in the sensuous world. The actions of
natural causes are, accordingly, themselves effects, and presuppose causes
preceding them in time. A primal action which forms an absolute begin-
ning, is beyond the causal power of phenomena.
Now, is it absolutely necessary that, granting that all effects are phe-
nomena, the causality of the cause of these effects must also be a phenom-
enon and belong to the empirical world? Is it not rather possible that,
although every effect in the phenomenal world must be connected with
an empirical cause, according to the universal law of nature, this empirical
causality may be itself the effect of a non-empirical and intelligible causal-
ity—its connection with natural causes remaining nevertheless intact? Such
a causality would be considered, in reference to phenomena, as the primal
action of a cause, which is in so far, therefore, not phenomenal, but, by
reason of this faculty or power, intelligible; although it must, at the same
321
The Critique of Pure Reason
322
Immanuel Kant
323
The Critique of Pure Reason
will not follow the order of things presented by experience, but, with per-
fect spontaneity, rearranges them according to ideas, with which it com-
pels empirical conditions to agree. It declares, in the name of these ideas,
certain actions to be necessary which nevertheless have not taken place
and which perhaps never will take place; and yet presupposes that it pos-
sesses the faculty of causality in relation to these actions. For, in the ab-
sence of this supposition, it could not expect its ideas to produce certain
effects in the world of experience.
Now, let us stop here and admit it to be at least possible that reason does
stand in a really causal relation to phenomena. In this case it must—pure
reason as it is—exhibit an empirical character. For every cause supposes a
rule, according to which certain phenomena follow as effects from the
cause, and every rule requires uniformity in these effects; and this is the
proper ground of the conception of a cause—as a faculty or power. Now
this conception (of a cause) may be termed the empirical character of
reason; and this character is a permanent one, while the effects produced
appear, in conformity with the various conditions which accompany and
partly limit them, in various forms.
Thus the volition of every man has an empirical character, which is
nothing more than the causality of his reason, in so far as its effects in the
phenomenal world manifest the presence of a rule, according to which we
are enabled to examine, in their several kinds and degrees, the actions of
this causality and the rational grounds for these actions, and in this way to
decide upon the subjective principles of the volition. Now we learn what
this empirical character is only from phenomenal effects, and from the
rule of these which is presented by experience; and for this reason all the
actions of man in the world of phenomena are determined by his empiri-
cal character, and the co-operative causes of nature. If, then, we could
investigate all the phenomena of human volition to their lowest founda-
tion in the mind, there would be no action which we could not anticipate
with certainty, and recognize to be absolutely necessary from its preceding
conditions. So far as relates to this empirical character, therefore, there can
be no freedom; and it is only in the light of this character that we can
consider the human will, when we confine ourselves to simple observa-
tion and, as is the case in anthropology, institute a physiological investiga-
tion of the motive causes of human actions.
But when we consider the same actions in relation to reason—not for
the purpose of explaining their origin, that is, in relation to speculative
reason, but to practical reason, as the producing cause of these actions—
we shall discover a rule and an order very different from those of nature
324
Immanuel Kant
and experience. For the declaration of this mental faculty may be that
what has and could not but take place in the course of nature, ought not
to have taken place. Sometimes, too, we discover, or believe that we dis-
cover, that the ideas of reason did actually stand in a causal relation to
certain actions of man; and that these actions have taken place because
they were determined, not by empirical causes, but by the act of the will
upon grounds of reason.
Now, granting that reason stands in a causal relation to phenomena;
can an action of reason be called free, when we know that, sensuously, in
its empirical character, it is completely determined and absolutely neces-
sary? But this empirical character is itself determined by the intelligible
character. The latter we cannot cognize; we can only indicate it by means
of phenomena, which enable us to have an immediate cognition only of
the empirical character.* An action, then, in so far as it is to be ascribed to
an intelligible cause, does not result from it in accordance with empirical
laws. That is to say, not the conditions of pure reason, but only their
effects in the internal sense, precede the act. Pure reason, as a purely intel-
ligible faculty, is not subject to the conditions of time. The causality of
reason in its intelligible character does not begin to be; it does not make
its appearance at a certain time, for the purpose of producing an effect. If
this were not the case, the causality of reason would be subservient to the
natural law of phenomena, which determines them according to time,
and as a series of causes and effects in time; it would consequently cease to
be freedom and become a part of nature. We are therefore justified in
saying: “If reason stands in a causal relation to phenomena, it is a faculty
which originates the sensuous condition of an empirical series of effects.”
For the condition, which resides in the reason, is non-sensuous, and there-
fore cannot be originated, or begin to be. And thus we find—what we
could not discover in any empirical series—a condition of a successive
series of events itself empirically unconditioned. For, in the present case,
the condition stands out of and beyond the series of phenomena—it is
intelligible, and it consequently cannot be subjected to any sensuous con-
dition, or to any time-determination by a preceding cause.
*The real morality of actions—their merit or demerit, and even that of our own
conduct, is completely unknown to us. Our estimates can relate only to their
empirical character. How much is the result of the action of free will, how much
is to be ascribed to nature and to blameless error, or to a happy constitution of
temperament (merito fortunae), no one can discover, nor, for this reason, deter-
mine with perfect justice.
325
The Critique of Pure Reason
But, in another respect, the same cause belongs also to the series of
phenomena. Man is himself a phenomenon. His will has an empirical
character, which is the empirical cause of all his actions. There is no con-
dition—determining man and his volition in conformity with this char-
acter—which does not itself form part of the series of effects in nature,
and is subject to their law—the law according to which an empirically
undetermined cause of an event in time cannot exist. For this reason no
given action can have an absolute and spontaneous origination, all actions
being phenomena, and belonging to the world of experience. But it can-
not be said of reason, that the state in which it determines the will is
always preceded by some other state determining it. For reason is not a
phenomenon, and therefore not subject to sensuous conditions; and, con-
sequently, even in relation to its causality, the sequence or conditions of
time do not influence reason, nor can the dynamical law of nature, which
determines the sequence of time according to certain rules, be applied to
it.
Reason is consequently the permanent condition of all actions of the
human will. Each of these is determined in the empirical character of the
man, even before it has taken place. The intelligible character, of which
the former is but the sensuous schema, knows no before or after; and
every action, irrespective of the time-relation in which it stands with other
phenomena, is the immediate effect of the intelligible character of pure
reason, which, consequently, enjoys freedom of action, and is not dy-
namically determined either by internal or external preceding conditions.
This freedom must not be described, in a merely negative manner, as
independence of empirical conditions, for in this case the faculty of rea-
son would cease to be a cause of phenomena; but it must be regarded,
positively, as a faculty which can spontaneously originate a series of events.
At the same time, it must not be supposed that any beginning can take
place in reason; on the contrary, reason, as the unconditioned condition
of all action of the will, admits of no time-conditions, although its effect
does really begin in a series of phenomena—a beginning which is not,
however, absolutely primal.
I shall illustrate this regulative principle of reason by an example, from
its employment in the world of experience; proved it cannot be by any
amount of experience, or by any number of facts, for such arguments
cannot establish the truth of transcendental propositions. Let us take a
voluntary action—for example, a falsehood—by means of which a man
has introduced a certain degree of confusion into the social life of human-
ity, which is judged according to the motives from which it originated,
326
Immanuel Kant
and the blame of which and of the evil consequences arising from it, is
imputed to the offender. We at first proceed to examine the empirical
character of the offence, and for this purpose we endeavour to penetrate
to the sources of that character, such as a defective education, bad com-
pany, a shameless and wicked disposition, frivolity, and want of reflec-
tion—not forgetting also the occasioning causes which prevailed at the
moment of the transgression. In this the procedure is exactly the same as
that pursued in the investigation of the series of causes which determine a
given physical effect. Now, although we believe the action to have been
determined by all these circumstances, we do not the less blame the of-
fender. We do not blame him for his unhappy disposition, nor for the
circumstances which influenced him, nay, not even for his former course
of life; for we presuppose that all these considerations may be set aside,
that the series of preceding conditions may be regarded as having never
existed, and that the action may be considered as completely uncondi-
tioned in relation to any state preceding, just as if the agent commenced
with it an entirely new series of effects. Our blame of the offender is
grounded upon a law of reason, which requires us to regard this faculty as
a cause, which could have and ought to have otherwise determined the
behaviour of the culprit, independently of all empirical conditions. This
causality of reason we do not regard as a co-operating agency, but as com-
plete in itself. It matters not whether the sensuous impulses favoured or
opposed the action of this causality, the offence is estimated according to
its intelligible character—the offender is decidedly worthy of blame, the
moment he utters a falsehood. It follows that we regard reason, in spite of
the empirical conditions of the act, as completely free, and therefore, there-
fore, as in the present case, culpable.
The above judgement is complete evidence that we are accustomed to
think that reason is not affected by sensuous conditions, that in it no
change takes place—although its phenomena, in other words, the mode
in which it appears in its effects, are subject to change—that in it no
preceding state determines the following, and, consequently, that it does
not form a member of the series of sensuous conditions which necessitate
phenomena according to natural laws. Reason is present and the same in
all human actions and at all times; but it does not itself exist in time, and
therefore does not enter upon any state in which it did not formerly exist.
It is, relatively to new states or conditions, determining, but not deter-
minable. Hence we cannot ask: “Why did not reason determine itself in a
different manner?” The question ought to be thus stated: “Why did not
reason employ its power of causality to determine certain phenomena in a
327
The Critique of Pure Reason
328
Immanuel Kant
329
The Critique of Pure Reason
which exists necessarily, it is not requisite that the condition should form
part of an empirical series along with the conditioned.
In the case of the apparent antinomy with which we are at present deal-
ing, there exists a way of escape from the difficulty; for it is not impossible
that both of the contradictory statements may be true in different rela-
tions. All sensuous phenomena may be contingent, and consequently pos-
sess only an empirically conditioned existence, and yet there may also
exist a non-empirical condition of the whole series, or, in other words, a
necessary being. For this necessary being, as an intelligible condition, would
not form a member—not even the highest member—of the series; the
whole world of sense would be left in its empirically determined existence
uninterfered with and uninfluenced. This would also form a ground of
distinction between the modes of solution employed for the third and
fourth antinomies. For, while in the consideration of freedom in the former
antinomy, the thing itself—the cause (substantia phaenomenon)—was
regarded as belonging to the series of conditions, and only its causality to
the intelligible world—we are obliged in the present case to cogitate this
necessary being as purely intelligible and as existing entirely apart from
the world of sense (as an ens extramundanum); for otherwise it would be
subject to the phenomenal law of contingency and dependence.
In relation to the present problem, therefore, the regulative principle of
reason is that everything in the sensuous world possesses an empirically
conditioned existence—that no property of the sensuous world possesses
unconditioned necessity—that we are bound to expect, and, so far as is
possible, to seek for the empirical condition of every member in the series
of conditions—and that there is no sufficient reason to justify us in de-
ducing any existence from a condition which lies out of and beyond the
empirical series, or in regarding any existence as independent and self-
subsistent; although this should not prevent us from recognizing the pos-
sibility of the whole series being based upon a being which is intelligible,
and for this reason free from all empirical conditions.
But it has been far from my intention, in these remarks, to prove the
existence of this unconditioned and necessary being, or even to evidence
the possibility of a purely intelligible condition of the existence or all sen-
suous phenomena. As bounds were set to reason, to prevent it from leav-
ing the guiding thread of empirical conditions and losing itself in tran-
scendent theories which are incapable of concrete presentation; so it was
my purpose, on the other band, to set bounds to the law of the purely
empirical understanding, and to protest against any attempts on its part at
deciding on the possibility of things, or declaring the existence of the
330
Immanuel Kant
331
The Critique of Pure Reason
332
Immanuel Kant
gible things, of which we have not the least knowledge, which nature
taught us to use in the formation of empirical conceptions. Experience
made us acquainted with the contingent. But we are at present engaged in
the discussion of things which are not objects of experience; and must,
therefore, deduce our knowledge of them from that which is necessary
absolutely and in itself, that is, from pure conceptions. Hence the first
step which we take out of the world of sense obliges us to begin our sys-
tem of new cognition with the investigation of a necessary being, and to
deduce from our conceptions of it all our conceptions of intelligible things.
This we propose to attempt in the following chapter.
We have seen that pure conceptions do not present objects to the mind,
except under sensuous conditions; because the conditions of objective real-
ity do not exist in these conceptions, which contain, in fact, nothing but the
mere form of thought. They may, however, when applied to phenomena, be
presented in concreto; for it is phenomena that present to them the materi-
als for the formation of empirical conceptions, which are nothing more
than concrete forms of the conceptions of the understanding. But ideas are
still further removed from objective reality than categories; for no phenom-
enon can ever present them to the human mind in concreto. They contain
a certain perfection, attainable by no possible empirical cognition; and they
give to reason a systematic unity, to which the unity of experience attempts
to approximate, but can never completely attain.
But still further removed than the idea from objective reality is the Ideal,
by which term I understand the idea, not in concreto, but in individuo—
as an individual thing, determinable or determined by the idea alone. The
idea of humanity in its complete perfection supposes not only the ad-
vancement of all the powers and faculties, which constitute our concep-
tion of human nature, to a complete attainment of their final aims, but
also everything which is requisite for the complete determination of the
idea; for of all contradictory predicates, only one can conform with the
idea of the perfect man. What I have termed an ideal was in Plato’s phi-
losophy an idea of the divine mind—an individual object present to its
pure intuition, the most perfect of every kind of possible beings, and the
archetype of all phenomenal existences.
333
The Critique of Pure Reason
334
Immanuel Kant
Every conception is, in relation to that which is not contained in it, unde-
termined and subject to the principle of determinability. This principle is
that, of every two contradictorily opposed predicates, only one can belong
to a conception. It is a purely logical principle, itself based upon the prin-
ciple of contradiction; inasmuch as it makes complete abstraction of the
content and attends merely to the logical form of the cognition.
But again, everything, as regards its possibility, is also subject to the
principle of complete determination, according to which one of all the
possible contradictory predicates of things must belong to it. This prin-
ciple is not based merely upon that of contradiction; for, in addition to
the relation between two contradictory predicates, it regards everything as
standing in a relation to the sum of possibilities, as the sum total of all
predicates of things, and, while presupposing this sum as an a priori con-
dition, presents to the mind everything as receiving the possibility of its
individual existence from the relation it bears to, and the share it possesses
in, the aforesaid sum of possibilities.* The principle of complete determi-
nation relates the content and not to the logical form. It is the principle of
the synthesis of all the predicates which are required to constitute the
complete conception of a thing, and not a mere principle analytical repre-
sentation, which enounces that one of two contradictory predicates must
belong to a conception. It contains, moreover, a transcendental presuppo-
sition—that, namely, of the material for all possibility, which must con-
tain a priori the data for this or that particular possibility.
336
Immanuel Kant
under the former as the genus. The transcendental principle of the com-
plete determination of all things is therefore merely the representation of
the sum-total of all reality; it is not a conception which is the genus of all
predicates under itself, but one which comprehends them all within itself.
The complete determination of a thing is consequently based upon the
limitation of this total of reality, so much being predicated of the thing,
while all that remains over is excluded—a procedure which is in exact
agreement with that of the disjunctive syllogism and the determination of
the objects in the conclusion by one of the members of the division. It
follows that reason, in laying the transcendental ideal at the foundation of
its determination of all possible things, takes a course in exact analogy
with that which it pursues in disjunctive syllogisms—a proposition which
formed the basis of the systematic division of all transcendental ideas,
according to which they are produced in complete parallelism with the
three modes of syllogistic reasoning employed by the human mind.
It is self-evident that reason, in cogitating the necessary complete deter-
mination of things, does not presuppose the existence of a being corre-
sponding to its ideal, but merely the idea of the ideal-for the purpose of
deducing from the unconditional totality of complete determination, The
ideal is therefore the prototype of all things, which, as defective copies (ectypa),
receive from it the material of their possibility, and approximate to it more
or less, though it is impossible that they can ever attain to its perfection.
The possibility of things must therefore be regarded as derived-except
that of the thing which contains in itself all reality, which must be consid-
ered to be primitive and original. For all negations-and they are the only
predicates by means of which all other things can be distinguished from
the ens realissimum—are mere limitations of a greater and a higher—nay,
the highest reality; and they consequently presuppose this reality, and are,
as regards their content, derived from it. The manifold nature of things is
only an infinitely various mode of limiting the conception of the highest
reality, which is their common substratum; just as all figures are possible
only as different modes of limiting infinite space. The object of the ideal
of reason—an object existing only in reason itself—is also termed the
primal being (ens originarium); as having no existence superior to him,
the supreme being (ens summum); and as being the condition of all other
beings, which rank under it, the being of all beings (ens entium). But
none of these terms indicate the objective relation of an actually existing
object to other things, but merely that of an idea to conceptions; and all
our investigations into this subject still leave us in perfect uncertainty
with regard to the existence of this being.
338
Immanuel Kant
339
The Critique of Pure Reason
all things as deduced from a single possibility, that, to wit, of the highest
reality, and presupposes this as existing in an individual and primal being?
The answer is ready; it is at once presented by the procedure of transcen-
dental analytic. The possibility of sensuous objects is a relation of these
objects to thought, in which something (the empirical form) may be cogi-
tated a priori; while that which constitutes the matter—the reality of the
phenomenon (that element which corresponds to sensation)—must be given
from without, as otherwise it could not even be cogitated by, nor could its
possibility be presentable to the mind. Now, a sensuous object is completely
determined, when it has been compared with all phenomenal predicates,
and represented by means of these either positively or negatively. But, as
that which constitutes the thing itself—the real in a phenomenon, must be
given, and that, in which the real of all phenomena is given, is experience,
one, sole, and all-embracing-the material of the possibility of all sensuous
objects must be presupposed as given in a whole, and it is upon the limita-
tion of this whole that the possibility of all empirical objects, their distinc-
tion from each other and their complete determination, are based. Now, no
other objects are presented to us besides sensuous objects, and these can be
given only in connection with a possible experience; it follows that a thing is
not an object to us, unless it presupposes the whole or sum-total of empiri-
cal reality as the condition of its possibility. Now, a natural illusion leads us
to consider this principle, which is valid only of sensuous objects, as valid
with regard to things in general. And thus we are induced to hold the em-
pirical principle of our conceptions of the possibility of things, as phenom-
ena, by leaving out this limitative condition, to be a transcendental prin-
ciple of the possibility of things in general.
We proceed afterwards to hypostatize this idea of the sum-total of all reality,
by changing the distributive unity of the empirical exercise of the understand-
ing into the collective unity of an empirical whole—a dialectical illusion, and
by cogitating this whole or sum of experience as an individual thing, contain-
ing in itself all empirical reality. This individual thing or being is then, by
means of the above-mentioned transcendental subreption, substituted for our
notion of a thing which stands at the head of the possibility of all things, the
real conditions of whose complete determination it presents.*
340
Immanuel Kant
341
The Critique of Pure Reason
342
Immanuel Kant
question unanswered till we have fully weighed both sides—in other words,
when we are merely called upon to decide how much we happen to know
about the question, and how much we merely flatter ourselves that we
know-the above conclusion does not appear to be so great advantage, but,
on the contrary, seems defective in the grounds upon which it is sup-
ported.
For, admitting the truth of all that has been said, that, namely, the infer-
ence from a given existence (my own, for example) to the existence of an
unconditioned and necessary being is valid and unassailable; that, in the
second place, we must consider a being which contains all reality, and
consequently all the conditions of other things, to be absolutely uncondi-
tioned; and admitting too, that we have thus discovered the conception of
a thing to which may be attributed, without inconsistency, absolute ne-
cessity—it does not follow from all this that the conception of a limited
being, in which the supreme reality does not reside, is therefore incompat-
ible with the idea of absolute necessity. For, although I do not discover the
element of the unconditioned in the conception of such a being—an ele-
ment which is manifestly existent in the sum-total of all conditions—I am
not entitled to conclude that its existence is therefore conditioned; just as
I am not entitled to affirm, in a hypothetical syllogism, that where a cer-
tain condition does not exist (in the present, completeness, as far as pure
conceptions are concerned), the conditioned does not exist either. On the
contrary, we are free to consider all limited beings as likewise uncondi-
tionally necessary, although we are unable to infer this from the general
conception which we have of them. Thus conducted, this argument is
incapable of giving us the least notion of the properties of a necessary
being, and must be in every respect without result.
This argument continues, however, to possess a weight and an author-
ity, which, in spite of its objective insufficiency, it has never been divested
of. For, granting that certain responsibilities lie upon us, which, as based
on the ideas of reason, deserve to be respected and submitted to, although
they are incapable of a real or practical application to our nature, or, in
other words, would be responsibilities without motives, except upon the
supposition of a Supreme Being to give effect and influence to the practi-
cal laws: in such a case we should be bound to obey our conceptions,
which, although objectively insufficient, do, according to the standard of
reason, preponderate over and are superior to any claims that may be
advanced from any other quarter. The equilibrium of doubt would in this
case be destroyed by a practical addition; indeed, Reason would be com-
pelled to condemn herself, if she refused to comply with the demands of
343
The Critique of Pure Reason
344
Immanuel Kant
It is evident from what has been said that the conception of an absolutely
necessary being is a mere idea, the objective reality of which is far from
being established by the mere fact that it is a need of reason. On the
contrary, this idea serves merely to indicate a certain unattainable perfec-
tion, and rather limits the operations than, by the presentation of new
objects, extends the sphere of the understanding. But a strange anomaly
meets us at the very threshold; for the inference from a given existence in
general to an absolutely necessary existence seems to be correct and un-
avoidable, while the conditions of the understanding refuse to aid us in
forming any conception of such a being.
Philosophers have always talked of an absolutely necessary being, and
have nevertheless declined to take the trouble of conceiving whether—
and how—a being of this nature is even cogitable, not to mention that its
existence is actually demonstrable. A verbal definition of the conception is
certainly easy enough: it is something the non-existence of which is im-
possible. But does this definition throw any light upon the conditions
which render it impossible to cogitate the non-existence of a thing—con-
ditions which we wish to ascertain, that we may discover whether we think
anything in the conception of such a being or not? For the mere fact that
I throw away, by means of the word unconditioned, all the conditions
which the understanding habitually requires in order to regard anything
as necessary, is very far from making clear whether by means of the con-
ception of the unconditionally necessary I think of something, or really of
nothing at all.
Nay, more, this chance-conception, now become so current, many have
endeavoured to explain by examples which seemed to render any inquiries
regarding its intelligibility quite needless. Every geometrical proposition—
a triangle has three angles—it was said, is absolutely necessary; and thus
people talked of an object which lay out of the sphere of our understand-
ing as if it were perfectly plain what the conception of such a being meant.
All the examples adduced have been drawn, without exception, from
judgements, and not from things. But the unconditioned necessity of a
judgement does not form the absolute necessity of a thing. On the con-
trary, the absolute necessity of a judgement is only a conditioned necessity
of a thing, or of the predicate in a judgement. The proposition above-
345
The Critique of Pure Reason
mentioned does not enounce that three angles necessarily exist, but, upon
condition that a triangle exists, three angles must necessarily exist—in it.
And thus this logical necessity has been the source of the greatest delu-
sions. Having formed an a priori conception of a thing, the content of
which was made to embrace existence, we believed ourselves safe in con-
cluding that, because existence belongs necessarily to the object of the
conception (that is, under the condition of my positing this thing as given),
the existence of the thing is also posited necessarily, and that it is therefore
absolutely necessary—merely because its existence has been cogitated in
the conception.
If, in an identical judgement, I annihilate the predicate in thought, and
retain the subject, a contradiction is the result; and hence I say, the former
belongs necessarily to the latter. But if I suppress both subject and predi-
cate in thought, no contradiction arises; for there is nothing at all, and
therefore no means of forming a contradiction. To suppose the existence
of a triangle and not that of its three angles, is self-contradictory; but to
suppose the non-existence of both triangle and angles is perfectly admis-
sible. And so is it with the conception of an absolutely necessary being.
Annihilate its existence in thought, and you annihilate the thing itself
with all its predicates; how then can there be any room for contradiction?
Externally, there is nothing to give rise to a contradiction, for a thing
cannot be necessary externally; nor internally, for, by the annihilation or
suppression of the thing itself, its internal properties are also annihilated.
God is omnipotent—that is a necessary judgement. His omnipotence can-
not be denied, if the existence of a Deity is posited—the existence, that is,
of an infinite being, the two conceptions being identical. But when you
say, God does not exist, neither omnipotence nor any other predicate is
affirmed; they must all disappear with the subject, and in this judgement
there cannot exist the least self-contradiction.
You have thus seen that when the predicate of a judgement is annihi-
lated in thought along with the subject, no internal contradiction can
arise, be the predicate what it may. There is no possibility of evading the
conclusion—you find yourselves compelled to declare: There are certain
subjects which cannot be annihilated in thought. But this is nothing more
than saying: There exist subjects which are absolutely necessary—the very
hypothesis which you are called upon to establish. For I find myself un-
able to form the slightest conception of a thing which when annihilated in
thought with all its predicates, leaves behind a contradiction; and contra-
diction is the only criterion of impossibility in the sphere of pure a priori
conceptions.
346
Immanuel Kant
Against these general considerations, the justice of which no one can dis-
pute, one argument is adduced, which is regarded as furnishing a satisfactory
demonstration from the fact. It is affirmed that there is one and only one
conception, in which the non-being or annihilation of the object is self-con-
tradictory, and this is the conception of an ens realissimum. It possesses, you
say, all reality, and you feel yourselves justified in admitting the possibility of
such a being. (This I am willing to grant for the present, although the exist-
ence of a conception which is not self-contradictory is far from being suffi-
cient to prove the possibility of an object.)* Now the notion of all reality
embraces in it that of existence; the notion of existence lies, therefore, in the
conception of this possible thing. If this thing is annihilated in thought, the
internal possibility of the thing is also annihilated, which is self-contradictory.
I answer: It is absurd to introduce—under whatever term disguised—
into the conception of a thing, which is to be cogitated solely in reference
to its possibility, the conception of its existence. If this is admitted, you
will have apparently gained the day, but in reality have enounced nothing
but a mere tautology. I ask, is the proposition, this or that thing (which I
am admitting to be possible) exists, an analytical or a synthetical proposi-
tion? If the former, there is no addition made to the subject of your thought
by the affirmation of its existence; but then the conception in your minds
is identical with the thing itself, or you have supposed the existence of a
thing to be possible, and then inferred its existence from its internal pos-
sibility—which is but a miserable tautology. The word reality in the con-
ception of the thing, and the word existence in the conception of the
predicate, will not help you out of the difficulty. For, supposing you were
to term all positing of a thing reality, you have thereby posited the thing
with all its predicates in the conception of the subject and assumed its
actual existence, and this you merely repeat in the predicate. But if you
confess, as every reasonable person must, that every existential proposi-
tion is synthetical, how can it be maintained that the predicate of exist-
ence cannot be denied without contradiction?—a property which is the
characteristic of analytical propositions, alone.
I should have a reasonable hope of putting an end for ever to this so-
phistical mode of argumentation, by a strict definition of the conception
of existence, did not my own experience teach me that the illusion arising
from our confounding a logical with a real predicate (a predicate which
aids in the determination of a thing) resists almost all the endeavours of
explanation and illustration. A logical predicate may be what you please,
even the subject may be predicated of itself; for logic pays no regard to the
content of a judgement. But the determination of a conception is a predi-
cate, which adds to and enlarges the conception. It must not, therefore, be
contained in the conception.
Being is evidently not a real predicate, that is, a conception of some-
thing which is added to the conception of some other thing. It is merely
the positing of a thing, or of certain determinations in it. Logically, it is
merely the copula of a judgement. The proposition, God is omnipotent,
contains two conceptions, which have a certain object or content; the
word is, is no additional predicate—it merely indicates the relation of the
predicate to the subject. Now, if I take the subject (God) with all its predi-
cates (omnipotence being one), and say: God is, or, There is a God, I add
no new predicate to the conception of God, I merely posit or affirm the
existence of the subject with all its predicates—I posit the object in rela-
tion to my conception. The content of both is the same; and there is no
addition made to the conception, which expresses merely the possibility
of the object, by my cogitating the object—in the expression, it is—as
absolutely given or existing. Thus the real contains no more than the pos-
sible. A hundred real dollars contain no more than a hundred possible
dollars. For, as the latter indicate the conception, and the former the ob-
ject, on the supposition that the content of the former was greater than
that of the latter, my conception would not be an expression of the whole
object, and would consequently be an inadequate conception of it. But in
reckoning my wealth there may be said to be more in a hundred real
dollars than in a hundred possible dollars—that is, in the mere concep-
tion of them. For the real object—the dollars—is not analytically con-
tained in my conception, but forms a synthetical addition to my concep-
tion (which is merely a determination of my mental state), although this
objective reality—this existence—apart from my conceptions, does not in
the least degree increase the aforesaid hundred dollars.
By whatever and by whatever number of predicates—even to the com-
plete determination of it—I may cogitate a thing, I do not in the least
augment the object of my conception by the addition of the statement:
This thing exists. Otherwise, not exactly the same, but something more
348
Immanuel Kant
than what was cogitated in my conception, would exist, and I could not
affirm that the exact object of my conception had real existence. If I cogi-
tate a thing as containing all modes of reality except one, the mode of
reality which is absent is not added to the conception of the thing by the
affirmation that the thing exists; on the contrary, the thing exists—if it
exist at all—with the same defect as that cogitated in its conception; oth-
erwise not that which was cogitated, but something different, exists. Now,
if I cogitate a being as the highest reality, without defect or imperfection,
the question still remains—whether this being exists or not? For, although
no element is wanting in the possible real content of my conception, there
is a defect in its relation to my mental state, that is, I am ignorant whether
the cognition of the object indicated by the conception is possible a pos-
teriori. And here the cause of the present difficulty becomes apparent. If
the question regarded an object of sense merely, it would be impossible for
me to confound the conception with the existence of a thing. For the
conception merely enables me to cogitate an object as according with the
general conditions of experience; while the existence of the object permits
me to cogitate it as contained in the sphere of actual experience. At the
same time, this connection with the world of experience does not in the
least augment the conception, although a possible perception has been
added to the experience of the mind. But if we cogitate existence by the
pure category alone, it is not to be wondered at, that we should find our-
selves unable to present any criterion sufficient to distinguish it from mere
possibility.
Whatever be the content of our conception of an object, it is necessary
to go beyond it, if we wish to predicate existence of the object. In the case
of sensuous objects, this is attained by their connection according to em-
pirical laws with some one of my perceptions; but there is no means of
cognizing the existence of objects of pure thought, because it must be
cognized completely a priori. But all our knowledge of existence (be it
immediately by perception, or by inferences connecting some object with
a perception) belongs entirely to the sphere of experience—which is in
perfect unity with itself; and although an existence out of this sphere can-
not be absolutely declared to be impossible, it is a hypothesis the truth of
which we have no means of ascertaining.
The notion of a Supreme Being is in many respects a highly useful idea;
but for the very reason that it is an idea, it is incapable of enlarging our
cognition with regard to the existence of things. It is not even sufficient to
instruct us as to the possibility of a being which we do not know to exist.
The analytical criterion of possibility, which consists in the absence of
349
The Critique of Pure Reason
350
Immanuel Kant
*This inference is too well known to require more detailed discussion. It is based
upon the spurious transcendental law of causality, that everything which is con-
tingent has a cause, which, if itself contingent, must also have a cause; and so on,
till the series of subordinated causes must end with an absolutely necessary cause,
without which it would not possess completeness.
351
The Critique of Pure Reason
352
Immanuel Kant
All illusions in an argument are more easily detected when they are
presented in the formal manner employed by the schools, which we now
proceed to do.
If the proposition: “Every absolutely necessary being is likewise an ens
realissimum,” is correct (and it is this which constitutes the nervus probandi
of the cosmological argument), it must, like all affirmative judgements, be
capable of conversion—the conversio per accidens, at least. It follows,
then, that some entia realissima are absolutely necessary beings. But no
ens realissimum is in any respect different from another, and what is valid
of some is valid of all. In this present case, therefore, I may employ simple
conversion, and say: “Every ens realissimum is a necessary being.” But as
this proposition is determined a priori by the conceptions contained in it,
the mere conception of an ens realissimum must possess the additional
attribute of absolute necessity. But this is exactly what was maintained in
the ontological argument, and not recognized by the cosmological, al-
though it formed the real ground of its disguised and illusory reasoning.
Thus the second mode employed by speculative reason of demonstrat-
ing the existence of a Supreme Being, is not only, like the first, illusory
and inadequate, but possesses the additional blemish of an ignoratio elen-
chi—professing to conduct us by a new road to the desired goal, but
bringing us back, after a short circuit, to the old path which we had de-
serted at its call.
I mentioned above that this cosmological argument contains a perfect
nest of dialectical assumptions, which transcendental criticism does not
find it difficult to expose and to dissipate. I shall merely enumerate these,
leaving it to the reader, who must by this time be well practised in such
matters, to investigate the fallacies residing therein.
The following fallacies, for example, are discoverable in this mode of
proof: 1. The transcendental principle: “Everything that is contingent must
have a cause”—a principle without significance, except in the sensuous
world. For the purely intellectual conception of the contingent cannot
produce any synthetical proposition, like that of causality, which is itself
without significance or distinguishing characteristic except in the phe-
nomenal world. But in the present case it is employed to help us beyond
the limits of its sphere. 2. “From the impossibility of an infinite ascending
series of causes in the world of sense a first cause is inferred”; a conclusion
which the principles of the employment of reason do not justify even in
the sphere of experience, and still less when an attempt is made to pass the
limits of this sphere. 3. Reason allows itself to be satisfied upon insuffi-
cient grounds, with regard to the completion of this series. It removes all
353
The Critique of Pure Reason
354
Immanuel Kant
355
The Critique of Pure Reason
capable of explanation and solution. For the very essence of reason con-
sists in its ability to give an account, of all our conceptions, opinions, and
assertions—upon objective, or, when they happen to be illusory and falla-
cious, upon subjective grounds.
356
Immanuel Kant
357
The Critique of Pure Reason
358
Immanuel Kant
If, then, neither a pure conception nor the general experience of an exist-
ing being can provide a sufficient basis for the proof of the existence of the
Deity, we can make the attempt by the only other mode—that of ground-
ing our argument upon a determinate experience of the phenomena of
the present world, their constitution and disposition, and discover whether
we can thus attain to a sound conviction of the existence of a Supreme
Being. This argument we shall term the physico-theological argument. If
it is shown to be insufficient, speculative reason cannot present us with
any satisfactory proof of the existence of a being corresponding to our
transcendental idea.
It is evident from the remarks that have been made in the preceding
sections, that an answer to this question will be far from being difficult or
unconvincing. For how can any experience be adequate with an idea? The
very essence of an idea consists in the fact that no experience can ever be
discovered congruent or adequate with it. The transcendental idea of a
necessary and all-sufficient being is so immeasurably great, so high above
all that is empirical, which is always conditioned, that we hope in vain to
find materials in the sphere of experience sufficiently ample for our con-
ception, and in vain seek the unconditioned among things that are condi-
tioned, while examples, nay, even guidance is denied us by the laws of
empirical synthesis.
If the Supreme Being forms a link in the chain of empirical conditions,
it must be a member of the empirical series, and, like the lower members
which it precedes, have its origin in some higher member of the series. If,
on the other hand, we disengage it from the chain, and cogitate it as an
intelligible being, apart from the series of natural causes—how shall rea-
son bridge the abyss that separates the latter from the former? All laws
respecting the regress from effects to causes, all synthetical additions to
our knowledge relate solely to possible experience and the objects of the
sensuous world, and, apart from them, are without significance.
The world around us opens before our view so magnificent a spectacle
of order, variety, beauty, and conformity to ends, that whether we pursue
our observations into the infinity of space in the one direction, or into its
359
The Critique of Pure Reason
illimitable divisions in the other, whether we regard the world in its great-
est or its least manifestations-even after we have attained to the highest
summit of knowledge which our weak minds can reach, we find that lan-
guage in the presence of wonders so inconceivable has lost its force, and
number its power to reckon, nay, even thought fails to conceive adequately,
and our conception of the whole dissolves into an astonishment without
power of expression—all the more eloquent that it is dumb. Everywhere
around us we observe a chain of causes and effects, of means and ends, of
death and birth; and, as nothing has entered of itself into the condition in
which we find it, we are constantly referred to some other thing, which
itself suggests the same inquiry regarding its cause, and thus the universe
must sink into the abyss of nothingness, unless we admit that, besides this
infinite chain of contingencies, there exists something that is primal and
self-subsistent—something which, as the cause of this phenomenal world,
secures its continuance and preservation.
This highest cause—what magnitude shall we attribute to it? Of the
content of the world we are ignorant; still less can we estimate its magni-
tude by comparison with the sphere of the possible. But this supreme
cause being a necessity of the human mind, what is there to prevent us
from attributing to it such a degree of perfection as to place it above the
sphere of all that is possible? This we can easily do, although only by the
aid of the faint outline of an abstract conception, by representing this
being to ourselves as containing in itself, as an individual substance, all
possible perfection—a conception which satisfies that requirement of rea-
son which demands parsimony in principles, which is free from self-con-
tradiction, which even contributes to the extension of the employment of
reason in experience, by means of the guidance afforded by this idea to
order and system, and which in no respect conflicts with any law of expe-
rience.
This argument always deserves to be mentioned with respect. It is the
oldest, the clearest, and that most in conformity with the common reason
of humanity. It animates the study of nature, as it itself derives its existence
and draws ever new strength from that source. It introduces aims and ends
into a sphere in which our observation could not of itself have discovered
them, and extends our knowledge of nature, by directing our attention to a
unity, the principle of which lies beyond nature. This knowledge of nature
again reacts upon this idea—its cause; and thus our belief in a divine author
of the universe rises to the power of an irresistible conviction.
For these reasons it would be utterly hopeless to attempt to rob this
argument of the authority it has always enjoyed. The mind, unceasingly
360
Immanuel Kant
361
The Critique of Pure Reason
herself to its purposes, as in the case of a house, a ship, or a watch, that the
same kind of causality—namely, understanding and will—resides in na-
ture. It is also declared that the internal possibility of this freely-acting
nature (which is the source of all art, and perhaps also of human reason) is
derivable from another and superhuman art—a conclusion which would
perhaps be found incapable of standing the test of subtle transcendental
criticism. But to neither of these opinions shall we at present object. We
shall only remark that it must be confessed that, if we are to discuss the
subject of cause at all, we cannot proceed more securely than with the
guidance of the analogy subsisting between nature and such products of
design—these being the only products whose causes and modes of orga-
nization are completely known to us. Reason would be unable to satisfy
her own requirements, if she passed from a causality which she does know,
to obscure and indemonstrable principles of explanation which she does
not know.
According to the physico-theological argument, the connection and
harmony existing in the world evidence the contingency of the form merely,
but not of the matter, that is, of the substance of the world. To establish
the truth of the latter opinion, it would be necessary to prove that all
things would be in themselves incapable of this harmony and order, un-
less they were, even as regards their substance, the product of a supreme
wisdom. But this would require very different grounds of proof from those
presented by the analogy with human art. This proof can at most, there-
fore, demonstrate the existence of an architect of the world, whose efforts
are limited by the capabilities of the material with which he works, but
not of a creator of the world, to whom all things are subject. Thus this
argument is utterly insufficient for the task before us—a demonstration
of the existence of an all-sufficient being. If we wish to prove the contin-
gency of matter, we must have recourse to a transcendental argument,
which the physico-theological was constructed expressly to avoid.
We infer, from the order and design visible in the universe, as a disposi-
tion of a thoroughly contingent character, the existence of a cause propor-
tionate thereto. The conception of this cause must contain certain deter-
minate qualities, and it must therefore be regarded as the conception of a
being which possesses all power, wisdom, and so on, in one word, all
perfection—the conception, that is, of an all-sufficient being. For the predi-
cates of very great, astonishing, or immeasurable power and excellence,
give us no determinate conception of the thing, nor do they inform us
what the thing may be in itself. They merely indicate the relation existing
between the magnitude of the object and the observer, who compares it
362
Immanuel Kant
with himself and with his own power of comprehension, and are mere
expressions of praise and reverence, by which the object is either magni-
fied, or the observing subject depreciated in relation to the object. Where
we have to do with the magnitude (of the perfection) of a thing, we can
discover no determinate conception, except that which comprehends all
possible perfection or completeness, and it is only the total (omnitudo) of
reality which is completely determined in and through its conception alone.
Now it cannot be expected that any one will be bold enough to declare
that he has a perfect insight into the relation which the magnitude of the
world he contemplates bears (in its extent as well as in its content) to
omnipotence, into that of the order and design in the world to the highest
wisdom, and that of the unity of the world to the absolute unity of a
Supreme Being. Physico-theology is therefore incapable of presenting a
determinate conception of a supreme cause of the world, and is therefore
insufficient as a principle of theology—a theology which is itself to be the
basis of religion.
The attainment of absolute totality is completely impossible on the path
of empiricism. And yet this is the path pursued in the physico-theological
argument. What means shall we employ to bridge the abyss?
After elevating ourselves to admiration of the magnitude of the power,
wisdom, and other attributes of the author of the world, and finding we
can advance no further, we leave the argument on empirical grounds, and
proceed to infer the contingency of the world from the order and confor-
mity to aims that are observable in it. From this contingency we infer, by
the help of transcendental conceptions alone, the existence of something
absolutely necessary; and, still advancing, proceed from the conception of
the absolute necessity of the first cause to the completely determined or
determining conception thereof—the conception of an all-embracing re-
ality. Thus the physico-theological, failing in its undertaking, recurs in its
embarrassment to the cosmological argument; and, as this is merely the
ontological argument in disguise, it executes its design solely by the aid of
pure reason, although it at first professed to have no connection with this
faculty and to base its entire procedure upon experience alone.
The physico-theologians have therefore no reason to regard with such
contempt the transcendental mode of argument, and to look down upon
it, with the conceit of clear-sighted observers of nature, as the brain-cob-
web of obscure speculatists. For, if they reflect upon and examine their
own arguments, they will find that, after following for some time the path
of nature and experience, and discovering themselves no nearer their ob-
ject, they suddenly leave this path and pass into the region of pure possi-
363
The Critique of Pure Reason
bility, where they hope to reach upon the wings of ideas what had eluded
all their empirical investigations. Gaining, as they think, a firm footing
after this immense leap, they extend their determinate conception—into
the possession of which they have come, they know not how—over the
whole sphere of creation, and explain their ideal, which is entirely a prod-
uct of pure reason, by illustrations drawn from experience—though in a
degree miserably unworthy of the grandeur of the object, while they refuse
to acknowledge that they have arrived at this cognition or hypothesis by a
very different road from that of experience.
Thus the physico-theological is based upon the cosmological, and this
upon the ontological proof of the existence of a Supreme Being; and as
besides these three there is no other path open to speculative reason, the
ontological proof, on the ground of pure conceptions of reason, is the
only possible one, if any proof of a proposition so far transcending the
empirical exercise of the understanding is possible at all.
364
Immanuel Kant
*Not theological ethics; for this science contains ethical laws, which presuppose
the existence of a Supreme Governor of the world; while moral-theology, on the
contrary, is the expression of a conviction of the existence of a Supreme Being,
founded upon ethical laws.
365
The Critique of Pure Reason
366
Immanuel Kant
367
The Critique of Pure Reason
368
Immanuel Kant
369
The Critique of Pure Reason
APPENDIX.
The result of all the dialectical attempts of pure reason not only confirms
the truth of what we have already proved in our Transcendental Analytic,
namely, that all inferences which would lead us beyond the limits of expe-
rience are fallacious and groundless, but it at the same time teaches us this
important lesson, that human reason has a natural inclination to overstep
these limits, and that transcendental ideas are as much the natural prop-
erty of the reason as categories are of the understanding. There exists this
difference, however, that while the categories never mislead us, outward
objects being always in perfect harmony therewith, ideas are the parents
of irresistible illusions, the severest and most subtle criticism being re-
quired to save us from the fallacies which they induce.
Whatever is grounded in the nature of our powers will be found to be in
harmony with the final purpose and proper employment of these powers,
when once we have discovered their true direction and aim. We are en-
titled to suppose, therefore, that there exists a mode of employing tran-
scendental ideas which is proper and immanent; although, when we mis-
take their meaning, and regard them as conceptions of actual things, their
mode of application is transcendent and delusive. For it is not the idea
itself, but only the employment of the idea in relation to possible experi-
ence, that is transcendent or immanent. An idea is employed transcen-
dently, when it is applied to an object falsely believed to be adequate with
and to correspond to it; imminently, when it is applied solely to the em-
ployment of the understanding in the sphere of experience. Thus all errors
of subreptio—of misapplication, are to be ascribed to defects of judge-
ment, and not to understanding or reason.
Reason never has an immediate relation to an object; it relates immedi-
ately to the understanding alone. It is only through the understanding
that it can be employed in the field of experience. It does not form con-
ceptions of objects, it merely arranges them and gives to them that unity
which they are capable of possessing when the sphere of their application
has been extended as widely as possible. Reason avails itself of the concep-
tion of the understanding for the sole purpose of producing totality in the
different series. This totality the understanding does not concern itself
with; its only occupation is the connection of experiences, by which series
370
Immanuel Kant
371
The Critique of Pure Reason
employ them for the interrogation and investigation of nature, and regard
our cognition as defective so long as it is not adequate to them. We admit
that such a thing as pure earth, pure water, or pure air, is not to be discov-
ered. And yet we require these conceptions (which have their origin in the
reason, so far as regards their absolute purity and completeness) for the
purpose of determining the share which each of these natural causes has in
every phenomenon. Thus the different kinds of matter are all referred to
earths, as mere weight; to salts and inflammable bodies, as pure force; and
finally, to water and air, as the vehicula of the former, or the machines
employed by them in their operations—for the purpose of explaining the
chemical action and reaction of bodies in accordance with the idea of a
mechanism. For, although not actually so expressed, the influence of such
ideas of reason is very observable in the procedure of natural philoso-
phers.
If reason is the faculty of deducing the particular from the general, and
if the general be certain in se and given, it is only necessary that the judge-
ment should subsume the particular under the general, the particular be-
ing thus necessarily determined. I shall term this the demonstrative or
apodeictic employment of reason. If, however, the general is admitted as
problematical only, and is a mere idea, the particular case is certain, but
the universality of the rule which applies to this particular case remains a
problem. Several particular cases, the certainty of which is beyond doubt,
are then taken and examined, for the purpose of discovering whether the
rule is applicable to them; and if it appears that all the particular cases
which can be collected follow from the rule, its universality is inferred,
and at the same time, all the causes which have not, or cannot be pre-
sented to our observation, are concluded to be of the same character with
those which we have observed. This I shall term the hypothetical employ-
ment of the reason.
The hypothetical exercise of reason by the aid of ideas employed as
problematical conceptions is properly not constitutive. That is to say, if
we consider the subject strictly, the truth of the rule, which has been em-
ployed as an hypothesis, does not follow from the use that is made of it by
reason. For how can we know all the possible cases that may arise? some of
which may, however, prove exceptions to the universality of the rule. This
employment of reason is merely regulative, and its sole aim is the intro-
duction of unity into the aggregate of our particular cognitions, and thereby
the approximating of the rule to universality.
The object of the hypothetical employment of reason is therefore the
systematic unity of cognitions; and this unity is the criterion of the truth
372
Immanuel Kant
373
The Critique of Pure Reason
374
Immanuel Kant
375
The Critique of Pure Reason
376
Immanuel Kant
different species, and these again different subspecies; and as each of the
latter must itself contain a sphere (must be of a certain extent, as a concep-
tus communis), reason demands that no species or sub-species is to be
considered as the lowest possible. For a species or sub-species, being al-
ways a conception, which contains only what is common to a number of
different things, does not completely determine any individual thing, or
relate immediately to it, and must consequently contain other concep-
tions, that is, other sub-species under it. This law of specification may be
thus expressed: entium varietates non temere sunt minuendae.
But it is easy to see that this logical law would likewise be without sense
or application, were it not based upon a transcendental law of specifica-
tion, which certainly does not require that the differences existing phe-
nomena should be infinite in number, for the logical principle, which
merely maintains the indeterminateness of the logical sphere of a concep-
tion, in relation to its possible division, does not authorize this statement;
while it does impose upon the understanding the duty of searching for
subspecies to every species, and minor differences in every difference. For,
were there no lower conceptions, neither could there be any higher. Now
the understanding cognizes only by means of conceptions; consequently,
how far soever it may proceed in division, never by mere intuition, but
always by lower and lower conceptions. The cognition of phenomena in
their complete determination (which is possible only by means of the
understanding) requires an unceasingly continued specification of con-
ceptions, and a progression to ever smaller differences, of which abstrac-
tion bad been made in the conception of the species, and still more in that
of the genus.
This law of specification cannot be deduced from experience; it can
never present us with a principle of so universal an application. Empirical
specification very soon stops in its distinction of diversities, and requires
the guidance of the transcendental law, as a principle of the reason—a law
which imposes on us the necessity of never ceasing in our search for differ-
ences, even although these may not present themselves to the senses. That
absorbent earths are of different kinds could only be discovered by obey-
ing the anticipatory law of reason, which imposes upon the understand-
ing the task of discovering the differences existing between these earths,
and supposes that nature is richer in substances than our senses would
indicate. The faculty of the understanding belongs to us just as much
under the presupposition of differences in the objects of nature, as under
the condition that these objects are homogeneous, because we could not
possess conceptions, nor make any use of our understanding, were not the
377
The Critique of Pure Reason
378
Immanuel Kant
ciple: Datur continuum formarum. This principle indicates that all dif-
ferences of species limit each other, and do not admit of transition from
one to another by a saltus, but only through smaller degrees of the differ-
ence between the one species and the other. In one word, there are no
species or sub-species which (in the view of reason) are the nearest pos-
sible to each other; intermediate species or sub-species being always pos-
sible, the difference of which from each of the former is always smaller
than the difference existing between these.
The first law, therefore, directs us to avoid the notion that there exist
different primal genera, and enounces the fact of perfect homogeneity;
the second imposes a check upon this tendency to unity and prescribes
the distinction of sub-species, before proceeding to apply our general con-
ceptions to individuals. The third unites both the former, by enouncing
the fact of homogeneity as existing even in the most various diversity, by
means of the gradual transition from one species to another. Thus it indi-
cates a relationship between the different branches or species, in so far as
they all spring from the same stem.
But this logical law of the continuum specierum (formarum logicarum)
presupposes a transcendental principle (lex continui in natura), without
which the understanding might be led into error, by following the guid-
ance of the former, and thus perhaps pursuing a path contrary to that
prescribed by nature. This law must, consequently, be based upon pure
transcendental, and not upon empirical, considerations. For, in the latter
case, it would come later than the system; whereas it is really itself the
parent of all that is systematic in our cognition of nature. These principles
are not mere hypotheses employed for the purpose of experimenting upon
nature; although when any such connection is discovered, it forms a solid
ground for regarding the hypothetical unity as valid in the sphere of na-
ture—and thus they are in this respect not without their use. But we go
farther, and maintain that it is manifest that these principles of parsimony
in fundamental causes, variety in effects, and affinity in phenomena, are
in accordance both with reason and nature, and that they are not mere
methods or plans devised for the purpose of assisting us in our observa-
tion of the external world.
But it is plain that this continuity of forms is a mere idea, to which no
adequate object can be discovered in experience. And this for two reasons.
First, because the species in nature are really divided, and hence form
quanta discreta; and, if the gradual progression through their affinity were
continuous, the intermediate members lying between two given species
must be infinite in number, which is impossible. Secondly, because we
379
The Critique of Pure Reason
380
Immanuel Kant
merely provides us with a rule or principle for the systematic unity of the
exercise of the understanding. Now, as every principle which imposes upon
the exercise of the understanding a priori compliance with the rule of
systematic unity also relates, although only in an indirect manner, to an
object of experience, the principles of pure reason will also possess objec-
tive reality and validity in relation to experience. But they will not aim at
determining our knowledge in regard to any empirical object; they will
merely indicate the procedure, following which the empirical and deter-
minate exercise of the understanding may be in complete harmony and
connection with itself—a result which is produced by its being brought
into harmony with the principle of systematic unity, so far as that is pos-
sible, and deduced from it.
I term all subjective principles, which are not derived from observation
of the constitution of an object, but from the interest which Reason has in
producing a certain completeness in her cognition of that object, maxims
of reason. Thus there are maxims of speculative reason, which are based
solely upon its speculative interest, although they appear to be objective
principles.
When principles which are really regulative are regarded as constitutive,
and employed as objective principles, contradictions must arise; but if
they are considered as mere maxims, there is no room for contradictions
of any kind, as they then merely indicate the different interests of reason,
which occasion differences in the mode of thought. In effect, Reason has
only one single interest, and the seeming contradiction existing between
her maxims merely indicates a difference in, and a reciprocal limitation of,
the methods by which this interest is satisfied.
This reasoner has at heart the interest of diversity—in accordance with
the principle of specification; another, the interest of unity—in accor-
dance with the principle of aggregation. Each believes that his judgement
rests upon a thorough insight into the subject he is examining, and yet it
has been influenced solely by a greater or less degree of adherence to some
one of the two principles, neither of which are objective, but originate
solely from the interest of reason, and on this account to be termed max-
ims rather than principles. When I observe intelligent men disputing about
the distinctive characteristics of men, animals, or plants, and even of min-
erals, those on the one side assuming the existence of certain national
characteristics, certain well-defined and hereditary distinctions of family,
race, and so on, while the other side maintain that nature has endowed all
races of men with the same faculties and dispositions, and that all differ-
ences are but the result of external and accidental circumstances—I have
382
Immanuel Kant
only to consider for a moment the real nature of the subject of discussion,
to arrive at the conclusion that it is a subject far too deep for us to judge
of, and that there is little probability of either party being able to speak
from a perfect insight into and understanding of the nature of the subject
itself. Both have, in reality, been struggling for the twofold interest of
reason; the one maintaining the one interest, the other the other. But this
difference between the maxims of diversity and unity may easily be recon-
ciled and adjusted; although, so long as they are regarded as objective
principles, they must occasion not only contradictions and polemic, but
place hinderances in the way of the advancement of truth, until some
means is discovered of reconciling these conflicting interests, and bring-
ing reason into union and harmony with itself.
The same is the case with the so-called law discovered by Leibnitz, and
supported with remarkable ability by Bonnet—the law of the continuous
gradation of created beings, which is nothing more than an inference from
the principle of affinity; for observation and study of the order of nature
could never present it to the mind as an objective truth. The steps of this
ladder, as they appear in experience, are too far apart from each other, and
the so-called petty differences between different kinds of animals are in
nature commonly so wide separations that no confidence can be placed in
such views (particularly when we reflect on the great variety of things, and
the ease with which we can discover resemblances), and no faith in the
laws which are said to express the aims and purposes of nature. On the
other hand, the method of investigating the order of nature in the light of
this principle, and the maxim which requires us to regard this order—it
being still undetermined how far it extends—as really existing in nature,
is beyond doubt a legitimate and excellent principle of reason—a prin-
ciple which extends farther than any experience or observation of ours
and which, without giving us any positive knowledge of anything in the
region of experience, guides us to the goal of systematic unity.
383
The Critique of Pure Reason
The ideas of pure reason cannot be, of themselves and in their own na-
ture, dialectical; it is from their misemployment alone that fallacies and
illusions arise. For they originate in the nature of reason itself, and it is
impossible that this supreme tribunal for all the rights and claims of specu-
lation should be itself undeserving of confidence and promotive of error.
It is to be expected, therefore, that these ideas have a genuine and legiti-
mate aim. It is true, the mob of sophists raise against reason the cry of
inconsistency and contradiction, and affect to despise the government of
that faculty, because they cannot understand its constitution, while it is to
its beneficial influences alone that they owe the position and the intelli-
gence which enable them to criticize and to blame its procedure.
We cannot employ an a priori conception with certainty, until we have
made a transcendental deduction therefore. The ideas of pure reason do
not admit of the same kind of deduction as the categories. But if they are
to possess the least objective validity, and to represent anything but mere
creations of thought (entia rationis ratiocinantis), a deduction of them
must be possible. This deduction will complete the critical task imposed
upon pure reason; and it is to this part Of our labours that we now pro-
ceed.
There is a great difference between a thing’s being presented to the mind
as an object in an absolute sense, or merely as an ideal object. In the
former case I employ my conceptions to determine the object; in the latter
case nothing is present to the mind but a mere schema, which does not
relate directly to an object, not even in a hypothetical sense, but which is
useful only for the purpose of representing other objects to the mind, in a
mediate and indirect manner, by means of their relation to the idea in the
intellect. Thus I say the conception of a supreme intelligence is a mere
idea; that is to say, its objective reality does not consist in the fact that it
has an immediate relation to an object (for in this sense we have no means
of establishing its objective validity), it is merely a schema constructed
according to the necessary conditions of the unity of reason—the schema
of a thing in general, which is useful towards the production of the high-
est degree of systematic unity in the empirical exercise of reason, in which
we deduce this or that object of experience from the imaginary object of
this idea, as the ground or cause of the said object of experience. In this
way, the idea is properly a heuristic, and not an ostensive, conception; it
384
Immanuel Kant
385
The Critique of Pure Reason
386
Immanuel Kant
387
The Critique of Pure Reason
388
Immanuel Kant
389
The Critique of Pure Reason
390
Immanuel Kant
391
The Critique of Pure Reason
392
Immanuel Kant
*The advantages which a circular form, in the case of the earth, has over every
other, are well known. But few are aware that the slight flattening at the poles,
which gives it the figure of a spheroid, is the only cause which prevents the eleva-
tions of continents or even of mountains, perhaps thrown up by some internal
convulsion, from continually altering the position of the axis of the earth—and
that to some considerable degree in a short time. The great protuberance of the
earth under the Equator serves to overbalance the impetus of all other masses of
earth, and thus to preserve the axis of the earth, so far as we can observe, in its
present position. And yet this wise arrangement has been unthinkingly explained
from the equilibrium of the formerly fluid mass.
393
The Critique of Pure Reason
on the heights of which it loses its power and collectedness, because it has
completely severed its connection with experience.
The first error which arises from our employing the idea of a Supreme
Being as a constitutive (in repugnance to the very nature of an idea), and
not as a regulative principle, is the error of inactive reason (ignava ratio).*
We may so term every principle which requires us to regard our investiga-
tions of nature as absolutely complete, and allows reason to cease its in-
quiries, as if it had fully executed its task. Thus the psychological idea of
the ego, when employed as a constitutive principle for the explanation of
the phenomena of the soul, and for the extension of our knowledge re-
garding this subject beyond the limits of experience—even to the condi-
tion of the soul after death—is convenient enough for the purposes of
pure reason, but detrimental and even ruinous to its interests in the sphere
of nature and experience. The dogmatizing spiritualist explains the un-
changing unity of our personality through all changes of condition from
the unity of a thinking substance, the interest which we take in things and
events that can happen only after our death, from a consciousness of the
immaterial nature of our thinking subject, and so on. Thus he dispenses
with all empirical investigations into the cause of these internal phenom-
ena, and with all possible explanations of them upon purely natural
grounds; while, at the dictation of a transcendent reason, he passes by the
immanent sources of cognition in experience, greatly to his own ease and
convenience, but to the sacrifice of all, genuine insight and intelligence.
These prejudicial consequences become still more evident, in the case of
the dogmatical treatment of our idea of a Supreme Intelligence, and the
theological system of nature (physico-theology) which is falsely based upon
it. For, in this case, the aims which we observe in nature, and often those
which we merely fancy to exist, make the investigation of causes a very
easy task, by directing us to refer such and such phenomena immediately
to the unsearchable will and counsel of the Supreme Wisdom, while we
ought to investigate their causes in the general laws of the mechanism of
matter. We are thus recommended to consider the labour of reason as
ended, when we have merely dispensed with its employment, which is
guided surely and safely only by the order of nature and the series of
*This was the term applied by the old dialecticians to a sophistical argument, which
ran thus: If it is your fate to die of this disease, you will die, whether you employ a
physician or not. Cicero says that this mode of reasoning has received this appella-
tion, because, if followed, it puts an end to the employment of reason in the affairs
of life. For a similar reason, I have applied this designation to the sophistical argu-
ment of pure reason.
394
Immanuel Kant
395
The Critique of Pure Reason
396
Immanuel Kant
itself, and relate to its own internal constitution. We can now establish
this assertion, which at first sight appeared so rash, in relation to the two
questions in which reason takes the greatest interest, and thus complete
our discussion of the dialectic of pure reason.
If, then, the question is asked, in relation to transcendental theology,*
first, whether there is anything distinct from the world, which contains
the ground of cosmical order and connection according to general laws?
The answer is: Certainly. For the world is a sum of phenomena; there
must, therefore, be some transcendental basis of these phenomena, that is,
a basis cogitable by the pure understanding alone. If, secondly, the ques-
tion is asked whether this being is substance, whether it is of the greatest
reality, whether it is necessary, and so forth? I answer that this question is
utterly without meaning. For all the categories which aid me in forming a
conception of an object cannot be employed except in the world of sense,
and are without meaning when not applied to objects of actual or possible
experience. Out of this sphere, they are not properly conceptions, but the
mere marks or indices of conceptions, which we may admit, although
they cannot, without the help of experience, help us to understand any
subject or thing. If, thirdly, the question is whether we may not cogitate
this being, which is distinct from the world, in analogy with the objects of
experience? The answer is: Undoubtedly, but only as an ideal, and not as a
real object. That is, we must cogitate it only as an unknown substratum of
the systematic unity, order, and finality of the world—a unity which rea-
son must employ as the regulative principle of its investigation of nature.
Nay, more, we may admit into the idea certain anthropomorphic ele-
ments, which are promotive of the interests of this regulative principle.
For it is no more than an idea, which does not relate directly to a being
distinct from the world, but to the regulative principle of the systematic
unity of the world, by means, however, of a schema of this unity—the
schema of a Supreme Intelligence, who is the wisely-designing author of
the universe. What this basis of cosmical unity may be in itself, we know
not—we cannot discover from the idea; we merely know how we ought to
employ the idea of this unity, in relation to the systematic operation of
reason in the sphere of experience.
*After what has been said of the psychological idea of the ego and its proper
employment as a regulative principle of the operations of reason, I need not enter
into details regarding the transcendental illusion by which the systematic unity
of all the various phenomena of the internal sense is hypostatized. The procedure
is in this case very similar to that which has been discussed in our remarks on the
theological ideal.
397
The Critique of Pure Reason
But, it will be asked again, can we on these grounds, admit the existence
of a wise and omnipotent author of the world? Without doubt; and not
only so, but we must assume the existence of such a being. But do we thus
extend the limits of our knowledge beyond the field of possible experi-
ence? By no means. For we have merely presupposed a something, of which
we have no conception, which we do not know as it is in itself; but, in
relation to the systematic disposition of the universe, which we must pre-
suppose in all our observation of nature, we have cogitated this unknown
being in analogy with an intelligent existence (an empirical conception),
that is to say, we have endowed it with those attributes, which, judging
from the nature of our own reason, may contain the ground of such a
systematic unity. This idea is therefore valid only relatively to the employ-
ment in experience of our reason. But if we attribute to it absolute and
objective validity, we overlook the fact that it is merely an ideal being that
we cogitate; and, by setting out from a basis which is not determinable by
considerations drawn from experience, we place ourselves in a position
which incapacitates us from applying this principle to the empirical em-
ployment of reason.
But, it will be asked further, can I make any use of this conception and
hypothesis in my investigations into the world and nature? Yes, for this
very purpose was the idea established by reason as a fundamental basis.
But may I regard certain arrangements, which seemed to have been made
in conformity with some fixed aim, as the arrangements of design, and
look upon them as proceeding from the divine will, with the intervention,
however, of certain other particular arrangements disposed to that end?
Yes, you may do so; but at the same time you must regard it as indifferent,
whether it is asserted that divine wisdom has disposed all things in confor-
mity with his highest aims, or that the idea of supreme wisdom is a regu-
lative principle in the investigation of nature, and at the same time a prin-
ciple of the systematic unity of nature according to general laws, even in
those cases where we are unable to discover that unity. In other words, it
must be perfectly indifferent to you whether you say, when you have dis-
covered this unity: God has wisely willed it so; or: Nature has wisely ar-
ranged this. For it was nothing but the systematic unity, which reason
requires as a basis for the investigation of nature, that justified you in
accepting the idea of a supreme intelligence as a schema for a regulative
principle; and, the farther you advance in the discovery of design and
finality, the more certain the validity of your idea. But, as the whole aim of
this regulative principle was the discovery of a necessary and systematic
unity in nature, we have, in so far as we attain this, to attribute our success
398
Immanuel Kant
to the idea of a Supreme Being; while, at the same time, we cannot, with-
out involving ourselves in contradictions, overlook the general laws of
nature, as it was in reference to them alone that this idea was employed.
We cannot, I say, overlook the general laws of nature, and regard this
conformity to aims observable in nature as contingent or hyperphysical in
its origin; inasmuch as there is no ground which can justify us in the
admission of a being with such properties distinct from and above nature.
All that we are authorized to assert is that this idea may be employed as a
principle, and that the properties of the being which is assumed to corre-
spond to it may be regarded as systematically connected in analogy with
the causal determination of phenomena.
For the same reasons we are justified in introducing into the idea of the
supreme cause other anthropomorphic elements (for without these we
could not predicate anything of it); we may regard it as allowable to cogi-
tate this cause as a being with understanding, the feelings of pleasure and
displeasure, and faculties of desire and will corresponding to these. At the
same time, we may attribute to this being infinite perfection—a perfec-
tion which necessarily transcends that which our knowledge of the order
and design in the world authorize us to predicate of it. For the regulative
law of systematic unity requires us to study nature on the supposition that
systematic and final unity in infinitum is everywhere discoverable, even in
the highest diversity. For, although we may discover little of this cosmical
perfection, it belongs to the legislative prerogative of reason to require us
always to seek for and to expect it; while it must always be beneficial to
institute all inquiries into nature in accordance with this principle. But it
is evident that, by this idea of a supreme author of all, which I place as the
foundation of all inquiries into nature, I do not mean to assert the exist-
ence of such a being, or that I have any knowledge of its existence; and,
consequently, I do not really deduce anything from the existence of this
being, but merely from its idea, that is to say, from the nature of things in
this world, in accordance with this idea. A certain dim consciousness of
the true use of this idea seems to have dictated to the philosophers of all
times the moderate language used by them regarding the cause of the
world. We find them employing the expressions wisdom and care of na-
ture, and divine wisdom, as synonymous—nay, in purely speculative dis-
cussions, preferring the former, because it does not carry the appearance
of greater pretensions than such as we are entitled to make, and at the
same time directs reason to its proper field of action—nature and her
phenomena.
Thus, pure reason, which at first seemed to promise us nothing less
399
The Critique of Pure Reason
400
Immanuel Kant
401
The Critique of Pure Reason
II.
402
Immanuel Kant
*I am well aware that, in the language of the schools, the term discipline is usually
employed as synonymous with instruction. But there are so many cases in which
it is necessary to distinguish the notion of the former, as a course of corrective
training, from that of the latter, as the communication of knowledge, and the
nature of things itself demands the appropriation of the most suitable expressions
for this distinction, that it is my desire that the former terms should never be
employed in any other than a negative signification.
403
The Critique of Pure Reason
well appear strange that reason, whose proper duty it is to prescribe rules
of discipline to all the other powers of the mind, should itself require this
corrective. It has, in fact, hitherto escaped this humiliation, only because,
in presence of its magnificent pretensions and high position, no one could
readily suspect it to be capable of substituting fancies for conceptions, and
words for things.
Reason, when employed in the field of experience, does not stand in
need of criticism, because its principles are subjected to the continual test
of empirical observations. Nor is criticism requisite in the sphere of math-
ematics, where the conceptions of reason must always be presented in
concreto in pure intuition, and baseless or arbitrary assertions are discov-
ered without difficulty. But where reason is not held in a plain track by the
influence of empirical or of pure intuition, that is, when it is employed in
the transcendental sphere of pure conceptions, it stands in great need of
discipline, to restrain its propensity to overstep the limits of possible expe-
rience and to keep it from wandering into error. In fact, the utility of the
philosophy of pure reason is entirely of this negative character. Particular
errors may be corrected by particular animadversions, and the causes of
these errors may be eradicated by criticism. But where we find, as in the
case of pure reason, a complete system of illusions and fallacies, closely
connected with each other and depending upon grand general principles,
there seems to be required a peculiar and negative code of mental legisla-
tion, which, under the denomination of a discipline, and founded upon
the nature of reason and the objects of its exercise, shall constitute a sys-
tem of thorough examination and testing, which no fallacy will be able to
withstand or escape from, under whatever disguise or concealment it may
lurk.
But the reader must remark that, in this the second division of our
transcendental Critique the discipline of pure reason is not directed to the
content, but to the method of the cognition of pure reason. The former
task has been completed in the doctrine of elements. But there is so much
similarity in the mode of employing the faculty of reason, whatever be the
object to which it is applied, while, at the same time, its employment in
the transcendental sphere is so essentially different in kind from every
other, that, without the warning negative influence of a discipline spe-
cially directed to that end, the errors are unavoidable which spring from
the unskillful employment of the methods which are originated by reason
but which are out of place in this sphere.
404
Immanuel Kant
405
The Critique of Pure Reason
406
Immanuel Kant
constructing a triangle. He knows that two right angles are equal to the
sum of all the contiguous angles which proceed from one point in a straight
line; and he goes on to produce one side of his triangle, thus forming two
adjacent angles which are together equal to two right angles. He then
divides the exterior of these angles, by drawing a line parallel with the
opposite side of the triangle, and immediately perceives that he has thus
got an exterior adjacent angle which is equal to the interior. Proceeding in
this way, through a chain of inferences, and always on the ground of intu-
ition, he arrives at a clear and universally valid solution of the question.
But mathematics does not confine itself to the construction of quanti-
ties (quanta), as in the case of geometry; it occupies itself with pure quan-
tity also (quantitas), as in the case of algebra, where complete abstraction
is made of the properties of the object indicated by the conception of
quantity. In algebra, a certain method of notation by signs is adopted, and
these indicate the different possible constructions of quantities, the ex-
traction of roots, and so on. After having thus denoted the general con-
ception of quantities, according to their different relations, the different
operations by which quantity or number is increased or diminished are
presented in intuition in accordance with general rules. Thus, when one
quantity is to be divided by another, the signs which denote both are
placed in the form peculiar to the operation of division; and thus algebra,
by means of a symbolical construction of quantity, just as geometry, with
its ostensive or geometrical construction (a construction of the objects
themselves), arrives at results which discursive cognition cannot hope to
reach by the aid of mere conceptions.
Now, what is the cause of this difference in the fortune of the philoso-
pher and the mathematician, the former of whom follows the path of
conceptions, while the latter pursues that of intuitions, which he repre-
sents, a priori, in correspondence with his conceptions? The cause is evi-
dent from what has been already demonstrated in the introduction to this
Critique. We do not, in the present case, want to discover analytical propo-
sitions, which may be produced merely by analysing our conceptions—
for in this the philosopher would have the advantage over his rival; we aim
at the discovery of synthetical propositions—such synthetical proposi-
tions, moreover, as can be cognized a priori. I must not confine myself to
that which I actually cogitate in my conception of a triangle, for this is
nothing more than the mere definition; I must try to go beyond that, and
to arrive at properties which are not contained in, although they belong
to, the conception. Now, this is impossible, unless I determine the object
present to my mind according to the conditions, either of empirical, or of
407
The Critique of Pure Reason
408
Immanuel Kant
409
The Critique of Pure Reason
*In the case of the conception of cause, I do really go beyond the empirical con-
ception of an event—but not to the intuition which presents this conception in
concreto, but only to the time-conditions, which may be found in experience to
correspond to the conception. My procedure is, therefore, strictly according to
conceptions; I cannot in a case of this kind employ the construction of concep-
tions, because the conception is merely a rule for the synthesis of perceptions,
which are not pure intuitions, and which, therefore, cannot be given a priori.
410
Immanuel Kant
411
The Critique of Pure Reason
efforts of reason in this direction are persisted in, even after the plainest
and most expressive warnings, hope still beckoning us past the limits of
experience into the splendours of the intellectual world—it becomes nec-
essary to cut away the last anchor of this fallacious and fantastic hope. We
shall, accordingly, show that the mathematical method is unattended in
the sphere of philosophy by the least advantage—except, perhaps, that it
more plainly exhibits its own inadequacy—that geometry and philosophy
are two quite different things, although they go band in hand in hand in
the field of natural science, and, consequently, that the procedure of the
one can never be imitated by the other.
The evidence of mathematics rests upon definitions, axioms, and dem-
onstrations. I shall be satisfied with showing that none of these forms can
be employed or imitated in philosophy in the sense in which they are
understood by mathematicians; and that the geometrician, if he employs
his method in philosophy, will succeed only in building card-castles, while
the employment of the philosophical method in mathematics can result
in nothing but mere verbiage. The essential business of philosophy, in-
deed, is to mark out the limits of the science; and even the mathematician,
unless his talent is naturally circumscribed and limited to this particular
department of knowledge, cannot turn a deaf ear to the warnings of phi-
losophy, or set himself above its direction.
*The definition must describe the conception completely that is, omit none of
the marks or signs of which it composed; within its own limits, that is, it must be
precise, and enumerate no more signs than belong to the conception; and on
primary grounds, that is to say, the limitations of the bounds of the conception
must not be deduced from other conceptions, as in this case a proof would be
necessary, and the so-called definition would be incapable of taking its place at
the bead of all the judgements we have to form regarding an object.
412
Immanuel Kant
new observations abstract some and add new ones, so that an empirical
conception never remains within permanent limits. It is, in fact, useless to
define a conception of this kind. If, for example, we are speaking of water
and its properties, we do not stop at what we actually think by the word
water, but proceed to observation and experiment; and the word, with the
few signs attached to it, is more properly a designation than a conception
of the thing. A definition in this case would evidently be nothing more
than a determination of the word. In the second place, no a priori concep-
tion, such as those of substance, cause, right, fitness, and so on, can be
defined. For I can never be sure, that the clear representation of a given
conception (which is given in a confused state) has been fully developed,
until I know that the representation is adequate with its object. But, inas-
much as the conception, as it is presented to the mind, may contain a
number of obscure representations, which we do not observe in our analysis,
although we employ them in our application of the conception, I can
never be sure that my analysis is complete, while examples may make this
probable, although they can never demonstrate the fact. Instead of the
word definition, I should rather employ the term exposition—a more
modest expression, which the critic may accept without surrendering his
doubts as to the completeness of the analysis of any such conception. As,
therefore, neither empirical nor a priori conceptions are capable of defini-
tion, we have to see whether the only other kind of conceptions—arbi-
trary conceptions—can be subjected to this mental operation. Such a con-
ception can always be defined; for I must know thoroughly what I wished
to cogitate in it, as it was I who created it, and it was not given to my mind
either by the nature of my understanding or by experience. At the same
time, I cannot say that, by such a definition, I have defined a real object.
If the conception is based upon empirical conditions, if, for example, I
have a conception of a clock for a ship, this arbitrary conception does not
assure me of the existence or even of the possibility of the object. My
definition of such a conception would with more propriety be termed a
declaration of a project than a definition of an object. There are no other
conceptions which can bear definition, except those which contain an
arbitrary synthesis, which can be constructed a priori. Consequently, the
science of mathematics alone possesses definitions. For the object here
thought is presented a priori in intuition; and thus it can never contain
more or less than the conception, because the conception of the object has
been given by the definition—and primarily, that is, without deriving the
definition from any other source. Philosophical definitions are, therefore,
merely expositions of given conceptions, while mathematical definitions
413
The Critique of Pure Reason
415
The Critique of Pure Reason
It follows from all these considerations that it is not consonant with the
nature of philosophy, especially in the sphere of pure reason, to employ
the dogmatical method, and to adorn itself with the titles and insignia of
mathematical science. It does not belong to that order, and can only hope
for a fraternal union with that science. Its attempts at mathematical evi-
dence are vain pretensions, which can only keep it back from its true aim,
which is to detect the illusory procedure of reason when transgressing its
proper limits, and by fully explaining and analysing our conceptions, to
conduct us from the dim regions of speculation to the clear region of
modest self-knowledge. Reason must not, therefore, in its transcendental
endeavours, look forward with such confidence, as if the path it is pursu-
ing led straight to its aim, nor reckon with such security upon its pre-
misses, as to consider it unnecessary to take a step back, or to keep a strict
416
Immanuel Kant
417
The Critique of Pure Reason
They only serve to conceal errors and fallacies, and to deceive philosophy,
whose duty it is to see that reason pursues a safe and straight path. A
philosophical method may, however, be systematical. For our reason is,
subjectively considered, itself a system, and, in the sphere of mere concep-
tions, a system of investigation according to principles of unity, the mate-
rial being supplied by experience alone. But this is not the proper place for
discussing the peculiar method of transcendental philosophy, as our present
task is simply to examine whether our faculties are capable of erecting an
edifice on the basis of pure reason, and how far they may proceed with the
materials at their command.
418
Immanuel Kant
419
The Critique of Pure Reason
420
Immanuel Kant
421
The Critique of Pure Reason
422
Immanuel Kant
like everything that springs from nature, must in its final purpose be con-
ducive to the good of humanity—to conceal our real sentiments, and to
give expression only to certain received opinions, which are regarded as at
once safe and promotive of the common good. It is true, this tendency,
not only to conceal our real sentiments, but to profess those which may
gain us favour in the eyes of society, has not only civilized, but, in a certain
measure, moralized us; as no one can break through the outward covering
of respectability, honour, and morality, and thus the seemingly-good ex-
amples which we which we see around us form an excellent school for
moral improvement, so long as our belief in their genuineness remains
unshaken. But this disposition to represent ourselves as better than we are,
and to utter opinions which are not our own, can be nothing more than a
kind of provisionary arrangement of nature to lead us from the rudeness
of an uncivilized state, and to teach us how to assume at least the appear-
ance and manner of the good we see. But when true principles have been
developed, and have obtained a sure foundation in our habit of thought,
this conventionalism must be attacked with earnest vigour, otherwise it
corrupts the heart, and checks the growth of good dispositions with the
mischievous weed of air appearances.
I am sorry to remark the same tendency to misrepresentation and hy-
pocrisy in the sphere of speculative discussion, where there is less tempta-
tion to restrain the free expression of thought. For what can be more preju-
dicial to the interests of intelligence than to falsify our real sentiments, to
conceal the doubts which we feel in regard to our statements, or to main-
tain the validity of grounds of proof which we well know to be insuffi-
cient? So long as mere personal vanity is the source of these unworthy
artifices—and this is generally the case in speculative discussions, which
are mostly destitute of practical interest, and are incapable of complete
demonstration—the vanity of the opposite party exaggerates as much on
the other side; and thus the result is the same, although it is not brought
about so soon as if the dispute had been conducted in a sincere and up-
right spirit. But where the mass entertains the notion that the aim of
certain subtle speculators is nothing less than to shake the very founda-
tions of public welfare and morality—it seems not only prudent, but even
praise worthy, to maintain the good cause by illusory arguments, rather
than to give to our supposed opponents the advantage of lowering our
declarations to the moderate tone of a merely practical conviction, and of
compelling us to confess our inability to attain to apodeictic certainty in
speculative subjects. But we ought to reflect that there is nothing, in the
world more fatal to the maintenance of a good cause than deceit, misrep-
423
The Critique of Pure Reason
424
Immanuel Kant
425
The Critique of Pure Reason
But, it will be said, must we not warn the youth entrusted to academical
care against such writings, must we not preserve them from the knowl-
edge of these dangerous assertions, until their judgement is ripened, or
rather until the doctrines which we wish to inculcate are so firmly rooted
in their minds as to withstand all attempts at instilling the contrary dog-
mas, from whatever quarter they may come?
If we are to confine ourselves to the dogmatical procedure in the sphere
of pure reason, and find ourselves unable to settle such disputes otherwise
than by becoming a party in them, and setting counter-assertions against
the statements advanced by our opponents, there is certainly no plan more
advisable for the moment, but, at the same time, none more absurd and
inefficient for the future, than this retaining of the youthful mind under
guardianship for a time, and thus preserving it—for so long at least—
from seduction into error. But when, at a later period, either curiosity, or
the prevalent fashion of thought places such writings in their hands, will
the so-called convictions of their youth stand firm? The young thinker,
who has in his armoury none but dogmatical weapons with which to
resist the attacks of his opponent, and who cannot detect the latent dialec-
tic which lies in his own opinions as well as in those of the opposite party,
sees the advance of illusory arguments and grounds of proof which have
the advantage of novelty, against as illusory grounds of proof destitute of
this advantage, and which, perhaps, excite the suspicion that the natural
credulity of his youth has been abused by his instructors. He thinks he can
find no better means of showing that he has out grown the discipline of
his minority than by despising those well-meant warnings, and, knowing
no system of thought but that of dogmatism, he drinks deep draughts of
the poison that is to sap the principles in which his early years were trained.
Exactly the opposite of the system here recommended ought to be pur-
sued in academical instruction. This can only be effected, however, by a
thorough training in the critical investigation of pure reason. For, in order
to bring the principles of this critique into exercise as soon as possible, and
to demonstrate their perfect even in the presence of the highest degree of
dialectical illusion, the student ought to examine the assertions made on
both sides of speculative questions step by step, and to test them by these
principles. It cannot be a difficult task for him to show the fallacies inher-
ent in these propositions, and thus he begins early to feel his own power of
securing himself against the influence of such sophistical arguments, which
must finally lose, for him, all their illusory power. And, although the same
blows which overturn the edifice of his opponent are as fatal to his own
speculative structures, if such he has wished to rear; he need not feel any
426
Immanuel Kant
427
The Critique of Pure Reason
is accidental and not necessary, it must incite me, in the first case, to a
dogmatical inquiry regarding the objects of which I am ignorant; in the
second, to a critical investigation into the bounds of all possible knowl-
edge. But that my ignorance is absolutely necessary and unavoidable, and
that it consequently absolves from the duty of all further investigation, is
a fact which cannot be made out upon empirical grounds—from observa-
tion—but upon critical grounds alone, that is, by a thoroughgoing inves-
tigation into the primary sources of cognition. It follows that the determi-
nation of the bounds of reason can be made only on a priori grounds;
while the empirical limitation of reason, which is merely an indeterminate
cognition of an ignorance that can never be completely removed, can take
place only a posteriori. In other words, our empirical knowledge is limited
by that which yet remains for us to know. The former cognition of our
ignorance, which is possible only on a rational basis, is a science; the latter
is merely a perception, and we cannot say how far the inferences drawn
from it may extend. If I regard the earth, as it really appears to my senses,
as a flat surface, I am ignorant how far this surface extends. But experience
teaches me that, how far soever I go, I always see before me a space in
which I can proceed farther; and thus I know the limits—merely visual—
of my actual knowledge of the earth, although I am ignorant of the limits
of the earth itself. But if I have got so far as to know that the earth is a
sphere, and that its surface is spherical, I can cognize a priori and deter-
mine upon principles, from my knowledge of a small part of this sur-
face—say to the extent of a degree—the diameter and circumference of
the earth; and although I am ignorant of the objects which this surface
contains, I have a perfect knowledge of its limits and extent.
The sum of all the possible objects of our cognition seems to us to be a
level surface, with an apparent horizon—that which forms the limit of its
extent, and which has been termed by us the idea of unconditioned total-
ity. To reach this limit by empirical means is impossible, and all attempts
to determine it a priori according to a principle, are alike in vain. But all
the questions raised by pure reason relate to that which lies beyond this
horizon, or, at least, in its boundary line.
The celebrated David Hume was one of those geographers of human
reason who believe that they have given a sufficient answer to all such
questions by declaring them to lie beyond the horizon of our knowledge—
a horizon which, however, Hume was unable to determine. His attention
especially was directed to the principle of causality; and he remarked with
perfect justice that the truth of this principle, and even the objective valid-
ity of the conception of a cause, was not commonly based upon clear
428
Immanuel Kant
insight, that is, upon a priori cognition. Hence he concluded that this law
does not derive its authority from its universality and necessity, but merely
from its general applicability in the course of experience, and a kind of
subjective necessity thence arising, which he termed habit. From the in-
ability of reason to establish this principle as a necessary law for the acqui-
sition of all experience, he inferred the nullity of all the attempts of reason
to pass the region of the empirical.
This procedure of subjecting the facta of reason to examination, and, if
necessary, to disapproval, may be termed the censura of reason. This censura
must inevitably lead us to doubts regarding all transcendent employment
of principles. But this is only the second step in our inquiry. The first step
in regard to the subjects of pure reason, and which marks the infancy of
that faculty, is that of dogmatism. The second, which we have just men-
tioned, is that of scepticism, and it gives evidence that our judgement has
been improved by experience. But a third step is necessary—indicative of
the maturity and manhood of the judgement, which now lays a firm foun-
dation upon universal and necessary principles. This is the period of criti-
cism, in which we do not examine the facta of reason, but reason itself, in
the whole extent of its powers, and in regard to its capability of a priori
cognition; and thus we determine not merely the empirical and ever-shift-
ing bounds of our knowledge, but its necessary and eternal limits. We
demonstrate from indubitable principles, not merely our ignorance in re-
spect to this or that subject, but in regard to all possible questions of a
certain class. Thus scepticism is a resting place for reason, in which it may
reflect on its dogmatical wanderings and gain some knowledge of the re-
gion in which it happens to be, that it may pursue its way with greater
certainty; but it cannot be its permanent dwelling-place. It must take up
its abode only in the region of complete certitude, whether this relates to
the cognition of objects themselves, or to the limits which bound all our
cognition.
Reason is not to be considered as an indefinitely extended plane, of the
bounds of which we have only a general knowledge; it ought rather to be
compared to a sphere, the radius of which may be found from the curva-
ture of its surface—that is, the nature of a priori synthetical propositions—
and, consequently, its circumference and extent. Beyond the sphere of
experience there are no objects which it can cognize; nay, even questions
regarding such supposititious objects relate only to the subjective prin-
ciples of a complete determination of the relations which exist between
the understanding-conceptions which lie within this sphere.
We are actually in possession of a priori synthetical cognitions, as is
429
The Critique of Pure Reason
430
Immanuel Kant
431
The Critique of Pure Reason
432
Immanuel Kant
To the uncritical dogmatist, who has not surveyed the sphere of his
understanding, nor determined, in accordance with principles, the limits
of possible cognition, who, consequently, is ignorant of his own powers,
and believes he will discover them by the attempts he makes in the field of
cognition, these attacks of scepticism are not only dangerous, but destruc-
tive. For if there is one proposition in his chain of reasoning which be he
cannot prove, or the fallacy in which he cannot evolve in accordance with
a principle, suspicion falls on all his statements, however plausible they
may appear.
And thus scepticism, the bane of dogmatical philosophy, conducts us to
a sound investigation into the understanding and the reason. When we
are thus far advanced, we need fear no further attacks; for the limits of our
domain are clearly marked out, and we can make no claims nor become
involved in any disputes regarding the region that lies beyond these limits.
Thus the sceptical procedure in philosophy does not present any solution
of the problems of reason, but it forms an excellent exercise for its powers,
awakening its circumspection, and indicating the means whereby it may
most fully establish its claims to its legitimate possessions.
This critique of reason has now taught us that all its efforts to extend the
bounds of knowledge, by means of pure speculation, are utterly fruitless.
So much the wider field, it may appear, lies open to hypothesis; as, where
we cannot know with certainty, we are at liberty to make guesses and to
form suppositions.
Imagination may be allowed, under the strict surveillance of reason, to
invent suppositions; but, these must be based on something that is per-
fectly certain—and that is the possibility of the object. If we are well as-
sured upon this point, it is allowable to have recourse to supposition in
regard to the reality of the object; but this supposition must, unless it is
utterly groundless, be connected, as its ground of explanation, with that
which is really given and absolutely certain. Such a supposition is termed
a hypothesis.
It is beyond our power to form the least conception a priori of the
possibility of dynamical connection in phenomena; and the category of
the pure understanding will not enable us to excogitate any such connec-
tion, but merely helps us to understand it, when we meet with it in expe-
rience. For this reason we cannot, in accordance with the categories, imagine
433
The Critique of Pure Reason
or invent any object or any property of an object not given, or that may
not be given in experience, and employ it in a hypothesis; otherwise, we
should be basing our chain of reasoning upon mere chimerical fancies,
and not upon conceptions of things. Thus, we have no right to assume the
existence of new powers, not existing in nature—for example, an under-
standing with a non-sensuous intuition, a force of attraction without con-
tact, or some new kind of substances occupying space, and yet without
the property of impenetrability—and, consequently, we cannot assume
that there is any other kind of community among substances than that
observable in experience, any kind of presence than that in space, or any
kind of duration than that in time. In one word, the conditions of pos-
sible experience are for reason the only conditions of the possibility of
things; reason cannot venture to form, independently of these conditions,
any conceptions of things, because such conceptions, although not self-
contradictory, are without object and without application.
The conceptions of reason are, as we have already shown, mere ideas,
and do not relate to any object in any kind of experience. At the same
time, they do not indicate imaginary or possible objects. They are purely
problematical in their nature and, as aids to the heuristic exercise of the
faculties, form the basis of the regulative principles for the systematic
employment of the understanding in the field of experience. If we leave
this ground of experience, they become mere fictions of thought, the pos-
sibility of which is quite indemonstrable; and they cannot, consequently,
be employed as hypotheses in the explanation of real phenomena. It is
quite admissible to cogitate the soul as simple, for the purpose of enabling
ourselves to employ the idea of a perfect and necessary unity of all the
faculties of the mind as the principle of all our inquiries into its internal
phenomena, although we cannot cognize this unity in concreto. But to
assume that the soul is a simple substance (a transcendental conception)
would be enouncing a proposition which is not only indemonstrable—as
many physical hypotheses are—but a proposition which is purely arbi-
trary, and in the highest degree rash. The simple is never presented in
experience; and, if by substance is here meant the permanent object of
sensuous intuition, the possibility of a simple phenomenon is perfectly
inconceivable. Reason affords no good grounds for admitting the exist-
ence of intelligible beings, or of intelligible properties of sensuous things,
although—as we have no conception either of their possibility or of their
impossibility—it will always be out of our power to affirm dogmatically
that they do not exist. In the explanation of given phenomena, no other
things and no other grounds of explanation can be employed than those
434
Immanuel Kant
435
The Critique of Pure Reason
mity to aims, the order and the greatness which we observe in the uni-
verse; but we find ourselves obliged, when we observe the evil in the world
and the exceptions to these laws, to employ new hypothesis in support of
the original one. We employ the idea of the simple nature of the human
soul as the foundation of all the theories we may form of its phenomena;
but when we meet with difficulties in our way, when we observe in the
soul phenomena similar to the changes which take place in matter, we
require to call in new auxiliary hypotheses. These may, indeed, not be
false, but we do not know them to be true, because the only witness to
their certitude is the hypothesis which they themselves have been called in
to explain.
We are not discussing the above-mentioned assertions regarding the
immaterial unity of the soul and the existence of a Supreme Being as
dogmata, which certain philosophers profess to demonstrate a priori, but
purely as hypotheses. In the former case, the dogmatist must take care
that his arguments possess the apodeictic certainty of a demonstration.
For the assertion that the reality of such ideas is probable is as absurd as a
proof of the probability of a proposition in geometry. Pure abstract rea-
son, apart from all experience, can either cognize nothing at all; and hence
the judgements it enounces are never mere opinions, they are either
apodeictic certainties, or declarations that nothing can be known on the
subject. Opinions and probable judgements on the nature of things can
only be employed to explain given phenomena, or they may relate to the
effect, in accordance with empirical laws, of an actually existing cause. In
other words, we must restrict the sphere of opinion to the world of expe-
rience and nature. Beyond this region opinion is mere invention; unless
we are groping about for the truth on a path not yet fully known, and
have some hopes of stumbling upon it by chance.
But, although hypotheses are inadmissible in answers to the questions
of pure speculative reason, they may be employed in the defence of these
answers. That is to say, hypotheses are admissible in polemic, but not in
the sphere of dogmatism. By the defence of statements of this character, I
do not mean an attempt at discovering new grounds for their support, but
merely the refutation of the arguments of opponents. All a priori syntheti-
cal propositions possess the peculiarity that, although the philosopher who
maintains the reality of the ideas contained in the proposition is not in
possession of sufficient knowledge to establish the certainty of his state-
ments, his opponent is as little able to prove the truth of the opposite.
This equality of fortune does not allow the one party to be superior to the
other in the sphere of speculative cognition; and it is this sphere, accord-
436
Immanuel Kant
ingly, that is the proper arena of these endless speculative conflicts. But we
shall afterwards show that, in relation to its practical exercise, Reason has
the right of admitting what, in the field of pure speculation, she would
not be justified in supposing, except upon perfectly sufficient grounds;
because all such suppositions destroy the necessary completeness of specu-
lation—a condition which the practical reason, however, does not con-
sider to be requisite. In this sphere, therefore, Reason is mistress of a pos-
session, her title to which she does not require to prove—which, in fact,
she could not do. The burden of proof accordingly rests upon the oppo-
nent. But as he has just as little knowledge regarding the subject discussed,
and is as little able to prove the non-existence of the object of an idea, as
the philosopher on the other side is to demonstrate its reality, it is evident
that there is an advantage on the side of the philosopher who maintains
his proposition as a practically necessary supposition (melior est conditio
possidentis). For he is at liberty to employ, in self-defence, the same weap-
ons as his opponent makes use of in attacking him; that is, he has a right
to use hypotheses not for the purpose of supporting the arguments in
favour of his own propositions, but to show that his opponent knows no
more than himself regarding the subject under ‘discussion and cannot
boast of any speculative advantage.
Hypotheses are, therefore, admissible in the sphere of pure reason only
as weapons for self-defence, and not as supports to dogmatical assertions.
But the opposing party we must always seek for in ourselves. For specula-
tive reason is, in the sphere of transcendentalism, dialectical in its own
nature. The difficulties and objections we have to fear lie in ourselves.
They are like old but never superannuated claims; and we must seek them
out, and settle them once and for ever, if we are to expect a permanent
peace. External tranquility is hollow and unreal. The root of these contra-
dictions, which lies in the nature of human reason, must be destroyed;
and this can only be done by giving it, in the first instance, freedom to
grow, nay, by nourishing it, that it may send out shoots, and thus betray
its own existence. It is our duty, therefore, to try to discover new objec-
tions, to put weapons in the bands of our opponent, and to grant him the
most favourable position in the arena that he can wish. We have nothing
to fear from these concessions; on the contrary, we may rather hope that
we shall thus make ourselves master of a possession which no one will ever
venture to dispute.
The thinker requires, to be fully equipped, the hypotheses of pure rea-
son, which, although but leaden weapons (for they have not been steeled
in the armoury of experience), are as useful as any that can be employed
437
The Critique of Pure Reason
438
Immanuel Kant
439
The Critique of Pure Reason
440
Immanuel Kant
441
The Critique of Pure Reason
442
Immanuel Kant
443
The Critique of Pure Reason
444
Immanuel Kant
this case impossible. If, for example, we presuppose that the world of
sense is given in itself in its totality, it is false, either that it is infinite, or
that it is finite and limited in space. Both are false, because the hypothesis
is false. For the notion of phenomena (as mere representations) which are
given in themselves (as objects) is self-contradictory; and the infinitude of
this imaginary whole would, indeed, be unconditioned, but would be
inconsistent (as everything in the phenomenal world is conditioned) with
the unconditioned determination and finitude of quantities which is pre-
supposed in our conception.
The apagogic mode of proof is the true source of those illusions which
have always had so strong an attraction for the admirers of dogmatical
philosophy. It may be compared to a champion who maintains the honour
and claims of the party he has adopted by offering battle to all who doubt
the validity of these claims and the purity of that honour; while nothing
can be proved in this way, except the respective strength of the combat-
ants, and the advantage, in this respect, is always on the side of the attack-
ing party. Spectators, observing that each party is alternately conqueror
and conquered, are led to regard the subject of dispute as beyond the
power of man to decide upon. But such an opinion cannot be justified;
and it is sufficient to apply to these reasoners the remark:
445
The Critique of Pure Reason
446
Immanuel Kant
pline, and not a canon. If, then, there is any proper mode of employing
the faculty of pure reason—in which case there must be a canon for this
faculty—this canon will relate, not to the speculative, but to the practical
use of reason. This canon we now proceed to investigate.
There exists in the faculty of reason a natural desire to venture beyond the
field of experience, to attempt to reach the utmost bounds of all cognition
by the help of ideas alone, and not to rest satisfied until it has fulfilled its
course and raised the sum of its cognitions into a self-subsistent system-
atic whole. Is the motive for this endeavour to be found in its speculative,
or in its practical interests alone?
Setting aside, at present, the results of the labours of pure reason in its
speculative exercise, I shall merely inquire regarding the problems the so-
lution of which forms its ultimate aim, whether reached or not, and in
relation to which all other aims are but partial and intermediate. These
highest aims must, from the nature of reason, possess complete unity;
otherwise the highest interest of humanity could not be successfully pro-
moted.
The transcendental speculation of reason relates to three things: the
freedom of the will, the immortality of the soul, and the existence of God.
The speculative interest which reason has in those questions is very small;
and, for its sake alone, we should not undertake the labour of transcen-
dental investigation—a labour full of toil and ceaseless struggle. We should
be loth to undertake this labour, because the discoveries we might make
would not be of the smallest use in the sphere of concrete or physical
investigation. We may find out that the will is free, but this knowledge
only relates to the intelligible cause of our volition. As regards the phe-
nomena or expressions of this will, that is, our actions, we are bound, in
obedience to an inviolable maxim, without which reason cannot be em-
ployed in the sphere of experience, to explain these in the same way as we
explain all the other phenomena of nature, that is to say, according to its
unchangeable laws. We may have discovered the spirituality and immor-
tality of the soul, but we cannot employ this knowledge to explain the
phenomena of this life, nor the peculiar nature of the future, because our
conception of an incorporeal nature is purely negative and does not add
anything to our knowledge, and the only inferences to be drawn from it
are purely fictitious. If, again, we prove the existence of a supreme intelli-
447
The Critique of Pure Reason
448
Immanuel Kant
*All practical conceptions relate to objects of pleasure and pain, and conse-
quently—in an indirect manner, at least—to objects of feeling. But as feeling is
not a faculty of representation, but lies out of the sphere of our powers of cogni-
tion, the elements of our judgements, in so far as they relate to pleasure or pain,
that is, the elements of our practical judgements, do not belong to transcendental
philosophy, which has to do with pure a priori cognitions alone.
449
The Critique of Pure Reason
Reason conducted us, in its speculative use, through the field of experi-
ence and, as it can never find complete satisfaction in that sphere, from
thence to speculative ideas—which, however, in the end brought us back
again to experience, and thus fulfilled the purpose of reason, in a manner
which, though useful, was not at all in accordance with our expectations.
It now remains for us to consider whether pure reason can be employed in
a practical sphere, and whether it will here conduct us to those ideas which
attain the highest ends of pure reason, as we have just stated them. We
shall thus ascertain whether, from the point of view of its practical inter-
est, reason may not be able to supply us with that which, on the specula-
tive side, it wholly denies us.
The whole interest of reason, speculative as well as practical, is centred
in the three following questions:
451
The Critique of Pure Reason
452
Immanuel Kant
453
The Critique of Pure Reason
454
Immanuel Kant
and with it, mere desert, is likewise far from being the complete good. To
make it complete, he who conducts himself in a manner not unworthy of
happiness, must be able to hope for the possession of happiness. Even
reason, unbiased by private ends, or interested considerations, cannot judge
otherwise, if it puts itself in the place of a being whose business it is to
dispense all happiness to others. For in the practical idea both points are
essentially combined, though in such a way that participation in happi-
ness is rendered possible by the moral disposition, as its condition, and
not conversely, the moral disposition by the prospect of happiness. For a
disposition which should require the prospect of happiness as its neces-
sary condition would not be moral, and hence also would not be worthy
of complete happiness—a happiness which, in the view of reason, recog-
nizes no limitation but such as arises from our own immoral conduct.
Happiness, therefore, in exact proportion with the morality of rational
beings (whereby they are made worthy of happiness), constitutes alone
the supreme good of a world into which we absolutely must transport
ourselves according to the commands of pure but practical reason. This
world is, it is true, only an intelligible world; for of such a systematic unity
of ends as it requires, the world of sense gives us no hint. Its reality can be
based on nothing else but the hypothesis of a supreme original good. In it
independent reason, equipped with all the sufficiency of a supreme cause,
founds, maintains, and fulfils the universal order of things, with the most
perfect teleological harmony, however much this order may be hidden
from us in the world of sense.
This moral theology has the peculiar advantage, in contrast with specu-
lative theology, of leading inevitably to the conception of a sole, perfect,
and rational First Cause, whereof speculative theology does not give us
any indication on objective grounds, far less any convincing evidence. For
we find neither in transcendental nor in natural theology, however far
reason may lead us in these, any ground to warrant us in assuming the
existence of one only Being, which stands at the head of all natural causes,
and on which these are entirely dependent. On the other band, if we take
our stand on moral unity as a necessary law of the universe, and from this
point of view consider what is necessary to give this law adequate effi-
ciency and, for us, obligatory force, we must come to the conclusion that
there is one only supreme will, which comprehends all these laws in itself.
For how, under different wills, should we find complete unity of ends?
This will must be omnipotent, that all nature and its relation to morality
in the world may be subject to it; omniscient, that it may have knowledge
of the most secret feelings and their moral worth; omnipresent, that it
455
The Critique of Pure Reason
may be at hand to supply every necessity to which the highest weal of the
world may give rise; eternal, that this harmony of nature and liberty may
never fail; and so on.
But this systematic unity of ends in this world of intelligences-which, as
mere nature, is only a world of sense, but, as a system of freedom of voli-
tion, may be termed an intelligible, that is, moral world (regnum gratiae)—
leads inevitably also to the teleological unity of all things which constitute
this great whole, according to universal natural laws—just as the unity of
the former is according to universal and necessary moral laws—and unites
the practical with the speculative reason. The world must be represented
as having originated from an idea, if it is to harmonize with that use of
reason without which we cannot even consider ourselves as worthy of
reason-namely, the moral use, which rests entirely on the idea of the su-
preme good. Hence the investigation of nature receives a teleological di-
rection, and becomes, in its widest extension, physico-theology. But this,
taking its rise in moral order as a unity founded on the essence of free-
dom, and not accidentally instituted by external commands, establishes
the teleological view of nature on grounds which must be inseparably
connected with the internal possibility of things. This gives rise to a tran-
scendental theology, which takes the ideal of the highest ontological per-
fection as a principle of systematic unity; and this principle connects all
things according to universal and necessary natural laws, because all things
have their origin in the absolute necessity of the one only Primal Being.
What use can we make of our understanding, even in respect of experi-
ence, if we do not propose ends to ourselves? But the highest ends are
those of morality, and it is only pure reason that can give us the knowledge
of these. Though supplied with these, and putting ourselves under their
guidance, we can make no teleological use of the knowledge of nature, as
regards cognition, unless nature itself has established teleological unity.
For without this unity we should not even possess reason, because we
should have no school for reason, and no cultivation through objects which
afford the materials for its conceptions. But teleological unity is a neces-
sary unity, and founded on the essence of the individual will itself. Hence
this will, which is the condition of the application of this unity in con-
creto, must be so likewise. In this way the transcendental enlargement of
our rational cognition would be, not the cause, but merely the effect of
the practical teleology which pure reason imposes upon us.
Hence, also, we find in the history of human reason that, before the
moral conceptions were sufficiently purified and determined, and before
men had attained to a perception of the systematic unity of ends accord-
456
Immanuel Kant
457
The Critique of Pure Reason
selves in harmony with the general system of ends, and warns us against
the fanaticism, nay, the crime of depriving reason of its legislative author-
ity in the moral conduct of life, for the purpose of directly connecting this
authority with the idea of the Supreme Being. For this would be, not an
immanent, but a transcendent use of moral theology, and, like the tran-
scendent use of mere speculation, would inevitably pervert and frustrate
the ultimate ends of reason.
458
Immanuel Kant
ment, which we have taken for its objective grounds, and thus explain the
deceptive judgement as a phenomenon in our mind, apart altogether from
the objective character of the object, we can then expose the illusion and
need be no longer deceived by it, although, if its subjective cause lies in
our nature, we cannot hope altogether to escape its influence.
I can only maintain, that is, affirm as necessarily valid for every one,
that which produces conviction. Persuasion I may keep for myself, if it is
agreeable to me; but I cannot, and ought not, to attempt to impose it as
binding upon others.
Holding for true, or the subjective validity of a judgement in relation to
conviction (which is, at the same time, objectively valid), has the three
following degrees: opinion, belief, and knowledge. Opinion is a consciously
insufficient judgement, subjectively as well as objectively. Belief is subjec-
tively sufficient, but is recognized as being objectively insufficient. Knowl-
edge is both subjectively and objectively sufficient. Subjective sufficiency
is termed conviction (for myself ); objective sufficiency is termed certainty
(for all). I need not dwell longer on the explanation of such simple con-
ceptions.
I must never venture to be of opinion, without knowing something, at
least, by which my judgement, in itself merely problematical, is brought
into connection with the truth—which connection, although not perfect,
is still something more than an arbitrary fiction. Moreover, the law of
such a connection must be certain. For if, in relation to this law, I have
nothing more than opinion, my judgement is but a play of the imagina-
tion, without the least relation to truth. In the judgements of pure reason,
opinion has no place. For, as they do not rest on empirical grounds and as
the sphere of pure reason is that of necessary truth and a priori cognition,
the principle of connection in it requires universality and necessity, and
consequently perfect certainty—otherwise we should have no guide to
the truth at all. Hence it is absurd to have an opinion in pure mathemat-
ics; we must know, or abstain from forming a judgement altogether. The
case is the same with the maxims of morality. For we must not hazard an
action on the mere opinion that it is allowed, but we must know it to be
so. In the transcendental sphere of reason, on the other hand, the term
opinion is too weak, while the word knowledge is too strong. From the
merely speculative point of view, therefore, we cannot form a judgement
at all. For the subjective grounds of a judgement, such as produce belief,
cannot be admitted in speculative inquiries, inasmuch as they cannot stand
without empirical support and are incapable of being communicated to
others in equal measure.
459
The Critique of Pure Reason
But it is only from the practical point of view that a theoretically insuf-
ficient judgement can be termed belief. Now the practical reference is
either to skill or to morality; to the former, when the end proposed is
arbitrary and accidental, to the latter, when it is absolutely necessary.
If we propose to ourselves any end whatever, the conditions of its at-
tainment are hypothetically necessary. The necessity is subjectively, but
still only comparatively, sufficient, if I am acquainted with no other con-
ditions under which the end can be attained. On the other hand, it is
sufficient, absolutely and for every one, if I know for certain that no one
can be acquainted with any other conditions under which the attainment
of the proposed end would be possible. In the former case my supposi-
tion—my judgement with regard to certain conditions—is a merely acci-
dental belief; in the latter it is a necessary belief. The physician must pur-
sue some course in the case of a patient who is in danger, but is ignorant of
the nature of the disease. He observes the symptoms, and concludes, ac-
cording to the best of his judgement, that it is a case of phthisis. His belief
is, even in his own judgement, only contingent: another man might, per-
haps come nearer the truth. Such a belief, contingent indeed, but still
forming the ground of the actual use of means for the attainment of cer-
tain ends, I term Pragmatical belief.
The usual test, whether that which any one maintains is merely his
persuasion, or his subjective conviction at least, that is, his firm belief, is a
bet. It frequently happens that a man delivers his opinions with so much
boldness and assurance, that he appears to be under no apprehension as to
the possibility of his being in error. The offer of a bet startles him, and
makes him pause. Sometimes it turns out that his persuasion may be val-
ued at a ducat, but not at ten. For he does not hesitate, perhaps, to venture
a ducat, but if it is proposed to stake ten, he immediately becomes aware
of the possibility of his being mistaken—a possibility which has hitherto
escaped his observation. If we imagine to ourselves that we have to stake
the happiness of our whole life on the truth of any proposition, our judge-
ment drops its air of triumph, we take the alarm, and discover the actual
strength of our belief. Thus pragmatical belief has degrees, varying in pro-
portion to the interests at stake.
Now, in cases where we cannot enter upon any course of action in refer-
ence to some object, and where, accordingly, our judgement is purely
theoretical, we can still represent to ourselves, in thought, the possibility
of a course of action, for which we suppose that we have sufficient grounds,
if any means existed of ascertaining the truth of the matter. Thus we find
in purely theoretical judgements an analogon of practical judgements, to
460
Immanuel Kant
which the word belief may properly be applied, and which we may term
doctrinal belief. I should not hesitate to stake my all on the truth of the
proposition-if there were any possibility of bringing it to the test of expe-
rience—that, at least, some one of the planets, which we see, is inhabited.
Hence I say that I have not merely the opinion, but the strong belief, on
the correctness of which I would stake even many of the advantages of life,
that there are inhabitants in other worlds.
Now we must admit that the doctrine of the existence of God belongs
to doctrinal belief. For, although in respect to the theoretical cognition of
the universe I do not require to form any theory which necessarily in-
volves this idea, as the condition of my explanation of the phenomena
which the universe presents, but, on the contrary, am rather bound so to
use my reason as if everything were mere nature, still teleological unity is
so important a condition of the application of my reason to nature, that it
is impossible for me to ignore it—especially since, in addition to these
considerations, abundant examples of it are supplied by experience. But
the sole condition, so far as my knowledge extends, under which this
unity can be my guide in the investigation of nature, is the assumption
that a supreme intelligence has ordered all things according to the wisest
ends. Consequently, the hypothesis of a wise author of the universe is
necessary for my guidance in the investigation of nature—is the condi-
tion under which alone I can fulfil an end which is contingent indeed, but
by no means unimportant. Moreover, since the result of my attempts so
frequently confirms the utility of this assumption, and since nothing deci-
sive can be adduced against it, it follows that it would be saying far too
little to term my judgement, in this case, a mere opinion, and that, even in
this theoretical connection, I may assert that I firmly believe in God. Still,
if we use words strictly, this must not be called a practical, but a doctrinal
belief, which the theology of nature (physico-theology) must also produce
in my mind. In the wisdom of a Supreme Being, and in the shortness of
life, so inadequate to the development of the glorious powers of human
nature, we may find equally sufficient grounds for a doctrinal belief in the
future life of the human soul.
The expression of belief is, in such cases, an expression of modesty from
the objective point of view, but, at the same time, of firm confidence,
from the subjective. If I should venture to term this merely theoretical
judgement even so much as a hypothesis which I am entitled to assume; a
more complete conception, with regard to another world and to the cause
of the world, might then be justly required of me than I am, in reality, able
to give. For, if I assume anything, even as a mere hypothesis, I must, at
461
The Critique of Pure Reason
least, know so much of the properties of such a being as will enable me,
not to form the conception, but to imagine the existence of it. But the
word belief refers only to the guidance which an idea gives me, and to its
subjective influence on the conduct of my reason, which forces me to
hold it fast, though I may not be in a position to give a speculative ac-
count of it.
But mere doctrinal belief is, to some extent, wanting in stability. We
often quit our hold of it, in consequence of the difficulties which occur in
speculation, though in the end we inevitably return to it again.
It is quite otherwise with moral belief. For in this sphere action is abso-
lutely necessary, that is, I must act in obedience to the moral law in all
points. The end is here incontrovertibly established, and there is only one
condition possible, according to the best of my perception, under which
this end can harmonize with all other ends, and so have practical valid-
ity—namely, the existence of a God and of a future world. I know also, to
a certainty, that no one can be acquainted with any other conditions which
conduct to the same unity of ends under the moral law. But since the
moral precept is, at the same time, my maxim (as reason requires that it
should be), I am irresistibly constrained to believe in the existence of God
and in a future life; and I am sure that nothing can make me waver in this
belief, since I should thereby overthrow my moral maxims, the renuncia-
tion of which would render me hateful in my own eyes.
Thus, while all the ambitious attempts of reason to penetrate beyond
the limits of experience end in disappointment, there is still enough left to
satisfy us in a practical point of view. No one, it is true, will be able to
boast that he knows that there is a God and a future life; for, if he knows
this, he is just the man whom I have long wished to find. All knowledge,
regarding an object of mere reason, can be communicated; and I should
thus be enabled to hope that my own knowledge would receive this won-
derful extension, through the instrumentality of his instruction. No, my
conviction is not logical, but moral certainty; and since it rests on subjec-
tive grounds (of the moral sentiment), I must not even say: It is morally
certain that there is a God, etc., but: I am morally certain, that is, my
belief in God and in another world is so interwoven with my moral nature
that I am under as little apprehension of having the former torn from me
as of losing the latter.
The only point in this argument that may appear open to suspicion is
that this rational belief presupposes the existence of moral sentiments. If
we give up this assumption, and take a man who is entirely indifferent
with regard to moral laws, the question which reason proposes, becomes
462
Immanuel Kant
*The human mind (as, I believe, every rational being must of necessity do) takes a
natural interest in morality, although this interest is not undivided, and may not be
practically in preponderance. If you strengthen and increase it, you will find the
reason become docile, more enlightened, and more capable of uniting the specula-
tive interest with the practical. But if you do not take care at the outset, or at least
midway, to make men good, you will never force them into an honest belief.
463
The Critique of Pure Reason
464
Immanuel Kant
465
The Critique of Pure Reason
466
Immanuel Kant
that the same distinction cannot be drawn here as in the case of philo-
sophical cognition. The reason is that the only way of arriving at this
knowledge is through the essential principles of reason, and thus it is al-
ways certain and indisputable; because reason is employed in concreto—
but at the same time a priori—that is, in pure and, therefore, infallible
intuition; and thus all causes of illusion and error are excluded. Of all the
a priori sciences of reason, therefore, mathematics alone can be learned.
Philosophy—unless it be in an historical manner—cannot be learned; we
can at most learn to philosophize.
Philosophy is the system of all philosophical cognition. We must use
this term in an objective sense, if we understand by it the archetype of all
attempts at philosophizing, and the standard by which all subjective phi-
losophies are to be judged. In this sense, philosophy is merely the idea of
a possible science, which does not exist in concreto, but to which we en-
deavour in various ways to approximate, until we have discovered the
right path to pursue—a path overgrown by the errors and illusions of
sense—and the image we have hitherto tried in vain to shape has become
a perfect copy of the great prototype. Until that time, we cannot learn
philosophy—it does not exist; if it does, where is it, who possesses it, and
how shall we know it? We can only learn to philosophize; in other words,
we can only exercise our powers of reasoning in accordance with general
principles, retaining at the same time, the right of investigating the sources
of these principles, of testing, and even of rejecting them.
Until then, our conception of philosophy is only a scholastic concep-
tion—a conception, that is, of a system of cognition which we are trying
to elaborate into a science; all that we at present know being the system-
atic unity of this cognition, and consequently the logical completeness of
the cognition for the desired end. But there is also a cosmical conception
(conceptus cosmicus) of philosophy, which has always formed the true
basis of this term, especially when philosophy was personified and pre-
sented to us in the ideal of a philosopher. In this view philosophy is the
science of the relation of all cognition to the ultimate and essential aims of
human reason (teleologia rationis humanae), and the philosopher is not
merely an artist—who occupies himself with conceptions—but a law-
giver, legislating for human reason. In this sense of the word, it would be
in the highest degree arrogant to assume the title of philosopher, and to
pretend that we had reached the perfection of the prototype which lies in
the idea alone.
The mathematician, the natural philosopher, and the logician—how
far soever the first may have advanced in rational, and the two latter in
467
The Critique of Pure Reason
*By a cosmical conception, I mean one in which all men necessarily take an
interest; the aim of a science must accordingly be determined according to scho-
lastic conceptions, if it is regarded merely as a means to certain arbitrarily pro-
posed ends.
468
Immanuel Kant
469
The Critique of Pure Reason
470
Immanuel Kant
in general, but not to any particular given objects (Ontologia); the latter
has nature for its subject-matter, that is, the sum of given objects—whether
given to the senses, or, if we will, to some other kind of intuition—and is
accordingly physiology, although only rationalis. But the use of the fac-
ulty of reason in this rational mode of regarding nature is either physical
or hyperphysical, or, more properly speaking, immanent or transcendent.
The former relates to nature, in so far as our knowledge regarding it may
be applied in experience (in concreto); the latter to that connection of the
objects of experience, which transcends all experience. Transcendent physi-
ology has, again, an internal and an external connection with its object,
both, however, transcending possible experience; the former is the physi-
ology of nature as a whole, or transcendental cognition of the world, the
latter of the connection of the whole of nature with a being above nature,
or transcendental cognition of God.
Immanent physiology, on the contrary, considers nature as the sum of
all sensuous objects, consequently, as it is presented to us—but still ac-
cording to a priori conditions, for it is under these alone that nature can
be presented to our minds at all. The objects of immanent physiology are
of two kinds: 1. Those of the external senses, or corporeal nature; 2. The
object of the internal sense, the soul, or, in accordance with our funda-
mental conceptions of it, thinking nature. The metaphysics of corporeal
nature is called physics; but, as it must contain only the principles of an a
priori cognition of nature, we must term it rational physics. The meta-
physics of thinking nature is called psychology, and for the same reason is
to be regarded as merely the rational cognition of the soul.
Thus the whole system of metaphysics consists of four principal parts: 1.
Ontology; 2. Rational Physiology; 3. Rational cosmology; and 4. Rational
theology. The second part—that of the rational doctrine of nature—may be
subdivided into two, physica rationalis* and psychologia rationalis.
The fundamental idea of a philosophy of pure reason of necessity dic-
tates this division; it is, therefore, architectonical—in accordance with the
*It must not be supposed that I mean by this appellation what is generally called
physica general is, and which is rather mathematics than a philosophy of nature.
For the metaphysic of nature is completely different from mathematics, nor is it
so rich in results, although it is of great importance as a critical test of the appli-
cation of pure understanding-cognition to nature. For want of its guidance, even
mathematicians, adopting certain common notions-which are, in fact, metaphysi-
cal—have unconsciously crowded their theories of nature with hypotheses, the
fallacy of which becomes evident upon the application of the principles of this
metaphysic, without detriment, however, to the employment of mathematics in
this sphere of cognition.
471
The Critique of Pure Reason
472
Immanuel Kant
Our Critique must have fully convinced the reader that, although meta-
physics cannot form the foundation of religion, it must always be one of
its most important bulwarks, and that human reason, which naturally
pursues a dialectical course, cannot do without this science, which checks
its tendencies towards dialectic and, by elevating reason to a scientific and
clear self-knowledge, prevents the ravages which a lawless speculative rea-
son would infallibly commit in the sphere of morals as well as in that of
religion. We may be sure, therefore, whatever contempt may be thrown
upon metaphysics by those who judge a science not by its own nature, but
according to the accidental effects it may have produced, that it can never
be completely abandoned, that we must always return to it as to a beloved
one who has been for a time estranged, because the questions with which
it is engaged relate to the highest aims of humanity, and reason must
always labour either to attain to settled views in regard to these, or to
destroy those which others have already established.
Metaphysic, therefore—that of nature, as well as that of ethics, but in
an especial manner the criticism which forms the propaedeutic to all the
operations of reason—forms properly that department of knowledge which
may be termed, in the truest sense of the word, philosophy. The path
which it pursues is that of science, which, when it has once been discov-
ered, is never lost, and never misleads. Mathematics, natural science, the
common experience of men, have a high value as means, for the most
part, to accidental ends—but at last also, to those which are necessary and
essential to the existence of humanity. But to guide them to this high goal,
they require the aid of rational cognition on the basis of pure conceptions,
which, be it termed as it may, is properly nothing but metaphysics.
For the same reason, metaphysics forms likewise the completion of the
culture of human reason. In this respect, it is indispensable, setting aside
altogether the influence which it exerts as a science. For its subject-matter
is the elements and highest maxims of reason, which form the basis of the
possibility of some sciences and of the use of all. That, as a purely specu-
lative science, it is more useful in preventing error than in the extension of
knowledge, does not detract from its value; on the contrary, the supreme
office of censor which it occupies assures to it the highest authority and
importance. This office it administers for the purpose of securing order,
harmony, and well-being to science, and of directing its noble and fruitful
labours to the highest possible aim—the happiness of all mankind.
473
The Critique of Pure Reason
This title is placed here merely for the purpose of designating a division of
the system of pure reason of which I do not intend to treat at present. I
shall content myself with casting a cursory glance, from a purely transcen-
dental point of view—that of the nature of pure reason—on the labours
of philosophers up to the present time. They have aimed at erecting an
edifice of philosophy; but to my eye this edifice appears to be in a very
ruinous condition.
It is very remarkable, although naturally it could not have been other-
wise, that, in the infancy of philosophy, the study of the nature of God
and the constitution of a future world formed the commencement, rather
than the conclusion, as we should have it, of the speculative efforts of the
human mind. However rude the religious conceptions generated by the
remains of the old manners and customs of a less cultivated time, the
intelligent classes were not thereby prevented from devoting themselves to
free inquiry into the existence and nature of God; and they easily saw that
there could be no surer way of pleasing the invisible ruler of the world,
and of attaining to happiness in another world at least, than a good and
honest course of life in this. Thus theology and morals formed the two
chief motives, or rather the points of attraction in all abstract inquiries.
But it was the former that especially occupied the attention of speculative
reason, and which afterwards became so celebrated under the name of
metaphysics.
I shall not at present indicate the periods of time at which the greatest
changes in metaphysics took place, but shall merely give a hasty sketch of
the different ideas which occasioned the most important revolutions in
this sphere of thought. There are three different ends in relation to which
these revolutions have taken place.
474
Immanuel Kant
everything else is merely imaginary; the latter, that the senses are the par-
ents of illusion and that truth is to be found in the understanding alone.
The former did not deny to the conceptions of the understanding a cer-
tain kind of reality; but with them it was merely logical, with the others it
was mystical. The former admitted intellectual conceptions, but declared
that sensuous objects alone possessed real existence. The latter maintained
that all real objects were intelligible, and believed that the pure under-
standing possessed a faculty of intuition apart from sense, which, in their
opinion, served only to confuse the ideas of the understanding.
475
The Critique of Pure Reason
Quod sapio satis est mihi, non ego curo Esse quod
Arcesilas aerumnosique Solones.
PERSIUS
— Satirae, iii. 78-79.
is their motto, under which they may lead a pleasant and praiseworthy
life, without troubling themselves with science or troubling science with
them.
As regards those who wish to pursue a scientific method, they have now
the choice of following either the dogmatical or the sceptical, while they
are bound never to desert the systematic mode of procedure. When I
mention, in relation to the former, the celebrated Wolf, and as regards the
latter, David Hume, I may leave, in accordance with my present inten-
tion, all others unnamed. The critical path alone is still open. If my reader
has been kind and patient enough to accompany me on this hitherto
untravelled route, he can now judge whether, if he and others will con-
tribute their exertions towards making this narrow footpath a high road of
thought, that which many centuries have failed to accomplish may not be
executed before the close of the present—namely, to bring Reason to per-
fect contentment in regard to that which has always, but without perma-
nent results, occupied her powers and engaged her ardent desire for knowl-
edge.
476