Teo2009CritPsy PDF
Teo2009CritPsy PDF
Teo2009CritPsy PDF
net/publication/260248407
Teo, T. (2009). Philosophical concerns in critical psychology. In D. Fox, I. Prilleltensky & S. Austin (Eds.), Critical psychology: An introduction (2nd ed.) (pp. 36-53). London: S...
CITATIONS READS
0 834
1 author:
Thomas Teo
York University
146 PUBLICATIONS 1,914 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:
All content following this page was uploaded by Thomas Teo on 19 February 2014.
,,•
Ethical-Political Concerns and Psychology's Praxis 47 ,
•
•
Current Issues for Critical Psychology 50 •
~
,i
I
I
f
An academic field of study is problematic when it does not address, let alone
resolve, basic issues. This has been the case with psychology, which has
excluded or neglected key problems or pretended they do not exist. As
described in this chapter, three interconnected issues make psychology
problematic: (a) a limited understanding of the complexities of psychology's
subject matter and ontology; (b) a preference for a selectively narrow episte-
mology and methodology; and (c) a lack of reflection (critical thinking) on
psychology's ethical-political concerns and praxis.
It would be inaccurate to suggest that these problems reflect only
contemporary concerns. Indeed, from its beginning as an institution and
independent field of study, psychology has had to cope with ongoing
critiques (see Teo, 2005; Woodward & Ash, 1982). One of the most influen-
tial critiques in the eighteenth century was developed by Immanuel Kant,
who argued that the study of the soul- this is what the term psychology origi-
nally meant - could not be natural-scientific because psychology could not
be made into an authentic experimental discipline like physics. Instead, he
recommended that the field limit itself to a description of the soul and focus
on the notion of moral agency, the ability of the person to act intentionally
according to moral principles.
In the nineteenth century, psychology was transformed from a philosophical
discipline into a natural-scientific discipline. Adopting the principles and
methods of the natural sciences meant that mainstream academic psychology
shunted aside genuine psychological topics such as subjectivity - subjective,
personal experiences and the meanings that human beings attribute to these
experiences. This transformation had intellectual, but more importantly,
sociohistorical origins: when psychology emerged as a discipline and was
struggling for academic respect in terms of money, power, and recognition, it
seemed more promising to align itself with the highly successful natural
sciences rather than with the seemingly ambiguous human sciences such as
history (Ward, 2002). Later it was hoped that the natural sciences would
appreciate psychology if the discipline committed itself to ostensibly objec-
tive topics such as behaviour rather than to notions of the soul or human
experience. This sentiment of establishing psychology as a rigorous discipline
was so strong that even Sigmund Freud intended psychoanalysis as a natural
science (see Habermas, 1968/1972).
This attempt to establish psychology as a natural science like physics led to
many critiques and also to what are known as crisis discussions within
psychology. Indeed, the first systematic book on the crisis of psychology was
published by Willy (1899), who challenged the dominant natural-scientific
oriented research programmes of his time. He identified speculative theory-
building and an inadequate methodology as sources of psychology's crisis.
The crisis literature has been on the rise since the 1920-1930s and again
since the 1960s and 1970s (for an overview, see Goertzen, 2005). A critique
of psychology's lack of ethical-political relevance can also be found in the
nineteenth century when Beneke (1845) suggested that psychology could
help overcome political, social, and religious tumults. He challenged
mainstream psychology's focus on theory rather than practice and he
protested that German psychology refused to deal with social reality.
A relevant question in a book on critical psychology is this: Should all
approaches that provide a critical evaluation of psychology's mainstream be
labelled critical psychologies? A general concept of critical psychology would
include all approaches that critique psychology's subject matter, or methodol-
ogy, or praxis, or a combination of these elements. A specific concept of critical
psychology, on the other hand, would include approaches sceptical of the
mainstream that give primacy to the ethical-political dimensions of praxis. I use
the term praxis in contrast to the term practice to emphasize the political nature
of human activity in any applied area. In addition, it should be mentioned that
while some psychologists use the label critical psychology to address their own
psychological position (see Fox and PrilleltenskYI 1997; Hook, 2004; Sloan,
or
Z(J(J(J; Walkerdine, Z(](]Z], others Who are critical the mainstream do not use
the term (e.g., some feminist or social-constructionist psychologists).
Very prominent in, but not limited to, critical psychology are cultural-
historical (Marxist), feminist, social-constructionist, and more recently,
postcolonial critiques. All have fuelled the critical literature on the
In philosophy, the term ontology refers to the study of Being (the study of
the fundamental characteristics of reality). In psychology, ontological studies
address the nature of the psychological 'object': What should psychologists
study? What are the specific and defining characteristics of the psychological
subject matter? Ontological discussions include the proper definition of
psychology, its appropriate subject matter, the models for representing
human mental life, metaphors for understanding human subjectivity, theories
of the human mind, theories of human nature, the relationship between
mind and body, and so on.
It is important to keep the following distinctions in mind: the word psychology
refers to a subject matter, a field of topics, a discipline, and a profession. In
Western history the word psychology has been used to refer to the study of
the soul, consciousness, mental life, behaviour, human experience, the mind,
or the brain, depending on the era and cultural context. Psychological topics
have been studied in the Western tradition since the classical Greeks, for
instance, when Aristotle in his pioneering work On the Soul discussed the
topic memory. However, psychology as an independent academic discipline did
not exist before the nineteenth century, and psychology as a profession became
a social reality only in the twentieth century. The term mainstream psychology
refers to an academic field of study as taught and researched in North
American and European institutions such as universities.
A few key issues regarding mainstream psychology's implicit assumptions
about its subject matter are discussed here. Some psychologists consider that
the most important models in psychology are technological ones and that the
history of psychology parallels the development of technology. For instance,
cognitive psychology's model and metaphors of human mental life are based
on the computer, whereas in earlier eras psychology made use of more basic
mechanical devices (e.g., clocks, steam engines, and radios). Machine models
are embedded within a network of ontological assumptions. One of these
assumptions is that a person reacts towards an external stimulus like a
mechanism; the machine model excludes notions of agency, the ability to
38 CRITICAL OVERVIEWS
reflect, choose, and act. Other models in psychology include animal metaphors
that, from a critical perspective, often neglect an understanding of how human
mental life differs from various forms of animal mental life.
Thus, psychology's mainstream operates with a mechanistic, and hence an
atomistic and reductionistic, model of human mental life. A mechanistic
concept of human action is also apparent in biological traditions such as
behaviourism. Despite a commitment to an evolutionary perspective by
many behaviourists, the machine model is dominant in behaviourism because
it is assumed that the individual responds to stimuli. Dividing psychological
life into stimulus and response (behaviourism) or into independent and
dependent variables (mainstream psychology) is problematic because it
neglects subjectivity, agency, and meaningful reflection and action in concrete
contexts (Holzkamp, 1992; Tolman and Maiers, 1991).
The selection of variables in the context of focusing on isolated aspects of
human mental life (atomism) does not do justice to the integration of human
mental life in concrete individuals. Instead of looking at the complexity of
human life, which is the source of human subjectivity, the mainstream in
psychology assumes that it is sufficient to study small parts. For instance,
cognition is divided further into attention, thinking, and memory. Memory
is divided further into long-term, short-term, etc. It is reductionistic to
assume that the parts sufficiently explain the complexity of human subjec-
tivity; yet, this is another consequence of the machine-model. In reality
human subjectivity is experienced in its totality. From the perspective of the
subject, cognition, emotion, and will (to use a Western division of mental
life) are usually experienced in their connection in concrete life-situations
and not as isolated parts. The idea that studying the parts of a whole is suffi-
cient and that the parts will fit together into a meaningful whole through
additive processes is based on a limited worldview. Parts do not just add up
when it comes to human mental life. Critics have argued that a psychology
that does justice to human subjectivity should begin with the nexus of
human experiences in order to understand the parts and not vice versa
(Martin, Sugarman, & Thompson, 2003).
The machine-model of human mental life has another consequence: because
it conceptualizes the person as individualistic and society as an external
variable, the model sees the individual and society as separate (see also Parker
& Spears, 1996). Seldom do psychologists realize that they base their theories
and research practices regarding the mind on an individualistic concept.
Consider the following: the fact that you speak a particular language, let's say
English, has become part of your self. But of course, if you had been raised in
Denmark with Danish parents, your language would be Danish. The passage
of time also matters: you can produce unique sentences in English, sentences
that have never been expressed before, yet these sentences are only meaning-
ful because they are embedded within a sociohistorical trajectory. Because
language changes, a sentence like 'I am reading a chapter on critical psychol-
ogy that challenges the problematic nature of psychological ideas' would
40 CRITICAL OVERVIEWS
Some hermeneutic oriented psychologists have emphasized the intentional,
dialogical, and active side of a person (Richardson) Rogers, & McCarroll, 1998).
A postcolonial critique begins with the argument that the psychological
subject matter is part of a wider historical and cultural context and the
theories that try to capture this subject matter are part of Western theoriz-
ing. Thus, it must be understood as Western models of human mental life
rather than universal ones (Teo & Febbraro, 2003). The question is how
concepts developed in Europe and North America can be applied meaning-
fully to different cultural contexts. The task for psychologists from other
countries is to find psychological theories} concepts, and practices that work
in their life-worlds rather than importing or exporting American ideas. For
instance, Freire (1970), who emphasized that learners should be treated as
subjects and not as objects, and Martin-Baro (1994), who applied Freirean
ideas to psychology, have developed categories dealing specifically with
psychological issues in Latin America.
Wilhelm Dilthey (1976) divided the sciences into natural and human
sciences. Following his lead, there has been increased discussion of the nature
of concepts to describe humans and human mental life. Danziger (1997), who
emphasized the social construction of psychological ideas and practices,
addressed whether psychological concepts have a different status from
natural-scientific concepts. He called this the difference between natural kinds
and human kinds. Natural kinds are physicat chemical and biological objects
and events and are arguably different from psychological categories: the study
of water or a rock formation is different from the study of IQ} grie£ or 'race'.
Psychologists need to understand that concepts in psychology are
constructed in a specific cultural context for specific purposes. Mainstream
psychologists often pretend that constructed concepts are natural concepts
because they have empirical support. But empirical support says nothing
about the ontological status of a concept. For instance, the fact that a certain
number of individuals identify themselves as British does not mean that being
British is a natural kind variable. Critical investigations emerged from the
historical fact that certain psychological concepts have become a reality in
social practice but their ontological status is completely problematic (for
instance, 'race' or IQ). But these socially constructed concepts have become
a central part of our identity: once the concept of IQ has been established
and you do well on IQ tests} it becomes a part of your psychological self-
understanding. Yet, at the same time psychological concepts such as IQ can
also be understood as sources of power and oppression (see Foucault)
1966/1970; Rose, 1996).
Once a concept has become a cultural phenomenon, it is important to
challenge the cultural familiarity of a specific concept and the socialization
into this concept that makes many psychological ideas seem self-evident
when, in fact, they are culturally embedded. The process of social construction
is easy to understand when relatively new concepts such as emotional intelli-
gence become part of our cultural self-understanding. Critical psychologists also
42 CRITICAL OVERVIEWS
Indeed, traditional psychology is a psychology of variables (Holzkamp, 1991).
From a historical point of view, one can reconstruct a shift from a science that
was interested in the why of psychological phenomena to the exploration of
the functional relationship between variables. For instance, psychologists do
not study the why of unemployment in a person's life, which would include
an analysis of the problem as a sociohistorical issue. Instead mainstream
psychology looks at the relationship between the variable of unemployment
and other variables such as wellbeing, depression, self-esteem, personality,
and so on. This functional relationship is understood in psychology, depend-
ing on the nature of the research design, as causal or correlational.
Typically, within the logic of mainstream psychological research, it has been
suggested that psychologists should formulate hypotheses derived from
theories (they are framed and understood within theoretical arguments); the
hypotheses should be expressed as law-like statements (if- then); theories and
methods should be formalized; hypotheses should be tested using objective,
valid, and reliable observations and measurements; and, based on the results
of hypothesis testing, psychologists can provide deductive-nomological (law-
providing) or statistical models of explanation and prediction. Many
mainstream psychologists consider the experiment to be the best or most
effective means of gaining knowledge in the discipline. Within a quantitative
methodology, psychology has developed a variety of methods (e.g., analysis of
variance, factor analysis, path analysis, etc.).
Yet, as pointed out earlier, psychological topics such as memory can be
studied from a natural-scientific perspective as well as from a human-scientific
perspective. If one looks at memory's physiological basis, its functions, princi-
ples, and divisions, one is not necessarily interested in an individually developed
memory in context, the very content of memory. As clinical psychologists are
well aware, a person's unique memory of past experiences that gives meaning
to a person's identity and action is part of a cultural-historical trajectory and as
such is the topic for a human-scientific perspective. From a disciplinary
perspective one could argue that studying the meaning of memory is as impor-
tant as researching the physiological basis of memory. Yet, the subjective
dimension of human mental life and subjectivity in general have been
neglected in psychology and excluded in the mainstream's ontology and thus
do not find a way back into methodology. Qualitative research that tends to
focus on the content of human subjectivity is still very much marginalized in
mainstream methodology.
Since Kuhn (1962), historians of science have emphasized the difference
between what researchers are supposed to do and what they actually do.
Critics such as Koch (1985) target the idea that psychology provides psycho-
logical laws by arguing that despite the discipline's natural-scientific orientation
for over a hundred years, despite the hundreds of thousands of experiments,
and despite the long accumulation of very technical writings, it would
be difficult to find statements in psychology that could be counted as
natural law in the sense of the natural sciences or in the sense of being
44 CRITICAL OVERVIEWS
the psychological subject matter, which includes the agency of persons
embedded in sociohistorical contexts. Even Wilhelm Wundt, still heralded
as the father of modern experimental psychology, was aware of the exper-
iment's limited value. Thus, he called for a psychology that includes the
sociohistorical context and uses what we would call qualitative methods
(see Danziger, 1990).
An experiment can only capture what goes into the theoretical and
methodological framework. For instance, if I stand up as a participant (or
'subject') in an experiment and suggest that the task demanded of me does
not make sense to me, I am excluded from the data as an error. Thus, my
reaction - based on a legitimate concern - is excluded. The experiment needs
the willing and well-behaved participant, but in social reality, humans can
stand up and change the world, or at least, their life-worlds. This cannot be
captured in an experiment. The experiment uses variables and looks at the
functional (causal) relationship of isolated variables, but in the real world, all
the factors that had been excluded in the experiment emerge and playa role
in human action (Holzkamp, 1972). Thus, psychological studies often do not
have practical relevance, let alone emancipatory relevance, which is a core
issue for many critical psychologies. Emancipatory relevance means that
research should contribute to overturning oppressive social situations.
There is a large literature regarding the critique of mainstream psychology's
identity as a science that supposedly provides universal laws, explanations, and
predictions. In addition, some critics have argued that psychology mistakes
reasons for causes and that empirical hypothesis-testing is not a test but an
application of good reasons (is your decision to study critical psychology
caused or do you have reasons for it?) and that if-then-statements have implica-
tive character (for some of these complex issues, see Smedslund, 1988). The
discussion of mistaking reasons of humans for physical causes points to another
important issue: psychology's hermeneutic deficit (see Teo, 2008). Because the
mainstream excludes hermeneutic methods (methods that emphasize an
understanding of human subjectivity), psychologists are often unaware of the
problems that are related to what assumptions go into the establishment and
interpretation of data. Interpretations impart meaning to data and make results
understandable, for the authors themselves, for peers, and for a general
audience and the mass media. Interpretations allow data to be understood
better than they present themselves. The mainstream rhetoric of psychologi-
cal 'facts' suggests that facts speak for themselves even when those 'facts' or
'empirical knowledge' contain data and interpretations.
This hermeneutic deficit becomes clear in the context of the interpretation
of group differences (e.g., gender or 'race' differences). I suggest that episte-
mological violence is committed when the interpretation of data (not data
themselves) leads to statements that construct marginalized groups as inferior,
restrict the opportunities of marginalized groups, and lead to aversive recom-
mendations for marginalized groups. For instance, if a researcher suggests that
a gender difference in faculty positions at elite universities is due to the lower
46 CRITICAL OVERVIEWS
not exclude the participant's authentic experiences. Obviously, qualitative
methods are preferred within such a framework.
In cultural-historical approaches, when it comes to educational psychol-
Ogyj research on assessment, teaching, and learning has been understood as
holistic. For example, in co-teaching models all stakeholders participate in the
design of a curriculum as well as in the actual teaching practices (see Roth
and Lee, 2007). Such a process provides a grounding of theories in praxis - a
method that has been applied to social workers and other professions.
According to German critical psychology, research should be able to capture
the standpoint of the subject. This means, for instance, that in psychotherapy
research how psychotherapy shapes a person is less interesting than how a
person contributes to his or her own change (Dreier, 2007).
Social-constructionist or postmodern thinkers (the label may be problem-
atic) such as Michel Foucault have inaugurated various methods of discourse
analysis. Critical discourse analysis, a method that focuses on the analysis of
written or spoken language, understands language as a social practice that is
infused with biases. This method operates based on the idea that language is
often embedded in ideological, oppressive, or exploitative practices.
Discourse analysis allows, for example, historical reconstructions of how
the multiple personality was made into an object of academic discussion
(Hacking, 1995) as well as the analysis of very specific discourses such as
racist discourses (Van Dijk, 1993). Foucault (1977) also provided suggestions
for an analysis of non-discursive practices: for instance, an analysis of prison
architecture allows an insight into the workings of power in the context of
human subjectivity and interpersonal relations.
In Martin-Baro's (1994) approach, epistemology is intertwined with critical
praxis. He suggests that psychology must base its knowledge production on the
liberation needs of the oppressed people of Latin America. This means that
knowledge must be generated by learning from the oppressed: research should
look at psychOSOCial processes from the perspective of the dominated; educa-
tional psychology should learn from the perspective of the illiterate; industrial
psychology should begin with the perspective of the unemployed; clinical
psychology should be guided by the perspective of the marginalized. What does
mental health mean from the perspective of someone who lives in a town dump?
Martin-Baro suggests an epistemological change from the powerful to the
oppressed and recommends participatory action research (see below). It must be
mentioned that feminist, sociohistorical, postmodem and postcolonial ideas can
be integrated into a meaningful methodology of the oppressed (Sandoval, 2000).
48 CRITICAL OVERVIEWS
School of critical theory, Max Horkheimer (1992) also pleaded for an end to
the separation of value and research, knowledge and action, and the individ-
ual and society. Instead of denying that values guide research and instead of
hiding interests, Horkheimer specifically laid out values to guide critical
research: an organization of society to meet the needs of the whole commu-
nity and to end social injustice. Critical social research should be gUided
by these ethical-political ideas and should generate knowledge that has
emancipatory relevance.
Two things should be emphasized: mainstream psychology is also guided
by certain values, beginning with the value of value-neutrality; and a lack of
reflection on the values that guide one's research maintains the status quo.
Critical psychologists have analysed psychology's role in maintaining capital-
ism, patriarchy, colonialism, and Western ideology (for instance, see
Weisstein, 1993). In not challenging the mainstream, psychology reinforces
the status quo, which also means performing psychology in the interest of the
powerful. This embeddedness of psychology in the market economy has
made it difficult to promote psychology as an emancipatory science. Even
social psychology, which has a history of contributing to emancipation, has
largely been transformed into a field that produces huge amounts of socially
irrelevant data.
To make this argument about the mainstream's primarily adaptive praxis
more transparent I would like to mention one example from psychotherapy.
A psychologist can work in a therapeutic setting with gays and lesbians to
make their homosexuality (seemingly) disappear. This was considered
adaptive by some people at a particular point in time. On the other hand,
working with such individuals on the transformation of personal attitudes
and societal perspectives, a praxis that may include social action can be
considered emancipatory. Rather than making homosexuality into a problem,
psychotherapy should be about working on problems that homosexuals
encounter in a particular society. An emancipatory praxis does not silence the
needs and concerns of people suffering from societal prejudices.
In terms of alternatives, cultural-historical, Neo-Marxist, and other
critical approaches in the West have acknowledged the primacy of praxis
but have often remained in the comparably safe environment of academia.
Thus, instead of becoming politically active outside the political
mainstream, many critical theorists have suggested that research, if not
emancipatory itself, should at least have an emancipatory intention
(Habermas, 1972). In fact, in critical thought one can find ethical-political
orientations that range from left-liberal progressive to radical. Many ivory
tower critical psychologists also justify theoretical research as a legitimate
option, because the production of knowledge is considered a form of
praxis (as is teaching) that is not inferior to concrete community-based
interventions in the abolition of social injustice.
Although Marxists, feminists, and social constructionists have developed
ideas on the unity of theory and practice, the most obvious consequences
50 CRITICAL OVERVIEWS
globalization for many nations, groups, and individuals, opportunities present
themselves for the theory and praxis of the discipline.
This opportunity can be described as internationalization (see Brock, 2006).
It should be noted that this term connotes two opposing strategies: it could
mean the propagation of Americanized psychology around the world; indeed
internationalization traditionally meant the world-wide distribution of
American psychology (or at best, cross-cultural studies based on a Western
ontology and epistemology). But the term could also mean a move away from
an American to a genuine global psychology. A global postcolonial psychol-
ogy involves a process of assimilation, by which mainstream psychology
incorporates non-Western concepts into the discipline, but more importantl~
a process of accommodation, by which the very nature of psychology changes
based on ideas from around the world. If one assumes that any local psychol-
ogy (including American psychology) could learn from other local perspec-
tives, then an international postcolonial psychology requires more than a
process of incorporation.
The notion of internationalization is based on the idea that Western
psychological concepts are neither universally applicable nor superior to
concepts from other cultural contexts. In addition, Western psychology
should pay attention, for instance, to the classical Indian concept of a fourth
state of consciousness (reaching a non-dualistic, undivided, and unchanging
Self through meditation; see Paranjpe, 1998) or to the concept of ubuntu
(personhood is understood in relationship with others) in South African
,
•
,~
psychology (Mkhize, 2004).
f
··,
.......... :: '. : :
.~~~:~~~.:
;~.:~~~~~~
'.:~~;~':'~~
~~ .. :-:.::
~~:·~tt~
.~
......
.:;~:::;~~~
.. ~ .. :.
ma-In chapter pO·I nls ~.~~~~~:~~: : .. .::-:.~:-:.~:
.. :~~::.~:.~:~ : '., : .
1 The various approaches to critical psychology can be studied along three philo~
sophically distjnctive, but in reality integrated, problem complexes: (a) ontological
discussions include a critique of the subject matter of psychology; (b) epistemo~
logical concerns focus on the methodology of psychology; and (c) ethical-political
frameworks challenge the practice of psychology.
• ethical-political concerns: the dash emphasizes that ethical concerns are also
political concerns and vice versa. In psychology those concerns influence the
praxis of psychology. The term praxis is used in order to emphasize the ethical-
political nature of all psychological practices.
reading suggestions
internet resources /
52 CRITICAL OVERVIEWS
• Marxist Internet Archive: www.marxists.org/index.htm
r
r•
I
~
~·
!I
··,
·
·~
53
View publication stats