Intersubjectivity and Transendental Idea
Intersubjectivity and Transendental Idea
Intersubjectivity and Transendental Idea
INTRODUCTION
This book concerns a claim which occupied Husserl for the last decade of his
problem it raised with regard to intersubjectivity. How, within the idealistic standpoint,
with the difficulties of such acknowledgement, Husserl did not abandon this standpoint.
Rather, he sought their solution by attempting to deepen the sense of the idealism which
he developed. The claim which he tirelessly sought to justify was that the very idealism
which raised such difficulties, when pursued to the end, provided their solution. Without
going into details, we can say that this solution rests upon the notion of a "primal ego" or,
as he also calls it, a "primal subjectivity" or "life." In Eugen Fink's words, this primal
subjectivity is "neither one nor many, neither factual nor essential." It is none of these
because it is the ground of such qualities. As such, it exists as prior to the distinction
exists as the pre-individual ground of the relations between this individual and other
monads.1 Thus, for Husserl, the claim that transcendental idealism can solve on its own
pursues its own method to the end. This method, that of the phenomenological
Notes
2
when we can grasp its notion that we can see how such idealism raises the problem of
Roman Ingarten. As the latter observes, "The controversy between realists and idealists
concerning the existence of the real world, is not about the question of whether the real
world, the material world in particular, exists in general ..." Both camps acknowledge
such existence. The controversy is rather "about the mode of the world's existence and
what its existential relation is to the acts of consciousness in which objects belonging to
the world are cognized" (On the Motives which led Husserl to Transcendental Idealism,
trans. A. Hannibalsson, Phaenomenenologica, No. 64, The Hague, 1975, p. 5). For the
realist, this mode is such that the objects of the world are regarded as having their own
qualities. We, thus, have a dependence of knowing on being. It is, the realist claims,
precisely because an object exists with such and such qualities, that it can be known as
such.2 For the idealist the reverse is the case. To borrow a word from Husserl, the
idealist protests against the realist's "absolutization" of the world (See Ideen I, ed. W.
Biemel, Husseriana III, The Hague, 1950, p. 135). This protest signifies that the world's
existence -- rather than being prior to consciousness in the sense that consciousness
depends upon it in order to know -- is, in fact, an existence posterior to, indeed,
dependent upon consciousness. As Ingarden writes, the protest signifies "that the
existence, which is only 'for' the conscious subject and does not possess its own essence,
Notes
3
is not to be considered as a being 'in itself' which is endowed with its own effective
essence" (On the Motives ..., ed. cit., p. 5). Transcendental idealism, then, is a doctrine
that makes knowing prior to being. Its denial of being in itself is a denial that being by
itself possesses an esence or nature, one which consciousness must seek out as belonging
The above does not mean that the idealist assumes that the entity has no essence,
itself" in the sense of this essence's being inherent -- i.e., designating the type of being
that the object itself is -- and the object's having this essence "by itself." The
controversy between the realist and the idealist involves the latter. As we shall see,
Husserl believes that even in the idealistic standpoint one can maintain that one knows
an object as it is "in itself." His disagreement with the realist concerns the explanation
the object "itself" or in terms of the dependence of the latter on knowing? Husserl opts
To put this position in a somewhat sharper focus, we can note that it involves
Husserl's notion of the presumptiveness of the thing, i.e., the presumptiveness of both its
existence and essence. The notion has as one of its conditions Husserl's characterization
of a thing's givenness. He writes: "... the givenness of the thing is not just givenness
through perspectives, but rather always and necessarily presumptive givenness; and this,
with respect to that point of the present in which the thing is bodily given as existing in
the now and existing in a certain way [i.e., with a certain essence]. Whatever is given
with respect to it could be a false pretention. It depends upon the continuance of the
harmonious perceptions" ("Beilage XIII," Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 398). Now, this
Notes
4
presumptiveness of the givenness to consciousness of the thing does not per se make the
thing itself presumptive. We must add a second condition. This is the doctrine of
transcendental idealism that being depends upon knowing or -- to speak more precisely --
its position that an object's being depends upon its being-given to consciousness. At this
point, we can assert with Husserl that "the being of the world ... exists only as the unity
of the totality of appearances that continue to validate themselves" ("Beilage XIII," Erste
hereafter cited as EP II, ed. R. Boehm, Husserliana VIII, The Hague, 1959, p. 404, italics
added). Indeed, it exists only so long as such validation occurs -- i.e., so long as the
appearances continue to give us the unity we call the world (See EP II, Boehm ed., p.
50).3 For the realist, on the contrary, the presumptiveness of givenness affects neither
the existence nor the essence of the world of things. These, as absolute, are independent
of consciousness. They have, by themselves, their being and their inherent natures. The
presumptiveness of the givenness of the thing is, thus, for the realist only the
attempts to know.
following words. It is, "... how, in the attitude of the reduction, other egos -- egos not as
merely worldly phenomena but as other transcendental egos -- could become positable as
egology" (Cartesianische Meditationen, hereafter cited as CM, ed. S. Strasser, 2nd ed.,
Husserliana I, The Hague, 1963, p. 117). Viewed in isolation, the problem appears to be
one of description. What it requires for its solution seems to be a description of the
Notes
5
longer one of mere description but rather of the nature of the subject being described.
twofold sense. He is such as an object -- i.e., as part of the "merely worldly phenomena"
as they appear to me. Here, like every other spatial-temporal object, he is, in his bodily
presence, the unity of the appearances I have of him. Yet, as a subject -- i.e., as
transcendental -- he is not the unity of appearances which I grasp but rather that of the
appearances which he himself experiences. He is their unity as their center or, as Husserl
puts it, as the "0 point" of their reference. This is the point out of which he himself
posits objects as existing -- i.e., as unities of apperances for himself. Given this
transcendental sense of the Other as a unity of appearances, I cannot reduce his being to
his being known or being given to me. I cannot because he himself is an embodiment of
this priority of knowing to being. The priority, in other words, points to him in his own
knowing and positing. Thus, to posit him as a transcendental unity of appearances, "what
I must obtain is the Other," as Sartre expresses it, "not as I obtain knowledge of him, but
as he obtains knowledge of himself ..." (Being and Nothingness, trans. H. Barnes, New
York: Washington Square Press, 1968, p. 317, italics added). I obtain knowledge of him
unity -- i.e., as a center or, as Husserl also writes, as an "ego pole" of the appearances
Given this distinction and given the fact that we do posit others with apparent
certainty, the question arises concerning the level of being on which such positing occurs.
Notes
6
If, with Husserl, we take up the stance of transcendental idealism, this is not the level of
objective or "transcendent" being. It is not, in other words, the level of the being that is
being known by us. The Other, however, is not just something known by us; he is a
knower. He is not just something standing against a subject; he is the center or the pole
against which things stand. The level of being on which the Other "could become
positable as existing" is, thus, one radically other than that of the objective being whose
absolutization transcendental idealism denies. It is, as we shall see, a level which escapes
from all the characterizations of individuality and plurality which are appropriate to
objective being.
For Husserl, as we cited him, the problem of Others is that of positing their
existence "in the attitude of the reduction." It is only within this attitude that Others can
reduction, their existence is not a legitimate theme for phenomenology. Thus, these
remarks signify that for a phenomenologist, the reduction must be taken as the method
which gives him his "legitimate" access to Others. It is his method of access to the level
of being which is appropriate to them. As such, the "attitude of the reduction" is crucial
to the problem of Others. It is what gives this problem its special phenomenological
significance.
We must, then, examine the reduction's character. Yet, before we consider its
performance and the transcendental idealism which springs from this performance, we
must first inquire into the motivations which form the context for its "attitude". Here,
our questions are: What led Husserl to propose it in the first place? What are the
Notes
7
problems which its performance is intended to solve? Afterwards, we shall have to ask
For Husserl the motivations for performing the reduction are epistemological.
They have to do with the conditions for the possibility of knowledge. In his view, such
conditions must first be secured before we can engage in a metaphysical inquiry into the
nature of being. What we have, then, is the thought that epistemology must take
discipline which follows metaphysics or even coincides with it; on the contrary, it
hereafter referred to as LU, 5th ed., 3 Vols, Tübingen, 1968, I, 224). As he elsewhere
insists: "Epistemology is situated before all empirical theory; it thus precedes all
explanatory sciences of the real -- i.e., physical science on the one hand and psychology
on the other -- and naturally it precedes all metaphysics" (LU, Tüb. ed., II/2, 21). This
precedence is to be taken in the strong sense of the term. It signifies the independence of
epistemology from all other sciences in its examining the conditions for the possibility of
knowledge; it also signifies that such conditions are to be seen as determinative with
We cannot here enter into a complete account of the arguments Husserl gives for
this twofold precedence of epistemology. 4 Let us simply state their main theme: A self-
expressed in terms of the demand that arises once we acknowledge this precendence --
i.e., acknowledge the independence and priority of the epistemological (or knowing)
relation: Such a relation must set its own standards for its validity. Thus, if it involves
standards, such as those for logical consistency, they must be considered as inherently
Notes
8
given with this relation in the sense of their springing from its very nature. This means
that the justification of such standards cannot be externally provided, but rather must be
made in terms of this nature. This demand follows directly from the notion of knowing.
If knowing cannot provide its own standards, it cannot justify them. At this point, it
cannot even justify itself as knowing. It cannot say that when it follows its standards, the
result is knowledge. Given this and given that epistemology is the science of the inherent
nature of the knowing relation, the violation of the precedence of epistemology can be
expressed as follows: It occurs whenever we take some other science and assert that the
relations it studies are external to those of knowing and, in fact, are determinative of
An example Husserl gives will clarify this. The science of evolution studies the
relations involved in the struggle for existence and natural selection. What happens
when we consider such relations as determinative of logical relations, i.e., those which
set the standards for the logical consistency of knowledge? For Husserl, this reversal
standards. As he writes:
That such skepticism is ultimately self-undermining can be seen by the fact that it calls
into question the very theory upon which it is based. Evolution is not just a descriptive
account. It is, concretely regarded, a theory based on logical inference. If the objective
validity of such inference is called into question, then so is the theory itself. To avoid
this fate, the theory must, at least in its own case, assume the independence and priority
of the knowing relationship. It does this whenever it asserts that its arguments and
inferences do reach the things themselves -- and this without regard to the evolutionary
general. It is meant to apply not just to all the particular sciences with regard to their
claims "concerning the possibility of knowledge (its possible validity)," but also to "the
being that is cognized by the sciences" (Idee der Phän., Biemel ed., p. 22). As such, it
applies to metaphysics, defined as "a science of being in an absolute sense" (Ibid., p. 23).
Specifically, this means that such a science cannot make being unknowable; it cannot, if
it wishes to justify itself as knowledge, give being a nature which conflicts with the
possibility of knowing this nature. In this regard, metaphysics is in the same position as
any of the particular sciences. Rather than being considered as independent, it must, to
writes, "This science, which we call metaphysics grows out of a 'critique' of natural
cognition ..." (Ibid.). In other words, instead of being considered as independent, "the
obviously dependent on the success of this science [of epistemology]" (Ibid., p. 34).
apparently contradictory qualities. The reduction begins with the action of "bracketing"
Notes
10
all assertions concerning being. We suspend our judgments with regard to their validity.
But then, "in the attitude of the reduction", we go on to discuss the nature of being and to
lay down standards of what can count for us as being or actual existence. The
phenomenology and epistemology, the above simply follows from their precedence.
over metaphysics means that it cannot presuppose the assertions of the particular sciences
about the nature of being. Such assertions must, therefore, be bracketed. This
determining, epistemology does and indeed must determine the principles of being
emerging from its "'critique' of cognition." A general sense of this determination is given
in the Investigations when Husserl considers the "doubt whether the actual course of the
world, the real structure of the world in itself, could conflict with the forms of thought."
follows because the priority signifies "... that a correlation to perceivability, intuitibility,
meanability and knowability is inseparable from the sense of being in general ..." (LU,
To see more clearly the motivation which leads to the performance of the
Investigations, knowing is taken in the strong, objective sense of the term. This means
that it is understood as reaching the object as it is "in itself" -- i.e., the object in its own
qualities or nature (See LU Tüb. ed., II/1, 90). Now, for Husserl, to deny the priority of
the epistemological relation is to deny the possibility of knowledge in this sense. Such
Notes
11
knowledge, we have seen him argue, is impossible when the epistemological or knowing
relation is taken as posterior -- i.e., as dependent on some other, external relation such as
that of natural selection. Logically, this means that the possibility of objectively valid
such priority, thus, translates itself into the task of securing the possibility of the
This task is one which motivates Husserl's work throughout his career. In the
Logical Investigations, which generally takes a "realist" stance, Husserl writes that his
goal is that of answering "the cardinal question of epistemology, the question of the
objectivity of knowledge." For Husserl, his other questions -- e.g., that of the theoretical
basis of logic and that of the relation of logic to psychology -- "essentially coincide" with
this "cardinal question" (LU, Tüb. ed., I, 8). Given that the task is directed to the
securing of the priority of epistemology, the inquiry here is not so much whether such
knowledge can exist but, more importantly, how it can. It is an inquiry into the
conditions for the possibility of objective knowledge (See LU, "Prologomena," §65-§66).
The same motivation is present when Husserl, through the method of the reduction,
adopts the stance of transcendental idealism. Such idealism does not rule out our
knowing the object as it is in itself, i.e., having objective knowledge in this sense.
Indeed, when Husserl defends his adoption of this stance, he describes his work as the
continuance of his search for the conditions of the possibility of such knowledge. He
writes:
... it simply concerns a motivated path which, starting from the problem of the possibility
of objective knowledge, wins the necessary insight that the very sense of this problem
leads back to the pure ego existing in and for itself, the insight that this ego, as a
presupposition for knowledge of the world, cannot be and cannot remain presupposd as a
worldly being, the insight therefore that this ego must, through the phenomenological
Notes
12
reduction and the epoché with respect to the being-for-me of the world, be brought, to
transcendental purity ("Nachwort," Ideen III, ed. M. Biemel, Husserliana V, The Hague,
1971, p. 150).
concepts of "motivation" and "motivated path" (see The Question of Being in Husserl's
Logical Investigations, Phaenomenologica, No. 81, The Hague, 1981, pp. 3-6). Here, we
can content ourselves with pointing out the salient features of the latter. It is, we can say,
completely satisfactory, the path should naturally come to an end. If, however, the
solution that is proposed is only partial, if, when worked out, it raises new problems with
respect to the original motivation, the path must continue. With this, we must emphasize
that the motivation involves a question and is not, itself, a solution. As such, it
determines the problems that may arise in terms of a solution, but it does not directly
knowable. They thus state the conditions implying the priority of epistemology, the
knowability of being is seen as requiring its division into the categories of real and ideal
-- i.e., into "being as species and being as individual" (LU, Tüb. ed., II/1, 125). To the
former belong all the universal "ideas or species," among which are counted all the
purely formal truths of logic and mathematics. Their being is a-temporal or unchanging
Notes
13
and, hence, is not subject to causal determination. To the latter category belong all
individual temporal beings, including the being of the individual, judging subject (See
Ibid., II/1, 123). The very temporality of real being is taken by Husserl as sufficient to
place it within the nexus of causality.6 From such a division, the following position on
causally determined but not the truth that 2 x 2 = 4" (LU, Tüb. ed., I, 119).
The problem that this solution gives rise to with regard to the guiding motivation
objective truth. Such a consciousness, as Husserl later realized, would think the object,
not as it is "in itself," but as it had been causally determined to think it. This
biological evolution mentioned above. The account of the Investigations is, then, that of
a halfway house. It is one where, as De Boer puts it, "Husserl overcomes the
p. 589). One feature of this shortfall is the fact that in the Investigations, both the real
and the ideal are taken as aspects of objective being. The doctrine of this work is that the
"universal sense of being" is equivalent to "that of object in general" (LU, Tüb. ed., II/1,
125). The subject, however, is not an object, not something "standing against" a knower.
As mentioned above, he is that "against which" objects stand when they are grasped and
known. A subject, then, is a "presupposition for knowledge of the world," since his
being as a knower is required for things to have -- apart from any merely "bodily"
presence things may have to one another -- an epistemological presence which results in
their being known. Otherwise put: It is not as real or ideal that a subject is that-in-
specify him as a knower. Indeed, he is missed entirely by such categories insofar as they
The problem that arises out of the solution of the Investigations is that of finding
a category of being appropriate to the subject, one which accounts for the possibility of
to this difficulty is to consider the subject in terms of a third category of being -- that of
the irreal. Husserl thus writes at the beginning of the Ideen, "It will become evident that
distinction must be made between real being and individual, simply temporal being"
("Einleitung," Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 7). 7 The individual, temporal being which is not
real, but rather irreal, is that of the experiences of consciousness. Irreality has for
Husserl a double significance. It signifies that such experiences are not subject to the
causal determination which characterizes real being. It also signifies that the experiences
of consciousness are outside of the "actual" or real world which defines its entities
through their causal relations. The assertion about the limitation of real being is, thus,
also an assertion "that all transcendentally purified 'experiences' are irrealities placed
outside of all ordering in the 'actual world'" (Ibid.). This means, as Husserl elsewhere
writes:
As such, it loses its sense of being naturally (causally) determined by this spatial-
temporal nature. It becomes, as Husserl says, "the transcendental ego -- i.e., the ego
Notes
15
considered as absolute in itself and as existing for itself 'before' all worldly being which,
itself, first comes to have the status of being within this ego" (Ibid, p. 146).
hence, to the reduction -- has essentially two stages. From the desire to avoid a self-
epistemology. Such insistence transforms itself into the task of securing the possibility
of objective knowledge. From this, there arises the second stage. It occurs once we see
that this possibility is undermined as long as we define the knowing (or subject-object)
relation in terms of the causality which defines real being. There, thus, arises the
motivation, first, to remove the formal objects of our knowledge -- the formal truths of
logic and mathematics -- from the category of real, causally determined being. Such
truths are declared to be ideal, non-temporal objects. When this proves insufficient, the
temporal subject is also removed from the category of real being. Since temporality is
inherent in his nature, he cannot be placed in the category of the ideal. Rather he is taken
entirely out of the division of objective being. He is considered irreal which means that
The nature of this reduction can be seen by looking at the method by which
Husserl makes the subject irreal or non-worldly -- i.e., makes it stand "before" the
objective world as its "presupposition." The method is, as Husserl says, that of the
reduction has two senses. It is "a leading back of every objectively (transcendentally)
consciousness." It is also "the leading back of objective (transcendent) being to the being
Husserls, Riga, 1928, p. 309). In its first sense, it signifies a reduction of our
connections through which the object is given to consciousness. As Celms writes, the
second sense signifies "the denial of any positing of what is reduced" -- i.e., objective,
transcendent being -- "as absolute." It is , positively regarded, "the inclusion of the sense
of the being of the reduced in the sense of being of the basis to which it is reduced" --
such basis being the just mentioned experiences and their connections in consciousness
(Ibid., p. 311). Both senses, as we shall now see, are required by the twofold priority of
epistemology.
Taken in its most general sense, the phenomenological reduction, as its name
objective judgment or -- to be more precise -- the judgment's thesis or claim about such
being. Initially, then, a thesis of judgment -- e.g., the thesis that one is perceiving a
phenomena which form its evidential basis. In this case, the evidence is the presence of
perceptual contents which are perspectivally arranged -- i.e., those contents which show
first one side and then another of the object. Now, the method by which this is
accomplished is, for Husserl, essentially that of suspension or epoché. I suspend the
thesis of my judgment, i.e., my belief in its validity, in order to free myself to regard
The logical reason for this suspension is intimately tied to its epistemological
motivation. Logically, one must perform the epoché in order to avoid the fallacy of the
petitio principii. This means that one cannot include the validity of a thesis as part of the
evidence brought forward for this validity. If one did, one would "beg a principle" and
assume what one was trying to evidentially validate. Thus, to avoid this, one must
Notes
17
suspend one's belief in this validity; one must "bracket," as Husserl says, the claims of
the judgments under consideration. When we universally apply this suspension to all the
claims of the particular sciences about the nature of being, we have satisfied the first of
the demands Husserl makes for the absolute priority of epistemology. Such priority
investigate their epistemological foundations -- i.e., the evidence that gives them their
As opposed to the first sense of the reduction, which implies restraint to the point
of silence with regard to the nature of being, the second does involve a thesis about this
nature. It is that objective or transcendent being -- including the being of the natural,
being, as Husserl writes, is "according to its sense merely intentional being. ... It is a
being that consciousness posits in its experiences ... beyond this, however, it is nothing at
all or, more precisely, for this being a notion of a beyond is a contradictory one" (Ideen I,
Biemel ed., p. 117). In other words, "the existence of nature is only as constituting itself
in the actual connections of consciousness" (Ibid., p. 121). What such assertions signify
is that the being of any existent thing, when reduced to its essential conditions, is only the
being of the experiences and connections of experiences which allow of its positing. The
ontological claim of the second sense of the reduction is, then, "... that the existence
(Dasein) of the thing itself, the object of experience, is inseparably implicit in this system
it would, thus, be unthinkable and obviously a nothing" (EP II, Boehm ed., p. 404).
Notes
18
We can clarify this claim by noting how it involves the irreality of consciousness
in its experiences. According to the above, an object is posited through the connections
such connections. Thus, a real spatial-temporal object is posited when our experiences
are connected so as to form a perspectival series. Its existence necessarily implies the
series which exhibits first one side and then another of an entity. Now as Husserl writes,
"an experience does not thus appear perspectivally" (Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 97). It
cannot since such appearing involves an ordering of experiences and not just an
experience has not the appearing which would allow us to posit it as real or spatial-
objects as their subjects. Here, in fact, we can say that the individual experiences are
"before" all such objects insofar as it is through them or, rather, through their
connections that the ongoing experience of the object, indeed, its very being for us,
becomes possible.
With this, we return to the idealism we initially defined. The reduction, taken in
its second sense, reduces being to being known. The possibility of a being is, in other
words, reduced to that of the connections through which it is experienced and known.
Such a reduction is meant to satisfy the second of the requirements for the absolute
determinative of the nature of being. The determination here is direct: Being is, in its
conditions, reduced to its being-given to consciousness. This means that the experiences
by which we know are, in their connections, determinative of the very being of the
known.
Notes
19
notion implicit in the reduction. It is, in fact, the reverse of our action in performing the
reduction. In the reduction, we move from the founded to the founding -- i.e., to the
phenomena owe their own appearing to the connections occurring between even lower
level phenomena, the reduction can be exercised again. It can be employed on such
lower level phenomena -- i.e., on the belief of their own independent or "original"
givenness -- to uncover an even more primitive, founding layer. Stage by stage, then, the
connections and phenomena. One suspends one's belief in the unconditional or original
givenness of a layer of phenomena. With this, one focuses on the lower level phenomena
and the connections which condition the previous layer's givenness. Now, constitution,
as the reverse of this, is the action of founding. It is the action of connecting phenomena
and of the "positing" belief in the unity that appears through such connections. This
performed. By contrast, the reduction which attempts by analysis to uncover the work of
The hidden, unconscious process which is uncovered is, according to the first
sense of the reduction, that by which we know being. According to the second, it is that
by virtue of which being is. The constitution which the reduction uncovers is, then, the
The claim of rationality made here refers, we can say, to the epistemological motivation
for performing the reduction. This is that of knowing being as it is "in itself." Such
knowledge is, apparently, at once secured if the action by which we know the sense of
being is productive of the being which bears this sense. The objectivity of knowledge
and, hence, the priority of "genuine epistemology" is, in other words, here secured by the
doctrine that "every conceivable sense, every conceivable being, whether the latter be
Does the idealism expressed in these last remarks square with the motives for
performing the reduction? What precisely is the difficulty which it raises with regard
to our acknowledgement of Others? Such questions, as we shall now see, are only
apparently distinct.
As we wrote in discussing the notion of a motivated path, such a path should end
if a solution put forward satisfies its original motivation. If, however, in the working out
of this solution, new problems arise with regard to the original motivation, the path must
continue. Now, the problem that does arise in working out the above solution concerns
the dual character of the knowledge which claims to get the object "in itself." Such
knowledge is knowledge which agrees with the inherent content of the object. Yet it is
also a knowledge whose content is necessarily and universally present in all judgments
Notes
21
concerning the object -- i.e., concerning some well defined feature or aspect of the
object. As Kant points out, these two are logically equivalent. The objective validity of
a content of knowledge (in the sense of its agreement with the object's inherent content)
analytically implies the necessary universality of such content in all valid judgments
concerning the object. One can also reverse this inference. In Kant's words, the first
implies the second "... because when a judgment agrees with the object, all judgments
concerning the object must agree with each other." In other words, insofar as each
judgment states the same thing with regard to the object, each has the same content.
Their agreement with the object is their universal mutual agreement. By parity of
reasoning, the second implies the first, for otherwise, "... there would be no reason why
other judgments would necessarily have to agree with mine, if it were not the unity of the
object to which they all refer and with which they all agree and, for that reason, must
If, with Husserl, we accept this equivalence, we can see how, in Fink's words, we
have formulated "... the objectivity of objects by the character -- if one will -- of
intersubjectivity." The formulation is such "that one cannot establish between objectivity
and intersubjectivity a relationship such that one or the other is prior; rather, objectivity
Alfred Schutz, Collected Papers III, ed. I. Schutz, Phaenomenologica, No. 22, The
Hague, 1966, p. 86). Their co-originality springs from the equivalence of objective and
universal validity and from the fact that the latter, as "validity for everyone," includes the
notion of Others as subjects for whom a given content of judgment is valid. For Husserl,
such co-originality signifies that the objective world is, by definition, an intersubjective
world. He writes: "Considered as objective, the sense of the being of the world and, in
Notes
22
particular, the sense of nature includes ... thereness-for-everyone, thereness as always co-
italics added). What we have, in fact, is an equivalence between the two "worlds," since
for Husserl, the intersubjective world is also an objective world. It is "a world for
What this signifies with regard to satisfying the guiding motivation is readily
apparent. If objectively valid knowledge does imply Others, then the securing of its
possibility must also embrace the possibility of Others. Can transcendental idealism
secure this latter possibility? The question concerns what Husserl calls its "solipsistic
limitation." The thought of such a limitation raises anew the "cardinal question" of the
objectivity of knowledge. The focus of the question is now on the relation between the
individual subject which constitutes (and, hence, knows) and the intersubjective
manuscript:
But the most difficult questions are not considered here: What characterizes subjective
relativity and mathematical objectivity within the solipsistic limitation as opposed to such
relativity and objectivity within intersubjectivity? How does logical universality obtain
its connection to validity for "every judging subject without exception"? Does not also
every "judgment of perception," indeed, every "solipsistic" judgment, have its "logical"
validity? Thus, the problem is that of the origin of the idea of a logic which is valid for
everyone and, hence, that of the idea of a universal science (Ms. B IV 12, p. 10, italics
added).
evidential basis for the validity of my judgments. In the second sense of the reduction, it
is from these that I am understood as positing both the sense and being of the world. The
Notes
23
problem of the "origin" engendered by this is that objective validity, as implying other
knowers, implies as well their experiences and connections. In other words, if, as the
phenomena, then objective validity, as validity both for myself and Others, seems to
include a range of evidence that is not directly available to me. This non-availability is
simply a function of the fact that I cannot see through a fellow subject's eyes; I cannot
directly intuit the phenomena that form the basis of his assertions.
... the objection by which we first let ourselves be guided, the objection against our
phenomenology insofar as it claims to be transcendental philosophy and, thus, claims to
solve the problems of the possibility of objective knowledge. It is that it is incapable of
this, beginning as it does with the transcendental ego of the phenomenological reduction
and being restricted to this ego. Without wishing to admit it, it falls into transcendental
solipsism; and the whole step leading to other subjectivity and to genuine objectivity is
only possible through an unconfessed metaphysics, through a secret adoption of the
Leibnizian tradition (CM, Strasser ed., p. 174).
This "transcendental solipsism" springs from the fact that I can verify through direct
perception only those statements which are true for me -- i.e., those which have a merely
private, subjective validity. To claim more than this, I must apparently make what
phenomena which could directly justify it. Insofar as objective knowledge does imply
Others, the objection Husserl is raising concerns their existence as perceiving subjects.
The objection is that such existence must remain a "metaphysical" assumption for
phenomenology. We can put this in terms of the suspension of belief with which the
reduction necessarily begins. When this is exercised on the claim of knowledge to have
Notes
24
objective validity, we must also bracket its claim to be universally valid. This
necessarily involves a suspension of belief in the existence of Others as having the same
perceptual evidence for an assertion as I myself have. The objection here is that there is
no way to re-establish this belief in terms of direct perceptual evidence. Such evidence
would demand the perception of the Other, not as an embodied subject standing over and
against me, but rather, as indicated above, as an actively functioning subject -- i.e., as the
object "in itself." The reduction, in its second sense, does this by making the known a
relationship between the subject and the world which it knows. Such a world, which
includes everything which stands against itself, becomes the subject's product. Now, by
reflecting on its own acts, the subject may be said to become aware that it is a "producer"
and not a "product." But this reflection only yields itself as a subject. In other words, it
is the only constitutively active subject, the only "transcendental ego" which seems to be
given to itself. Its givenness, then, is that of a solitary self -- a solus ipse. As Husserl
puts this objection: "When I, the meditating ego, reduce myself to my absolute
ipse; and do I not remain such as long as I carry out a consistent self-explication under
the name of phenomenology? Should not a phenomenology, which desired to solve the
us in our first chapter. At present, we may observe that the objection springs from the
what is solipsistically limited to me. If the phenomena and connections I experience are
only my own, then the world constituted out of such is in a private, solipsistic sense only
one tied to the guiding motivation of securing objective knowledge understood in its
twofold sense -- i.e., as agreeing with the object as it is "in itself" and as involving Others
and, hence, universality. The motivation is that of seeing the individuality of the subject
as itself constituted. It is, correspondingly, that of making the reduction reach beyond
this individuality. In Husserl's words, one performs it until one can uncover "my
speak, before there is constituted a world for myself and Others ..." (Ms. C 17 V, p. 30,
1931, italics added). This is a "radically pre-egological" level (See Zur Phänomenologie
der Intersubjectivität, Dritter Teil: 1929-1935, hereafter cited as HA XV, ed. I. Kern,
Husserliana XV, The Hague, 1973, p. 598). On this "original level," as we shall see,
level may be presented by recalling two points. The first is that it is the task of the
reduction to provide us with a method of access to the being appropriate to Others (See
above, p. 5). Secondly, the relation between epistemology and ontology also defines a
task; that of characterizing being such that objectively valid knowledge -- knowledge
involving Others and, hence, universality -- becomes possible (See above, pp. 9-11).
These two tasks, as is apparent from the way we have defined them, coincide. The being
which makes possible objective knowledge in its universal validity must be such as to
Notes
26
permit the access of the ego to Others. The reduction, as uncovering the level of being
appropriate to Others, must, then, uncover the level which permits of objective
knowledge.
Now, the nature of the results the reduction will achieve in accomplishing this
task can be indicated in advance by recalling its character. It is, as we have said, the
reverse of constitution. As for constitution itself, it is, for Husserl, the action of
grounding. In this action, one layer of phenomena grounds (or constitutes) the next
through the connections existing between its members. Implicit in this is a distinction
between the ground and the grounded: the individual phenomena on one level are
distinct from those which they constitute through their connections. An already cited
object and the individual experiences presenting such perspectives. The latter do not
show themselves perspectivally. As such, they have not the same sense of being as the
spatial-temporal object. With this, we can say that the action of grounding that
Fichte's words, "the ground lies, by virtue of the mere thought of the ground, outside of
the grounded." The assertion springs analytically from the notion of a ground. If the
ground had the same nature as the grounded -- if, in other words, it had the same sense of
being as the grounded -- it would not be a ground. It would rather show itself, like the
What this signifies for the results of the reduction should be clear. As the
reverse of the action of constituting objective, individual being, it must ultimately reach a
ground of objective, individual being, a ground which has not the sense of such being.
Here, we can see a further moment of the reduction in its uncovering of the ontological
conditions for the possibility of knowledge. Initially -- i.e., in Ideen I -- such conditions
were seen in terms of the being which was both individual and temporal but not real.
Notes
27
The reduction, pushed to its next step, goes beyond this to the ground of individuality
and temporality. Thus, the position of the late manuscripts is, in Fink's words, that "time
is grounded in a present which creates time and is not itself in time; the division of all
being (into essence and existence) is grounded in a prior unity which is neither 'factual'
nor 'possible,' neither one nor many, neither an instantiation nor a kind; [and] the
plurality of subjects is grounded in a depth of life before all individuation responsible for
selves" ("Die Spätphilosophie Husserls in der Freiburger Zeit." Edmund Husserl, 1859-
The exact nature of this description will be considered by us in the body of our
text. Here, let us apply its general sense to the reduction's task of uncovering the level of
original level of constitution." We can get some sense of what this original level is by
noting that constitution, taken as synthesis, occurs in and through time. Time is that in
which experiences are placed and, hence, connected (or synthesized) so as to form
persisting unities of appearing. For Husserl, this signifies that the fundamental layers of
the constitutive process are those of temporalization (Zeitigung) -- this being the process
by which our experiences are "timed." Such "timing" involves both the placing of
experience in time and the constitution of temporal places for such experiences. In other
words, it involves the constitution of time itself in the before and after of its successive
instants. Thus, the original level of constitution is that of the very beginning of the
temporal process. It is that of the timeless sources of time constitution. For Husserl, this
is also the level where we do have an immediate access to our Others. As he puts this:
"The original source-point of time constitution is, for each individual, the experience of
his present in an original mode and is, as well, the capacity of each to experience
Others ... i.e., the capacity of each, within his own living present, to experience Others in
an original manner and with this, indeed, to experience the original coincidence between
Notes
28
his own and the Other's being" (Ms. C 17 I, 4f, 1931). This assertion of coincidence is
meant quite literally. In moving to the "original sourcepoint" of time, the reduction also
and difficult to understand as it may sound, Husserl's position in these late manuscripts is
that our recognition of Others as Others requires that there be a level on which we exist
requires our having a sense of our identity as well as our difference with regard to them.
Identity is required insofar as genuine recognition demands a sense of the Other, not as
an object standing over and against me, but as a pole or center of experiences. To quote
Sartre again on this point: "What I must attain is the Other, not as I obtain knowledge of
him, but as he obtains knowledge of himself - which is impossible. This would in fact
suppose the internal identification of myself with the Other" (Being and Nothingness, ed.
cit., p. 317). The remark, "which is impossible," points to the requirement for my
difference from the Other. Such difference is required because a simple identity, when
transcendental solipsism. My individual, self-identical ego would be the only ego which
Husserl's response to these two demands is, we can say, that of avoiding their
conflict by meeting each on a different level. The demand for identity is satisfied on the
level of the ground; that for difference, on the level of the grounded. As satisfying both,
the process of our recognition of Others is, then, a move from the grounded to the
has within it the solution to the problem of intersubjectivity it raises. More direclty, it is
to show that the reduction, which raises the problem of transcendental solipsism,
Notes
29
overcomes this problem when pursued to the end. As we shall see, the solution involves
the fact that our sense of the Other as other is, phenomenologically, that of his not being
our "product." It is, positively regarded, a sense of his being a center of constitution,
actively functioning in the ongoing nowness of his being. Reductively analyzed in terms
of its origin in such nowness, this sense of difference reveals its ground in a layer of
original identity. Such identity is not solipsistic since it is prior to the individuality
which would permit the positing of a solus ipse who "produces" his private world. It is,
corresponds to the action of the reduction as it moves from the grounded to its ground,
CHAPTER I
THE ACCOUNT OF THE CARTESIAN MEDITATIONS
Recognition.
egos ... as existing" "within the attitude of the reduction." It is only within this attitude
success for his solution of this problem, Husserl, therefore, must also claim "that at no
point" in his account of the positing of Others "was the transcendental attitude, the
attitude of the transcendental epoché, abandoned ..." (CM, Strasser ed., p. 175). This
epoché is a suspension of belief in a thesis and a regard to the evidence -- the experience
and connections -- which lead to this belief. Recalling the logical point of its
performance, we can say that the attitude of the epoché is abandoned whenever we
assume, as part of the evidence for a thesis, something tantamount to the thesis itself. In
its full sense, the thesis in question is that of the intersubjective world -- the world that
presupposes Others in its being "co-intended" by them. Our position in this chapter is
that, in phenomenologically accounting for Others, Husserl does violate the epoché. His
evaluation of the evidence for positing Others makes use of a principle which assumes
In this regard, we must take note of the two aspects of the problem of
requires for its solution a descriptive analysis of our recognition of the Other in terms of
the how of his givenness. What it demands, in other words, is an account of the evidence
Notes
31
we have for the thesis of the Other. To counter an objection that may be raised against
the position of this chapter, we observe that for some authors the problem embraces only
this descriptive account. As David Carr expresses this: "The task which arises is to
explain how the Other exists for him, not whether the Other exists as such" ("The 'Fifth
Meditation' and Husserl's Cartesianism," PPR, XXXIV, 1973, 19). This view, we can
say, arises by virtue of our ignoring the idealistic context in which this task is set. The
context is that of the transcendental attitude with its epoché. Within this attitude, being is
reduced to being given. This means that the question of the givenness of the Other
becomes the question of the being of the Other. Husserl, thus, writes after claiming not
to have abandoned the transcendental attitude, "... our 'theory' of experiencing Others" is
"... an explication of the sense, 'Others' as it arises from the constitutive productivity of
that experiencing: the sense, 'truly existing Others,' as it arises from the corresponding
acknowledged, is eo ipso the existing Other for me in the transcendental attitude: the
alter ego demonstrated precisely within the experiencing intentionality of my ego" (CM,
trans. D. Carr, The Hague, 1960, p. 148, italics added; Strasser ed., p. 175). Granting
this identification, the question of whether the Other is given to me is tantamount to that
of whether he exists at all for me. In the transcendental attitude, the failure of this
"demonstration" -- i.e., the failure to find within the syntheses of consciousness sufficient
grounds for the positing of Others -- becomes the admission of transcendental solipsism.
We can also say that, in the attitude which reduces existence to its positability through
A further consequence can be drawn from the above: To commit the principio
principii on the descriptive level is also to engage in it on the ontological level. On the
Notes
32
descriptive level, violation of the epoché concerns the givenness of the Other.
Committing it involves my assuming that the Other is already given in analyzing the
evidence for his givenness. Since, within the attitude of the reduction, being is reduced
to being given, the assumption concerns not just the givenness but also the being of the
Other. Thus, in committing it, I "beg a principle" which implicitly assumes that my own
being is already a being-with-Others. This means that in my analysis of the evidence for
the intersubjective world. Inadvertently, the latter, which is the correlate of such Others,
principle, the being of the intersubjective world? What would it take to justify this
principle -- i.e., to phenomenologically ground it? What would such a justification imply
with regard to the being of transcendental subjects? The latter are subjects for whom
being is being given. They constitute the sense and being of the world through "the
accomplishment of knowing." Here, our inquiry concerns the connection between the
ontological principle of the intersubjective world and the nature of the subjects who are
its constitutive origins. The mutual recognition of the latter is implicit in their positing
of their world as intersubjective. Thus, an inquiry into the ontological principle of the
intersubjective world points back to the ontological requirements for mutual recognition.
With this, it serves as a clue to the being of the subjects who are recognized as engaging
in recognition.
consciousness in which objects manifest themselves. Put in terms of its goal, it can be
taken as an attempt to uncover the hidden functioning of the ego, the functioning which
allows Husserl to characterize this last "as a presupposition for knowledge of the
necessary.
former, in fact, is understood as the result of the latter. This means that the character of
Husserl, to be understood as resulting from the constitutive process. This process is one
of synthesis. Its fundamental form, that of "identification," leads to the presence of one
thing in many. Husserl uses the perception of a die to describe its action (CM, Stasser
ed., pp. 79-80). When we perceive the die, its appearances (from one side or the other)
"flow away in their temporal stretches and phrases ..." The fact that, in spite of their
multiplicity and transitoriness, they are nonetheless taken as appearances (as intentional
experiences) of "one and the same die" is the result of a "unity of synthesis." By virtue
of this synthesis, "... the unity of an intentional objectivity becomes constituted as the
same in the multitude of its ways of appearing." Even though we suspend our belief in
the die's transcendent, independent existence, "the one and the same appearing die is
our purposes, the crucial point of this account is the way in which the intentional object
object's objective sense. The object of consciousness, in its self-identity throughout the
flowing of experience, does not come from outside into such flowing; it is rather present
sense. To conceive the intentional object as a sense, we must, then, take the descriptive
experiences point beyond themselves. This they do when they can, in their multitude, be
taken as experiences of some one object (See Ideen I, S36). Insofar as it is the synthetic
act which itself sets up the presence of one thing in many, its result, according to its
greater detail. For the present, we note that this preliminary schema of the functioning of
consciousness gives us, on the subjective (or "noetic") side, the constitutive activity of
From this, the principle inherent in the notion of an "objective" world -- i.e., a world
common world is in principle, then, a world of senses or meanings that are common to
the subjects within it. 3 It is a world of shared meanings, such a world being a correlate
has been carried out and, ideally, could continuously be carried out in a harmonious
and harmonious constitutive systems." It presupposes "a harmony of the monads" -- i.e.,
individual subjects. More precisely expressed, it requires "a harmony in the genesis [of
objective senses] that is occuring in the individuals" (CM, Strasser ed., p. 138).
Intersubjectivity.
The question facing us is whether or not the above can be established without
implicitly presupposing it. Let us recall the special situation in which Husserl is placed
objective consideration of the world involves the suspension of our belief in its
independent existence. The world, along with its objects, becomes reduced to the status
of consciousness. Now, in such a situation, the questions arise: "How do I get out of my
of evidence win objective significance?" (CM, Strasser ed., p. 116). Such significance,
to these questions. The first is the necessity, mentioned above, of not abandoning the
"constituting both sense and actuality of being (Seinswirklichkeit)" (CM, Strasser ed., p.
Notes
36
97). Following this view, one must regard both Others and the resulting objective world
as constituted within one's subjective processes. As Husserl expresses it, one has to say
that "...there are transcendentally constituted in me, the transcendental ego, both other
egos and (as in turn constituted from the resulting transcendental intersubjectivity that
constitutively accrues to me) an objective, common world ..." (CM, Strasser ed., p. 117).
constituted out of data that are constituted on a more primitive level, then these last,
themselves, cannot have this objective sense. To assume that they do is to asume that the
higher level of constitution has already occurred. Recalling that constitution is a process
of grounding, it is to assume that, contrary to their definitions, the ground and grounded
have the same sense. Husserl, thus, asserts that within the more primitive, grounding
level, "... the sense of 'other subjects' that is in question cannot yet be the sense of
objective, worldly existing Others" (CM,, Strasser ed., p. 124). It cannot because this
sense is one that is grounded (or constituted) by its ground and, thus, is not a sense that is
The presence of the data on the constituting level is independent of that which they can
constitute through their connections. The presence of the constituted, however, depends
on the presence of the data which constitute it. Thus, Husserl writes of the constituting
(or grounding) level in relation to the sense of the Other it constitutes: "I clearly cannot
have the Other as experience and, therefore, I cannot have the sense, objective world, as
an experiential sense without having this [first] level in actual experience ..." "The
reverse of this," he adds, "is not the case" (CM, Strasser ed., p. 127). In other words, I
can have, independently, experience on the constituting level -- the level that excludes
the objective world. This first level is composed of "whatever the transcendental ego
Notes
37
constitutes ... as non-other, as uniquely his own (Eigenes) ..." It is, he claims, "within
and by means of this ownness that it ... constitutes the objective world ..." (CM, Strasser
As we indicated, the necessity for this distinction is that of not abandoning the
abandoned the performance of the epoché. If the notion of objectively existing subjects
occurred in the primary level of constitution, then the suspension of such subjects (or of
the world that is their correlate) would be impossible. We would not be able to regard
the ego as non-worldly in an objective sense, since all the primitive senses related to its
notion would involve the sense of the objective world. 4 In such a case we could not
apply the epoché, for intersubjectivity would be a primary category of meaning. It would
be a basic category for the explication of other meanings and, hence, the application of
The second necessity is, of course, the recognition of the other subject as other.
This presupposes, in Husserl's words, "that not all of my own modes of consciousness
belong to the circle of those that are modes of my self-consciousness" (CM, Strasser ed.,
p. 135, italics added). This means that, out of the data of the founding level, "the ego can
form new types of intentionalities ... with a sense of being (Seinssinn) whereby it
completely and totally transcends its own being." Their intended effect, the actual
positing of someone other, is suspended by the epoché that leaves us with the first level.
Yet one can see that what they point to has the sense of something more than "a point of
perceptions is, as we quoted Husserl, immanently present within them. It does not come
to them from "outside." If the Other were constituted in this way, then he would only be
merely be a moment of my own essence, and ultimately he and I would be one and the
same" (CM, Strasser ed., p. 139). This can also be expressed in terms of the different
levels of constitution. Taken by itself, the synthesis of identification gives me the level
of data whose senses pertain to me. On this level, my modes of consciousness are modes
In order, then, to grasp what is really other, a second type of synthesis must
come to the fore. Husserl uses a number of terms to descibe its process:
Appresentation is an intending of the presence of one thing on the basis of the actual
presence of another. Thus, on the basis of the presence of the front side of an object --
e.g., a chair -- I also co-intend what is not immediately present: the back. The back of
the chair can, of course, become originally present. I can walk around so as to view it
from the other side. For Husserl, however, the function of appresentation is not limited
to such examples. It can also occur in cases where I cannot make the co-intended
originally present. This is because the intention to one thing on the basis of the other
does not necessarily require the fulfillment of this intention. Thus, I can co-intend
things, such as the interior of the sun, which I am not in any position to make originally
present. I can also mistakenly co-intend things. What I co-intend is not there. My co-
Pairing is a special case of this process of appresentation. It requires for its basis
two similarly appearing objects. Here, "... two data are intuitively given and ... they
pair." Such constitution means that the sense which is intuitively present in one of them
can serve as a basis for the co-intending of the same sense with regard to the other. As
Husserl expresses this, the thought of one member "awakens" that of the other. There is,
each with the sense of the other" (CM, Strasser ed., p. 142).
Husserl calls pairing a "primal form" of association. We can, under this title,
find innumerable examples of the phenomenon he is describing. For instance, let us say
that we experience a connection between a person's appearance -- his style of dress, etc.
-- and a certain form of behavior. When we encounter another person similarly dressed,
we may "pair" him with the first individual. On the basis of a "unity of similarity," there
then may occur an associative transfer of sense. In harmony with our first example, we
expect the second to behave in a certain way. We can also say that the presence of a
given style of appearance makes us co-intend the presence of the expected behavior.
examples, the transfer of sense can misfire. As we said, there is no necessity in the co-
intended being originally present. Thus, nothing, per se, requires the transferred sense to
our expectations. He does so, however, not to reveal, but to conceal his intended
behavior.
data which are constituted as a pair form the first two members of the proportion. An
objective sense attached to the first of these gives us a third member. As for the fourth
associatively determined by the other three members. Thus, when data are paired
through a recognition of their given similarity, any additional sense that is attributed to
the first is transferred associately to the second. This process goes on more or less
interpretation of the object as possessing a similar sense" (CM, Strasser ed., p. 141).
Let us now consider this process in terms of our recognizing another subject.
The intuitively given data that are paired are my own and the Other's bodily appearing.
They are appearances that are to be considered as constituted on the primary level; that is
to say, they are constituted through the above described synthesis of identification. By
such appearing is understood not just the body as a static phenomenon, but also the body
in action. A third term is given by the sense I have of my ego acting through my body --
i.e., controlling its movements. The body conceived as bearing this objective sense is
understood as an "animate organism (Leib)." As for the fourth term in this proportion,
the Other's ego as controlling his own bodily movements, it is not and cannot be given
immediately to me. The bodily appearance of the Other "... does not prevent us from
admitting that neither the other ego himself, nor his experience -- appearances to him --
nor anything that pertains to his own essence becomes originally given in our experience"
(CM, Strasser ed., p. 139). The other's ego thus stands as an X, as an unknown in our
proportion. This, however, does not prevent the phenomenon of pairing from occurring
and, on this basis, the transfer of the sense "animate organism" to the Other in his bodily
Notes
41
appearing. With this, the Other's ego becomes determined as a subject "like myself" -- as
an ego acting through his body (See CM, Strasser ed., p. 143).
How is this transfer of sense to be confirmed? In the identity synthesis, the sense
appearances, and, thus, is continually regiven. Here, however, we are dealing with a
second level of constitution. Although founded on the first, it gives us the Other as
accessibility to what is not originally accessible" (CM, Strasser ed., p. 144). In Husserl's
doctrine, this means that confirmation continues to be a matter of the founding level, the
level of what is "originally accessible." It occurs, in other words, within the sphere of
ownness, the sphere that establishes the sense of three of the terms of the proportion. It
is, after all, out of the senses of this level that the sense of the Other must be constituted.
Concretely, this means that the "analogizing transfer" of sense continues only so
long as its basis remains intact. This basis is formed by the intuitively given data whose
similarity allows them to be "paired" or associatively linked. Now, in the case of the
recognition of the Other, the original pairing occurs, as we said, between my body and
that of the Other. This means that their appearances -- primarily in the matter of their
"The experienced animate organism of the Other continues to manifest itself as actually
an animate organism solely through its continually harmonious behavior ... The organism
(CM, Straser ed., p. 144). "Harmonious," here, means harmonious with my own
behavior. The Other's actions must "agree" with this in order to establish the similarity
necessary for pairing. As Husserl expresses this, the Other's ego is "determined as thus
governing his body (and, in a familiar way, constantly confirms this) only insofar as the
whole stylistic form of the sensible processes that are primordially perceivable by me
Notes
42
must correspond to what is known in type from my own governing my body" (CM,
Strasser ed., p. 148). This is also the case with the "higher psychical occurrences." They
have "their style of synthetic connections and their form of occurring which can be
The way I verify my recognition of the Other is, then, through the continuing
similarity of our behavior. The behavior that is primordially (or directly) perceived by
transfer to the Other the senses of the psychic determinations that I have directly
governing his body, as having "higher" psychic processes that are comprehensible
through the typical behavioral manifestations which I showed when similar processes
occurred in me. That throughout all of this, I remain the standard of behavior, the
standard for its harmoniousness, is, of course, self-understood. As I can never directly
perceive the Other's ego, it is only through an associative transfer of the senses of my
of the "here" and the "there." As he observes, each of us experiences his body in the
mode of the "here." It is, so to speak, a permanent "zero point" by which we mark off
spatial distances. The Other's body, in contrast, is always experienced in the mode of
world. There is, then, a crucial dissimilarity between the appearing of my own body in
the here and that of the Other in the there. Given that pairing does require similarity, we
must, then, say of the Other: "its manner of appearance is not paired in direct association
Notes
43
with the manner of appearance which my body always actually has (the mode, here)..."
What we have, in fact, is a double pairing. The pairing with the Other's body is
The nature of the latter concerns my ability, via my bodily movement to change any
there into a here. As Husserl writes, "this implies that, perceiving from the there, I
should see the same things, only in correspondingly different modes of appearance such
as would pertain to my being there ..." (CM, Strasser ed., p. 146). That, in fact, we do
also occurs with regard to our own bodies. Tied to the possibility of my movement is the
fact that "my bodily animate organism is interpreted and interpretable as a natural body
existing in space and movable like any other natural body" (Ibid.). Given this, the
presentation of my body in the here contains an implicit appresentation of the same body
"existing in space" at some distance from the here. In Husserl's words, I have the
possibility of appresenting "the way my body would look if I were there." The first
pairing, then, is between my body in the modes of the here and the there. It is with
regard to the body interpreted in the latter mode -- i.e., as there -- that the Other's body
Out of this twofold pairing, Husserl establishes 1) the otherness of the Other and
both 2) the transcendence and 3) the commonness of the world for both of us. Let us
consider these points, one by one. With regard to the first, we may observe that the two
pairings by which I apprehend the Other are distinguishable insofar as the first involves
possibility and the second, actuality. When the Other calls to mind the way I would look
were I there, the basis of this is the possibility I have of changing my position to the
Notes
44
there. The Other, however, is actually experienced as being there. Now, the contents of
the here and there exclude each other. My sphere of ownness is not such that,
maintaining its unity, it can simultaneously present the world from two different
positions. Thus, the fact that the pairing does involve the duality of the here and there,
while I actually remain in the here, means that I must appresent the other ego as other. In
other an actually distinct sphere of ownness. It is the sphere in which the world is
actually -- i.e., presently -- experienced from the there. By virtue of this, we can say
with Husserl, "... my primordial ego, through appresentative apperception, constitutes for
itself another ego which, according to its own nature, never demands or allows
fulfillment through direct perception (CM, Strasser ed., p. 148). It does not, for the
connections (See Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 111). His reference is to the types of
series thus shows the possibility of an indefinite continuance; a view of one side of the
object constantly calls forth the possibility of a view of another side. This means that the
spatial-temporal object, which appears in such a series, itself bears the sense of
Notes
45
something capable of indefinite exhibition. Its sense, in other words, is that of an object
which surpasses or transcends the sum of the actual views which I have already had of it.
and the possible. It is, phenomenologically speaking, the surpassing of the actual by the
possibilities implied by the actual. In the context of the solitary ego, the actual refers to
his given perceptions. It is these, through their perspectival connections, which give the
ego the implicit feeling of the possibility of having further perceptions. Here, the fact
that these are immanently or directly his own perceptions justifies Husserl in speaking of
when we do posit other subjects and posit the object as co-perceived by them, a second,
intersubjective sense of transcendence arises. At this point, as David Carr writes, "The
object is not only irreducible to any particular acts of mine; it is also not reducible to all
possible acts of mine, my whole actual and possible stream of consciousness, because it
is identically the same for Others and their acts as well" ("The Fifth Meditation ...," ed.,
cit., p. 18). This second, "objective" sense of transcendence involves more than the
actuality. It requires the actuality of the Other in his perceptual experiences. The
constitution of this sense of transcendence, thus, depends upon an Other who is actually
other.6 It is a function of granting the Other an actually distinct sphere of ownness. For
Finally, with regard to the commonness of the world (or "nature") for both of us,
this follows according to Husserl from the description of the first pairing. The pairing of
my body in the modes of the here and the there has its basis in my bodily movement.
Notes
46
Such movement, as Husserl writes, experientially presents the same nature "only in
body in the mode of the there, he too must experience "the same nature, but in the mode
of appearance: as if I stood there where the other's body is." This means that in the
appresented Other, "the synthetic systems with all their modes of appearance are the
same ... except that the actual perceptions and ... in part also the actually perceivable
objects are not the same, but rather precisely those that are perceivable from there as they
are perceivable from there" (CM, Strasser ed., p. 152). The reference to the identity of
synthetic systems should call to mind Husserl's goal of describing the constitution of an
resulting from these systems. With his account of the constitution of the other ego (and,
through reduplication of this, of a plurality of other egos), Husserl now assumes that he
inherent difficulty. Even if we grant its descriptions with regard to pairing and the
Nothingness, ed. cit., p. 316). In other words, granting that pairing occurs on the basis of
similarity, the fact that the first term of the pair is a body interpreted as an animate (or a
"psychophysical") organism means that the second term must also be regarded as such.
The appresenting term of the coupling is not my transcendental ego, but my own self-
given life as a psychophysical I ... And what is appresented by this pairing is first the
Notes
47
object in the outer world interpreted as the body of another human being, which as such
indicates the mental life of the Other -- the Other, however, still as a mundane
psychophysical unity within the world, as a fellow man, therefore, and not as a
transcendental ego ("Sartre's theory of the Other Ego," Collected Papers I, ed. M.
constitutive of the Other, the Other that is constituted by this process is not a
ego, the recognition of the Other as an animate organism cannot suffice to establish this
intersubjectivity. The embodied psychological ego, when being transformed into its
transcendental counterpart, "loses that which gives it the value of something real in the
näively experienced, pre-given world; it loses the sense of being a soul of an animate
cit., p. 145). Thus, in establishing the Other simply as an ego of an animate organism,
the process of pairing cannot reach the transcendental community that is Husserl's goal.
The same point can be put in a slightly different fashion. For Husserl, the ego is
not part of the world insofar as it is seen as constituting the world. To view it as
to consider it as constituted. The pairing of two embodied egos is, then, the pairing of
two constituted products. As such, it presupposes the deeper transcendental level which
results in these two. This is the level which first establishes the sense of myself as
worldly --i.e., as capable of motion in space with the accompanying notions of the "here"
and "there." It, thus, is also the level which establishes the sense of the Other as paired to
Notes
48
my worldly being in the "there." Now, to establish, rather than presuppose this level, we
must grasp the two subjects as constituting. What we require, then, is not a "parallelism
Disagreement may be expressed with the above insofar as Husserl does make
reference to the "synthetic systems" of both my own and the Other's ego. His account, he
claims, shows that the Other constitutes as I do and, thus, allows me to take him as a
transcendental ego like myself. A difficulty, however, still remains. It is that this
The senses that are accomplished by this constituting (the sense of nature for me) are also
transferred to the Other. When, in this context, we raise the issue of the legitimacy of
transfer can, apparently, only be validated by itself. In other words, we presuppose the
Let us put this in terms of the epoché. As we have stressed, the epoché applied
to a thesis requires a suspension of belief in the thesis. Thus, the thesis cannot be
assumed in evaluating the evidence for it. Now, taken in its full sense, the thesis in
question is that of the intersubjective world. Subjectively viewed, the thesis is that of a
a harmony of the senses generated by such systems. It, thus, appears as the thesis of
the world of shared senses or meanings. To establish this thesis, I must, then, establish
1) that there is someone else besides my "primordial" ego. I must further establish 2)
that this Other constitutes as I do and, hence, that we share the meanings of the world
generated by this constitution. Having performed the epoché, I cannot, therefore, make
Notes
49
use of these theses. In other words, in evaluating the evidence which is supposed to
establish them, I must keep open the possibility, first of all, that there is no Other. I
must also keep open the possibility that such an Other, if he exists, does not constitute
the way I do and, hence, does not share meanings with me.
For Husserl, as we have seen, it is through behavior that both theses are verified.
Thus, with respect to the first thesis, it is through behavior that is harmonious with my
own that I posit and constantly reconfirm my positing of the Other as an embodied
subject. A break in this harmony results in the dissolution of this positing. As Husserl
expresses this, "The experienced animate organism (Leib) of another continues to prove
itself as actually an animate organism solely in its changing but incessantly harmonious
is something discordant about its behavior" (CM, Strasser ed., p. 114). The continual
harmony of our behavior also results in my positing and reconfirmation of the Other as a
transcendental subject like myself. It is what gives me the constantly reconfirmed sense
of the Other as constituting as I do the objective sense of the world. It does this by
allowing me to pair the Other with myself in the "there" and to take him as experiencing
"the same nature, but in the mode of experience: as if I stood there where the other's
body is." Harmonious behavior thus permits the associative transfer to the Other in the
there of what I can primordially experience in my own case: the unchanging nature of
the constitutive system with regard to the here and the there. Granting this, we can say
that our positing of Others as embodied like ourselves and as constituting as we do both
have their evidential basis in the harmony of our behavior. With regard to the second,
harmonious behavior.
Can such verification proceed without assuming that I and the Other do share
meanings? Does it leave open the possibility of a negative result? This last would be the
Notes
50
admission that there is a possible Other who is other in a transcendental sense -- i.e., who
constitutes differently from myself. It is easy to see that this admission cannot be made.
According to the above, the Other who is positable must, first of all, be an embodied
subject. Yet the evidence for the Other as embodied -- i.e., as an "animate organism" --
is the same as the evidence for his constituting like myself. Given that disharmonious
behavior results in denial of the embodied Other, the only subjects I can posit on the
the epoché. It indicates that in positing the Other, I must already assume that we share
meanings. To make this explicit, let us note that an Other for whom the world had an
entirely different meaning and who acted accordingly would not have a behavior
harmonious with mine. Thus, he would not be recognized as a subject by me. This
means that only the behavior that is in accord with the meanings which I give to the
world counts as harmonious with my own and, thus, counts as evidence for the positing
of the Other as a subject. Such positing must, then, assume from the beginning a sharing
intentional behavior -- i.e., the behavior indicative of the presence of actual subjects as
intentional objects. Such objects, we have seen, are present to consciousness as objective
senses, senses which themselves are regarded as the accomplishments of the syntheses of
certain light. They are interpreted as having a certain meaning, a meaning which
behavior that is harmonious with mine must be defined as behavior in accord with the
meanings which I would give to a similar situation. Granting this, we can say that the
Notes
51
that the meanings which result from this system and prompt his behavior are already
shared by us. We can also say that such evidence presupposes a transfer of sense to the
Other from the intentional context of my actions. This follows since such senses serve as
standards for my evaluation of the harmoniousness of his behavior and, on this basis,
If the above is correct, then the transfer of sense -- or, equivalently, the world of
shared meanings established by this transfer -- is not something whose legitimacy can
his behavior. The circularity, then, of Husserl's explication is clear: its criterion for
the sharing of meanings is the harmoniousness of behavior; its criterion for this last is
the sharing of meanings. Now, the world of shared meanings is the underlying
principle. One can also say that Husserl commits a petitio principii -- the very thing
which the epoché was designed to avoid -- when he uses behavioral evidence to verify
We can deepen our understanding of this criticism by moving beyond the sense of
the reduction as an epoché to a consideration of its second sense. This sense, as Celms
writes, is a "leading back of the conditioned to its conditions" (Der Phän. Id. Husserls,
Notes
52
ed. cit., p. 310). The conditioned is composed of the being which is transcendent to
existing within a spatial-temporal world. As for the conditions, these are composed of
the experiences and connections of consciousness. The relation of the two -- as the
have being only insofar as the conditions have being. This means, negatively, that the
conditioned cannot exist on its own. Positively, it signifies that the reduction is to be
regarded as the inclusion of the sense of being of what is reduced (i.e., the conditioned)
in the sense of the being of the conditions to which it has been reduced. Taken in this
sense, the reduction is, thus, an ontological shift. It no longer concerns itself just with
explain how the subjective functioning of the ego makes it a "presupposition" for
knowing. In the second sense of the reduction, this functioning becomes understood as
Closely tied with the move from the first to the second sense of the reduction is a
structures of conscious life, inquiry into sediments in respect of their history, tracing
back all cogitata to intentional operations of the on-going conscious life. ... But
structures, from an explanation of the sense of being, into the foundation of the
The relation of this change to that of the meaning of the reduction follows from a
point we earlier made: for Husserl, constitution is the reverse of the process of the
reduction. What the reduction does is uncover layer by layer the constitutive process.
Thus, the claim that the reduction uncovers the independent conditions for the being of
This latter claim can be made concrete by considering three different ways of
constitution -- that is, to a different sense of itself which is constituted by its own
functioning. The first is the view that natural science takes of the subject. The subject
world in both its conceptions and behavior. The second way of viewing the subject is
brought about by the first sense of the reduction which suspends the above. It does so,
we have stressed, in order to inquire into the experiences and acts by which the first
view is affirmed. On this second level, the ego is viewed as a center of acts and
intentions. Its relation to the world is one where the ego acts to interpret the sensuous
data it receives from the world. Now, this view can be so interpreted that it approaches
the Kantian position. For Kant, rather than being considered as passively determined
by the world, the subject's conceptions of the world -- including those of its spatial and
temporal features -- are regarded as almost totally the result of its own activity. We
say "almost totally" since the externally existing "things in themselves" act to provide
consciousness with a "transcendental affection" -- i.e., with "data." Out of such data,
objective sense of the world. This sense, rather than being revelatory of the world "in
itself" points back to the activity and categories of consciousness. In itself, i.e., in its
The relation of the third to the second view of consciousness is the same as that of
the latter to the first. It is brought out by suspending the second and explaining it in
move from this level is that from the grounded to its ground. This means that the
elements of the ground cannot have the characteristics of the level which they ground.
Consciousness on this third level thus loses its inner-worldly or receptive character.
writes, "is not a Kantian idealism which believes it can keep open, at least as a limiting
concept, the possiblity of a world of things in themselves ..." (CM, Strasser ed., p.
118). It is, in other words, unconcerned with "inferences leading from a supposed
itself ..." (Ibid.) This implies, with regard to the supposed receptivity of consciousness
to such entities, that it is, as Husserl says, "not an idealism which seeks to derive a
of consciousness which first gives constitution the character of creation. 7 It does this,
understood in the most basic sense of perceptual presence in the now, becomes
taken not just as embracing the constitution of sense, but also as embracing, in its
signifies that consciousness is productive or creative of the very data which, on the
second level, were assumed to be externally given to it. Thus, in opposition to the
view that limits constitution to the function of interpreting given sense data, here we
must maintain that "the appearing thing becomes constituted because in the original
Zeitbeusstseins, hereafter cited as Ph. d. i. Z., ed. R. Boehm, Husseriana X, The Hague,
1966, p. 92).9
noting the following: If consciousness is the independent origin of the data which
compose its experiences, it is also the independent (or creative) origin of the positing
which results from such experiences. Now, within the transcendental attitude, being is
reduced to such positing. If the object can be adequately posited -- i.e., adequately
grasped in terms of the synthesis of our experiences -- then, as Husserl says, "... eo ipso
the object is truly existent -- wahrhaft seiend" (Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 349). Thus, if it
is the independent origin of its positing, it is also the independent (or creative) origin of
Husserl does not shrink from applying this doctrine to consciousness itself
considered in our first and second ways of viewing it. Its being on the levels
second level, it is taken as receptive, as an entity within the world subject to the
"transcendent affections" it receives from the things in themselves. Yet, on the deeper
level, it is not receptive. The view from this level, as Husserl writes, "yields the fact
Notes
56
that every affection springs from already constituted unities ..." (Ms. C 10 V, 1931).
Correspondingly, the ego which is affected is, as pertaining to the second level, an
already constituted one. In Husserl's words, "The ego which has recourse to affection
is always already constituted as an identical 'lasting and streaming' ego 'for' its world
which is already totally constituted for it" (Ibid.). We can understand this last remark
data," i.e., as the basic "units of sensation," are themselves constituted. Our ignorance
of this fact when we remain on the second level, leads us to suppose that such
affections are externally provided. With this, we posit things in themselves. They are
virtue of such positing, consciousness acts to posit itself within the world. In other
words, it independently constitutes itself as an entity among entities, both affecting and
being affected by such things in themselves. Once the receptive ego has been
constituted, we have the possibility of a further constitution -- one that results in our
first view of consciousness. This is the constitution accomplished by the acts and
intentions of the receptive ego which results in the positing of the world which is
explicated by modern science. Here, as we said, the ego is posited as passive. Its
nature that is posited on this level. As passive, what Husserl calls its "self-
That such self-externalization does not occur on the most original level of
is the independent or creative source of both the data of its experiences and what is
implicitly containing both. We can put this in terms of Celm's assertion that the
Notes
57
reduction to this third, most primitive level is actually "the inclusion of the sense of
being of the reduced in the sense of being of the basis to which it is reduced" (Der
Phän. Id. Hus., ed. cit, p. 311). This does not mean that the sense of the constitutively
constitutive process -- includes both the positing and the posited (the constituting and
the constituted) being. It includes, in other words, all the levels of its own being as
well as those of the world's being which are correlated to these. It is on the basis of
consciousness ... conceals in itself all worldly transcendencies ... constituting them in
itself ..." (Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 119). Given that such constitution involves not just
the transcendent but also the immanent -- i.e., the sensuous experiences of
consciousness -- this signifies that "every conceivable sense, every conceivable being,
whether the latter be called immanent or transcendent, falls within the realm of
transcendental subjectivity as that which constitutes sense and being" (CM, Strasser
ed., p. 118, italics added). The same understanding, we may also note, is what gives
both the context and the urgency to what Husserl called the "Humean problem." This
is "the problem of the world in the deepest and most ultimate sense, the problem of a
world whose being is being from subjective performances, and this with such evidence
that another world is not thinkable at all ..." (Die Krisis der europaeischen
What is the notion of being that underlies these last assertions? An answer can be
found by returning to the passage where Husserl calls what is constituted a product or
Notes
58
inferences which lead from a supposed immanence to a supposed transcendence ... has
plain terms, this passage asserts that being itself is a product of knowing; it is an
creation, a crucial change in the notion of sense must occur. Creation, understood in a
radical manner, is an ontological affair; it refers to being. The inference, then, is that
the sense, which is this accomplishment, is itself to be taken as the "being itself." To
reverse this, we can say that the ontological basis of the above assertions is an
constituted sense.
The Husserlian texts for this understanding are often quite explicit. He writes, for
example, "All real unities are unities of sense. ... Reality and world are simply titles
for certain valid unities of sense essentially related to certain specific connections of
validity" (Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 134). Such texts lead De Boer to write:
Notes
59
In psychology, sense is the result of an abstraction, of an abandonment of the
supposedly independent existence of the external world. It concerns a limitation to
what is phenomenal because the "actual" thing is seen as unreachable. In
transcendental phenomenology, however, sense is being itself. At the end of the
Fundamentalbetractung, when it is said that the world can only exist as a sense or
phenomenon, with this is understood the world's very mode of being
("Zusammenfassung," op. cit., p. 597).10
being. It is not the "being itself," but rather something which requires the action of the
latter on consciousness. It is what consciousness "lifts off" or abstracts from the being
as the latter affects it. Its ontological status is, in other words, that of the sense of the
being, the phenomenal appearance of some reality. It has not the status of the "real
unity" itself. Let us put this in terms of the Kantian "psychology" referred to by De
Boer. Here, the positing of things in themselves results in a total abstraction of sense
from being. The "actual thing" for Kant is unknowable. Its connection with
consciousness "makes sense" of acording to its own categories. Now, the Husserlian
equation of being with sense immediately rules out any notion of being which is
distinct from sense. It, thus, rules out the notion of the Kantian Ding-an-sich, which is
consciousness could grasp. To reverse this, we can also say that the denial of an
independently existing thing in itself immediately collapses being and sense. The
denial signifies that there is no being beyond sense to which this latter could refer.
The above holds generally for all positions which see constituted sense as an
abstraction from being. The distinction of such sense from being rests on the notion of
the dependence of consciousness in its sense giving function. As long as this function is
taken as requring an externally provided material, the senses it constitutes point beyond
themselves. They are taken as referring to entities whose "transcendental affection" was
necessary for their formation. The result is that sense is conceived, not as the "being
itself," but as a dependent expression of such being. It is taken as the appearance of the
latter. To eliminate this position, we must eliminate its basis. This means that the
consciousness. At this point, consciousness becomes the independent origin of all the
senses it can grasp. It becomes absolute in its sense giving function. Insofar as such
such senses, becomes understood as constituting being. Otherwise put: its sense giving
function -- rather than being considered an abstraction from being -- is seen as creative of
the latter.
when Husserl writes, "... the world itself has the whole of its being as a certain 'sense,'
one which presupposes absolute consciousness as the field of sense giving" (Ideen I,
Biemel ed., p. 135). The former, Husserl adds, is "dependent," the latter (absolute
consciousness) is "independent." What does this signify? Given the equation between
constituting sense and constituting being, the notion of creation seems unavoidable. As
De Boer writes, "The expressions 'creation' and 'production' do not appear in Ideen I;
discourse about being, then the terms which Husserl does use -- 'independence' and
'dependence' -- exactly express what he means. At that point there can be no more talk
Notes
61
cit., p. 598).
We can fill out this picture by noting two further positions it involves. The first
itself," only if can, indeed, constitutes all possible worldly beings -- i.e., all possible
senses of the world. The inclusivity of consciousness with regard to such beings (or
true being as something that stands outside of the universe of possible consciousness ...
outside is precisely nonsense" (CM, Strasser ed., p. 117). Besides the implicit equation
of sense and "true being," what is striking here is the assertion that consciousness is
"the universe of possible sense." It is because every sense per se is to be found within
function. Husserl writes in this regard: "The positing of unities of sense [real, existent
unities] ... presupposes sense giving consciousness which, on its side, is absolute and
does not exist through sense bestowed on it from another source" (Ideen I, Biemel ed.,
p. 134). The reason why consciousness does not exist through some external sense
bestowal is that it is the original generator of sense. Sense is here conceived as a "one
in many" whose material -- i.e., the "many" -- is formed out of the immanent
insofar as it is only within consciousness that the experiences and connections can be
found which result in sense. This is why the place of sense is within consciousness
The problems this doctrine raises for the constitution of Others are enormous.
Their general tenor can be indicated by recalling that for Husserl the Other must first
the evidence for both positings is the same. Now, as embodied, the Other is a "worldly
the Other is not a sense per se. He may indeed be called the place of sense, "the
universe of possible sense." But this is because he is the ground of sense. It is only
within him that one finds those experiences and connections which result in sense.
This is why Husserl calls the transcendental subject "absolute," and asserts that he
"does not exist through sense bestowal from some other source." Given this, he cannot
that the embodied ego I confront is too much my product to be really other. As for the
efforts at sense constitution. Thus, we cannot follow Husserl and say that the evidence
for both the embodied and the transcendental ego is the same. We also cannot say,
without lapsing into solipsism, that it is "the sense, 'truly existing Others'," which "is eo
ipso the existing Other for me in the transcendental attitude" (italics added, see above,
p. 30). If the constitution of sense is the constitution of being, then this "existing
We can express the above in terms of the demand for the constitution of the
actuality of the Other. The demand arises from the original project of securing the
Others as co-perceivers of the world. It, thus, implies the transcendence of the world
Notes
63
we indicated, the Other in the actuality of his sphere of ownness. We require him
actually being there, while I am here, co-perceiving the world so as to give it its
intersubjectively established sense. Now, such an actuality is not that of the Other as a
constituted sense. Qua constituted, he is the result of my acts of perception. For the
constituted. For this, however, I require the Other, not as a constituted sense, but
It is easy to see that the constitution which begins with the Other as embodied
cannot satisfy this demand. As Schutz remarks, even if we accept all of Husserl's
transcendental We, is ever established. On the contrary, each transcendental ego has
now constituted for himself, as to its being and sense, his world and in it all other
subjects including myself; but he has constituted them just for himself and not for all
Husserl," op. cit., p. 76). This view follows insofar as the constitution which does
begin with the embodied Other is not a genuine reaching out to the Other as
individual. To make this explicit, we note that the pairing that forms the basis for such
constitution is one between two worldly transcendencies. It begins with the pairing of
my own and the Other's body. Now, for Husserl, the transcendental subject "conceals
in itself all worldly transcendencies ... constituting them in itself." Both bodies, then,
within its sphere of ownness as real unities -- i.e., unities of sense. Thus, the original
pairing is between two constituted products, products which point back to a single
Notes
64
constituting subject. This implies that, proceeding from this basis, both this subject's
sense of his own and his sense of the Other's body as animate and human spring
directly from himself. That this is, in fact, the case can be gathered from Husserl's
assertion that it is through an "analogous transfer of sense" that the Other is constituted
as human. In such a transfer, the senses which do pertain to the primordial ego (in his
subject. The Other, therefore, must appear via the transfer as a self-externalization of
The same point can be made by observing that three of the four terms involved in
bodily appearing of the Other, and 3) my own sense of self as governing my body. As
determine the value of the fourth. The fourth element, the Other as subject of his body,
has a value expressable only in terms of the three. Since the three are senses valid for
myself (and not for Others as they have not yet been constituted), the Other, here, is
only for myself. The same point follows in the reduplication of this process which
creates a plurality of Others for me. Insofar as I do not consider them as independently
constituting -- but rather transfer to them my own processes -- the being and sense of
the world that is their correlate seems to keep the status of something constituted for
myself alone.
such a world must be presupposed. The sense of this embodied Other as constituting --
if such a sense be granted -- occurs only by transfer from the original primordial ego.
To the point, however, that a transcendental ego seeks to confront another ego as
Notes
65
genuinely transcendental (as independently sense giving), all basis for this
presupposition escapes us. In the latter case, our acts of sense giving could be
understood as concealing, rather than as revealing, the Other's actual sense bestowing
acts. In the former case, the problem does not arise, but only because we do not
present the Other as actually like ourselves -- i.e., as independently sense bestowing.
"absolute" in its sense giving function. It is, when regarded on the primitive level of its
constitutive process, totally active. This action results, as we said, in the production of
the very data required for sense constitution. Thus, given that such constitution does
externalization of the constituting self. With this, we can see why, on the descriptive
level, the Other can only appear through a transfer of sense from the primordial ego.
The description, we can say, has been shaped by Husserl's desire to make it conform
with his idealistic doctrine. The necessity imposed by such doctrine is apparent.
Given its position that the ego's sense of being affected results from its own activity of
positing itself in the world, the Other that it finds in this world must be a result (via a
What this implies is that the petitio principii on the descriptive level is essentially
tied to the notion of consciousness as creative in its functioning. To the point that it is
absolute in its sense giving function. It is independent. Everything else derives its
sense from its acts. It thus has by definition an asymmetrical relation to all that
appears to be other than itself. In such a context, it is obvious that a world of shared
meanings cannot be a matter of demonstration. That everything has only the meaning
that the primordial ego gives to it is presupposed in the understanding of its acts of
sense giving as independent or creative. Thus, one cannot, without circularity, proceed
Notes
66
to establish from such given senses the sharing of senses by the ego and its Other; for
these senses cannot here count as unbiased or "objective" sources of evidence with
§12. The Petitio Principii and the Level Required for Intersubjective Recogntion.
What is the "transcendental clue" which appears in the above? What does the last
section's impasse reveal about the nature of being, i.e., its nature as presupposed by
intersubjective recognition? To answer such questions, let us first recall what we said
at the beginning of this chapter: it is the reduction of being to being given which
moves the petitio principii from the descriptive to the ontological level. On the
descriptive level, the petitio is the presupposing (rather than establishing) of the
givenness of the Other. The reduction of being to givenness is what makes this a
presupposition of the being of Others. Now, a regard to our previous sections reveals
what is involved in our reducing being to its givenness. Its principle is Husserl's
equation of being with sense. The equation signifies that sense is no longer to be
data. What we have, then, is the denial of any independent "giver" (or being) in our
thought of givenness. Indeed, the equation of being and sense signifies that the "being
itself" is to be considered as the result rather than a cause of such givenness. It is the
sense which is constituted out of the experiences and connections of this givenness. It,
thus, can be reduced to the latter -- i.e., to its being given -- as the conditioned can be
reduction considered as "the leading back of objective (transcendent) being to the being
The very same equivalence, we may also observe, is what shows the ontological
equivalent to being, then what this recognition presupposes is the transcendental notion
of the being of the intersubjective world. We say "transcendental," since in the attitude
however, is implicit in the equation of being with sense. Granting this, we can say that
the world of shared senses is the ontological principle of the intersubjective world. It
is "hidden" insofar as we do not make explicit the above understanding, i.e., see how it
implies the equation of being and sense. It also may be called "hidden" insofar as we
do not recognize such a world as a presupposition. Here, we attempt to derive it, while
presupposing it, and, thus, wind up with the circularity of the principio principii.
Let us turn to the constituting subject, the subject for whom being is being given.
The equation of sense and being underlying this characterization has the following
implications: As we have seen, the constituting subject, at its most basic level, is not a
sense but a ground of sense. If objective being is equivalent to sense, such a subject
considered as a ground of such entities. This means that the level at which we
ground. It has to allow us an access to the Other, not as a sense -- i.e., as a "real unity"
indicate the most striking characteristic of this level, let us recall that the transcendental
outside." This implies that the level where we do recognize him as an ultimate ground
How is the approach to this level, the level of the "inside" of the Other possible?
Contrary to the position of the Cartesian Meditations, the approach cannot be through
the process of constituing the Other. Two objections stand in the way of this view.
The first is that constitution is a process that results in sense. Yet the actuality of the
Other which is required for Husserl's purposes is, as indicated, not that of a sense, but
that of a constituter of sense. What is required, in other words, is the givenness of those
experiences and connections which result for him in sense. The second objection
concerns the fact that constitution, transcendentally viewed, is the process of the self-
including the being of the human subject -- which are taken as having external relations
to one another. The result, in other words, is the positing of beings which are
Constitution, then, takes us away from, rather than towards, the level where, as inside
of the Other, we recognize him as an ultimate ground. Not constitution, but rather its
reverse is, thus, required. We need a movement from sense back to its ground, a
movement from externality of beings back to the primitive grounding level which first
With this, we have an indication of how we should approach the level required
can observe that for Husserl, in his last years, the reduction is characterized as allowing
us "to discover the absolutely functioning subjectivity, to discover it not as human, but
as that which objectifies itself, at least at first, in human subjectivity" (Krisis, 2nd
Biemel ed., p. 265).11 The claim here is that the human subjectivity, whose worldly
Notes
69
being is presupposed along with the world of meanings it shares, can itself be grounded
CHAPTER II
THE GROUNDING OF THE THING AND THE EGO
is the thought that such consciousness does not acknowledge an "outside." Fink put this
as follows: "The world becomes understandable as the aggregate of the end results of the
constitutive life processes of transcendental subjectivity; it is, thus, not outside of this
life as such. And we further recognize that the idea per se of an 'outside' situated beyond
Cartesiennes'," Aug. - Oct. 1932, ed. Dr. Holl and Dr. Ebeling, Freiburg, hereafter
referred to as "Proposal," p. 172; F., 172). 1 The implications of this view are quite far-
reaching. They concern the significance, within the phenomenological context, of such
Thus, with regard to the first, we have to say that "creation" cannot be
i.e., a creation of the world out of nothing by a god who is transcendent or external to
characterizing the "natural" attitude's description of being, then the relation in question
does not seem to involve the type of being which this attitude describes. This implies
that the totality of beings considered by the natural attitude is not an "absolute" totality.
There is, in other words, something beyond it. If by the word, "ontology," we refer to
the study of individual beings, then such a study does not embrace the phenomenological
notion of an all-inclusive "absolute." In Fink's words, "While the worldly concept of the
Notes
71
does not signify a totality of beings" ("Proposal," ed. cit., pp. 172-173; F., 173). It does
relation which is not ontological. The totality of individual, worldly beings is, itself,
related to what cannot be considered a worldly being. This last is the creative
consciousness which does not, like such worldly beings, have an outside (See Ibid., p.
The import of this for our notion of created being is expressed by Husserl in
terms of a "reversal." The reversal involves what in itself is primary and what we take to
In Husserl's words,
There is, thus, a reversal in the usual sense of the discourse about being. The being
which for us is first is, in itself, second -- i.e., it is what it is only in "relation" to the first.
It is not as though a blind ordering of laws had ordained that the ordo et connexio rerum
must direct itself according to the ordo et connexio idearum. Reality, both the reality of
the thing taken singly and the reality of the entire world, essentially (in the strong sense)
lacks independence. It is not something absolute in itself. It is not something binding
itself to another in a secondary way. Rather it is absolutely nothing in an absolute sense.
It has no "absolute essence" whatsoever. It has the essential nature of something which is
only intentional, only consciously known or presentable, only actualizable in possible
appearances (Ideen I, Biemal ed., p. 118).
Carefully read, this passage makes the following assertion: Objective being --
attitude, objective being is the individual entity "in itself." As such, it is taken by this
entities that are related, not vice versa. In opposition to this attitude, Husserl claims that
Fink expresses this claim in a number of ways. It involves, first of all, "... the
recognition that being possesses the constitutive dignity of an end product, a result ..." of
the constitutive activity of consciousness. ("Proposal," ed. cit., p. 173; F., 173). This
recognition involves a reversal insofar as it involves the thought "... that what we had
taken as the non-relative and ultimately independent totality of beings presents in truth
only an abstract layer of constitutive becoming, that the universe of beings, the world, is
only a relative 'universe' which is, itself, related back to transcendental, constituting
subjectivity" (Ibid., p. 171; F., 172). As Fink observes, such a thought involves a
reversal in the very sense of being. Being, understood as individual entities, can no
longer have the sense of something absolute in itself. In other words, the "totality of
beings" can no longer be taken as that which functions as an ultimate ground. If this
members, it must be thought of as resulting from what is other than these -- i.e., from
The central, fundamental thought of transcendental idealism is: Being is, in principle,
constituted in the processes of the life of transcendental subjectivity. Not just the being
with transcendence's type of givenness but also, just as much, being as immanence --
indeed, the whole world taken as the ensemble of the immanent interiority of
experiencing life and the transcendent outside world -- is a unitary constitutive product.
Transcendental idealism is best characterized through the description: "constitutive
idealism." While worldly idealism attempts to explain being by means of being, the
ontological world-thesis of transcendental idealism presents the interpretation of being by
means of the constitution which is "before being" (Ibid., p. 196; F. 201).
Notes
73
The significance of this for the nature of the consciousness which is considered
considered a "worldly being." If it could, it would not be that which, for Husserl, is
"first," but only that which is "second" -- i.e., exists "in 'relation' to the first." In other
words, it would show itself as dependent. Once again, the applicable principle is
Fichte's: "The ground lies, by virtue of the mere thought of a ground, outside of that
which is to be grounded." Thus, the ground and the grounded cannot have the same
nature. To the point that the former shows the nature of the latter, it shows itself not as a
ground, but as in need of a ground -- i.e., as dependent. Granting this, and granting as
well that the characteristics of worldly being are singularity and externality of relations,
If we accept the above inference, then the question we are faced with is that of
the nature of absolute consciousness in a positive sense. To indicate the answer for
which this chapter will lay the groundwork, we can say that the consciousness which is
outside, it does not exist as a "numerical singular" -- i.e., as one among many. It exists
plurality of similar individuals. For such singularity, there are no others which are
similar. This characterization applies at once to the consciounsess (or ego) which is
taken, not as an individual entity, but as the necessary and sufficient ground of the
constitution. As a sufficient ground, it has no need of anything else for its constitutive
activity. Its notion as necessary and sufficient thus excludes the notion of another,
Notes
74
distinct co-constituter of the world since the assumption of two self-sufficient grounds of
the world would rule out our calling either of them "necessary." Either would suffice
and neither would be indispensable. With regard to the creatively constituting ego, we
must, then, say with Husserl: "In an absolute sense, this ego is the only ego. It is not
With this, we may ask how far this uniquely singular ego is our own. Can we, in
our action of constitutively "making sense" of the world, claim to be uniquely singular
grounds of this sense? Can we, in Husserl's words, say "I am the only one (der Einzige);
whatever exists for me is my own from the singularity (Einzigkeit) in which I function"
unique singularity which ultimately grounds and the numerical singularity (the one
Our present chapter will engage in an investigation of the latter. It will inquire
into the phenomenological notion of being an individual -- a one among many. What do
we mean when we say that a thing exists in this way? How far can the ego itself be
terms is, for Husserl, to speak of constitution. It is to describe the constitution of the
individual existence of both the thing and the ego. Ultimately, our sense of the
constitutive stages which must obtain for the ego to be individually defined will give us a
sense of its existence prior to such stages -- i.e., its existence as pre-individual. It will
thus lead to the subject of our following chapters: the investigation into how, in a
positive sense, the ego can be called singular and yet not be taken as an individually
At times, Husserl expresses a close sense of affinity with the Kantian method of
philosophizing. He writes, for example, "... the revolution in the very nature of
philosophical thought which Kant promoted and allowed to arise in the powerful,
perhaps even violent proposal of a new science is still the challenge of the present; and
this new science is our own task and a task which can never be abandoned in all the
future" ("Kant und die Idee der Transzendentalphilosophie," May 1, 1924, in Erste
Hague, 1956, hereafter cited as EP I, p. 240). This revolution is Kant's proposal of "a
Feb., 1924, EP I., p. 227). As he elsewhere expresses this, Kant "brought about the
recognition that the world, which is for us, only exists for us in our cognition and that the
world for us is nothing but that which, under the title of objective knowledge, takes shape
in our experiences and thought" (Ms. F I 32, "Natur und Geist," 1927, p. 114a).
The reason for this sense of affinity is easy to see. For both Kant and Husserl,
1911, III, 125). For both, an object is defined as "that in whose concept there is unified
the multiplicity of a given [total] intuition" (Ibid., B 137; ed. cit., III, 111). What this
Its appearing sense, or "concept," is a function of its being one in many, i.e., its being a
In spite of this agreement, there is, as noted in the last chapter, a considerable
difference between the two philosophers. The gulf separating them can be said to spring
Notes
76
from Kant's limiting these definitions to the phenomenal object. Implicit in the notion of
this limitation is the thought of the object as existing beyond its phenomenal or sensible
presence to consciousness. For Kant, this is the thought of the object as a noumenon, a
thing in itself. He writes that "... this concept [of a noumenon] is necessary to prevent
sensible intuition from being extended to things in themselves and, thus, to limit the
objective validity of sensible knowledge (for the remaining things to which it does not
apply are specifically called 'noumena' in order to show by this that such knowledge
cannot extend its domain over everything which the understanding thinks)" ("Kritik d. r.
V.," B 310; ed. cit., III, 211, italics added). What we have in this passage is a distinction
between Denken -- i.e. the "thought" of the understanding -- and the "knowing," the
connected perceptions." The two are not the same since Denken, rather than terminating
in such knowledge, can be employed to show its limitations. Here, Denken is considered
as reaching beyond what can be sensibly given and, with this, as thinking the sensible
object as a "mere" representation of what, in itself, is not sensibly given. In other words,
it is conceived as intending (though, not knowing) the nominal object in itself. It is such
Now, as Ricoeur notes, this distinction between Denken and Erkennen does not
occur in Husserl's later work (See Husserl, An Analysis of his Phen., ed. cit., pp. 186ff).
His rejection of Kant's notion of the nouminal thing in itself is also a rejection of the
thought cannot pass beyond the sensibly given since, for Husserl, the latter is not really
separable from the thing in itself. In other words, the Husserlian collapse of the
distinction between Denken and Erkennen is implicit in his position that the being in
itself of an object coincides with its being for us in its phenomenal presence. Because of
Notes
77
this, such presence cannot be thought of as concealing the object "in itself," but rather as
constituting its very being. Here, the intention of thought is understood as reaching its
final goal when it comes to rest on the connections occurring in our perceptual
experience of the object. Thus, in its intending the "in itself" of the object, it misses the
mark if it attempts to go beyond this experience rather than seeking a point of unification
To fully understand the above, we must, first of all, qualify De Boer's assertion
Husserl's statements that "all real unities are unities of sense ... Reality and world are
simply titles for certain valid unities of sense ..." Husserl, after making these remarks,
concludes that "the world itself has the whole of its being as a certain 'sense'" -- i.e., the
sense which arises in consciousness considered "as the field of sense giving" (Ideen I,
Biemel ed., pp. 134-135). Yet, later in the same work, he feels compelled to refine this
position. If we take sense as that which we can objectively describe and conceptually
express with regard to some entity, then its apprehension is not that of the individual
existence or the "thisness" of an object. The thesis of such individual existence (or
being) concerns not the sense, but rather the "bearer" of this sense.
Before we cite Husserl on this point, a brief glossary of his terms is necessary.
The individual acts by which we apprehend an object's features are termed noeses. Their
correlates are termed noema. They are the senses by which we conceptually express
what we find in the object. The sum of such senses gives us the sense of the object as a
whole. It is an all-inclusive noema which contains all that we can say in objectively
Husserl terms it the noematic object and writes in its regard: "The 'sense,' which we have
Notes
78
repeatedly spoken of, is this noematic object 'in the how' along with everything the above
conceptually express." "This 'how' ('Wie')," he explains, "is to be taken as precisely what
the present act prescribes as actually pertaining to its noema" (Ideen I, Biemel ed., p.
322). It is, in other words, the sum of senses which conceptually express "how" the total
object is presently understood. As a final term, we have the noematic nucleus. This is
considered nuclear because it is the relatively unchanging "core" of the noematic object.
As such, it consists of the most stable of the object's descriptive predicates. This nucleus
is the object's "sense in its mode of fullness" (Ibid., p. 323). It is what we can expect to
encounter when we see the object. It is its stable sense as given in the "fullness" of
intuition.
This sense, Husserl stresses, is not the "meant as such." This means that it is not
what we intend when we focus on the "thisness" of the object -- i.e., on its individual
existence. In such an intention, our "... glance passes through the noematic nucleus." It
passes through it to the "most inward moment of the noema" (Ideen I, Biemel ed., p.
318). The latter "is not the nucleus itself (within the objective sense) which has just been
described. It is rather something which, so to speak, forms the necessary central point of
the nucleus and functions as the 'bearer' of the particular noematic characteristics which
as such'" (Ibid.).
What exactly is this bearer (Träger) of the noematic sense? Husserl uses a
number of terms to describe it. He calls it "... 'that which is identical,' the 'determinable
subject of its possible predicates' -- the pure X in abstraction from all predicates" -- in
abstraction, "... more precisely, from the predicate noemata" (Ideen I, Biemel ed., p.
321). He writes: "It is the central point of unification we spoke of above. It is the point
of connection or the 'bearer' of the predicates ... It must necessarily be distinguished from
Notes
79
such predicates, although it must not be placed beside them and [in this way] separated
from them; just as, contarrywise, they are themselves its predicates, not thinkable without
it, yet separable from it" (Ibid., p. 320). When it is so distinguished from the predicates,
it is simply an "empty X." The terminology here is recognizably Kantian (Cf. Kritik d. r.
V., A 104-105). One may ask, what is the meant as such, when conceived as an "empty
X," if not a Kantian thing in itself? The conception of this last is one of something
beyond the object's intuitably presentable sense. But this seems to be what we intend
when we think of this X as empty. If this interpretation were correct then our last section
would be incorrect. Husserl, like Kant, would have to distinguish Denken from
Erkennen. He would have to take this X as the object of the thought (Denken) which
unambiguously rejects this suggestion. Far from pointing to a nouminal entity existing
for itself, the X exists within the senses which an entity has for us. It is only something
for consciounsess since it is only posited when the senses which we can predicate of the
Stated most generally, Husserl's position is that the X is empty, but it is not
experience. Yet as something set up by the connections between experiences, it has as its
beyond experience -- and, hence, as beyond the senses which are also part of experience
If, for a moment, we limit the term "experience" to refer to the perceptions we
have of an object, the relation between the X and these perceptions can be expressed
between two elementary types of judgment. The first is a judgment expressed in the
Notes
80
form "I see ..." The second type, to take the simplest case, is a judgment which has the
form "there is ...," i.e., there is something there of which I am having perceptions. Now,
the assertion that the object is there is distinct from the assertion that we are having a
perceptual experience. As Husserl observes, the object cannot be identified with any of
'presents itself differently'; it is 'the same,' but it is given with other predicates, with
another determining content ..." (Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 320). This happens when it
shows itself "from different sides," and when, in the context of our different perceptions
of it, we take different "determining contents" as the predicates of the assertion "I
see ... ." The object, as the unity of this perceptual multiplicity (i.e., as the subject of
indefinite continuance of such experiences, it cannot be identified with the sum of the
perceptions we have actually had of it. If the object cannot be identified either with an
individual perceptual experience or with the sum of such experiences, then the thesis of
the object as there (the object as existent) cannot per se be a thesis (or judgment) of
What makes them, within the flow of experience, perceptions of one and the same object,
i.e., the object considered as an individual existent, is the ordered connections which they
exhibit.2
According to Husserl, the same point holds when we refine this analysis and
speak of our experience of the senses of the object. The basis of such senses are the
multiplicities of perceptions directed to particular features of the object. The noetic acts
Notes
81
(noeses) which apprehend such features are acts of synthesis. They are a grasping of one
in many. As such, the object of such acts is a sense -- a sense which we employ in the
conceptual description of some particular feature. To grasp the sense of the object as a
whole, a further act of synthesis is required. Here, we unify the senses (the "predicate
noemata") which are the results of our first set of acts. Now, the object of this higher
level synthesis can be described as the noematic object -- i.e., as simply the sum of the
object's senses. But this, our earlier description, does not do justice to the process by
which it is apprehended. Our object is not simply a collection of senses, but rather their
synthetic unity. It is a "real unity" considered as a "unity of sense." Its status as a one in
many means that inherent in it is a "point of unification" -- i.e., Husserl's "empty X."
The same thing can be said of the senses we obtained on the lower level. They, too, as
the results of distinct acts of synthesis, must be considered as inherently containing their
distinct X's -- i.e., their points of unification. In each case, we have to say that it is the
ordered connections between the synthesized elements (be they perceptions or senses)
which allow us to assert that they pertain to one and the same thing. Thus, as Husserl
writes with regard to such an assertion: " ... distinct senses are related to the same object
only insofar as they are capable of being ordered into unities of sense, unities in which
the determinable X's of the unified [lower level] senses achieve a coincidence with each
other and with the X of the total sense of the ongoing unity of sense" (Ideen I, Biemel
ed., p. 322).
The above indicates how Husserl can make what appear to be contradictory
individual existence, our glance, he asserts, must pass "through the noematic nucleus" --
i.e., through its given, appearing sense. Yet, in almost the same breath, he claims that it
does not really pass through it, but rather comes to rest on what is inherent in this sense.
The terminus of this glance is simply "the most inward point of the noema." The key,
Notes
82
here, is Husserl's genetic understanding of sense. If a sense is a one in many which has
been synthetically constituted, then, in intending the X which is the noema's "point of
unfication," we do not really pass beyond it. The thesis of the X, which is the thesis of
the object's individual existence, is also the thesis of its sense. In positing the latter, we
posit it as a one in many; but to posit this is also to posit the X as a "point of unification."
This is the understanding which allows Husserl to say that a real unity --i.e., an
individual existent -- is a unity of sense. Yet, the same understanding, with a certain
change of emphasis, also allows us to speak of passing beyond the object's sense in
then this "point of unification" is, as Husserl says, a "point of connection." Here, its
notion reaches beyond sense to include the ground of sense -- i.e., the ordered
distinguish the ground from the grounded, it is correct to say that in our intending the
nucleus or sense.
There is a certain tie between Husserl's position and the traditional metaphysics.
predication, but is not capable of being predicated of anything else. Those entities which
are capable of being predicated of others are not individuals (i.e., singular things) in a
primary sense. They are rather universals with regard to those entities which receive
their predication (See Categories, 2a, 11--4b, 19; Metaphysics, 1078b, 30-32). The same
thing is implied by Husserl when he speaks of the noematic object as the sum of what we
can describe and conceptually express about some object. The meant as such -- i.e., the
existing individual -- is not what we intend when we think of the predicates (the
individual noemata) composing this description. To intend the meant as such, we must
intend the "point of connection" between the predicates. Thus, individually regarded, the
Notes
83
senses which we predicate of the entity could just as well be predicated of some other
entity. In this, they display their "universality." They are not individual existents but are
rather prior to such. They give rise to the latter through their coming together to form a
"unity of sense." The same point can be made, mutatis mutandis, with regard to the
constitutive elements of such senses. The perceptual experiences from which they arise
must also be regarded as pre-individual and universal. Their universality consists in the
fact that, taken in isolation, they are not tied to a definitie "this." They can, as we said,
The claim that senses and perceptual experiences are prior to individual
existence indicates the distinction with the traditional (Aristotelean) metaphysics. For
Husserl, such priority signifies that they are the constitutive elements out of which the
actual object arises. Their interconnections constitute the actual being of this object. As
Later, when we come to consider the role of time in the constitution of the "actual
object," this position will have to be modified. For the present, however, Husserl's
meaning is clear. If, indeed, an object is only a "title for the essential connections of
consciousness," to distinguish its actual existence from its sense, we must point to the
connections which ground its sense. It is these which give rise to "actual object"
considered as "the unitary X." In other words, the connections ground "the point of
Notes
84
connection" which stands as the existing subject of our various predicates. Husserl's
idealism is equally clear. He can claim that the actual object is only a "product" of
consciousness because it is simply a point of connection -- i.e., a sense filled one in many
this signifies is that our grasp of these elements is not to be taken as simply our particular
(merely subjective) apprehension of the thing. The connected elements, (i.e., the
"determining contents" and senses,) pertain to the thing itself. This follows since without
them there would be no connections and hence no "this," no individual existence, which
we would be apprehending.
Husserl, in our last cited passage, speaks of "rational connections" and "rational
also be considered as inherently rational. The basis of this doctrine is to be found in the
relation he draws between the positing which results in such a product and rationality.
He treats these two as mutually equivalent notions. Thus, the positing act is called by
him an "act of reason" -- i.e., a "rationally motivated" act (Ideen I, Biemel ed., pp. 335-
36). As for reason itself, it is understood as "reason in the widest possible sense, a sense
extended to all types of positing" (Ibid., p. 348). The equivalence beween reason and
positing signifies the "general insight ... that not just 'truly existing object' and 'object
capable of being rationally posited' are equivalent correlates, but so also 'truly existing
object' and the object which is capable of being posited in an original, complete thesis of
reason" (Ibid., p. 349). The full assertion, here, is that the thesis of positing, which is the
being there (Dasein) of an object, is equivalent to the thesis of reason which focuses on
the object as something "rationally motivated," i.e., as something which can be rationally
Notes
85
inferred from given conditions. Here we may observe that if we do accept this assertion,
we also accept the final statement of Ideen I. This is the claim, in Husserl's words, that
"an all-sided ... solution of the problems of constitution" -- i.e., problems involving the
reason in all its formal and material formations ..." (Ibid., p. 380).
The "formal" formations referred to are those of formal, symbolic logic. They
concern the reasoning process in abstraction from all content. As for the "material"
formations, the reference is to what Husserl calls a logic of content. This concerns the
role of the material contents of our perceptions in determining our inferences. The
fundamental notion of such a logic is that of the dependence of one type of content on
another. Thus, the essential dependence of the contents of color and spatial shape on that
of extension allows us, given the former, to infer the necessary presence of the latter.
Similarly, the pitch and loudness of a tone are contents considered to be essentially
dependent on the presence of a third material content, that given by our sense of duration.
Here, too, the relations of dependence between such contents serve as a basis for the
processes of reasoning with the processes by which we constitute being. There is, first of
all, his identification of a real entity with the unity of sense. The unity of the former is
identified with the X conceived as the unity of the predicate senses. Regarded
phenomenologically, this identification implies that the thesis of the being of an object is
always simultaneous with the thesis that it possesses some unified sense. As we have
seen, we posit being through the "making sense" of our given perceptions, i.e., through
their manifesting one in many characters. The presence of such characters is the
presence of the "predicate noemata" -- i.e., the predicate perceptual senses. Their
unifiability within a single subject of predication gives us, on the one hand, the "total
Notes
86
sense" of the object and, on the other, the "X of the total sense" -- i.e., the object
considered as there, as an individual being. Granting this, we can say that the laws
governing the unifiability of senses within the total sense are also the laws governing the
constitution (or positing) of being. With this, we come to the second part of the twofold
root. It is the identification of the laws by which we unify senses with the laws of logic
-- i.e., the laws of formal inference as given by symbolic logic and those of material
inference as given by Husserl's logic of content. By following such laws, we can avoid
both formal and material contradictions. Positively speaking, these laws allow us to
bring about that formal and material unity of senses which, when intuitively present, is
the rationality that finds objective expression within such "logical" laws is inherent
within the process of constitution. We can also say, with Husserl, that "the ordo et
connexio rerum must direct itself according to the ordo et connexio idearum." It is not,
as he says, a "blind ordering" which makes this necessary. It is rather the fact that the
forms of unification given by our formal and material logics are simply representations
i.e., the individual thing. Because of this, logic has a field of applicability in our
sensible, material world. The logical relations existing within it -- relations which allow
us to infer and reason about it -- are actually expressions of the laws governing its
constitutive grounding.
petitio principii fatal to his account of the positing of Others. According to the above,
grounding. This follows insofar as such laws of inference are simply mirrors, so to
speak, of the laws by which the phenomenal presence of entities is established. The
Notes
87
notion of such mirroring can be made more vivid by imagining for a moment what it
would be like to live in a radically "irrational" world. Such a world would be one in
which nothing, broadly speaking, made any "sense." The phenomenological picture of
such a world is given by applying Husserl's assertion that "all real unities are unities of
sense." A completely senseless, irrational world would, thus, be one where nothing --
i.e., no real objects -- could be posited on the basis of our experiences. Our perceptions
would not fit together; no synthesis -- at least no objective synthesis of them -- would be
possible. By way of contrast, a rational world is one where we can "infer" objects from
our perceptions. Our perceptions are indicative of something being there affording us
perceptions. Since a number of objects result from the operation of the same laws of
"inference" -- i.e., have the same factors for their constitution -- such a world also allows
us to encounter similar objects. We have the possibility of forming logical classes such
as all A's, all B's, etc. A rational world, thus, begins to afford us, with its stable and
similar groups of objects, the possibilities of the logical inference which is based on the
relations of the "essences" -- i.e., the universally applicable senses -- of these objects. 4
Others should be clear. If his description is accurate and if it does involve the circularity
of reasoning implicit in the principio principii, then it indicates that the conscious
processes by which we attempt to recognize the Other are themselves logically faulty.
Given that this violation of logical inference is also a violation of the processes of
constitution, the Other at this point could never appear. Such positing would simply
have the status of an empty pretension; for the very laws of grounding by which the
Other achieves his "being for us" would have been violated. 5
Intimately involved in his identification of the logical with the constitutive laws
this interpretation, we must first sketch out the general terms by which Husserl defines
Notes
88
Husserl as the study of the laws growing out of the logos or essence of each of the onta.
More closely regarded, the notion of ontology is tied to that of a "region," the region of
the entities for which it is considered the ontology. The region, itself, is defined by an
essence, the essence being that which specifies the type of objects which pertains to a
specific region. Thus, to take Husserl's example, the essence "physical thing" specifies
the objects which belong to the region of "physical nature"; and the laws springing from
what is involved in this notion are the subject of the ontology of physical nature. Such
general essences can, of course, overlap. Thus, the notion of an animate physical thing
can be included under the notion of physical thing, and the region of the former can be
thing can be included in the more general essence of a perceptual thing. A crucial
element in this description is the distinction Husserl makes between "formal" and
"material" ontologies. According to him, there are as many material ontologies as there
are general essences with a specifically definable "material" content. There is, however,
only one formal ontology. The essence which defines its region of objects does not have
a definite, material content, but is rather, as Husserl writes, "a completely 'empty' one, an
essence which, in the matter of an empty form, fits all possible essences ..." (Ideen I,
Biemel ed., p. 27). This materially empty essence is that of an "object per se." As for
the region defined by it, "it is actually not a region, but rather the empty form of a region
as such ..." (Ibid.). Insofar as it specifies the formal relations of the objects of all
possible regions -- this by specifying the formal laws that pertain to the essence "object
per se" -- this "formal ontology also contains the forms of all possible ontologies -- i.e.,
all 'proper,' 'material' ontologies ..." It does so, Husserl adds, because it "prescribes to
rational structure. As for their laws, they are identified by Husserl with the laws of
material and formal logic. Thus, the laws springing from the most general of the
material essences, that of the perceptually appearing thing, are those of the logic of
content. They are the laws concerning the unifiability of perceptual meanings in sensible
objects. As Husserl expresses this in the Investigations, they are "concerned with the
corresponding intuition in the unity of objectively adequate knowledge" (LU, Tüb. ed.,
II/2, 106). Such compatibility concerns the possibility of positing an object (and, hence,
objectively knowing it) with the perceptual senses designated by such combinations of
meanings. To turn to formal ontology, its laws are those of "pure logic" (Ideen I, Biemel
ed., p. 27). Its purity is purity from specific contents. Since it concerns simply the
notion of object per se, it is able to proceed analytically and to symbolize with letters the
perceptual contents of objects insofar as "object per se," understood formally, embraces
everything that can be a logical subject of an assertion. The fact that the object must
include both a material and a formal compatibility of contents is indicative of the above
with the reduction. The reduction, itself, is a move from the constituted to the
presence. Now, this reduction of the onta requires a corresponding reduction (and
reinterpretation) of the logos or essence pertaining to each. The essence must become
understood as the essence of the reduced onta. Once we accept this, "then," as Husserl
writes, "all ontologies, as we expressly demand, fall to the reduction" (Ideen III, Biemel
Notes
90
sense, this is an interpretation in which "everything presented by the sciences of the onta,
the rational and empirical sciences (they all can be termed 'ontologies' in a broadened
sense insofar as it is evident that they all concern unities of 'constitution') resolves itself
into phenomenological elements ..." (Ibid., p. 78). Specifically, this means that "the
certain essential connections of pure experiences" (Ibid., p. 77). As he also expresses this
a few lines later, "The transcendental interpretation of all ontologies would also belong
factually given set of "transcendental connections" (Ideen III, Biemel ed., p. 77). As for
its essence or logos, this points to the type of connections required to set up a thing of a
definite type. Such essences are the "basic concepts" of ontologies insofar as they
experiences" points to the fact that certain connections are essentially demanded if
objects of a given type (and, hence, of a given region) are to be posited. With this, we
have the corresponding interpretation of "each position" (or law) of ontology. They
become understood as laws giving us the formal rules for connecting experiences
according to certain types. The "quite definite connections" they point to are those
Two points follow from the above. The first is that it establishes a certain
identity between essence and thing -- i.e., between the species and its instance. The
identity is such that given the thing, we also have its predicable essence. This follows
apprehend the thing. In other words, the transcendental thought of the thing involves the
thought of the esence insofar as 1) the former is simply the thought of a unity established
by the connections of experience and 2) the latter is the thought of the "essential
connections" which allow of the positing of this unity. Thus, to take Husserl's standard
example, the thought of an individual, real existent involves the thought of the
perspectival type of connections which permit this existent to appear. Since such types
are, for Husserl, objectively interpretable as essences, we can say that the possibility of
essence (or species) of it. The second point involves the fact that not just essence but
also the logical laws are implicitly given with the thing. These laws, which involve the
formal and material comatibility of contents, have been reinterpreted. They now count as
connections which permit the positing of an object with compatible contents of a certain
kind and, hence, as an object of a certain species. Thus, like the species or essence, the
possibility of such laws being applicable to the thing is correlated to the possibilty of the
thing's apprehension. This cannot be otherwise, given that the laws in question are, in
fact, laws governing the essential possibilities of the thing's positing. It is, we can say,
their inherence in such positing which makes it a "rational act." For Husserl, then, the
actuality of the thing, i.e., the actuality of its connections, is a sign of the actual operation
of these laws. "Rationality" and "constitution" are, in other words, simply descriptions of
the ordered, lawful process by which consciousness grounds the presence of the thing.
With this, we may note that we have answered one of the questions we posed
about "being an individual -- a one among many." We asked: "What do we mean when
we say that a thing exists in this way?" Its individual existence we can now say is a
this involves the thought of the thing's essence, we also have the thought of the thing's
Notes
92
being one among many. Its individual existence includes the possibility of its being a
member of a class, one of a number of similar individuals to which the same essence
Our account of Husserl's conception of the thing would not be complete without
our adding two further elements: the presumptiveness and the ideality of its individual
existence. To begin with the first, its conception always occurs in tandem with that of
the thing's rationality. The notions of its presumptiveness and rationality are, in fact,
developed simultaneously by Husserl. Both have their roots in the notion of the thing as
an "empty X" -- i.e., a point of unification established by the ordering of the connections
not equivalent to its appearances. Thus, its appearances cannot completely represent it.
As Husserl expresses this position: "The positing on the basis of the bodily appearing of
the thing is, indeed, a rational positing, but the appearance is always a one-sided,
whether we take "appearance" (Erscheinung) as a single view of the thing or as the senses
synthesized from a number of such views. Indeed, it occurs even if we take this term to
denote the sum of such views and resulting predicate senses. Thus, Husserl writes:
"There are objects -- and all tanscendent objects, all 'realities' included under the title of
nature or world, belong here -- which cannot be given with complete determinability and
Since, in fact, the very definition of a transcendent object is that of an entity which
surpasses or transcends the finite sum of our actual view of it, this last statement follows
as a matter of course. Its implication, with regard to our positing of the thing is equally
A real thing, a being with this sense, can in principle only "indequately" appear within an
appearance which is finite or limited. Essentially connected with this is the fact that no
rational positing which rests on such an inadequately presenting appearance can itself be
"final," "incontrovertible," that no rational positing, in its particularity, is equivalent with
the straight-forward assertion, "The thing is actual," but only to the assertion, "It is
actual" on the supposition that the continuation of experience does not bring about
"stronger rational motives" which exhibit the original positing as one that can be
cancelled in the wider context. The positing is rationally motivated only through the
appearance (the incompletely fulfilled perceptual sense) considered in and for itself in its
singularity (Ibid., pp. 338-39).
In this passage the Husserlian theses of the presumptiveness of the thing and its
inherent rationality are thought together. Their common root is the notion of the thing as
unifiability -- the rational, logical forms. It, thus, appears as inherently rational -- i.e., as
a result of positing conceived as a lawful, "rational" act. The same doctrine, however,
separates the thing from the views and senses we have of it. In placing the being of the
thing, not in the latter, but rather in the ongoing unity established by their connections, it
makes such views or senses (or any finite sum thereof) an inadequate representation of
this being. The doctrine, then, which asserts the rationality of the posited entity, gives
this rationality a factual or contingent character. This character follows from the position
that such positing is "rationally motivated only through the appearance," but such
appearance, as distinct from the thing, can never fully justify this positing. If it could,
then the thing would not be the X. It would, on the contrary, be equivalent to its
appearance -- i.e., to what Husserl calls its "fulfilled perceptual sense." It would, in other
words, be the same as the noematic object or the sum of its objective senses. Its non-
identity with the latter is, however, involved its definition as something showing itself as
Notes
94
the same in different "appearances" -- i.e., as the same object for all the multiple senses
which its experience may afford us. It is inherent in its notion of being, not the noematic
sense conceived as our present understanding of the object, but rather the "bearer" of
such. So conceived, it can never exhibit the finality of a closed concept, i.e., that of a
completely conceived and defined sense which is not open to addition or revision.
For Husserl, the proper conception of the thing as this "bearer" is given, not by a
closed concept, but rather by a "Kantian idea." "The perfect givenness of the thing ...,"
he writes, "is traced out as an 'idea' (in the Kantian sense) ..." The idea involves the
notion of "an infinite process of appearing which is absolutely determined in its essential
significance of this language is apparent from the above discussions. Such lawfulness, as
essential, pertains to the type of connections which are present in this infinite continuum.
The connections are conceived as occurring according to the logical (or constitutive)
laws of ordering which gives us a real unity -- i.e., a thing which is definitely determined
according to its type. Given the tie between the thesis of the X and the "rationality" (or
essential lawfulness) of the positing act, we can say with Husserl, "this continuum is
more closely defined as an all-sided, infinite one which is composed, in all its phases, of
appearances of the same determinable X ..." It is, in other words, a continuum "in which
one and the same constantly given X is continually and harmoniously determined 'more
This idea of the perfectly given thing is not of a reality which we can intuitably
encounter. The idea involves the notion of infinity; yet our actual, intuitive encounters
are always finite. Thus, we can say that the idea is "Kantian" precisely because it points
to a reality which is beyond the finite limits of our experience. To see what this implies
as to the notion of the thing, we must return to Husserl's basic premise that being is
Notes
95
equivalent to being given. The implication, here, is that the thesis of a thing's being is
never absolute, never something that can be established by its being intuitibly given to
us. Were we, in such a context, to attempt to absolutize the being of a thing -- i.e., to
think of it as completely given -- we would not transform it into a being in itself. The
thing is perfectly given only in idea. Thus, if being is equivalent to being given, its being
is only that of "an idea in the Kantian sense." As such, it is a being for us, a being for the
subjects who, reflecting on their experience, develop this idea. Once again, we have a
context where the thesis of the being in itself of a thing is thought of as coincident with
the thesis of its being for us. The context, in other words, demands that we acknowledge
Summing up, we can say that the thesis of the thing as an X -- i.e., as an
individual existent -- is one that involves three interdependent notions: those of its
rationality, presumptiveness, and ideality (or being for us). Insofar as these
§6. Consciousness as Grounding the Ego -- the "Reality" of the Real Ego.
remarkable textual difficulty faces us. Throughout his career, Husserl repeatedly asserts
that the ego or subject is a constituted, "founded" unity. Yet, beginning with the Ideen,
he also progressively develops the doctrine that the ego, considered as a "pure ego,"
development from one position to another. 7 Rather, from the time of the Ideen, both
positions are maintained and developed.8 To resolve the paradox springing from such
conflicting positions, we must carefully distinguish the different concepts Husserl has of
the ego. As we shall see in a subsequent chapter, the multitude of these concepts is a
Notes
96
function of our notion of time. Because of its involvement, indeed, its identification with
the temporal process, the notion of the ego is ultimately to be explained in terms of all
At this point, we are not in a position to establish this conclusion. The work of
description must first precede. Let us first distinguish the "real ego." Broadly speaking,
this ego is understood as the objective identity of a subject in the intersubjective world.
Its "reality" is its thereness for everyone -- i.e., its "objectivity," understood as that which
I and my fellow subjects regard. We can also say that the real ego is the individual
human being with all the characteristics which form his objective "worldly" identity.
These include his social and professional position, his family ties and his personal
features. The latter include both his bodily appearance as well as his "real" psychological
habits and dispositions. When a person is asked, "Who are you?", he may reply, "I am a
businessman, I am John's father, I am tall, a hard worker," and so forth. All of these
personal identity. As the facts of growth and education make apparent, what is referred
constituted throughout a lifetime. This signifies, from the transcendental point of view,
that "... real egos, just like realities in general, are merely intentional unities" (Ideen II,
Biemel ed., pp. 110-111). For Husserl, they are the constituted products of "pure egos,"
acting both individually and collectively (See Ibid., p. 111). Passing from such objective
"intentional unities" to their subjective, but not yet "pure," correlates, we have the second
the same way as before. An ego that has habitualities thus possesses what we objectively
and consistently acts on this. Such consistency is a necessary condition for its self-
identity. As Husserl writes: "I also exist in these [my position takings] and am a priori
takings; every 'new' position taking establishes a lasting 'opinion' or a theme (a theme of
experience, of judgment, of joy, of will) so that from now on, as often as I apprehend
myself as the same as I previously was, or as the same who is now and was previously, I
also hold fast to my themes, take them up as actual themes just as I have previously
Husserl has written a great deal on this habitual or person ego. His position can
be summarized by describing this ego's essential characteristics. The first of these is that,
like the real ego, this subjective counterpart is a progressively constituted ego. It is, in
other words, an ego of change and growth which is built up out of a series of successive,
yet lasting position takings. In this constitution, one position taking -- i.e., one
Husserl's words:
I exist as an ego of validities for me, validities acquired from myself. I also exist as an
ego of constantly new anticipations of future validities which actively spring from myself
-- i.e., the new setting of goals, new intentions, aims whose active realization is a basic
foundation (Urstiftung) for new acquisitions, a foundation for what is voluntarily done,
yet done as that which continues to be valid in the manner of something accomplished
(Ms. B I 13, VI, p. 8, 1931).
Examples of what Husserl is pointing to are almost too numerous to cite. We must "do"
arithmetic in order to do higher math. The elementary propositions of any science are
always the first and serve as the basis for what follows. The same can be said for our
general understanding of the world. What we learn in chidhood games continues to serve
Notes
98
us in basic (though often hidden) ways as we go about the practical business of being an
adult. It gives us the bases -- such as the ability to speak a language -- of our "present
The second feature of this ego concerns its constant striving for unity in its
growth. Insofar as its identity is constituted out of its lasting opinions -- i.e., its
"convictions" -- the striving is actually directed to the maintenance of its personal self-
preserve my one and the same ego -- my ideal ego of the understanding -- when I can
constantly and securely continue to strive towards the unity of the aggregate of my
An important corollary of this position is that this striving for personal unity in
one's lasting theses is also a striving after the unity of the world. Thus, Husserl continues
the last sentence with the remark that his personal unity is maintained "when an object-
world remains constantly preserved for me with the open possibility of being able to be
determined more closely." The connection between the two is that between the positing
and the posited -- i.e., between the noetic and the noematic. Given this tie, the unity of
the subject in its positing is correlated to the unity of the posited world. Husserl
This position, which is ascribed to Kant, appears as Husserl's own in later manuscripts.
unified ego, "... has constituted beforehand, in all its experiences, a unity of the
experiential world ..." This means that "as a person, it thus has within itself a universal
unity of life, one embracing both the actual and the possible, one which is, with respect
anticipatory unity. It possesses, in its streaming life, the active style of an ego constantly
preserving itself through correcting itself as it takes positions based on experience. This
is the unity of a person as someone who always possesses a world: the one, single world
as a fact" (Ms. E III 9, ca. Nov. 15, 1931, HA XV, Kern ed., p. 404).
to the third point of this description. As we recall from our discussion of the object as an
intentional X, the being of the object is always presumptive. Its thesis is, thus, always
absolutely given -- i.e., as an absolute being -- then our conception is simply that of an
"infinite" Kantian idea. For Husserl, the same point holds with regard to the world of
objects. He writes: " ... everything in nature and nature itself, according to its essence, is
not an absolute being, a being which a knower could absolutely possess and comprehend;
it is rather an idea related to the correlative idea of a freely available universe of possible,
harmonious experience." This cannot be otherwise, given that the individual objects of
this nature are, absolutely considered, only "ideas." Thus, Husserl continues: "This last
idea" -- i.e., that of nature -- "is related to the essence of a necessarily presumptive,
objectivities." It is, in other words, an idea of ideas. Like its components, the individual
X's, "such an idea is a necessary, subjective product albeit a rationally motivated one ... it
is inseparable from the basis that motivates it, inseparable from the experiences which,
even as 'possible' and not actual experiences, have their tie to the related [experiencing]
ego ..." ("Beilage XXXII, 1921 or 1922, "Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität,
Zweiter Teil: 1921-1928, ed. Iso Kern, The Hague, 1973, p. 280; hereafter cited as HA
XIV).
The import of these remarks with regard to the habitual ego should be apparent.
Given the tie of this ego to the world, its "self-correction" by which it preserves itself is
also a correction and preservation of the world. Now, the thesis of the world is in need
of "constant correction" precisely because the world is never absolutely given. As a total
Considered as absolute, it has simply the status of a "mere idea." The same thing must be
said of the ego positing this world. Given that it can preserve its self-identity only to the
point that "it can maintain the objectivity it thinks of as constantly self-identical," the
presumptiveness of this latter is also its own presumptiveness. In other words, if the
thesis of the existent, self-identical object can be completely realized only in idea, the
same must be said of the ego which thinks it. As Husserl says of "the ego which
constantly and harmoniously preserves itself," "... this ego is actually a mere idea" (Ms. B
I 13, VI, p. 9, 1931). It exists as "an idea giving the goal (Zweckidee) of the rational
self-development of the ego, of its genuine and true 'self-preservation'" (Ms. A V 21, p.
105b, 1916). Husserl explains this by adding: "The ego necessarily strives (as an ego)
for self-preservation and in this there lies -- implicitly -- a striving towards the ideal of
absolute subjectivity and the ideal of an absolute and all-around perfect knowledge. A
presupposition pertaining to this is that there be a world, at very least, that there be a
Notes
101
physical nature which harmoniously preserves itself ..." (Ibid., p. 106a). This
presupposition is, as we have stressed, one which can never be finally established. The
posited "physical nature" exists only as an ideal; and, hence, we have the similarly ideal
status of the positing ego which is correlated to this world (See Ms. B I 13, VI, pp. 9-10,
1931).
just said that the presumptiveness of the world is also a presumptiveness of the ego which
preserves itself by preserving its world. Now, the possibility of this preservation is never
guaranteed. To recall a few of Husserl's statements on this point, let us note that for him,
"... the being of the world ... exists only as the unity of the totality of appearances which
continues to confirm itself ..." (EP II, Boehm ed., p. 404). Given that this unity involves
established. This means that the world's present "bodily self-givenness never excludes,
in principle, its non-being" (Ibid., p. 50). In other words, we have the continuing
possibility of the collapse of our thesis of the world. As Husserl expresses this:
It is conceivable that experience -- and not just for us -- teems with inherently
unresolvable contradictions, that experience, all at once, thus shows itself as obstinately
opposed to the demand that the things which it posits should ever harmoniously persist.
It is conceivable that experience's connections forfeit the stable rules of ordering
perspectives, apprehensions and appearances and that this actually remains in infinitum
the case, in short that there no longer exists a harmoniously positable and, thus, existing
world (Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 115).
For Husserl, this possibility is also the possibility of the collapse of the ego. This
follows, once we admit with Husserl, "The assertion that I remain who I am as the same
transcendental ego -- as the same personal ego -- is equivalent to the assertion that my
world remains a world" (Ms. B I 13, VI, p. 4, Dec. 15, 1931). Granting this, "One can
Notes
102
With this, we can say that the same three features which characterized the
constituted thing are also displayed by the individual ego of habitualities. The latter, too,
is characterized by rationality, presumptiveness and idealty. Thus, its positing, like that
preserve the world and, hence, itself, it must exhibit the "essential types" of connections
which allow us to posit definite types of unity within multiplicity. Further, insofar as
such positing involves a certain presumption with regard to the maintenance of such
unities in future experiences, its own thesis, like that of the thing, remains a "presumptive
supposition." It has, thus, absolutely considered, only the status of an ideal -- i.e., that
traced out by a Kantian idea. This does not mean that this ego is itself a thing, but only
that the conditions for the being of an individual thing are, correlatively, its own
Here, what is ultimately indicated is the fact that both the subjective experience
and the experienced objectivity are correlatively constituted at one and the same time. 10
The correlativity of noesis and noema indicates, in other words, their parallel
constitution. As Husserl writes: "In the constitutive sense of all life in which the origin
themselves in parallel and that the subjectivities are constituted unities just as much as
their objectivities are" ("Gemeingeist II," 1918 or 1921, HA XIV, Kern ed., p. 203).
This parallel constitution points back to a correlativity of the conditions for their
constitution.
§8. The Pure Ego as the Pure Subject of the Personal Ego.
Notes
103
The pure ego has a special relation to the personal ego. It is not identical with
the latter and yet, as Husserl asserts, it is essentially tied to it. Their lack of identity is
indicated by the fact that the pure ego is capable of being adequately grasped by an act of
reflection. Each time such an act directs itself to it, it grasps it completely and grasps it
as something identically the same.11 In contrast to this, the personal ego, which has only
the status of an infinite, Kantian idea, can never be completely grasped. Husserl writes:
"The pure ego is not the person. How do I distinguish them? The personal ego is the
identical element in the change of my ego-life, of my being active and being affected. It
is not adequately given in reflection; it points, in principle, to the experiential data related
to the infinite horizon of my past life and to an infinitude of advance [in the future]
towards the completion of this data ..." (Ms. A VI 21, p. 20b, 1927?). Now, the pure ego
does not require such an infinitude of experiences for its complete apprehension. Indeed,
as Husserl elsewhere writes: "To know that a pure ego is and what it is, an ever so great
straightforward cogito. It would be senseless to think that I, the pure ego, might not
actually exist or might be quite different from the ego [presently] functioning in this
cogito" (Ideen II, Biemel ed., p. 104; cf. Ms. F III 1, p. 240b, ca. 1915). Husserl's point,
here, is that the accumulation of fresh experience does not add anything new to our
knowledge of the pure ego since this ego, in fact, always shows itself as identically the
same. In other words, "the pure ego, as is evident, is numerically, identically the same in
memory and is the same as the ego which can be discovered and grasped in a reflection
directed to this apprehending, and so forth" -- i.e., with regard to a further reflection
directed to this act of reflection and so on ad infinitum. (Ms. A VI 21, p. 21a, 1927?).
constituted unities, it "... does not present itself just from one side; it does not manifest
itself only in particular characteristics, sides, moments which, on their part, only appear
[in the multitude of their perspectives]; rather it is given in absolute selfhood in its non-
perspectival unity. It can be adequately grasped in the reflective turning of one's glance
back upon it as a center of functioning" (Ideen II, Biemel ed., pp. 104-05). It is, then, the
Since such an ego does not involve any multiplicity, it "evidently" must remain
The contrast, here, between this simple unity and the synthetic unity of the
personal ego could not be greater. The latter preserves itself by correcting itself. The
very notion of the personal ego's identity involves change and multiplicity. Indeed,
because of its heterogeneity with the unchanging pure ego, there is, Husserl admits, a
composed of the pure and personal aspects of the self, cannot be considered as a
"substantial" one. In Husserl's words: "The ego's identity in the change of position
takings and its identity in the change of habitualities, in which I am a past-present ego, is
not yet a substantial identity. For precisely within such change, I am the same and yet
constantly another; the same, so it appears, as an empty pole and another insofar as I
have had constantly to abandon, change the 'self' who has taken a position" (Ms. E I 7,
1920's, HA XIV, Kern ed., pp. 296-297). The "empty pole" referred to here is the ego
considered as a pure, non-perspectival unity. It remains the same even as the ego of
Despite this difference, there is an essential connection between the personal and
pure egos. The connection is formed by the cogito, the "I think" that is the act of
position taking. Insofar as the personal ego is made up of position takings, it necessarily
involves the "I" of the "I think." The latter is not "the 'self' who has taken a position" --
Notes
105
i.e., the self that is the very act of position taking and changes with the change of this act.
It is rather the self which is the subject of all such acts. It is the identical subject who can
be said to have different positions. If this latter is thought of as pure, then according to
Husserl, it must be included in the personal ego. Thus, after enunciating the differences
between the two egos, he goes on to say: "This pure ego, however, lies included in the
personal ego; every act or cogito of the personal ego is also an act of the pure ego" (Ms.
A V 21, p. 21b, 1927). Given that the "real ego" is simply a noematic correlate of the
personal, position taking ego, the same thing can be said with regard to the real ego. In
other words, we can say, "there are as many pure egos as there are real egos ...," the latter
the [respective] pure egos ..." (Ideen II, Biemel ed., p. 110).
To see more clearly the nature of the connection between these three different
characterizations of the ego, we must examine the doctrine of the ego as the "pure"
subject of the cogito. The initial context of this doctrine is Husserl's description of the
Ideen I describes this, "There lies in the very essence of every experience not just that it
indeterminate manner it is this ..." (Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 80). According to Husserl,
this character involves the notion of the ego and its "glance" (Blick). As he writes on the
following page: "When an intentional experience is actual, i.e., performed in the manner
of the cogito, then the subject (the 'ego') 'directs' itself within it to the intentional object.
There pertains to the cogito itself an immanent 'glance at' the object, which, on its part,
springs from the 'ego,' which therefore can never be absent." According to Husserl, this
ego is not "an experience among experiences." It is not, in other words, something
"arising and again disappearing ... with the experience ..." (Ibid., p. 137). Neither is it
the "glance" of the ego. As Husserl explains this, "The ego seems to be constantly,
Notes
106
necessarily there ... its 'glance' goes 'through' every actual cogito to the objectivity. This
ray of the glance (Blickstrahl) is something that changes with each cogito, shooting forth
anew with the new cogito, disappearing with it. The ego, however, is something
identical. Every cogito, at least in principle, can change, can come and go ... But, as
opposed to this, the pure ego seems to be something necessary in principle; and, as
something absolutely identical in all actual and possible change of experiences, it cannot
in any sense be taken as a real component or moment of the experiences" (Ibid., pp. 137-
38).
This statement simply repeats in somewhat greater detail the passage we quoted
about the heterogeneity of the pure and personal egos. The pure ego remains the same
even as the personal ego shows itself differently -- i.e., avails itself of fresh experiences
and, on this basis, exists in the performance of new cogitata or position takings. The
ground of its absolute identity has also been noted. It is its non-perspectival character.
This means, as Husserl writes in 1921, it is not, like the thing, "a one-sided, founded
unity which, in the constant passage from distinct to distinct, is only describable in such
[passage]" (Ms. E I 6, June 1921, HA XIV, Kern ed., p. 50). Now, a founded unity is a
through their connections. What about the ego which does not appear perspectivally --
i.e., which does not appear through a perspectival ordering (or connecting) of
is obviously not a constituted unity. Its continual sameness is, in other words, simply a
reflection of its non-constituted status. What this signifies with respect to our experience
of this pure "experiencing self" is put by Husserl as follows: "The experience of the ego,
the experience of an experiencing self, has an essential pole of unity which is not
constituted in these [experiences] as is the case with all temporal being where in the
continuity of filled time a changing or unchanging unity constitutes itself in the filled
Notes
107
duration" -- i.e., the duration "filled" with perceptual content (Ibid., p. 49). The implicit
claim, here, is that as non-constituted -- i.e., as something not given through the temporal
extended being. As Husserl explicitly writes: "The self, which is the 'thoroughly'
identical, is not temporal or even temporally extended in the same sense as the
What we have here is a further contrast between the pure ego and the "concrete
self" -- i.e., the personal or habitual ego. Husserl takes the latter as constituted through
time. Because of this, the ego they constitute is experienced as enduring through such
perspectivally appearing ego lacks the very basis for appearing as an enduring,
Let us now take note of another aspect of Husserl's doctrine of the pure ego. It is
one which, in distinction to the above, leads him to claim that the pure ego can, in a
certain "relative" sense, be considered as constituted. The origin of this claim is his
continual insistence that the givenness of the pure ego is dependent on the givenness of
experiences. This dependence, itself, is a function of the ego's position as the "pure
subject" of the cogito. As before, the general context of Husserl's remarks is his
consciousness of some object, i.e., some "cogitatum," then cogito and cogitatum are
given together. With this, the pure "transcendental" ego is also given. Speaking of "the
Notes
108
transcendental or absolute ego which corresponds to the human person," Husserl remarks
that "I am an awake soul by virtue of a specific egological structure facing the structure
of the pregivenness of the world." Since this pregivenness is formed by the experiences
whose connections constitute the cogitata, the "awake" ego of the cogito exists only when
it possesses such experiences and connections. In Husserl's words, "... the transcendental
ego is a relative ego, an egological structure facing what is pre-given to the ego ..." (Ms.
the pure ego. The necessity for the ego's lack of "material," experiential content comes
from the ego's absolute self-identity. As perfectly identical, it cannot be identified with
any of the changing contents of consciousness. Hence, it appears as quite distinct from
what it experiences. Its purity is purity from such experience. As Husserl writes of this
ego, "An ego does not possess a proper general character with a material content; it is
quite empty of such. It is simply an ego of the cogito which [in the change of
which it is also dependent ..." (Ms. E III 2, p. 18, 1921). Such dependence is not just that
of the "awakeness" of the ego on the presence of the stream; rather it is the dependence
of it in its individuality on the stream. As contentless, the ego is not unique since it lacks
the material features which would distinguish it from another ego. In other words,
considered by itself apart from the stream, it has only the general character of an
egological structure, an "empty form" of an ego. As Husserl puts this: "One can say
that the ego of the cogito is completely devoid of a material, specific essence,
comparable indeed with another ego, yet in this comparison an empty form which is only
'individualized' through the stream: this in the sense of its uniqueness" (Ibid.).
Notes
109
This dependence of the uniqueness of the ego on the stream has two
consequences. The first is the tie between the pure, personal and real egos. The second
is the view that the pure ego can, at least analogously, be seen as constituted.
With regard to the first, Husserl writes: "The pure ego, it is to be expressly
stressed, is a numerical singular with respect to 'its' stream of consciousness" (Ideen II,
Biemel ed., p. 110). The stream is essential for the individualization of the pure ego into
(Umgebung) of this ego. Now, since this environment is a constituting one -- i.e., one
resulting in the presence of realities through the connections of the stream -- the tie of the
ego to the stream is also a tie to the realities it constitutes. As Husserl expresses this:
"The ego is only possible as a subject of an 'environmemt,' only possible as a subject who
has facing it things, objects, especially temporal objects, realities in the widest sense ..."
(Ms. E III 2, p. 46, 1921). In Ideen II, this tie explicitly involves both the personal and
real egos considered as constituted entities. According to Husserl, "... every real ego,
like the whole real world, belongs to the 'environment,' to the 'field of vision' of every
pure ego ... And with this, every pure ego ... possesses the human ego, the personality as
an object of its environment" (Ideen II, Biemel ed., p. 110). The tie between these egos
can be expressed in terms of the self-interpretation of the pure ego. If, as an individual,
constituted world, then it can always interpret itself in terms of this world. It can think of
itself as a real ego situated among the "things, objects" of this world. It can also think of
itself as the subjective, "personal" correlate of this objective ego. What we have, then, is
the possibility of having an individualizing stream of consciounsess and, with this, the
Thus, as Husserl notes, to posit a real ego or a personal "human" ego is also to posit, as
Notes
110
pertaining to these, a singular pure ego (See Ibid.). This follows since the presence of
the personal ego is also the presence of the constituting environment which makes
possible the presence of a numerically singular pure ego. What is ultimately pointed to
here is, as we shall see, the notion of the pure ego as a center or pole of an already
constituted "surrounding world." As such a center, it can always interpret itself as a real
If the pure ego is tied to a constituted environment, then the temptation arises to
this position. He writes, for example, "I thus see here an essential lawfulness of the pure
ego. As the one identical, numerically singular ego, it belongs to 'its' stream of
experiences, which is constituted as a unity in unending, immanent time. The one pure
ego is constituted as a unity with reference to this stream-unity; this means that it can
find itself as identical in its course" (Ms. F III I, p. 248b, ca. 1918, 2nd italics added).
This position is repeated with reference to Kant. Husserl writes: "What is called
constitution, this is what Kant obviously had in mind under the ruberic, 'connection as an
operation of the understanding,' synthesis. This is the genesis in which the ego and,
correlatively, the surrounding world (Umwelt) of the ego are constituted. It is passive
genesis -- not the [active] categorial action which produces categorial formations ..."
(Ms. B IV 12, pp. 2-3, 1920). A close study of Husserl's doctrine reveals that these
remarks are not in contradiction to the passage from the same period which we quoted
above. They are not to be taken as asserting that the pure self-identical ego "shows itself
perspectivally," that it is, in other words, a constituted, "founded unity" in the sense that a
thing is. What is at issue in the just quoted texts is the numerical singularity of the ego.
According to Husserl, the pure ego is such a singularity with reference to the constituted
unity of its stream -- i.e., its constituted "surrounding world." As we shall see, what is
constituted here is not the ego, but rather its reference. It is this reference which first
Notes
111
gives it its singularity as a center or pole of a surrounding world which itself has become
To make this last point, we must first raise the question of the necessity of the
pure ego. What exactly are the functions that it performs which require its positing? As
we quoted Husserl in introducing its notion, "Every act or cogito of the personal ego is
also an act of the pure ego" (See above, ). The question, here, is of the necessity of
this "also." Let us give the general lines of the solution we shall explore. It consists, first
of all, in the claim that the pure ego is necessary as an experiencer who is distinct from
experience. Only as distinct and, hence, as "pure," can it "find itself as identical in [the]
with the changing contents of experience. To put this somewhat more radically, we may
note that there is a certain connection between being and self-identity. Real loss of self-
identity is not the change of some subject. As involving the very subject of the change, it
is to be counted as annihilation pure and simple. The underlying thought here is that the
ego must have some separation from what changes if it is to continue in being -- i.e.,
continue to find itself as in some way connected to what it was before. Now, in the
Logical Investigations, this separation is effected by a doctrine that separates act and
experience. In the Ideen, however, the intentional act of the position taking ego is
composed of the experiences that form the stream of consciousness. The necessary
identity of the ego in the latter work is, thus, seen as demanding the positing of a "pure"
ego; it demands, in other words, an ego whose purity is purity from the changing
experiences composing its changing, position-taking acts. This first claim leads quite
naturally to a second. This is that the pure ego is not required for the function of
synthesizing the stream of experiences. The pure ego is, thus, not to be regarded as a
Notes
112
synthesizer which organizes the stream into a constituted surrounding world. Insofar as
the acts which accomplish this synthesis are distinguished from itself, it is not a
constituter, but only an experiencer of an already constituted world. Hence, the acts of
the personal ego can only in an analogous sense be considered as acts of the pure ego.
This claim is strengthened by the fact that when we enter into the more basic layer of
what Husserl calls "passive constitution," we find that neither the personal nor the pure
Investigations with the Ideen. As is well known, the Investigations does not put forward
a doctrine of the pure ego. Indeed, it explicitly denies this ego (See LU, "Investigation
V," §8). Ricoeur sums up its position in the following words: "The Logical
Investigations asserted that the ego is outside among the things and that subjective life is
only an interconnected bundle of acts which does not require the referential center of an
This does not mean that in the Investigations there is no I or ego. It does,
however, signify that its doctrine of the ego is an early form of what Husserl was later to
present under the title of the "personal ego." Thus, in the Investigations, the unity of the
ego is conceived as the unity of its acts or position takings. Essentially, this unity is a
logical one. It is based on "the pure logical laws" which, according to Husserl, spring
from "the ideas of sensibility and understanding per se" (LU, Tüb. ed., II/1, 197). As in
the Ideen, the laws springing from such ideas are simply the subjective expression of the
"rationality" of the world which is sensed and understood. In other words, the logical
laws for the unity of the posited are viewed as laws which also hold for the unity of the
ego that posits. Thus, the laws springing from the idea of sensibility are those of
material, synthetic logic. The laws whose roots are in the pure idea of the understanding
are those of analytic, symbolic logic. Noetically regarded, both sets of laws determine
Notes
113
what types of acts can come together so as to found the unity of the ego which is made
up of such acts. Concretely, this signifies that a particular type of act -- e.g., that of a
perception of color -- is taken as requiring a second act type -- here the perception of an
extension. Together with other act types which are also essentially demanded, they form
the "founded unity" which the Investigations considers as the "I" or the unity of a
consciousness which is sensibly perceiving. (See LU, "Investigation V," §4). The same
sort of position, mutatis mutandis, is expressed for the ego that understands. Its unity is
founded on the "categorial act types" of conjunction, alternation, negation, etc. -- i.e., the
types of conscious connections which are expressed by such words as "and," "or," "not"
etc. Out of such elements, logical relations such as formal implication are composed. As
for the ego which understands these relations, its unity is simply that of formal non-
make logical assertions about their relations, it cannot contradict itself. If it did, it would
violate the logical unity which defines it as an understanding subject. In Husserl's words,
"An understanding without the pure logical laws would be an understanding without
among the things." What this signifies is that this ego is understood as receiving its
sensuous data -- i.e., the data of its experience -- from transcendent sources. It, thus,
accepts itself as positioned within a transcendent world and as dependent on its entities
for its experiences. Now, if we ignore the epistemological difficulties inherent in such
"worldly" dependence -- difficulties involving the causality of the world with respect to
the acts of consciousness -- we can remain indefinitely on the egological level put
forward by this early work. Within the context of the Investigations, there are, in fact,
two main reasons why the ego need never be anything beyond the founded, logical unity
of its acts which we have just described. The first is the book's rigid separation between
Notes
114
experiential content and subjective act. Husserl asserts that he "can find nothing more
evident" than their distinction (LU, Tüb. ed., II/1, p. 383). As in the Ideen, the act is
one in many is termed an "objective interpretation" of such contents. This means that it
makes "objective sense" of the latter by taking them as contents or "sensations" of some
object. But, here, the act is understood as one thing -- a part of an individual reality; and,
itself never ever allows itself to be reduced to an influx of sensations. It has the character
of an act ..." (Ibid., II/1, 381). Furthermore, "... under the title sensations, we understand
1st Halle ed., II, 707-08). This implies that when we reflectively regard an act itself, the
sensations which its "sensuous perception" affords us are distinguished from the
sensations which we receive when we perceive an external object. The act being part of
an individual reality -- that of the subject -- and the external object being a reality distinct
from this, the contents they afford us are by definition distinct (See LU, Tüb ed., II/2,
177-8, 180). In other words, the contents springing from the "real act" are never those
which the act itself objectively interprets when it engages in external perception. This
means that we can never confuse the experiencer -- i.e., the subject as an "interconnected
bundle of acts" -- with the contents which it externally experiences. Its logical unity is
the unity of a distinct reality. As such, its is the unity of an experiencer distinct from
experience. Husserl can thus present it as a relatively self-identical unity vis-a-vis its
The second reason for the Investigations' refusal to posit a pure ego concerns the
issue of functioning. The acts which make up its "personal" ego function by themselves
to synthesize the stream of experiences. Their action includes both the straightforward
Notes
115
perceptual synthesis of an individual object as well as the higher level, explicitly logical
"categorial synthesis." Thus, it sees no necessity to posit an ego as a synthesizer over and
When we come to the Ideen, we notice first of all a shift in terminology. "Acts,"
in the sense of the Investigations, are equated with "intentional experiences" (Ideen I,
Biemel ed., p. 80). These last are identified with the Cartesian cogito. Thus, just as
the essence of every actual cogito to be consciousness of something" (Ibid., p. 70). This
equation of act and intentional experience undermines the sharp distinction the
Investigations drew between the act and the experiential contents it acts upon. This
idealism, does not want to picture experience as something which is externally provided.
If subjective acts are taken receptive of the experiential contents which they act to
interpret, then, as just noted, the ego of such acts appears to be "outside among the
outside. To reach this position, Husserl in the Ideen continues the doctrine of the acts as
active synthesizers of the stream of experiences. (We leave aside, for the moment, the
question of passive synthesis). Yet, to this he adds the doctrine that the experiences of
the stream, rather than being external to such acts, are, in fact within them. Each cogito,
experience or cogito and the individual momentary experiences that make it up. Not
every "experience," taken in the generic sense of the term, is per se intentional. In
Husserl's words: "Under experience in the widest sense, we understand everything and
anything that is to be found within the stream of pure experiences, therefore, not only
concreteness -- but all the inherent moments found within the stream and its concrete
parts" (Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 80). "It is easy to see," Husserl adds, "that not every
inherent moment within the concrete unity of an intentional experience has itself the
something'" (Ibid., p. 81). It possesses this character not by itself, but by virtue of being
an "inherent moment" of the connected unity which it forms -- i.e., by being part of the
in our discussion of the empty, intentional X. Its main point is that consciousness
becomes consciousness of something only when the experiences within it exhibit through
their connections a "point of unification." Noetically, this means that the experiences
close up together to form the more extended unity known as the intentional experience.
Noematically, it means that they form the intentional unity which is the object conceived
While satisfying the demands of transcendental idealism, this new doctrine is not
without its own problems. Once we abandon the position that consciousness has its own
distinct reality and its object another, how do we distinguish between the two? As
separate itself out for us? How can consciousness itself be distinguished as a concrete
being in itself, namely as what is always my consciousness ...?" (Ideen I, Biemel ed., p.
89). The problem arises because, according to the idealistic standpoint, consciousness
has no outside. Thus, my consciousness "includes the continuing perception and what is
apprehended in this, the latter being the perceived entity understood as an 'opposite' to
consciousness and as 'an in and for itself'" (Ibid.). The problem achieves its particular
urgency from the fact that according to the doctrine just presented both the "subjective"
cogito as well as the "objective" cogitatum are the results of the connections of
experience. Husserl's question, then, is how these same connections can result in the
Notes
117
distinction of my consciousness from the world, the latter being taken as its "opposite" --
The answer which Ideen I gives ignores the deeper issues involved in the
constitution of time. Within its own limits, however, it can suffice for our present
the distinction between the individual experience and the cogito. The individual,
momentary experience is not per se intentional. The cogito, which is formed by the
individual experience and the "perceived entity." The latter, taken as a spatial-temporal
reality, is something which shows itself perspectivally. Its perspectives are formed by
the individual experiences which are objectively interpreted as experiences of this reality.
Such experiences are never confused with the reality since, regarded individually, they
manifests itself through the ordering of connected experiences. In other words, this
grant that the perspectival appearing of the reality involves the thought of an indefinite
continuance of such appearing, we can distinguish this reality from the cogito which
grasps it. Here, the distinction between the two is simply a function of the transcendent
quality of the reality. To posit it as distinct from the cogito is to posit it as transcending
the finite sum of the experiences making up the cogito. It is to conceive of it, at least in
"idea," as pointing beyond these to further experiences. The difference between the
cogito and the "perceived entity" is, thus, simply one between the actual experience
making up the cogito and the idea of the indefinite continuance of this experience which
its positing as an infinite, "Kantian idea." It is easy to see how the perspectival appearing
of a reality involves the thought of this idea. The reality which appears pespectivally is
not posited as any one of its experiences (or the actual sum thereof). It is rather posited
as an "empty X." This means that it is taken as the persisting "point of connection" of
to subsist as such -- i.e., as their connecting point. Hence, it always distinguishes itself,
qua "X," from the definite number of experiences making up the cogito.
In terms of the Ideen and the original context of the positing of the pure ego,
three consequences follow from the above analysis. The first is that the ego which
consists of acts can no longer be considered as a relatively stable, identical subject vis-a-
vis its changing experiences. It is, in other words, no longer qualified to serve as an
it was regarded as one thing -- i.e., a separate, "sensibly perceivable" reality -- which
could exist independently of the experiences it synthesized. But now, in the Ideen, the
very cogitationes -- i.e., multiple acts of cogito -- which compose it as an ego of acts are
with regard to the personal, position taking ego, it constantly shows itself as "another" as
it moves from position to position. This otherness is that of its "glance." It is the
otherness of the experiences composing this "glance" which is its cogito, i.e., its act of
position taking. Now, if we do assert that the ego must have some separation from that
other with each new cogito -- then we must look beyond this personal ego to find an
identical experiencer. With this, we have Husserl's motivation for positing a "pure" ego.
The doctrine that the ego's cogitationes are themselves made up of experiences leads to
the demand for the purity of the ego. Such purity is understood as a purity from such
Notes
119
changing experiences and, hence, from the changing cogitationes made up of such
experiences. With this, the necessary identity of the subject is once again secured. The
ego again appears as something that "can find itself as identical in its course." Here, let
us observe that the positing of this ego can also be regarded as part of Husserl's answer to
his question: "How can consciousness itself be distinguished ... as that which is always
unchanging center to which I refer all the changing acts and experiences forming my
consciousness. Indeed, it is because the latter do refer back to one and the same
unchanging center, a center for which they form the necessary "environment," that they
The second consequence is that the ego which we are here motivated to posit as
pure is not posited as a synthesizer of the stream. This point can be expressed in two
different ways. We can say, first of all, that insofar as the pure ego is distinguished from
the acts which are regarded as synthesizing the stream, it is distinguished as well from
their action of synthesis. Only analogously can such acts be taken as "its" acts. A second,
more profound way to express this is to observe that, according to the above, the acts
themselves are composed or constituted out of the experiential elements of the stream.
As we quoted Husserl, the cogitationes are both "within" the stream and are made up of
"inherent moments" which are individual experiences drawn from the stream. The
significance of this view for the Investigations' doctrine of acts -- i.e., of acts' being
considered as independent synthesizers of the stream -- can be put in terms of this work's
pursuing a level of constitutive analysis which is less profound than that of the Ideen.
The Investigations explores a level of constitution in which the synthetic action originally
pertaining to the stream seems to be an independent action of the subjective acts. At the
deeper level, which is explored by the Ideen, the acts themselves appear as constituted
products of the stream. Thus, on this latter level, the stream must be considered as
Notes
120
synthesizing itself. In other words, the very acts which formally were regarded as
synthesizing the stream are now conceived as the results of the stream's own self-
synthesis.
The conclusion, then, is that neither the pure ego, which is distinguished from
the cogitationes, nor the personal ego, which is composed of such, is ultimately
responsible for the synthesis of the stream. With this, we can say that what Husserl calls
"passive synthesis" is possible precisely because both the supposed "activity" of the
cogito and the supposed "pasivity" of its experiential data are contained within the stream
itself. They are simply different layers of one and the same, self-synthesizing stream.
As Husserl expresses this, "'Passive' signifies here without the action of the ego ... the
stream does not exist by virtue of the action (Tun) of the ego, as if the ego aimed at
actualizing the stream, as if the stream were actualized by an action. The stream is not
something done, not a deed in the widest sense. Rather, every action is itself 'contained'
in the universal stream of experiences which is, thus, called the 'life' of the ego ..." (Ms.
Our third consequence springs directly from the fact that this 'life' of the ego is
not a result of the action of the ego, the fact, as Husserl puts it, that "the individual,
egological life is passively constituted in immanent time" (Ms. B I 32, I, p. 16, May or
Aug., 1931, italics added). As we quoted Husserl, the ego is "dependent" on "a stream of
experiences" -- the very stream that has now been identified as its life. This means that
the individual ego (taken either as personal or as pure) cannot be regarded as the
independent origin of the constitutive action of the stream. In other words, as dependent
on the stream which it does not actively constitute, it cannot be said to be creative of the
entities which result from the stream's self-constitution. Such entities form the
surrounding world, the environment of the individual ego. "The ego," Husserl maintains,
"is only possible as a subject of an 'environment,' only possible as a subject who has
Notes
121
facing it things, objects ..." (Ms. E III 2, p. 46, 1921). The notion that the latter are,
ultimately, passively constituted, thus, leads Husserl to assert: "In the subjectivity to
which essentially belong both the ego and the 'stream of experiences,' the lasting world
constitutes 'itself' for the ego, but the ego, as much as it participates by its activity" -- i.e.,
by its acts -- " in this constitution, does not create it, does not produce it (schafft sie
nicht, erzeugt sie nicht) in the usual sense, just as little as it produces its past life,
produces its stream of original sensibility ..." (Ms. A VI 30, p. 9b, Nov., 1921). This
statement holds for the personal ego, since, as we have seen, the acts by which it
participates in world-constitution are both within and constituted out of the "stream of
original sensibility." It also holds for the pure ego, given that it is, qua numerical
This consequence has an important result for the analyses of our first chapter.
As we recall, the solution put forward by Husserl was bedeviled by the notion of the
creatively constituting ego. This was the ego which, in not having an "outside," had to
be regarded as the independent origin of its own sensibility. We can now say that this
concept is not that of an individual ego. This implies that to recognize the Other as an
individual is to recognize him as not being creative of the world which we share in
common. This follows since our being as individuals is a being that is dependent on the
stream of consciousness and, hence, on what is constituted out of this. The significance
of this result will be evident in a subsequent chapter when we come to propose a solution
Returning to the question of the necessity for positing the pure ego, we can say
that this ego has neither the necessity of a constituter of the stream nor that of a
constituted product. The first is ruled out by the ego's dependence on the stream; the
second, by its "purity" from the elements of the stream. Thus, given that the ego's purity
synthesis. It is not, like the ego of the Investigations (or the later "personal," "habitual"
ego), a unity which is"founded" on experience. Such purity, however, does not rule out
its dependence. It still remains the ego of the cogito, the ego (or subject) of the
surrounding world which is presented by the ongoing cogito. If we think both its purity
and dependence together, we come up with only a single necessity for its positing: the
surrounding world. Its necessity is that of an observer distinct from, yet essentially
Husserl writes, quoting Kant on the just mentioned necessity, "The 'I think' must
later writes, "... intentional experiences ... demand their pure ego as the subject of their
functioning ..." (Ideen II, Biemel ed., p. 110). The nature of this demand can be put by
recalling that the cogito is an extended unity of connected experiences. It is, according to
Husserl, a constituted product of the "life" which is the stream of experiences. Granting
this, the demand for the pure ego only occurs when the connections arise which form this
unity. It is only then that we can say "cogito" and from thence proceed through the
Kantian proposition about the "I think" to the necessity of this pure ego.
This move, for Husserl, is one to the "center" or "pole" of the stream which is
our life. If we are to distinguish the ego from its life -- and, with this, distinguish it from
the connected unity of the cogito, and finally from the entities posited through the cogito
-- then the ego only appears as their subjective center. In Husserl's words, "We
distinguish the ego and its life, we say that I am who I am in my life and this life is
experiencing ... the ego, however, is the 'subject' of consciousness; subject, here, is only
another word for the centering which all life possesses as an egological life, i.e., as a
Notes
123
1931). As he earlier expresses this: "The central ego is the necessary ego pole of all
experience and of all noematic and ontic givenness which can be legitimated by
experience ..." (Ms. M III 3, XI, p. 21, Sept., 1921). For Husserl, then, the ego which is
demanded by the connected unity of experience which forms the cogito is the center or
pole of this experience. The cogito, or the extended intentional experience, positions the
The notion of the pure subject as a center reveals the special character of its
Husserl above, the pure ego is "only 'individualized' through the stream ..." It becomes
"a numerical singular with respect to 'its' stream of consciousness" -- i.e., the very stream
that forms the individualizing environment of the ego. We can now say that the pure ego
is such a singular only to the point that the experiences and connections making up this
stream allow the presence of a surrounding, singular world. In other words, the ego
exists as such a singular only by being positioned as a singular subject or center of this
world. To make this concrete, we need to note that the harmonious, perspectival
ordering of experiences has a double effect. It yields, on the one hand, the appearing of a
unitary, spatial-temporal world. On the other, it also yields a distinct observer of this
world -- i.e., an ego with a "particular point of view." This particularity (or numerical
singularity) is simply a function of the ego's being positioned as this world's spatial-
temporal center. As its spatial center, it occurs in the "here." This means that the
experiences forming its constituted environment have been so arranged that the subject
always stands at the referential "0-point" which marks off the distances of its world.
Similarly, as the world's temporal center, the subject always occupies the "now." In this
case, its experiences position it as constantly existing between the flowing future and
past.
Notes
124
In both cases, we can say that the ego as a center is not itself constituted but is
rather individualized by the constitution that gives it its surrounding world. The
constitution of such a world is the individualization of its center. Thus, without the
perspectival ordering of experiences, notions such as "near" and "far" and, hence, "here"
would lose their experiential sense. To express this phenomenologically, we can say that
an object is interpreted as approaching the "here" insofar as its appearances are ordered in
time so as to progressively fill up more and more of the visual field. The limiting point
of this series is the "here," interpreted as the case where the object's appearance fills up
the whole of the visual field -- i.e., blocks out the view of all other objects. Another
factor in the setting up of our sense of distance is the rate at which an object's
perspectives unfold. Thus, in a walk through a park, a distant tree appears relatively
stationary while one taken as "nearer" unfolds itself more rapidly in a series of
perspectival views. In this instance, distance is not necessarily measured by relative size
but by the relative rates of the unfolding of perspectives. Once again, the notion of a
"here" is set up as an ideal limit of a progressive series -- but this time the series is one of
as a center involves both memory and anticipation. Memory is required for the
large and small or of rates of change would be possible. Anticipation is required because
the "here," in almost all cases, is simply an ideal limit. It is something anticipated by
getting progressively closer. Granting this, the dissolution of the world in a "tumult" of
remembered and anticipated experiences. As such, it involves both the world's past,
Notes
125
remembered being as well as its future, anticipated being. In Husserl's words, such
dissolutions would signify that "... I would not have the spatial-temporal field of a
nullified (wäre zunichte geworden). It would not have been nullified in a worldly sense"
-- i.e., the sense whereby an entity within an existing world is considered to be destroyed.
"Rather being itself, the being of the world per se (das Weltsein überhaupt) would have
been nullified. It would have ceased ever to have been through the loss of its validity, its
validity for me as an ego who would remain perplexed in my inner temporality" (Ms. B I
As is indicated by the context of this pasage, the point here is that such
affects my very "inner temporality" -- i.e., my sense of myself as a center between the
remembered past and the anticipated future. Husserl, thus, writes shortly before the just
quoted passage, "That I remain who I am, as a transcendental ego, as the same personal
ego, this signifies equivalently that my world remains a world" (Ibid., p. 4). He
immediately follows the passage with the words: "If the world existed, it still exists; and
if it exists, it existed. If it existed, it also will exist [in the future]. The world cannot
cease to be; this is senseless as long as I exist and, equivalently, as long as the present
exists and the past existed" (Ibid., p. 5). Thus, the fact that the world is successively
constituted from the temporal ordering of my experiences means that its temporal
structure is parallel to my own. Its being present is, correlatively, my being present as a
"central ego" with a retained past and an anticipated future. This means that the
destruction of my retained past is the destruction of the world's validity for me as past.
As we cited Husserl, such a destruction would signify that "it would have ceased ever to
have been ..." This follows since this "have been" is for me a correlative result of the
constitution which gives me a past. The same point holds, mutatis mutandis, for the
Notes
126
world's future. As long as I exist, i.e., as long as I have a present that implies, through
anticipations). They order our experience in time and thus temporalize the world which
is present through this ordering. We are not ready to discuss this constitution. Yet, we
must take note of its bearing on our present theme: the individual existence of the pure
level" (Ms. B III 9, p. 10, Oct. - Dec. 1931). Since the ego is not yet present here,
Husserl terms it a level of "non-ego." This "non-ego," he writes, "... we can designate as
(Ibid., p. 23). Occurring before the central ego, this is a "passive" temporalization, i.e.,
one that occurs before any activity on its part. It is also, Husserl claims, a
temporalization which results in such activity. It results in the individual ego being taken
According to Husserl, this last point depends upon our viewing the temporal
field both as a "fixed continuum of form" and as a field whose contents stream. The
former arises through the constitution of the continua of what we retain and what we
anticipate -- i.e., the continua of pastness and futurity. The result of this constitution is
the positioning of the ego as their "middlepoint." More precisely put, the ego becomes
present -- i.e., comes into being -- as the now which we constantly occupy, the now
which is at the center of our temporal field. To see this center as active, we must see the
field as active. In other words, the contents placed in its "fixed continua" must not
Notes
127
themselves be seen as fixed, but rather as streaming. A later chapter will consider the
origin of this streaming. For the present, we have to simply observe that such streaming
as past or future cannot be seen as fixed in relation to our now. Insofar as they are in
time, insofar as time itself is something which is continually "passing" or streaming, they
must stream. The experience which is past sinks into further pastness; future experiences
constantly draw nearer to the present. We can, thus, say that the streaming of experience
from futurity to pastness is a streaming through the now which we constantly occupy.
This cannot be otherwise, since the very constitution which gives us a streaming past and
future positions us as a point of passage between the two. With this, we have the
constitution of the ego as an active center. Its constitution as a point of passage is its
constitution as a point where its experiences "well up" as present and actual. As Husserl
puts this, "And in this streaming, there is constituted a lasting and remaining primal now
as a fixed form for a content which streams through it ... there is constituted a fixed
continuum of form in which the primal now is a primal welling middle point for two
continuum of what is just past and that of futurities" (Ms. C 2 I, p. 15, Aug. 1931, second
italics added).
This passage should not lead us to believe that the ego, as an unchanging and
temporal experiences. As we quoted Husserl above, the ego's purity from experiences is
also its purity from their temporality. In Husserl's words, "The self, which is the
'thoroughly' identical, is not temporal or even temporally extended in the same sense as
the experiences" (See above, p. ; see also Mss. E III 2, p. 50; C 10, p. 21). What is
constituted is this self's relation to its field, i.e., its status as a "fixed form" for the content
which appears to flow through it. The individual ego appears as the point of the welling
Notes
128
point" for a temporally extended content which is, itself, constituted as temporally
flowing. With this, the significance of the remark about the ego which remains
"perplexed" in its "inner temporality" becomes clear. If the individual ego only exists as
a center of a temporal field, the dissolution of this field, in its continua of pastness and
futurity, must amount to a dissolution of the active, individual ego, the very ego for
The above allows us to make a point with regard to the pure ego's availability for
our introspection. This availability is twofold. The pure ego is, first of all, available as
the ego which is demanded and positioned by the cogito. It appears as the present ego of
necessary for its apprehension. Such a multiplicity, in fact, "is no more informative than
the ego's availability goes beyond this single experience. It is its availability as that
which is the same in multitude of temporally distinct, reflective acts. Here, the ego
Husserl also puts this, "... in each reflection, I find myself, and find the same ego in
necessary self-coincidence" (EP II, Boehm ed., p. 411). This "self-coincidence" does not
just concern the acts of memory. The ego which appears in the acts which I remember
coincides with the ego I presently am and coincides with the ego of my anticipated acts.
When I reflect on such acts, "there immediately emerges the original identity: in the
form, I, the ego of the primal present along with the primal, original representations
existing in this present, am the same ego which was present in memory along with the
Notes
129
remembered, the same ego which, in anticipation, will be present along with what is to
come" (Ms. C 16, VI, p. 28, May, 1932, italics added). As we noted, this form of
availabilty of the ego which "can find itself as identical in its course" (See above).
second type of availability. First of all, in contrast to the first, it demands a multitude of
acts. This means that we must have the capacity for memory and reflection. Without
this, we could not grasp the pure ego considered as the "original identity" of past and
present acts. In Husserl's words, this original identity is able to appear "by virtue of
'memories' and to these pertain, as to all acts, the capacity for the identifying repetition
[of the past acts] and the capacity for reflection" on the acts which have been "repeated"
-- i.e., brought up unchanged to the present (Ms. C 16 IV, p. 29, May 1932). A second
time. The pure ego which is available to us at one time through acts of memory and
reflection is equally available whenever we perform these acts. Its sameness for us at the
different times we perform such acts points back to its own sameness at the different
times when it was originally present. Thus, we remember the ego as it was originally
present in temporally distinct acts. Yet, in reflecting on such memories, we find it "in
necesary self-coincidence." Whenever it was originally present, it was always the same.
-- and identified as the same as the present ego. For Husserl, this signifies that this ego is
" ... there is inferred or constituted as existent the totality of my (the identical ego's)
the universality of my momentarily present, my past and my future conscious life ..."
characteristic of this second type of availability. As Klaus Held notes, what is "inferred
any particular temporal location. Held, thus, concludes that this ego has "the mode of
Phaenomenologica, No. 23, The Hague, 1966, p. 124). It possesses, in other words, the
availability of an idea.
Husserl on rare occasions does speak of the pure ego as an idea (See, e.g.,
476). The reasons for this are clear. Like the idea, it is grasped in an "overreaching act"
of identification; it also possesses the idea's one in many character and, hence, its
themselves, have unfortunately led to a certain confusion. The pure ego, qua idea, is not,
as Held believes, a Kantian idea. Its availability is not limited to this form (See Held, op.
cit., pp. 126-28).14 Once we grant this, we can also say that its twofold availability does
not mean that we are dealing with two distinct, even contradictory concepts of the ego as
Eduard Marbach maintains (See Das Problem des Ich in der Phänomenologie Husserls,
Phaenomenologica, No. 59, The Hague, 1974, pp. 289ff.). We, thus, need not follow
Marbach in attempting to assert that the ego which is "tied to the analysis of the acts of
re-presentation" -- i.e., the ego that appears through memory and reflection -- is the only
ego which genuinely deserves the title of "ego" (See Ibid., pp. 298, 338-39).15
To make these points, we must first recall that a Kantian idea involves an infinite
"continuum of appearances." This is a continuum "in which one and the same constantly
given X is continually and harmoniously determined 'more closely' and never 'otherwise'"
(Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 351). The conception here is one of infinite advance in the
Notes
131
determination of some entity. The entity appears rather like the "limit" in calculus. It
has the position of a defined, yet never actually reachable limit in the advance of closer
and closer determination. This, however, is not the position of the ego which appears as
something which always appears "absolutely" identical, it rules out any notion of
progressive advance in its determination. Each further view of it does not present us
with something new which could add a further determination; rather, this ego always
shows itself as simply the same. This means that, in regarding its appearances, we are
Admitting that the availability of the ego, qua idea, is not that of a Kantian idea,
we can see the consistency of the two forms of its availability. Both, we can say, spring
from the ego's position as a center. Thus, as the ego which is positioned and demanded
by the cogito, i.e., the ego of a present ongoing act, its position is that of a spatial-
environment of pastness and futurity. In the representation of a past cogito, the ego
occupies the same relative position. In all remembrances of myself and my acts, I always
appear as occupying the here and the now of such acts. The recollection of a stretch of
past experience always includes my position as subject or center of such a stretch. It is,
therefore, this central position which forms the basis for the act of identification which
constitutes the idea of the ego. Indeed, the content of this constituted idea is nothing
other than that which I apprehend in "a single experience of a straightforward cogito." In
the latter, I have the immediate sense of myself as subject or center. In the act of
Let us attempt to summarize the results of our examination of the pure ego. Our
general conclusion is that the pure ego is the "center" of its constituted world. As
Husserl tells us, this world is presumptive in its givenness and, hence, in its being. Thus,
our first observation is that the same presumptiveness applies to the pure ego positioned
as its center or pole. To put this in even stronger terms, we can say that the dissolution
dissolution. We have, on the one hand, a dissolution of the constituted world which is
presented through the cogito. On the other hand, we also have the dissolution of the pure
ego as demanded and positioned by the connected unity of the cogito. The disordered
cogito has no definite point of experiential focus. Insofar as the pure ego is defined in
terms of "the centering which all [conscious] life possesses" through the cogito, the loss
of the focus is the loss of the pure ego in its raison d'etre. A similar point can be made
with regard to the pure ego's being as a numerical singular. The dissolution of the ego's
leaves the ego "worldless." As a worldless ego, it is in the position of expressing a "here"
and a "now" without a corresponding reference to the spatial and temporal fields which
would give such terms an individual sense. Thus, spatially, it becomes a "here" without
"now" without any reference to a definite before and after which would temporally locate
it. In both cases, then, it appears as a center without any reference to the whole whose
center it is.16
The above allows us a sense of the presumptiveness of the world which is deeper
than the one which we hitherto considered. The first sense of such presumptiveness
involves the givenness of the world. To this we can add the sense of the presumptiveness
of the ego to whom the world is given. The first sense is based upon the world's
existential status as an infinite, Kantian idea. Existing "absolutely" as such, it can never
Notes
133
be grasped or "established" by the finite perceptions of a finite ego. This sense can now
be strengthened by the further realization that this finite ego is insufficient as a ground of
the world. It cannot assure us of the world's continuing givenness because it itself
presupposes such givenness. It is given along with its world as its center or pole. This
means that what grounds the world also grounds it. Both are co-grounded by one and the
same process.
We can put this in terms of the "life" of the ego -- i.e., the ongoing stream of
experiences. As we quoted Husserl, "Every action [of the ego] is itself 'contained' in the
universal stream of experiences which is, thus, called the 'life' of the ego ..." (Ms. C 17
IV, p. 2, 1930). This stream is called the ego's life because the ego "lives" through its
acts, its cogitationes. But since the latter are made up of the experiences forming the
stream, they do not represent a "life" which is distinct from that of the stream. Indeed, as
"'Passive' signifies here without the action of the ego ... The stream does not exist by
virtue of the action of the ego, as if the ego aimed at actualizing the stream, as if the
stream were actualized by an action. The stream is not something done (Getanes), not
some deed (Tat) in the widest sense of the word" (Ibid., pp. 1-2). It is rather a doer and,
as such contains all action. Thus, the stream itself is the ground of the actions by which I
establish my surrounding world and, with this, my own existence as its center. Both my
cogitationes and the centered world which they present are co-grounded by the same
question receive this name for they concern the action by which experiences are placed in
time so as to produce the ongoing stream of experiences. We are not yet prepared to
discuss such processes. We can, however, note that when Husserl discusses the
dependence of the ego on its life (or stream), this dependence is normally expressed in
Notes
134
terms of the temporal ordering of this life. Thus, such dependence means that "I only
exist as living within this streaming life; and I only possess temporal being in its
generally describable features [of past, present and future] by virtue of the particular
[temporal] structure of this life" (Ms. C3 II, p. 4, Nov. 1930). This temporal structure is
not the result of the action of the individual ego. Rather, "the individual egological life,
Aug. 1931). Husserl elsewhere describes such passive constitution as "a passive, primal-
which is thereby constituted in its living temporality, a temporality which extends itself
along with its temporal modalities: present (the present of the streaming), past (the just
past streaming), future ..." (Ms. C 16 VI, p. 29, May 1932). The mechanics of this
process will be the subject of a later chapter. We here simply observe that it is by virtue
of this passive constitution of the modalities of past, present and future that "I exist in the
unity of a life which, qua constituted life, bears within it a temporal order ..." (Ms. B I
32, p. 17). When I regard myself as a pure ego, this existence is that of a "middle point"
between past and future (See above, ). It is only in terms of my being in the now --
i.e., in this "middlepoint" -- that I can call myself the "center" or the "pole" of my life.
As Husserl writes: "I am I, the center of things pertaining to the ego (Ichlichkeiten), but I
exist only as the ego of associatively bound unities in which everything ... possesses
words, "I exist -- I live, and my life is an unbroken unity of the primal, streaming
temporalization in which all the multiple temporalizations are hidden ... I, that means
here, first of all, only the 'primal pole' of 'one's' life, one's primal stream in which all
unities, which are called existents, temporalize themselves as persisting unities" (Ms. C 2
Husserl's doctrine, then, is clear. Insofar as the ego exists as a temporal "middle
its life and positions it as such. The same point holds mutatis mutandis for the
constitution which gives it its position as a "here." Indeed, as we have already indicated,
would not grasp the temporal ordering of perspectives which positions him as a center of
occurring within definite points of the past would not occur; and, with this, the
The result of this analysis is apparent. It is the undermining of any notion of the
individual ego as a self-sufficient center of activity. As we have seen, the notion of the
ego as active depends upon the cogito having already been constituted. It presupposes, in
other words, a level of constitution in which the experiences composing the cogito have
already been ordered and connected in time. With this, there is also the constitution of
the objectivity which exists as persisting through such experiences. It is only at this level
that an ego can be "active" in the sense of actively directing its glance (Blick) at an
objectivity. Husserl, thus, writes: "Proceeding from the deepest ground, we therefore
have an essential two layeredness which we can designate as non-ego and ego ..." The
first layer he describes "as the realm of the constituting association which is non-active,
as temporalization." The second is "the realm of the activity which is related to the
the primary-streaming existents (Seienden), the activity centered in the ego as the
identical source of all action and all the retention in memory (Behalten) which results
from action." This second layer depends on the first, for as Husserl immediately adds:
"The active retention in memory (das active Behalten) is what concerns the ego as its
which lies before all proper being and makes possible being as something which can be
accomplished through activity" (Ms. B III 9, p. 23, Oct.-Dec. 1931). Husserl's claim,
here, is that all egological activity, including the activity of remembering, is dependent
understood as temporalization, which first gives us the cogito and its objects as persisting
The conclusion this leads to has already been noted. According to Husserl,
passive constitution is what first "makes possible" persisting or lasting being. Thus, as
we quoted him with regard to the "lasting world," the individual, active "ego ... does not
create it, does not produce it in the usual sense" (See above, ). Iso Kern expresses
this conclusion in the following words: "Transcendental subjectivity is not the sufficient
ground of the being of the world. World constitution, according to Husserl, is therefore
radically given, as Husserl says, a 'wonder'" (Husserl und Kant, ed. cit., p. 298). The
"wonder" includes both the being of the individual subject as well as that of the world
which surrounds it. Both, in their being, are dependent on a constitution which "lies
before all proper being." As non self-sufficient, both are presumptive and both, as Kern
existent. As such, they do not apply to the consciousness (or ego) which we mentioned
at the beginning of this chapter. The latter is not a numerical, but rather a unique
singular. It is such by being a necessary and self-sufficient ground of the world (See
above, ). Two admissions follow from this. The first is that I cannot consider
"passively" breaking the intersubjective harmony. The passive constitution required for
this is not my own. That it is not is, indeed, the mark of my lack of self-sufficiency.
harmony actually obtains. To establish the latter, we must turn to the consideration of
the consciousness which Husserl does consider to be absolute, i.e., as absolutely self-
sufficient in its grounding function. It is here, as we shall see, that we catch our first
harmony.
Notes
138
CHAPTER III
FACTICITY AND INTERSUBJECTIVITY
A bridge can be made from the considerations of our last chapter to those which
points: the ego, the a priori, and facticity. In a certain sense, Husserl's doctrine can be
defined as a reaction against the Kantian. The consideration of this reaction will give us
consciousness.
doctrines of the pure ego. Kant calls this ego "the transcendental unity of apperception."
116). As such, it manifests a pure, non-perspectival unity which is distinct from the
similarity with Husserl's pure ego is its status as a referential center (or pole) of
experience (See Ibid., B 134). Finally and most importantly, both authors agree that the
unity of this ego is essentially correlated to the unity of the appearing world.
permit the intuition of a unitary object and, over and beyond this, the intuition of a
unified, self-consistent world of objects. According to Kant, the thought of one's self-
identity as a subject is also the thought of the objective synthesis determined by the
categories. In Kant's words, "The original and necessary consciousness of one's self-
identity is, thus, at the same time a consciousness of an equally necessary unity of the
Notes
139
which ... determine an intuitable object for these appearances, i.e., determine the concept
unitary object]" ("Kritik d. r. Vernunft," A 108; Kant's Schriften, Berlin, 1911, IV, 82).
According to this correlation, we can say that the violation of these categories or rules --
commenting on the Kantian correlation between the unity of the ego and that of its
world: "Kant further believed that he could demonstrate that the categories are the
concepts through which the pure ego must think the correlative object-world, the very
world which the ego, itself, demands. If it is going to think of this world harmoniously
objects according to the basic categorical laws" ("Beilage XXI," EP I, Boehm ed., p.
398). For Husserl, the same point follows because the pure ego is positioned by the
world as its unitary center or pole. Thus, to think the ego's unity is also to think the unity
of the world which centers or defines it. It is, moreover, to think of the operation of
this unified world. For Kant, as we shall see, this point has a fundamentally different
basis. Indeed, all of his agreements with Husserl on the nature of the pure ego spring
nouminal, it has the status of an experiencer distinct from its ongoing experience. It does
not appear through the connected unity of a multiplicity of appearances which forms an
ongoing intuition. On the contrary, as Kant writes, "... through the ego, as a simple
which is distinct from this [representation] ..." ("Kritik d. r. Vernunft," B 135; Kant's
Schriften, Berlin, 1911, III, 110). The fact that it cannot be represented through the
does not change, i.e., show itself from another side, in the change of appearances making
representations, a complete identity. In Kant's words, "We are conscious a priori of the
thoroughgoing identity of ourselves in all representations which can ever belong to our
knowledge ..." (Ibid., A 116; Kant's Schriften, IV, 87). In other words, since my self-
representation is not given to me by an intuition, "I am, therefore, conscious of the self as
identical with respect to the multitude of the representations which are given to me in an
The notion of the self as nouminal or non-intuitable cannot per se arise from
intuition. What is directly posited on the basis of intuitive experience has, itself, an
intuitable character. What this signifies is that the simple representation of the self as
nouminal is one that arises from a deductive necessity. It springs from the ego's position
as a transcendental ground of the appearing world's unity. Kant puts this point in terms
of the "understanding" -- i.e., that faculty which works according to the categorical ruels
according to rules ... Such nature, however, as an object of knowledge in our experience
with everything which it may contain, is only possible in the unity of apperception. The
93, italics added). This transcendental ground of nature -- i.e., of the appearing world --
is, as Kant remarks, not something which, itself, is formed by combination; it is rather
the ground of all combination. It is that which, itself, "first of all makes possible the
Notes
141
concept of combination" (Ibid., B 131; Kant's Schriften, III, 108). As such, it makes
possible the categorical concepts which express the various types of synthetic
combinations. It also makes possible the understanding in its formulation and logical
employment of such concepts. It is, thus, represented as "that which contains the ground
of the unity of the different concepts in judgment and, with this, the ground of the
From this, the nouminal status of the ego (or "unity of apperception") necessarily
follows. The categories are rules of synthesis governing the ongong intuition of an
object. As the ground of the categories and, hence, of all objective synthesis, the ego
cannot be represented as the result of such synthesis. Insofar as this result is what
objectively appears, the ego cannot be thought of as objectively appearing. We can also
express this in terms of Kant's concept of the ego as the uncombined ground of all
multiplicity of an ongoing intuition. Thus, admitting that all objective intuition occurs
unity at once positions it as an "I in itself" -- i.e., as the non-intuitable, "nouminal" ego
combination, we come to a second aspect of the deduction leading to this ego. It begins
with our acknowledging that "an object is that in whose concept there is united a
multiplicity of a given intuition" ("Kritik d. r. V.," B 137; Kant's Schriften, III, 137). It
then adds the apparently necessary proposition that union or combination requires the
action of a combiner. Where are we to locate this combiner whose action results in the
intuitive presence of the object? The Kantian answer is that the action of combination or
synthesis is present in the subject itself. It is an act of its very "selfhood." As Kant
Notes
142
expresses this, there is "an action of the understanding which we may name with the
general title of synthesis in order, thereby, to draw attention to the fact that we cannot
represent to ourselves anything as combined in the object without ourselves first having
combined it and that combination ... can only be performed by the subject itself since it is
an act of its selfhood" (Ibid., B 130; Kant's Schriften, III, 107). The deduction, then is
from the givenness of the phenomenal action of synthesis to the necessity of the subject
In regard to this last, it is to be noted that Kant and Husserl agree that the identity
of the subject requires its purity from experiences. If my subject were identified with its
changing contents of consciousness, then, as Kant remarks, "... I would have as motley
and diverse a self as the conscious representations which I possess." Now, for Husserl,
this thought of the subject as a simple identity vis-a-vis its changing experiences implies
its conception as their referential center. The unchanging subject gives the changing
words, the field of experiences composing this consciousness belongs to its center or
subject since the field forms the subject's essential "centering" environment. For Kant,
however, this belonging has an even stronger sense. As indicated, it springs from the
proposition that all combination requires a combiner. Kant writes, "The thought that the
representations given in an intuition one and all belong to me is, accordingly, equivalent
to the thought that I unite them in one self-consciousness or at least can so unite them"
("Kritik d. r. V.," B 134; Kant's Schriften, III, 110). The conclusion follows once we
admit that whatever exists solely by virtue of the synthetic action of the ego -- here, each
Notes
143
of the ego's intuitive synthetic representations -- necessarily belongs to the ego (See Ibid.,
B. 135). Such belonging signifies that its intuitive representations are the ego's
"products," i.e., that they are incapable of existing without the ego.
between the ego's unity and the unity of the world should now be apparent. As we saw in
our last chapter, Husserl does not conceive of the pure ego as a transcendental ground of
the appearing world's unity. Quite the contrary, the ego's unity, understood as its
i.e., as capable of undergoing dissolution once these experiences are disorganized into a
"tumult." For Husserl, then, it is the unity of the appearing, constituted world which
necessarily implies the singular unity of the pure ego. In Kant's doctrine, the reverse
of the synthesis of appearances and, hence, the unity of the appearing world. It does so
because this self-identity is the "transcendental ground" of the unity of the appearing
that of an actor who has acted so as to combine appearances into a unitary world. Given
this order of implication, a certain logical consequence follows: if the thought of the
transcendental unity of apperception does imply the process of synthetic action according
to the categories, then the violation of such action also implies the absence of this
transcendental unity or Kantian ego. It does not, however, follow from this that, as we
quoted Husserl, this ego "demands" for its own unity the "basic categorical laws" by
which it intuits a unified world (See above, ). Insofar as this demand would signify
the dependence of the ego on the appearing world, it would reverse the Kantian order of
implication. It would make the ego presumptive. It would make it dependent on the
presence of the unified appearing world which its own unity supposedly "demands."
Notes
144
Now, if it is a ground of the latter, it cannot be dependent on it. A condition for the
world's appearing lawfulness is, as such, not conditioned by this lawfulness. We can put
this in terms of the fact that, as a ground or condition, this ego for Kant is a nouminal
ego. The dissolution of the world in a tumult of appearances does not affect this
This point can be made slightly more concrete by noting that although the
Kantian ego is the necessary and sufficient ground of the lawfulness of the world, it is
only a co-ground of the world's appearance. For the latter to occur, it requires a
"transcendent affection" from the things in themselves. This affection provides the
necessary material for its synthetic action according to the categorical rules. Given this,
we can say that the presence of a transcendental unity of apperception implies the
presence of its synthetic action; but we must add that this action has a sensible effect only
in the presence of a transcendent affection. The absence of the latter, thus, implies the
absence of any appearing result of the egological action; it does not, however, imply that
the ego, as understanding -- as the sufficient ground of the world's lawfulness -- has itself
been disrupted.1
There is, as indicated, a twofold deduction by which Kant arrives at the notion of
the ego as the nouminal ground of the appearing world. As a ground, it is deduced under
the principle that all combination requires a combiner, i.e., an active synthesizer. As
combination cannot be intuited. Here, Kant presupposes that all intuition occurs through
Broadly speaking, this is a method which proceeds from what is empirically given to
deduce the universal conditions which must obtain if such givenness is to be possible.
Notes
145
Husserl's sharpest criticisms of Kant concern his use of this method. He writes,
for example:
One complains about the obscurity of the Kantian philosophy, about the
incomprehensibility of the evidences of his regressive method, of its transcendental-
subjective "faculties," functions, formations, about the difficulty of understanding what
transcendental subjectivity actually is, how its functioning, its accomplishment comes
about, how through this functioning objective science in toto is supposed to be made
intelligible. In fact, Kant falls into his own type of mythic speech whose literal meaning
certainly points to something subjective, but to a mode of the subjective which we, in
principle, cannot make intuitive to ourselves, either by factual examples or by genuine
analogy (Krisis, Biemel ed., p. 116).
The point of this complaint is familiar to readers of the Critique. It essentially concerns a
certain duality in Kant's conception of his regressive method. On the one hand, it is
faculties and functions are conceived as serving as necessary conditions for the
lawfulness of the appearing world. In this employment, many of its results appear
the other hand, the Kantian method is also conceived as a regression to the ground of
appearance per se. In this view, it is not the phenomenal, but rather the nouminal subject
who (along with the nouminal world) is represented as serving as a necessary condition
for the appearance of the world. Thus, the faculties and functions are conceived as those
of the nouminal subject and, as such, as operations which "we cannot, in principle, make
intuitive to ourselves ..." With this move, the value for Husserl of the regressive method
is undermined. In seeking the ground of appearance per se, the method undercuts the
evidential quality of its account of how the ego functions as such a ground. Thus, the
descriptions of the functioning of the appearing ego. There is an enforced silence with
regard to the actually functioning ego, which, as nouminal, is positioned beyond all
We can illustrate this criticism with a reference to two of Kant's most important
doctrines -- those of the categories and of inner sense. With respect to the categories, the
categorical concepts, e.g., those of substance and accident, of cause and effect, etc., is a
way of characterizing reality. Each corresponds, according to Kant, to a logical form and
also to a synthetic judgment. Thus, to the concept of causality there corresponds the
form of the hypothetical assertion and also the synthetic judgment, "If there is an effect,
correlated to the form of categorical assertion, "A is X," and to the synthetic judgment
that A exists with the predicate X inhering in it. As these examples indicate, each
synthetic judgment has the logical form which corresponds to its categorical concept. All
of this is rather straightforward; yet it raises for Kant a number of questions: Why is
reality categorizable at all? How can we make synthetic judgments about our
experiences and claim that such judgments are not just valid for ourselves but hold for
everyone regarding their objects? Finally, how can we apply our logical forms to our
appearing, intuitable world? We do apply the logical forms of our assertions to what we
experience and use them to deduce what we can expect to experience. What accounts for
the success of such deductions? Furthermore, when our logical forms of inference are
ask how the resulting science of nature is possible. Put in terms of givenness, our
nature.
judgments about it. The objective validity of these judgments indicates the applicability
of their logical forms to nature. We can further see that if certain synthetic judgments
have an a priori, universal validity, i.e., hold for every possible object of experience, then
these forms will also have a corresponding validity. They will validly apply to every
true, a priori, that nothing occurs without its cause, then we are entitled to assert with
respect to every state of affairs: "If it occurs, then there must be a corresponding cause."
This implies that the form of a hypothetical judgment has an unlimited applicability with
regard to the occurrence of experiential objects. The same argument can be made with
regard to the form of categorical assertion if we can assert that, a priori, every accident
inheres in a substance -- i.e., every predicate we make must attach itself to a persisting
being. Put in this way, we can say that the question of givenness concerns that of formal
symbolic logic with its unrestricted applicability to all possible objects of experience.
Kant, in following the first aspect of his regressive method, explains such
givenness in terms of "the necessary and universal connections of the given perceptions
§19; Kant's Schriften, IV, 298). The explanation, in other words, is in terms of a
perceptions. By virtue of its obtaining, we possess the synthetic (or connected) unity of
the intuition whose objects confirm a particular type of synthetic judgment with its
particular logical form. Thus, as Kant writes with regard to that which determines the
Notes
148
synthetic judgment as necessary and, hence, as universally valid, "... this can be nothing
else than that [categorical] concept which represents the intuition as determined in itself
with regard to one form of judgment rather than another, i.e., a concept of that synthetic
unity of intuitions which can only be represented by a given logical form of judgment"
(Ibid., §21a; Kant's Schriften, IV, 304). Now, if we ignore the last few words of this
universal applicability of the logical forms to the world, we are first called upon to make
a "table" or list of those synthetic a priori judgments of experience -- e.g., the universal
judgment of causality -- which embody the basic logical forms -- e.g., the form of a
hypothetical judgment. We then are invited to interpret these judgments in terms of the
connections obtaining between our "given," i.e., our actually experienced, "perceptions."
These are to be taken as the connections which "determine" our intuition in its "synthetic
Tempting as this invitation is, it is one which Kant must eventually refuse when
he propounds his doctrine of "inner sense." The regressive method, having brought Kant
to the realm of "inner sense" -- i.e., to the realm of direct introspection -- follows its own
logic and moves him beyond this. Its logic is that of proceeding from the given to
explain the conditions of the possibility of such givenness. Now, for Kant, the regress to
the conditions of the possibility of what is subjectively given through inner sense -- i.e.,
through our reflections on our acts -- involves his teaching on the constitution of time.
ordering. It is by virtue of their ordering in time that the connections arise which yield
the synthetic unities of intuition. What this signifies is that temporal relations form the
whole of the sphere of what is proper to the subject. Time, thus, appears as the "formal
condition of inner sense." It is that in which the representations available to this sense
Notes
149
"must one and all be ordered, connected, and brought into relation" ("Kritik d. r. V.," A
99; Kant's Schriften, IV, 77). Granting this, a direct, phenomenological investigation of
such relations would seem to give us the subjective conditions for the possibility of
experience. In his section on the "Schematism," Kant does, in fact, provide an analysis
of the temporal relations which are required if we are to experience objects in conformity
with the categories. Yet, what we have called the "logic" of the regressive method moves
him beyond such analysis to inquire into the conditions of the possibility of time itself.
The move, in other words, is from inner sense, the last of the directly intuitable realms,
to the condition for its possibility as a field of temporal relations. Kant's teaching, here, is
that temporalization is one of the hidden, constitutive functions of the subject. Briefly
put, his doctrine is that being in time is not a feature of entities in themselves; it is rather
something which the subject adds to them so as to make their appearance possible. With
regard to our self-perception, this signifies that the temporal relations which we do
observe through inner sense are relations descriptive of the appearing, and not of the
acting subject considered "in itself." Inner sense is, thus, limited to the results, as
opposed to the underlying causes, of the self's activity. In Kant's words, "This sense
This statement follows once we admit, with Kant, that we, qua appearance, are
subject to the same conditions which we, qua active, impose to make appearance
possible. In other words, insofar as the functioning of the ego appears to inner sense, it
has already been subject to a second, hidden functioning which makes this appearance
possible. For Kant, the nature of this ultimate functioning is necessarily shrouded in
mystery. The most that can be said is that it is the constitutive functioning of the ego qua
conception of the ego as such a ground and his conception of it as nouminal, i.e., as
Notes
150
something beyond experience, imply each other. Indeed, as developed by Kant, they are
correlative conceptions.
Husserl's reaction to this final result of the regressive method is one of sharp
disappointment. The attempt to give "an intuitably redeemable sense" to the Kantian
claims about the ultimate conditions for the possibility of experience must be abandoned
once "... we call to mind the Kantian doctrine of inner sense according to which
method." For Husserl, the root of this incomprehensibility lies in Kant's unlimited
application of his method. Taken as a method which proceeds from the conditioned to its
be applied to those things which, for us, are the grounds of all evidence. It cannot, in
other words, be applied to appearance per se. The applicable principle here is, once
again, Fichte's. Given that "the ground lies, by virtue of the mere thought of a ground,
itself, count as evidence. Otherwise put: an evidential ground of evidence is, in a strict
Fichtean sense, impossible. This does not just express an analytical truth. For Husserl, it
points to the fact that we cannot follow Kant and separate Denken from Erkennen (See
Husserl to undermine the notion of evidence itself. If evidence in the strong sense exists,
then it must exhibit the quality of being self-evident (per se nota). It must show itself as
being a last ground for whatever assertion we make -- i.e., as something which declares
itself in need of no further ground outside of itself. To ask for a ground (or reason) for
some evidence is, thus, to declare that it is not evidence in the strong sense of the term.
If we further say with Kant that appearance is for us the basis of our evidence, but it
Notes
151
itself needs to be grounded on what does not appear, we have not just undermined our
notion of what counts as evidence, we have also undercut the ultimate comprehensibility
In its broadest terms, the Husserlian position can be described as a reaction to this
feature of the Kantian method. It embraces, first of all, Husserl's refusal to separate
Denken from Erkennen. This, as we noted, involves his position that the "being in itself"
of the object is equivalent to its being for us in its phenomenal presence. In other words,
such phenomenal presence is understood as the ultimate or final ground for the positing
of being (See above, ). Implicit in this position is the fundamental insight that
They must rather be taken as something radically given -- i.e., as a final source of
evidence. From this, there results the most basic definition of what phenomenology as a
method is. It is a refusal to step out of the determining priority of appearance. This
comparison between Kant and Husserl. Kant, we can say, must follow his regressive
method in spite of its obscurity. The method is the only way he can accomplish his goal
of grounding the possibility of synthetic a priori judgments. To see this, let us first recall
Kant's statement that the categorical concept or rule, which determines the intuition "with
regard to one form of judgment rather than another, ... can only be represented by a given
logical form of judgment." If we ask why this rule cannot be directly represented, i.e.,
Notes
152
Husserl agree. It is that such inspection establishes only an instance of a rule. It does not
establish its necessary and universal validity. Thus, inner sense, for Kant, can only give
hence, intuitively establish -- the necessity and universality of "the given perceptions."
The latter, however, is what is required if we are to ground a universal, categorical rule
and, with this, a universal synthetic judgment based on this rule. This fundamental
proposition is actually a basic insight into the nature of empirically based judgments. All
such judgments are limited by the fact that whatever can be established by experience can
also be overthrown by this same experience. The proof and the refutation are on the
same level, springing as they do from what we experience. Given this, experience per se
contains no guarantee that it will continue to validate the propositions which we draw
from it. For such a guarantee, we require a notion of an a priori of experience. This is
the notion of that which is universally valid -- not by being grounded, like empirical
propositions, on our given experience -- but rather by being the ground of the very
method, in its second aspect of proceeding to the nouminal, can ultimately satisfy.
Kant's and Husserl's agreement on this point provides the necessary basis for their
divergent positions. For Kant, the facticity of experience -- i.e., its empirical
nouminal ego, this being conceived as "the transcendental ground of the necessary
Schriften, IV, 93). In his "transcendental deduction," the necessity of the categories and,
with this, the necessity of synthetic a priori judgments are deduced from the uncombined
unity of the nouminal ego. It is not to our purpose to give the steps of this deduction.
Notes
153
We can, however, take note of its two fundamental premises. The first of these is Kant's
position that the ego's unity implies the unity of the appearing world -- i.e., a
"transcendental unity" of the synthesis of the world's appearances. This means that a
violation of the categorical rules for synthesizing appearances into such a unity implies a
corresponding violation of the ego's unity (See above, ). Its second premise is given
by Kant's assertion that synthesis or "combination ... can only be performed by the
subject itself since it is an act of its selfhood" (See above, ). The premise here is that
of the ego (or subject) understood as an active synthesizer, understood, in fact, as the
ground of synthesis per se. As we said, such a ground of synthesis cannot, itself, be a
world, the ego, then, must be uncombined. It must, in other words, be a simple unity, in
Kant's words, "a thoroughgoing identity." With this, we can say that the necessity of the
categorical rules for synthesis follows from a double implication. The violation of these
rules implies a violation of the ego's unity, but this unity is implicit in the thought of the
ego as the ground of all synthesis. Thus, if synthesis is to occur at all, it must, on these
premises, occur according to the categorical rules. Now, once we do have the necessity
of the categories and that of the corrresponding synthetic a priori judgments, the resulting
rationality (or lawful structure) of the appearing world must also obtain.
logic, i.e., the logical forms of judgment, to the world. It also includes the necessity of
consciousness. There is not just science as a fact. Science should and must exist.
15, ca. 1915). For Kant, this absolute consciousness is the individual subject, which, as
nouminal, is the sufficient ground of the lawfulness of the world and, with this, of the
Notes
154
grounding in the unity of this subject. Given this, we can also say that the eidos "world"
with its necessary rationality precedes and specifies the factual world of experience.
As is well known, all of these positions are explicitly denied by Husserl. His
refusal to follow Kant in his regressive method results in his limiting himself to the
empirical givenness of experience. It, thus, leads him to assert that we cannot establish a
necessary and universally binding a priori for experience. For Husserl, then, the facticity
absolute which we uncover is absolute 'fact' ('Tatsache')" (Ms. E III 9, Nov. 13, 1931;
Intersubj. III, Kern ed., p. 403). From this position flow his denials of the successive
elements of Kant's system. Thus, for Husserl, the pure, self-identical ego is not
determinative of the factual course of experience. Rather than being a ground of the
its stable rules of ordering experience, which give it its surrounding world. Concretely
speakng, it depends upon its "life," i.e., on its ordered stream of experiences. Now, this
"life" for Husserl is not such that it could guarantee the necessary continuance of the ego.
It has not the necessary a priori lawfulness. In Husserl's words, "... this life is not a life
which is ideally constructable, not, let us say a 'logical' life" (Ms. B I 32, p. 19, May or
Aug. 1931). Given the ultimacy of facticity, we must, indeed, admit, "'Factual'
consciousness has no law ..." (Ms. D 13 XXI, p. 137, 1907-09). It cannot fall under a
advance.
in the Kantian sense. Neither the necessity of synthetic a priori judgments nor that of the
Notes
155
applicability of logic to the world can be deduced from the presence of a pre-given,
unitary subject. Husserl's position on this point dates from the period which follows the
have to be considered as posterior to the givenness of experience; but, then, they would
not really be prior in the sense of being prescriptive of experience. Thus, as Husserl
laws which are based on the idea of nature (the nature which appears to us or the nature
which is taken as the basis for such types of appearance) naturally cannot prescribe any a
priori rules for the course of experiences ... they rather already presuppose the thesis of a
nature in order that they can be applied" (Ms. D 13 XXI, pp. 27-28, 1907-09). The
presupposition concerns the fact that experience has been so ordered as to make the thesis
of nature possible. As Husserl later expresses this: "And Kant's transcendental questions
concerning synthetic judgments a priori? ... Why must they be valid, whence their
"necessary and universal validity'? ... The factual (Das Factum) to which they can be
made applicable is a subject matter for itself and must itself give an account of itself"
(Ms. K IV 2, pp. 11-12, 1925). In other words, we must first see whether the factual can
instantiate such judgments before we can consider the extent of their validity. Without
this prior account of the factual, synthetic a priori judgments, understood as giving
essential laws, can only present us with possibilities. They express only hypothetical as
opposed to categorical (or absolute) necessities. Thus, Husserl writes, "Facts are, in
principle, incapable of being derived from essential laws; such laws, in the manner of
ideal norms, only specify facts with regard to possibility" (Ms. F I 14, p. 49, June 1911).
They specify, in other words, the possibilities of what would obtain, if certain factual
conditions were, indeed, given. They do not, however, prescribe the obtaining of such
factual conditions. In Husserl's words, "These laws ... cannot pronounce with regard to
an actuality -- i.e., whether or not there exists an actuality which corresponds to them.
Notes
156
Essential laws possess a meaning for the real if something real (an individual being) can
be given which falls under the essences, the ideas" (Ms. D 13 XXI, p. 26, 1907-09).
fundamental form is: if the factual course of experience is such as to constitute a unified
world and, with this, a unitary pure ego situated as an experiential center of this world,
then the Kantian laws springing from the presence of this unitary ego do apply. It is, in
other words, only at this point that the synthetic a priori judgments "must" have a
Each of the above points may be considered as implicit in the next statement.
Husserl writes:
Let us consider the following: When we proceed from factual nature and factual
consciousness, the phenomenological a priori consists simply in the essences of the types
of consciousness and in the a priori possibilities and necessities based on these essences.
The factual (das Factische) is the course of consciousness. This holds for every case,
whether or not this consciousness be sufficient for the constitution of an exact nature,
i.e., our nature, and whether or not it be, as well, one which requires this. ... It is also
clear, however, that appearances and, in general, the formations of consciousness must
proceed in a determinate manner in order for reason to be able to univocally designate a
nature within them, i.e., indicate that the nature should be placed under them. Prior,
then, to transcendental phenomenology, it is, therefore, a fact that the course of
consciousness is so structured that within it a nature as a "rational" unity can constitute
itself ("Beilage XX: Zur Auseinandersetzung meiner transcendentaler Phaenomenologie
mit Kants Transcendentalphilosophie," 1908, EP I, Boehm ed., p. 393).
The use of the word, "rational," points to the coincidence of the theses of rationality and
positing. For Husserl, as we recall, the positing of being is a "rationally motivated act."
It depends upon the stable rules of ordering experiences and, hence, on the essences
Notes
157
positing. Without the "fact" of experience proceeding according to such rules, there is no
actually obtaining a priori of nature; and, hence, there are no universally applicable
synthetic a priori judgments. As we quoted Husserl, these judgments are "understood ...
as essential laws" for the constitution of a nature. They specify the factual according to
the "ideal possibilities" of what can be constituted from its given, empirical course. But
as Husserl asks, "What use are these ideal possibilities which pertain to judgments, to
evidence, and the norms which they afford when a 'senseless tumult' is there, one which,
in itself, does not permit the cognition of a nature?" (Ms. D 13 XXI, p. 138, 1907-09).
Not just nature is dependent on the factual course of consciousness. Without the fact of a
nature "as a rational unity," there is also no ego which could be posited to observe its
collapse into a "senseless tumult" of experiences. Thus, Husserl asks: "What could the
ego be which has no nature facing it, an ego for whom -- if nature is not even given as
instead, be given a mere tumult of sensations?" (Ms. K IV 2, p. 14, Oct. 10, 1925).
Husserl's answer to this question has already been given. The ego cannot exist without
its centering environment. As he writes in the same manuscript, "a complete dissolution
of the world in a 'tumult' is equivalent to the dissolution of the ego ..." (Ibid., p. 10).
With this dependence of both the world and its egological center on the factual
course of experience, Husserl's denial of the remainder of the Kantian system follows as
a matter of course. Logic has not a universal and necessary applicability. It is not valid a
priori. As for the world or "nature," its rationality is not a priori determined. Hence,
natural science, conceived as expressing such rationality, is not essentially necessary, but,
indeed, only a fact. With regard to the validity of the logical laws, Husserl first notes
that "transcendental phenomenology reduces this validity to the essential connections, the
position approaches Kant's. As we recall, the logical forms of judgments are embodied
by the synthetic a priori judgments. The latter, for Kant, are also reduced to the essential
-- i.e., to "the necessary and universal" -- connections of consciousness. These are the
consciousness. The agreement ends at this point; since Husserl, with an eye to the factual
course of consciousness, goes on to ask: "Why must the logical laws have field of
back to consciousness, contains the grounds for a possible nature but none for a factual
nature" ("Beilage XX," 1908, EP I, Boehm ed., p. 394). Since facticity is an ultimate
ground of the unities of ego and world which would demand the applicability of logic.
The same point holds for the Kantian conception that the world must be rational.
For Kant, this a priori rationality stems from the rationality of consciousness -- i.e., its
following the categorical rules for combining perceptions. Its ultimate ground is the
nouminal ego conceived as an uncombined combiner. Having denied this basis, Husserl
must assert: "It cannot be demonstrated that consciousness must be rational. It is evident
from the essences of its acts that it must stand under norms. But that, according to ideal
normative laws, there must be produced a unitary and, hence, a rational order of
consciousness, that a nature must be able to exist, ... this is not 'necessary'" (Ms. B I 4, p.
2, 1908-09). In this passage, the norms referred to are only conditional necessities. They
specify the conditions which must obtain if there is to be a unitary, rational order of
consciousness. They do not, however, categorically assert that such conditions must
factually obtain.
Since the possibility of natural science depends upon such obtaining, Husserl
cannot, then, accept the Kantian "presuppositions" he lists in this regard. He cannot
consciousness. There does not just exist science as a fact. Science should and must
exist. Absolute consciousness must develop itself so that science is possible" (Ms. B IV
9, p. 15, 1915). Such statements would lead us to the idea of a rational, mathematically
describable nature. This nature would be the only nature possible and would have its
necessary existence from a consciousness which, broadly speaking, would follow a fixed
determinate rule for its syntheses. For Husserl, "Such a fixed rule of consciousness,
which would be indicated by this idea [of nature], need not actually be realized" (Ms. K
IV 2, p. 2', 1925; see also Ibid., pp. 7-8). On the contrary, as he elsewhere remarks, "... it
does not lie within the universal essence of subjectivity that it be related to one nature
and to the ideal, identical, 'the one and the same' nature, just as, on the other hand, [it
does not lie with this essence that] every subject must universally be related or be thought
of as related to the realm of the idealities" -- i.e., the ideal essences and corresponding
logical laws which would serve as norms for the constitution of such a nature (Ms. B IV
The relation Husserl sees between the factual world and the eidos "world"
composed of such idealities should now be clear. It is that "... the fact of the world (das
Factum Welt) ... precedes the essential-eidos world (Weseneidos Welt)." Husserl
explains this by immediately adding: "Every imagined world is already a variant of the
factual and can only be construed as such a variant; therefore, the invariant eidos of all
obtainable variations of the world is bound to the factual" (Ms. E III 9, p. 15, 1929). The
reference to "variations" relates to Husserl's method of intuiting the essences once the
latter are conceived as posterior to the factually given. The method consists in taking an
example of the factually given and varying it in imagination in order to examine the
essential limits of its type of givenness. Thus, to take his standard example, no matter
depends upon its appearing perspectivally. Now, for transcendental phenomenology, the
Notes
160
What this signifies with regard to the example is that the connections, which are
essentially required to set up this perspectival appearing, stand as the invariant eidos --
the "one in many" -- of all the imagined modes of givenness in which a spatial-temporal
object can be posited. Since this method starts off with the factually given, its variations
and, hence, the resultant eidos, are by definition bound to the factual. As Husserl later
expresses this, the "factual bares all the possibilities in itself, it contains the universe of
examples which govern all the variations" (Ms. B I 13, vi, p. 2, 1931). The factual, then,
determines the variations by giving them the examples which serve as their necessary
starting points. It provides the factual example which we can imaginatively vary so as to
Let us sum up Husserl's view of the priority of the factual by mentioning three
points which will be crucial for our later remarks. The first is that there is no necessary
were, then such an essence, understood in terms of the Kantian a priori for connecting
perceptions, would require that the subject constitute a specific world with a specifically
given essential structure. The necessity of this structure would be derivable from the
experience marked out by certain essential formations. But it is not a matter of insight
that actual experience could proceed only in such forms of connections. This cannot be
inferred purely from the essence of perception per se ..." (Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 114).
This follows because this essence does not present a determining necessity, but only a
possibility of the factual. The realization of this possibility depends on the actual
(or perceiving) consciousness. "Consciousness" here designates the concrete subject and
includes both the ego and its ordered stream of experiences. The ordering of the stream
has a number of possible variations, variations distinct from its present actual ordering
which need not result in the ego's dissolution. On the other hand, we have possibilities
involving types of existent worlds. These can be matched to those involving types of
experiencing consciousness. Thus, as Husserl writes, "... the correlate of our factual
experience, called the 'actual world,' shows itself as a special case of multiple possible
worlds and non-worlds which, on their part, are nothing other than correlates of the
essentially possible variations of the idea of 'experiencing consciousness' with its more or
less ordered connections of experience" (Ibid., p. 111). In other words, the actuality of
our given world with its essential structure is simply the result of the facticity of
Implicit in the above is the notion that the factually given connections of
forms could have been otherwise that the actual consciousness and its actual world are
only special cases, i.e., "possible variations." The status of the actual world as one of
many "possible worlds and non-worlds," thus, occurs in coincidence with the notion of
the contingency of the factual order of things.2 Our second point, then, is that, as
contingent character. We have already discussed this character at length. It is one which
leads Husserl to ask, once again in opposition to Kant, "Must there always exist an ego
("Beilage XIX, zur Vorlesung: Hat Kant wirklich das Grundproblem der Erkentniskritik
getroffen," 1908, EP I, Bohm ed., p. 393). Given that such "formations" or forms of
the end of his career: "But is it not apparent that the being (the actual existence) of
Notes
162
nature is an open pretension on every level ...? (Ms. K III 2, Oct. 10, 1935). In other
words, we constantly have the possibility that "the unity of nature resolves itself into
only empirically regulated matter with whose collapse we must come to terms" (Ibid., p.
10). With this, we have what we may call the third aspect of the phenomenological
The first aspect was given by us when we noted with Husserl that direct intuition
could never completely establish the thesis of the thing regarded as a noematic bearer or
"pure X." Such intuition could establish the present predicates of the thing, but not its
continual existence as their "bearer." The second aspect came through the
acknowledgement that the ego or subject to whom the thing was given was itself
contingent or dependent on the givenness of "the world of things, of objects." It, thus,
could not serve as its guarantor. Our third aspect essentially coincides with these two
grounded. Empirical experience cannot per se establish universal and necessary rules.
Such rules, however, are required if we are to establish the thesis of the thing as there,
i.e., as constantly affording us, from its being-in-itself, perceptions of a certain type and
ordering. As we cited Husserl, the thesis of the being-in-itself of a thing involves the
notion of "an infinite process of appearing which is absolutely determined in its essential
established, i.e., "the necessary and universal connections of the given perceptions"
which yield the ongoing intuition of the thing. Husserl's self-limitation to the empirically
Notes
163
given, thus, denies him the thesis of the inherent actuality of the thing. It makes all
positing of being a presumptive positing (See Ibid., p. 339-39). To put this in terms of
the remarks of our Introduction, we can say that Husserl's self-limitation to the intuitively
given leads him to the equation of being with being-given in intuition. From thence, it
idealism. Our third point is that insofar as this equation leads to the ultimacy of facticity
and its contingency, such idealism must stand oposed to that of Kant and his followers.
As Iso Kern expresses this: "In his interpretation of the facticity of world-constitution or
fundamental opposition to German idealism." For the latter, as represented by Kant, the
ego is prior to and determinative of the factual. For Husserl, the reverse is the case.
Regarding the resultant contingency of both the ego and its world, Kern expresses this
opposition as follows:
Insofar as Husserl teaches that world-constitution or, as the case may be, the ego who
possesses the world (the 'ego of transcendental apperception') does not, itself, have a
basis in a transcendental subjectivity which would make this constitution necessary and
permit the positing of the ego itself as necessarily possessing the world -- or, better,
insofar as world-constitution does not have a basis in a transcendental subjectivity which
could guarantee the genesis and continuance of this constitution so that there would not
continually exist for transcendental subjectivity the possibility of the dissolution of the
cosmos and the 'ego of transcendental apperception' -- there results for Husserl a concept
of transcendental idealism which is basically different from those of German idealism
(Husserl u. Kant, pp. 297-98).
A. A transcendental clue
Notes
164
As is well known, Kant never gave the problem of intersubjectivity any special
attention. The reason for this is clear. This problem, for Kant, is not really one at all,
since its solution falls so directly from his basic assumptions. If we reconstruct this
solution, we find, first of all, that the Kantian approach to the problem is remarkably
similar to Husserl's. But we also find that its solution is one which Husserl cannot
accept.
Insofar as Kant can be said to treat of intersubjectivity, his focus (like Husserl's)
we noted in the Introduction, such knowledge involves Others since for Kant (as for
valid judgment holds, not just for ourselves, but, as Kant writes, "holds, in the same way,
for everyone else" ("Prologomena," §18; Kant's Schriften, IV, 298). To claim such
validity for our judgment is, thus, to claim that Others judge (and perceive) as we do.
How is this claim to be secured? Both philosophers attempt this by a reduction to the
different manner. Kant's solution is contained in his asertion that the universal validity of
a judgment is secured if, "in this judgment, we know the object (even though, how it may
be in itself, it remains unknown) through the universal and necessary connections of the
which determines as a rule the connections of perceptions. The rule is understood as that
which first makes possible the synthesis of perceptions into an objective intuition; it is,
thus, seen as a rule which necessarily and universally holds for all intuiting subjects.
Therefore, once we admit its "a priori" character, we also admit Husserl's "harmony of
avail himself of this guarantee. His stress on the ultimate character of facticity requires
him to admit that neither "nature" nor the individual ego has any a priori guarantee.
Thus, with regard to the first, he writes: "... that there exists a nature, this is not at all a
priori: this, even though the idea of nature be proposed and the ontological laws
XXI, pp. 25-6, 1907-09). The same point holds with regard to the individual ego.
Speaking of "facts and possibilities (eidetic data)," he notes that "on the lowest level, we
do not yet have an ego, a person, a physical thing, a physical and a mental world" (Ibid.,
p. 124). For Husserl, there is no a priori guarantee that the factual and the possibilities it
contains will ever result in these. With this, we may formulate the special problem
possibility of an intersubjective harmony. Two pure spontaneities [of two distinct factual
courses of consciousness] can only accidentally and only for a time agree. In this
facticity, it expresses only a possibility: the possibility of Others being like oneself if
their factual courses of consciousness are the same. The establishment of a genuine
intersubjectivity requires not just the bare possibility of Others. It requires that the
conditions be given for their actually constituting as I do. It, thus, requires a real
similarity in the factual courses of consciousness that are present in myself and Others;
Notes
166
for only then would the essential possibilities which I find in myself be considered as
direction which Husserl must follow. It is one that we have remarked upon twice before.
The first reference concerned the assertion that transcendental subjectivity "does not
acknowledge an outside." This implies that to know such subjectivity, we must, in some
sense, come into coincidence with it, i.e., approach it from the "inside". The second
concerned the reveral of the Seinsrede.) This signified that the ultimately constituting
unique singularity. Here, we may express the same general point of departure in terms of
facticity. The above mentioned "problem" of facticity arises from locating its pure
harmony between individual subjects only accidentally possible. To place the pure,
by the individual. Granting, however, the ultimate quality of facticity as well as the
grounded quality of individual being, neither notion is warranted. Facticity can exist, on
the lowest level, without there being "an ego, a person, a physical thing ..." As the
"absolute" which Husserl uncovers, it is to be taken as the ground of these. The direction
which Husserl is compelled to take is, thus, clear. Our "clue" is that since Husserl cannot
beyond objective individuality. The solution, in other words, must come from an
poses for the establishment of an intersubjectivity. Let us put this in terms of a remark
which we made in the Introduction. We asserted "that the reduction, which raises the
problem of transcendental solipsism, overcomes this problem when pursued to the end"
to experiences solipsistically regarded as those which are mine and no one else's. As we
shall see, it overcomes this problem because, when we do pursue it to the end, it passes
beyond the objective individuality which is implicit in such words as "mine." It uncovers
the ground of such individuality in the impersonal facticity of experience. Now, the very
possibility of the reduction accomplishing this task rests on the following point: the
experiences. This follows because its dependence on a truly prior facticity is its
dependence on a level on which there is not yet an ego which could serve as a solipsistic
To establish this, we must first take note of the use Husserl makes of the
reduction in Ideen I. It is that of overcoming the "general thesis" of the natural attitude.
independently "available" (Vorhanden) for our various activities. As Husserl notes, this
is a perfectly general thesis, one underlying any particular thesis about an object's
up prior to any explicit thinking about objects. Husserl formulates it in the following
words:
Notes
168
The presently perceived, the clearly or obscurely presented [entity] -- in short, everything
from the world of nature which is experientially known before any [explicit] thought --
all this bears, in its totality and in every one of its articulated features, the character of
being "there," of being "available." This is a character which essentially permits the
with itself (Ideen I, Biemel ed., pp. 63-64). This agreement is with the character of being
there or available. The object, which is asserted to exist, is asserted as there, as available
When we inquire into our own availability, the answer of the natural attitude
object, our availability is simply that of a part of the spatial-temporal world. Within the
natural attitude, my assertion is: "I find constantly available, as something facing me (als
belong as do all other persons found within it and related in the same way to it" (Ibid., p.
63). We are related to it as parts of the same whole. As for the whole, it is the world;
and in the natural attitude, "'The' world, as reality, is always there ..." (Ibid.). If,
however, I take my being, not as a thing, but rather as the experiences I have of things,
they are experiences. Consciousness, here, is a kind of mirror. The contents which
distinguish it are only there by virtue of the thereness of the entity whose presence is
reflected in it. Thus, taken as a field of experiences, consciousness has only a dependent
being. Its availability is that of its object; it is there only if its object is present.
Husserl, in arguing against this position, proposes what can be called a thought
apperceptions of nature, but such as are continually invalid, apperceptions which are
cancelled in the process of further experience; let us imagine that they do not allow of the
harmonious connections in which experiential unities could constitute themselves for us"
(Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 132). Objectively speaking, the result is that, in thought at least,
"the whole of nature" has been "destroyed"; and this includes the "animate organisms"
(Leiber) of myself and Others conceived of as parts of the natural world. In other words,
with the disordering, "there are no more animate organisms and, with this, no human
beings (Menschen). As a human being, I would no longer exist and a fortiori there
would not exist for me fellow humans" (Ibid., p. 133). All the ordered connections
been nullified. Now, subjectively speaking, the results of this disordering can be
of a person. In Husserl's words, "If there would be something still remaining which
(Seinsgultigkeit). The experiences, then, would remain as pure experiences ... Even
mental states (Auch psychische Zustände) point back to the ordering of the absolute
experiences in which they constitute themselves ..." (Ibid.). The result is the cancellation
real mental states" (Ibid., p. 134). It is the dissolution of what Husserl calls the "personal
ego" -- i.e., the ego of the ordered connections which form the cogito. This experiment,
dissolution of the world in a 'tumult'," leaves us, in fact, with no ego at all. Its final result
capable of being constituted. Otherwise put, what we have here are simply experiences
Notes
170
whose connections have been abstracted from all ordering principles. Husserl, in the
Ideen, continues to call the stream of such experiences "consciousness." Yet the term
now has the sense of an egoless streaming. It denotes simply the elements from which
Husserl, the first result of this experiment is the reverse of the thesis of the natural
even when we disorder the patterns which make these into experiences of some thing.
Thus, consciousness, in the above defined sense, continues to be there, available for our
thought after we have eliminated the conditions for the availability of the thing.
Granting this, how can we say that, in principle, the availability of consciousness
depends on the availability of the thing, that its Dasein has as its essential condition the
latter's Dasein? As the experiment reveals, the dependence is actually the reverse. The
presence of the thing depends upon the presence of the ordered connections of
absolute in the sense that "... it requires in principle no 'thing' in order to exist" (Ideen I,
... it is evident that the being of consciousness, that of the stream of experience per se,
would indeed be modified by a destruction of the world of things, but it would not be
disturbed in its own existence. Modified, certainly! For the destruction of the world
correlatively means precisely this: that certain, ordered experiential connections and
also, correspondingly, certain connections of the theorizing reason which orient
themselves according to the former connections in the stream ... would be excluded. But
this does not imply that other experiences and connections of experiences would be
excluded (Ibid.).
Notes
171
In other words, what is absolute is the stream itself; this, no matter what possible
This absolute quality is also expressed by Husserl in terms of the doctrine that
and from which nothing can slip away, a connection which has no spatial-temporal
outside ..." (Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 117). This lack of an "outside" follows from the fact
that the spatial-temporal world and, hence, the whole basis for the notions of "inside" and
possible connections, including those which result in the notion of an "inside" and
"outside." Thus, the thought of a world as "beyond" it, as there "outside" of it, "is an
absurdity." (Ibid.). In fact, what we have here is the thought of consciousness as the
ground of the world. This result immediately reveals the nature of Husserl's thought
experiment. The latter is nothing more nor less than the actual practice of the reduction,
regarded in its second, ontological sense. As we quoted Celms, this sense is "the leading
consciousness" (Der phaen. Idealismus Hus., ed. cit., p. 309). These modes are the ways
in which experiences can be connected to make possible the presence of objective being.
Thus, the "being" to which constituted entities are led back is not that of the individual
ego considered in its pure, personal or real aspects. The thought experiment, which
experiences, reveals the dependence of both the ego and its world on such connections. 3
Once we disorder the latter, what remains as "absolute" -- i.e., as unconditionally given --
When we ask for the condition of the possibility of this reduction -- i.e., for the
guarantee that it can reach this "absolute" -- we come to the claim we made above: the
reduction is impossible without the ultimacy of facticity. Here, we can say that the
reduction is in the curious position of uncovering the grounds of its own possibility of
performance. To make this concrete, let us recall that it is this ultimacy which makes
this, "it is not," for Husserl, "a matter of insight that actual experiences can proceed only
in such connections" -- i.e., those connections which give us a coherent world (Ideen I,
Biemel ed., p. 114). Once we admit this, then the crucial step of the thought experiment
can be made. This is given by Husserl's assertion that the exclusion of these connections
"does not imply that other experiences and connections of experiences would be
excluded" (Ibid., p. 115). Indeed, admitting that any and every type of connection is
possible, the thought experiment can proceed to its end. If there is no a priori, binding
form for the connections of experience, then we can conceive of the dissolution of
everything posited through such connections. In Husserl's words, the lack of such a form
signifies that
it is thinkable that experience -- and not just for us, but rather inherently -- teems with
unresolvable contradictions, that experience, all at once, shows itself as obstinately
opposed to the demand that its positings of things should ever harmoniously persist. It is
thinkable that experiences' connections should forfeit the stable rules of ordering
perspectives, apprehensions and appearances and that this actually remains ad infinitum
the case, in short, that there no longer exists a harmoniously positable and, hence,
existing world (Ibid.).
Notes
173
Thus, once we assert the ultimacy of facticity and, correlatively, deny the existence of
any a priori (categorical) rules for connecting perceptions, two results follow. We have,
first of all, the possibility of conceiving experiences in abstraction from any binding
forms. We also have the possibility of conceiving such experiences in abstraction from
the world which is constituted through such forms. This second result is the possibility
We can put this in the negative by noting that the denial of the absolute quality of
facticity is equivalent to the assertion of an a priori form for perception. This follows
since this absolute quality is facticity's character of not being determined beforehand --
i.e., of not standing under a priori rules. If there are such rules pertaining to what is
factually given in perception, then the latter has a determining form. If it does, we have
the cogivenness of consciousness and the world. Thus, in our present state, we actually
which this is accomplished are a priori determined, then the givenness of the field of
consciousness necessarily implies such connections and hence implies the givenness of
the world which is constituted through these. At this point, the revesral of the natural
On this premise, both consciousness and the world are always co-available.
The same sort of argument can be applied to Husserl's reversal of the Seinsrede.
As we said, the reversal's point is the de-absolutation of individual, objective being. For
Husserl, such being is only "second." It is constitutively dependent on the being which is
this reversal, as we quoted Fink, is that individual, worldly "being is, in principle,
constituted ..." ("Proposal," ed. cit., p. 196; F. 201). We, thus, have to say, "The world,
Notes
174
taken as the totality of real being, ... with the multiplicity of being as stone, plant, animal
and human, ... is only a moment of that absolute." We assert, in other words, that "the
world has the sense of a constituted product, that, hence, it presents only a relative
'totality' in the universe of constitution" (Ibid., pp. 174-75; F. 175). Now, the world
produce it. Such determination would result in the co-givenness of consciousness and
the world. It would, thus, imply that the "thereness" and "availability" of consciousness
is not prior to the "thereness" and "availability" of the world and, hence, that
which takes it as "first" is, in other words, an implicit reduction. It states the reduction's
conclusion which is that this field is "first"by virtue of being the constitutive ground of
everything else. Granting this, the reversal must, like the explicit reduction, presuppose
grounds. As a streaming field, it "needs no thing" i.e., no constituted result of its action
-- "in order to exist." Now, if we take the practice of the reduction as that of
presence of the thing, we can see how the reduction demands such independence.
Without this, the point of its performance is lost. Thus, in suspending the connections
between experiences, its aim is to examine the experiences themselves. If, however, the
experiences were bound to the connections which form them into a synthetic unity,
bound so that their own presence depended upon the presence of such connections, they
could not be independently regarded. In this event, the thought experiment of the
Notes
175
reduction would not yield a residuum. The dissolution of the world in a tumult would be
equivalent not just to the dissolution of the connections through which it is posited, but
also to that of the experiences which occurred in such connections. It would, in other
words, leave us with nothing at all. Since we do have a residuum, we can say that the
pure experiences are independent of their connections. With this, we can assert the
grounding, it, too, implies Fichte's axiom of grounding: namely that the ground is both
distinct from and independent of what it grounds. Thus, if the ground -- i.e., the separate
constituting phenomena -- were not distinct from the grounded, then the constitutive
process would not result in anything new. It would be a process of mere collecting and
reassembling. It would not result in the presence of a synthetic unity with new
phenomena were not independent of the unities which they constitute, the constitutive
process would be impossible. As we recall, the process is the reverse of the reduction. It
ever higher levels. Thus, as the reduction descends level by level by bracketing the
establishing such connections. Its highest point is the thing with all its predicates and
external relations. It is its being in the world. Now, if the lower levels were dependent
on the higher in the sense that their givenness demanded the later, then the distinction
between the constituted and the constituting would collapse. We could no longer
distinguish between constituting experience and constituted object since our experiences
would not be there, available to us, without those connections which resulted in the
thereness of the object. At this point, we could no longer speak of constitution as the
Notes
176
progressive, ongoing production of something new -- i.e., the object as opposed to the
experiences we have of it. The very logic of its notion, thus, demands that the
constitution have the same premise as the reduction: that of the independence of the
constituting phenomena vis-a-vis what they constitute. The givenness of the former does
not necessarily demand the givenness of the latter, since the former can exist apart from
the latter. This, of course, is what we should expect. It follows from constitution and the
reduction being the reverse of each other. Both concern the same character of worldly
being, even though they regard it from opposite perspectives. The one concerns itself
with its possible dissolution, the other with its ongoing production. But they both
mention two further doctrines. The first is that of the dependence of the ego on its
surrounding world. This dependence is actually dependence of both ego and world on
thereby showing the dependence of the ego on this streaming. Thus, if we make the
reduction impossible by denying the ultimacy of facticity -- or, what is the same, by
the method by which we can exhibit that the individual ego requires its world, i.e.,
teaching that all constituted unities are contingent. The premise is that last grounds of
such unities -- i.e., the ultimate elements of experience -- are ultimately factual. This
means that they display with regard to the whole of the constituted world an
unconditioned givenness. It also means that none of the levels of constitution which may
follow them must do so as a matter of a priori necessity. Thus, the results of the
Notes
177
constitutive process must, one and all, be regarded as contingent. They may or may not
be constituted -- and this, no matter what level constitution has attained. This follows
because the phenomena on one level are not dependent on the connections which result in
the constitution of the next. Granting this, we have to say with Husserl, "But is it not
apparent that the being (the actual existence) of nature is an open pretension on every
level ... ?" (Ms. K III 2, Oct. 10, 1935, italics added). To express the same point in an
equivalent fashion, we may note again that insofar as the constituting ground is
considered as independent, it has no necessary tie to its constituted results. Given the
ground, we are not necessarily given the grounded. The final assertion of Husserl's
field of experiential elements, is based on the fact that its own givenness does not
demand that a constituted world also be given. Thus, from the point of view of the
ground, the presence of the grounded must be regarded only as a contingent and never as
a necessary result.
With this, we come to the fourth aspect of the phenomenological notion of the
contingency of being. It is one which encompasses the three which we have hitherto
from the separation of experience and object, of ground and grounded, which is inherent
in the constitutive process that results in being. The basis of contingency is, then, the
of objective being. We, thus, have to say that such an "absolute" can only ground
contingencies since its character, as an absolute which the reduction can uncover,
involves necessarily the notion of its undetermined independence or, what is the same, its
ultimate facticity.
Notes
178
which come to the fore. The first of these is that it is a concrete expression of what is
implied by the reversal of the Seinsrede. The reversal signifies not just the de-
absolutization of individual, objective being, but also the grounding of such on the being
because they are prior to such "things," constituting them by their connections.
We can develop this last remark into a definite conception of the absolute's
unity. As we earlier noted, Husserl places the basis of this unity in the constituting
connections of consciousness and not in the experiences and perceptual predicates taken
in isolation (See above, ). The latter are not what we intend when we intend the
"meant as such" -- i.e., the existing individual. Our intentions pass from experience to
object, from perceptual predicate to its "bearer." The former have, in this context, the
character of universality with regard to the latter. Thus, our experiences, taken in
isolation, can be considered as experiences of any number of objects. The same holds for
the perceptual predicates. They, too, can be taken as one thing applicable to many -- i.e.,
many possible "bearers" of their specific senses. In aiming at the individual entity, rather
than at such "universal" features, our intention comes to rest on the point of
universal elements into features of one specific entity. Granting that the thesis of
be made on the level of the experiences whose connections have been suspended in
thought. Such experiences, then, must be regarded as pre-individual, i.e., as before the
Another way of expressing the above is to say that the being of such experiences
is not that of one among many things, but rather that of one in many things. What is one
among many the character of numerical singularity. It is the sort of being which always
plurality of individual beings, one which always allows the addition of further members.
Thus, to take an example, the totality of men, conceived as a totality of individual beings,
is simply a collection. One can always conceive of adding another man to this collection,
and this addition is its real enrichment. We can also say that within the categories of
numerically singular being, the totality represents the numerical sum of non-unique
individuals. The fact that this sum can always be added to signifies that we cannot,
within these categories, grasp being as a unique singular -- i.e., a singular not having a
beyond. To achieve a conception of the latter, we must focus on the common elements
of being -- the elements which show themselves as one in many. This is being as a
predicable sense and, ultimately, being as an experience considered in isolation from its
connections. In strictly phenomenological terms, this point follows because sense, taken
connections with other such multiplicities would make it the sense of some one existent.
predicable of many existents. A fortiori, we have the one in many (or universal)
character of the separate experiences. Regarded apart from the connections which form
them into a predicate noema, they can apply to many such noemata and, hence, to the
multitude of objects which are apprehended through the connections of such noemata
Now, such senses and experiences are unique singulars vis-a-vis the multiplicities
in which they are present. Thus, to grasp the totality of men as a uniquely singular
whole, we must apprehend it in terms of the predicable sense which defines its individual
members. We here conceive of the sense as determining which entities are to count as
entities which fall under its notion. The same is the case with regard to the experience.
The multiplication of noemata and, ultimately, of things which exemplify its content
does not result in its own multiplication as such a content. It remains one thing, an
experience with a specific content, which continues to be present in many noemata and,
hence, in many intended objects. The focus on the being which does not have a
"beyond" is, thus, a focus on unconnected senses and, ultimately, on the unconnected
experiences (understood as experiential contents) forming these senses. Only such being,
as one in many, is not meaningfully multiplied by the many. In other words, since it
does not possess the individuality of things, it is not multipliable in the way they are and,
hence, does not possess a "beyond" as the latter do when they are grasped as collections
or numerical sums. Another man can always be added to the sum of man. But there is
only one defining sense of this collection if it is to be grasped as an all embracing totality
of a specific sort of entity. Granting this conclusion, these senses (and, a fortiori, the
pointed to by the reversal of the Seinsrede. Such unconnected elements manifest with
regard to the beings of the world the quality of unique singularity, of not having a
beyond. This, however, is precisely what we require to distinguish them from the
numerical singularity of the individual beings which they form through their connections.
statement, "The absolute which we uncover is absolute 'fact' ('Tatsache')" (Ms. E III 9,
ca. Nov. 13, 1931, HA XV, Kern ed., p. 403, ca. Nov. 13, 1931). According to Husserl,
Notes
181
"Facts (Tatsachen) are 'contingent'; they can just as well not be, they could be otherwise"
(LU, Tueb. ed., I, 122). As he elsewhere writes, this contingency embraces "every fact
(Factum) and, thus, also the fact of the world ..." (EP II, Boehm ed., p. 50). If this is so,
the question arises whether or not this embraces the absolute. Is the latter, qua fact, itself
contingent? Husserl's answer to this question is based on the "absolute" character of this
fact -- i.e., its character of being a ground for everything else. He writes: "The absolute
has its ground in itself; and, in its non-grounded being (groundlosen Sein), it has its
absolute necessity as the single, 'absolute substance.' ... All essential necessities are
moments of its fact (Factum), are modes of its functioning in relation to itself -- its
modes of understanding itself or being able to understand itself" (Ms. E III 9, Nov. 5,
1931, HA XV, p. 386). The import of this statement can be grasped by noting the nature
"this," rather than a "that," both of which are considered as equally possible for it. To
take an example, to regard it as a contingent fact that an object is here, we must view it as
here rather than there, and consider both locations as possible for it. Now, the
under the aspect of possibility. They are rather this aspect of possibility itself. They are,
in other words, that by virtue of which we can consider individual things as contingent.
Noetically, they are the ground of the possibility of any number of definite experiential
contexts. Noematically, they can function in the constitution of any number of objects.
By themselves, they are indifferent to the cogitationes and corresponding cogitata which
they can come together to form. These last, for Husserl, are merely expressions or, as he
Notes
182
experiences.
Here, we must recall that it is the separation of experience and object -- i.e., the
lack of any essential necessity in the tie between them -- which permits the experiences
to exist in any number of connected contexts. The ground of the possibility of such
because this being is independent -- i.e., has no further ground determining it, that
Husserl can call it a grundloses Sein. Its "absolute necessity" signifies its not being
considered as being determined in advance to produce a single "actual" world. Here, the
the contingency of such being. This means that the specific world which our connected
experiences form is merely possible, i.e., a contingent fact in the sense that it is possible
for it either to be or not be. To reverse this, we can say that the world's relation to its
ground, considered as a ground of mere possibility, is the reason why we can proceed
possibility and the ground's status as an "absolute necessity" are, therefore, concepts
implying each other. Hence, to view the given world in terms of its ground is to view it
Given the above, the absolute, rather than being conceived as a mere possibility,
ground for its actually obtaining. It is contingent upon the conditions which result in its
cannot be in this position. It is, through the connections which may obtain between its
Notes
183
elements, itself the condition of the possibility of all possible worlds and non-worlds.
We cannot, then, assert that such worlds are by chance, in the sense that their absolute
condition is itself a chance, i.e., something contingent. As Husserl writes, "... chance
Zufällige) signifies one of the possibilities, the very one which has actually occurred"
(Ms. C I, Intersubj. III, Kern ed., Sept. 21-22, 1934). The contingent implies such a
horizon because, grasped as contingent, it is grasped as a "this" rather than a "that." Its
very notion, then, includes the horizon of the "that" -- i.e., the possible ways it could
have existed. As such, its notion points to the possibility which includes all possibilities.
It points to the grounding field of experiences whose "pure" possibility remains after all
possible worlds have been rendered impossible by the suspension of this field's
-- cannot itself be contingent since it is, in fact, a ground of contingency. It is that which
This leads to the characterization of the absolute as the horizon of all horizons.
Here, it is thought of as the ground of all possible experiential horizons. The notion of a
horizon has been extensively elaborated by Husserl. Its basic concept is that of a series
of experiences which have been connected and, in their connections, determine the
further experiences which can join this series. Thus, in the appearing of a spatial-
temporal object, the experiences which we have grasped form the actually experienced
portion of a larger horizon. This horizon is composed of the experiences which can "fit
in" with the perspectival views we have already had. Such fitting in signifies, negatively,
that they do not undermine the theses already made concerning the object of experience.
Positively, it signifies that they join with our previous experiences so as to more closely
determine the object's sense. Every real object, taken as a unity of sense, has its horizon
Notes
184
This horizon is not just "internal" to the object; it is also what Husserl calls
"external." In the latter case, it concerns the individual object in its numerical
singularity, i.e., in its being one among the many objects of the world. As Husserl
describes this:
The experiences forming the external horizon link the sense of the object to senses of the
objects composing its surrounding world. The object thereby acquires its worldy sense
of acting upon other objects as well as having others act upon it. Even more importantly,
it is by virtue of this horizon that the object has the sense of one among many, its sense
Regarding the absolute in terms of this notion, several things can be said. The
first is that the experiences forming the field of the absolute are the ground of every
possible experiential context. It is by virtue of their possible connections that they form
a possible horizon of experiences. Separately regarded, i.e., regarded apart from the
specific connections which they can form, they thus can be regarded as an ultimate
horizon, one which involves all possible horizons in the manner of a ground. Here, of
course, we must add that just as the possibility of all possibilities is not itself a "mere"
possibility, so this absolute horizon does not have the same sense as the horizons it
Notes
185
grounds. The sense of the latter involves the notion of specific types of connections --
e.g., the perspectival. The final or absolute horizon abstracts from all specifically given
other words, its all-inclusivity is a function of this lack of differentiation. Such all-
inclusivity is, in fact, what allows it to function as the ground of the numerically singular
being of the thing. As all-embracing, the final horizon grounds the internal and external
The external horizon pertains to the thing "as a thing in the field of things" -- i.e.,
as a one among many. This "many" does not just refer to the things which are given in
an actual perceptual field. It refers as well to things with similar senses which could be
given through possible variations of this perceptual field. Thus, it includes, for example,
the variations of spatial and temporal position which would yield the thing as "there"
instead of "here," as "then" instead of "now." This cannot be otherwise since all the
determinations which would limit the final horizon to presenting just one set of objects or
conditions are foreign to its notion as an unconditioned ground. Thus, its grounding of
the thing as one among many includes, a fortiori, all the many possible ways by which
the thing could be given as a member of its class. With this, we may note that just as the
thought of a thing's contingency implies the thought of the absolute as containing all the
possibilities which the thing could have but did not realize, so the thought of the thing in
terms of its horizon of possible experiences implies the thought of the absolute as its final
horizon. In involving all the possible experiences involved in the thing's internal and
external horizons, this latter thought embraces the entire "perceptual world" with all the
possibilities of experience this involves. Such possibilities are the same as those of the
final horizon when we take our given, actually perceived world as contingent. Once we
do, the horizon of this world must be extended to include all the possible worlds which
Notes
186
happen not to be actualized. So extended, it reaches its terminus in the final horizon
For Husserl, the same conclusion follows even when we take up the natural, pre-
philosophical attitude and deny this contingency. In such an attitude, we regard the
world as all that there is -- i.e., as the absolute totality of existents which forms, qua
external to itself which could determine it -- i.e., determine it to become other than itself.
Husserl counters this view by examining what it implies. He asserts that the thing's
horizon still terminates in the absolute or final horizon; for, in maintaining that the world
exists as a unique singular, we have implicitly transformed its thesis. The thesis of the
if we do consider the world as all there is, then it cannot exist in the same way as an
individual thing. The latter is always one among many, but we are taking the world as
"the totality (All) of things ..." (Krisis, 2nd Biemel ed., p. 145). Thus, as the all-
embracing totality which cannot have a beyond, "... the world does not exist like an
entity, an object, but exists in a singularity for which the plural is senseless" (Ibid., p.
146). Granting this distinction in the manner of their being, "... there is," he concludes,
"fundamental distinction in the way in which we are conscious of the world and the way
in which we are conscious of the thing ..." (Ibid.). In apprehending the thing, we regard
it in terms of the horizon of possible experiences, i.e., the experiences which may
confirm its positing and determine it more closely. In apprehending the world, we regard
Things, objects are "given" as presently obtaining (geltende) for us (in some sort of mode
of ontological certainty), but in principle only in such a way that we are conscious of
Notes
187
them as things, as objects within the world-horizon. Each is something, "something
from" the world which is apprehended by us continually as a horizon. ... Every plural
and every singular taken from it presupposes the world-horizon. This difference between
the mode of being (Seinsweise) of an object within the world and that of the world itself
obviously prescribes a basically different mode of conciousness relative to each" (Ibid.,
last italics added).
its mode of presence as a world. Now if, in the natural attitude, we assert that the things
of the world are "truly existing," we can see how this necessitates the infinite extension
never otherwise." The thing, then, is "something from" the world, regarded as an
indefinitely extendable horizon, precisely because its own thesis demands the indefinite
extension of its own internal and external horizons. In other words, it is "of" the world in
the sense of its requiring the world as an unending horizon of possible experiences.
If we ask why we must regard the world as a horizon, indeed, as a final horizon
assertion of the world's unique singularity. The attitude assumes that only individual
existents count as being; it insists that the world is not existent as a horizon, but only as
the collection of such individuals. But this is incompatible with the thesis of the world's
an all-embracing totality, a totality that has no beyond. They form collections, pluralities
of beings, to which further members can always be added. To engage, then, in the thesis
of the world's unique singularity, we must reverse the usual sense -- the natural attitude's
sense -- of our Seinsrede. The being which is first, in the sense of being that from which
Notes
188
all others are, is not the world understood as a collection of entities. It is the world taken
the world as uniquely singular, we must regard it in terms of the experiences which we
described as having the "one-in-many" type of being. This is a being which is not
multiplied by the various experiential contexts which these experiences can form through
their connections. Only through such a regard, can we grasp them as forming a unique
totality, one which is not capable of being enriched by the addition of individual
have Husserl's conclusion. The thesis of the world as a unique singular has been
transformed into a corresponding thesis concerning the absolute as a final horizon. With
this, the thought of the thing as "something from" a uniquely singular world is itself
transformed. It becomes the thought of its horizon terminating in the final horizon.
It is not just that the experiences of consciousness are prior to the constitution of the
spatial distinction, "within" and "without." They are prior to every distinction which
which implies all particular experiential horizons, an absolute consciousness cannot have
anything beyond itself. It is, itself, that totality which the natural attitude assumes the
world to be; and this, in a far deeper sense, insofar as it grounds all possible worlds and
foreign to the absolute. This follows since the absolute is the ground of all
contingencies, all "facts," as well as being the ground of all essential necessities. It
grounds the latter insofar as it can, through its connections, result in a positable and,
hence, in a "rational" world with its particular essential necessities. It is what gives such
Notes
189
undetermined by them. In Husserl's words, "Its necessity is not an essential necessity ...
All essential necessities are moments of its fact (Factums)" (Ms. E III 9, HA XV, Kern
ed., p. 386, Nov. 5, 1931). The same sort of argument has been made about individual,
worldly "facts." The absolute is the ground of such facts in their character of things
which "could have been otherwise"; but as their ground, it is distinguished from them. It
is not really a fact even though Husserl writes: "The absolute which we uncover is
absolute 'fact' ('Tatsache')." Thus, he corrects the usage of this and similar statements by
writing, "Absolute 'fact'" -- the word, 'fact' (Factum), is, according to its sense,
improperly applied here; so also the word, "Tatsache," [literally: thing-done]. There is
no doer (Täter) here. There is only the absolute which also cannot be described as
[essentially] 'necessary.' The absolute lies at the basis of all possibilities, all relativities,
all limitations, giving them their sense and being" (Ms. C I, Sept. 21-22, 1934, HA XV,
Kern ed., pp. 669-70). Such possibilities, relativities, limitations are not "beyond" the
absolute insofar as it lies at their basis, i.e., stands as their unconditioned ground.
Precisely as such, however, it escapes these characterizations which are appropriate only
Since this relation is that of a ground, the examination necessarily concerns its process of
grounding individuals. In the Krisis, Husserl's favorite terms for describing this process
We shall learn to understand that the world, which continually exists for us in the
flowing change of modes of givenness, is a universal spiritual (geistige) acquisition. It
Notes
190
has developed as such and it also continues to develop as the unity of a spiritual form, as
a product of sense, as a product of a universal, ultimately functioning subjectivity. It
belongs essentially to its world constituting accomplishment that subjectivity objectifies
itself as human subjectivity, as an element within the world. All objective consideration
of the world is a consideration of the "outer" (im "Aussen") and grasps only what is outer
(Aeusserlichkeiten), i.e., objectivities. The radical consideration of the world is the
systematic and pure inner consideration of the subjectivity which "externalizes" [or
"expresses"] itself in the outer (der sich selbst im Aussen "äussernden" Subjectivitaet).
Krisis, 2nd Biemel ed., pp. 115-16.
The same sort of language is used in raising the question of the reduction to the absolute.
Here, too, the absolute is viewed as the "ultimate" subjectivity which undergoes a "self-
can it be made more concretely intelligible that the reduction of humanity to the
phenomenon, 'humanity,' which is included in the reduction of the world, allows this
subjectivity which ultimately functions at all times and is, therefore, absolute?" (Ibid.,
pp. 155-56).
The problem Husserl is raising with his question concerns both the world and the
individual subjects located in it. If, as the natural or ("life-world") attitude believes, the
world is the totality of all that there is, the reduction cannot find fitting terms for a proper
(Weltvorstellung) as the totality of our presentations of what is. 4 It also holds if, with
the natural attitude, we take the world as the totality of all that is. In the former case, our
abstraction empties our consciousness, qua intentional consciousness, of what is. In the
latter case, our abstraction of consciousness from the world is its separation from all that
is, including its own being! Furthermore, if, as this attitude believes, "To live in the
Notes
191
world is always to live in the certainty of the world," then an abstraction from the world
is an abstraction from all the certainty that life affords (Krisis, 2nd Biemel ed., p. 145).
In other words, the actual practice of the reduction appears impossible as a natural, life-
world activity. The individual subject, conceived as part of the world, cannot be
separated from it without losing all being and certainly concerning being. The
conclusion here is that either the reduction is not performable or, if it is, it cannot be
Thus, when Husserl asks about the subjective "life" which we live in the life-world:
How and in what manner can it be uncovered, how can it be shown as a self-enclosed
universe for its own theoretical and consistently maintained inquiry, how can it be shown
disclosing itself as an ultimately functioning, accomplishing subjectivity, the subjectivity
which is responsible for the being of the world, the world for us as our natural life
horizon? (Ibid., p. 149),
his answer is that it cannot be studied in the attitude of the life-world. In Husserl's
words, "The life that accomplishes the world-validity of natural world-life does not
permit of being studied in the attitude of natural world-life" (Ibid., p. 151). Such an
attitude makes the reduction incomprehensible. But the reduction is precisely what
makes the proposed study of this accomplishing life phenomenologically possible. What
of the attitude of natural life" (Ibid.). We must suspend this attitude's view of the world
-- which includes the notion of ourselves as individuals within the world's totality -- to be
The above gives the context for yet another passage from the Krisis where
The ground had become evident to us. The problem of the fundamental validity of the
world as a world, the world which is what it is through actual and possible cognition,
through actual and possible functioning subjectivity, had pe se announced itself. But
powerful difficulties had to be overcome in order not just to begin the method of the
epoché and the reduction, but also to bring them to a full self-comprehension and, with
this, to discover, first of all, the absolutely functioning subjectivity, discover it not as
human, but as that which objectifies itself in human subjectivity or, [at least] at first in
human subjectivity (Krisis, Biemel ed., p. 265).
The claim of this passage, which is a claim implied in our previous quotations, is that the
we take it as an abstraction of a finite subject from the world, which is understood as the
totality of finite beings, it levaves us, as we said, with nothing at all. Considered as a
reducing of the world to such a subject, it leaves us with a skeptical solipsism. The latter
follows because the reduction, so taken, becomes understood as a reduction of the whole
to a part, i.e., a limitation of the world to one of its components. At this point, the
individual. This alone is "proper" to the subject if we understand him as a mere part of
the whole. It goes without saying that such a subject can never be a ground of the being
of the world or its "fundamental validity." Qua individual, the subject is one among
many and, hence, is not in a position to be the unique ground of many individuals. It can
only be an individual or private ground of what it constitutes in its private acts. It, thus,
can only constitute a world "for itself" -- not an objective or true world (a "universally
non-solipsistic ground of the world is its possibility of proceeding beyond the individual.
The reduction is neither the abstraction of a finite consciousness from the world nor a
Notes
193
reducing of the world's totality to this finite consciousness. It is rather the attempt to
reach a consciousness to which we can transfer the quality of the world as a totality of
would allow to assert with Husserl: "We have actually lost nothing [through the
reduction], but have won the totality of absolute being which, properly understood,
contains in itself all worldly transcendencies ... 'constituting' them in itself" (Ideen I,
Biemel ed., p. 119). For Husserl, such a consciousness is "the domain of experiences qua
and yet without the boundaries which would separate it from other regions. ... it is the
totality of absolute being in the definite sense which our analyses have allowed to come
forward" (Ibid., p. 121). This sense is not that of an individual consciousness -- a one
among many. It is rather that of the domain of separately regarded experiences which
stand as unique singulars with regard to the individuals they constitute. We can, thus,
say that they are called "absolute essentialities" because they function as one in many;
they are elements which, in their own being, are not meaningfully multipliable by the
multitude of transcendencies which they can constitute. As our last section showed, only
such a "domain of experiences qua absolute essentialities" can have the unique
singularity which the natural attitude attempts to ascribe to the world. Thus, the
reduction of the world in its singularity can only be to consciousness conceived as this
domain. But at this point, it is not a reduction but rather a transfer of the quality of
The same point can be made by noting that "the fundamental validity
(Bodengeltung) of the world as world" springs from the assumption that the world is "the
totality of things." It is as such a totality that it is assumed to provide all the evidence
which could validate any particular proposition. It is because of this that it is assumed to
be a ground (Boden) of all validity. Now, the transfer of this quality to consciousness
Notes
194
arises by virtue of two insights. The first is that it is experience that validates. The
second is that the totality of things, i.e., the world, can only be apprehended as a horizon.
"absolute essentialities." It is from these, in their various possible connections, that all
validity (or obtaining) arises. The world's quality of being the ground (or root) of
validity is, thus, properly assumed by consciousness understood as the field of "pure," or
essentially regarded experiences. This cannot be otherwise, since it itself is the graspable
totality which the world claims to be when it claims to be the ground of all possible
validity.
separately regarded elements which form the domain of the absolute consciousness can
the presently existing world of individual existents. The "writing" of the world is the
insertion into time of the letters of this alphabet. More precisely put, it is the connection
of such experiences through their being ordered according to definite temporal locations.
Abstracting as we have done from the question of time, the nature of this temporal
ordering cannot be considered here. It will find its place as the subject of a following
chapter. As we shall see, this examination will require the performance of a reduction
which is parallel and yet distinct from the reduction we have just described (See below,
).
Our present description is, however, sufficient to give a first answer to the
question which naturally arises when we read Husserl's remarks about the subjectivity
number of ways. He notes that "the title, 'world,' does not apply to a, so to speak, private
Notes
195
the transcendental community of monads." He then asks "whether, with the analytical
ultimately determined ...?" ("Proposal," ed. cit., p. 175; F. 176). The question, in other
determination of constituting life, one not capable of being annulled by the reduction ...?"
Given that the reduction is supposed to reach the absolute, this is also the question of
"whether the absolute itself is divided into a plurality of members and [hence] subjected
to individuation -- or whether all divisions into pluralities of members are only self-
articulations present in the absolute which itself can finally only be thought under the
idea of the 'one'?" (Ibid., p. 176; F. 177). The same question, formulated in terms of the
individuality of the subject, is, according to Fink: "whether the individuation of the
positioned before all individuation ...?" (Ibid., p. 180; F. 182-3). The answer to these
questions should be clear. Insofar as we maintain that all individual being is constituted
characterized by (or "subjected to") the thesis of individuation. The thesis of individual
being is based on the connections of experience. It, thus, cannot apply to the
Granting this, we can pose with Paul Rocoeur a further question. It is: "In what
intersubjectivity?" (Husserl: An Analysis ..., ed. cit., p. 28). The elements which
provide an answer to this question have already been given by us. They may be put in
terms of three theses. The first is that the ultimate subjectivity is not an experiencing
Notes
196
subjectivity. As we quoted Husserl, "... there is no actor (Täter) here. There is just the
absolute ..." (Ms. C I, Sept. 21-22, 1934, HA XV, Kern ed., p. 669). In itself, the
absolute is the possibility of all experiential possibilities; it is the horizon of all possible
experiential horizons. As such, it is prior to the intentional acts or cogitationes which are
formed from the definite connections of experience. The absolute, we can say, grounds
the personally experiencing ego -- the ego of acts -- but is, as a ground, distinct from this
latter. Thus, the connections which make possible an individual experiencer are only one
the absolute. Our second thesis follows from this when we take this domain as a flowing
stream: Granting that the ego of acts is itself constituted, the constitution of the world
from the stream of experiences does not require an individual agent exterior to the
stream. For Husserl, both the acting ego and its surrounding world, which appears
through its acts, are passively constituted by the stream in its factually given relations.
The dependence of both on the facticity of the stream is one that concerns their being as
subjects. As Husserl expresses this: "If, proceeding systematically, we display from the
observed: We naturally presuppose the fact of the actual content [of experience] in its
streaming components with respect to the essential form [of the pre-given world]. This
holds just as obviously for the 'absolute,' transcendental intersubjectivity per se" (Ms. E
III 9, ca. Nov. 13, 1931, HA XV, Kern ed., p. 403). This passage concludes with the
remark we have already quoted. The absolute which is genuinely independent is not such
Before we consider our third thesis, let us note certain items with regard to this
egological fact. The latter follows when we regard it on the level of our "alphabet" of
experience -- i.e., as a horizon of horizons from which all temporal relations have been
abstracted in thought. It also holds when we consider it, as the above passage does, as
the "actual content [of experience] in its streaming components." As Husserl writes:
"The structural analysis of the original present (the lasting-living streaming) leads us to
the structure of the ego and to the underlying levels of egoless streaming which
constantly found it. It leads back to the radically pre-egological through a consequent
inquiry back to that which makes possible sedimented activity and to that which such
activity presupposes" (Ms. E III 9, Sept. 1933, HA XV, Kern ed., p. 598). These
underlying levels which "found" the sedimented structure of the personal or habitual ego
are prior to what they found in their factual course. They cannot be regarded as
springing from an egological source. Husserl, thus, asserts: "The primally streaming and
primally constituted non-ego is the hyletic universe [of actual experiential contents]
egological sources (aus Quellen des Ich); it, therefore, occurs without the participation of
the ego" (Ms. C 10, p. 25, 1931). This dependence of the egological on the factual
Our last item, then, is that insofar as such dependence on the factual results in the
in terms of his doctrine that "a complete dissolution of the world in a tumult of
experiences is equivalent to a dissolution of the ego ..." He asks, "What would an ego be
which has no nature facing itself, ... which, instead of this, would be given a mere tumult
Notes
198
of experiences?" He observes that in such a case there would be no Others for me.
There could not be since I would no longer exist. As he puts this in a pair of rhetorical
questions: "And could such an ego have other egos alongside of itself, indeed, is a
plurality of egos thinkable here? Would not the recognizing ego, for whom this plurality
same point holds for Others considered as egos like myself. Insofar as they are
understood not just as objects for me, but as subjects like myself, they are, as I am,
dependent on the pre-egological levels which found the ego. Their being as real,
personal and pure egos is contingent on the factual givenness of the "hyle" not being that
of a tumult. Such a tumult would make impossible the ordered unity of experience
known as the cogito. It would also rule out any notion of the pure ego as a center or pole
With this, we can give our third thesis: The ego, which appears as a personal and
pure experiencer of the world, appears only when the experiential stream -- Husserl's
world of experiences which, through its connections, allows of a distinct point of view.
sense, it is a world whose experiential horizons have been so structured as to place the
subject in their center. It is, we asserted, from the vantage point of the here and the now,
i.e., from the point of the spatial and temporal center of his experiential horizons, that the
pure subject first can appear as an experiencer (See above, ). This can also be put in
terms of Husserl's double assertion, namely: 1) "The pure ego is, we expressly stress, a
numerical singular with respect to 'its' stream of consciousness" and 2) "... every pure ego
has ... the human ego has personhood (persönlichkeit) as its surrounding object (Ideen II,
Biemel ed., p. 110). The individualization of the stream into one's own stream is its
Notes
199
arrangement so as to form a distinct point of view, a 0-point or center in space and time.
cogitationes and, with this, the personal ego of acts. In other words, it is the constitution
of the acts which present one with one's own surrounding world -- i.e., the world in
which one is positioned as a center and in terms of which one can interpret oneself as
"real." As we observed in our last chapter, the pure ego, although not itself constituted,
can only appear when the conditions obtain for the presentation to it of its surrounding
subjects at the level where the conditions for this plurality obtain. At the constitutive
level where the conditions do not yet obtain -- Husserl's "radically pre-egological" level
-- subjectivity is not yet a plurality. At this level, however, it is also not yet an
concealment. The individual subjects in which it has objectified itself express particular
points of view. They are tied to the finite surrounding worlds which define them. They
are, thus, led to interpret themselves in finite worldly terms. They understand themselves
as individual beings among the beings of the given world. This self-interpretation is both
incorrect insofar as it fails to note the ground of this status. With regard to its
myself as experiencing a world in my experiences ..." (Ms. C 7 II, p. 19, ca. June 15,
Notes
200
1932). This inconceivability comes from the fact that the world is my defining condition
noted, tied to the preservation of my surrounding world. Given this, "there is always the
real world; every ego must construct it (aufbauen) and itself ..." (Ms. C 17 V, p. 24,
1932, italics added). Without it, the ego could not preserve its individual being. In other
words, the fact of its being an individual involves necessarily the fact of the world as the
beings. It must constitute beings. What sort of 'must' is this? The fact of this world, the
fact of this I (ego), this cogito and the fact of this stream, the stream of historicity
(Geschichtlichkeit) which is this ego and from which it came to be and is becoming"
(Ms. K III 1, viii, pp. 4-5, 1935). The "must," then, springs from the fact of the
constitution of the ego and its defining world through the "historicity" or occurring of the
stream. The presence of the ego as a being signifies that the stream is constitutive of
beings. On the objective level the ego is, thus, perfectly justified in interpreting itself as
a being among the beings of the world. Furthermore, since the givenness of the world in
such constitution is itself a condition of the ego's individuality, the world along with its
"Others" is not something given to it as if the ego could exist apart from the world. The
world is rather always something already there -- i.e., something pre-given to it. This
signifies, in Husserl's words: "I have 'the' world pre-given [to me], pre-given in my
intentional life. There pertains to this pre-givenness, i.e., to the pre-given sense of this
world, that fellow human beings belong to it, to my world, that I myself am objectively
As justified as this view may be, it is a concealment of the absolute -- i.e., the
egoless streaming -- which objectifies itself in the individual subject. Husserl describes
the nature of this concealment in a number of ways. Speaking of the absolute's "self-
Notes
201
individual development from birth to death ..." (Ms. A V 10, p. 20, Nov. 9, 1931). The
individual subject has, in other words, a defined "lifetime." It is a period of time between
birth and death which locates the individual within the natural succession of generations
(See Ms. K III 12, p. 38, 1935). As such, the ego's life is conceived as a mere section of
world-time. Now, what the individual in his self-interpretation fails to realize is that this
depends upon the prior constitution of objective, worldly time. It further requires that
subjects be constituted as incarnate, i.e., as possessing bodies which are subject to birth,
growth and decay. For Husserl, this means: "Death pertains to the duration (Bestand) of
event in the world of humans, in the constituted world" (Ms. A V 20, pp. 23-24, Nov. 18,
1934). This does not make death (or birth) any less of a human necessity. But it does
point out the fact that "the difference between [a] lifetime and world-time is egologically
constituted, the first a mere section of the second" (Ms. C 8 I, p. 16, Oct. 1929). As
constituted, a finite lifetime cannot pertain to the constituting level, the level at which the
absolute functions. Here, in fact, Husserl speaks of the absolute as "preserving" itself,
qua egological constitution, in its objective "modes," the latter being the constituting
lives of individual subjects. The notion is one of the "universal self-preservation of the
absolute in [its] lasting and remaining constitution, renewing itself in each individual
person (from birth onwards) as an invariant self-constitution ..." (Ms. C 17 V, pp. 22-23,
1931). As Husserl also expresses this, we have the thought of "the absolute persisting in
eternity in the eternal changes of its modes, at first through ordinary birth and death, but
also through the birth and death of humanities, etc." (Ibid., p. 47).
Notes
202
These statements point out the fact that a finite lifetime, which is a necessary
concealment of itself in its pre-objective, unlimited character. With regard to the latter, it
must be observed that the notion of the absolute as persisting and preserving itself
through individual lives should not be taken as implying that the absolute is, itself,
contingent on the presence of such lives. As already indicated, the absolute per se is not
every dependence, including that on individual lives. For Husserl, then, "the
transcendental totality of subjects is contingent ...," not the absolute ground of such a
totality (Ms. K III 12, p. 39, 1935). This, at least follows once we take the absolute in its
character as streaming field of experiences whose elements form the alphabet for
constitution of organic bodies capable of birth and death. Actually, the constitution of
the sense of my own birth and death proceeds through the apprehension of these
phenomena as pertaining, first of all, not to myself, but to Others in their embodied
character. Despite its mediated quality, this constitution does require that I possess, like
my Others, an organic body; and this brings us to a further aspect of the self-concealment
objectification as the 'soul' of its natural body and as a soul which, in its psychologized
(psychologisierten) being for itself, conceals in a certain way even its mental
known in terms of a horizon, a person of a mental life which brings both nature and
world to appearance in concealed ontical and noetic horizons" (Ms. A V 10, pp. 20-21,
Notes
203
Nov. 9, 1931). The reference to the "psychologized" being of the soul most probably
According to its arguments, the soul itself is a real, worldly being. Like other such
beings, it is subject to the laws of material causality. Its quality of being intentionally
related to the world -- i.e., of intentionally bringing it to appearance -- is, thus, concealed
Husserl's mention of the soul's knowing both itself and its world in terms of
horizons brings to the fore yet another aspect of the concealment of its ground. As a
finite expression of the absolute, the individual's access to both time and space is finite.
His lifetime is limited, is only a "section" of world time. Because he lacks the time to
explore, his access to the world's spatial dimension is also limited. In Husserl's words, he
"lives ... in a 'finitude' in which the 'infinitude' of being is concealed" (Ms. A V 10, p. 21,
Nov. 9, 1931). Another way of putting this is to say that he lives in a world which has
the quality of being both known and unknown. He experiences it as a horizon with a
central, familiar core surrounded by undefined areas which he has not yet explored.
Now, as Husserl observes, this conception of "the finitude of the surrounding world," of
the world's being actually explored only in part, is correlated to its sense as presumptive.
which would establish the theses of its beings. Here, of course, "finitude" has a special
from the point of view of pure experience, does not signify an abstract limitation
(determination and negation) of the cosmic infinitude ... Rather infinitude is already
present in each individual reality of the surrounding world [when taken] as an intentional
unity with an open horizon. In this open horizon, there is already present, in a certain
sense, the ideal infinity ..." (Ms. A VII 21, p. 8, June 10, 1933). This "ideal infinity"
Notes
204
refers to the infinitude of experiences required to establish the entity's "being in itself."
Given that the thesis of such being is actually that of a Kantian idea, the horizon of
available to me (See Ms. B III 7, p. 7, 1933). The same point holds, a fortiori, for the
world as a whole. Even if I were to assert that the realities of my finite surrounding
world are actually existent "in themselves," it would still be the case that "the existence
of the cosmos would lie under a presupposition," namely that of the "possibility of [my]
was tied in Husserl's thought to the contingency of the world which the absolute grounds.
We can now put this point in terms of the self-concealment of the absolute. The horizon
of the absolute is all embracing. As such it excludes the notion of contingency. The
horizon of the world which the individual subject actually experiences is finite. It is
something which the subject can only piecemeal experience and make actual to itself.
The second horizon thus acts to conceal the first. This concealment is simply a function
finite access to the world. Each is finite by virtue of being spatially embodied and,
of such finitude, each must experience the world, and himself within it, as a mixture of
the known and the unknown -- i.e., in terms of the second, finitely experiencible horizon.
By virtue of this last, each must regard the world -- the totality of beings and subjects,
including himself -- under the aspect of contingency. Taking the totality of the world as
the ultimate self-expression (or objectification) of the absolute, there is, then, a double
the Heideggarian themes of the "thrownness" and "finitude" of human experience. For
Husserl, the individual is thrown into the world since it is "there" before him, pre-given
as his condition. He is not free in its constitution; the ego must necessarily "construct it
and himself." Such construction, however, proceeds under the conditions of finitude.
All of the finite subject's experiential acquisitions are regarded as contingent and relative.
None of them has the stamp of permanence. This living "horizonally" -- i.e., living "in
the consciousness of finitude in an infinite world" -- is, for Husserl, the basic "structure
... living as a human being, I am conscious of myself as a finite creature in the infinity of
the spatial-temporal world. This world, however -- this infinity, which is known in the
manner of a horizon and which, in all living access to the horizon, remains ad infinitum
in its horizonality -- is constantly concealed even in [its] constant disclosure. And
everything is concealed, even the quite well known, even one's own human being
(Menschsein), one's own bodilyness, one's own being as an ego; they are always in
finitude, in the relativity of obviousness and hiddenness, and this according to each and
every [feature]. This is the structure of human existence (Dasein als Mensch), of the
existence of the world for it; and there also corresponds to this, in a worldly sense, the
structure of the soul's world-consciousness; there corresponds the structure of each
possible world-conception as something finite in a horizon of infinite cognitions, as
something which exists in a relativity in which no cognition is final" (Ibid., p. 21).
These remarks may be compared to Heidegger's when the latter asserts that "being," as
revealed by Dasein, "is essentially finite" ("Was ist Metaphysik?", Wegmarken, Frankfurt
As Husserl constantly asserts, the "pre-givenness of the world" does not just
involve my own presence as "objectively real within it," but also that of Others, of fellow
Notes
206
human beings belonging to it (See, e.g., Ms. C 17 II, p. 5, ca. Jan. 1, 1931). This pre-
givenness of Others as independent subjects "in and for themselves" is, as we shall see, a
For the natural attitude, the presence of Others is taken as a simple given of
experience. Others, from our earliest experience, are given as parents, relations, siblings,
etc. The presence of one generation is seen as biologically necessary for the next. What
of the epistemological necessity for the presence of Others? Activities, such as teaching
and learning, do require Others; though, this, of course, presupposes that we all share a
terms of its fundamental proposition that every reality is a being in itself. To be such is
to be objectively real; but this is also to be real for everyone. It, thus, adopts the Kantian
equation of objective and universal validity (validity for everyone). As Husserl puts this:
"The world in the natural attitude is experienced with the sense: the world for everyone,
the world which, therefore, everyone can experience and think of as the same and which
everyone must insightfully determine as the same when they do experience it with
individual realities, of each of the beings of itself" (Ms. K III 12, p. 36, 1935). Here, the
When we first take up the transcendental attitude, the necessity for Others is
considered along similar lines. It is thought in terms of the equivalence of being and
being given. The being of the world in its infinite extent seems to involve the necessary
Husserl expresses this in a number of ways. What is common to them all is the
dialectic of finitude and infinitude which characterizes human existence in its horizonal
structure. We have, first of all, the dialectic of the finitude of my lifetime vis-a-vis the
infinitude of world-time. As Husserl writes: "My life becomes a human life in the
Notes
207
world ... My life in its open infinitude is, indeed, finite in and according to objective
spatial-temporality. It will cease as a human life in the world; I shall die." (Ms. C 8 I, p.
22, Oct. 1929). Granting this, the question is: What is the relation of my worldly
finitude to the world's infinitude? Husserl's answer to this is twofold. On the one hand,
he points out that the sense of my finitude, i.e., of my lifetime as bounded by birth and
death, requires the apprehension of Others for its constitution. He asserts, on the other
hand, that the constitutive sense I do have of Others and, corresponding to this, my sense
the sense of my own finitude. Self and Others, finitude and infinitude, are, in other
words, correlative concepts. They are concepts which are involved in a dialectic where
Thus, with regard to my sense of birth and death, Husserl notes that these are not
as a beginning, one would have to experience what went before it. But before such a
beginning, there is, by definition, no such experience available to me. The same holds,
mutatis mutandis, for the case of death. The underlying point here is that "life and death
are in objective time and limit the temporal existence of every human being, i.e., limit its
human duration which, like every objective duration, has its relations of coexistence,
overlapping, length and shortness, etc." (Ms. C 8 I, p. 23, Oct. 1929). In such objective
time, to experience the beginning or the end of something is always to experience its
before and after. In terms of organic life, it is to experience the birth of a living body by
having an experience of what preceded it. Similarly, it is to experience this body's death
by being aware of that which follows its organic cessation. Given that organic birth and
death have the worldly sense of the beginnings and ends of objective experience, they
cannot be personally experienced. Their worldly sense can only be given in a mediated
Notes
208
fashion. This sense can be constituted only by my drawing an analogy between the
organic birth and death of Others and the fact that I myself am an embodied subject. The
conclusion, here, as Husserl expresses it, is that "my death as a worldly phenomenon can
only be constituted for me when I experience the death of Others ... The death of Others
is the death that is constituted prior to this. Just so in the case of the birth of Others " (A
VI 14, p. 3, 1930). Since birth and death do bound my lifetime, my sense that I have a
Others that I have "the constituted difference between a lifetime and world-time, the first
a mere section from the second" (Ms. C 8 I, p. 18, Oct. 1929). From this, my "essential
finitude" is easily derived. Its worldly sense is that of my having a finite access to the
world; but this is inherent in my having a finite lifetime. As Husserl expresses this
conclusion:
My essential finitude shows itself here in the fact that I (and we) can reach in original
experience only a finite part of nature as my natural surrounding world, although this
part is, in its way, an open non-bounded part. If I perform a primordial reduction [i.e., a
reduction to what I can directly or primordially experience], I, thus, get a finite nature or
world. Certainly this finitude is concealed so long as my birth has not been discovered,
so long as I have not brought into play the co-being (Mitsein) of Others (Ms. C 17 II, p.
7, ca. Jan. 1, 1931).
Having asserted that the sense of my finitude requires Others for its apprehension,
we can reverse this proposition. We can say that my sense of Others has its
phenomenological basis in the sense I have of my own finitude. To make this point, we
must first observe that my finitude implies my living in the world as a finitely accessible
horizon. As we just quoted Husserl, my finitude shows itself in the fact that I can
directly experience "only a finite part of nature." This part is recognized as such because
Notes
209
it is seen as included in a greater whole -- i.e., that of the world which surpasses each of
its parts. Now, to live in the world as a finitely accessible horizon is precisely to
of what would be available if one's lifetime were extended. Here, the familiar core of the
subject's "surrounding world" is always bordered by the progressively less well known.
Husserl puts this in terms of the "if-then" quality of subjective experience. He writes:
Everything, both the consciousness of being and the assertion of being, rests on
presumptive certainties in relation to my 'I can' ... If my powers were extended on
and on, then something new and a new 'I can' would enter into the experiences
which spring from the new and then the presumptive certainties would also
disclose themselves according to the style of my experiencing life, the life which
constitutes in experience (Ms. C 8 1, pp. 18-19, Oct. 1929).
This "if ... then" quality signifies my continual sense of the hypothetical character of my
"I can." My "I can," in thought, can always be extended; and, with this, the thought
arises that, were it actually extended, a new "I can" would arise. This very thought is the
who experiences "only a finite part of nature." Because of this I always experience the
world as a finitely accessible horizon, a horizon which I explore part by part but which
Once we express our finitude in these terms, it becomes a motivating basis for our
positing of Others. Two elements of this basis are 1) the correlation of the world to my
"I can," and 2) the surpassing quality of the world. Both are involved in my sense that it
that the world ever achieves any certainty of being. Now, such certainty of being is the
motivating goal of all my positing. This follows once we recall that the unity of my ego
Notes
210
is correlated to the unity of the world in which I find myself. My ego's active striving for
self-preservation is, when noematically regarded, also a striving for the harmoniousness
words, my "will to live" (Wille zum Leben) is also a "will to true being" -- i.e., the being
of which I can have some certainty (Ms. E III 9, Nov. 5, 1931, HA XV, Kern ed., p.
378). We thus, have, on the one hand "... the ongoing style of an ego which, in the
On the other hand, we have its striving "to bring all its experiential certainties with every
experiential content into a harmonious, universal certainty, albeit through the correction
[of such certainties and content]" (Ibid., p. 404, Nov. 13, 1931). The all-pervasive
quality of this striving towards harmoniousness and, hence, towards the establishment of
being is noted in another manuscript of the same year: "And, indeed, a tendency
being qua constituted unity] pervades the whole, a tendency towards the overcoming of
disharmoniousness, towards correction" (Ms. B I 32, p. 13, May or Aug., 1931). Given
this, we can say that the establishment of certainty of being through correction is the
motivating goal of all intentional life; it is what all my attempts at positing are striving to
achieve.
When we put this together with the fact that my primordial certainty of being is
have the motivating basis for my positing of Others. By myself, I can have only a
hypothetical certainty of being. The goal of my positing is, however, an actual certainty.
This goal motivates me to posit Others as subjects like myself -- i.e., as possessing the "I
Notes
211
can," whose actual extension is required for actual certainty. Such positing can, thus, be
looked upon as a transfer to Others of the sense of my "I can" with the result that my
contained in this spatial-temporal infinity [of the world], but contained within it as a
finitude. It is through Others, namely, and through their experiential data which I 'take
over,' that my at first finite world in space and time, my experiential world, constantly
expands itself" (Ms. C 17 II, pp. 1-2, ca. Jan. 1, 1931). As he also puts this: "The
The motivation for this transfer can be expressed both on a natural and a
transcendental level. If, in the natural attitude, "to live is always to live in the certainty
of the world," then the very structure of my being in the life-world requires the presence
of Others. This follows because the world appears as the final ground of all my
certainties, but I myself, in my finitude, cannot maintain the thesis of the world -- the
world as the totality of all there is. For this (so I assume) I require Others, fellow
subjects by means of which the world can be extended ad infinitum. The same
expressed through the notion that being is equivalent to being given. The world is given
What we are confronted with is a nexus of three interrelated themes: the world's
surpassing quality, my finitude vis-a-vis the world, and my positing of Others as subjects
actually distinct from myself. Quite apart from any question of motivation, we can say
my finitude. This point follows directly from Husserl's analysis of the "analogizing
have, first of all, a pairing of my animate body in the here and the there. We then have
the pairing of the Other with myself in the there. It is by virtue of this second pairing
that I posit the Other perceiving "the same nature, but in the mode of appearance: as if I
stood there where the Other's body is" (CM, Strasser ed., p. 152). Now, the first pairing,
position, to change a given there into my here. It is, we can say, part of the hypothetical
character of my "I can." In distinction to this, the second pairing involves the actuality of
the Other's being there. He is taken as actually being in the position which I could
hypothetically occupy, were I to change my position (See above, ). With this, the
sense of my own finitude enters to play its indispensable part. As an embodied subject, I
am limited, at any moment, to one definite position. I cannot be in two distinct locations
simultaneously, which means that, outside of the actuality of my present "here," all other
positions are grasped as hypothetical -- i.e., as possible positions which I could have, but
did not realize. Without such finitude, my "I can" would, thus, not have its hypothetical,
"if ... then" character. But without this last, the world would not have its
phenomenological character of always surpassing me. Furthermore, the fact that I cannot
simultaneously be both in the here and the there means, for Husserl, that the Other I do
finitude is, thus, an essential element in my apprehension of both the surpassing quality
of the world and the equally surpassing quality of Others as present within this world.
Such Others are posited as subjects directly experiencing those portions of the
world which are outside of my grasp. This is inherent in their surpassing quality being
tied to that of the world. We, thus, come to Husserl's frequent assertion that the
givenness of the world in its surpassing, horizonal quality is, correlatively, the givenness
Notes
213
of Others. Their givenness, as we quoted Husserl, "pertains ... to the pre-given sense of
this world." This sense is one which I acquire through my horizonal experience of the
world -- i.e., by virtue of the fact that my own givenness as a subject in the world is one
of living "in a 'finitude' in which the infinitude of beings lies concealed" (Ms. A V 10, p.
21, Nov. 9, 1931). Others, then, are implicit in the world as the Others to whom this
infinitude can presumably be given. They are implicit in me insofar as I live in the world
grasp. Thus, Husserl, in explicating the notion of "living as a human being in the world,"
writes: "The world for me = the world of 'all of us' ('Wir alle'), the 'all' which exists for
me, which is implicit in me" (Ms. D 14, p. 8, March 1931). As he elsewhere puts this:
"My consistent pure self-knowledge as a bearer (Traeger) of the world which exists for
me and is valid for me also conceals in itself a pure knowledge of fellow subjects, fellow
validators-bearers [of the world] ..." (Ms. B I 14, xi, p. 22, Sept. 1935).
Others being implicit in what we earlier called, the "second, intersubjective sense" of the
world's transcendence (See above, ). On the ultimate level which corresponds to the
absolute, it has quite a different import. Here, the implication of Others as fellow
concealment of the absolute. The first indication that this is the case can be given by
recalling our remark that self and Others, finitude and infinitude are dialectical concepts.
By this is meant that the full development of the sense of each demands that of the other.
Thus, according to the arguments we have just sketched out, it is from my sense of
embodied finitude -- i.e., my being limited by my body only to one place at one time --
that I can posit Others as actually other. These Others, however, are required if I am to
posit my body's temporal finitude -- i.e., its organic birth and death.
Notes
214
birth has not been discovered, so long as I have not brought into play the co-being
(Mitsein) of Others" (Ms. C 17 II, p. 7, ca. Jan. 1, 1931). The full sense of my body's
finitude, thus, requires the co-being of those Others which are posited from the basis of
the first, spatially oriented sense of its finitude. Now, to see the complete circle of this
dialectic, we need only note what this full sense implies. According to it, Others in their
succeeding generations are taken to represent the actual, unbounded lifetime against
which my own finite lifetime is measured. Similarly, in their occupying positions "there"
in the world, they represent the indefinite spatial extendability of the actual world against
which my own surrounding world is measured in its finitude. Hence, their actuallity is
understood as containing my own insofar as they "bear" and "validate" the whole of the
spatial-temporal world in which I find both my embodied self and my surrounding world
as mere dependent parts. This dependence is not just the formal one of the logical
Husserl, it is Others who reveal to me the fact of my birth as a finite living body. They
give it the sense of a body which comes to be from the activity of Others, a body which
will cease to be. Thus, part and parcel of what I learn from them is the notion that my
very being as embodied is dependent on Others, understood as existing before me. The
developed sense of my embodied finitude includes, in other words, the natural attitude's
view that I exist in a chain of generations, that my embodied being is the organic result
of those Others who existed before my body was "given" in a worldly sense. With this,
we apparently negate the beginning of the dialectic which asserted that it was from the
prior givenness of my worldly, embodied finitude that Others are first constitutively
concealment. First of all, the worldly sense of my embodied finitude, a sense which
Notes
215
includes the notion of its dependence on Others, conceals from me the role of this
finitude in positing Others. If I couldn't be here at all without Others in the form of my
parents, how can I say that the positing of actually existent Others depends upon the
finitude of this, my "here"? Such reflections lead Husserl to write: "Worldliness is, so to
inaccessible to one and also closes off [before the reduction] any possible conception of
it" (Ms. A V 10, p. 23, Nov. 5, 1931). Now, this first concealment is actually a
finitude in positing Others, we still have to face the fact that our worldly status as
form of [its] spatial-temporal objectification as the 'soul' of its natural organic body
(Naturleibes) ..." (Ibid.). This concealment is not just that of the nineteenth century
his worldliness lives in pre-givenness, his own and that of the world; that is, he lives in a
horizon, he lives in the consciousness of finitude within an infinite world" (Ms. A V10,
subject within the spatial-temporal infinity of the world. Existing as such, I necessarily
experience the world in the manner of a horizon stretching from the near to the far, from
the known to the unknown. This horizon, itself, is understood in a worldly, spatial
temporal sense. It is a function of the givenness of my finite body and the givenness of
Both forms of givenness were assumed by the starting point of our dialectic. It
took for granted that the surpassing quality of the world referred to the world's given,
spatial-temporal character. In asserting that I could not simultaneously occupy both the
Notes
216
here and the there, it also assumed the givenness of my body as a specific object in the
spatial-temporal world. But for Husserl such assumed givenness is itself a concealment.
He writes immediately after the sentence we just quoted: "This structure of the pre-
givenness of the world for the human being, [this structure] of the human being for
himself, is now, in a second sense, that in which the human being lives in the confines of
necessarily remains concealed to him in his natural life as a human being or, what is the
same, insofar as the transcendental subjectivity lives concealed in his humanity" (Ms. A
This switch from his to the transcendental subjectivity points to the fact that the
whole notion of embodiment, which allows us to posit both ourselves and Others as
which "lives" in our finitude. With this, we can say that the dialectic which asserts both
that my embodied finitude is a prior basis for my positing of Others and that Others must
pre-exist me in order that I may be born organically -- i.e., have a birth of my embodied
finitude -- is itself a "transcendental blinding." Rather like the Kantian antinomies which
derive opposite conclusions from what is ultimately the same premise, our dialectic also
throws its underlying premise into question. For Kant, we may recall, the ultimate
premise is that of the final reality of the visibly appearing world -- i.e., its claim to be a
being in itself (See Prologomena, § 52 a-b). For our dialectic, the premise is that
subjectivity is ultimately given in embodied particularity, i.e., that such particularity is its
final reality. Let us put this in terms of horizon. Either, as the dialectic assumes, the
temporal world or this very finitude is itself to be understood as co-given with the
horizonality of experience. In the second case, the embodied finitude of myself and
Others is not an absolute, but only a constituted phenomenon. If this is correct, then the
Notes
217
dialectical claims of my own and Other's embodied subjectivity to ground one another
are an illusion based on the fact of their being co-grounded in a single subjectivity which
and, hence, in the world and each of its individual, embodied subjects.
This last position, we may observe, rests on two fundamental insights. The first
is that my world horizon is, concretely speaking, the connection of my experiences into
certain perspectivally ordered series. It is such connections which first give me the sense
that the absolute, in objectifying itself in me, must objectify itself in an experiencer who
lives in horizon. This follows both in a specific and a general sense. Specifically, I am
individual, it must, then, give rise to the connections which result in such a world. But
according to the first insight, this is precisely what results in the experiencer living in
speaking, the same point follows because the absolute, in objectifying itself in me, cannot
whose experiences point to what transcends his actual grasp. What we have here is a
living in horizon in which the "I can" always points beyond itself and, in so doing,
surpassing, spatial-temporal world, one whose central core of the familiar or the well
This last sense of finitude stands at the beginning of the dialectic of self and
subjective embodiment. It is only because I am embodied, that the birth and death of
Others has a reference to me. Behind this sense of embodiment is the connection of my
extensions of my "I can" rests on embodiment and, hence, on the perspectival ordering of
my experience. This ordering locates my "I can" in a definite "here" (a "here" which
excludes its also being "there"). It situates this "I can" in a world of things whose
perspectival appearing always points beyond what I have experienced. In this way, it
the world implies them in a sense deeper than that of their simply being fellow "bearers-
validators" of the world. The implication is through the ground of my being in the
world. I posit my Others on the basis of my finite access to the world; but the ordering
finite. This ordering, then, is the basis of my positing of Others. Our conclusion
individual experiencer; but it also recognizes that the very same ordering gives this
experiencer a sense that it is dependent on Others for the explication of the world in
which it lives. It, thus, asserts that my finitely explicating subjectivity and the similar
finite subjectivity of Others are both correlated to the horizonal, perspectivally ordered
ultimately points, not to my finitude as objectively human, but rather to the ground of
which cannot embody itself in an individual experience without surpassing him. This
Notes
219
surpassing implies the Others which are also his particular, finite objectifications. Here,
self and Others imply each other, not directly, but through their surpassing ground.
We can enlarge the above in terms of Husserl's assertion that "the disclosure of
the absolute, the transcendental being, shows that even the life of each transcendental
subject is a life of a finite being immersed in infinity, an infinity which reflects itself, so
to speak, in the concealment of human finitude and ... manifests itself in concealment"
(Ms. A V 10, p. 24, Nov. 9, 1931). The assertion of this passage is that human finitude is
a concealment in which "infinity" reflects and manifests itself. Let us first take this
infinity as the spatial-temporal infinity which is attributed to the world. This infinity
appears in the guise of the indefinitely extendable horizons of objects -- their "internal"
A perspectival series has the sense that no particular view of an object is the last, i.e., is a
view that inherently excludes the possibility of other views of the object. Thus, the
object which appears perspectivally has the sense of indefinite exhibition. Its own sense
experiences, one in which the actual views we have had are always capable of being
surpassed by the possible experiences which the object seems to afford. The same
experiences which allows these to have a defined 0-point in space and time; but this last,
for Husserl, is the pure ego understood as a subjective "center" of experience. Granting
that both the ego and its indefinitely extendable world are both co-given with the
series manifests its potential infinity in a process that conceals as it reveals. Thus, a
perspectivally appearing object can only disclose one of its sides by concealing the other,
follows that "this world, this infinity, which is known in the manner of a horizon, ... is
To this we may add the point that my own sense of embodied finitude is given to
embodied finitude signifies that I cannot be in two places at the same time. I cannot
view simultaneously both the front and the back of an object. By itself, then, it implies
the object's disclosing one of its sides to me only by concealing its other sides. We can,
thus, say with Husserl that the infinity of the world "manifests itself" in the
"concealment" occasioned by human finitude. It does so because the very same ordering
an embodied experiencer who can only reveal by concealing. In other words, my own
According to the above, "infinity reflects itself ... in the concealment of human
finitude" since its own sense is implicit in the latter. The "concealment of human
correlative phenomena. Each is implicit and, in this way, "reflects itself" in the other.
Now, when we turn to their ground, this reflection takes on a second, "absolute" sense. It
does not signify the implication of a correlative, but rather the manifestation of the
ground in the grounded. We can put this in terms of our earlier remark that the reduction
is possible only when it is considered as a transfer to the absolute of the qualities which
make the world a world. These qualities are the world's claims to be the all-embracing
totality of beings and to be the ground of all certainty of being. Now, the manifestation
of the absolute occurs through its constitutive objectification. Since, as we have seen,
constitution and the reduction are the same process in reverse order, the manifestation of
Notes
221
the absolute through constitution should evince the reverse of the transfer the reduction
occasions. The "infinity" of the absolute with respect to being and certainty should
manifest itself by being transferred to the world. By recalling the arguments we have
sketched out, we can gain a certain indication of the nature and the necessity of this
individual, necessarily takes the form of an experiencer who sees the world as an all-
embracing infinity -- i.e., as possessing "the totality of absolute being" which Husserl
egological "center," must experience the world perspectivally. His own appearance,
then, is one with his sense of embodiment and his sense of being a part of a world which,
necessary result (or "reflection") of the objectification of the absolute in the individual's
The same argument holds, mutatis mutandis, for the transfer to the world of the
absolute's quality of being the ground of all certainty. If the absolute is to manifest itself
in an egological center who is certain of his own existence, it must take the form of an
central ego is tied to the world which centers or defines it. Thus, the unity of my world
points to myself as a unity of acts and, ultimately, to myself as a unitary ego, an ego who
experiences through acts. This also holds when we reverse the order of implication.
Thus, my certainty with regard to my being a uniting center is also my certainty with
Granting this, we can say that the manifestation of the absolute in the individual
is not just its occurrence in a subject who necessarily lives in a world-certainty which is
To see this, we must again observe that the world's perspectival character -- i.e., the
indefinite extendability of its horizons -- extends the world to infinity. This character
always makes the world's unity something which surpasses my own finite powers of
indeed, given in connection with this surpassing world-unity, it must be given in relation
to subjects which can "bear" and "validate" the later. My self-certainty, in other words,
must imply the presence of those Others whose "I can" supplements my own limited
abilities in establishing the world's unity. Through Others, I take myself as overcoming
inherent in my positing through persepctival series. They are taken as being in a position
to see, simultaneously with myself, the sides of objects which my own embodied status
The above should, of couse, not be seen as denying that on the level of my
connections through which the absolute brings about the world. The necessities here are
only hypothetical. We can only assert that if the absolute does ground a world and, with
this, its own objectification as a finite experiencer, then the above described transfers do
occur. With regard to the transfer of certainty, it then follows that the absolute's "infinity
reflects itself ... in the concealment of human finitude" by virtue of this finitude's self-
pluralization. This follows since it is only through the indefinite multiplication of such
finite experiencers that the self-certainty of the absolute -- i.e., its own lack of
Notes
223
presumptiveness and contingency -- could ever hope to achieve any objective, constituted
manifestation. Only then could the world's quality of being the totality of beings
achieve, as an experienced and validated totality, the status of being the experiential
Once we assert that the manifestation of the absolute occurs on the worldly,
objective level of "the concealment of human finitude," we must also assert that this
manifestation is, itself, a concealment. This follows both with regard to the individual
and the plurality of individuals. Considered in itself, the absolute's infinity is its
defined word, can only embody one of these horizons, the absolute's manifestation in his
infinite extent -- i.e., in its ability to ground not just this individual's surrounding world,
but every possible horizonal structure of a world. Similarly, it can be said that the
manifestation of the absolute as a plurality of finite subjects conceals its own nature as a
pre-plural ground for the constitution of every possible singular subject and
corresponding plurality. Here, we pass beyond the argument of our last few paragraphs.
ground the world in the certainty of its being. The assumption, however, is a further
concealment. This follows because such subjects do not ultimately act as "validators-
bearers" of the world in its indefinitely extendable horizons. In the finitude which
pertains to each experiencer, their status, as we have seen, is simply that of correlatives to
We can gain a certain insight into this concealment by attempting to ground the
world horizon through a subjective plurality. What prevents our success is, in the first
instance, simply this horizon's basic character of always surpassing any actual subjective
grasp. This holds not just for my subject but also for any finite totality of individual
Notes
224
experiencers. The horizon remains a horizon, i.e., a structure with the central core of the
familiar shading off into the unknown. It is always experienced in the manner of "I -- or
actually had of it. This sense is not cancelled by the bringing in of other subjects.
Collectively regarded, their actual experiences never equal the infinite exhibition which a
perspectivally appearing world is capable of. They, too, as finite, live in the horizonality
of experience or, what is the same, in the transcendence of the world they experience. In
such a situation, we cannot assert that the world, as the totality of all that is, is their
constituted product. The actual experiences from which they constitute are only a finite
part of the whole which the world affords. Such experiences are, thus, never
constitutively equal to the surpassing whole itself. Because of this, Husserl first writes,
"The transcendence in which the world is constituted exists by virtue of its constituting
itself by means of Others and the generatively constituted co-subjectivity." But then he
(leichtsinnig). Of course, the primordial world [of an individual subject] is finite; but the
intersubjective, human surrounding world, the 'earthly' surrounding world, is also finite.
experience, actual exhibitability ..." (Ms. C 17 II, pp. 7-8, ca. Jan. 1, 1931). Husserl's
point is that the world's transcendence, when understood in terms of the horizonality of
experience, can never be a constituted result of the actual experiences of a finite totality
of subjects. It rather shows itself in its quality of always surpassing such experiences.
What about the attempt to ground the world horizon in terms of possibility -- i.e.,
the possible experiences of continually possible new human subjects? Husserl sometimes
Notes
225
considers this notion. He writes, for example, "We, in [our] finitude, only have a world
from the finitude of the fellow subjects actually involved with us -- but, in horizon, [we
have] the possibility of continually new human beings entering in [to the intersubjective
community]" (Ms. B III 7, p. 7, 1933). The difficulty with this attempt, as he notes in
another manuscript from the same year, is the assumption it makes about being. He
writes: "As opposed to the world, which is relative to constituting subjectivity, the latter,
actually exists absolutely? Does it not, itself, have a limited duration -- this, when we do
not wish to assume [its] being in an actually infinite time ...?" (Ms. C 11 I, p. 2, 1933).
The necessity for assuming this infinite being follows from the infinite exhibitability of
extendability. Thus, to "catch up," as it were, with this ever expanding horizon, the
would have to be thought of as present everywhere, extending through infinite space and
individual beings as long as we limit our thoughts to the categories of such beings.
Given that such categories are substantiality, individuality and plurality, they only allow
us to conceive of sums or collections to which new members can always be added. Such
Husserl notes, if we are really to think of the possibility of continually new subjects, then
the "openness" of possibility demands that we also conceive of the possibility that there
The being of unknown Others, Others which are not distinctly and determinately
indicated, is a real possibility of being, a real possibility of being able to reach
them; but it is not excluded that nothing will be reached, that there are final
Others and "over and beyond this, there is nothing"; but that is just a mere
possibility and remains a possibiilty. Openness remains openness.
Transcendental all-subjectivity is constituted as the totality of those whom I and
we have factually reached (with a horizon of the possibility of error); and this
nucleus has its horizon of possible unknown, still unreached Others, with the
possibility that there are no Others" (Ms. K III 12, p. 38, 1935).
This "openness" of possibility results from the Husserlian position that possibility does
not itself express an a priori guarantee. Possibility for Husserl remains mere possibility
as long as we exclude from its notion the facticity which would give it a "real"
significance.
equivalent notions. The ultimacy of facticity gives us, as we said, the correlative notions
of the non-contingency of the absolute and the contingency of the world which it
grounds. Now, this contingency is, itself, correlated by Husserl to the horizonality of our
experiences of the world. That we experience the world perspectivally means that we
experience it in terms of a finitely accessible horizon. This, in turn, signifies that the
world can never be completely validated by us, i.e., confirmed as an absolutely existing
"being in itself". The world, then, is not just contingent when viewed from the vantage
point of its unconditioned ground; it also remains contingent from the vantage point of its
horizonally experiencing subjects. To add yet another concept to this nexus, we note that
horizonality of our experience. The senses of the world's contingency and transcendence
are, thus, always given together insofar as they have the same condition. Granting the
Notes
227
above, the attempt to think of an infinite plurality of subjects which could ground the
world's transcendence undoes the web of these interrelated notions. Such an infinite
plurality would be able to establish the thesis of the world's "being in itself." It would,
then, overcome what Husserl sees as the necessary contingency of the world. With this,
it would assume the position of the world's unconditioned ground. Furthermore, insofar
as we conceive of such subjects as finite and embodied, we conceive them as parts of the
immanent in the world. In other words, if the world contains the guaranteed possibility
itself -- i.e., within its own possibilities -- its unconditioned ground. With this
actual ground of the world by the thought of a plurality of individual subjects acting as
its ground.
For Husserl, this concealment is shown to be such once we realize that subjects,
in their finitude, are correlatives of the world's horizonality. This signifies that they are
always given and always exist within such perspectivally structured horizonality. In
terms of their own thesis, they must, therefore, be regarded as contingent -- i.e., as
dependent -- on a givenness which always surpasses their grasp. In Husserl's words, "...
because horizons are just open possibilities of being and necessarily have the character of
am contingent ..." (Ms. K III 12, p. 39, 1935). The basic position here is one that we
have referred to a number of times. The constant extendability and openness which
"And everything is concealed, even the quite well known, even one's own human being,
Notes
228
one's own bodilyness, one's own being as an ego; they are always in finitude, in the
relativity of obviousness and hiddenness, and this according to each and every [feature]"
Put in these terms, the assertion of this "openness" is simply another way of
recalling the fact that the world appears contingent (or open) both from the perspective of
the horizonally experiencing subjects and from the view of the ultimate facticity of their
ground. In terms of such openness, there is, then, not just the possibility that we may
reach Others beyond which there are no Others, i.e., that we may be prevented from
infinitely extending the intersubjective community. There is also the possibility that the
may collapse. The openness of the horizon makes us treat the thesis of a plurality of
finite, worldly experiencers no differently than that of any other thesis concerning
individual entities. It conceals the thesis' finiality from us and, hence, makes us regard
The collapse of the attempt to ground the world horizon by an actual or potential
plurality of subjects returns us to our earlier conclusion. The world horizon is not the
result of the pluraltiy of subjects. As correlative to such subjects, it is rather the result of
what grounds both itself and such subjects. The nature of this grounding can be specified
by recalling Husserl's assertion that "the absolute lies at the basis of all possibilities ..." It
is, as we said, the grounding possibility of all possibilities. As such, it always surpasses
not just our actual world but also every particular possible world. Included in its
could collapse into a "tumult" with the consequent dissolution of both the perspectivally
ordered world horizon and the egological centers which this horizon situates. The
horizonality which the absolute grounds is, thus, an open horizonality in a double sense.
It is open in the sense that it is, itself, contingent in its ordered, perspectival structure. It
Notes
229
is also open in the sense that it contains all the possible worlds which this structure is
capable of. The same assertion follows for the subjects which exist in horizonality. For
Husserl, to live "in finitude, in the relativity of obviousness and hiddenness" -- in short,
in horizonality -- "... is the structure of human existence." Implicit in this structure is the
possibility of the collapse of such human existence as well as its openness to every
possible form of existing. Both follow from the surpassing quality of the ground. In
surpassing its paticular, finite self-expressions, the ground manifests itself in the
horizonal structure of the latter by making this structure imply infinite, open-ended
connections can ground all possible beings, Husserl, thus, writes: "... the totality of
monadic being exists as being in horizonality, and infinity pertains to this -- infinite
potentiality. Infinite streaming as implying the infinities of the stream, infinity, the
iteration of potentialities" (Ms. C I., Sept. 21-22, 1934, HA XV, Kern ed., p. 670).
concealment. Its very openness conceals from the intersubjective community its possible
extent and its possible continuance in being. Both concealments, we may observe, can be
directly derived from the description of the absolute as an alphabet of experience, i.e., its
which all temporal relations (and, hence, ordered connections) have been abstracted.
Thus, with regard to the concealment of the extent of the intersubjective community, it is
to be recalled that an examination of the essence of "man" leaves open the question of
how many men there are. The essence expresses only a common notion which can be
exemplified by some number of indiviuals. The same point holds for the essential
elements of experience, the "alphabet," forming the absolute. They too have the
character of one in many with regard to the individuals which they can form. What this
signifies is that the openness of the extent of the intersubjective community -- including
Notes
230
the open possibility that it might collapse and, therefore, not have any extent at all -- is
simply a function of the absolute's own character. It is the latter's indeterminacy which
prevents this concealment from ever being overcome. Mutatis mutandis, we can make
the same claim about the concealment of the finality of the thesis of subjective being.
The elements which form this being are those of the alphabet. But the latter exist
independently of the unities they form. The lack of any necessary tie between the two
signifies, as we said, that the dependent, constituted unities can never be regarded as
We may sum up our conclusions by drawing out what they imply with regard to
Others being implicit in me. We have, first of all, the conclusion that our positing of
concealment, we said, is revealed to be such because such subjects themselves exist and
are given along with the horizonality of the world. This is shown by the fact that both
perspectivally structured horizonality. Our last remarks which trace this concealment to
the absolute -- i.e., to its inherent indeterminacy as a ground -- point again to the fact that
the horizonal givenness (or existence) of subjects is simply a result of their being
grounded by the absolute. The concealment involved in positing Others as grounding the
world horizon is, therefore, a concealment of the absolute in its own function of
Let us express this conclusion in terms of the formula, "being equals being
given." Prior to the reduction to the absolute, it signfiies "being equals being given to a
subject" -- i.e., to myself alone or myself in conjunction with fellow subjects. With the
reduction to the absolute -- i.e., to the lowest level of constituting phenomena -- this
Notes
231
interpretation no longer holds. As Husserl writes, "On the lowest level, we do not yet
have an ego ..." (See above, ). There is, then, no ego or subject to whom being can
be given. Here, the positing of egos as ultimate factors explanatory of being shows itself
being which provides not just the "data" but also the egos to whom such data are given.
The sign that this is so is, as we said, the very structure of egological being as being-in-
horizonality.
Let us now relate this to our positing of Others. As just noted, when we first
enter into the transcendental attitude, the necessity for Others is thought under the
whom the world's surpassing quality can be given. They are thought of as grounding the
being of the world in its surpassing extent. Corresponding to this, I assert that Others are
implicit in me by their "bearing" and "validating" the world horizon which I implicitly
world which surpasses me. Once, however, I do perform the reduction to the absolute
level, this assertion shows itself to have the same concealing character as the
interpretation of "being given" on which it is based. I then assert that the presence to me
the world. I also claim that this transcendence or horizonality is not a result of their
constitutive action. Thus, I do not see Others as "bearers-validators" of the world, but
see them as "born" along with the world its horizonality and transcendence. I see them in
terms of the absolute which is the ultimate ground of such horizonality and
finitude and, in so doing, always implies Others. Its possibilities exceed my own.
Implicit, then, in its infinitude, is not just my "I can," but also the "I can" of every
possible Other which I may (or may not) encounter through the horizonality of my
objectified being.
Notes
233
CHAPTER IV
A FIRST SOLUTION TO THE PROBLEM OF INTERSUBJECTIVITY
It is now time to take the themes of the earlier chapters and view them together.
Together they form what can be called a first solution to the problem of
intersubjectivity.
Let us begin by reviewing our analysis of the problem. At its heart is the
distinction between the factual process of recognition and the principle presupposed by
ourselves, our process is one of attempting to apply or "transfer" to him those meanings
with which we are familiar in our own regard. These are the meanings which are tied to
our being in the world: We are the beings to whom the world appears, the beings for
whom it has certain meanings. These meanings prompt in us certain "typical" responses,
pleasure, fear, etc., which manifest themselves in our behavior. The bodily appearance
of our behavior points back to the fact that our being in the world is that of a
or animate organism. Now, what is at issue is not this factual process of recognition, but
the principle presupposed by it. As we said, the principle is that of sharing meanings, of
having a world of shared meanings in common with Others. Expressed subjectively, i.e.,
in terms of Husserl's doctrine of the constitution of meanings, the principle is that of the
harmony of our constitutive systems. These are the systems which, through synthesis,
generate the perceptual meanings which form for each of us our appearing, surrounding
worlds.
Notes
234
The legitimacy of our transfer to Others of the meanings which are familiar to us
and form our surrounding worlds presupposes this principle. Without it, the factual
petitio principii. The petitio is such that the criterion for our sharing meanings is the
observed similarity of our behavior; and the criterion for the claim that our behavior is
actually similar is the sharing of meanings. To break this circle, we must assume that the
perceptual meanings we gather from the world, in particular, those of one another's
advance that the constitutive systems, which Husserl sees as generating meanings, are
already harmonious.
To continue this review, let us mention again the difficulties in establishing this
principle through the arguments which are given in the Cartesian Meditations. Such
Schutz writes, this is because their initial term is "my own self-given life as a
psychophysical I" (Collected Papers I, ed. cit., p. 197). Thus, the basis for my transfer of
senses to the Others as "like me" is, necessarily, my finite embodied being -- i.e., my
being within the world as a finite "empirical (or "real") ego. "Like me" signifies being
finitely embodied as I am. The first difficulty, here, is that although the factual process
egos is not what Husserl should be aiming at. What the arguments of the Cartesian
empirical. As Husserl defines them, they do not have "the value of something real in the
naively experienced, pre-given world"; they do not have "the sense of being a soul of
certain sense, be considered as prior to all appearing behavior within the world. This
priority receives its definite sense by the fact that the transcendental ego is the
constituting ego. Given this, two conclusions follow. The first is that a harmony of
transcendental, i.e., as constituting. The second is that the pairing or parallelism, which
Husserl establishes between embodied, appearing subjects is one which links only
systems, but rather is itself a pairing which presupposes a deeper, constitutive level.
constitution is constitutive of both being and sense. Taking the two as equivalent,
"creative" subjects could only accidentally share meanings in common. A truly creative
subject is one that is truly independent. The latter signifies that its constitutive activities
are not limited beforehand -- either formally, through presupposing a priori rules of
from which it constitutes. Such independence, thus, means that there is no ground or
reason for supposing that they necessarily constitute (and, hence, share) meanings in
common. In Schutz's words, the assumption of this independence implies that each ego
could creatively constitute a world with its Others "just for himself" alone. To assume
otherwise is to commit the petitio. It is to assume what we have no ground for assuming:
this being the harmony of their independent syntheses or, objectively speaking, their
The root of this last difficulty is not per se with the notion of constitution as
productive or creative. Indeed, insofar as this notion springs from that of the absolute
As we remarked, this idea presupposes the independence of the constituting from the
constituted (See above, pp. 171f.). It, thus, leads us to conceive that which is ultimately
Rather than the foregoing, the difficulty, we can say, results from our wishing to locate
follow. Thus, we would be forced to conclude that the plurality of subjects formed a
the world. If we wished to avoid the apparent contradiction in this notion, we would
could not have a plurality of self-sufficient grounds for its being, each of which was
conceived as necessary for it. The final result, then, would be a transcendental solipsism,
locate the creative function of constitituion within an individual being is to ignore the
reversal of the Seinsrede. The reversal signifies, in Fink's words, that "being is, in
principle, constituted ..." ("Proposal," ed. cit., p. 196; F. 201). The sense of objective
something constitutively dependent on the "life" which constitutes it. A second, but no
stated, the ground must show different characteristics from what it grounds (or
constitutes). The conceptions of the two, ground and grounded, are distinct by
definition. Given this, we cannot talk about the constitutive ground in the same way as
Notes
237
about the being which it grounds. We, thus, can understand the call for a "reversal in the
usual sense of the discourse about being" in terms of the sense springing from the
familiarity of our living on the level of the grounded. We must reverse this sense if we
To make these two reversals concrete, we have only to note that all objective,
real being has the characteristics of numerical singularity, of being one among many.
The first reversal signifies that such being is not independent. The second signifies that it
is constitutively depend on what, per se, is not an individual, not a numerically singular
being. This point applies directly to the subject considered as a "real" or "personal" ego.
These aspects of its individual being are, for Husserl, "constituted objectifications."
They result from the connections of experiences forming the individual cogito and
forming, as well the personal ego, taken as the unity of its cogitationes. The same point
Although this ego is not constituted, it is dependent in its singularity on the "centering"
of the constituted. It receives its numerical singularity by virtue of having its stream of
consciousness, and its surrounding world, the latter being constituted so as to situate the
The application of this double reversal to the being of subjects prevents us from
precisely put, the two reversals signify that we can no longer assume a plurality of
numerically singular being. Such being is, itself, a function of constitutive synthesis. It
results directly or indirectly from it. It, thus, follows that the plurality of numerically
singular subjects -- subjects which exist as one among many -- is posterior, not prior, to
the synthesis which is productive of numerically singular being. In other words, the
creative or productive synthesis must already be given for there to be singular egos, each
Notes
238
with its singular, surrounding world. This pre-givenness, we may observe, is reflected in
the passive nature of lower level constitution. For Husserl, "passive" signifies, first of
all, "without the action of the ego ..." It signifies, secondly, that which is constitutive of
the ego in the individuality of its life (Ms. C 17 IV, pp. 1-2, 1930).
With regard to the intersubjective harmony, the import of the above may be
expressed in a number of ways. Its negative significance is that the individual subject is
The creative power which is capable of such disruption is not a function of its being, i.e.,
its an sich Sein as one thing which exists among many. Such power, insofar as it
constitution. But as we quoted Husserl, "On the lowest level, we do not yet have an ego,
To put the same point in terms of another strand of Husserl's thought, we note
that the conception of an individual being which possesses, in its independence, creative
powers, is a conception opposed to the primacy of facticity. Such primacy implies that
all individual being is contingent -- i.e., dependent on the factual course of experiences
which form the being's constitutive elements. It further implies, as we quoted Kern, that
guarantee the genesis and continance of this constitution ..." (Husserl u. Kant, ed. cit., p.
297). This follows since the subject is itself contingent on the very facticity which
posit, like Kant, an individual, subjective unity behind the appearances of the world.
Such a subjective unity, as independent of the facticity of the appearances of the world,
With this, we can express the positive significance of the above. We can assert
that the self-objectification of the absolute into a plurality of individual subjects leads to
absolute is a unique singular. It, thus, lacks the self-otherness -- i.e., ontological self-
synthesis presupposes that the synthesizers are actually other. It assumes that they
already form a plurality of distinct beings, each of which is capable of a distinct action.
Yet on the "lowest" level, the level on which the absolute does creatively constitute, there
are no distinct indivdiuals or pluralities thereof. Otherwise put: the notion of a plurality
objectification into such a plurality. Granting this, we can think of this self-
are appropriate, not to itself, but to the individuals which it grounds. To put this in terms
of individual subjects, we can say that to the point that we do consider them as creatively
constituting, they must be seen as "reflections" of one and the same, uniquely singular
subjectivity. The word, reflections, perhaps, gives too great a sense of their distinctness.
To eliminate this, it can also be said that to acknowledge the creative function of my own
we shall see in the following chapter, this acknowledgement is not, for Husserl, a
phenomenologically to establish.
Notes
240
Let us now turn to the significance of the reversal with regard to our process of
recognizing Others. The first thing to be observed is that the reversal implies a
contradiction between our attempting to recognize the Other as individually Other and, at
the same time, as a separate, independent ground of the world. We have, first of all, a
characteristic of that which can be individually other; while the second, as we have seen,
is appropriate only to the ground of the world, the ground of the totality of numerically
singular entities. The contradiction, then, is one of attempting to apply to the same
essentially say the same thing when we characterize the contradiction as one involving
two levels of the absolute: the absolute in itself and in the "first" of its self-
objectifications. It is only in itself that it is the independent ground of the world. When
it is objectified as human subjectivity, it loses this quality but gains those of plurality and
otherness. A third way of characterizing the contradiction is to assert that it involves the
activity and passivity of the ego. As individually acting, the ego does not ground the
world. The world pre-exists for it; in Husserl's phrase, it is "pre-given to it" as the field
for its activity. The world, here, presents itself as the objects and circumstances upon
which the ego can act and make a difference. In distinction to this, the passivity of the
ego points to what first results in this pre-given world. The constitutive processes
referred to as "passive" are those which ground the world; but, as we quoted Husserl,
such passive constitution takes place "without the activity of the ego ..." Given that the
pre-given world is what situates and, hence, individualizes the ego, this contradiction is
one between processes which are prior to the ego and processes which presuppose it. It
is one between the "before" and the "after" of the individual ego.2
Notes
241
must necessarily fail. We cannot recognize the Other as both a numerical singular and as
a ground of all sense and being. As we earlier observed, the connection of rationality
and positing is such that the logical laws coincide with those of constitution. A logical
transcendental ego involving the above contradictions can, thus, never appear to us. It
description of the transcendental subject as a constitutive ground of the world's being and
sense prevented us from considering it in terms of the latter. It signified that the
i.e., as an objective "unity of sense." Thus, it can never be recognized as such. The way
it could be recognized as ultimately constituting was indicated by the assertion that this
subject "does not acknowledge an outside." This implied, as we noted, that the
recognition appropriate to the being of such a subject was not one which regarded him
from the "outside" as individually other, i.e., as a subject who is "over and against me" in
the separateness of his being. It is, rather, a recognition which proceeds from my
acknowledgement that I am, in some sense, coincident with him on the level of our
ultimate constitution. On this level, I must, as it were, be "inside" of him; for only in this
way could my recognition and this subject's self-recognition, which denies an "outside,"
be said to agree.
Once we grant that the original demands for recognizing the Other are
contradictory, we can answer the objections we have cited. The first of these is that
Husserl does not consider or give any evidence for the existence of the Other as
ego. The objection, in other words, is that the only thing which Husserl actually
Notes
242
answer that the numerically singular ego does not independently constitute. As a pure
ego, it is tied to its surrounding world as its center. Its dependence on "its" world rules
constitutive function. Thus, our answer is that there is no ego possessing the
characteristics which the objection assumes. The demand that we consider the Other as
terms. As such, there can be no evidence for its existence; its constitution as an
With the above, the objection that Husserl establishes only a "parallelism of
constituting transcendental egos which are individually Other. Indeed, insofar as such a
parallelism is the goal of the Cartesian Meditations, it sets itself an impossible task.
Here, we should recall that a parallelism of real, empirical egos is also a parallelism of
"pure" egos. For Husserl, "There are as many pure egos as there are real egos ..." In
other words, if an ego posits another ego as real -- i.e., "as a human being with a human
personality, it then posits as implicitly belonging to him a pure ego with its stream of
consciousness" (Ideen II, Biemel ed., p. 110). The tie between the two is that between
the pure ego and its surrounding world. The latter is necessary for the individual being
of the pure ego. Thus, as we indicated, the pure ego can always be interpreted in terms
of its real, surrounding world. It can be taken as a reality among worldly realities. This
interpretation is correct for the level where the ego achieves its individuality. Given its
dependence on its world, the ego's objectification as a worldly reality and as a "pure"
individual who experiences the world are, in fact, simultaneous. Otherwise expressed:
to acknowledge another ego's separate "real" being is to acknowledge that it has become
This acknowledgement does not involve the notion of this ego's independence --
its creative functioning. On the contrary, it is one that views the ego as a passively
world. As "here" in this world, it must have the sense of existing in a "pre-given spatial-
temporal nature." This follows since its being as a center inherently demands the
temporal world. As Thomas Seebohm writes, " ... the difference between the 'here' and
the 'there' is a difference which belongs to the sphere of [its] ownness and thus to
immanence.3 By definition, then, the notion of a pure ego is distinguished from that of
the independently constituting transcendental ego. It is the latter which, by virtue of its
opposed to its "here." We can, thus, say that to acknowledge the Other as a "pure"
acknowledge his inability, parallel to my own, to break the passive basis of the
intersubjective harmony.
Let us relate this last point to the presupposition for recognizing Others through
him as a pure subject like myself, I must move from his bodily, worldly reality to his
world. The presupposition for this is, as we said, our sharing of senses. Behavior similar
to my own points to the Other as a subject like myself if I can assume that it is a behavior
prompted by the same typical senses of the world which I experience. It is only at this
point that I can move from the bodily reality of the Other to his existence as a subject --
i.e., as a subject to whom the world is given in the form of experiential unities of sense
said, that two "creative" subjects could only accidentially share meanings or senses in
individual constitutive systems. The senses of the appearing world could not serve as
independent criteria for each subject's evaluating the behavior of Others if such senses
were the private constructs or individual creations of each subject. With this, we have
the presupposition that the individual subjects capable of mutual recognition are
passively given the senses of the world. The typical senses by which the world appears
to them as a field for their activity, for their "behavior" taken in its broadest terms, are
assumed to be passively constituted, pre-given senses. Now, the notion of this pre-
givenness, when combined with the definition of the subject as that to whom the world is
given, implies a second presupposition. Subjects must not just be taken as behaving
according to the pre-given senses of the world, they must also be considered as defined
by the latter. In other words, bodily behavior points to the Other as a subject only if we
can say that the senses corresponding to this behavior are senses which first establish
individual, subjective existence. Without this, the argument which proceeds from
behavior to sense and, thence, to the existent subject cannot reach its final term. The
argument, thus, demands that this final term be taken as a center of experience whose
its functioning in recognition, the notion of a world of shared senses must involve both
the pre-givenness of these senses and, with this, the notion that the giving of such senses
situates and defines the experiencing subjects who apprehend them. This, of course, is
the implicit basis of our statement that an acknowledgement of the Other as "real" -- i.e.,
§4. The Reduction and the Two Forms of Evidence for the Other
According to the above, behavior can point to the existence of the Other only
when placed in a shared and ontologically defining world of pre-given senses. Insofar as
Thus, our first chapter related the difficulties which arise when we take behavioral
evidence as establishing both the presence of a world of shared senses and the presence
of the Other. In such a case, this evidence cannot avail itself of the premise of the
sharing of senses. If it did, it would violate the epoché. It would assume part of what it
was attempting to establish. Now, such a violation actually does arise in the arguments
of the Cartesian Meditations. It arises because its arguments attempt to use behavioral
evidence as their sole foundation and because, in fact, the evidential quality of behavior
rests on the assumption of a world of shared senses. As a result, we have the above
premise for evaluating the behavioral evidence which is, then, taken as establishing this
very premise (See above, ). To break this circle, this premise must be recognized as
such. It must, in other words, be seen as something requiring its own evidence. Once we
admit this, we can say that our verification of the presence of the Other rests, indeed, on
behavioral evidence. But we also admit that the evaluation of this evidence requires a
prior premise -- one which demands its own mode of evidence for its verification.
The nature of our access to this evidence follows from our last remarks. Since
the presence of a world of shared senses is prior to the analysis of behavior, its evidence
cannot be drawn from the latter. It must be drawn from what is prior to my apprehension
of my putative Others and their activities. It, thus, requires the suspension of the thesis
of the objective, intersubjectively valid world and, with this, a reduction to what exists
prior to this. Now, the true nature of this reduction can be given by recalling our
Notes
246
assertion that the world, with its Others, is not something given to the individual ego as if
this ego could exist apart from this world. For the mature Husserl, self, Others and the
world in which they live are all co-grounded phenomena. The reduction to what is prior
Understood as providing the evidence for the premise, the reduction has a
twofold character. It is, first of all, a reduction to the ground of sense -- i.e., to the
reduction to the ground of the individuals who are given such senses and, with this, their
being as centers. Both characteristics are encompassed in the notion of the reduction as a
the world are given through such connections. As we recall, for an object to be
sense. Its presence is that of a unity within the multiplicities of experience, one which is
themselves defined in their individuality by such senses, the same point holds, mutatis
world. Therefore, the constitution of the sense of this world through the perspectival
individual. We can also say that individuals are distinguished, one from the other, by
their possessing different "here's" and, if they are not contemporaries, by their possessing
different "nows." Both the "here" and the "now" receive their individual content from
the context of a surrounding world, considered as extended in space and time. The
suspension of the connections which yield a surrounding world is, then, not just a
suspension of the "giving" which results in an individual, but also a suspension of what
results in the distinction between different individuals. Thus, in proceeding to the ground
Notes
247
which, in "giving" sense, is prior to sense, I also proceed to a level prior to the distinction
for the fact that both sense and self are co-grounded. There is, in other words, a common
root to the senses, whose sharing defines an intersubjective community, and the distinct
Others (or "selves") who share such senses. This conclusion, we may observe, is the
same as the one reached through the analysis of the horizonality of experience. The
world horizon cannot be grounded by self and Others since they are co-grounded
claimed, both the sense of the world in its horizonal, infinite quality and, correlatively,
the subjects who, as finite, perspectivally experiencing centers, apprehend the world
horizonally. Putting this in terms of the reduction, we can say that our sharing in the
senses of the world is our sharing in the individual, subjective existence which is the
correlative to such senses. The original sharing is one of the ground of sense which is
also the ground of our individual, finite subjectivity. Considered apart from that which it
grounds, what we share in on this original level is not the constituted sense of the world
and, hence, not the constituted, worldly distinction between self and Others. We can,
thus, say with Husserl, that the evidence yielded by the reduction is that for "my
speak, before there is constituted a world for myself and Others ..." (Ms. C 17 V, p. 30,
The evidence for this prior coincidence is precisely what is required to establish
level" where such senses are first constituted, then, they cannot be considered my
for each of the subjects who arises from this original coincidence. This follows
Notes
248
analytically from the fact that subjects do not, as individuals, pre-exist these senses;
they, therefore, cannot be considered as their individual authors. Thus, to repeat what
the world's senses. To consider myself as such a creator is only "to acknowledge my
essential coincidence with the absolute". The reduction, we are claiming, is what
reduction. The latter is a move from the constituted to the constituting. Given that
identity. This identity is a feature of the constituting level. This signifies that when we
it as what will become a co-constituting plurality. We can also say that it reveals posited,
original intersubjective identity. Within the individual, this original identity continues to
manifest itself in the occurrence of passive synthesis. Such synthesis, as pertaining to the
subject. Rather, it constantly establishes this subject's being. Now, as pointing to the
pre-egological, the evidence of the reduction can never count as evidence for the
individually existing Other. Its terminus ad quem is not the individual, but rather the
we do wish to evidentially validate the actually existing Other, we must turn to the
constituted level on which such otherness is given. This is implicit in our seeking the
required evidence from the observation of the Other's behavior. Insofar as this behavior
is that of an individual subject acting within the world, the evidence is drawn from the
level on which there already exists a constituted world with its ontological distinction of
self and non-self and, with this, self and Others. In directing itself to the level "before
Notes
249
there is constituted a world for myself and Others," the reduction, thus, provides, not
behavioral evidence, but the evidence for the premise required for its evaluation. The
essential character of the latter is its limitation. Directing itself to the original
coincidence of subjects and to the sharing of senses which this implies, it corresponds to
the demand that the latter be recognized as a premise requiring its own unique evidence.
Its limited character, in other words, is just what is required when we assert that the
evidence for the sharing of senses cannot have the same source as that for the actually
existent Other. The reduction, then, is what prevents us from violating the epoché.
Let us turn to another facet of the evidence for the premise. We can do so by
quoted David carr, the object, considered as transcendent in this sense, "is not reducible
to all possible acts of mine ..." The world of such transcendent objects bears,
my acts. This is because its second, intersubjective sense involves the notion of the
actualilty of other experiencers. They are considered as simultaneous with me and yet
as experiencing the object from different points of view. Each experiences the object
from a "here" which is distinct from my own and which I have no possibility of
"here" and what for me is the Other's "there" points, of course, to the fact that my own
experiencer.
Let us put this together with the notion of Others being implicit in me. On one
level, this sense is simply that of their being "fellow validators-bearers" of the world.
They are what gives the world this second, intersubjective sense of its transcendence.
Notes
250
They are implicit in me insofar as I possess this sense. Here, I assert that my being as a
center of worldly experience requires Others in order that this experience achieve its
sense of implying more than the possibilities which spring from my acts. As our last
correct on the level which sees the intersubjective plurality as grounding the being and
the sense of the world I experience. It is incorrect insofar as it asserts that this level is
ultimate. In other words, its insistence on one constitutive level conceals the existence of
a prior level. Once we break through this concealment, a second sense of the
perspectivally unfolding, horizonally structured sense of this world. If the world and its
subjects are co-grounded, then their implicitness in me becomes, on this new level, our
transcendence. When I take this together with the thought of our common grounding, the
possibilities transcend my own, the ground, itself, must exhibit such transcendence. This
does not mean that it has to contain existent Others as actual individuals. It must,
premise for recognizing actual Others, must imply possibilities surpassing my own,
Our last chapter showed that this view of the ground is precisely what the
reduction reveals. Indeed, the very possibility of performing the reduction is tied to the
fact that it reveals a ground which surpasses me, i.e., surpasses the limited possibilities
which my acts embody. Admitting this, we can qualify the assertion of our last section.
We said that the move from the constituted to the constituting exhibits an underlying
Notes
251
essential coincidence. Now, such coincidence should not be taken as implying a simple
otherness of individual subjects never implies that each subject reduplicates the
recognition that is essential if we are to admit the existence of an Other who is truly
other: namely, the recognition that the world which appears from the "there" of his
it. What underlies this recognition is, we assert, the absolute's surpassing quality.
with the absolute -- and, hence, with Others -- is always my coincidence with something
greater than myself. To put this somewhat paradoxically, we can say that I am always
more than myself when I am regarded in my identity with my ground. The self that is
considered identical with the ground surpasses the self which I can grasp on the level of
plurality results in selves which manifest not just an identity of constitutive systems, but
also the otherness which makes their relation a harmony as opposed to a mere unison.
The nature of this Otherness can be indicated by recalling our remarks about
contingency. The ultimate root of subjective otherness is, we claim, the ground's
surpassing quality; but the same quality is at the basis of contingency. Because the
ground contains more possibilities than a finite subject can actualize, what he will
concealed ... even one's own human being, one's own bodilyness, one's own being as an
ego ..." (Ms. A V 10, p. 22, Nov. 9, 1931). This means that a subject cannot make
unconditioned assertions about these facets of his being for himself. His theses about his
being are contingent on what he would experience were he to go further in his horizonal
Notes
252
explication. His horizons are understood as having an "open" character -- i.e., as not
determining in advance the theses which they will confirm. Now, for Husserl, this
openness results from the ground's surpassing quality in two ways. On the one hand, as
involving more possibilities than the subject can ever realize, it necessarily objectifies
itself in a subject whose experiences point to possibilities beyond those which are
exemplified in his present theses. On the other hand, the ground surpasses the individual
given individual, which means that this individual is a contingent rather than a necessary
result of the ground's self-objectification. Thus, not just my theses with regard to the
nature of my being, but also my theses concerning the fact of my being are considered as
It requires that I view my given finitude along with the infinitude of my ground. I am a
particular subject with finite characteristics; but I am always more than this when I am
associated with my ground. In terms of the possibilities which the ground seems to offer
me, I am, in other words, always more than the self which I can objectively grasp. The
dual root of my contingency is, then: 1) the fact that on my constituting level -- the level
coincidence with my ground and 2) the fact that, in itself, this ground has a surpassing
we must first observe that contingency, when viewed from the perspective of the
openness and independence of the ground, is a feature of what is possible rather than
necessary. This means that to regard something as contingent is to regard it as that which
could have been otherwise or, indeed, through its lack of inherent necessity, could not
have been at all. We essentially say the same thing when we assert that a contingent
individual's status is one of being a "this" rather than a "that." As contingent, its thought
Notes
253
as a "this" always includes the notion of a "rather than." Hence, its notion as a
contingent "this" implies the possibility of a "that," the possibility of something which,
by definition, is other than itself. Applying this to the thought of my own contingent
being as "this" subject, I can, then, assert that implicit in the recognition of my contingent
status is the thought of another contingent subject. The latter is not simply a
being here implies that I could have been there. Instead of my existing here, I
acknowledge that I could have existed there with a different surrounding world defining
me. Given that I cannot simultaneously both be here and there, the thought implicit in
possibilitites in his presently being there while I am here. Now, the nature of this
thought, which is an implicit recognition, should be clear from its premise. This is the
coincidence with a ground which is always more than myself. Thus, the implication of
the Other in my contingency is just the thought of his being implicit in the absolute
which exists as my ground. As Husserl describes the latter, "It is precisely the
absolute, ... lying at the basis of all possibilities, all relativities, all contingencies, which
gives them their sense and being" (Ms. C I, KSept. 21-22, 1934, HA XV, Kern ed., p.
668). The absolute, then, underlies the possibilities of both the "this" and the "that." I, in
my contingency, imply the possibility of Others -- i.e., subjects who are other than the
The words "objective" and "pre-objective" should recall the duality of the
evidence for the Other. The inference from my contingency does not amount to a
Notes
254
recognition of the Other as a distinct, objectively existing individual. For this, I require
the perceptual evidence of the Other as he acts in an already constituted, objective world.
In such a world, otherness -- the distinction of being from being -- is already given. My
ground. Such an Other is both in coincidence with me and implicitly other than me. He
beings have not yet been constituted. He is implicitly other since this level of our
coincidence always represents more than myself when I take myself as an objectified
possibility present in the world. Otherness, here, simply points to another facet of the
evidence of the reduction. As exhibiting the absolute as the totality of all possibilities,
the reduction always shows it as other than my limited, worldly possibility. It shows that
the absolute can manifest itself in the self-otherness which is objectively present in a
plurality of subjects.
Associated with his ground, he always transcends or surpasses himself. This surpassing
points to Others and indicates the connection between his self-transcendence and the self-
question: "Why many?" -- i.e., why, in Husserl's view, there must be a plurality of
individual subjects. In a certain sense, the answer is logical. It follows from a mere
analysis of the terms which Husserl employs in his doctrines of contingency, solipsism,
facticity and the reduction. All of these teachings imply the notion of self-transcendence;
and this notion can be used in connection with them to show the logical necessity for
Notes
255
Others. In drawing out this necessity, we need not merely conclude that the absolute can
must manifest itself in Others. Here, indeed, we can say that my actuality, taken as its
particular manifestation, implies the actuality of other such manifestations. This means
that such Others are "logically" implicit in me because my actuality implies their
actuality.
The logical moves by which we can draw out these implications do not, of
analysis indicates is simply the nexus of Husserl's various doctrines. It shows how the
meanings of their terms forces him to conclude that there cannot be a solitary, actually
existent subject.
Let us begin by observing the consequences which arise when we deny the
quality of our ground. To assert this quality is, as we said, to affirm that the otherness of
Others is potentially present in this ground. The two are equivalent which means that the
denial of the ground's surpassing quality is a denial of this otherness. Now, such a denial
I am expressive of a "this" rather than a "that," e.g., a subjective "here" implying the
possibility of a subjective "there" at the same time. Otherwise expressed, I assert that
surpassing quality is to deny its otherness from myself, i.e., from the "this" of my
objectified possibility. It is to assert, in other words, that the absolute ground contains
assume the total possibilities of the ground are exhausted in what I can objectively
ascertain with regard to myself, such possibilities cannot be said to display an openness
or independence with regard to myself. My possibilities are the only conceivable ones,
which signifies that, in regarding myself in my coincidence with the ground, I do not
what I have already exhibited. This horizon does, of course, remain perspectivally
structured; but, here, I must deny what we earlier asserted. I have to say that
simply repeats and reconfirms what I have established. Thus, all of my present theses --
including those of my being for myself -- are securely established; contingency and
Here, since the possibilities expressed by myself and my ground are equivalent, I
become identified with my ground. The definition of one, in terms of its essential
elements, is also the definition of the other. In this case, to speak of the independence
the existence of the ground as it is the only possibility contained within it. As for the
possibilities, the synthetic connections it forms between its elements are determined in
advance to produce me. Thus, ground and self are, here, collapsed into one. The
"alphabet" of experiences can only "write" one world with one central subject. It is no
longer really an alphabet, i.e., something whose elements are independent insofar as
original denial. If, indeed, there is only the possibility of my subjectivity, I at once
become a solus ipse. Others, if I posit them, are simply reduplications of my original
possibility. Husserl writes that to posit another ego as genuinely other, one must be able
to assert that the ego can form new types of intentionalities "... whereby it completely
and totally transcends its own being" (CM, Strasser ed., p. 135). This is not an assertion
self, I must, rather, admit that "... all my modes of consciousness belong to the circle of
those which are modes of my self-consciousness" (Ibid., italics added). The posited
Other, then, becomes nothing more than my product. He becomes "a point of
and Others, who share my ground, also surpassing me. The equivalence signifies that the
denial of the one is also a denial of the other. I cannot, then, deny my self-transcendence
without also denying the transcendence of the Other. Now, the denial of my self-
contingency and my being with Others, I must also refuse to admit the ultimacy of
facticity. I cannot, in other words, accept the position that the factual course of
experiences unconditionally determines both myself and my world. If I did, then I would
have to deny that there is an a priori of perception. But I must accept this a priori once I
limit my ground to expressing only the possibilities of my subject and its surrounding
world. If the ground is determined in advance to objectify itself in one specific world,
then the perceptual form of this world is also determined in advance. The ordering form
of the experiential connections which yield the world's perceptual presence must be seen
Notes
258
as a pre-determined, a priori form. The same point follows from the statement that my
equivalence with my ground signifies that the synthetic connections between the ground's
elements are determined in advance to produce me. As such, they are also determined to
produce the perceptual world whose experience situates and defines me as a self.
Granting this, we must admit that the factual givenness of experience is not ultimately
consequence can be drawn from the tie between the ultimacy of facticity and the
performance of the reduction. Since the latter depends upon our admitting the former,
our original denial can be shown to deny the very possibility of the reduction. To put
this more directly, we need only recall that the reduction's possibility depends upon its
revealing a ground that surpasses me. The denial of this surpassing, thus, immediately
quality of my ground results in the denials of the ultimacy of facticity and the possibility
of the reduction, the affirmation of the latter can be said to imply the affirmation of the
first. Husserl's positions on facticity and the reduction, thus, both imply the surpassing
quality of my ground. Now, my ground's supassing me implies that the Others, who
share this ground, also surpass me. Accordingly, granting that the reduction is possible,
we must say that this ground contains more than my objectified possibility. It includes
the corresponding possibilities of genuine Others. With this, we can explicitly affirm the
connection we mentioned at the beginning of this section. We can assert that the
subject. Only a plurality could make it objective since, by its very nature, it implies
The same point follows when we reverse the implication which led to the denial
of contingency. If this denial follows from the denial of my ground surpassing me, then
containing both the "this" and the "that." Here, with Husserl, we think of the absolute
quality which my contingency implies in its regard. Limited to one possibility, it could
not be conceived as the totality of different possibilities. Rather than having the essential
existence would be equivalent to its own. The result of this limitation would necessarily
be a transformation of its own nature. Identified with its single objective expression, it
expression, its own nature would be transformed since it would have to be considered as
necessary rather than contingent. Such necessity, we noted, would be that of my own
self-given existence. Thus, once I admit the contingency of my existence, I reverse this
implication. I affirm that the absolute, in its own nature, can never be limited to just one
can never occur alone. The implication of the "that" in the "this" becomes, on other
words, Husserl's affirmation that "a possible ego immediately implies a universe, a
totality of egos coexisting with it" (Ms. E III 9, HA XV, Kern ed., p. 383, Nov. 5, 1931).
It must imply this totality since, as grounded by the absolute, it is only possible as
contingent; but, as we just said, such a contingent subject cannot occur alone.
Notes
260
This inference can be reformulated so that it explicitly leads to the actuality (as
opposed to the mere possibility) of Others. To do so, let us list its necessary premises.
The first is that the absolute is regarded as the necessary and sufficient ground of
individuals. This allows us to say that the actuality of its constitutive results directly
implies its own actuality. My actuality as a contingent individual, thus, implies the
actuality of my surpassing ground. The second is that this ground can, itself, be active
only as grounding a number of individuals. In its own nature, it is pre-objective and pre-
individual. To limit its action to a single result is, as we stressed, to transform its nature.
by virtue of its spelling different words. An alphabet determined in advance to spell just
one word is simply that word. Another way of putting this is to observe that the
inference demands that we apply the reversal of the Seinsrede to the action of the ground.
If we fail to do this, then we conceive this action as arising from an individually singular
agent. From the determinateness of this agent, we infer that it could ground just one
determinate result. To reverse this, the result, which is understood as springing from a
actuality implies that of my ground, and its actuality implies its grounding more subjects
This inference, however, does not imply the fact of my actually recognizing
these Others. For this, I require the evidence of their behavior. Here, however, the focus
encounter most of my Others. With this, we may state another element in the above
inference. It is that this contingency represents, on the level of the plurality of the
grounded, the nature of the absolute ground. The latter is the totality of possibilities.
subjects whose possibilities supplement his own. In Husserl's scheme of ground and
Notes
261
grounded, the "open" plurality of subjects, thus, becomes the objective manifestation of
the all-encompassing ground. Each subject, in its contingent givenness, implies other
subjects and, at the same time, declares that its own inherent necessity is no greater than
inference here to the necessity of Others, though their necessity is the same as my own.
This discussion can serve as an interpretive context for Husserl's remarks on the
Every example of an ego, [be it taken] as actual or possible, presents the same eidos. But
this eidos has the remarkable property that each of its eidetic singularities yields (as a
possibility) an individual, transcendental ego. This is an ego which intentionally implies
a universe of transcendental egos as a compossible possibility -- i.e., as a universe of
possibilities that, indeed, are eidetic singularities of the eidos, transcendental ego -- but
implies it as well as the universe of necessarily co-existing "Others" in the sense that the
setting up of each ego as existing must be in accord with this universe of existing egos.
The possibility of one eidetic singularity [understood] as an ego is, at the same time, the
possibility of a co-existing universe of Others pertaining to this ego (Ms. E III 9,
Intersubj. III, Kern ed., p. 383, Nov. 5, 1931).
These remarks can be understood as a consequence of our taking the eidos of the ego as
the eidos of a "self," this being understood as the objective expression of the ground of
egological being. Since this ground includes the totality of the possibilities for such a
self, the eidos has this totality for its content. Its notion, in other words, is that of a
universe of selves or transcendental egos, all of which are "compossible" in the ground.
Each "eidetic singularity [understood] as an ego" represents one finite possibility, one
determinate, objectified expression of this universe of possibilities. Yet it implies all the
The exhibition of this eidos occurs through the process of free variation. This is
a process which varies in imagination the features which are given in our original, factual
example. If this process is to continue to result in a positable ego, the variation must be
without abandoning the notion of this existence. Thus, imagination varies such things as
the "here" of an ego, transforming it to a possible "there." It only varies the notion of the
ego existing as a center of some given surrounding world to show that this is not
similarly transformable. Granting that exhibition of the eidos displays both the
contingent and the necessary, we can say that, in displaying the former, it does exhibit
"the possibility of a co-existing universe of Others pertaining to this ego" -- i.e., the ego
of our originally given, factual example. This universe is simply an expression of the
supplementing possibilities of the "that" which the original egological "this" implies in its
contingency implies in itself (in sich schliesst) a horizon of possibilities in which the
contingent itself specifies one of the possibilities, precisely the one which has actually
occurred" (Ms. C I, Sept. 21-22, 1934, HA XV, Kern ed., p. 668-9). The context of this
remark is, we may recall, the description of the absolute. It is in terms of this context
that we must widen the notion of the eidos. Originally, it was understood as including
only the necessary, non-transformable features of its original example. In relating the
eidos of the ego to the surpassing quality of its absolute ground, we broaden its notion to
Our last few sections have linked the premise for our recognizing Others to the
of the meanings which we gather from the world. Taking such meanings as constituted
Notes
263
constitutive systems. Now, a harmony is not a unison. It involves both identity and
difference. The identity of our constituting systems was traced by us to the fact that we
are not the independent authors of those most basic meanings which give each of us a
contingent upon its givenness -- we are not capable of breaking the passive basis for this
indicates the pre-individual coincidence of the constitutive systems which result in each
subject with his surrounding world. The distinction between subjects can also be traced
cited Husserl in our last section, "... contingency implies in itself a horizon of
possibilities ..." My "this" in its contingency implies the thought of the "that." It implies
the horizon of possibilities taken as alternatives to my given "this." Such alternatives are
not examples of simple otherness. They are linked by being variations on a common
theme -- that of a surrounding world with its subjective center. Insofar as subjects are
of the original identity which springs from the pre-egological level. This is the identity
of those constitutive systems which must be given if the basic features of a surrounding
world are to be given. Contingency, then, points to the theme of subjective existence and
to its variations.
Having linked our premises to contingency, we may ask what the independent
evidence is for the latter. As we recall, the premise for analyzing the behavior of Others
cannot be established by regarding such behavior. It must have its own source of
evidence. The same can be said for the notion of my contingency. It cannot imply a
exemplified in the "that" of Others. If it did, then the notion would already assume the
presence of Others and could not be used as a premise for such presence. In other words,
if it assumes their presence, it would not "in itself" imply a horizon of possibilities -- i.e.,
presence through behavior. Such verification can only occur if the Other's behavior
agrees with a possibility which is given before I encounter his behavior. This possibility
is not that of my "this," for then it would not point to the Other. Yet, if it is to be prior to
my encounter with the Other, my "this" must already include it "in itself."
We earlier remarked that the reduction provides, not behavioral evidence, but
rather the evidence for the premise required to evaluate behavior. It is what prevents us
from violating the epoché by committing a principio principii. The same point applies
here. My "this," in its contingency, can imply "in itself" the "that" of my Others only if I
perform the reduction. The latter is a suspension of the objectively existing world and,
hence, of the Others present in this world. It provides the evidence that the stream of
grounding, that I do not have the unconditioned, "ground-less" being which Husserl
constitute my being as a pure and personal ego, i.e., as a "central" observer and actor.
The implication springing from the passive constitution of my life is, then, that my being
presupposed given. It is other than the being which arises from my constitutive activity.
This otherness of what I am given and what I can constitute is, in fact, my contingency.
We can express this in terms of Kern's remarks quoted above. Husserl's position,
this author writes, is that "transcendental subjectivity is not the sufficient ground for the
being of the world." This follows because the reduction shows that it is not the sufficient
ground of its own egological being -- i.e., the being from which it constitutes both the
world and itself as objectively real within the world. This signifies that both are in
"danger" of "collapse" (Husserl u. Kant, ed. cit., p. 298). The resulting contingency is
that of being capable of existence and non-existence. It is that of lacking any inherent
necessity to be. It is at this point that the features which I experience in myself and my
that alphabet of experiences which is the final terminus of the reduction of my "this."
Such features imply, in terms of this alphabet, other possibilities. At the basis of my
contingency is, then, my exhibited self-otherness. The self that I make through my
action is not the self lying at the basis of my action. Only if my being were within my
myself. Now, this transcendence of the ground from myself is, we said, also the
transcendence of Others who share this ground. To express this in terms of the evidence
of the reduction, we can say that, admitting that my own being is not my product, I must
admit that that Other in his being is also not my product. I cannot constitute the Other
Husserl, the primordial basis for my attempts to constitute the Other. It is that from
which I perform the "analogizing apperception." That such self-existence is not within
my powers shows that I lack the basis for an independent constitution of the Other. It
With this, I reverse the implication I drew from the denial of my contingency. The
denial implied that I was the only possibility. It, thus, led to the conclusion that all that
was possible fell within my constitutive capabilities. Here, on the contrary, the
capabilities.
This surpassing points to the origin of those transcending intentions which are
directed to the Other. It shows how, prior to its encounter with the Other, "the ego, in
itself, has and can always form afresh such new types of intentionalities, intentionalities
with a sense of being (Seinssinn) whereby it completely and totally transcends its own
being (Sein)" (CM, Strasser ed., p. 135). The key to the formation of such intentions is
the equivalence between the ego's self-transcendence and the transcendence of his
Others. It is because the ego is inherently self-transcendent that it can, "in itself," form a
transcendent intention. Its self-transcendence is shown by the fact that its self-existence
(its being as an ego) is not in its power. Granting that egological being, per se, exceeds
its constitutive powers, its intention to the being of its Other must, from the start, be
counted as transcendent.
Let us express this in terms of our statement that the ego's self-transcendence is
the transcendence of the ground of its being. It is because it is not self-grounding that its
egological being is not in its power. It is not self-grounding because that out of which it
acts always transcends the results of its action. The results are finite while the ground is
infinite. The latter, thus, escapes any definitions as a finitely given "this." The most we
can say about it is that it is the indefinitely extendable horizon of the possibilities which
stand as alternatives to my given "this." Such possibilities, we assert, form the prior, pre-
means that they are the elements of my intention to another subject with his self-
consciousness and constitutive syntheses. Since the ground of my being, out of which
they arise, is not in my power, neither is the subject which they point to.
This intended subject is, thus, transcendent to me. Yet, when I regard myself in
coincidence with my ground, he is also implicit in me. This follows since implicit in
my ground are the alternatives to my ways of being and acting. On the ultimately
constituting level, I must regard myself in my coincidence with my ground. But the
ground surpasses the self that I objectively am. Thus, implicit in me -- i.e., in my
ground -- is the very surpassing which points to the Other. To put this in terms of my
contingency, it can be recalled that the surpassing quality of my ground gives my "this"
the sense of something which "could have been otherwise". This means that my
because of this that I "can always form afresh" the "new types of intentionalities"
To sum up, the origin of the ego's transcending intentions is its underlying
coincidence with its ground. On the ultimately constituting level, there are always
present the elements of those intentions which point to more than the ego can
objectively manifest. As prior to both the ego's self-existence and the existence of his
Others, these intentions, in their elements, are simply factually given. The ego's sense
that this is so is both its sense of its factual contingency and its sense that Others can
exemplify the possibilities which it has foregone in becoming a factually given, finite
"this."
Notes
268
A later chapter will fill out the details of the above. For our present purposes,
harmony. This harmony is implicit in the claim that a subject "in itself" -- prior to his
encounter with his Other -- can intend a fellow subject. Such intentions are inherent in
the individual because they spring from that out of which he acts so as to define himself
as a self. They spring from the point of his identity with his ground. Now, once we
grant with Husserl that subjects are in coincidence on the level of their ground, we have
the common origin of such transcending intentions. We also have the commonality of
their objects. The latter consists in the range of subjective possibilities which the
the horizon of alternatives to each individual subject. Thus, each subject is in harmony
with his Others insofar as the horizons of each overlap in the horizon (ultimately, the
Let us put this in terms of the identity and difference of subjects. With regard to
the former, I can say that my intentions to Others are intentions to subjects who are like
me in having a common origin. This origin makes them intend more than they can
possibly exemplify. It, thus, situates them in a nexus of intentions which can only be
fulfilled (and this, never completely) in their encounters with each other. With regard to
difference, we can say that such encounters involve transcendence since each subject
exemplifies a possibility which is other than that of his fellow subjects in their objectified
are present at the common origin of each subject's action. The special nature of the
resulting harmony can be indicated by recalling the conclusion of our last chapter. It
asserted that the totality of subjects is itself contingent. This totality must be considered
self-transcendent in the sense that it cannot ground itself. This means that the
possibilities of being and behaving which subjects exemplify are never equivalent to
Notes
269
those of their ground. Admitting this, the harmony between subjects can never be
thought of as static. It involves an openness to possibilities which have not yet been
actualized. Inherent in its nature is both contingency and the possibility of newness.
To further pursue these themes, we must make a radical turn in our next chapter.
Thus far, our results have proceeded from considering experience apart from time. We
of the ground of the intersubjective harmony has been limited to considering this aspect
of the absolute's presence. There is, however, another side. It is one which we touched
upon when we said that the subject was to be considered as a temporal center, i.e., as the
now-point of its temporal environment. This is the aspect which allows Husserl to say,
"The absolute is nothing other than absolute temporalization" (Ms. C I, Sept. 21-22,
1934; HA XV, Kern ed., p. 670). We grasp it when we perform a reduction parallel to
the above -- i.e., when we consider time apart from experience. Our focus on the
resulting "pure" temporal process is one which regards it as purified from all reference to
particular experiential contents. The absolute temporalization which comes into view
will allow us to restate the themes of our present chapter in a less formal, more intuitive
manner. Thus, we shall gain fresh insight into the distinction between the subject and his
ground which is also the distinction between the constituted and the ultimately
constituting. We shall also see Husserl's justification for his claim that on the level of his
ground, each subject is "in coincidence" with his Others. Since these themes provide the
context for regarding the subject as contingent, such contingency will receive a new
expression. Indeed, as our next chapter will show, temporality itself is the fourth and
CHAPTER V
THE TEMPORAL DIMENSION OF SUBJECTIVE LIFE
Our last chapter ended with a reference to time as an "aspect" of the absolute's
presence. In raising the issue of time, we find ourselves in a position similar to that
... time is a title for a completely self-contained sphere of problems, one of exceptional
difficulty. It will be seen that our previous presentation has, in a certain sense, been
silent on a whole dimension and, necessarily, had to be silent so as to maintain, free of
confusion, what first comes into view only through the phenomenological attitude and
what, apart from this new dimension, does form a self-consistent area of investigation.
The transcendental "absolute" which we have laid bare through the reductions is in truth
not the ultimate absolute. The former is something which in a certain profound and
completely unique sense constitutes itself and has its source in an ultimate and true
absolute (Ideen I, Biemel ed., pp. 197-98).
As the context of this passage makes clear, this "new dimension" is that of the
temporality of conscious life. Consciousness is not just the contents of experience, but
is also their ordering in time. In our focus on the former -- i.e., in our presentation of
rather "constitutes itself" and, as such, "has its source in an ultimate and true absolute."
The first is that this "transcendental absolute" is not the alphabet of experiences per se.
Such an identification is ruled out by the remark that the transcendental absolute
the alphabet. It cannot apply to the alphabet per se since the latter is unered by
suspending these connections. What Husserl has in mind when he speaks of the
stream of experiences. Up to this point, the Ideen has considered this as the constitutive
origin of the world. More precisely put, Hussel has thus far shown that the world, in its
consciousness as the latter streams in time. Now, if we ask why we can call this
the world insofar as the latter depends upon consciousness and insofar as consciousness,
itself, is independent of the world. Such independence signifies that consciousness is not
dependent on the connections which give us a world. Its ultimate presupposition is that
may be engaged. From this, indeed, we come to the doctrine of the absolute as a field of
The remark that the "transcendental 'absolute' ... constitutes itself and has its
primal source in an ultimate and true absolute" points, in this context, to a second aspect
of consciousness, that of the dimension of time. This also expresses a quality which
allows us to consider consciousness as absolute. To see this, two things are required.
We must show that the presence of the world depends upon the temporal dimension of
consciousness. We must also show that this dimension, itself, is independent of the
presence of the world. The first follows as a matter of definition. The world achieves its
Notes
272
synthesis of our experiences in time. Without time, then, there is no world constitution.
reduction. As we indicated in our last chapter, we can consider experience apart from
time. We can also consider time apart from experience. The first consideration occurs
through the "thought experiment" which involves our progressively stripping from our
experience all those connections which allow us to posit individual objects. We, thus,
objective experience. Here, the independence of such contents from their given
temporal positions is also an independence of the latter from the former. If content is
independent of time, then it also follows that the moments of time do not per se demand
to be filled with some particular experiential content. Thus, such moments can occur
even though the contents they bear are not such as to permit world constitution. In other
words, the givenness of time is independent of the presence of a constituted world. Its
moments can be given even though the contents they bear result simply in a "tumult" of
successive sensations.
absolute. We can also say that, corresponding to the reduction to the absolute's presence
as an alphabet, we have the possibility of a second reduction, one to its presence as a pure
temporal process. The "purity" of the alphabet is its purity from all pre-determined
process is its purity from all pre-determined experiential content. In general terms, the
conditions for the possibility of both reductions are the same. They begin with a
constituting consciousness which requires for its activity both content and time. To
Notes
273
time -- from the determinate qualities of that which we bracket when we perform the
epoché. Given that we bracket either content or time and given that contents are
independent of their particular temporal ordering if and only if time is independent of the
particular contents it bears, these two possibilities of bracketing come down to the same
thing. Thus, in spite of what we just said, they do not really designate two separate
reductions. They are not, in fact, two separate ways of reducing the world to a tumult of
sensations. What they indicate is simply two possible interpretations of the reduction
conceived as a suspension of the relations between content and time, the relations which
permit world constitution. What they point to, then, is the duality of the aspects of the
This duality does not mean that we are dealing with two concrete wholes. Our
focus is rather on two independent aspects of one and the same whole. To put this in
terms of an analogy, we note that color and figure manifest the same kind of
independence as content and time. We can conceive of color apart from figure insofar as
a particular color does not inherently demand a particular figure. The same point holds
in reverse order. This ability to separately consider color or figure does not mean that
they are independent wholes. Color is experienced as the color of some figure.
Similarly, figure cannot be distinguished from its background without its having some
color. The same relationship obtains between content and time. Contents are
experienced as a flowing of contents. This holds even though a particular content does
The mutual dependence of color and figure can be indicated by saying that each
demands and is, in some sense, founded on a third quality, that of extension. Extension,
itself, is capable of exhibiting all possible colors and shapes. In this as well as in its
Notes
274
Color and figure are, we can say, "aspects" of extension. The same point can be made,
mutatis mutandis, for content and time. Each, considered separately by means of the
reduction, represents an aspect of one and the same quality -- that of the absolute's being
the grounding possibility of all possible synthetic formations. The alphabet of contents is
ordering. Contents have the possibility of being arranged in every possible temporal
ordering. To reverse this, we note that when we abstractly regard the pure temporal
experiential content. We, thus, can say that all experiential contents are possible with
regard to the moments of time, this being implicit in our asserting that all temporal
orderings are possible with regard to the alphabet of contents. Both possibilities come to
the same thing; or rather, they are aspects of one and the same thing. We are simply
regarding in different ways the absolute's quality of being the world's unconditioned
ground. It is the possibility of all the world's possibilities. Because of this, it can be
having a beyond, not being one among many. The totality of possibilities does not admit
of any possibility beyond itself. It is, by definition, unique. Both time and content, in
results of its activity. When we reflect upon this, we find a certain ambiguity which
we have encountered before (See above, ). What is the ultimate reference of this
Notes
275
perform the reduction on ourselves, each on his own individual consciousness. Such
consciousness, however, is not independent. The reduction shows its tie to its
surrounding, constituted world. The question, then, is where are we to locate this
Both interpretations can find support from passages drawn from Husserl's
The absolute is nothing other than absolute temporalization; and even its interpretation as
the absolute which I directly encounter as my stationary streaming primordiality is a
temporalization, a temporalization of this into something primally existing (zur
Urseienden). Therefore, the absolute totality of monads -- i.e., the primordiality of all
the monads (allmonadische Urtümlichkeit) -- only exists by virtue of temporalization
(Ms. C I, Sept. 22-23, 1934; HA XV, Kern ed., p. 670).
According to this passage, my "stationary streaming primordiality" is, itself, the result of
presupposes this very temporalization. Without it, my primordial being as an ego would
not exist; which signifies that, in itself, this temporalization is an aspect of what is prior
to me. The same point can be drawn from a pair of earlier manuscripts. Husserl asserts
that "temporalization possesses its 'layers' ... the 'layers' beneath the ego (unterichliche
'Schichte') and the egological 'layers' (Ms. B II 9, p. 10, Oct.-Dec. 1931). In other words,
Notes
276
first there is "the primal being, the inherently self-temporalizing absolute ... then the
primal being as [an] ego ..." (Ms. C 5, p. 14, 1931). The same point holds for the totality
temporalization, then all the monads in their "primordiality" -- i.e., in their being as egos
further support for this position can be found. In the manuscript we first cited, Husserl
this regard:
This primordial aliveness is, for Husserl, that by virtue of which individual subjects live
and function. As such, its unity must be thought of as prior to that of their individual
lives. The latter, as arising from it, must be considered as a constituted level of this pre-
individual aspect of the absolute. Thus, we read on the next page of the same
manuscript:
Everything is one -- the absolute in its unity: the unity of an absolute self-
temporalization, the absolute in its temporal modalities temporalizing itself in the
absolute stream, the "stationary aliveness" of the primal present, of the absolute in its
unity -- the unity of everything! -- which in itself temporalizes and has temporalized
Notes
277
everything that is anything. Within this, the levels of the absolute: the absolute as an
absolute, "human" totality of monads (Ibid., second italics added).
the being of an individual ego, if, indeed, it results in this ego's "primal being," then it
cannot result from the functioning of the latter. This means that absolute temporalization
however, seems to deny this conclusion when he writes: "I am the only one (das
Einzige). Whatever exists for me is my own from the singularity (Einzigkeit) in which I
the existence of time. Indeed, from the very same manuscript which we quoted in
time is constituted" (Ms. C I, HA XV, p. 667). Here, the individual subject seems to take
up the stance of the absolute. If he does, then presumably "all time and world" would
have to be found within him. In support of this conclusion, we may cite Husserl's
remarks about the "'human' temporalization" which occurs within the members of a
developing monadic community. He claims that "... actually implicit within their
individual living present (ihrer individuaellen lebendigen Gegenwart) is the world, the
This ambiguity with regard to the aspect of time points to a deeper ambiguity.
Time is an aspect of what, itself, is uniquely one. It is, we said, an aspect of unique
singularity of the absolute. When Husserl declares that "everything is one," his reference
one of "the levels of the absolute," a level which results from an original temporalization.
The inference, here, is that unique singularity pertains to this original level. Its "place" is
multiplicity of individual egos. We can, however, find passages asserting the opposite
conclusion. Thus, Husserl argues that each individual ego must affirm, " ... I am also
unique. I am not a numerical singular (numerisch Einer), a human being among others, a
one among many ..." Each subject, in regarding himself, finds "the non-numerical
singularity of the ego -- the ego simply, the primal pole, the primal source of the
streaming functioning ..." (Ms. B I 32, V, p. 19, Spring, 1934). This is because I am
given as the only center of experience which I can directly encounter. As such, I am the
only thing to which I can affix the title "I." In Husserl's words, "The I is absolutely
unique ... the Other is my Other and, as such, he is not 'I' ..." (Ms. B I 14, XI, p. 25, Sept.
1935). The same point follows when we regard the subject as the being to whom the
world is given. Here, the subject, in his own being given, stands "as a presupposition for
all presence" (Ibid.) This means, as Husserl earlier writes, "Everything which I discover
and can discover as existent presupposes my being. The certainty that it exists, or
possibly exists, is my certainty, etc." (Ms. B III 1, pp. 7-8, ca. Nov. 1, 1929). In other
words, my subjectivity, which I experience as the being to whom all other being is given,
The same claims of uniqueness are made with regard to the notion of the ego as a
then, as a constituter of the same, it must also be unique. It must, in other words, take
In an absolute sense, this ego is the only one. It does not allow of being meaningfully
multiplied. Put more pointedly: it excludes this as senseless. The implication is: The
'surpassing being' ('Ubersein') of an ego is nothing more than a continuous, primordially
streaming constituting. It is a constituting of various levels of existents (or "worlds") ...
(Ms. B IV 5, 1932 or 1933; HA XV, Kern ed., pp. 589-90).
Notes
279
The solipsism implicit in this passage is readily apparent. An ego which is not
"meaningfully multipliable" would not have Others whom he could recognize as egos
like himself. This inference, however, is denied by Husserl. Thus, when he asserts
that he is "not a numerical singular," not "a one among many," he immediately adds
"and yet, at the same time, I am just a man, just one among a whole collection of men"
(Ms. B I 32, V, p. 19). In asserting the ego's unique singularity, what is actually
asserted is "one's own life and other lives; I myself, the absolutely non-numerable,
singular ego in connection with other egos -- i.e., multiple egos and myself as one
among many -- and each ego, however, as a non-numerical singular ... who constitutes
a world that is non-numerically singular as existing for himself" (Ms. B I 22, V, pp.
This passage concludes with the words, "How is this to be understood?" The
difficulty, here, is one which we have noted before. A plurality of unique singulars, all
of the same type, is a contradiction in terms. A uniquely singular ground of the world is
its necessary and sufficient condition. By definition, it is simply one. If I ignore this, a
certain paradox appears. When I take myself as the ground of everything conceivable, I
have to assert that "every conceivable transcendental ego ... is one which must be
constructed from my actuality and from my capacity [for constitution]" (Ms. E III 9,
Nov. 5, 1931; HA XV, Kern ed., p. 383, note 1). Yet, if I assert that other egos are also
uniquely singular grounds of the world, I would have to add as Husserl does: "Every
insofar as it is from its being that I am actual and possible for it. Yet, its being, taken
here as a possible being is only possible from my actuality" (Ibid.). What we confront,
then, is the paradox of each ego being considered as a product of his Others even as he
considers his Others as his products. The paradox springs from each ego claiming, "My
Notes
280
being is the apodictic ground for everything which has sense and being for me." To posit
the Other as able to make this claim is to assert that "out of my apodicticity, I posit the
being of the Other as a ground which exists apodictically for itself, a ground for
The above returns us to an issue which occupied us in our last chapter: that of
the identity and difference of the individual with regard to his pre-individual, uniquely
singular ground of being (including the being of its Others) is a paradox springing from
the coincidence of each ego with its ground. To use the language of our third chapter,
the paradox springs from the manifestation of the ground in the concealment of human
finitude. We can also say that each ego claims its uniqueness in terms of its identity with
its "apodictic" ground; but in terms of such identity, its uniqueness entails its pre-
egological coincidence with its Others. Thus, identified with its ground, each ego has
what Husserl calls a "surpassing being (Übersein)." It transcends itself in its worldly
individuality once it takes up the standpoint of its ground. For Husserl, the latter is "a
existents (or 'worlds') ..." The reference, here, is to the absolute considered as the process
The project of this chapter will be to consider our self-surpassing in terms of this
the origin of temporalization -- i.e., in terms of "the primal present which is not a
modality of time," but rather its source. We will regard this source both in itself and in
its relation to the individual subject. In this way, we shall consider the temporal
dimension of our coincidence with our ground and, hence, with each other. In involving
Notes
281
our self-surpassing, this dimension, as we shall see, will entail our contingency as finite
individuals.
as an abstraction based on a change of focus. We turn our attention from content to time.
We consider the temporal flow of consciousness apart from the particular contents it
bears. Now, to reach the source of the temporal flow, we require something further. The
search for a constitutive source implies that we take time as a constituted phenomenon.
For Husserl, this involves the notion of retentions and protentions. Thus, a content
chain of retentions. Each further member of this chain marks it as increasingly past.
Similarly, a content appears to advance from the future because of a chain of protentions,
the length of which determines our sense of its futurity. It is the decrease of the chain
which gives us the sense of the content approaching the present. The exact description of
this process will have to wait for our final chapter. For the present, we need only to
accept a single point. If we scramble the order of our retentions and protentions, the ego
becomes "perplexed" in its "inner temporality" (See above, ). This implies that it is
the ordering of retentions and protentions which constitutes our sense of contents
occupying definite positions in the past and the future. Such an ordering is not a
"short term" memories and different anticipations -- of one and the same content. These
different presentations do not occur in different moments of extended time; rather, their
connections are what first results in our apprehension of such moments. Granting this,
we can say that a bracketing of such connections is a suspension of our sense of the
flowing past and future understood as parts of extended time. For Husserl, this
Notes
282
suspension forms the heart of the temporal reduction. It can be called a "reduction within
the reduction" insofar as its context is the temporal flow as such, the latter being
Inherent in this notion is the distinction between the ground and the grounded. The
latter achieves new predicates through the connections obtaining between the
the constituting phenomena, these predicates must disappear. As Husserl puts this in
The phenomena which constitute time are, therefore, objectivities which are evidently
different in principle from those that are constituted in time. They are neither individual
objects nor individual processes; and the predicates of such cannot be sensibly applied to
them. Thus, it is senseless to say to them -- to say with the same meaning [which is
applicable to the constituted] -- that they are in the now or that they were previously, that
they temporally succeed one another or that they are simultaneous with each other, etc.
(Zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewusstseins, Boehm ed., Haag, 1966, pp. 74-75).
We can gain a specific sense of these remarks, which were written in 1905, by adding a
radical 'limitation' to the living present and a desire to speak only about this ..." (Ms. C I
3, p. 2, Nov. 1930). Thus, once I bracket the connections between retentions and
protentions which give me my past and future, I am limited to this "living present." We
cannot say that this present is "in the now" understood as a moment which will slip into
the past. Equally, it cannot be taken as a limiting point between the past and the future.
The bracketing of the connections which yield our sense of extended time rules out these
Notes
283
interpretations. What remains is simply my "primal present," the present which is "not a
modality of time."
ambiguity we encountered in our last section. If, as we cited Husserl, "It is from me that
this position, we can cite the passage: "One requires a reduction within the
temporalization and time, to grasp the primal temporalization, the primal time ... This is
the reduction to the streaming, primal 'immanence,' to the primal unities constituting
themselves in this [immanence] ..." (Ms. C 7 I, pp. 31-32, Jan. - July 1932). "Primal
'immanence'" signifies what is primally within me. The reduction, thus, appears to lead
to myself as a "presupposition for all presence." Against this, we can place Husserl's
claims that temporalization is pre-egological, that it possesses "'layers' beneath the ego."
This implies that the reduction to primal temporalization is a reduction to what is before
me. To reach its underlying levels, "... I must not terminate the reduction in my
bracketing of the world and, with this, my spatial-temporal, real human being in the
do perform this reduction, I reach what Husserl terms "... the pre-being (Vor-Sein) which
bears all being, including even the being of the acts and the being of the ego, indeed, the
being of the pre-time and the being of the stream of consciousness [understood] as a
being" (Ms. C 17 IV, p. 4, 1930). All of this results from primal temporalization. When
I regard this temporalization, I find as "constituted" formations "all the levels of existents
for the ego and also, correlatively, the ego itself" (Ibid., p. 5).
Notes
284
Two points can be drawn from these remarks. The first is a general one
concerning individual beings or existents (Seienden). The move from being to pre-being
implies that all such existents have a temporal being. As Husserl explicitly says:
existent: a present existent with the past of the same existent, with the future coming to
presences, both past and future" (Ms. C 13, III, p. 1, March 1934). In other words,
noted, when we suspend the connections of the retentional and protentional chains, we
suspend objective time. We suspend its constant becoming which means that we also
suspend the notion of persisting in time. With this, we bracket the individual existent
understood as the "concrete presence" which persists through the moments (or
"presences") of time. Applying this to the individual subject, we can say that it is no
longer present as an ego of habitualities. It no longer has its persisting "themes" or ways
of approaching the world. As for its status as a pure ego or center of its temporal
environment, this too must be bracketed. The "now" which it represents is stripped of
Granting this, the reduction in passing from the individual existent to the "pre-
being" which is its ground, passes from the individual ego to its pre-individual ground.
'immanence,' we have to say that within me there is something prior to me. Our second
point, then, is that, qua individual, I exist in time. This existence, however, is based on
that which, per se, is not an individual object or process. It is based on that which is
and as "streaming"; yet a temporal sense is denied to these terms. Thus, Husserl writes:
"The regressive inquiry, which begins with the epoché, leads to the primary, stationary
(strehende) streaming; in a certain sense, it leads to the 'nunc stans,' the stationary
present. Properly speaking, the word 'present' is unsuitable in this context insofar as it
already indicates a modality of time" (Ms. C 7 I, pp. 30-1, June-July 1932). His point,
here, is that a "modality of time" -- such as the past, the prseent or the future -- involves
Such moments slip from presence to pastness. Thus, the now of the present slips into the
"just past'' and, from thence, to further degrees of pastness. In contrast to this, the
present uncovered by the epoché is, Husserl observes, "'now' and only 'now'." When he
calls it a "stationary present," this does not mean that it is static -- i.e., a dead as opposed
We can explain this by saying that because it remains now, it is stationary; but because of
this, it can be said to stream with regard to what does not remain now. Thus, its
stationary quality is also its transcendence of the moments of successively ordered time
as they slip into pastness. The sense of this continual transcendence is that of its
continual streaming with regard to such moments. As Husserl observes, this streaming
constant present, the present that is not a modality of time. As such, it lacks the sense of
In other words, we can say that this present streams; but we cannot say that it streams
The strict sense of this stationary streaming can be given by contrasting two
different ways of viewing the living present. Before the reduction, this present appears
to be that through which objectively extended time flows. Thus, from the standpoint of
the now which I constantly occupy, time seems to stream towards my nowness from the
future and away from it into pastness. Thus, the nowness which I occupy appears as a
stationary point of passage for the flowing of the extended temporal stream. The
reduction, however, brackets the connections which result in the "apartness" or extension
of time. After its performance, I limit myself solely to my immediate nowness or "living
present simply in the context of this present. When I do, then what appeared to transit
through it shows itself as a "welling up" within it. Passing through, in other words, is
exhibited as the successive production in this present of what comes to be regarded as the
successive moments of time. This present's stationary streaming is its constant action of
generating time.1
Two points follow from the above. The first is Husserl's claim that the living
"present is 'absolute actuality'; it is actuality in the proper sense as that which is primally
productive" (Ms. C 17, Sept. 20-22, 1931; HA XV, Kern ed., p. 348). The claim
Notes
287
this, "primally generating (Urzeugend)." For Husserl, this present is actuality in the
sense of being in act, the act being the welling up which is productive of the distinct
moments of time. As we cited him above, "The absolute itself is this universal,
primordial present. Within it 'lie' all time and world in every sense. Itself streaming, [it
is] actuality in the strict, worldly sense of 'being present'" (Ms. C I, Sept. 22-23, 1934;
ed. cit., p. 668). In other words, "Both time and world are temporalized in the absolute
which is the stationary streaming now" (Ibid., p. 670). Thus, the present, in
temporalizing -- i.e., in producing the moments of time -- is that which makes things
Our second point is that this production of time is not, itself, in time. It is not
in the present, the primal nowness, which has been brought into view by suspending
connections between retentions and protentions which fix the moments of time in an
considered as a process of synthesizing the contents which are successively given to us.
The condition of such constitution is the production of the successive positions of time,
i.e., of time itself in its apartness. As Husserl observes, the ultimate basis of this
condition cannot, itself, be conditioned by it. Thus, the welling up of time is not, itself,
to be described in terms of the apartness of time which will result from it. This means
14, XI, p. 18, 1934). Becoming in an "ontical" sense refers to world constitution. It
concerns the becoming of synthetic, "real" unities in already constituted time. "Pre-
Notes
288
becoming" refers to the coming to be of time itself, i.e., of the moments which will be
These points may seem abstract; but we can make them concrete by relating
them to the nowness of our functioning. Such nowness signifies that the individual
subject is immediately present to himself as he performs his various acts. The acts slip
away into pastness. Action becomes past action. "But I," Husserl says, "the identical
[subject] of my acts, am 'now' and only 'now' and am, in my being as an accomplisher,
still the accomplisher of the action ..." (Ms. C 10, p. 26, 1931). The same point can be
constantly share a now with the latter. The now of the object, however, constantly slips
into pastness. The present tone of a melody gives way to another. Its now is replaced by
the next in the order of succession. "Yet this temporalization," Husserl remarks, "ought
not to cover up the fact that I am egologically-continually-streamingly now and only now
...," this as the "performer" of the perception (Ibid.) There is, we can say, a double
necessity for this constant nowness of the perceiving, acting subject. If the subject
himself became past, he would cease to be an actor. What is past is fixed. It is not an
accomplishing, but a having accomplished. On the objective side, this constant nowness
is required so that the object can successively unfold its contents. If the subject were to
remain fixed in the moment when he perceived a particular content, he could not
apprehend any others. The possibility of such further apprehension is the possibility of
the moment with its content slipping into pastness vis-a-vis the perceiving subject. This,
however, is the possibility of the subject, in his constant nowness, transcending the
When we turn the reduction on this last possibility, we see that it is based on the
of what wells up -- i.e., the constituted moments of time. The latter depart into pastness
Notes
289
required for perception; and the reduction reveals its dependence on the "stationary
streaming" or welling up of time. The same point holds for all egological actions. As
Husserl observes, the ego in its constant self-presence "is stationary and remaining in a
special sense: it, itself, does not stream [away in time], but it does act. It posits its thesis
(setzt seinen Satz), and this acting is a letting loose from itself. It is a primal welling up,
a creative allowing to depart from itself of that which, itself, streams, namely the acts
(Ms. B III 9, pp. 13-14, Oct.-Dec. 1931). Thus, the departure in time of our contents of
experience is also the temporal unfolding of our perceptual acts. Composed of non-
intentional contents the acts synthesize them into intentional unities. The "streaming" of
these acts is the departure of their contents. The welling up upon which this is based also
allows the acts themselves to depart. It gives the ego which remains now the possibility
In this context, a certain identification seems all but inevitable. If the ego acts by
virtue of "a primal welling up" and if the source of this welling up is the living present,
then the acting ego, qua actor, seems to be identical with this present. Husserl, in fact,
"transcendental subjectivity [taken] in the primal form of its being." Such a form is "the
primally streaming present." Describing the latter, he asserts, "This, in fact, is the 'primal
phenomenon' which all transcendental, regressive inquiry leads back to in the method of
the reduction (Ms. C 2 I, p. 13, Aug. 1931). I perform the reduction on myself, on my
own subjectivity. Thus, the nowness which it discovers at the source of egological action
conclusion: "... the ego which is always now and remains now (which, as a stationary
and lasting now, is actually now a now in an objective sense) is this living, this
Notes
290
'supertemporal (überzeitliche)' now, [is] the ego of all accomplishing ... (Ms. C 10, p. 29,
1931).
"I am. It is from me that time is constituted." A question, however, remains as to the
identity of this "I am." The ego, taken as a persisting, individual unity is constituted
through the successive moments of time. How can we identify this with the ego whose
functioning includes the welling up of time? As Husserl observes, the attempt to identify
the two is fraught with difficulties. Paradoxes and infinite regresses appear. They
spring, we can say, from the distinction between the constituting and the constituted. If
then we cannot say that time constitution is the result of the functioning of an individual
existent. The individual ego, taken as a constitutor of time, would then require for its
own being in time -- i.e., its own individual existence -- a prior constitution of time. If
we were to assert that this prior constitution is, itself, the result of the functioning of an
individual, we would then have to posit another indivdiual ego behind the first and so on
between the constituting and the constituted ego and egological time." We would be led
back "to an infinity of transcendental egos," each constitutively responsible for the next
(Ms. B I 14, XI, p. 18; see also Ibid., pp. 16-17, 1934). The same regress appears when
we speak of the streaming life of the ego. Husserl writes: "I exist in my streaming life.
I am, as it will appear, not this streaming life itself; but I am who I am only within the
ontological form of this streaming life ..." The regress appears when I say that the ego
"temporalizes the first immanent sphere [the sphere of its streaming life], but itself only
exists by virtue of a temporalization, and so on again and again" (Ms. C 3 III, p. 7, Nov.
1930).
Notes
291
Husserl's doctrine that all real, individual existents are unities of sense. As we earlier put
this, the thesis of the X, which is the thesis of the object's individual existence, is also the
thesis of its sense. Both follow from the fact that the object is posited through the
synthesis of our successive experiences. The result of this is a one in many -- i.e., the
object which is present as one thing exhibiting itself in many successive appearances. Its
one in many character makes it a sense. It also makes it a Seiende since it means that we
grasp it as persisting through the successive moments of time. Now, we can break the
above regress by distinguishing the ego which "temporalizes the first immanent sphere"
from the ego which "exists by virtue of a temporalization." The latter, we can claim, is a
real unity and, hence, a unity of sense. As for the former, we must say that it is prior to
such. Thus, if it is from me that time is constituted, I cannot say that I am, as its
constituter, in time.2 If I did, the regress would recur since I would have to say that the
constituter of time requires time in order to be such a constituter and, hence, requires a
prior constitution of time. This cannot be my status if, as Husserl insists, "... I am the
actor of the nunc stans," for here he associates me with the "primal willing up" which, in
constituting time, permits my action (Ms. B III 9, p. 25 Oct.-Dec., 1931). Thus, as the
nunc stans' actor, I must be before all connectedness in time; I must be before all the
individual existents and corresponding senses which arise through the synthesis of what I
temporally experience. Qua functioning, I am, therefore, without any objective sense
constituter of time. None of the names which can be drawn from the objective senses of
arises from our applying the principle, "What is ultimately constituting is not itself
constituted" (Ms. B I 14, XI, p. 19, 1935). For Husserl, however, my anonymity is
Notes
292
also something which I can immediately encounter. All I have to do is attempt to grasp
occupied with myself and my specific egological functions, I have this distinction
between what I am occupied with and myself, i.e., between my being actively engaged
and that with which I am actively engaged. ... The actively functioning 'I do,' 'I
brought up by a new functioning ego," an ego which is not, itself, attended to (Ms. A
VII, 11, pp. 90-92, Oct. 26, 1932). As Husserl elsewhere puts this:
... the ego which is the counterpart (gegenüber) to everything is anonymous. It is not its
own counterpart. The house is my counterpart, not vice versa. And yet I can turn my
attention to myself. But then this counterpart in which the ego comes forward along with
everything which was its counterpart is again split. The ego which comes forward as a
counterpart and its counterpart [e.g., the house it was perceiving] are both counterparts to
me. Forthwith, I -- the subject of this new counterpart -- am anonymous (Ms. C 2 I, p. 2,
Aug. 1931).
This inability to grasp myself as presently perceiving arises from the necessities
inherent in perception. For an object to unfold its contents to me, I must remain now
while the moments bearing its contents depart into pastness. Thus, the object whose
sense results from the synthesis of these contents is not now in a primary sense. It arises
from a retaining in the now of what, in fact, has departed from the now. This means that
its contents are presently grasped as occupying the positions of departed time. Without
this, what is synthesized from them -- the object itself -- would not be seen as persisting
through these positions -- persisting even as they continue to depart from the present.
For Husserl, this analysis implies that, "I am always ahead of myself" when I attempt to
Notes
293
objectively grasp myself (Ms. C 16 VI, p. 7, Aug. 1932). 3 This cannot be otherwise
given the contrast beween the nowness in which I function and the departure from it
which is required for objective apprehension. To cite Husserl again: "In reflection, I
encounter myself in the temporal field in which my just past (mein Soeben) has
functioned ... But in the now point, I am in contact with myself as functioning" (Ms. A V
5, p. 3, Jan. 1933).
When I turn to this point of contact, I find something other than the "given" of
functioning existents who possess in our functioning the sense of their [i.e., objects']
being. This functioning is constantly anonymous ..." (Ms. K III 4, p. 8, 1934-35). What
is not anonymous are the objects which are given to us with a nameable sense. What is
anonymous is the subjectivity which goes before the latter, constantly "ahead" of them in
its nowness. It is the subjectivity which is associated with the giving which precedes all
the stationary streaming now. It is the latter whose streaming gives the given. In
Husserl's words: "The primal phenomenon of the streaming is the phenomenon of all
phenomena, of all existents for us in every possible sense; for everything exists in the
primal streaming as 'giving itself' within it and, in the broadest sense, exists as a self, a
persisting unity in its streaming moments" (Ms. C 2 I, p. 13, Aug. 1931). It exists, we
can say, by virtue of the welling up of time, the very welling up which makes possible
With this, we can see why Husserl chooses to break the above regress by
insisting that he is, indeed, "the actor of the nunc stans." The anonymity of the
Notes
294
functioning subject which results from this position is a directly observable phenomenon.
As such, it serves as evidence confirming it. In other words, my very inability to grasp
myself in the nowness of my being points to this nowness as a giving which is distinct
from the objectively given. For Husserl, then, this nowness is what I am in the core of
sense. To put this in terms of the theme of this chapter, we can say that this nowness
represents the temporal dimension of our coincidence with our ground. In coincidence
with it, we engage in perception, we function. Yet in the same coincidence, we transcend
our worldly identity. We surpass ourselves as objective unities, which means that the
when we take it in the context of what wells up -- i.e., the constituted moments of
objective time. According as we view it, we can say that such moments transcend the
present as they depart into pastness; we can also say that the present transcends these
departing moments in its remaining now. No matter what our perspective, the basic
between the constituting and the constituted. Thus, on the one hand, we have the now
which is engaged in primal temporalization, the now which is not, itself, a modality of
time. On the other hand, "we have, in this primal temporalization, the primal present,
the primal past and the primal future, themselves as constituted temporal modalities
which, for their part, stream ..." (Ms. C 7 I, p. 17, June-July 1932). This streaming can
be expressed in terms of the timelessness of the original present. The latter is not a
time is one with its escape from this position. To speak in terms of the present's
transcendence we can say that it is constantly "ahead" of itself -- i.e., ahead of its
objectification as a position in time. Its timelessness, then, implies its departure; and
its departure is the occasion for its further appearance in what will be the next position
in time. It is, thus, always appearing as the next present; yet even as it appears in time,
it is always departing from this appearance to what will be the next. This departure,
we can say, is its anonymity. It is its inability to be grasped in terms of the fixed,
objectively given positions of time. Reversing our perspective, we can speak of the
departure from the now of the "constituted temporal modalities" formed by such
positions. Here, the timelessness of the now, i.e., its distinction from such positions,
Either way we look at it, the phenomenon we face is that of separation. For
Husserl, this signifies that "... in the primordial sphere, worldly perception
(Wahrnehmung von Weltlichkeiten) and the world separate themselves ..." This sphere
is that of "the being of streaming as a stationary lasting" (Ms. C 7 I, p. 2). It is the sphere
of the streaming of time understood as the continual separation of the stationary present
from the present which is its constituted appearance. By virtue of this separation, an
original temporal distance opens up. It is the distance which allows the object to be a
Gegenstand -- i.e., to be present as "standing against" the subject. The non-identity, the
transcendence implied in this standing against is temporal. In other words, the original
transcendence is that of the constituting now as it distinguishes itself from its constituted
appearance. In transcending its appearance, it remains now. As for the appearance itself,
it becomes, vis-a-vis the constituting now, a just past now. It appears as what has welled
up, what has been let loose from its constituting source. This process goes on continually
and its result, for Husserl, is the continual "intentional modification" of the constituted
into greater and greater pastness. As more and more just past moments successively
Notes
296
intervene, an increasing temporal distance opens up between what was once "just past"
appearance, then I can say with Husserl, "In every present taken as a phrase and, thus, in
the stationary lasting present, I am such that I transcend my present being" (Ms. C 7 I, p.
5). Reversing my perspective, I can also say that this momentary "present being"
transcends me as it slips into pastness. Here, I assert: "The not now transcends the now;
in particular [it transcends] the [present] consciousness of the not now. Thus, the
Thus, in the modifications which successively turn my present appearance into a just past
myself to what stands over and against me, I grasp myself "not as the self I am but as the
constituted ..." (Ms. C 7 I, p. 6). In the streaming away from myself of my temporal
cannot be otherwise given that I identify myself with the originally constituting now.
From the perspective of the constituted, the appearing of this now is one with its
departure from this appearance. Its timelessness is its transcendence, its escape from the
fixed positions it constitutes. Reversing our perspective, we can say that this escape is its
constitution of time. It is its "letting loose," its "creative allowing to depart from itself"
of the moments of successive time. It is, thus, its continual creation of temporal
constant now and what "passes away to make place for another" (Ms. D 13 III, pp. 9-10,
Notes
297
July 7, 1933). As Husserl puts this: "In the whole continuity [of time], I am ... the
and future. ... I exists in the streaming creation (schaffen) of transcendence, in the
These constituted modalities of time succeed one another in their successive order. In
distinction to this, "I exists, I in the lasting (Währen) which I am; and I am always
already such lasting in this type of being which is one of a multiple, continuous
transcendence of my primal modal being as now" (Ms. C 7 I, pp. 5-6). The "type of
being" (Seinsart) referred to is that of streaming, understood as the streaming away from
"my primal modal being as now." Because the latter, in its remaining now, does not
itself stream into pastness, it can be called "lasting." Because it lasts, there is the
phenomenon of transcendence, i.e., the primal now's being transcended by what does not
Two conclusions follow from the above. The first is that the timeless, "lasting"
subject distinguishes itself from its temporally unfolding objects by not possessing the
"over-againstness" of the latter. Its self-presence is its lack of the temporal distance
which would allow it to be objective. It, thus, remains anonymous. 4 This anonymity,
however, is constantly changing to its opposite. The ego which is not over against itself,
i.e., not self-transcendent, "exists," as Husserl writes, "in the streaming creation of
transcendence." A regard to the presently functioning ego is, then, a regard to "the
primordium in its first temporalization, in its first existential mode of creating temporal
present and is always already constituted (Ms. C 7 I, p. 7). The constitution of this
constitution of the "outside" of the functioning ego. With this, we have our second
"transcendental consciousness does not acknowledge an outside ..." because this outside
§6. Ego--Cogito--Cogitatum
underpinnings of this threefold distinction. For ease of presentation, let us first turn to
the division:
A. Cogito--Cogitatum
perceived object is understood as other than the perceiving cogito insofar as it is taken as
offering us more than what is actually contained in the cogito. In other words, the
connected experiences making up the apprehending cogito are seen as only a finite part
of what could be grasped in viewing the object. There are experiences "of" the latter in
the sense that they are only a part of what the object can provide. Now, for an object to
have this indefinite availability, none of the experiences it affords can be understood as
the last of a series. Each actual experience must call up the possibility on another, and so
on indefinitely. It is because of this indefinite availability that an object can have the
true one in many does not per se specify the multitude of its many. It rather leaves
Granting that the manyness of the objective unity is that of its appearances in
time, the indefinite continuance of the latter demands the indefinite continuance of time
itself. Time must be such that the appearances occupying its moments can continually
succeed one another. Thus, if time is constituted, its moments must be continually
constituted and constituted such that each gives way to the next. Like the appearance it
bears, each moment must declare that it is not the last, that, in fact, the very possibility of
Notes
299
its existence is equivalent to the possibility of what is to come. With this, we can say that
the temporal dimension of the object's transcendence arises from time's non-temporal
and, hence, unvarying constitutive root. To put this in terms of the welling up of the
now, we can say that insofar as this action is prior to time, it does not have the "time" in
which it could vary. As Husserl expresses this invariability: "In streaming, taken as
stationary, the [temporal] stream constitutes itself. 'Stationary' signifies [its] unvarying
31, June-July 1931). This stationary welling up or streaming of the now can, of course,
be viewed in the context of its results. Here, the timelessness of the constitutive now
appears as its inability to be fixed in a given position of time. Thus, even as this now
appears as a now in time, it seems, in this view, to be departing to what will be the next
such appearance. By virtue of this departure, no given moment (or "appearing" now) can
be the last. Indeed, the momentary now is such that its possibility is one with that of the
succeeding moment. This follows since the present moment exists by virtue of its origin;
but the latter is the now which cannot appear except through departure. Thus, the very
departure which allows the present moment to exist as the timeless now's appearance is
"even now" creating the "space," so to speak, for a new appearing -- i.e., making possible
To relate this to Husserl's distinction between the cogito and cogitatum, we must
consider the latter as a unity of sense. At the basis of this unity is a recurrent pattern of
perceptions. By virtue of it, an object has continually exhibited itself as the same. Each
recurrence of this pattern has reconfirmed our original positing. When we add to this
process our feeling of the indefinite continuance of time itself, the object is taken as
being able to show itself as the same in an indefinite number of instances. It achieves the
status of being a unity of sense. So conceived, the transcendence of this unity -- i.e., its
distinction from the cogito -- is based upon the contrast between the finite, elapsed time
Notes
300
of the cogito and the indefinite continuance of time itself. The cogito is "of" the
cogitatum because its finite time is seen as only a part of the time available for the full
appearance of the cogitatum. In other words, the latter surpasses the cogito because its
time.
This insight, we may observe, is essentially Kantian. Kant writes: "To time,
itself unchangeable and abiding, there corresponds, in the [field of] appearance, the
unchangeable in existence, i.e., substance ..." ("Kritik d. r. V.," B 183, Kant's Schriften,
III, 137). To relate this to the above, we can take the abiding of time as its inability to
"run out." Its unchanging abiding is its "unvarying being as a process." When we see
this feature as a condition for the possibility of positing substance, we essentially repeat
the arguments we have just given. Like the cogitatum, substance is posited as other than
the cogito by virtue of its abiding. Even when the cogito is directed elsewhere, substance
is thought to abide and, as such, to constantly offer to the cogito the possibility of its
further experience. This, however, is only possible if time itself abides. Only then can
we have the substance qua abiding, i.e., qua its unending potential for self-exhibition in a
the thought of the continuance of the time in which the substance's appearances can
original now. It is this, which in constantly remaining now, can never run out" as it
B. Ego-Cogito
The temporal basis for distinction seems clear. As far as we have gone, we can
say with Husserl, "The ego in its most original originality is not in time" (Ms. C 10, p.
21, 1931). We can also say that everything which is in time is not the original ego. In
Notes
301
and continues to constitute itself within it is the non-ego on various levels" (Ibid.). Thus,
the non-temporal ego is not the cogito understood as a temporally extended act.
Similarly, it is not the persisting cogitatum. 5 Both must be regarded as "levels" of the
non-ego.
Statements occur which seem to undermine the non-temporal character of the ego pole.
Thus, in one manuscript, Husserl first asserts, "Naturally, it is senseless to consider the
ego as temporal"; but then he continues a couple of lines later: "Immanent time is the
constant and necessary form of the environment of the ego, and it remains a priori its
environmental form. Afterwards, the necessary temporal relatedness of the ego makes
temporal world ..." As a part of the latter, there is constituted "the human ego which
exists in the world, the ego which becomes identified with the [original, non-temporal]
ego pole ..." (Ms. E III 2, p. 50, date uncertain). In another passage, this "necessary
temporal relatedness" becomes understood as the ego's inseparable oneness with the
temporal: "The original ego, and what is originally its own, is inseparably one
(untrennbar eins) with what, first of all, primally exists for it. It is one with the
temporalized as such; or rather, it is one with the living temporalization in which the
The question is, how are we to understand this unity? How can Husserl assert
both the non-temporality of the ego and its being "inseparably one ... with the
second chapter: Is the ego other or is it one with its temporal acts?
Notes
302
To resolve the above, we first observe that, as temporally constituting, the ego
regard. Their conclusion is always the same. It is that "in its original functioning, the
functioning pole is never in the temporal field" (Ms. A V 5, p. 3, June 1933). This does
not mean that this pole does not have a relation to the temporal. It constitutes the
temporal. Thus, the very functioning which demands that the ego not be considered as
temporal -- i.e., as fixed in the field's successive ordering -- also demands that it cannot
be thought of apart from time. Its notion as originally functioning -- i.e., as a "living
Concretely speaking, this signifies that the functioning ego implies its cogito. It
is never without its cogito, although it can never be identified with the latter. For
Husserl, their relation is one of stationariness to streaming, this being understood as the
relationship of actor to act. The crucial statement of this is one which we have already
cited:
Everything which is contained in the streaming [of time] streams. It possesses the
indescribable, primal form of streaming ... Yet the ego is stationary and
remaining in a special sense: it, itself, does not stream, but it does act. It posits
its thesis, and this acting is a letting loose from itself. It is a primal welling up, a
creative allowing to depart from itself of that which, itself, streams, namely the
The import of this passage is plain. As a temporal process, the cogito or act can be
understood as the result of the ego's constitution of time. By virtue of the latter, we have
constituted moments intervene between it and its constitutive origin. The moment
Notes
303
manifests the action of streaming away from its "stationary and remaining" origin. Now,
this action is the underlying action of the cogito. In other words, the unfolding cogito --
the ongoing act -- is, temporally speaking, just this streaming away. It is the manifest
result of the ego's "primal welling up" -- i.e., the ego's "creative" letting loose of the
The same point can be made by calling the cogito the temporal appearance of the
functioning ego. This description follows from two of our earlier conclusions: 1) the
functioning ego is such by being identified with the anonymous now, and 2) the now in
Admitting that the now in time streams away, we can say that the "action" of the cogito,
which is that of constantly streaming away, is the appearance of the anonymous now, i.e.,
exhibition in time. Husserl makes this point while speaking of the presently reflecting
ego. He writes: "... the ego reflected upon in reflection is not the living pole, but the
that its functioning is constantly temporalized; and, thus, the functioning exists for the
actively functioning ego in the field of its conscious [temporal] possessions" (Ms. A V 5,
pp. 2-3, Jan. 1933). If we restrict ourselves to speaking of the ego's functioning as
almost a tautology. Being temporalized (or placed in time) is, by definition, the result of
such functioning. Thus, the original now functions to constitute time by becoming
one with its escape from such signifies that its functioning appears as the departure of
this moment. A constituted now appears to stream away. The constant streaming away
of such moments -- understood as the temporal dimension of the living cogito -- is thus,
Notes
304
per se, the temporal exhibition of the original now's (the ego pole's) functioning. It is
also, we note, an exhibition of the latter's anonymity, i.e., of the fact that it "is never in
the temporal field." This follows because the moments which we can objectively grasp
are not the same as their original source point; they rather are those which are departing
We can pursue these thoughts on the relation of the constituting now to what it
actuality in the proper sense as that which is primally productive." Its being in act, we
said, is the "welling up" which yields the departing moments of time. "As such," Husserl
continues, "it exists ontifying [or objectifying] itself in the temporal mode. Primally
always has already generated temporal being. Constantly in the present, I [am] the
always apprehended as the ego who I am and as the same as the ego I was, I have a lived
life behind me and have what I have acquired from this, etc. ..." (Ms. C 17, Sept. 20-22,
1931; HA XV, Kern ed., p. 348). Reflecting on this passage, several things can be said.
The first is that my being in the constituting present is my existence as surrounded by the
"constant and necessary" environmental form. The thought of such an environment is,
thus, correlated to the thought that my present constitutes immanent time. Furthermore,
constituting present always appears as the present between the anticipated (or not yet
constituted) future and the given, already constituted past. Existing in this central
present, I thus, always exist in the point from which futurity and pastness is measured.
Once again, we may observe that it is precisely because I exist at this 0 point that I must
transcend myself. A certain temporal distance must open up. Thus, I can imaginatively
anticipate what I will be in the future. I can also recall what I was in the past. Both are
transcendent to me insofar as the one lies "before" me, the other "behind." When,
Although I am anonymous as the center of my temporal field, this does not prevent me
from asserting that I can, as a center, be considered as the result of a constitutive process.
According to Husserl, "I exist in the unity of a life which, as constituted, bears in itself an
immanent temporal order ..." (Ms. B I 32, p. 17, May or Aug. 1931). It is the order of
pastness and futurity in which I am situated at the 0 point. Insofar as this environing
then, is the constitution of my "central" being through the constitution of that which
centers me -- i.e., that in relation to which I can be called a center. This means that to
the point that I can be said to constitute this temporal environment, I can be said to
Whether or not "I" can be considered as active on this fundamental level is, of
course, deeply problematical. What we can say is that the constitution of this
constitution of the streaming which, for Husserl, is the underlying action of the ongoing
cogito. Such action appears as ongoing because temporal constitution is itself ongoing.
Appearing moments are always being added to the temporal field. Thus, the field is
constituted as streaming. Since I am always at the center of this field, this streaming can
remaining at its temporal midpoint is my constantly transcending what was "just now" its
center before this slipped into pastness. The centering environment shifts and, with it,
Notes
306
the midpoint between the past and anticipated future undergoes a displacement. A
change of perspective is, however, always possible. What appeared as the motion of the
center can appear as its own "letting loose," its own action of allowing the moment which
was the center to be added to the past. In other words, from the perspective of the center,
rather, to be the actor whose action is the welling up of the positions of time.
We can put this even more directly by beginning with this welling up. For
Husserl, welling up is the action of the present which is "absolute actuality." Insofar as
the action of this present results in its being surrounded by a past and an anticipated
future, its action appears as that of the present which divides the two. It appears as my
certain sense, my appearance as the source point of time matches my reality. Actually
present in the center of the field, I am in coincidence with the source point. In the
of the nunc stans must be read. He writes that the original now's "basic structure is that
of constituting itself as the nunc stans of a unitary streaming ..." In this, it appears, not
just as "a stationary and remaining primal now," but also as a "primal source point" --
i.e., as "a primally welling primal now" (Ms. C 2, 1, p. 15, Aug. 1931). As the context of
these remarks indicates, Husserl is not asserting that the ultimately constituting now is
itself constituted. What is constituted is its appearance as such. Thus, his focus is on its
(Ibid.) This character requires that the original now be viewed in relation to what can
appear. More precisely, it must be viewed in terms of the streaming which is the
Notes
307
temporal appearance of its functioning. When we take this view, we can say with
Husserl:
A lasting and remaining primal now constitutes itself in this streaming. It constitutes
itself as a fixed form for a content which streams through it and as the source point for all
constituted modifications. In union with [the constitution of] the fixed form of the
primally welling primal now, there is constituted a two-sided continuity forms that are
just as fixed. Thus, in toto, there is constituted a fixed continuum of form in which the
primal now is a primal welling middle point for two continua [understood] as branches of
the modes of [temporal] modifications: the continuum of what is just past and that of
futurities (Ibid.).
Despite its somewhat labored prose, this passage has a clear doctrine. It is that the
constitution of the now as a "fixed form," through which time appears to flow and in
which its moments appear to well up as present and actual, occurs "in union with" a
second constitution -- that of the continua of the past and the future. With the latter, we
have the constitution of the temporal environment which allows the source of time to
appear as a "middle point" within this environment. In other words, we have the
If such being is not "mere appearance," but rather reveals the reality of which it
is the appearance, then we can draw a sharp distinction between Kant's and Husserl's
doctrines of the anonymity of the functioning subject. This distinction arises in spite of
certain similarities between the two. For Kant, as for Husserl, anonymity arises because
of the limitation of the "inner sense" of reflection. "This sense," Kant writes, "presents
in ourselves" ("Kritik d. r. V.," B 152-53; Kant's Schriften, III, 120). Both agree that our
condition for the possibility of appearance, but is, itself, concealed by such appearance
(See above, ). What is concealed is the nouminal ego since it, for Kant, is the actor
who functions to constitute time. Turning to Husserl, we cannot say that behind the
appearing ego, there is concealed a second, the first being "the mere appearance" of the
latter. The acting ego is inseparable from its appearance since, as a central ego, it
This may be put in terms of Husserl's statement that the actual ego, "the living
not point back to a non-appearing self, but rather to a process which is prior to the self.
The appearance of the self is not the latter's concealment, but rather its individualization.
Thus, the individual ego appears as the "place" of temporalization; it appears as the point
where time wells up. With this, the original functioning which establishes the "living
pole" is exhibited as the ego's own functioning, i.e., as the streaming of its cogito. With
regard to the anonymity of the original functioning, which is that of a giving which is
distinguished from what is given, this, too, is exhibited in the ego's phenomenal being. It
is exhibited by the central ego's lack of self-transcendence. As the place of the streaming
of the cogito, it is not "over against itself," but rather appears as the point where
transcendence and, hence, givenness first emerge. We can also note that, fixed as it is
between the past and the future, the ego appears, not just as a primal welling up but also
as "a stationary and remaining phenomenon." Here, it mirrors the constant nowness and
the timelessness of the ultimate source of time. The latter, we recall, is stationary or
invariant since it is prior to the time which is required for change. In all this, the
presence of the phenomenal being of the subject does not conceal, but rather manifests,
the features of its source. For Husserl, then, the "living pole" exhibits itself as
anonymous and functioning since these are the conditions for its existence as my living
pole. The conditions point back to what is prior to such existence, but not individually
Notes
309
prior. Thus, appearance and reality are not to be considered as having distinct referents,
i.e., as assignable to two different entities, one somehow standing behind the other.
What we confront is simply the process which results in a self, a process whose
characteristics and origin become exhibited when we examine this self's functioning.
The whole primal welling up, amidst the streaming away [of the past] and the streaming
towards of what is to come, is the unity of a stationary and remaining primal
phenomenon. The welling up is a stationary and remaining change, the primal
phenomenon of my "I act" ("Ich tue") in which I am a stationary and remaining ego and,
indeed, am the actor of the "nunc stans." I act now and only now, and I "continuously"
act (Ms. B III 9, p. 25, Oct. - Dec., 1931).
stationary streaming. I appear to act insofar as "amidst" the "streaming away" and
"streaming towards" of the past and the future, there is a stationary point of passage, a
point where the welling up of time appears. In other words, action is manifest at the
place through which time appears to stream and in which its moments appear to well up
as present and actual. Insofar as this is my place, the welling up appears as the welling
up of my action. It appears as the action of the cogito of my central ego. Given that this
ego is, itself, established by the streaming of what comes to be taken as its cogito, we can
see why it is never without its cogito. The central ego is not just the place of the
streaming of the cogito, it is also the place which is established by what, in this very
establishment, comes to be regarded as its "I do." Thus, situated in this place, which is
that of the appearing nunc stans, it "continually" acts. Indeed, the cessation of its action
would be its own loss of place, i.e., its dissolution as a central ego. Returning to our
comparison with Kant, we can see why, in this context, the appearing actor is the same as
Notes
310
the actually existing actor. The latter, qua individual, is not a nouminal subject which is
somehow to be seen as "behind" the streaming of its acts. His existence is actually co-
given with such streaming. Thus, when we search for something behind the appearing
action, we do not find a self at all. We find what is prior to every individual entity or
process. This, in fact, is why this prior factor's predicates are predicates of the appearing
that which is common to many individuals, a one which appears in the many. When we
apply this to the original now in its relation to the phenomenal being of subjects, we do
not just claim that its pre-individual processes are the common origin of such being. We
also claim that its processes appear within it, i.e. appear as features predicable of its
individual existence.
The result of the above is that we can predicate timelessness of the appearing
ego. This, however, does not rule out this ego's undergoing a certain temporalization.
Because it cannot exist without its cogito, it must "continuously act." The result of this
In the constancy of the primal phenomenon in which I am the active now, there
springs forth the act as a temporalized process. In its temporality, I myself have
my position in time. I am, in a certain sense, a co-temporalized ego. With the
extended egological act, I have my extension, my temporal duration. Thus, I am
given to myself as an existent extended through time -- streamingly given as what
has just past away and yet persistingly exists. This means that I am given to
myself as the "nunc stans" which is presently graspable, capable of being
experienced, thematized by me; this, in new acts which, when I allow them to
actually spring forth from me, become immediately temporalized, and so on again
and again (Ms. B III 9, pp. 25-26).
Notes
311
We can explicate this passage in terms of our assertion that the cogito is the temporal
appearance of the functioning ego. The cogito's welling up is this ego's exhibition when,
in its functioning, it assumes the position of the active now. The welling up is the
exhibition of this now's production of time. Concretely this means that my givenness as
active, i.e., as the welling up of the cogito, is the givenness of the streaming away of my
acts from myself. The self-temporalization this involves results in my temporal self-
when viewed in terms of the temporal environment which is its result, my streaming can
can say that "I am given to myself as an existent extended through time." The result is
speaks of his being "presently graspable" as a nunc stans, his reference is to this
objectively extended temporal being. More precisely, it is to the nunc stans which stands
over against him as he recalls his past action. As we earlier put this, "In all
remembrances of my past acts, I always appear as occupying the here and the now of
such acts" (See above, ). It is as their 0 point that my being as a nunc stans can be
"thematized" -- i.e., be made the subject of an act of identification which brings together
the self I recall and the self I am. The possibility of such identification does not cancel
my central anonymity, since whenever I confront myself in recollection, the self I recall
is one who could not, when he functioned, grasp his central being. Thus, even when I do
thematize my extended being, I still appear as the anonymous center of such being. This
center can be said to "persist" through the"times" which are recalled by me, since, in
every remembrance, I always appear as the self-same place where the streaming seems to
originate.
Notes
312
We can explore the deeper nature of this thematization by restating two items
from our last section. The first is the essential anonymity associated with my lack of
environment. If we ask how these two fit together, then, as indicated in our last section,
we must say that the ego's constitution is its individualization. It is the determination of
anonymity into what each ego can call "this, my anonymity." This conclusion may be
put in terms of the fact that the nunc stans (or constant temporal center) is not directly
successive time. In Husserl's words, the apprehension is through "acts ... which become
"externalizes" or "expresses" itself in its temporalized act -- i.e., in the streaming cogito.
The latter places it in time -- i.e., in a surrounding temporal environment; and it is only in
terms of such placing that the ego can be thematized as the place of the cogito.
the center of its environment. Its placing and its escape from place give it its status as the
now between the streaming past and future. Together they make it into the place of the
streaming understood as the welling up of time from time's "midpoint." Another way of
expressing this is to say that my being an ego in the central now requires both the
objectivity of the constituted as well as the anonymity involved in this now's departure
from the objectively known -- i.e., the objectively constituted in time. What I can
objectively grasp is, first and foremost, my stream of consciousness. The latter is
something which I can characterize as a "this." Thus, for Husserl, it is "in relation" to
this stream, that the ego can be characterized as this ego -- i.e., as "a numerical singular"
(See Ideen II, Biemel ed., p. 110). Its singularity involves its relation to a singular,
Notes
313
knowable stream. Now, because this relation is that of its being the stream's center, the
ego's anonymity is also required. Anonymity -- as implying its departure from the
constituted -- gives it the temporal distances which are needed for the stream to
objectively appear. Without such departure, it itself would not be constantly situated at
the appearing stream's center. The ego is, thus, a singular by virtue of an essential
anonymity which makes it the anonymous core of a knowable, objective stream. With
For Husserl, of course, the full notion of my subjectivity involves all three of its
aspects: ego, cogito, and cogitatum. It therefore includes anonymity, streaming, and
constituted, objective sense. Their relation can, perhaps, best be seen through the image
of peeling an onion. Let us take the outer layers as representing my fully constituted
sense as a being in the world, i.e., my sense as an objective, persisting being. Peeling off
a few leaves, I find as a presupposition for this sense or cogitatum the fact that "I am
given to myself as an existent extended through time -- streamingly given as what has
just past away and yet still persistingly exists" (Ms. B III 9, pp. 25-26). Proceeding
further, I find "the primal phenomenon in which I am the active now." This is the
welling up of the moments of time which yield my being as the cogito -- i.e., my
phenomenal being as "the actor of the 'nunc stans'" (Ibid.). From this streaming, I pass to
the place of the streaming, the nunc stans or stationary now in which the streaming
appears as a welling up. This nunc stans is the very center of the onion. Yet, objectively
regarded, it is nothing at all. Once the layers which define it have been peeled away, I
am confronted with sheer anonymity. Regarded together with the surrounding layers, it is
still this, my anonymity. Without such layers, the this and the my fall away. Thus, it is
no longer viewed as the anonymous, stationary center of the flowing time which I have
Notes
314
experienced. It is rather the now considered as stripped of its association with every
which follows upon our taking up of a particular standpoint in the constitutive relation --
that of the "central ego" in a constituted field. In fact, insofar as we have bracketed (or
"peeled away") the surrounding layers of constituted time, the relation of constitution has
itself been bracketed. With this, even the now's action of constituting the temporal field,
i.e., the phenomenon of its welling up, loses its sense. Such welling up cannot be seen as
a "departure" or "letting loose" since we have bracketed the transcendence, the distance
which is the correlate of such departure. The central ego, with its central anonymity,
must of course, be seen as constituting. It only exists by virtue of the constitution which
both establishes it as a center and, by virtue of this, makes it appear as a central source
point. The same, however, cannot be said of the now whose anonymity has been stripped
Placed in time, it will, as a matter of essential necessity, escape from this place. It will
appear as a welling up, a letting loose from what will come to be regarded as the place of
the central ego. There is, however, no necessity that such placing shall occur.
The same point can be made by noting that through an analysis of the essence of
"now," we can assert that the now in time is the appearance, the objective expression of
the original, anonymous now. We cannot, however, conclude from this that the original
now must appear, i.e., must have an objective expression. This follows because, when
we bracket constituted time to directly regard its origin, we lose the sense of the now "in
time." The time in which the now is placed has been peeled away. As we put this in
describing the reduction, the now which is uncovered does not pertain to a moment
which "slips into the past." Thus, it cannot be seen as transcending this moment as the
Notes
315
latter departs and, hence, as remaining "a present between the past and the future" (See
above, ). Certainly the reduction, in its penultimate moment, does exhibit the now
Welling up is exhibited by regarding, in the context of the present, what appears to transit
through the present -- i.e., the moments of constituted time. When, however, we abstract
from all consideration of such moments, even the phenomenon of their constitution as a
welling up or letting loose disappears. The now is primally generating; but its own
being, as revealed by the final moment of the reduction, does not demand that it be such.
Like the alphabet of contents, its being is independent of its constituted results. Thus, its
placing and escape from place which characterizes the central ego. Existing prior to its
constitutive results, the now's stationary presence requires no constitutive action at all.
Stripped of all relation to a temporal field, the now that remains as our residuum
can be said to be unique. There is no "present" beyond itself which would allow it to be
seen as a one among many. Its stationary quality includes,then, the notion that there is
nothing beyond itself into which it could move or be placed. We can also say that since
as all the moments of time outside itself have been bracketed, this now represents, in its
presence, the whole of time. By definition, such a whole cannot "become" or change
itself into another time. To add a further element to its description, we note that this
reduced now is both pure "presence" and pure "absence." This description is not a
contradiction since the reference of these terms are different. "Absence" refers to the
lack of objective presence; it is the absence of entities understood as beings within time.
Their absence is a result of the absence of an absence, i.e., the absence of those temporal
distances which would allow temporal beings to appear. Here, we may take the peels of
the onions as representing constituted layers of being. When we do so, this nothingness
at the heart of the onion signifies a nothingness at the heart of being. Its is the absence of
Notes
316
individual beings (Seienden). To turn to the other term of our description, we observe
that this absence or nothingness is, itself, a result of the residuum's (the reduced now's)
sheer, unique presence. It is a function of its uniqueness insofar as that which does not
have a present beyond itself does not allow of the temporal distance -- the "opening," as
it were -- into which a being could appear. Thus, if we assert that being (Sein), as
It is, in other words, a feature of its ousia (or being) understood as parousia ( or
presence).6
A further element must be added if our image of the onion is to represent the
relation of the layers of subjective being. The image is static while the relation is
dynamic. We must, then, imagine our onion as set in motion, as constantly moving
outward from its anonymous core. This motion represents the continuous pasage from
ego to cogito to cogitatum. Temporally, it represents the passage from what Husserl
calls the "non-temporal" or "super temporal now" to the "active now" and, from thence,
to the now that is regarded as fixed in the order of time. Each of these notions of the
now corresponds to a particular notion of the subject -- the subject regarded as ego or
cogito or cogitatum. The actively functioning subject involves all three. More
precisely, its temporalization involves it in a continuous transition from one to the next.
Thus, the cogito appears as a streaming which fixes itself in the cogitatum --i.e., in a
stable, persisting unity of sense. Similarly, the ego appears as that which "expresses"
in time, it can be "thematized" as a point of passage between the non-temporal and the
temporal. The ego can be taken as the place where anonymity transforms itself into
The above allows a certain insight into Husserl's remarks on the uniqueness of
the ego. At issue in our discussing these was the referent of his assertion: "In an
absolute sense, this ego is the only one". Is this ego mine, or is the referent to something
which surpasses me? In a certain sense, we cannot directly answer this question. Insofar
as I thematize my ego as a point of passage, I take myself as standing between what is the
"only one" and what is one among many. For Husserl, as we stated, the uniqueness of
the ego is tied to its anonymity. Its is uniquely singular insofar as it is not objectively
present but, rather, a "presupposition" for objective presence. In other words, its unique
individual beings. Thus, to the point that the ego is temporally incarnate, it is not
uniquely singular. The constituted ego has its "temporal position," its "extension" in
expressing just one of many possible positions or extensions. Turning to the thematically
given ego, we see that it has neither the numerical singularity of being just one among
many nor the unique singularity of being "the only one." It is at this borderline of a
process that begins in uniqueness and ends in individuality. In other words, as the place
of the streaming, I am between the designations: "one in many" and "the only one."
Thus, because my own status is ambiguous with regard to such terms, I cannot
If I attempt to place my being on one side or the other of this divide, I still
cannot escape this ambiguity. As we cited Husserl, "I exist in the streaming creation of
is that I have to say that "it is from me that time is constituted." Yet, I also have to claim
process which creates transcendence, I exist in the constant motion which proceeds from
include the ground of time and if the very process which moves me from ego to cogito
incarnation. The description of this "I" is, then, necessarily ambiguous in the sense that
either we take it as borderline or, in attempting to unambiguously fix it, we find that it
constantly changes.
The fact that the subject is constantly in motion does not mean that we cannot
perform the reduction, that we cannot, through its practice, regard the origin of this
motion. As part of the process of the subject's becoming incarnate, this origin can be
The reduction to the living present is the radicalized reduction to that subjectivity in
which everything is accomplished which is valid for me -- i.e., to that subjectivity in
which all ontological sense (Seinssinn) is sense for me as experientially apprehended,
obtaining sense. It is a reduction to the sphere of primal temporalization in which the
first and originary (urquellenmässige) sense of time comes forward -- time as the living,
streaming present. All further temporality -- be it "subjective" or "objective," whatever
be the sense which these words might take on -- receives its ontological sense and
validity from this present (Ms. C 3 I, pp. 3-4, 1930).
The explicit claim of this passage is that, if I do identify my subjectivity with the living
present, then I identify it with the source of ontological sense and validity for me. This
we recall, this ground is "... the pre-being which bears all being, including even the
being of the acts and the being of the ego, indeed, the being of the pre-time and the
1930). Identified with subjectivity, this "pre-being" still holds its position as the origin
of all the ontological sense assumed by the words "subjective" and "objective."
With this, we have the claim which the context of the above passage makes
explicit. As the origin of the senses which pertain to all individual existents, the ground
(i.e., the living present) is prior to such. It is not, then, my living present. In Husserl's
words:
In its concrete presence as a primal ground and source, it is, in fact, pre-individual.
To continue to call this ground "subjectivity" is, first of all, to remind oneself
reduction discovers what is prior to me. I call this "subjectivity" insofar as it is at the
core of my functioning being. Its welling up results in the appearance of my welling up.
point," i.e., the welling up of the ego taken as the place of the cogito. This place, we can
say, is coincident with that which establishes it. It is coincident with its source, which
means that it is coincident with that which is prior to the distinction between self and
others. As such, it does not just express the point of my coincidence with my ground. It
speak, before there is constituted a world for myself and Others" (Ms. C 17 V, p. 30,
1931).
producing different, content laden environments, results in different egos. Each of the
latter can call this source "mine" since its welling up appears as his welling up. Yet the
central anonymity common to each place of this welling up still points back to a level of
Thus, each subject, in regarding his own central being, does not find those temporal
distances which would allow him to formulate the distinction between ego and object.
This means that he cannot speak of his Other as somehow standing over and against
himself. The source, when taken as prior to those temporal distances which result from
its streaming, must be regarded as prior to every thesis of objective being, every thesis of
individual, persisting being. Husserl puts this in terms of the atemporality or lack of
There is, indeed, community [of self and Others] -- the word "coincidence" has,
unfortunately, the connotation of extended coincidence (Deckung in Extension), of
association ... [The ego's] life, its appearances, its temporalization have an immanent
extension in the stream's time, and so does that which is within the stream as something
materially, temporally constituted. Everything which is temporalized, everything
temporalized by the streaming modes of appearances within the immanent temporal
stream and then, once again, by the 'external' (spatial-temporal) appearances, has a unity
of appearance [and hence] a temporal unity, a duration. [But] the ego as a pole does not
endure. Therefore, also my ego and the other ego do not have any extensive distance in
the community of our being with each other. But also life, my temporalization, has no
distance from that of the Other (Ms. C 16 VII, pp. 5-6, May 1933).
Notes
321
transcendence vis-a-vis our present being. It is the lack of those temporal distances
The final assertion that not just ego poles, but also lives -- i.e., temporalizations
XV, p. 668). We, thus, have the asertion of "a single, stationary, primal aliveness -- that
of a primal present which is not a modality of time." This is "the aliveness of the totality
of monads" (Ibid.). The claim that monads temporalize and, hence, share a "life" in
common comes from the fact that we cannot distinguish them once we limit our regard to
of us could assert that his temporalization was the result of his activity. For Husserl,
however, the reverse is the case. Each subject appears as individually active because of a
prior temporalization. It is the latter which results in his "phenomenal being" as a source
environment -- i.e., peel the onion -- what remains, as we noted, is a present which does
not have a beyond. The temporal distances which would allow us to distinguish this
present from other such presents have been stripped away; and, with this, we lose the
condition for regarding the ego as one among many actors. "His" action, in other words,
The claim of the above is remarkable. We search almost in vain for language to
describe it. Fink expresses it in terms of the "idea of a primal ego, a primal subjectivity,"
one which is "prior to the distinction" between self and Others (See note 1 to the
Introduction). This idea is not a metaphysical abstraction, but rather something which
the reduction exhibits. The latter displays the uniqueness of the functioning which
Notes
322
phenomena. Following Fink, we can, thus, say that the "primal ego" is the ego of
coincidence, the coincidence of the anonymous centers of these extended lives. We can
say that the welling up of these centers, when differentiated by differing contents, results
in the plurality of persisting lives; yet, before this differentiation, we really cannot speak,
absolute itself," he writes, "is this universal, primordial present" -- i.e., the present in
which egos are in coincidence (Ms. C I, HA XV, p. 668). Each individual, temporally
extended life is seen as a "mode," a way in which the absolute expresses itself in a given,
noted in our third chapter (See above, ). There, the absolute is seen as the "life"
which individuals live and temporally express. We, thus, have the concept of "the
absolute unendingly persisting in the unending changes of its modes, at first through
ordinary death and birth, but also through the birth and death of humanities ..." (Ms. C 17
V, p. 47, 1931). In itself, however, the absolute does not persist. It persists only in its
constituted, temporalized expressions. The latter endure, i.e., have their defined "life
times." The absolute, like the ego poles whose coincidences it expresses, is prior to such
enduring. Thus, "persistence" applies immediately to individual lives and only mediately
to the absolute insofar as it is their "aliveness." Husserl uses the word, erfüllen -- to fill
up, impregnate, fulfill, accomplish or realize -- to express the relation between the two.
He writes:
The absolute is "now," persisting in the streaming changes of its modes. Awakeness,
sleep, death as [its] modes. Eternity, non-temporality, and temporality. The all-temporal
identity of structure; the invariant forms of the totality of temporality and the
temporalized. What is is invariably stationary and remaining fills up (erfüllt), stationary
Notes
323
and remaining, a transcendental-absolute egological community. It accomplishes
(erfüllt) a stationary-remaining coexistence of egological subjects of an experiencing (or
conscious) life; this, in the stationary and remaining streaming of a primal present (Ibid.,
pp. 21-22).
Interpreting Husserl, we can say that the absolute's "aliveness" (Lebendigkeit) refers to
considered at its origin. What this process "fulfills" or "accomplishes" is, first of all, the
creation of those temporal distances which result in the "over and against" of objectivity
and, hence, distinguish each ego, qua subject, for all that is not itself. The process is,
secondly, the accomplishment of the very persistence through time by virtue of which the
The notion that there is no extensive distance between ego poles raises the
question of empathy. Such poles exist in a streaming present, a present that manifests the
"aliveness" just defined. Husserl asks: "Does there also pertain to this [present] empathy
understood as a primal empathy -- not the empathy which is explicating -- but rather a
32, 1931). The "explicating" empathy functions in the analogous transfer of sense to the
Other. It explicates the Other's bodily behavior by attempting to transfer to him my own
sense of self as an embodied subject. The question is whether there is an empathy before
this -- i.e., an empathy which exists before the constitution of the embodied behavior
which the second empathy interprets. The same question is put in terms of the
functioning of the present in which I exist, i.e., the functioning which is prior to the
realities which stand over and against me. Husserl asks: "Am I only conscious of Others
Notes
324
These questions are only rhetorically posed. Their answer is known from the
start. Thus, for Husserl, once "I deconstruct [the constituted world] and return to the
primordial," I find that "in the realm of the primordial, there also belongs all my
functioning. Expressed in its terms, the assertion of empathy becomes the claim: "... in
reflectively conscious of myself as a functioning ego" (Ms. B I 22, V, pp. 21-22). This
us that "the correlate of a performing is not [itself] a performing. The ego as a theme of
nameable, objectively given "this." Thus, the claim that I am aware of Others in my
functioning is not a claim regarding an objective presence. The "we" is not present as a
given, departing experiences which, in their departure, stand over and against my primal
functioning. The assertion is that both the "I" and the"we" are present in this functioning
"When ... I return to my living present ..., [it] is not mine as opposed to that of other
human beings" (Ms. C 3 I, p. 3). It is not one among many such presents, i.e., the
presents of many distinct subjects. Rather, it is uniquely one. Granting this, we can say
Notes
325
with Husserl: "I experience Others and, naturally, with regard to myself, I have self-
experience. I discover that 'in my now, I experience the Other' and his now. I discover
my now and his now are existing in one ..." (Ms. C 17 I, Sept. 1931: HA XV, Kern ed.,
prior to that which explicates the constituted, objective senses which pertain to self and
Others. At the basis of such senses is the functioning which constitutes them. At the
basis of this last is the unique living present in which all functioning poles exist in
another. Here, it is interpreted on the level where the functioning nows of ego poles are
seen as "existing in one" underlying now. Accordingly, to say that I experience Others in
that "my ego and the Other's ego do not have any extensive distance in the community of
our being together" (Ms. C 16 VII, p. 6). Because of this, there is a common constitution
of those senses which individual subjects explicate in later, less primordial acts of
empathy. That they do discover that they share senses in common points to a primal
empathy and its revelation of the common temporal origin of such senses.
The main point here is that subjects can experience themselves as grounds of the
world -- i.e., of its senses. They can grasp themselves, not as worldly individuals, but as
experience of Others insofar as the distinction, self and Others, does not yet obtain on the
level which is constitutively prior to individual givenness. We can, thus, say that the
assertion of an "I" is, on this level, the assertion of a "we" -- or, rather, it is the assertion
I am the subject who produces the world which obtains for me. ... I am such, however, on
the underlying basis (Untergrund) of an intentional producing (Bildung) of pre-worldly
Notes
326
being understood as a founding (Fundierung) of the latter. In this founding, my Others
first exist for me. In this [founding], primordial nature which is other (fremde) with the
ego who is other both achieve their existential obtaining through a modification
(appresentation). [In this founding], the ego is in coincidence with Others (Ms. B III 4,
pp. 65-66, caa. Sept. 1, 1933).8
Interpreting Husserl, we can say that before there is given the explicating empathy which
appresents the Other, the Other as other (as fremde) does not existentially obtain for me.
Before this, he only "exists," so to speak, in the coincidence which is at the origin of all
"we" on the original level. What I require to do so is, as initially noted, a sense of the
motion of the reduction (See above, ). This is a motion which brings me from the
intersubjective world with its Others back to the original residuum. It is in terms of this
movement that I can see the residuum as containing my Others -- not explicitly -- but
rather implicitly as their ground. Otherwise expressed: When I reverse the sense of
in the process of founding or constituting the "pre-worldly being" which will ultimately
of temporal positions, one which is the same for the objects we experience. Time is
considered as that in which things are ordered. Thus, according to their temporal
positions, events can be considered as successive or simultaneous. The same point holds
when we speak of the simultaneity of subjects and observe that their sense of the passing
of time seems to come from the changing, successive quality of their experiences. 9
Husserl writes: "In the broadest sense, the form of the universal coexistence of all the
Notes
327
souls is the universal time which is contained within the souls themselves as experience
(Ms. C 17 I, Sept. 1931; HA XV, 334). Here, the assertion of a universal time becomes
that of a common timing of experiences. Each co-present subject experiences the world
"at the same time" as his Others, each experiences world-time as something common
this means that the experiences of each undergo change at the same equitable rate. For
each, a momentary experience changes into a just past experience an from thence into a
just, just past experience and so on in such a way that temporal coincidence obtains not
just in a shared present but also in the moments which preceded this. This simultaneous
p. 668).
The leading idea, here, is that of reduction. The claim of a universal objective
flowing and passing away of the experiences by which each subject obtains his sense of
the temporality of experienced objects. What is the phenomenological basis for this
Husserl, the answer is provided by the reduction to the origin of time. At the basis of
Our experience of our oneness in this now is also a primal empathy by which we grasp
For Husserl, subjects are in "intentional coincidence" by virtue of the fact that the
intentions they form are temporally coincident. This means that the experiences
constituting such intentions are timed together. It is because of this that they can be said
to simultaneously intend one and the same object. Now, the evidence for such objective
appointments and keeping them. A subject who always temporalizes his world faster or
slower than Others would not experience this on a worldly level. The flow of
experiences which gives him his sense of world-time would not per se contradict this
sense. What is required is our ability to experience, not the results, but the "primal
modal present" which is the source point of temporal constitution. It is the coincidence
of subjects in this present which makes their experience of this present an implicit
We, thus, return to the remark we cited at the beginning of this chapter:
"Everything is one -- the absolute in its unity: the unity of an absolute self-
absolute stream, the 'stationary aliveness' of the primal present, of the absolute in its
unity -- the unity of everything! -- which in itself temporalizes and has temporalized
Notes
329
everything that is anything" (Ms. C I, HA XV, p. 668). This passage continues with a
listing of the results of this absolute temporalization: the "'human' totality of monads,"
"reason," and "history in the strict (prägnanten) sense." All of these are termed "levels"
of the absolute. They are such insofar as they are manifestations of its original unity.
Thus, humanity, understood as an interrelated totality of subjects who are "for one
possible without the coincidence of the intentions of subjects. This means that each
experience a world in union (in eins) with Others, Others whom I co-experience as
existing in the world" (Ms. A V 5, March 7-9, 1930; HA XV, pp. 64-5). Husserl, in
seeking an evidential basis for this assertion, examines "my subjective temporality as the
asserts: "Everyone in his immanent present finds this immanent present in coincidence
with the present of every other person and finds it enclosed in the present as an
These last remarks are from a manuscript directed "to the beginning of the
'Second Meditation'" (Ibid., p. 64). It is as this point that the Meditations raises the
Husserl writes of the phenomenology which results from the reduction: "Certainly, it
albeit a transcendental solipsism" (CM, Strasser ed., p. 69). The question he faces is
how, without abandoning the reduction, he can escape from this solipsism. Here, his
answer is that, temporally speaking, the experience uncovered by the reduction is not, at
Notes
330
its lowest level, private or "merely" subjective. At this level, experience has a "we"
character, one corresponding to a "we-present." The answer, in other words, is the same
as that which can be drawn from a passage cited in our last section: "I discover that 'in
my now, I experience the Other' and his now. I discover my now and his now as existing
in one (in eins), so also my appearances and his, my appearing [object] as obtaining for
me and his [as obtaining for him], but both the same" (Ms. C 17 I; HA XV, 332). This
sameness is temporal. What is the same is the streaming departure of appearances, the
very departure which is at the basis of our sense of time. The object which is grasped as
a unity of the departing appearances is taken as that which persists in time, i.e., persists
through the temporal distances created by this constant departure. Thus, the temporal
sameness in our grasp of the appearing object is a function of the unity of our nows, i.e.,
of our having one and the same living present from which such departure is ascertained.
With this, we also have the temporal dimension of the answer to the objection:
Can I not think of an Other who is genuinely Other -- i.e., an Other whose constitutive
style is radically different from my own? As already noted, the lack of any objective,
worldly evidence to support this hypothesis does not dismiss it. My constitutive
processes might cover up those of the Other. Since my objective evidence is based on
Every other ego possesses an egological structure, one which I apodictically grasp
as an essential structure within me. ... I cannot think of my Other as other, for --
in a primordiality and in a common, synthetically harmonious, intersubjective
world existing in this [primordiality of the] living present, in this [present's]
previous self-temporalization and in this [present's] apodictic anticipation of my
future -- there exists apodictically for me an intersubjective and objective world, a
world which contains all Others in the same style of being, the style of the living
present, etc. (Ms. K III 12, pp. 33-34, 1935).
Notes
331
Reduced to its essentials, the claim of this passage is that I cannot think of an Other as
other and think of him as engaged in this living present. The givenness of the latter is, as
already noted, the givenness of a "we-present" and, with this, the givenness of a
"common ... intersubjective world existing in this living present." To affirm the genuine
otherness of the Other, I must, then, assert that his style of being is not that of my own --
i.e., is not a being-in-and-through the living present. For Husserl, such an assertion is
impossible. There is no factual basis which could give it any meaningful content. The
appeal, here, is not to my constituted worldly experience, but rather to the functioning
affirm each time I assert that I presently function. Here, we may recall that facticity is
prseupposition for all "free variation," conceived as a process of uncovering the essence
or eidos. Thus, I must take account of the constant factual givenness of my living
present in every thought which I can have of possible Others. In Husserl's words:
The possibilities of varying in imagination the eidos [of a possible ego] do not
float free in the air. They are rather constitutively related to me in my facticity,
in my living present which I factually live, the living present which I
apodictically encounter along with everything lying within it which can be
uncovered (Ms. K III 12, p. 35).
When, in thought, I attempt to eliminate the fact of this living present, I do not conceive
of a possible variant of myself, one which could stand as a conceivable alter ego. The
ego's aliveness. Given this, a conceivable Other who is alive, who is engaged in
functioning, must be an Other who exists in the living present. The same point holds,
Notes
332
mutatis mutandis, for the Other's "egological structure" -- i.e., its "style of being" as
temporally constituting insofar as this is identified with "the style of the living
present."11
Carefully regarded, the "fact" of the living present is rather special. I can
ceasing to animate my acts. I cannot, however, vary this fact in the way that I can vary
other facts. Other facts have some given objectively representable content. In the free
play of fantasy, I can take the features or arrangements of these and imagine them
of this, its life and its anonymity are one and the same. Thus, I cannot use it to imagine a
possible Other who is other in the fact of his living present. We essentially say the same
thing when we assert that I cannot vary my being in the living present so as to yield the
thought of a functioning Other who is not in the present of "my" functioning. Both
presents must be taken as the same since in the absence of any nameable content, there is
no possibility of a distinct "mine" and "thine." With this, Husserl's answer to the
solipsistic objection is, thus, seen to turn on an "absolute fact" which underlies and yet is
The distinction between the fact of the living present and all other facts I
between essence and existence, i.e., between what a thing basically is and the fact that it
is.12 The underlying "what," defined as the essence, can be uncovered through the
process of free variation. The latter allows us to take a given fact and to distinguish
between the accidental and the essential. The accidental can be varied without changing
Notes
333
the thing's being what it basically is --e.g., its being a spatial-temporal object. The
essential cannot. Thus, I cannot say that a spatial-temporal object can show itself only
from one side, that it has no "back." To admit this kind of variation is to cancel per se
the notion of its spatial-temporality. As indicated in our last section, this process of free
variation can be applied to every fact with a nameable, objective content. Given such
content, we can always proceed from the accidental to the essential. It is only when
confronting the fact of the living present that such variation becomes impossible. The
present's lack of objective content thus points to an absence of any uncoverable essence.
It indicates that this present does not tell us what a thing is. In characterizing a thing as
present, we simply pronounce on whether it is, i.e., on the fact of its being presently or
actually existent.
with a particular essence is to appear . In other words, the essence is a rule for ordering
unfolding of its contents in time. Now, if we say that an object exists, it is "because,
is now and continues to be now. This means that its existence or actuality is such
"actuality in the strict worldly sense of 'being present'." "It is actuality in the proper
Notes
334
sense as that which is primally productive." "Primally temporalizing," it is the act of the
entity's existence since its action of producing the distinct moments of time allows an
a concrete being is both existence and essence. Existence (or continued nowness) is
of contents involving this passage. What existence does is make the essence into a rule
that obtains for an actually occurring temporal passage. It becomes an actually obtaining
"what" -- i.e., a rule for successively ordering contents which is embodied in a given,
persisting presence.
The fact that both existence and essence are required for an entity to be does not
mean that they are the same. Existence, by its very anonymity, is other than the
nameable essence and, hence, is other than the finite entity which possesses a definite
essence. Let us put this in terms of the persisting presence of a spatial-temporal thing.
This entity persists through the departure of its contents in time. The fact of this
departure results in its objectivity. The order of the departure yields its essence -- i.e., its
being this rather than that type of objectivity. This departure, however, is a departure
from that stationary or non-departing nowness whose action is the act of existence, the
very "to be" of the thing. Thus, the thing is objectively present with a definite essence in
its constant separation -- in its dynamically flowing otherness -- from the act of its
existence. Another way of expressing this is to say that a thing exists only through a
process which constantly surpasses its given being. The process is that of
constantly adding to the given yet another now. This next now is required for a thing's
continual presence; yet it is not inherent in it. The persisting thing is only present
through its departure into pastness. But this ongoing departure requires the continual
production of additional moments which, as they become successively past, increase the
Notes
335
pastness of those which preceded them. As we just said, the next now or moment is not
inherent in the thing's given unity. The latter consists of already given contents and
temporal positions, which means that the addition of moments surpasses what is already
given in an objective sense. With this, we can say that temporalization is a giving which
both surpasses the objective givenness of the thing and, in so doing, brings the latter
about.
The contingency of a thing follows as a matter of course from the above. What
is given is always given as contingent insofar as it relies on an addition to itself for its
continuing givenness. Thus, its "to be," understood as the welling up of time in the
stationary streaming now, is not inherent in the thing's objective givenness. Its
contingency is its dependence in its "to be" on a non-inherent or "external" ground. This
contingency is present in the whole of nature considered in its objective character and
essential knowability. As Husserl writes in 1935: "But isn't it apparent that the being
(the actual existence -- die wirkliche Existenz) of nature is an open pretension" (Ms. K
III 2, p. 9). For Husserl, the pretension involves the fact that "time and world are
temporalized in the absolute which is the stationary streaming now" (Ms. C I, Sept. 21-
22, 1934; HA XV, Kern ed., p. 670). It involves the fact that "the absolute" -- conceived
as a pure act -- "is nothing but absolute temporalization" (Ibid.). The pretension is that
this temporalization will continue. Nothing in the objectively given world can assure us
of its continuance. This follows from the fact that what is at issue is not its givenness,
Since the essence of a thing pertains to the ordering of its contents in already
constituted time, it pertains to the objective realm -- i.e., to the realm of what is already
given. As such, its consideration does not remove this "pretension." An appeal to the
essential structures of givenness cannot establish that the addition to givenness will
continue -- i.e., that the given will continue to be present and actual. As Husserl writes
Notes
336
of the laws springing from the essences of things: "These laws ... cannot pronounce
with regard to an actuality -- i.e., whether or not there exists an actuality which
corresponds to them. Essential laws possess a meaning for the real if something real
(an individual being) can be given which falls under the essence, the ideas" (Ms. D 13
XXI, p. 26, 1907-09). In other words, "... such laws ... only specify facts with regard
The same point is expressed in terms of the transcendental logic which delineates
the formal relations between essences once the latter have undergone their
back to consciousness, contains the grounds for a possible nature, but none for an actual
nature" ("Beilage XX," 1908, EP I, Boehm ed., p. 394). As we recall, the original
context of these remarks was Husserl's stress on "factual nature and factual
consciousness". Factiticity was ultimate in the sense that it was not determined
beforehand by the essence conceived as a rule for connecting experiences. The obtaining
of this rule was considered as dependent on the factual -- i.e., actually occurring -- course
of experiences. We can now say that it is ultimately dependent on the fact of the
entity's essence, we bracket this fact. We suspend the consideration of the giving by
which the entity persists. As such, in considering its essence, we abstract from the
of contents in time is required. The giving of the moments of time is not a result of this
rule; it cannot be derived from it. On the contrary, it is what the rule itself presupposes
for its actual obtaining. Thus, when Husserl writes, "... the phenomenological a priori
consists simply in the essences of the types of consciousness and in the a priori
Notes
337
possibilities and necessities based on these essences," the "necessities" referred to are
only hypothetical. They only specify the "possibilities" of essences being given. The
fulfillment of such possibilities requires "the absolute which is the stationary streaming
now." It requires, in other words, the act of existence -- the fact of the "primal
The situation is no different when we turn from the given to speak of giving in
relation to its results. Placed in the given of time, the original now will escape from this
or a "letting loose" from what will come to be regarded as the place of the central ego.
This, however, does not mean that the central ego must appear. The most we can say is
that if a central ego is given, then it must appear as a "middle point," i.e., as a central
"source point" of constitution. Similarly, we can say that if the original now is to appear
as a moment of time, this appearance will not be such as it fix it; it will not make it the
last such appearance. This, however, does not remove the "pretension" that
temporalization will continue. It does not allow us to assert that the original now must
appear, that it must have a relation to the given. Regarded in itself, the original now
presents a sheer anonymity, one that is devoid of any tie to the given. Its otherness from
that which it objectively constitutes means that, in directly regarding it, we have no
phenomenological basis for saying that it must "give" -- i.e., that its constitution is a
The fact that the original now need not constitute does not mean that it need not
be. This would only follow if its being were dependent (somehow grounded) on its
results. For Husserl, however, the reverse is the case. The now, conceived as a
complete independence. As Husserl puts this: "The absolute has its ground in itself; and,
Notes
338
in its ground-less being (grundlosen Sein), it has its necessity as the single 'absolute
substance'" (Ms. E III 9, Nov. 5, 1931; HA XV, Kern ed., p. 386). This statement can be
constituted" (Ms. B I 14, XI, Sept. 1935, p. 19). Thus, considered as ultimately
constituting, the absolute is without a prior constitutive ground and can be called
self-caused "absolute substance," one having "its ground in itself." Its action, then, is
This means, as Husserl immediately adds: "Its necessity is not an essential necessity
which permits the contingent. All essential necessities are moments of its 'fact'
('Factums'), are modes of its functioning in relation to itself ..." 15 The functioning
and, with this, in objectivity understood as the quality of standing over and against a
subject. Insofar as they are objective, all essential necessities are "moments" of the
absolute's fact" -- i.e., are dependent on the fact of its functioning. This, of course, is
why such necessities are hypothetical, why they only express possibilities. For actual
time to an actual ordering. The fact of such temporalization is, thus, prior to all essential
necessities as that which allows them, whatever their particular character, to be actually
obtaining necessities. It is in this sense that Husserl can speak of "the absolute" as "lying
at the basis of all possibilities, all relativities, all limitations, giving them their sense and
being" (Ms. C I, Sept. 21-22, 1934; HA XV, Kern ed., p. 669). With regard to
specific set of objectively given entities. It is rather that of the presence which makes
such be -- this no matter what they are. Thus, what we confront in the temporal
dimension of the absolute is not a necessity based on essences, but rather one based on
Notes
339
Unlike the essential necessity "which permits the contingent" -- which itself is
contingent on temporalization and which leave open contingency in areas not specified
by its general rules -- this existential necessity is all embracing. To express this
tautologically, everything that is is. The necessity of its being is prior to the obtaining of
any further necessities. Considered as the necessity of nowness per se, nowness in its
otherness from objectively given entities and their essential structures, it is an absolute
necessity. We may express this in terms of the anonymity of such nowness. We can, as
features. The absence of objective content in nowness per se means that we cannot in
this process conceive of it as other than what it is. Can we conceive of it as simply not
being? We can, after all, imagine the non-existence, the permanent absence from
nowness, of an entity which once was present. Against such a supposition is the
assertion that such nowness is "not a modality of time." Considered in itself, i.e., apart
from the time it constitutes, it is absolutely stationary. Thus, its non-temporality is its
stationary, it cannot change. What we have been calling its "existential necessity" is, in
fact, its inability to depart from the constant nowness which it is. That which can so
depart is what it constitutes. Indeed, the latter, as "persisting presence" has its being
through departure. This is its lack of existential necessity. We can, thus, say that given
that anything is present and actual, the original now must be. Its being is such that it
must always be -- and this, unchangingly. The reverse proposition does not hold. The
being of this now does not imply that its constituted results, which lack its necessity,
As we have delineated it, the situation of the absolute now is exactly parallel to
independence with regard to the results of constitution. This, indeed, is why the
reduction, in bracketing these results, can uncover them. Requiring "no thing in order
to exist," they can be viewed apart from every constituted reality. We can also say that
both are "ground-less" -- i.e., are not the result of any prior constitutive activity. They
are not determined beforehand, which means that both may be considered to be
Not tied to what they may result in, they are also not determined by any ground or
cause to result in any particular given. In other words, their status is such that they can
only result in contingencies in the sense that what may follow from them has, in itself,
no necessity. Since what they have already constituted does not determine what they
can constitute, their action always contains the possibility of newness. It can surpass
These common features point back to the conclusion of our first section. The
alphabet, as the origin of content, and the original now, as the origin of time, are both
aspects of the absolute which, in every sense, lies "at the basis of all possibilities." They
are features of the absolute as the possibility of all possibilities. They are, in other
words, ways of regarding its action of grounding every possible relation between content
and time. Such relations may result in a synthetic whole -- i.e., a constituted given. But
they need not. As we said, the moments of time do not, per se, demand that they be filed
with some particular experiential content. The contents they bear could result in nothing
more than a "tumult," a chaos of experiences. If we ask why this is so, we have to say
that the moments, themselves, still have the anonymous character of their origin. They
are not contents, but rather containers of contents. As such, they lack the sensuous
quality, the given "what," which could allow us to draw a necessary relation between
Notes
341
them and what they contain. Thus, there is no possibility of applying a logic of content
to this relation. This logic, we recall, specifies the dependence of one type of content on
another. It asserts, for example, that if pitch is given, then loudness must also be present.
Here, however, we are dealing with a relation between content and the presence which is
other than content. This otherness is a function of the moment's original anonymity. It
springs from the lack of content which allows it to have a relation to every possible
content. It can contain it without altering it. That this is so indicates something more
than the contingency of an entity's existence tout court. It implies the lack of necessity of
its what conceived as an ongoing relation between its content and time.
We cannot conclude this section without observing that although we have just
spoken of moments as containers, this does not imply that time, per se, consists of
discrete units. For Husserl, it does not proceed atomistically, but rather "streams."
Behind such streaming is the lack of any inherent distinction between time's moments.
Their what -- or rather their inherent lack of what -- is always the same. Because of this,
they form, not a collection, but rather a continuum. In a certain sense, such moments can
be said to bind a being together as it persists through time. They are its existence; and as
long as a thing does exist, it exists continually and not intermittently. This holds even
The question of the contingency of the monad can be raised in terms of its
factual character. What are the possibilities included in the fact that it exists? We can
set the context of this question by looking at Husserl's description of this fact:
The first thing, then, is the fact of the I am (ego). This fact, however, only exists in the
style of infinitely open possibilities which distinguish themselves through the actuality of
Notes
342
life itself. All eidetic possibilities are, therefore, pre-contained (im voraus beschlossen)
in its style form. They are not individual determined (individuell bestimmt); but as [a
subject of] transcendental phenomenology, they are a priori constructable and
theoretically graspable (Ms. B I 13, VI, p. 3, Oct. 1, 1931).
To understand this passage, we must first observe that its referent is the method of free
variation. Husserl is discussing the "disengagement [of the essence] through pure
fantasy, the passing over into pure possibilities, the move to the pure ideas" (Ibid.). At
issue is the relation of "the fact of the I am" to the "pure possibilities" which essences or
"pure ideas" delineate. Now, the fact that I exist is the fact that I am in the stationary-
streaming present. The latter is "my living present which I factually live" (Ms. K III 12,
p. 35, 1935). Thus, when Husserl speaks of the "style form" of the fact that I am, his
reference is the ego's style of existing in and through this living present. Similarly, the
assertion that all eidetic possibilities are pre-contained in this style form is a claim that
they are pre-contained (or predetermined) by this present. With this, we can understand
Husserl's point that they are "not individually determined," but rather "distinguish
themselves through the actuality of life itself." Taking this "actuality" as the streaming
of time which proceeds from the present's "primal welling up," we can interpret this in
terms of our last section. The welling up of time is, we stressed, required if the essence
itself) as an actual ordering of conscious life. This means that all eidetic (essential)
possibilities are "pre-contained" in the "style form" of the living present since if they
obtain, they must obtain through its determination, i.e., through the action of its style
form. That this action occurs without any necessary relation to a particular content
means that it does not determine the ordering of contents -- i.e., individually determine
Let us restate our question in a more precise form. The passage we cited states
that "the fact of the I am -- i.e., the fact of the living present -- "... exists in the style of
those of birth and death. How do I understand this? How does the fact of the living
am," understood as the fact of the anonymous center of a monad, and the monad itself.
The full notion of a monad involves both the thought of a center and that of the content
laden time which surrounds it. Considered simply as centers, "monads," as Husserl
remarks, "can neither begin nor end." Indeed, so considered, "the transcendental totality
of monads is self-identical" (Ms. A V 22, p. 45, 1931). Such a totality is not a plurality
at all. It is simply the point of identity of monad within monad -- i.e., the point of
coincidence of their anonymous centers in the original present. This present, we stressed,
has a categorical necessity. It cannot begin nor end. If we were to assume that the death
of a monad meant this present's elimination, then the coincidence of monads would mean
that, with his death, all would die. Husserl, of course, does assert that "transcendental
totality of monads is contingent" (Ms. K III 12, p. 39, 1935). Yet, given the original
present's necessity, we cannot say that the contingency of monads is the latter's
contingency. Contingency pertains to monads insofar as they are the results of its
functioning. Concretely, this means that we do experience the death of Others without
our own demise. We continue functioning in the world while Others do not. For
Husserl, then, "death ... is an event in the world of humans, in the constituted world"
(Ms. A V 20, pp. 23-24, Nov. 18, 1934). It pertains to a monad qua constituted, i.e., it
To see this contingency as arising from "the fact that I am," we must turn to
Husserl's account of birth and death. His starting point is the ego's being-alive, i.e., its
Notes
344
functioning. As we cited him, the living ego "acts, it posits its thesis; and this acting is a
letting loose from itself, a primal welling up ..." The welling up of this acting is
temporalization. Thus, before its being-alive, i.e., prior to its birth, such temporalization
does not occur. Husserl, accordingly, describes birth as a transition from a "primal sleep"
to a "primal awakening": The "primally sleeping ego" is "that which possesses nothing
as an existent and has nothing pre-given; it is, equally, an ego which is temporalizing
nothing and has not temporalized anything as an existent." Because of this, it is an ego
which "does not, in any sense, have an actual consciousness of anything and, thus, does
not have a habitual directedness to anything. Therefore, it is not even temporalized for
itself. In other words, my 'primally sleeping ego' or monad is nothing for itself ..." (Ms.
A VI 14, p. 7, 1930). This does not signify that this ego is nothing in itself -- i.e.,
nothing at all. What Husserl is describing is similar to the phenomenon that occurs in the
dreamless sleep which does not give any sense of the passage of time. To the point that
the sleeping ego does not temporalize -- and, hence, does not have a sense of departing
time -- it may be regarded as a life which is collapsed into its center. In other words, the
lack of its functioning implies its reduction to the now which is prior to all objective
temporalization. Stripped of its being for itself, its being in itself is its being in the
anonymous, original present. The latter remains with its categorical or absolute necessity
through all of its contingent expressions. Thus, to the point that the statements about the
"primally sleeping ego" have a referent, it is to that now concerning which Husserl
writes: "The absolute is 'now,' persisting in the streaming changes of its modes.
With the mode of awakeness, we do have temporalization. The ego's birth is the
beginning of its "primal temporalization." The departure in time brought about by this
temporalization creates those temporal distances in which objects can appear, can be
temporalized into existents. As awake, my ego can be said to act. With the
Notes
345
temporalization inherent in my acts, I can achieve "my being for myself in temporality."
this includes my self-objectification -- i.e., my being "something for myself, the human
self which I now am ..." (Ms. A VI 14, p. 7). The same points, but in reverse order, are
made about death. Death is the collapse of the wakefulness just described. In a certain
sense, it is a return to the egological state which existed before birth, i.e., before the
temporalization which gives the ego its life. It is, thus, the "cessation of all conscious life
and, with this, also the cessation of the ego as the identical pole of this life and [the
cessation] of the capacities pertaining to it" (Ms. C 8 I, p. 8, Oct. 1929, italics added).
This is not a collapse into nothingness; it is rather a return to the now which is the
independent origin of this life. What remains is the now which, in temporalizing, first
resulted in the ego's presence as a pole, i.e., a middle point, of its life.
The reason why this collapse is a possibility of "the fact of the I am" is that this
fact is distinct from what it factually constitutes. The fact in question is the fact of my
now; but this now, which is the independent origin of my life, is such by constantly
distinguishing itself from my life in its objective givenness. This givenness includes the
essential structures or rules for ordering experiences which, with a particular sensuous
content, make my life my life. Such structures are part and parcel of my habitualities,
my capabilities as an ego pole. The now actualizes them by making them obtain from
present to present. It does this, however, only through its constant transcendence of the
something present ..." (Ms. D 14, May 7-9, 1934).17 This dying is a "dying away" into
pastness of the moments which make up my objective life. It is their separation from the
now which is the source of this life. On the one hand, this separation is an absolute
necessity if my life is to be objectively given -- i.e., exist in time. On the other, this same
All of the arguments of our last section apply here. My life, as inherently other
than its constitutive origin, has no inherent claim on this origin. It cannot demand that
formation, its necessary otherness from that which actualizes it and maintains it in being
continue to be. Thus, the essential structures which characterize the necessities of a life
have the possibility of no longer having a field of applicability. If they cease to, then a
regard to the subject is no longer a regard to a full monad, i.e., to a center and a
centering, content laden life. Only the anonymous center remains; and, without its
anonymity stripped of the "this" and the "my." In other words, it becomes the now
which, for Husserl, is before all division into mine and thine. This is the now which
We can conclude this chapter by reducing this argument for our contingency to
its most elementary terms: The now, which is the source of my self-existence, is always
"ahead" of me. Because it is, I cannot seize it so as to fix it as something which I have,
once and for all, grasped or acquired. Thus, I cannot posit my self-existence with the
Behind this reasoning is the point that, from the perspective of the constituted, the now
appears as ever new, ever lapsing into pastness, constantly transcending itself and, hence
constantly other than itself. As such, the now appears as the pure form of the factual in
its contingency. As we cited Husserl, "facts are contingent." Their very meaning as facts
is that "they could be otherwise". From the perspective of the constituted, the ever new
now is the very possibility of otherness, i.e., of a new stage for settling the world's
accounts. This otherness is a possibility springing from "the fact of the I am" when we
take this fact as including both the original, timeless now and the time it constitutes.
Notes
347
Since the original now can remain now only by transcending its objectification in time, it
can remain now in time only by appearing as the ever new now of successive time.
Taking such newness as facticity, we can say that facticity is the inevitable result of the
appearing of the nunc stans in time. Since the fact of our existence is that of such
All of this, of course, is from the perspective of the constituted. Yet, we cannot
avoid the conclusion of our contingency when we shift to the standpoint of the original,
constituting now. From its own perspective, the original now is never other. It remains
lacks any relation to the constituted and, hence, any basis for our supposing that it must
continue to constitute. We can also say that the sheer uniqueness of its presence is such
CHAPTER VI
A SECOND SOLUTION TO THE PROBLEM OF INTERSUBJECTIVITY
Given Husserl's doctrine of the uniqueness of the now in which egos function, it
is not surprising that the question which initially confronts him is not that of the
compatibility of functioning egos. If that by which they function is one, then such
compatibility may be assumed. The first question is that of the otherness of egos, i.e.,
their distinctness as numerical singulars. This, as Husserl remarks, is the "reverse" of the
usual way of posing the question of intersubjectivity. We do not, as is usual, first assume
a plurality and then pose the question of compatibility. Having performed the reduction
on an individual, we rather ask how the structures we uncover must involve a plurality.
There is not, first, a plurality of souls and the question: Under what conditions are they
"compatible" with one another in their existence? Rather, the question is: When I am
certain of a soul and when (in self-giving intuition) I steep myself in its proper essence,
how can I gather from this that it is merely "a" soul and can only be as such? How can I
infer that this soul must point to other souls in its very essence, that this soul is, indeed,
an in-and-for-itself, but yet only has sense in a plurality which is grounded in itself and
which must develop from itself (Ms. C 17 I, Sept. 20-22, 1931; HA XV, Kern ed., p.
341).
The problem, here, concerns the "proper essence" of a soul. A regard to it must
show that the soul is only "a" soul -- i.e., one soul among many. The same regard,
however, must also show that this multitiude is grounded in the soul and develops from
it. This essence, then, expresses a duality in the soul's relation to the intersubjective
plurality; on the other, it points to the soul as a grounded member of such a plurality.
We can also say that since this essence involves both the ground and the grounded, it
points to what is self-grounding. The essence is such that the soul, in grounding a
plurality, includes the ground of its own objectification as a member of this plurality.
When we ask how we can "infer" the above from the "self-giving intuition" of a
soul's essence, we must keep in mind the duality of ground and grounded. For a soul to
ground itself as a member of a plurality, it must, as a ground, contain more than its
other words, surpass the realization provided by its numerically singular, objective being.
If this were not the case, then its objectified expression would be limited to one soul and
not to a plurality (See above, ). Thus, on the level of the ground, what Husserl
requires to establish the otherness of souls is the evidence of the ground's surpassing
quality in relation to its objectified expressions. This evidence can be taken as that of the
implies my ground's surpassing quality". As for the evidence for this contingency, this,
according to our last chapter, is provided by the very fact of subjective existence. Since
this is the fact of the appearing of the nunc stans in time, it inherently involves
contingency. Any direct evidence of the ground's surpassing quality must, of course,
involve the reduction. It is the latter which, in exhibiting the ground as the possibility of
What about the level of the grounded -- i.e., that of the individual members of
the intersubjective plurality? Husserl writes in this regard, "Monads in the plural,
coexisting monads as a possibility: inherent in this is that the being of the one leaves
open the possibility of the being of the other" (Ms. C 17 I, HA XV, p. 335). This leaving
open (offen lassen) is, we can say, the objectified expression of the surpassing quality of
Notes
350
the ground. If the possibilities of the ground surpass any particular objectified
expression, then that expression exhibits this by showing itself as one among many -- i.e.,
surpassing ground means that it does not exhaust the possibilities of being "a" soul. Its
being, qua grounded, thus, allows the inference of alternate possibilities understood as
alter egos.
objectifications. If the ground must, through its surpassing quality, objectify itself as a
plurality, then each member of this plurality must leave open the possibility of other
members. Here, the otherness of ground and grounded is expressed by the surpassing
nature of the ground; and this is matched, on the objective level, by the otherness implied
To add a word of caution, this doctrine must not be taken as signifying that its
propositions could be verified by two separate regards, one to the ground, another to the
grounded. A regard to the ground does not per se reveal its surpassing quality.
such, the individual soul is not, per se, present within it. Thus, the individual soul, as
that which is surpassed, must be regarded if we are to regard the ground as surpassing.
Similarly, to speak of a soul as implying its alternative egos, we must consider both itself
and its ground. The latter is what situates it in a horizon of alternative possibilities. The
soul implies these, not as an independent "in and for itself", but rather in its dependence
on something greater. With this, we see that it is the full essence of the soul which must
be regarded -- i.e., its essence as containing both ground and grounded. To focus on
evidence of otherness which neither aspect of the soul can provide when separately
Notes
351
regarded.1 With this proviso, let us take as our focus the leaving open which occurs on
For Husserl, when I speak of my being as a ground of the world, the reference is
to my coincidence with the primal present. The latter forms the non-worldly, anonymous
world. Regarded in itself, it does not just ground my world. As we quoted Husserl, there
is present "within it ... all time and world in every sense." Thus, to the point that I imply
this present, I imply something more than a private ground. Let us put this in terms of
the notion of leaving open. When Husserl speaks of the being of one monad leaving
open the possibility of the being of another, he adds that "the possibility of my monadic
functioning center by virtue of my being in the primal present. The claim, then, is that
my being in this primal present -- i.e., in nowness per se -- is, on the objective level, my
There are a number of ways in which this claim can be understood. The first
dependence on the stream of experience which passively constitutes his individual life.
This dependence signifies that egological being is not within the subject's constitutive
powers. He cannot actively constitute either his own or another's life. We can deepen
this argument by saying that nowness per se is now within my constitutive powers. The
life. It gives me my being as the center of this life. Yet, as we noted, this nowness is
always "ahead" of me. I cannot objectively grasp it. I cannot posit it as my constituted
conclusion arises when we assert that such nowness is my actuality and also claim that
individual activity. In a certain sense, this actuality is not "mine" at all. Identified with
nowness per se, it is prior to all division between "mine" and "thine." It is only when we
speak of "a" soul that we can speak of a definite possessor. What possesses this nowness
is part of the soul insofar as the soul's essence includes its ground. Yet it is also other
than the soul insofar as it indicates what is prior to its being "a" soul.
said to constitute Others in the nowness of their being. My being as "a" soul, a being
possibility of other souls who are similarly grounded. This means that each soul must be
considered as other in the sense that no soul can be considered as the product of other,
already individualized souls. The surpassing quality of the ground, thus, expresses itself
in the fact that Others must be regarded as surpassing an individual's constitutive powers.
To put the same point in a slightly different fashion, we can say that when we regard the
soul's full essence, we regard both the primal, constituting nowness and the individual
expression of this which such primal nowness surpasses. In implying more than what the
individual can constitutively accomplish, this nowness implies the possibility of this
"more" in a specific sense. It implies the possibility of more than one individual soul,
A second way to understand the claim of leaving open is in terms of the notion
point functioning in time. As we earlier put this, "In all remembrances of my past acts, I
always appear as the here and the now of such acts". In a certain sense, what I confront
Notes
353
individualizes the self; it defines it as a central observer and actor. Thus, a succession of
identification. Apprehending what is the same in all these remembered selves, the act
time. This identity includes my present being insofar as I also take it as in time, i.e., as a
Here, I focus on my "ego in its most original originality" -- i.e., on it in coincidence with
primal nowness. As we cited Husserl, such an ego is "not in time". This means that "in
its original functioning" -- i.e., its functioning in coincidence with the origin of time --
"the functioning pole is never in the temporal field" (Ms. A V 5, p. 3, June 1933). Such
functioning results in the temporal field and, hence, in the "apartness of time." When,
however, we take it as a feature of the now which is "not a modality of time," we cannot
describe in such terms. In Husserl's words, this now's functioning "is 'continuously'
p. 4, 1930). Thus, to affirm the identity of the ego which functions to constitute time, I
must assert "as continuity which is basically different than the external continuity of an
i.e., my objective self-otherness as a series of past selves. It provides the elements for
my identity as a persisting center. Yet, as Husserl observes: "The constant ego, the
constant source, [is] not identical through an act of identification, but rather is such as a
Notes
354
primally single being (ureinig Sein) existing in the pre-being (vor-Sein) which is the
What we are confronting are two forms of self-identity: one before time and
another posterior to it. These two forms are, in fact, indicative of the duality of the soul's
essence. Its full essence includes its notion both as ground and grounded. It comprises
its notion as functioning before time to ground "all time and world" and its notion as a
result of such functioning. To grasp its self-identity on the functioning level is to grasp it
in its unique, "primally single being." Thus, insofar as I take myself as a presently
them, not as past, but as present in the unique nowness of all functioning. Such nowness
is before all placing in time, before all temporal departure into pastness. As such, it does
not, per se, include the pastness of the self. The apprehension of my functioning self-
identity is, therefore, founded on the lack of temporal distance between my past and
present functioning selves. It is the apprehension of such selves "in common," i.e., in the
the case if, in asserting the former, I denied the reality of the elements -- the past selves --
which constituted the latter. Yet, the past selves do exist. They exist as the results of the
functioning self. Thus, as our last chapter pointed out, the ego is "transcendency in
from one form of self-identity to another. By virtue of the temporalization which creates
ongoing act of identification, it is continually identified as one and the same. In this
context, temporalization can be seen as a process which mediates between these two
Notes
355
open of the nunc stans. If I am in communion with my past selves in the constant now,
then I also have to say that this communion includes my potential Others. To return to a
There is, indeed, community ... There is community [of self and Others] in the
same way as there is such with regard to my non-temporally extended one and the
same ego which supports the temporality which streams and constitutes.
Community with oneself [i.e., one's past selves] and with Others is concerned
with the union of ego-poles. My ego as an ego which is now and my past ego --
the pole -- have no distance; there is no temporal stretch between them ... The ego
as a pole does not endure. So also my ego and the other ego in the community of
our being with each other do not have any extensive distance [from one
another] ... (Ms. C 16 VII, p. 5, May 1933).
identity, then it must leave open the possibility that the same founding includes Others in
their persisting identity. This follows from the duality of my essence. This duality
includes both what is private and what, in its uniqueness, can be common. It includes the
identity of "a" soul and the identity of that which is prior to this. To affirm my self-
identity in terms of this essence, I must, then, accept a level of my being which implies
they exist) share a common ground for our functioning and, hence, for our being
temporally objective. This implies that, on the level of my coincidence with this ground,
through memory. The latter provides the elements for the synthesis of my persisting
taken as the "primal empathy" discussed in the last chapter. It is rather to be understood
as that which reaches out to my Other in his objective persence. Expressed in these
terms, the conclusion is that memory and empathy delineate the same basic relationship.
They spring from a common root which is the level of my coincidence with my ground,
and they express this ground's common relation to both myself and Others considered as
objective. If we grant this, then memory must leave open the possibility of empathy. I
cannot deny the relation of empathy without also denying that of memory. This follows
since the claim of the above is that I am in contact with my Other in the same basic way
Husserl makes this claim again and again in the 1930's. A couple of passages
Thus, even though space and time separate me from my past existence, through memory
I remain "in contact (in Fühlung)" with this existence. The assertion is that my relation
to the Other is like this. Another manuscript from the same year puts this in terms of the
I say as well [that the Other is] "outside" of my monad, but this existing outside is itself
included in my monad as an intentional unity which is confirmed through the harmonious
course of re-presentations (Vergegenwärtigungsverlauf). Just as my own past is included
in my present as an intentional unity of my multiple memories, a unity which is
harmonious albeit by correction, and just as my past is not nothing within me (not
nothing within my proper being as a present being) but rather possesses actuality and
constantly maintains this within me as my past, i.e., possesses actuality in the continuing
perceptions which stream from present to present: just so, the Other, the co-present
[person] is not nothing within me, but rather is within me as my Other; and I am who I
am only as bearing in myself this Other and all Others" (Ms. C 17 I, Sept. 1931; HA XV,
Kern ed., p. 336).
The main assertion of this passage is clear. Insofar as they are objectively present, both
self and Others have an intentional presence. Each is an "intentional unity" -- i.e., a one
in many -- which is established through the synthesis involving the "harmonious course"
his objectified self and his objectified Others -- returns us to our initial observation. As
functioning, he is who he is in his coincidence with the source of this functioning. The
source, however, bears the same relation to Husserl and his Others. As temporally
objective, they are both the results of the source's functioning and, thus, are equally
To put this in terms of memory and empathy, let us note with Husserl their
common features. The first is that both lack original presence. For memory, this is
Notes
358
immediately clear. When Husserl remarks, "Isn't perception the unreachable limit of
intuition through memory, he answers by observing that if we crossed this limit, the
would have eliminated "the pastness of memory." Empathy also has an unreachable
limit. As Husserl draws the analogy, "In the same way, the givenness of the Others's
concrete present in empathy cannot have the full intuitability of a self-perception ...
Empathy can never become perception" (Ms. E III 9, Sept. 1933; HA XV, p. 598). The
reason for this is equally clear. If my perception of the Other reached the point of my
of the Other would be eliminated. We cannot have both perceptions for "one would
the limit of empathy, it is also the limit of self-remembering. This limit can never be
reached, for if I were to achieve "the full intuitability of a self-perception," I would grasp
only the anonymity of the presently functioning self. Here, the realm of the intuition in
which subjects are immediately present to themselves -- i.e., present without any
the self. It directs itself to the level where selves presently function; but this is a level
where they are identified with the original present in its stationary streaming. Thus, as
Husserl here observes: "The structural analysis of the original present (of the stationary,
living streaming) leads us to the structure of the ego and to the lower levels of non-
egological streaming which constantly found this structure ..." It leads, in other words,
"to the radically pre-egological" (Ibid.). Granting this, the full intuitability of self and
Others can only occur by reaching a level where the distinction of self and Others no
longer obtains. This level ties memory and empathy together insofar as it is the limit of
both. It is also their intersection point since to reach it is to eliminate their separate
Notes
359
objects. To reverse this, we can say that from the perspective of this limit, which is that
With this, we have a second feature which memory and empathy share. They are
both presentative, but neither can directly present its object. Both, then, must be
perceived. Its non-originality consists in the fact that it cannot directly grasp the
nowness which once animated the contents of a perception. In its grasping the past as
past, this nowness must, in a certain sense, present itself as absent. The same point holds
objective to myself "as intentional unity of my multiple memories." This, we must add is
the only way in which I can be objective since a direct grasp of my nowness yields only
"Empathy is also re-presentation," and for the very same reason (Ms. B I 22, V, p. 23,
1930's). I have to grasp the Other as a unity of multiple memories. I have to grasp his
external object. The re-presentational quality of the latter can, we implied, be matched to
since I cannot directly grasp a self. On closer inspection, this contrast is deceptive.
unities require what Husserl calls "the harmonious course of re-presentations." In other
words, taking re-presentation in its general sense as a presenting again of what was once
when we note that in constituting an object, the contents I directly apprehend constantly
give way to others. They are continuously departing into pastness as the object
temporally unfolds its contents to me. Now, if these contents are not to vanish the
moment I apprehend them, they must be made present again. Only as co-present with
my ongoing act can they be synthesized into a persisting unity of sense. Thus, a "direct"
elements, then it is in the same position of the intentional unities of self and Other. Re-
The above does not mean that there is no distinction between memory and
This distinction does not obviate a point which Husserl is attempting to make in
gives us a temporal distinction between the constituting ego and the unities it constitutes.
It results in the contrast between the original nowness of constitution and the nowness
immediately present, i.e., to nowness stripped of all re-presentation -- self, Others and,
indeed, the objects of external perception are indistinguishable. Yet out of this nowness
Notes
361
a difference is constituted, a difference whereby I can say, "The Other exists for me as a
co-present ego ... I possess his present as a co-present ..." (Ms. C 3 III, p. 33, March
1931). Husserl puts this in terms of the "absolute ego" and the "new synthesis" which is
The absolute ego is the ego which in streaming constancy constitutes and has constituted
the world. Within it, as the basis of this universal constitutive performance, there is
present the self-alienation (selbst-entfremdung) of monadization and, hence, the
constitution of a monadic universe of mutually equivalent and essentially similar
monads. The latter display themselves in the absolute ego as a distinct temporal sphere
which can be differentiated or [what is the same, they display themselves] as a universal
co-existence ... In establishing a community of monads as a monadic universe within
monadic time, we have a new synthesis, one which, in temporalizing, produces a unity
withhin multiplicity, a unity of co-existence, that of a single time to which immanent
times or immanent unities -- the streams of experience and their centering ego poles -- all
being (Ms. E II 1, Jan. 15, 1934, HA XV, Kern ed., p. 636).
This "new synthesis" moves us beyond primal empathy. In the latter, when I regard the
and his now as existing in one ..." (Ms. C 17 I; HA XV, p. 332). Here, however,
nowness is presented as absent, i.e., at a remove which allows it to be "a distinct temporal
synthesis. The now in its absence is the now that has departed into pastness. My re-
departed from presence. The recalled now, insofar as it implies this departure, is not the
same as the original now which served as its point of departure. Hence, its return to
presence makes it co-present rather than coincident with the latter. The same point can
Notes
362
be made in terms of Husserl's assertion that self and Others are objectively present as
Thus, when I assert that I am "in contact" with my past self through re-presentation, I am
presupposing the temporalization which first made this self depart into pastness. The
case is no different for my objectified Other or, indeed, for the inanimate objects which I
synthesize along with my objective self. The otherness impicit in their temporal co-
existence is an otherness which the departure, the flowing into pastness, of already
constituted time imposes between the originally present and the re-presented. Thus, as
present. It can only re-present it in terms of what has departed from it. Because of this,
its result is never the sheer coincidence which characterizes the point from which this
departure occurs -- i.e., the original present of the "absolute ego." Quite the contrary,
objects whose temporal syntheses involve an equal remove from this present -- i.e., a
flowing off of contents into equal degrees of pastness -- can be apprehended as co-
and empathy. Let us conclude by expressing this section's result in terms of leaving
open. Our initial claim was that we cannot deny the relation of memory without also
denying empathy. We can now say that memory must be such that it leaves open the
possibility of empathy since what makes it possible -- which is the action of re-
presentation -- is also what makes empathy possible. Both depend on our grasp of
nowness as absent. Both require its re-presentation as the nowness which stands over
against the original present of functioning. Let us put this in terms of simultaneity.
Simultaneity is the existence of non-exclusive presents. Each such present permits the
presents are, thus, distinguished from the uniquely singular, exclusive present of the pre-
Notes
363
temporal now. If the latter is thought of as their ground -- i.e., that which bears them as
its temporal exhibitions -- then the otherness of ground and grounded is a condition for
the leaving open -- i.e., the non-exclusivity -- of simultaneity. Concretely speaking, this
This condition, we should note, is inherent in the full essence of the soul. As involving
includes both primal nowness and the re-presented nowness which has the possibility of
co-presence. As including in its notion the continuous transition from one to the other,
this essence inherently leaves open the possibility of other, co-present souls or "monads"
distinguishes between the original and the re-presented present. It is also capable of
the same degree of pastness, however, its powers of differentiation fail. Confining
ourselves to the "pure" temporal process, the re-presentation of that which involves the
same degree of departure is, in fact, the same. It leaves open the possibility of
simultaneity -- i.e., of non-exclusive presents; but it does not contain the conditions
Let us put this in terms of the analogous case of considering extension by itself.
positions. It cannot distinguish between one and the same position. For this, we require
time. We must make the distinction: "here at times x, y, or z." To reverse this, in
Notes
364
distinguishing the same time, we must be able to say: "now at positions x, y, or z."
content. The temporal stream must be content laden. Its contents must succeed each
other in an order which yields the perspectival appearing of a visual field if we are to
dimensional world.
Granting this, we cannot speak of self and Others as co-present without assuming
content. Indeed, without this assumption, we cannot differentiate ego from ego.
Considered as a temporal center, the ego is only an "empty form". It is something which
(and within this, the ego as a center, as the ego of this stream) is concrete as an immanent
temporal form which is continuously filled." What fills it is "the content which
composes the perception of the world" (Ms. C 7 II, p. 16, ca. June 15, 1934). This
position is repeated again and again with minor variations. Content is said to be what
distinguishes my world as my own. It is what underlies the relativity of the world -- i.e.,
centers viewing the world in its different aspects. Husserl, for example, asks: "Can the
other ego, the other concrete streaming present be the same as my ego and present? But,
each, as apperceiving the same world, must necessarily have different aspects, etc. (and
only so, can he be an Other). Accordingly, he cannot have the same fields of sensation
with the same data of sensation, etc." (Ms. E III 9, Sept. 1933; HA XV, Kern ed., p.
598).
Behind this necessity for different sensuous contents is the fact that, regarded as
"the identical persisting pole in the changes of immanent temporal events," the ego is not
yet individualized. "I have always said," Husserl writes, "that the pure ego is abstract; it
Notes
365
is concrete only through the content of the streaming present" (Ms. C III 3, p. 28, March
1931). It is through such changing content, as opposed to its invariant temporal form,
that the ego achieves its uniqueness, its distinction from its Others. Thus, for Husserl,
"The absolute uniqueness [of the ego] lies in the content of the ego itself, [this]
notwithstanding the universal form, the universal essence through which the ego is an
ego" (Ms. C 8 I, p. 23, June-July, 1932). The latter is the universal form of temporal
centering. It results in the "streaming center 'now,' the streaming just past and what is to
come ..." -- i.e., the advancing future. With content, we have "the center of the 'absolute
here' which corresponds to the now and pertains to it" (Ms. B III 1, p. 85, end of Oct.-
Nov. 4, 1929). For this here and now to be unique -- i.e., be distinguished from those of
We stress this point because of what it indicates about the basis of re-
presentation. When Husserl writes that along with memory, "empathy is also re-
presentation," he adds a third feature which they share in common. An original presence
singular ego" because my functioning is identified with its functioning -- i.e., its making
present. Thus, I apprehend this present in its "primal mode" when I apprehend it as the
Notes
366
uniquely singular core of my functioning. In this context, to call memory and empathy
grounded by the original making present. Both must synthesize their objects by re-
presenting what is contained in the uniquely singular present. Since this present is
unique, the original (non-represented) presence of self and Others must be the same.
Yet, through re-presentation, both must be distinct. With this, we set the character of the
basis for their re-presentation. If we are to have distinct heres corresponding to the now,
content must enter into this basis. Thus, this original present must contain content, a
content appropriate to its "non-numerically singular" status. In other words, its presence
must be that of the absolute whose underlying character is exhibited by the aspects of
Let us take a moment to clarify this last assertion. We earlier remarked that time
and content are part of the absolute insofar as they are features of its being the ground of
all possible syntheses. We now assert that this ground is present in the anonymous core
of subjective functioning. Here, we have a dual claim. Insofar as time is an aspect of the
absolute, we are asserting that, pre-objectively, the whole of the time required for every
possible synthesis is present in the pre-temporal now of this core. Considering the
absolute as an alphabet of contents, we are asserting that the alphabet, itself, is present in
this now. In other words, in the nowness of our functioning, we do not just have the
contents of the impressional moment -- i.e., the sensuous contents of our immediately
present visual field. Our claim is that this nowness contains the totality of the content
To show that the whole of time is present in the core, we must return to the
arguments dealing with our functioning self-identity. As we cited Husserl, this identity is
that of "a primally single being existing in the pre-being which is the most primal" (Ms.
of time since it does not have a beyond. Insofar as it is prior to extended time, it cannot
be thought of one among many nows, each being considered "external" to the others.
Pre-objectively, there is no such thing as a temporal distance, which means that the
phenomenon, but rather that which manifests the character of one in many (See above,
). The pre-temporal now is the presence manifesting itself in each successive moment.
As present, none of them are outside it -- this, even though, objectively speaking, they
The above can also be put in terms of our earlier remark that the now in time is
the objective exhibition of the pre-temporal now. Granting this, we can say with Husserl,
"When the ego is exhibiting its past, when it is actually remembering and finding itself in
successive being, it is, in fact, exhibiting its full present, exhibiting what it is now, what
[pre-objectively] lies within it as an ego" (Ms. A V 5, p. 10, Jan. 1933). The basis of this
statement is Husserl's assertion that "the ego is continually a pole; it has no breadth, no
[temporal] extension; it has nothing of the character of apartness ..." (Ibid.). This
signifies that, in functioning to constitute time, "the present ego is self-shaping (sich
selbst gestaltend) and bears within itself its past self-shapings" (Ibid.). The ego "bears"
(trägt) its past self-shapings through its acts of re-presentation of what it originally
presents or exhibits. It shapes itself through the "streaming making present" of its life.
In this way, its exhibition or "explication (Auslegung) leads necessarily to the time of
consciousness and to its self-temporalization as a quasi-extension of the ego over time ..."
(Ibid.). The key point, here, is that re-presentation depends upon presentation; but the
latter is a temporal exhibition of what is pre-temporally present in the ego's core. This
implies that the ego becomes in time what, in a certain sense, it already is before time.
Notes
368
Per se, its "'living present' is not the stream of consciousness" -- i.e., the stream of
impressional moments (Ms. C 2 I, p. 22, Aug. 1931). Thus, the temporal exhibition of
what is in this present is not an exhibition of something which, per se, is already
temporal (See Ibid.). When the ego is exhibiting "what it is now," it is engaged in a
objectively, contains "all time and world" to what, objectively speaking, is only a
particular exhibition of this. With this, Husserl's position may be stated as follows: In
the original present, with its lack of temporal distances, we cannot distinguish self and
Others or the objects of our surrounding world. In this present's "all at once," the past,
the momentary present and the advancing future are "now" but are not yet distinguished.
It is through presencing and re-presentation that we have these distinctions and, hence,
self and Others can become particularized into subjects, each with his distinct here and
now.
Since such particularization involves content, let us turn to our second claim:
namely that the alphabet of contents is present in the anonymous core of the functioning
contents forming it have the possibility of being arranged in every possible temporal
ordering and, thus, help to ground every possible synthesis. To speak of contents in this
definite ordering, they are prior to all objectively nameable unities of sense. They are
simply the elements of such unities, elements which are abstracted from all temporal
orderings. Their "place," then, is in that which has "no breadth, no [temporal]
extension." They are not in time, but rather in the pre-temporal now which is at the core
of subjective functioning. "Exhibiting what it is now," this core produces the present
impressional moment with its limited content. It does this repeatedly. This "spelling
Notes
369
out," so to speak, of what it contains produces the definite temporal order of contents
time. That is to say, it must be regarded as already containing all the contents which
With this, we have the context for Husserl's position that, on the level of the
original making present, memory and empathy have a common root. Their source is
within me insofar as it forms my functioning core. Yet it results in more than what I can,
Don't we finally arrive at the fact that even what is hidden (das Verborgene) in
sedimentation and [its] activization still plays its role in the living present as the present
of a concrete subjectivity; [don't we arrive at the fact] that streaming being (constituting
qua streaming each and every entity for me) contains in a concentrated fashion [every]
entity in itself and temporality in itself. It is what it is (in its manner of being) precisely
as the living present, as the living constituting present; and, hence, as pertaining to this, it
is what it is as the potentiality for such [world] constitution ... There [in the living
present], every Other, every other ego, every other transcendental being-present is also
constituted in me, constituted precisely as a streaming co-present subjectivity which is,
itself, concrete in its streaming living present. This, just as there is streamingly
constituted in me my own temporality of being as a past being, as a concrete streaming
present and this [as a present] for every past" (Ms. C III 3, p. 32, March 1931).
The point of the first part of this passage is that the constitutive potentiality of the living
present extends beyond what the passage of time has laid down (or sedimented) as a
subjective possession. Reactivated, this acquisition can play its role in constitution. Yet
constitution employs even what is "hidden" in such activization (Weckung). It has at its
disposal the content of the living present -- i.e., the present which "is what it is" precisely
as the potential for an all-embracing world constitution. The passage's closing remarks
Notes
370
focus on the fact that the constitution of myself as a "concrete streaming present" requires
the constitution of my past. This past makes the present "concrete" by making it appear
as the leading edge of an extended life, i.e., as a present "for" a definitely given past life.
Here, Husserl's claim is that the very temporalization which gives me a past and, hence,
gives me the data which I can synthetically re-present as my persisting self performs the
same service for my Other. The claim, then, is that the original making present which
results in subjective concreteness is ultimately "the origin of Others and of myself as one
among many within the objective world ..." (Ms. K III 4, p. 77, Jan. 20, 1936). What is
being asserted is, in fact, our co-constitution. Because of this, Husserl can say: "I exist
as a streaming present; but my [objective] being for myself is itself constituted in this
streaming present ... The Other exists for me in the same way ..." (Ms. C III 3, p. 33).
This notion of existence "for me" should not be taken in a solipsistic sense. It is
not as a solis ipse that I can assert that "every Other ... is also constituted in me." In fact,
appresented in him ... I am a subject for everything that exists and a subject for all those
who, themselves, are subjects for everything that exists including myself. The absolute
subject bears Others in himself as self-appresentations ..." (Ms. C III 3, p. 33). His point
is that this absolute subject is not my objective subjectivity. It is rather the constituting,
egological character of this core's temporalization, Husserl can speak of "the 'primordial'
and the re-presented Other in the streaming now." He can assert that "the stream does
not just have a self-implication but also the implication of other streams -- the
constitution of unities within the stream ... I and Others as [constituted] unities in the
stream" (Ms. D 14, p. 8, March 1931). The "primordial" Other is, in fact, the same as my
primordial self. Both are indistinguishable in the stationary streaming now. From the
Notes
371
point of view of this now, both self and Others are represented or constituted unities.
Thus, each subject, in taking up the standpoint of his ground can be said to bear both his
Let us put this in terms of memory and empathy. If from the standpoint of my
ground, the Other can be considered as my self-appresentation, then from this standpoint
memory and empathy are not distinct. They become distinct after individualization, i.e.,
It is only at this point that I can speak of memory as recalling what is distinctly my own.
intentions. These are the intentions which reach out from my living present to that of the
environments.
Now, the fact that the full essence of my soul includes both levels -- that of my
ground and that of this ground's objectification into what is proper to me -- allows me to
make opposing assertions. I can assert that memory and empathy are not distinct. I can
also claim the opposite. Husserl, focusing on the full essence of the soul, attempts to
combine the perspectives of both assertions by writing: "... in the originality of empathy,
(ein Selbterinneren der Anderen) in the course of which the being co-present of Others is
understood as that of another living present which related to my living present. The co-
depends upon the individualization of self and Others into distinct unities. As such, it is
soul. From the perspective of the latter, the relation of living presents, concretely taken
this present since the originally present "self," which is here thought of as remembered, is
not yet considered as the self of an individual which stands over against his Others. If
this is the case, then we have a reciprocity which allows a second interpretation of "the
self-remembering since the object of what counts for me as empathy has the same origin
The same points hold with regard to Husserl's assertion, "The co-being of Others
coincidence with my ground that I make myself present. It is as something made present
(as an objectified presence), that I exist with "the co-being of Others." Since the full
making present.
There are two ways to understand this last assertion. We can say that the co-
being of Others is dependent on my making present. Here, we focus on the basic notion
original way must be grounded on the originally present. A second understanding goes
further than this. It claims that I cannot make myself present without also appresenting
the co-being of Others. In other words, such co-being does not just imply my making
present, but also the reverse. This last, of course, is Husserl's position. As we cited him,
the "soul must point to other souls in its very essence ..." Accordingly, it "only has sense
Notes
373
in a plurality which is grounded in itself and must develop from itself" (Ms. C 17 I, Sept.
To move from the first to the second understanding, we must draw out what is
originally present, its basis is the anonymous core of my functioning. On the one hand,
this core is that by virtue of which I am a self -- i.e., a functioning center. It is, on the
other hand, the absolute in both of its aspects. This means that in the non-extended unity
of my core, I possess the totality of time and content required for every possible
synthesis. As we earlier put this, the core by which I function contains the possibility of
all synthetic possibilities. Now, this core is the original presence which re-presentation
presents. It thus follows that my self re-presentation must include its presence. My
that present by virtue of which I am a self. Since the latter contains more than the
possibilities which I can objectively manifest, its re-presentation must involve my re-
make myself present as one among many subjective possibilities of being and behaving.
This can be put in terms of the assertion that the soul "only has sense in a
plurality which is grounded in itself." For Husserl, this means that the soul (qua re-
presented) has a sense only as a member of a plurality grounded in itself (qua originally
present). Thus, as a constituted unity, it has its sense only in terms of the open ended
plurality of constitutive possibilities which are grounded in its original present. Such a
what surpasses its objective presence. Yet, if we grant this, it is senseless to conceive of
a solipsistic soul. To be a soul, it must be a self. This means that its essence must
include its status as re-presented and as originally present. As originally present, it has
an anonymous core of its functioning. Yet, the re-presentation of this core, which yields
Notes
374
the objective presence of a soul, always surpasses it and, hence, makes us understand it as
"a" soul -- i.e., as one among many possible manifestations of subjective existence. Qua
re-presented (or what is the same), qua constituted, it must, then, always leave open the
Our last section concluded that I cannot re-present myself without re-presenting
other possibilities of being and behaving. This should not be taken as indicating that all
such re-presentations are on the same level. Thus, it does not mean that the Other is
upon the presencing of my core. The latter results in the stream of impressional
moments which I take as my stream of consciousness. The synthesis of its contents gives
me my world with my Others. Admitting this, I cannot say that my self re-presentation
involves my viewing the world from multiple perspectives. Only one perspective is
actual for me. Our conclusion accepts this, but asserts that this perspective is re-
moments.
Let us put this in terms of the double perspective which our last section
attempted to maintain. From the perspective of the absolute -- considered as the non-
extended unity of my core -- my objective presence is the same as the presence of the
Other. As we earlier put this, the absolute, in its own nature, cannot be limited to one
objectification. Thus, if it does objectify itself, its objectification cannot occur alone.
For Husserl, this means that "a possible ego immediately implies a universe, a totality of
egos co-existing with it" (Ms. E III 9, HA XV, p. 383). In other words, the possibility of
world, immediately implies the possibility of other presencings -- other streams. Since
no objectification of the absolute can occur alone, we may, of course, extend this. We
can assert that the actuality of my stream implies the actuality of Other streams. Now,
from the absolute's perspective, all streams are self-explications. All temporally exhibit
its non-extended content. Here, the absolute subject bears all subjects as self-
This perspective both is and is not my own view of the matter. It is insofar as I
limit myself to the sheer anonymity of my core -- i.e., regard this core through a
reduction which brackets everything which has temporally departed from it. It is not my
i.e., regard it as "this," "my" anonymity. In the second case, I take up an individual as
opposed to an absolute perspective. With this, the Other appears as another specification
center of my world and the presencing which results in the Other. One presencing -- one
resulting stream of impressional moments -- is said to pertain to me; and its alternative is
taken as pertaining to the Other. The second takes its place in the horizon of possibilities
presencing which could have but did not specify it. Here, the Other's presence to me
becomes a matter of leaving open. I re-present myself such that I leave open the
possibility of the presencing which results in him. This leaving open, taken as a regard
When we combine both perspectives, we assert that the Other re-presents myself
as more than myself. This means that the self-transcending intentions of empathy exhibit
possibilities which are inherent in my ground and also that such possibilities surpass what
Notes
376
I exhibit in my objective presence. These intentions, then, are not fulfilled by me. They
are filled by the presence of those Others whose ways of being and behaving objectively
presencing, one which I still recognize as related to mine insofar as my own presencing
terms of re-presentation. How does re-presentation actually result in the intention to the
Other? Our difficulty stems from the fact that re-presentation depends upon making
alternative self. Yet, how do I perform this second re-presentation? How can I speak of
notion plays a crucial role in the doctrine that the absolute cannot be limited to one
objectification, i.e., to one making present which results in the presence of a solitary
subject. If it were so limited, then this objectification would have to be considered as its
necessary result. The subject, in its objective presence, would not be considered
contingent. When we reverse this implication by assuming that the subject is contingent,
we deny its premise. We assert that the absolute cannot be limited to exhibiting itself in
just one subject -- i.e., in the single presencing which underlies this subject (See above,
).
As is obvious, the lynch pin of this argument is the assertion that the objectively
present subject is contingent. Given that re-presentation is the original mode of objective
presence, this can be considered as included in the assertion that all re-presentations have
Notes
377
what has departed from the original present. This present, in its constant making present,
is the very "to be" of the objects which I grasp. Yet, as we noted, it is not inherent in
their own objective presence. Qua re-presented, objects are at a temporal remove from
their "to be"; they are present by virtue of their not being now in an original sense. We
can, thus, say that all re-presented objects are inherently contingent since that by virtue of
which they continue to be -- the presencing or giving of the original present -- is not
directly grasped in their presence. As we earlier put this, they continue to be given
this giving, the contingency of what we re-present is not dispensed with. We rather lose
objective givenness, since we reach the anonymity which is prior to all re-presentation.
This is why re-presentation is the original mode by which we grasp objective presence.
Contingency, of course, does not just pertain to the fact of an object's existence.
It also affects the temporal ordering of contents which gives us the object's what -- i.e.,
its essence. There is no inherent necessity in this "what" since contents, per se, do not
have any necessary link to particular temporal positions. We can also say that as part of
the given, an object's essential structure lacks any existential necessity -- i.e., any
necessity which would demand that they continue to be given as the structure of an
objective world. This means that such essential structures are variable. They do not
determine what must be -- and, hence, what must continue to be. They only express
possibilities; they are the structures of what is contingently given -- i.e., what could have
been given with different structures. Here, of course, the contingent is thought of as an
includes a horizon of possibilities in which the contingent itself signifies one of these
possibilities, precisely the one which actually occurred" (Ms. C I, Sept. 21-22, 1934; HA
At the basis of such contingency is the original present. Its making present, i.e.,
impressional moments. As such, it makes the essence actual as an order which obtains
for successively given contents. To this, however, we must add a consideration springing
from the independence of time and content. The fact that temporal positions are not tied
to particular contents signifies that the primal present, in its primal temporalization, is
independent of what it makes present. Such independence implies 1) its capacity for
actualizing different essential structures, 2) the lack of any necessity for a particular
which could just as well be actualized. This directly applies to the re-presented unity of
my life with its sedimented "essential" structures which I call my habitualities and
capabilities. The contingency of this unity is the possibility of varying these structures.
A double conclusion follows from the above. First of all, in establishing the
contingency of the re-presented subject, we have secured its non-solipsistic nature. From
the absolute's perspective, all subjects are its re-presentations. All have departed from its
original presence and, hence, all must be regarded as contingent. Given that the absolute
directly manifest the presencing -- the original temporalization -- which makes them
turns to regard the immediate content of his presencing he finds that the stream of
impressional moments doesn't directly manifest, but only re-presents the non-extended
content of the original present. This present is independent of what it presents; its
original, if anonymous presence is the origin of all making present. As the original
this, we can say that to re-present the origin in terms of what it presents is to apprehend
the latter as contingent. The origin presents itself as the present impressional moment.
Re-presented in terms of the latter, the origin appears as the moment whose content could
have been otherwise. The same point holds when I synthesize my representations of
world. To re-present the origin in terms of myself and my world is to see them as having
an origin which is independent of their presence. In other words, the independence of the
inclusion of the result in a horizon of alternatives, alternatives which could have been
From this, it is clear what is wrong with the objection which we raised. We do
not go far enough when we say that re-presentation depends upon a presencing which
intention to the Other can be grounded in this presencing, we must add that this
presencing is, itself, the result of a re-presentation. Thus, as we earlier noted, the
moment of time is the appearance, the objective expression of the original, anonymous
present (See above, ). It is not the same as the original; it is its temporal re-
terms of what establishes this existence. It re-presents the pre-temporal now as a member
Notes
380
of the stream of momentary content-laden nows. The independence of the former is re-
presented as the contingency of the latter. Thus, inherent in the givenness of my making
could have been otherwise. This points beyond my functioning to another life. It forms,
further point can be made. The absolute cannot be re-presented as a single, contingent
subject. From its perspective, I cannot occur alone. Thus, my becoming concrete is not
just the sign that I intend Others who are equally concrete. It also signifies that the
absolute has objectified itself in more than myself. Here, the absolute is viewed as
grounding both my self-transcending intentions and the Others who, if I encounter them,
would act so as to fulfill what I intend. Their behavior, in other words, would be the
and my empathy are also seen as co-grounded. The givenness of what I re-present as
myself is, by virtue of its contingency, matched by an intention to its could have been
otherwise. To see more clearly the tie between the two, we can turn to a passage which
Every re-presentation has the constantly streaming making present as its foundation. In
this making present, I am the ego in its primal mode ... My functioning life, however, is
not just [this] making present. It is a re-presenting which constantly modifies the making
present, the present [which has been presented] and the ego of making present. ... The
function which re-presents does not change the stream which makes present. In its own
continuity during its own streaming, the re-presenting functioning has the presenting
stream as its constant lower stratum (Untergrund) ... Re-presentation, then, is an
"intentional modification" of making present, one on the basis of the making present
Notes
381
which is presently functioning; but the latter is not modified through re-presentation.
The living making present is not [itself changed into] the re-presented. All re-
presentation is making present "as if" (Ms. B I 22, V, pp. 23-24).
The distinction which Husserl is attempting to make is one between a modification which
actually transforms what it modifies and one which leaves it untouched. Thus, the re-
presentative function does not interfere with what is presented in the stream of
impressional moments. Similarly, it does not affect the living-making present which
results in this stream. What it does is intentionally modify the material of its basis by
beginning, there is the original present which my functioning core re-presents in its
"living making present." The resulting temporalization re-presents the timeless now as if
it were successively present. We thus have the stream of impressional moments, each of
which appears only to depart into pastness. To engage in a perceptual synthesis, I must
retain them. This retention (or short term memory) re-presents the past moment as if it
were present. The same point holds for long term or ordinary remembering. The latter
re-presents my earlier action of perceptual synthesis. Remembering, I recall not just the
results of this syntheses, but also myself as engaged in perception. What I do is re-
eliminate the basis for my re-presentations. Thus, my "living making present" does not
dispense with my original present. The latter still appears as the anonymity of my core.
In temporalizing, my core still appears as pre-temporal -- i.e., as that which is "now and
only now." Similarly, the retention of the impressional moment does not dispense with
its having departed. If it did, then the retained moment would be indistinguishable from
the present impressional moment. In other words, my re-presenting what I have made
Notes
382
Husserl, the latter is not changed into the former. My original making present doesn't
become its re-presentation. Thus, to grasp the retained moment as past is only to
present, content-laden moment. The same point can be made with regard to ordinary
perceiving.
With empathy, we have a further modification, one which modifies the results of
another "ego of making present." The present which results from my making present
they were the Other's. Only in this way can I re-present and, hence, intend the Other's
present as if it were the leading edge of an alternative past. This, of course, involves the
emphasize that it is also a modification which leaves its base intact. The re-presentation
directed to the Other does not change my self-representation. It does not imply that the
Other is present in the way that I am. What I re-present on the basis of my self-presence
The fundamental insight here is that all re-presentation is contingent. It, thus,
inherently has this "as if" character. It presents its material as if it were other, and its
own results are themselves capable of being re-presented as if they were other. From the
standpoint of the original present, whose presencing is the "lower stratum" of re-
presentation, these alternatives are all inherently possible. The re-presentation of this
Notes
383
present which yields the impressional stream is its exhibition as one such alternative. It
is also the implicit presence of the could be other of this alternative. It is the alternative's
capacity to be re-presented as if it, itself, were other. Thus, I can re-present my past
could just as well be made present now. Similarly, the independence of the primal
present is such that what counts as my past perceptual synthesis could just as well be a
presentation achieves its object through the constant mode of taking an alternative to the
We can put this in terms of our earlier remarks. According to the above, a
subject can re-present something as if it were other because, regarded in terms of the
origin of re-presentation, it could just as well be other. This means that the origin is not
tied to a specific re-presentation. It is, in fact, the independent ground of all its
this, we re-present the independence of the origin in terms of what follows from it by
grasping the latter as contingent. The re-presented is seen as that which could have been
otherwise and, hence, as that which can, itself, be re-presented as if it were otherwise.
the given is ultimately a re-presentation of the original presence which implies, in its
independence, both the presence of the given and that of its alternative. Re-presentation,
then, is necessarily the transforming regard which takes its object as if it were other. It
Notes
384
must result in an alternative to the presence it re-presents. This follows since this
origin of all presence. Thus, to take an example, such independence means that it is
possible for the primal present to presently appear as the moment which I take as past.
This possibility is re-presented through the transforming regard which takes this departed
When I re-present departed moments as if they were present, I am, in fact, re-
have "infinity existing only in the form of temporality, existing as the temporal
however, this infinity "is included in the nunc stans" (Ms. E III 9, Nov. 5, 1931; HA XV,
Kern ed., pp. 379-80). Thus, the nunc stans (or original present) is the "all-at-once" of
"the temporal succession of finitudes" -- i.e., the successive impressional moments. I re-
present this all-at-once by re-presenting these departed moments as if they were still
of all subsequent re-presentations. It makes them always treat their objects as if they
were present. Thus, its ultimate result is my intending the co-presence of a fellow
subject. For Husserl, this co-presence is simply an objective re-presentation of the fact
that, pre-objectively, my now "is not mine as opposed to that of other human beings"
(Ms. C 3 I, p. 3). It re-presents the fact that in the original now, "I discover my now and
It is time to turn to the mechanics of empathy -- i.e., to the details of the process
by which I take the Other as an object of a self-transcending intention. Our chief text
here is a passage where Husserl completes his parallel between memory and empathy.
Notes
385
inward which re-presents and transforms what is inwardly present. Husserl's crucial,
though implicit, point is that the first three types of re-presentation -- ordinary
Together they define me as a subject who has a definitely given past and specific
Before we look more closely at this process, there are two things which must be
kept in mind. The first is the dependence of empathy on memory. Without the latter,
there are no objective Others as objects for my empathy. In Husserl's words, "As a
human being, I am objective along with my Others. The Others are not for me originally
do, however, presuppose my memories at that according to which they are modifications"
(Ms. K III 4, p. 77, 1936). Our second point is that the process of modification is present
and then modification sets to work to produce my objective Other. Rather, as we cited
Husserl, "... every mode of re-presentation can re-present the re-presentations of all other
modes. Every mode can be a transformation of them" (Ms. B I 22, pp. 22-23). This
means that in the process of my becoming objective to myself, I have an interplay of the
modes of re-presentation which achieve this objectivity. As we shall see, the lower
modes found the higher. I cannot anticipate unless I appresent; I cannot appresent unless
I remember. This, however, does not mean that I cannot remember what I appresented,
that I cannot appresent what I anticipate. Each higher mode is, in fact, subject to the
being. When the latter is complete -- i.e., fully defined -- so are its alternatives. The
co-grounding allows me to say that "... I am who I am" -- i.e., a fully concrete self --
"only as bearing in myself the Other and all Others" (Ms. C 17 I, Sept. 1931; HA XV, p.
336). When I am concrete, the process of re-presentation which gives my definite status
is accomplished; and the process which intends my Others as distinct alternatives is also
complete.
Notes
387
We can give the mechanics of this process by first turning to the stages by which
I achieve my definite status. In the passage we have cited, the first stage is that of
ordinary remembering. This, of course, is not the absolutely first stage since memory
action of a past perceptual synthesis. This synthesis presupposees short term memories --
remembering "points back to memories which are not yet memories of objects and to
memories which are not yet [objective] self-rememberings" (Ms. K III 4, p. 76). The
transformation worked by this short term memory is that of re-presenting the past
perceiving self. This is a position taking self, a self which posits objects out of its
temporal depth. It recalls what I have done or failed to do. As such, it is a re-
presentation of my past position taking selves --a treating them as if they were present.
What Husserl calls "co-remembering" extends this concreteness by further specifying the
objects which arise from my perceptual syntheses. It re-presents (or appresents) the
features of my surrounding world which count as co-present -- this, even though such
features are not directly perceived. Thus, in appresentation, I re-present the back of a
chair while I perceive the front. This second type of re-presentation leads to a third. In
"pre-remembering," I anticipate that I could see the back of the chair. The back of the
front. My concreteness in this case involves my futurity -- i.e., what I shall do or fail to
do.
It is easy to see the order of these types. I cannot anticipate unless I appresent.
Since I anticipate what I appresent -- e.g., the back of the chair -- the latter focuses the
appresent the back of an object because fronts and backs have been paired in my
appresentation. They, in fact, specify its content. Thus, the more the present case
which is not, itself, present. Thus, in its bringing past experience to bear on the present,
appresentation takes what is not perceived -- e.g., the back of the chair -- as if it were
forward to the future thereby anticipating that the future will confirm my appresentation.
Here, I treat the not yet as if it were present -- i.e., as if its features were already those of
my present appresentation.
With this, we should note that in the actual process of my becoming concrete,
these modes of Er-innerung hardly ever occur in a pure form. My memories of myself
include the recall of my past appresentations and the anticipations which are based on
these. They help form the content of my remembering what I have done or failed to do.
What I have done is seen as a fulfillment of my past anticipations. What I have failed to
do is viewed as a lack of such fulfillment. The same point can be made by saying that to
the point that my anticipations are not an empty intending, they involve the expectation
that what I recall will, in its general features, be repeated. The structure of the
remembered, thus, prefigures the future I anticipate. This, of course, is why Husserl calls
anticipation a "pre-remembering."
Notes
389
one-sided. As we cited Husserl, "... I am who I am" -- i.e., a fully concrete subject --
"only as bearing in myself the Other and all Others." This means that my concreteness
transcending intentions are inherent in the sense I have of myself as fully concrete. Thus,
to describe the stages by which I achieve my objective presence, I must take account of
This can be put in terms of Husserl's assertion that empathy is a "higher order re-
to his future. The latter is pre-figured by a different past. Now, these differences cannot
imply that he is intended as a subject whom I cannot encounter -- i.e., that I intend him as
objective presence in the world -- requires my intentions to him. This signifies that his
presence in the world is intended as a presence which helps to establish and confirm my
We must be taken as subjects who, in intending their objective presence in the world,
To see how the transformations worked by empathy achieve this result, we must
begin by recalling that a subject's objective status involves that of the world. He is
objective as part of an objective world. Now, the world's objectivity is defined in terms
of its universality -- i.e., its being apprehended as the same world for everyone. For
Notes
390
Husserl, the initial basis of this objectivity is my inner plurality. "Everyone," in the first
instance, is limited to the co-existing plurality of my re-presented past and future selves.
Each of these remembered and anticipated selves is re-presented as having a world, i.e.,
as having synthesized its unity out of his multiple experiences. Insofar as this unity is the
same for all, it is taken as continuously the same for me. When we turn to objectivity in
its full sense, the world's thereness for me is included as an element of its thereness for
everyone else. The world is taken as the same -- i.e., as exhibiting the same unity -- both
for myself and for my Others. Now, if we take empathy as a transformation of the re-
presentations which yield my inner plurality, it is clear that the second sense of
objectivity is actually an overlay on the first. The inner plurality which makes up my
Other is intended as a series of alternatives to my own inner plurality. This means that
each of these alternatives is taken as a remembered or anticipated self who has his world
and that these worlds come together in a unity which defines a central self who
continuously has one and the same world. This world is a variant, an overlay of my
could experience it through an alternative course of action. We essentially say the same
thing when we note that the possibility which I re-present as my Other's world is a
done or failed to do. The notion of my failing to do what I could have done implies that
Indeed, it could have been formulated exclusively in terms of my memories and their
transformations. This is not the case for the process which establishes my own presence
as an object in the world. To consider this presence as the same for myself and my
Others, I must bring in appresentation. When I do, my Other appears as the unity of the
stand facing a chair. I perceive its front and appresent its back. My appresentations of
its back can be varied. I can conceive of an appressentation which is directed to its front.
This implies a standpoint which directly presents what I appresent -- i.e., the chair's back.
The schema can be applied to my bodily presence. Its objective thereness for me --
appresentations. Given my permanent position in the "here," I can only appresent, never
directly perceive, myself as "there." Thus, my bodily unity is, for me, a synthesis of such
appresentations. If I vary these, then I can conceive of the standpoints from which I
could be directly perceived. A synthesis of such variations would yield the unity of my
bodily appearing for the Other who successively occupies such standpoints. Since the
unity of the perceived is correlated to that of the perceiver, it would also yield the re-
Two conclusions follow from this analysis. The first is that my thereness for
myself and for my Other are related constructs, the second being an overlay on the first.
the Other must be harmonious with my thereness for myself. The second point is that the
concreteness this brings about is clear. I and my Other do not just share a common
the Other as perceiving myself. Adding another layer of appresenting, I can take the
other as appresenting his self-appresentations. With this, I take him as intending myself
The last stage of concreteness is given by anticipation. Its form is Husserl's "pre-
remembering which, beginning with the self-present, re-presents the intended which
agrees with this as what is to come ..." Subjectively regarded, what is "self-present" is
"these" characteristics and not others. This finitude involves my memories of what I
have done or failed to do. Even more immediately, it involves my "fresh past," i.e., what
I have just accomplished. Accordingly, it includes the standpoint -- the "here" in the
world -- I have just taken up. As Husserl writes, "This 'fresh past' ('frische
prefigured according to the constituted past ... the ego expects that what is prefigured will
itself become present through actualization, through the fulfilling present" (Ms. C 4, p. 1,
Aug. 1930). Thus, having taken up my standpoint in a new "here," I expect that my
surrounding world will show itself in a manner which is harmonious with my earlier
standpoint which, itself, is taken as fulfilling or failing to fulfill the anticipations of still
cascading effect. Insofar as such alternatives vary my "here," they vary what I appresent.
As such, they also vary what I anticipate -- i.e., what I intend from the standpoint of the
"here." In other words, these different pasts make me prefigure the future differently
and, hence, envision alternative futures. Now, these futures are not those prefigured by
that past which has yielded my present thisness. They do, however, remind me that what
is prefigured by my past is not predetermined by it. Thus, a regard to the could have
precisely the one which has actually occurred." As a consequence, my own present
thisness has an open character. It, too, is seen as implying its own range of possibilities.
Notes
393
What I shall do or fail to do is not determined by it. Rather, my actions are seen as
anticipation, we can say that the sense of the future has a double horizon. Those futures
which are not prefigured by my past are seen as the futures which I have foregone
through my past actions. Those which are still within my powers are those which I
that the future will continue the relation between the could have been otherwise of my
past and the alternatives to my present thisness. Thus, I take my present status as
pointing to the future in such a way that I confront the alternative possibilities of my
The origin of this double horizon is, of course, the independence of the primal
presentation of such alternatives gives me the horizon of futures which are based on pasts
which are different than mine. When I anticipate, the same relation is projected into the
present manner of being and behaving as if it were past. Once again, the independence
past being and behaving. Correlatively, I re-present as present the alternative futures
which could spring from such alternatives. To add an important, if obvious, point, we
may note that nothing in my originally present being prevents this transforming action of
anonymity which neither confirms nor rejects any alternative. This is why I must
In re-presenting my present on-going action as past, I give it the temporal distance which
Notes
394
different future. Yet, given my finitude -- i.e., my status as occupying this (and not
another) standpoint -- only one of these futures can be brought about. In a certain sense,
otherness. They become foregone possibilities -- possibilities which I could have but did
not realize. In other words, the fulfillment of their otherness is one with my achieved
having an alternative future. In this process, I grasp him as other than myself and yet as
possibility of being and behaving which would have been instantiated in my "this" if my
To see how far such empathy extends is to see what could be varied in the notion
of a life. I can re-present what my life would have been had I made different choices,
had I, for example, pursued a different career. I can also imagine what it would have
been if its uncontrollable factors had been different. Thus, I can imagine what my life
would have been had the circumstances of my birth being different -- i.e., had I been
Notes
395
statement: "The first thing, then, is the fact of the I am (ego). This fact, however, only
exists in the style of infinitely open possibilities which distinguish themselves through
the actuality of life itself" (Ms. B I 13, VI, p. 3, Oct. 1, 1931). As we earlier remarked,
the "fact of the I am" is the fact of the living present. This present cannot be varied since
it must be given for a life to be given. Its givenness, however, does not limit the
possibilities of a life. As an aspect of the absolute, this present inherently implies the
totality of life's possibilities. In a certain sense, then, we can say with Husserl: "The
totality of human possibilities is present in the newborn child, while it is fate, a matter of
fact (Schicksal, Factum) which of these will become developed capabilities (Vermögen)
and which will ultimately become actualized in their [initial] environment and in the
future environments they [subsequently] enter" (Ms. E III 9, Nov. 5, 1931; HA XV, Kern
ed., p. 384, note 1). This, of course, does not mean that every child has the potentiality
to become, say, a Mozart. The focus, here, is on the totality of possibilities, a totality
which is at the basis of every "this" including that of the newborn. Such a totality is,
properly speaking, prior to the newborn since his birth is already a "fact" which implies
actions cuts off a possible future in order to actualize another. Thus, in choosing to do
this rather than that, I avail myself of the possibilities inherent in the this and externalize
those afforded by the that. Insofar as I intend the Other as the person I would be if I did
have a different set of anticipations, the process of foreclosure is matched by the growing
which was available to me, enriches the stock of alternatives to my anticipations. Each
Notes
396
such alternative allows me a fresh intention to my possible Others. We can put this in
terms of the Latin root of "intention" which signifies a stretching out or forth. My
available to me through the ground of my thisness. This means that the otherness of the
Other -- i.e., the fact that I must extend myself to meet him -- is a function of my own
With regard to the newborn child, we can say that the fact of my birth already
implies a multitude of Others since it implies a finite thisness and hence the foreclosure
of a whole range of possible futures. Such subjects are not like me in the sense that I
could have chosen to have a life like theirs. They are my alternatives on the level of the
original givenness of the circumstances of my life. They are like me insofar as they
express what I could have been given had I been a different manifestation of my ground.
we must again consider the Other as an extension of my "I can." As including my future,
will, in fact, be confirmed. In this regard, the future is seen as an extension of my "I can"
-- i.e., my ability to confirm these theses. Thus, I assume that "if my powers were
extended on and on, ... then the presumptive certainties [of my theses] would also
Oct. 1929). I assume that if I could go further, then my extended "I can" would confirm
what my past prefigures with regard to my future. Now, as we recall, for Husserl the
having the extension which I anticipate. As we earlier put this, I intend my Others "as
possessing the 'I can' whose actual extension is required for actual certainty" (See above,
Notes
397
apperception" my anticipated "I can." I re-present this "I can" as present, thus assuming
intending my Others as persons who can confirm my theses. Thus, the Other in the
"there" is intended as having the experience which I anticipate I could have had if I had
taken up his standpoint. With this, I treat our collective experience as harmonious -- i.e.,
concreteness.
Let us take a closer look at the role that pre-remembering plays in the above. Its
general form is that of re-presenting the future as if it were present. Thus, pre-
remembering re-presents as present the self which I anticipate in choosing this rather than
must focus, not on what I anticipate, but rather on what I anticipated in the past. Its
material must be given by memory. I must, then, remember the alternatives which once
were included as possibilities of my thisness. These are the alternatives which once
confronted me in the choice of expressing my "I can." Each possible choice had its series
"according to the general style of my experiencing life." Since I could only choose one
course of action at a time, most of these anticipated disclosures never occurred. Now,
occurring. This means that I treat the harmonious experience I anticipated but never
the experience which, in fact, I chose not to have. The result is a re-presentation of
myself in terms of an excluded "I can" -- an "I can" which once was anticipated as
Notes
398
confirming my theses. Considered as present, this "I can" -- which is different than my
own -- becomes intended as that of a co-present subject. The latter is taken as a subject
who can confirm my theses. Pre-remembering thus leads me to intend the self I once
anticipated as actually present in the form of the Other. It does this continually as my
growing concreteness closes off some possibilities and opens up others. This process
this, the more my finitude implies the horizon of its alternatives. As a consequence, my
other egos define my thisness ever more closely and are seen as confirming it from their
perspectives.
This analysis simply follows Husserl's dictum: "... every mode of re-
presentation can re-present the re-presentations of all other modes. Every mode can be a
transformation of them." Let us conclude by observing that we can add the mode of
apply this to the above, I reverse the relation just delineated between self and Others. I
Let us turn from the detailed analyses of our preceding section to consider a
conclusion which is implicit in their arguments. They imply that empathy and freedom
have the same basis. This follows because both involve the sense of alternatives. If
empathy is the intending of the Other in terms of my alternatives, freedom is the choice
between alternatives. Without my sense that there are alternatives, I would not be aware
-- "this" rather than "that." Such awareness, like that of empathy, is based on the all-
alternative and is, in fact, that in and through which I act, that my action has the feeling
alternatives.
freedom is the independence of my ground. Because the ground could have expressed
itself in an alternative objectification, its independence signifies its ability to surpass any
alternatives to the already given and, in anticipation, by being aware of the alternatives
which could be given through my actions. The fact that such alternatives are implicit in
the presenting core of human action means that they are alternatives which could be
made present by such action. Thus, in anticipation, I do not confront them as abstract
possibilities, but rather as possible choices of a course of action. Since each such choice
choice of my "this."
The above does not imply that there are no limits to my embodied freedom.
Equally, it cannot be taken as asserting that there is no distinction between active and
passive constitution. If subjects through their freedom could break the pre-individual,
passively given basis for their constitution, then each could be considered as purely
To avoid this result, we must first draw a parallel between the contingency of
freedom and that of constitution. Their contingency results from their self-surpassing
quality; and this is correlated to the surpassing quality of their ground. In each case,
what is surpassed is the given. Thus, a free act cannot be completely determined by what
Notes
400
has gone before. It has an ultimately factual quality which means that what is given in
time does not completely determine its present choice. There is, then, an irreducible
element of contingency (of not being determined beforehand) in both the choosing and
the given it results in. Now, the same contingency follows from the surpassing quality of
not self-determining. This means that its givenness is surpassed by what will be given.
Each addition to the given, each new content-laden moment -- is not completely
regarded, the contingency of the given which results from freedom is the given's
contingency qua constituted. Both are considered as resulting from the pure spontaneity
of the absolute which underlies all givenness. Thus, the alternative selves which I
confront in choosing my "this" are the possible results of such spontaneity. Similarly, the
presently acting is never objectively given, I cannot take what is objectively given -- i.e.,
achieved thisness as actively or passively constituted. In neither case does the constituted
lose its character of being surpassed. In neither case does it present itself as active -- i.e.,
We can say with Husserl that "the individual, egological life is passively constituted in
immanent time" (Ms. B I 32, I, p. 16, May or Aug., 1931). We can also assert our
freedom in choosing our thisness. The key point here, as in the whole of this chapter, is
the assertion of the duality of the individual's essence. My essence is such that I can
claim both my identity with my ground and my difference from it. Qua constitutively
Notes
401
given, I am not free. I am free only to the point that, in my primal constitution, I exist in
of being in its distinction from essence -- i.e., a manifestation of the being per se which
cannot be limited to a given entity with its particular essence. Concretely, this means
that my freedom is my coincidence with the primal present -- the present "which is
actuality in the proper sense as that which is primally productive" (Ms. C 17, HA XV, p.
348). This present makes everything be present; yet since it is not inherent in the
Now, my duality is such that I act in and through the original present; yet I can only
as a surpassing of the given which results in the constitution of a new given. It, thus,
follows the paradigm of the original present which surpasses the given by a giving which
results in yet another given. The resulting objectively fixed order of time is, we can say,
the concealment of the spontaneity which generated it. Here, the fixed character of
memory, which comes with already accomplished time, designates what is not in my
power. What is in my power is the addition to this. In other words, my coincidence with
through my memory.
We can combine this with the notion of the passive constitution of my life "in
concerns the defining environment which results from my memories as they occur in
immanent time. Now, to assert that there is a level of passive constitution is to observe
with Husserl that "transcendental subjectivity is not free in its possibilities of constituting
beings or non-beings. It must constitute beings" (Ms. K III 1, viii, p. 4, 1935). This
follows from the fact that the dissolution of its surrounding world is its own dissolution
Notes
402
as an active center. The freedom to break off the passive synthesis which results in this
would cancel his objective givenness. He would, in other words, disrupt that part of the
The distinction between active and passive synthesis is clear from the above.
"individual, egological life." Active synthesis concerns the type of life I lead. It
being. The process is such that the past necessarily pre-figures the outlines of my future
the Meditations:
... that I, who am, can be conscious of someone else -- someone I am not, someone who
is other than me -- presupposes that not all of my modes of consciousness belong to the
circle of those which are modes of my self-consciousness. ... the problem is how to
understand the fact that the ego, in itself, has (and can always construct anew)
intentionalities of such a new kind, intentionalities with a sense of being whereby it
totally transcends its own being (CM, Strasser ed., p. 135).
The being which is transcended is my being in its thisness. The modes of consciousness
which are not apprehensions of my thisness are those directed to its alternatives. In the
Meditations, the condition of the possibility of the escape from my thisness through
transcending intentions is not yet given. We confront the teaching that what I am
directly given is always my own. It comes together to form my "this," i.e., the sense of
Notes
403
doctrine of the surpassing ground of my "this" which provides the key to my constant
escape from being characterized as a "this." Its all-inclusiveness situates the "this" as
gives my essence its dual character. I am more than the "this" which I objectively grasp.
To put this in terms of freedom, we can say that the formation of transcending
duality of my essence. On the one hand, they are anticipations arising from the
givenness of my past. On the other hand, they surpass this givenness by virtue of my
coincidence with the origin of givenness. The same point holds with regard to their
fulfillment. The duality of my essence is such that only one of these possibilities can be
actualized by me. The fulfillment of my intention to my chosen "this" is, as we said, the
the objective part of my essence, the part which gives me my individuality as a center. In
coincidence with my ground, I can intend multiple possibilities of being and behaving.
Yet, in active synthesis, my freedom is always finite. I can only act to fulfill one of these
alternativse since the fulfillment of more than one would disrupt the identity of my life.
a "this."
Since freedom and empathy have the same basis, the same point can be made
with regard to my intentions to my Others. They are also structured by the duality of my
not distinguished from what I re-present through empathy. This follows insofar as the
ground of the presence of each is the same. The separation of memory and empathy
comes through the second part of my essence -- that of my objectively present being. In
other words, it comes through the fulfillment of my intentions to my chosen "this" which
is also an alienation of its alternatives. Thus, I remember the possibilities of being and
The same duality structures the way in which the appearing Other fulfills my
alter ego. He must show himself as other than me -- i.e., as manifesting a possibility of
being and behaving which transcends the capabilities of my achieved "thisness." Yet, in
his actions, he must also show that he is like me. Our similarity refers to our common
origin, i.e., to that part of our essence which is the same. Accordingly, I recognize him
as like me insofar as his actions re-present one of the possibilities of being and behaving
which is implicit in our common origin. I recognize this as a possibility which was
originally open to me or, by extension, as a possibility which could have been open to me
if the circumstances of my life had been different. In either case, he is similar insofar as
his action exhibits a possibility of selfhood which is implicit in the freedom which is at
the origin of my own self-surpassing. Thus, he is seen as like me insofar as his actions
To fill out this picture, we must recall Husserl's assertion that the ego is "self-
shaping" in its self-development. This means that when it finds "itself in successive time,
it is, in fact, exhibiting its full present, exhibiting what it is now, what [pre-objectively]
lies within it as an ego" (Ms. A V 5, p. 10, Jan. 1933). What is pre-objectively now
designates my primordiality as containing "all time and world." Implicit within it is not
Notes
405
just my bodily appearing but also the bodily appearance of the Other. Both are part of
this primordiality's objective exhibition as it unfolds (or "finds") itself in time. In this
insofar as my functioning is one with this primordiality taken as the non-finite aspect of
my essence. Thus, the possibility which the Other actualizes is inherent in me because
one aspect of my essence -- the aspect which makes me free -- is this primordiality. As
by my fellow subject also has its basis in me. Yet this time its basis is the aspect of my
This leads us to take note of a theme which will be central to our last chapter.
The duality of my essence is such that the process of my self-shaping can be described in
This means that what will be accomplished by this process is not just its goal but also its
determining ground or cause. Let us apply this to Husserl's assertion that the ego, "in
finding itself in successive time," is actually "exhibiting what it is now." This statement
implies that the ego is, qua now, what it will be in time. What it will be is its not-yet, its
goal. What it is now in a pre-objective sense is the primordiality which grounds its
action. If what the ego will be is implicit in the ground of its action, if in some sense the
two are identical, then its self-shaping can be called teleological. The goal designates
what will be; but this can be seen as grounding the process of the ego's actualization
insofar as the possibilities of the goal are coincident with those of the ground of the ego's
actualization. Here, the duality of the ego's essence allows us to call it self-actualizing.
Its full essence includes not just the "thisness" which is its goal, but also the primordiality
implies more than the "thisness" which is the ego's finite goal. That its primordiality
includes "all time and world" means that it implies more than what the ego can exhibit
through its non-transcendent intentions. Thus, if the ego achieves its goal through its
exhibiting the possibilities of its ground, its goal actually implies more than itself. In
other words, because the possibilities inherent in its ground surpass what it can intend as
itself alone, it must re-present what "lies within it as an ego," not just as its own
possibilities, but also as the possibilities of those Others who are intended as establishing
The same teleological identification of the ground and the goal can be applied to
involves my sense of alternatives. To put this in terms of leaving open, it can be said
that, as free, I always possess the horizon of my empathy. I have the sense of my could
have been otherwise, which means that my being and behaving leave open the
possibilities of Others. Now, as we said, the surpassing quality of the ground is matched
by the "leaving open" of that which it grounds (See above, ). This indicates that
ground. Freedom determines (or grounds) my being as a self that preserves itself through
The crucial point with regard to such determination is that a plurality of results is
inherent in it. Freedom cannot be limited to producing the self I shall become. If it
were, it would not be real, but illusory freedom. Real freedom involves the spontaneity
of not being determined beforehand. It is, in fact, the openness of my ground projected
Notes
407
possibilities and is, itself, mirrored by my openness to these. With regard to myself, this
follows from my primordiality being both a ground and a goal -- i.e., something which,
exist as part of a process which surpasses me. It is because of this that I possess the
and to my Others. The same reason allows me to say that I exist as part of a process
containing more than what it objectively presents. This "more" is not just the freedom at
the core of my being. It is also the non-appearing self of the Other. As that which
This transfer can be made because freedom as self-surpassing inherently involves self-
pluralization. It implies something more than what can be given by any specific
individual.
intentions to Others. It also appears as the goal of such intentions insofar as what fulfills
like me insofar as his actions imply more than himself. He is seen as a self insofar as he
CHAPTER VII
TEMPORALITY AND TELEOLOGY
the universal being of transcendental subjectivity" (Ms. E III 9, Nov. 5, 1931; HA XV,
Kern ed., p. 378). He speaks of the teleology "immanent" within subjects "as the form of
their individual being, as the form of all the forms in which subjectivity exists" (Ibid., p.
380). He then goes on to assert that "teleology can be exhibited as that which concretely
and individually determines, that which ultimately makes possible and thereby actualizes
process is inherently temporal. As we cited Husserl, it is the result of the "welling up" of
time. Specifically, egological action "is a primal welling up, a creative allowing to
depart" of the constituted -- i.e., of the egological acts and their objects -- in time (See
Ms. B III 9, pp. 13-14, Oct.-Dec., 1931). If we assume that this "primal welling up" is
teleologically determined, then so is the constitution which it results in. Teleology, thus,
becomes "the form of all the forms" in which subjectivity manifests itself when we
assume that it is the form of the temporality which constitutively grounds subjective
in which a specific teleological causality has its form ..." (Ms. K III 4, p. 48, 1934-35).
They possess this temporality because "each transcendental ego has something innate.
Notes
409
Within itself, it innately bears the teleological ground of its streaming, constituting,
transcendental life. This is a life where the ego, in temporalizing its world, temporalizes
itself as a human being" (Ms. E III 9, p. 11). This statement identifies what is "innate" to
an ego with what functions as the ground of its temporalization. The latter, of course, is
the primal present. As we cited Husserl, this present is what is "primally temporalizing".
To call this ground "teleological" is, thus, to assume the teleological nature of this
present. We can thus say that, for Husserl, the universality of teleology is premised upon
the teleology of the "constituting, transcendental" lives of individual egos; but this
assumes the teleological structuring of what is "primally generating" -- i.e., the primal
The above may be applied to the arising of individual egos and also to the
acquisition, a continuously further acquired) ontical unity" (Ms. C 17 Sept. 20-22, 1931;
HA XV, 348). This unity is that of the ego as an active center of its life. If the
temporality which constitutes this unity is teleological, then so is the very coming to be
of the ego. We can, thus, speak with Husserl, of "the new awakening (Erwachen) of egos
teleology included in the universal teleology" (Ms. E III 5, Sept. 1933; HA XV, Kern
follows from it, including our arising as egos. The same point holds for the
awakening (Wachwerden) of the teleology immanent within it ..." (Ms. E III 9, Nov. 5,
1931, HA XV, 380). This teleology is understood as determining the forms of its
Notes
410
focus on the present but also on the not-yet. It involves a recognition of the goals which
will ultimately become located as a problem for practical reason. First, howver, we must
turn our attention to the premise behind all of these statements, that of the teleological
constitution.
When we first mentioned the temporal reduction, we said that our sense of
extended time is dependent on the ordering of our retentions and protentions (our short
term memories and anticipations). This ordering constitutes our sense that our
extended time. Its result is a reduction which Husserl characterizes as "a radical
'limitation' to the living present," the present which is "not a modality of time" (See
above, ). These remarks were made only in passing. Our present focus,
however, demands that we ask: What, precisely, is the phenomenological meaning of the
terms, "retention" and "protention"? How does their ordering constitute our sense of
time?
diagrams which Husserl provides. First, however, we must add a word of caution.
Notes
411
There are, however, no such points. As Husserl notes, the now-point or discrete
impressional moment "is only an ideal limit, something abstract which can be nothing for
itself." He adds that "this ideal now is not distinct toto coelo from the next now, but
rather continuously mediates itself with the latter" (Zur Phaenomenologie des inneren
Zeitbewusstseins, ed. R. Boehm, Haag, 1966, p. 40, hereafter cited as HA X). In other
words, just as a continuous line is not made up of discrete points, although points can be
identified by cutting the line, so time should not be conceived as made up of distinct
moments. It, too, is a continuum. Indeed, its continuous quality is implicit in its
Behind this continuity is, we may recall, the lack of any inherent distinction
beween time's moments. Insofar as such moments are not per se tied to definite sensuous
contents, they do not inherently exhibit what could distinguish one moment from the
next. As we earlier put this, their what -- or rather their inherent lack of a what -- is
always the same. Another, teleologically oriented reason for the moment's being
"nothing for itself" will be explored by us later. This will involve the moment's
dependence.
We shall begin with an objective reading of these diagrams. By this, we mean a reading
which takes time as something already given and attempts to analyze the components of
our sense of this givenness. The first such component is the series of successively given
now points. The horizontal lines of our diagrams designate successively given time.
Reading from left to right, each of the points of these lines represent later moments. The
vertical lines designate a second component. They represent the "horizon of pastness"
which is associated with each given moment. To descend the vertical is to enter into an
increasing sense of pastness. Husserl draws the diagonal lines of his diagrams to indicate
the connection of this sense of pastness with the sense of successively given time. If we
exclude its topmost point, the points of vertical line EA' can be considered as the
endpoints of lines drawn parallel to the diagonal line AA'. With the advance of time --
i.e., with the movement of line EA' to the right -- such end points descend along EA'.
This sinking down represents an increase in the sense of pastness associated with such
end points. The diagonal lines, which connect these points to the moments of
successively given time, thus represent the "sinking down" into pastness of such
moments. The moments, having been experienced as present, are experienced as "just
Notes
413
past" and then as just "just past" and so forth. The experience is one of time's expiration,
When Husserl draws the diagonal lines AA', PP' parallel to each other, this
apprehended as sinking into pastness at the same rate. This signifies that their original
order of succession is not temporarily scrambled while they are grasped as expiring. In
other words, the order of points given by the intersections of the diagonal lines with the
vertical is also the order of the successively given now points. As a consequence, the
horizon of pastness associated with a now point is taken as reproducing the horizon of the
For Husserl, the vertical line also designates enduring time -- i.e., time
apprehended as duration. To see how this is so, let us examine a problem for which the
diagram is supposed to give a solution. Suppose I see a bird flying through the garden.
How have I been able to "see" this? What is required, with regard to my sense of time, to
grasp this flying or, for that matter, any motion at all? To grasp the flight as temporally
extended, I must grasp its moments as successive -- i.e., as occupying distinct temporal
consciousness the instant after their apprehension. To grasp the flight as a whole, I must
retain them in the present -- the present of the ongoing act of apprehension. Thus, what
is required is both the temporal distinction of these moments and their simultaneous
presence in the ongoing now. The vertical line designates the fulfillment of both
demands. Its points signify temporally distinct, successive moments insofar as to each is
however, are all given along with the now (the topmost point of the vertical line). They,
thus, represent a retention, in the ongoing now, of the moments which were successively
Notes
414
melody "not just because the extension of the melody is given point by point in an
extended perception, but also because the retentional consciousness, itself, still 'holds
fast' the expired tones in our apprehension and, hence, produces the ongoing unity of the
consciousness which is directed to the unitary temporal object, e.g., the melody" (HA X,
Boehm ed., p. 38). This "retentional consciousness" is made up of the retentions or short
term memories of the successively given content laden moments. The elements of this
consciousness are all co-present on the vertical, which means that this line can be said to
represent our retentional consciousness. Insofar as the latter is made up of our present
succession.
Let us take a closer look at this solution. The diagonal lines designate, we said,
the sense of expiration, of "sinking down" into pastness. Now, this sense is that of
greater and greater removal of a past moment with its impressional content from the ever
new, momentarily actual now. This sense of constant removal, of removal proceeding at
a uniform rate, is that which first gives us the sense of a content laden moment as
occupying a definite position in the past. The moment, according to Husserl, is sensed as
sinking into pastness at just such a rate as to fix it in a definitely given order of past (or
The best way to see this is to analyze this "sinking down" along the diagonal line
into its horizontal and vertical components. With each new stretch of time, the retention
of a past moment is brought up to the present. As such, it remains on the vertical which
represents our present retentional consciousness. Yet, with each new stretch, the
retention also moves down a corresponding distance on this vertical line. The downward
moment, thus, corresponds to the movement of the vertical line to the right as it advances
to a new now point in the horizontal line of successive time. To say that a past
Notes
415
impressional moment is experienced as expiring at a constant rate signifies, here, that the
downward movement of its retention has a fixed ratio to the horizontal advance of time.
This gives us our sense of this moment being fixed in the order of past time since this
downward movement is just such as to permit the present retention to keep the same
One can also put this by saying that it is our sense of constant expiration which
constitutes for us the givenness of a content at a definite point in the past. Applied to a
multitude of contents, all expiring at the same rate, but distinct in their degrees of
pastness, this sense allows us to grasp in the now, the order of successive time.
Use Word 6.0c or later to
As we said, the parallelity of the diagonal lines indicates that this order is not scrambled
with the advance of time. This, however, requires that the increase of our sense of
continues, we can speak of a "continuous passage" from what is actually perceived to that
which is immediately and then mediately retained (HA X, Boehm ed., p. 29). Husserl
also describes this sense as a "constant continuum of retentions such that each later point
in the now. This impression is retained, then this immediate retention is itself retained,
retentions" of the original content (Ibid, p. 199). Our last diagram may be taken as
applying this to a multitude of contents. The contents originally given along line AP are
retained on line A"P' which is itself retained on line A'''P''. Proceeding along one of the
diagonal lines, e.g., line A'''A, we can say that each retention retains all the retentions that
preceded it and, thus, retains the original content to which all the retentions on the line
are serially related. Each, however, also modifies this content. Each of the retentions
adds a sense of greater expiration or pastness to it. In other words, the sense of the
If we ask what, strictly speaking, is this sense of pastness, two things can be said.
The first is that we experience its increase through the sinking down of our present
retentions. This sinking down is their self-modification -- i.e., their modification into
retentions of themselves. Thus, in our diagram, PA' sinks down to P'A'', and P'A'' is the
retention of the retentions along PA'. Our second point becomes apparent when we view
the diagonal lines as chains of retentions. Here, we have to say that the sense of pastness
is a relational sense. It is the sense of the serially ordered retentions -- i.e., retentions of
retentions -- which intervene between the present moment and that of an original
How far back can this retentional chain stretch? As indicated by the formula,
"short term memory," our actual retentional consciousness is always finite. If we wish to
recall a distant event, we must rely on the action of long term memory. We must re-
present the results of an earlier action of retaining departing moments. Having said this,
however, we must mention that the opposite view of retentional consciousness is implied
by Husserl's position. We can, in fact, argue that the retentional consciousness is infinite.
consciousness gives us our sense of the present moment as a moment in time by locating
it as the leading edge of past time. From the perspective of our apprehension of time, an
earlier time must pertain to any moment which is grasped as being in time. Each
necessarily grasped with its horizon of later time. This points to Husserl's "law" that "an
earlier and a later time pertain to any time" (HA X, Boehm ed., p. 10). Here, a second
"law" is easily derived. If every moment, located in the fixed order of time, must have
its horizon of pastness, then we have to say that "the fixed temporal order is an infinite
assures us that no moment is the first. Thus, the fixed temporal order gasped by retention
must be "infinite" in the sense of having no beginning. This infinity is, in fact, a function
would simply be the successively given time which is designated by the horizontal line of
the time diagram (line AE in our last figure). As retained, the horizon of pastness
accompanying each moment allows us to draw a vertical line beneath each point of the
experienced time. Since this second dimension is what first allows us to posit successive
Notes
418
time and since it does not allow us to posit its beginning, we have the infinity of time's
first dimension.
expresses this, "The diagram takes no notice of the limitation of the temporal field. It
does not assign an end to the retentions and ideally a consciousness is, indeed, possible in
which everything is retentionally present" (HA X, Boehm ed., p. 31, fn. 1). In other
words, if we can imagine no end to past time, then the "horizon of pastness," which
consists of the retentions of such time, also has no end. Thus, the vertical line, which
A later section will discuss the nature of this all embracing consciousness. For the
the latter is always finite. The individual's grasp of time, thus, implies a temporal
According to our last section, the sense of expiration is that of a serially ordered,
constant process. The nature of this process can best be seen by considering in somewhat
greater detail what cognition requires of our sense of time. These requirements were first
outlined by Kant in his Critique of Pure Reason. On this point, Kant seems to have
directly influenced Husserl. The latter's copy of the Critique shows the signs of a
frequent reading. In particular, the passages discussing these requirements are heavily
however, profitably review them by following Kant's formulations. The first involves
the fact that the apprehension of a temporally extended object involves a "multiplicity" of
impossible "if the mind did not distinguish time in the succession of impressions
following one another" ("Kritique d. r. V.," A 99; Kant's ges. Schriften, IV, 77). The
impressions must be given distinct temporal positions. They must, we can say, be
inserted into definite, unchanging positions in objective, successively given time. The
second condition is that of reproduction. As Kant says,, "... if I were to lose from my
thought the preceding impressions ... and not reproduce them when I advance to those
which follow, a complete presentation would never arise ..." (Ibid., A 102; IV, 79). The
requirement, then, is that of making co-present the impressions which I must distinguish
according to successive temporal positions. For Husserl, the retentional process satisfies
both requirements by retaining (or reproducing), at each temporal position, the content
which was retained in the previous position. Thus, at every moment of my apprehension,
the past is brought up to the present. In the series of such moments, the past is serially
follows when we grant that the sense of their distinction -- of greater or less pastness -- is
a relational one: a sense of a retention being related to its original impression through
can fulfill its function of bringing the past up to the present only if we are capable of
recognizing that the retained content is the same as the content originally given in the
past. In Kant's words, "Without the consciousness that what we think is, in fact, the same
was what we thought a moment before, all reproduction in the series of presentations
would be useless" (Ibid., A 103; IV, 79). In other words, without this consciousness, the
distinguished from the impressions which we are presently experiencing. Now, the
grant that a retention presents what it retains through a series of retentions and grant as
well that a consciousness of this series is, in fact, that of the pastness of the retained.
The former does not exhibit a dependence on what is not presently given, the latter does.
phase and also a basis for the retentional consciousness of the next phase" -- i.e., a basis
for a retention of this retention (HA X, Boehm ed., p. 118). This means that a retention
cannot be given unless what it retains is first given, the latter being the retention that
serves as its basis. The same holds for each of the members of the retentional chain.
Together, they form a chain of dependencies. The chain is anchored in its first member,
How does the attachment of this chain to the presentation exhibit the latter's
pastness? The answer takes us to the origin of time's intentionality. We are aware of a
retention's dependence by virtue of its functioning as a sign -- i.e., by its pointing beyond
itself. The dependence of its being in the now upon what is not now is exhibited by its
reference. It refers beyond itself, in its present givenness, to that upon which it is
immediately and, then, mediately dependent. Reference to something else is, however,
the primitive form of intentionality. We, thus, have two possible descriptions of the
retentional chain, the first being the inner of which the second is the outer manifestation.
Since the members of the chain are all dependent, the chain can be described as a
"continuity of constant changes ... inseparable into phases and points of the continuity
that could exist for themselves" (HA X, Boehm ed., p. 27). Since dependence, or
incapability of existing for oneself, shows itself in intentionality, the chain can also be
back from the present retention to the independently given "primary datum" (Ibid., p.
81).
should now be apparent. The former presents its content immediately without any
further temporal reference. As for the latter, it presents what it retains through a serially
members of the chain. Now, since each of the members, by virtue of its dependence, is
intentionally "of" the previous members of the chain, none of them, as a retention, can
past moment. With this, we can see how each adds the modification of pastness to what
which presents itself as a past moment, is to grasp it through a stretch of past time.
Temporally speaking, the content's appearance is also the appearance of the pastness
through which it is given. This follows since we cannot retain this content without also
retaining the pastness which is presented by each of the retentions of the content. Thus,
the content is presented as an impression which is at a temporal remove from our present
act of retention -- i.e., our retention of all the retentions which are dependent on the
content's original givenness. We can also say that the increase of this chain of retentions
involves the increase in our sense of the pastness of the impressional content since each
additional member of the chain adds the modification of not-newness or further pastness
to it.
The crucial point in this analysis is that of the serially structured dependence of
the members of the retentional chain. Each retention, in its now, is dependent on a
retention which, relative to it, is not now. It is this dependence of the now of each
retention on the relative not-nows of what precedes it which must be assumed if we are to
Notes
422
explain how the resulting diagonal intentionality involves a sense of pastness, i.e., a sense
of the givenness which is no longer now. Otherwise put: dependence on the not-now
proceeds along the retentional chain, whose members are dependent, each upon the next,
must, a fortiori, also assume this dependence to explain our apprehension of successively
given time. Such time corresponds to the increasing sense of the pastness of a content as
all expiring at the same rate, arises from our retentional chains being linked to a
multitude of contents. The different lengths of these chains give us our sense of the
recognition that the retained impressions are the same as the originally given ones, we
must, according to Kant, have the recognition that the retained "form a whole." The
multiplicity of contents that we retain in the now must be viewed as united "into a
presentation" ("Kritik d. r. V.," A 103; ed. cit., IV, 79). This requires, we can say, the
have seen, each moment of the diagonally represented retentional chain is "of" a previous
moment in this chain because it cannot exist or be conceived without the latter. To
repeat Husserl's remarks: "We know with regard to the phenomenon of expiration that it
temporal stretches that could exist for themselves and inseparable into phases and into
points of the continuity that could exist for themselves." Now, the diagonal lines of
retentions end, at every moment, in a vertical line, one which represents the presence of
the retained at that moment. With this, we can say that the same inseparability exists in
Notes
423
the vertical direction. No single retention of the vertical line can be grasped in isolation
from the later members of this line. This follows because the present retention's
reference to a past moment occurs serially through all the moments separating it from
this past instant. Its reference, thus, demands the moments which followed this past
instant. These moments, however, are themselves retained on the vertical. Accordingly
each moment of the vertical line, by virtue of the fact that it has sunk down and is
grasped as such, implies these later moments of time. Its having sunk down is, we can
say, a consequence of the presence on the vertical of those retained moments which
Here, of course, the diagram simply represents the fact that the sense of the
pastness of what we retain demands a sense of the time which followed it. As Husserl
puts this: "... every past indicates a future ..." (Ms. E III 9, p. 19, 1929). It "has its
horizon of futurity which has already fulfilled itself ..." (Ms. C 17, Sept. 22, 1931; HA
XV, Kern ed., p. 344). Because each of the moments of this already fulfilled horizon are
retained on the vertical, each of our present retentions points beyond itself. Each has a
vertical reference to our retentions of later moments. The retention of what has been,
U se Wo rd 6.0c or la ter to
v i ew Ma ci n to sh p i ctu re .
dependence on the not-now manifests itself in an intentionality which presents this not
now. The "not-now," here, is not the past, but rather the future. This different sense of
the not-now follows from the fact that vertical intentionality rests on the diagonal
intentionality in which the not-now does have the sense of pastness. In the above
diagram, the retentions of later moments (along line A''B') are connected to these
moments (along line AB) by decreasing retentional chains. Each of these chains, by
virtue of its diagonal intentionality, presents a not-now in its pastness. Yet since the
chains decrease as we ascend the vertical, these retained moments along A''B' exhibit a
retained impression includes a grasp of what followed it. The intentionality implicit in
its dependence on the retentions which follow it -- the retentions along A''B' -- unites its
apprehension with a grasp of its already fulfilled horizon of futurity. Thus, the retained
"form a whole" in my apprehension. Their contents, in Kant's words, are united "into a
presentation."
must turn to a further requirement for cognition. Husserl writes that through the vertical
intentionality "immanent time constitutes itself. This an objective time, a genuine time in
which there is duration and the change of what endures" (HA X, Boehm ed., p. 83). He
adds, in an appendix, "Duration is the form of something that endures, the form of an
enduring being, of something identical in the temporal succession that functions as its
duration" (Ibid., p. 113, italics added). Kant makes the same point when he calls the
concept" ("Kritik d. r. V., A 103; ed. cit., III, 79). A concept is a one in many. Thus, we
must be able to recognize identical characteristics within the multitude of our distinct
impressions in order to say that our impressions are of something identical -- are
Notes
425
impressions of an appearing object with definite qualities. The same point holds when
duration when they exhibit an identical character. In considering duration per se, i.e., in
considering time as abstracted from content, we are, of course, performing the first
temporal reduction (See above, ). This reduction reveals that the moments of
time are not per se tied to particular contents. As such, it shows that the identical
character we are seeking is the quality of the moments' being, one and all, empty
the diagonal direction results in impressional moments' being retained with distinct
temporal referents. In the vertical direction, its result is that our retentions of such
moments are united with one another in the ongoing present. In Husserl's words, the
intentionality which arises from this dependence "is constitutive of the unity of these
primary memories within the flux" (HA X, Boehm ed., p. 80). As a consequence, our
intentionally refers to a distinct moment in the past. Each, however, is unified with a
portion of the retentions along the vertical insofar as the pastness of what it retains
implies later moments which are themselves retained. We, thus, have a situation where
we are required to think the retentions along the vertical as temporally distinct in their
reference to past impressions and, yet, as forming a continuous whole -- i.e., as incapable
of "existing for themselves."3 This second condition points to the required element of
unity. To grasp our presently held retentions as a whole is to grasp them in their
coincidence. It also is to grasp them such that their similar qualities reenforce one
When, for example, we take an object and, in turning it, continually view its
features, the same contents appear again and again. The object repeats itself as it again
shows the sides which we earlier viewed. According to Husserl, the object is
experienced as the same -- i.e., as a one in many -- by virtue of the coincidence and
retained in the ongoing present. This means that each is placed in a "unity of
coincidence" with the other retained contents. This coincidence does not affect their
generate the re-enforcement of qualities that are the same. Like a series of overlapping
what is the same and, to a lesser degree, of what is similar. Husserl writes in this regard:
... "lines of likeness" run from one [retained content] to another and, in and, in the case of
similarity, "lines of similarity." We have, here, a certain mutual relatedness
(Aufeinanderbezogneheit) which is not constituted in a reflective act of drawing
relations, a relatedness which, prior to all "comparison" and "thinking," stands as a
presupposition for the intuitions of likeness and difference (HA X, 44).
This "mutual relatedness" follows upon the union of the retentions of like contents, i.e.,
upon the coincidence with results from their protentionally directed, temporal
dependence. In the late manuscripts, Husserl uses the term "merging" (Verschmelzung)
to describe the situation. He writes: "The whole of the hyletic material is united in
harmonious is united in the particular mode of merging" (Ms. E III 9, p. 21, 1929). In
other words, every thing retained is brought together in the "concrete now" -- the vertical
of the time diagram. But, in this, there is a particular coming together. We have
Notes
427
continuous merging according to similarities" (Ibid., p. 5). By virtue of this, the merged
qualities "stand out." They reenforce each other and, hence, distinguish themselves from
the heterogeoneous qualities whose union does not result in their merging (See Ms. C 13
This merging gives us the object's "noematic nucleus" -- i.e., the connected,
relatively stable features which allow us to recognize the object in its appearances. The
same point can be made about the duration of the object's appearing. Here, as we
indicated, the similar quality which is brought into coincidence is each moment's
character of being an empty container for some possible content. The similarity of
moments, insofar as they are not inherently tied to particular contents, results in their
own merging. In Husserl's words, "All of the moments in the streaming, which pertain to
the different, [successively] simultaneous local data of the impressions, are completely
alike and, as such, merge ..." (Ms. C 7 II, p. 9, June 1932). With this, we have the unity
of the duration which corresponds to the unity formed by the merging of the object's
... primarily merging, the temporalizations unite together and thereby produce a
unity of a temporalization for all the times [of particular tonal imprssions -- i.e.,
for] their temporalizations and times. Here, however, the homogeneity of the
tones plays its part. The unities [of the retained tonal impressions] merge
according to their contents and the times [of such impressions] merge according
to the constant, homogeneous form which arises from the homogeneous
temporalization (Ms. C 15, p. 5, 1931).
In both cases, the merging results in the Kantian "synthesis of recognition in a concept"
contents of some object by virtue of the merging of the qualitative elements, a merging
which produces each of the object's features. For the same reason the moments bearing
these contents become moments of the object's duration. Each moment, in its ability to
bear every possible content, is of the duration which exhibits all the object's contents.
duration, the retained impressional moments must not, in their merging, lose their distinct
temporal referents. This condition is satisfied by the fact that the vertical intentionality,
which results in this merging, cannot occur without the occurrence of the separate,
diagonal intentionality. The latter, as we recall, is what gives our retained impressions
their sense of being more or less past and, thus, permits the vertical intentionality which
proceeds through our retentions from the past to what is relatively future.
Summing up, we can say that this section's analyses have an overriding theme:
cognition requires the dependence of the moment. Dependence along the retentional
chains gives us the diagonal intentionality of each of our retained impressions. Each is
direction gives us the corresponding vertical intentionality. Here, each retention is not
just "of" the subsequent retention of a later impression. It is actually "of" the object
which appears through the merging of our retained impressions.5 This "ofness" includes
the object in its present, momentary givenness since dependence in the vertical direction
proceeds through each retention of a later moment until it reaches the presently given
moments, we would not have the consciousness of either succession or duration -- and,
hence, would not be able to grasp an object as enduring through successive time, i.e., as
experience and its object are co-constituted. As Husserl puts this: "In the same
[process], the perceived object is also constituted" (HA X, Boehm ed., p. 91). In other
words, "... necesarily the one is constituted with the other" (Ibid., p. 92). This
constitution does not imply that experience and object are the same. They have, as we
thing, it can show itself perspectivally. Its enduring involves change as it shows itself
first from one side and then from another. This is not the case with an experience of the
thing. In Husserl's words, "An experience does not, like a thing, show itself
appearing results, for Husserl, from the twofold intentionality of the temporal process.
By virtue of the diagonal intentionality proceeding from our present retentions, there is
stretch of successive time. This phase may embrace the perspectival appearing of some
object. The phase, however, does not change -- i.e., appear perspecivally -- as it is
constantly retained as one and the same stretch of past experience. We can also express
this by saying that the retentional process does not exhibit the change of perceptual
contents which would be required for the phase to perspectivally appear the way a thing
does. As Husserl writes of the flux of retentions of retentions: "In principle, no phase of
the flux can be broadened out into a continuous successeion, i.e., the flux cannot be
thought of as so transformed that the phase extends itself into an identity with itself" (HA
X, Boehm ed., p. 74). The claim, here, is that, when we limit ourselves to pursuing the
the perspectival appearing of a thing. Because of this, as Husserl concludes: "There is,
thus, lacking here every object that changes; and, insofar as 'something' goes on in every
process, there is no question here of a process. There is nothing changing and, therefore,
there can be no talk of something enduring" (Ibid.). To grasp this enduring, we must
turn to the intentionality which proceeds in the vertical direction. The latter is
Behind these changes is a constant adding to the retentions which form the ongoing
constantly merging them wtih the retentions we have "just now" acquired from the
ongoing perceptual process. Thus, the identity generated by this merging is, by virtue of
the addition of constantly new contents, an identity which persists through the changing
Once we see experience and object as resulting from the diagonal and vertical
follows because, as Husserl writes, these two intentionalities are "like sides of one and
the same thing." They are distinct; yet they are "intentionalities which promote one
another and are interwoven in the single, unique flux of consciousness" (HA X, Boehm
ed., p. 83). Thus, the diagonal intentionality, which gives us our sense of successive
time, is interwoven with the vertical intentionality which proceeds from the retention of
an earlier moment to that of a later. In the time diagram, the vertical line is simply the
advancing front of the retentional chains. The process of this advance, which results in
the retention of a phase of experience, also results in the present retentions forming the
vertical. The advance, thus, continuously gives rise to the vertically directed
mentioned in our last section. It is the constitution of the intentional relation between
"of" an object because its content is one of many similar contents whose merging forms a
particular feature of the object -- e.g., its color. It is because of this that we say that the
object exhibits itself in the multiplicity of our experiences, each experience pointing to
consciousness itself. Speaking of this dual intentionality, Husserl writes that "the flux of
consciousness constitutes itself as a unity ..." (HA X, Boehm ed., p. 80). He adds, with
regard to the temporality implicit in the references of our retentions, "This pre-
itself' (Ibid., p. 82). The point of these remarks is that, with the constitution of
experience and object and the intentionality linking them, we have the constitution of
consciousness itself as a distinct temporal form. In other words, before the constitution
of successive and enduring time, we cannot speak of the unity of consciousness. Such a
unity embraces experience in its relation to the appearing object; but without the
intentionalities which arise from our present retentions, this relation does not obtain. We
can put the same point slightly differently by saying that without the constitution of
successive and enduring time, there is no central acting ego. Before such constitution,
the temporal field which allows the ego to appear as a center does not obtain. Because of
this, there is no "acting" in the sense of the ego's allowing its acts to temporally depart
from itself. This means that the constitution of time cannot be taken as following from
the action of an already given ego; it is, as we have stressed, a "passive" constitution.
Notes
432
With this, Husserl and Kant come to the parting of their philosophical ways. For
Kant, the temporal requirements for cognition give the conditions for the appearing of
the subject. The acting subject, which constitutes its appearance by satisfying these
conditions in its temporal constitution, does not, itself, appear. Thus, for Kant, the "inner
sense" by which we grasp our temporal unity presents us "only as we appear to ourselves,
not as we are in ourselves" (Kritik d. r. V., B 152-53; ed. cit., III, 120). "In ourselves" --
present the experiences which have successively departed, and to synthesize what we
reproduce into the unity of a persisting object. Yet such action springs from our non-
appearing being, i.e., our being as a "nouminal," non-temporal actor. We reverse this
position when we assert that our being "as genuine egos, as centers of acts in relation to a
surrounding world" is a being which results from temporal constitution. At this point,
the arising of the process of temporal constitution is our own arising or "awakening" as
To uncover the ground of this process, we must reverse our reading of the time
assumed that the "horizon of pastness" attached to the now point is the result of our
retaining successively given impressional moments. Thus, we began with the assumption
of successively given time and attempted to analyze how, through the process of its
retention, we acquire our sense of successive time. Husserl, however, also gives a
subjective reading of the diagram. Here, he assumes as given only what is immediately
present in the "concrete," ongoing now. In such a now, we find the data along the
vertical -- i.e., the co-present retentions which, per se, are not in successive time. As for
the diagonal lines designating the chains of retentions of retentions, we are not
immediately given the extension of these lines through successive time. In other words,
the drawing of these lines is considered the result of an interpretation based upon our
Notes
433
immediately given retentions. So is the drawing of the horizontal line which designates
"the series of now points" in successive time. Thus, in this second, subjective reading,
such now points (or impressional moments) are not taken as immediately given. They
This shift in the reading of the diagram may be put in terms of the meaning
Husserl gives to the term "retentional modifications." Such modifications are not seen as
modifications of a content which is already given in the fixed order of successive time.
There are rather modifications which fix (or insert) this content in a temporal order
(Abwandulungen) and the circumstance that they are constantly retentions of the
constantly preceding ones, there is constituted in the flux of consciousness the unity of
the flux itself as a one dimensional quasi-temporal order (HA X,82, italics added).
does not include time's second dimension, that of enduring or persistence in time. It is
simply the fixed order of successively given, content laden moments. As we mentioned
above, we grasp this order because the contents we experience collectively expire or sink
into pastness at the same rate. When we see this "sinking own" as constituted by the
We can put this in terms of the first thing we confront in a subjective reading of
the time diagram. This is the constant modification of the contents which are given in
the vertically represented horizon of pastness. The modification is constant; and it can be
line as new retentions are constantly added to what we presently retain. Husserl calls our
present retentions "a multitude of modified primary contents which are characterized as
virtue of the process of their retentional modification, "these primary contents are carriers
the temporal unity of the immanent content in its sinking back into apstness. 'Contents,'
in the case of perceptual appearances, are just such wholes of appearances that are
constituted as temporal unities" (HA X, Boehm ed., p. 92, italics added). The "primary
given by the distance along the vertical which separates this content from the momentary
now or topmost point of the vertical. The "retentional modification," which forms the
The same view of temporal constitution appears in the late manuscripts. They
invite us to consider the downward motion of the vertical line as representing the phases
of a content as it "appears in the now point, is now, is immediately modified into the just
past and, in the modification of a [further] just pastness of this just past, etc., is [a
content] fixed as the same, as the same in the changes of its temporal modalities ..." In
other words, "it is precisely through this process [of retentional modification] that it is
constituted as the same, as an identical point in the fixed form of the primal now and the
just past, etc." When we apply this to a multitude of contents, all undergoing the same
modification, we see that "there is constituted an identical form with identical temporal
positions as phases of this form and as identical 'concrete' unities ..." (Ms. C 2 I, p. 17,
Aug. 1930; see also Ms. D 15, p. 1, Nov. 1932). The claim of the above is that the
Notes
435
process which we took to be that of the retention of an already given moment is, in fact a
position" in departing time (Ms. C III 3, pp. 26-27, March 1931). Such a constitution is,
then, the insertion of a content into what comes to be constituted as the fixed order of
moment in such time. Because of this, Husserl can affirm: "All impressions, the primary
contents as well as the experiences which are 'consciousness of' [some object] constitute
themselves in primary consciousness" (HA X, Boehm ed., p. 89). In other words, quite
them to be taken as experiences of some object, the retentional process still constitutes
In a certain sense, this position is similar to Kant's. For Kant, the insertion of a
content into a definite temporal position is also the result of time constitution. Such
allows it to be grasped as the same content with the same departing temporal reference.
Yet, even here, Husserl's position does not explicitly differ from Kant's. Thus, given his
distinction between the constituting and the constituted, Husserl must say, "The
phenomena which constitute time are objectivities which are evidently different in
principle from those which are constituted in time" (HA X, Boehm ed., pp. 74-5). The
predicates which are applicable to the latter -- such as having a definite temporal position
constituting phenomena (Ibid.). Thus, our present retentions are not per se in time. Only
that which is posited out of a retention's ongoing modification -- i.e., the content in its
that "we cannot speak of a time of the ultimately constituting consciousness" (Ibid., p.
78).
Yet even this interpretation of consciousenss does not fully capture the
object" (Ibid., 112 italics added). "Consciousness," here, cannot refer to the data on the
vertical. Although, as constantly now, they are not in time, yet they are constantly
undergoing retentional modifications. As such, they are not absolutely timeless. In other
words, to reach the aboslutely timeless, we must abstract from the downward movement
of the vertical. Behind this movement is the successive addition of new retentions, each
new retention occasioning the "sinking down" of the retentions which preceded it. Thus,
to speak of what is absolutely timeless, we must abstract from this addition and the
multiplicity it implies.
Is this the nouminal ego which is posited by Kant as the timeless source of
temporal constitution? Kant does say that the ego is a "throughgoing identity" (Kritique
d. r. V., A 116; ed. cit., IV, 87). Its unity is such that when we attempt to represent it,
"nothing multiple is given" (Ibid., B 135; III, 110, italics added). Yet, as already
ground" of the fact that its temporal constitution satisfies the requirements of cognition.
It is, thus, a ground of its own appearing as a knowable presence. For Husserl, however,
there is no hidden actor behind the appearing ego. The individual actor is the appearing
ego. This means that the "absolutely timeless" source of temporalization is prior to both,
but not individually prior. It is the pre-individual condition for the constitution of every
Another section will be required to get at the ground of the temporal process and,
hence, at the ground of our own arising as appearing, acting egos. For the present, we
note that Husserl's reference to an "absolutely timeless" source of this process points
beyond the subjective reading of the time diagram. In regarding the vertical of this
diagram, we have only reached the end of the first stage of the temporal reduction. We
can conclude by recalling this stage and relating it to the subjective reading. In this way,
we can gain an insight into how the diagram represents the "living present" which is
point of transit for the moments of successive time. Time seems to stream towards me
from the future and to depart into pastness. After I perform its first stage, I limit myself
to considering only my immediate self-presence. With this, the passing through appears
as a "welling up" in my "living present" of the moments which, before the reduction, I
assumed were already given -- i.e., as already extended through objective time (See
above, ). To relate this to the time diagram, we have to note that the downward
movement of its vertical represents what Husserl later calls the "stationary streaming"of
the living present. As Husserl writes of this present, "It contains within this streaming
the continuity of the intentional modifications of the momentary, primal mode: now"
(Ms. C 7I, p. 5, June - July, 1932). Such modifications are this now's retentional
modifications. The latter constitute distinct temporal positions. Thus, the welling up of
"moments" from my living present is, as constitutive of objective time, actually a welling
constant letting loose (Aus-sich-entlassen) of retentions ..." (Ms. A V 5, pp. 4-5, Jan.
1933). Thus, the functioning is stationary insofar as the retentions on the vertical, i.e.,
the retentions which have been "let loose" (or added) from its topmost now-point, are all
Notes
438
constantly now.6 Yet it is also a streaming functioning since, by virtue of this letting
loose, the retentions stream, i.e., constantly move downward on the vertical.
impression keep its identical reference to one and the same position in the past (See
above, ). In a subjective reading of the time diagram, we can say that this
downward movement is what constitutes this position in its streaming into further
pastness.
Its tie to its increasing line of diagonal reference indicates that it is modified into a
retention of the very retention it "just now" was. The diagonal lines are drawn to
designate this relation of retention of retention. Yet, as Husserl remarks, such retentions
"are included in one another" (Ms. C 17; Sept. 21-22, 1931; HA XV, Kern ed., p. 346).
This means that all the members of a retentional chain are included in the retention which
is present on the vertical. The diagonal line is simply a diagramatic representation of the
contents of the present retention. Thus, it is from the latter that an impression's temporal
the vertical, we are representing its constitution of this position in its flowing into
pastness. We are also diagramatically depicting the constant modification which makes
This view, as we said, is that which is afforded by the end of the first stage of the
reduction. The second stage leaves us with the nunc stans. It leaves us with the timeless
now which is stripped of all relation to temporality. Before we reach this final stage, we
can still speak of a moment in time as the appearance, the objective expression, of the
nunc stans. We can also say that the nunc stan's appearance as a moment in time is one
with its departure from this appearance. This follows because, as Husserl writes, "When
we return to the primal now," we find that it "has modified itself and is modifying itself
in the modes: the retentional and the protentional ..." (Ms. C 7 I, p. 8; June-July, 1932).
In other words, its objective appearance is one with its retentional modification, a
modification which posits it as a moment in time. This is why this now's temporalization
is "a constant letting loose of retentions." Such letting loose is, in fact, the now's
constant self-modification. The retentions which express this modification are the
retentions of itself as particular temporal positions. Its successive departure from these
positions follows from the fact that, in remaining constantly now, it distinguishes itself
from its retentional modifications -- the very modifications which result in the increasing
pastness of its temporal appearances. Here, of course, it can also be said to have a
further letting loose of retentions, will come to be considered as the next now.
How does this relate to the final stage of the temporal reduction? Before we
reach this stage, the letting loose of retentions appears as the engine of the temporal
process. To justify the claim that there is an "absolutely timeless" origin of time, we
must see how this engine -- this letting loose of retentions -- is itself implicit in the
process, not as a series of random events, but as directed towards a fixed goal, then this
goal appears as its timeless element. As Aristotle first observed, the goal is that towards
which the process advances. As fixed, it is the one thing in the process that does not
progress (See Physics, 198 b, 1-3). Thus, to speak of a process's timeless element as its
ground or cause is to understand this as its goal -- i.e., as its "final cause." It is to
implicitly identify the goal and the ground and, hence, to see the process as teleological.
Now, the goal of the temporal process is nothing less than time itself -- time as the
totality of its moments. When we take this process as having a timeless ground, we must
see this goal as its ground, which means that we must take temporalization as a
teleological process. But, how can we understand time itself as such a ground? How can
we identify the totality of time with the "timeless now" -- the now that is revealed by the
To answer these questions, let us first return to the stance of our third section.
This section began by assuming the existence of the moments of successive time. It
viewed the temporal process in terms of its results -- i.e., in terms of its goal having, in
part, already been accomplished. Its question was: how do we grasp already
accomplished time? Its answer was to point to the dependence of the moment, seeing
primitive root, is the reference of one thing to another. A moment refers to the moments
moments. Thus, its dependence on the moments preceding it gives rise to a diagonal
intentionality presenting these moments. This presents them as past -- i.e., as something
considered as responsible for the retentional process itself. It is what makes the past
moment intentionally present in the form of a retention. Similarly, the dependence of the
Notes
441
intentionality. Here, the "protentional" reference of past moments signified that every
The reason why we mention this is that it provides one of the three conditions
which must be met to answer our initial question. To see the totality of time as the
ground of the temporal process, we must, first of all, see it as the ground of every
moment of time. It must ground it as "nothing for itself," which means that it must
ground it as dependent on all the other moments of time. The second condition requires
that we see dependence as the origin of time's intentionalities and, hence, as the origin of
the retentional process. This is the insight provided by the above. As for our third
condition, this was given by our last section. Taking up its stance, we must see the
intentionalities which proceed from the moment as productive. Thus, in accordance with
our second condition, the dependence of the now on the not-now has to be seen as
manifesting itself in an intentionality springing from the now. Our third condition
requires that this intentionality be taken, not just as presenting the not-now, but also as
The result is what may be called a "teleological circle." It is a circle in which the
totality of time -- understood as the goal of a process -- brings itself about by grounding
this process. Thus, the whole of time, understood as grounding the moment in its
dependence, brings about the intentionality which is based on such dependence. It, thus,
results in the retentional process; and this process, constitutively understood, brings about
Since the second and third conditions have been the subjects of our last two
sections, let us begin by turning our attention to the first. The notion of the totality of
time as the ground of every moment comes when we see every moment as dependent on
Notes
442
every other. Thus far, we have spoken of the dependence of the moments of past time.
This implies that no moment of already experienced, "filled" time can be conceived apart
from the moments which precede and follow it. In the forward direction, such
surpassing our already acquired experience of it. What we do is anticipate that it will
continue to provide us with further experience. For Husserl, the root of this
transcendence is the fact that the dependence of time does not end at the present moment.
It passes through it, linking it with the moments of anticipated or future time.
To see this, let us recall our earlier argument that no moment of past time can be
the first -- i.e., stand as an absolute beginning of time. For a moment to be initially given
as a moment in time, it must, as we said, have its locating horizon of pastness. When the
moment sinks down into pastness, this retained horizon accompanies it. It, thus, prevents
us from taking the past moment as a beginning of time -- i.e., as something with no
pastness relative to it (See above, ). Now, the linchpin of this argument is the
fact that the present moment must have this horizon of pastness. This follows because it
such a moment is "only an ideal limit, something abstract which can be nothing for
itself." This means that it is "not differentiated from the not-now, but rather continuously
mediates itself with the latter" (HA X, Boehm ed., p. 40). The fact that it can only exist
Notes
443
conceive of a now "which nothing preceded" (Ibid., p. 70). Hence, as we said, we must
always give it its locating horizon of pastness. The same argument can be made with
regard to the future. The "not-now" which surrounds the present moment also includes
what follows it. Thus, the mediation of the now with the not-now implies that we cannot
conceive the present moment as the last instant of time. We must give it a horizon of
anticipated, future time. The result is Husserl's "apriori law" according to which "there
If we ask why the present moment cannot exist by itself -- why it must exist only
as an "ideal limit" -- we come to the fact that retentions are required to insert a moment
into the fixed order of successive time. Since this insertion is in terms of past -- i.e.,
retained -- time, the positing of a present moment is something that occurs in terms of "a
continuum which advances towards an ideal limit" (HA X, Boehm ed., p. 40). It is
posited, not directly, but as a limit of our retentions of past moments. As such, it is
linked to every moment which precedes it. It is "nothing for itself" because its positing
as the leading edge of past time depends upon the givenness of the moments of past time.
The same can be said about each of these past moments. Each was first presented as the
leading edge of its past. Having sunk into pastness, it still possesses its own horizon of
pastness. Indeed, a moment's position in past time is partially dependent on this horizon.
We say "partially" because these past moments also have their protentional reference.
Each is dependent, in its pastness, on the moments which are presented as following it.
Since the present moment is posited as the limit of this series, it, too, shares this
given as a present protending the nowness which is always "ahead" of it. 7 In other
Notes
444
words, its givenness is such that the dependence of time passes through it linking it with
on every other. All we need to do so is to see the dependence which passes through the
present as embracing the whole of future time. The future is grasped in anticipation
which means, as our last chapter showed, its presence is a matter of the re-presentation of
what we have already experienced. Thus, in anticipating the future as objectively given,
we depict its moments as having the same relations of dependency as those which link
together the past. By virtue of their dependency, the moments of the past are
future. Not only are its moments depicted as dependent, but such dependence passes
through every moment we might conceive as terminating the future. So conceived, the
future cannot have an end, i.e., a last moment which does not point beyond itself.
With this, we move from the thought of the dependence of time's moments to
that of time's infinity. From the latter, we can see how time as a whole can serve as a
ground for each of its moments. Yet before we do so, let us pause and make clear to
ourselves the levels of dependence which are implicit in our arguments. We first have
the dependence which characterizes moments qua objectively given as part of the fixed
order of time. Here, the infinity of time -- its not having objectively presentable first and
last moments -- is derived from the dependence of such moments. No moment can be
the first since each requires its horizon of pastness. None can be the last since every
moment that is objectively presented as now has already entered into the "over and
is objective, the nowness which is always "ahead" of it, always appearing as the next
now. To move to the next level of dependence, we must consider the process through
Notes
445
which moments are objectively presented. Here, the objective dependence of moments
appears as a function of the retentional process. Thus, the fact that each moment occurs
with its locating horizon of pastness can be traced to each moment being the limit of a
series of retentions -- i.e., its being the limit of the co-present retentions along the vertical
which present this horizon. Similarly, the objective dependence of each moment on what
retentions. Each retention, in its having "sunk down," depends on further retentions
having entered the vertical. With this, we may speak of a third level of dependence.
This is the original dependence which results in time's intentionalities and, hence, in the
retentional process itself. The retentions on the vertical present the moments of past time
because each may be seen as including a whole series of retentions of retentions. Each
such retention, in its now, is dependent on a retention which, relative to it, is not now.
As such, it gives rise to an intentionality presenting the latter. The result, as we said, is
the presence of the past -- i.e., the moment which is presented as retained rather than as
impressionally given. Once we engage in a subjective reading of the time diagram, this
prior to the objective presence of time, results in such presence. Put more radically, this
dependence results in the very existence of that which it makes intentionally present.
The obvious question here is how we can speak of the dependence of moments
before such moments actually exist. In speaking of the third form of dependence, we
refer to the "nows" and "not-nows" of our various retentions; and, in a subjective reading
of the diagram, we assert that their relation -- ultimately, their dependence -- results in
time. As such, it is what results in the distinction between the now and the not-now.
How is this possible? The answer involves the various levels of dependence as they
function in the above mentioned "teleological circle." The circle is such that the
which, as we shall see, gives rise to the productive intentionalities which result in the
accomplishing of time and its objective dependence. This circle, we may note, is implicit
in the move from the objective to the subjective readings of the time diagram. Having
time, we turned and considered the results of such dependence -- the retentional
involved in a process in which it is both a goal and a determining ground. It is, thus,
dependent on the moments which surround it. Since the latter are also dependent on their
every objective moment is linked to every other through a serial chain of dependencies.
As such, its ultimate dependence is on nothing less than the whole of time understood as
When applied to experiences, the above conception gives us Husserl's claim that
"temporality ... designates not just something universally pertaining to every experience,
but a necessary form binding experiences with experiences" (Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 198).
An experience, in having its time, is necessarily and formally bound to other experiences.
This follows because, as objectively presented, its first and last moments are linked
through a chain of dependencies with the moments surrounding this experience. Several
conclusions can be drawn from this. The first is that the independence of a content laden
count as fully independent. Each, in its connection, 'stands in need of completion.' This,
according to its form and type, is not just any connection. It is rather a linked connection
Notes
447
from the continuity of time. The latter follows from time's dependence -- i.e., from the
fact that each of its moments is "nothing for itself." Another conclusion is that every
experience, by virtue of its duration, necessarily "... takes its position in an unending
filled horizon of time. This also signifies that it belongs to an infinite 'stream of
experience'." The individual experience, in having its finite duration, can begin and end,
"but the stream of experiences can neither begin nor end" (Ibid., p. 198). This unending
quality of the "continuum of durations" follows from the arguments that there cannot be a
although time in its moments is transitory, time itself, considered in its wholeness, is not
transitory. In Kant's words, "time ... is unchanging and abiding." This means that "time
does not flow away (verläuft sich nicht)," for, if we regard it as a whole, then there is no
"time" -- i.e., a time outside of the wholeness of time -- into which it could flow (Kritik
d. r. V., B 183; ed. cit., III, 137). For Husserl, this quality of time as a whole is also the
quality of the stream of experiences. The latter, as structured by the form of time in its
wholeness, "can neither begin nor end" -- i.e., progress into another time.
Let us recall our repeated assertion that a whole which does not have a "beyond"
is a unique singular. Such a singular exists simply as one and not as one among many
singulars, each having the same nature. Why is it that we must regard time as unique?
Why cannot we think of it only in terms of finite durations -- i.e., think of it as finite
times among finite times? What we are actually inquiring about is the basis for Kant's
assertion: "The infinity of time signifies nothing more than that every determinate
quantity of time is only possible through the limitations of one single time taken as a
ground underlying [this quantity]" (Kritik d. r. V., A 32; ed. cit., IV, 37, italics added).
Notes
448
An answer can be provided by admitting that the Kantian conditions for the objective
grasp of successive and enduring time require the dependence of the moment (See above,
). The resulting interdependence of time's objective moments doesn't just lead to the
thought of the infinity of time; it also requires us to speak of time as a whole -- i.e., as a
mediately, its dependence on this whole. Thus, in the view which sees time as a series
ofobjectively graspable moments, this whole must be taken as the ground of each
and, hence, as ultimately dependent on the whole of time, then the thought of the
moment's existence implies the thought of this whole's existence -- i.e., the existence of
the "unchanging and abiding" totality of moments. We can also say that the dependence
of the moment demands the independence of time in its wholeness. Only as independent
can the latter function as the ultimate ground of each of its moments. Independence,
here, means: not being dependent on another "time" in order to be. The thought of the
moment in its dependence, thus, leads to the thought of the whole of time as a "single
time" -- i.e., as a unique singular. In other words, it implies its thought as the abiding
totality of its moments, a totality which, in its all-inclusiveness, excludes another time
How does this totality or whole function in the temporal process? Before we
answer this question, we should emphasize the difference between a teleological process
process is that its actuality depends upon the actuality of its agent. In other words, the
cause must be actual in order for the effect to be actualized. This view is not just that of
modern physics with its focus on efficient causality. It also finds experession in the
interpretation of formal ontology which takes this as the science of the principles from
which the actual relations of facts can be derived. The principles, as exemplified by
Notes
449
Plato's "really real" eidh, are regarded as causes pre-existingthe relations which they
not objectively given before the relations which instantiate them. They are first brought
into objective being by these relations. This does not mean that the facts which are
related have no inherent necessity in their relations -- i.e., no determining ground for
their being related in particular ways. It does, however, signify that this necessity is not
to be found in an already existent cause of the process forming these relations, but rather
in a goal towards which this process is directed. The goal, in other words, is the
determining ground of the process. This means that what is to be actualized -- i.e., the
goal -- determines the being of the actual and, in so doing, brings about its own
progressive actualization.9
To see the temporal process as teleological is to show that it does involve this
identity between ground and goal. Let us put this in terms of the fact that when, with
Husserl, we equate actuality and presence, we seem to be asserting that only the presently
given moment is actual. The past moments have expired and the future moments are not
yet given.10 Yet Husserl also asserts that the present moment is "nothing for itself." To
dependent on their totality, time as a whole. The latter can, thus, be taken as determining
the being of the actual moment -- i.e., as grounding it in its dependence. In so doing, it
makes possible the intentionality which is based on the dependence of the now on the
not-now.
As we said, this intentionality presents this not-now. It makes the past moment
present in the form of a retention; and it makes this retention refer to the past moment.
Concretely, this means that the dependence of the now on the moments preceding it
yields a diagonal intentionality which can be read in two directions. It can be read as
making the earlier moments present in the form of retentions -- the very retentions which
Notes
450
are the now's co-present "horizon of pastness." It can also be read as providing the
intentional references of our present retentions to successively given moments in the past.
Here, our present retentions refer to the transitory moments of time. Yet, taken in
themselves, i.e., in their co-presence with the ongoing now, such retentions do not pass
away. Nothing retained has to be lost. In Husserl's words, "... ideally a consciousness is,
indeed, possible in which everything is retentionally present" (HA X, Boehm ed., p. 31,
fn. 1). We can thus say that the ultimate result of the dependence of the moment is the
and abiding in its wholeness. Time's presence in the form of retentions is its presence as
abiding -- this, even though these retentions refer to its moments as transitory. Here, of
course, we must add that such abiding requires that we speak of the dependence of every
moment, not just on the moments which preceded it, but also on those which follow it.
The intentionality occasioned by this dependence of the earlier moments on the later
moments. Its result is the "merging" which yields the abiding of time in the form of an
several things are required. First, we must say that temporal dependence does not end at
the present moment or actual "now." It passes through it to the next. We must also say
that the dependence of the now on the next now exhibits itself in an intentionality
presenting the latter. If, in accordance with our third condition, we take this
intentionality as productive, then the intending of the next now constitutes it in its actual
givenness. The result is a new now and, hence, the modification of the present instant
into what is no longer a new now, i.e., its modification into a just past instant. The latter
speak of only our present retentions as immediately given. It would see the intentionality
which produces the next now as Husserl's vertical intentionality. This, it would claim, is
the origin of time. It unifies our present retentions into an accomplished duration.
Passing through our present retentions, it always points to what will be given as the next
moment. Considered as producing what it intends, it would, thus, advance this duration
from present to present by constantly adding the next moment to it. Yet behind such
intentionality is the dependence of moments; and behind this is the independence of time
considered as an abiding totality of moments. As already indicated, the latter is the goal
of the process which results in an increasing duration. But since it is what grounds every
The teleological nature of this conception becomes apparent when we say that
the process which results in the abiding totality of time is, itself, the result of the
moment's dependence on this same totality. We, thus, have the "teleological circle"
speaking of the existence of the effect, we presuppose the existence of the cause. In such
an understanding, nothing can be self-caused -- i.e., bring itself into existence through its
effects. This, however, is precisely what we are asserting with regard to the totality of
progressively brings about the object of this dependence. Our claim is that the whole of
time, which grounds the intentionality of each moment (and is, in fact, its ultimate
object) causes its own objective existence through this same intentionality. Here, of
course, we must add that, in any finite time, this whole cannot exist as something actually
given. Its objective givenness as an accomplished duration would require the totality of
time. It would demand the actual retention of all of time's moments which would, itself,
imply the exhaustion of time -- i.e., the pastness of all of its moments. Thus, as long as
Notes
452
time continues, such a whole remains a goal of this process. As determining the process,
it functions as its teleological ground. Since, in fact, there is no time outside of the
wholeness of time into which this whole could progress -- i.e., change and become other
than itself -- this ground is absolutely timeless. The identity of ground and goal
contained in the notion of the whole of time signifies, then, that this whole is a timeless
All of this, of course, requires our granting that the intentionality which arises
from a moment's dependence is, in fact, productive. To review our conclusions, we can
say that since this dependence is twofold, so is this requirement. Thus, we must assert
that the intentionality which proceeds from the present moment to the next is actually
productive of this next moment. Its bringing the new now into existence is one with the
passing away or expiration of what was "just now" the present moment. Since the later
requirement. The intentionality based on the dependence of the present moment on the
moment preceding it must be taken as re-producing the latter -- i.e., as making it present
widest sense)," including, as part of this, the intentionality found in social and sexual
drives. He asks whether, quite apart from any transcendent references to actually given
Others, such intentionality "has a preliminary stage (Vorstufe), one prior to a developed
systematic drive -- literally a "drive system" (Triebsystem). The last is understood as "an
original lasting streaming." His point is that our relations to Others have their basis in
Husserl concludes this reflection with the assertion, "This would lead to the conception
quoted makes the claim that it is responsible for the temporal process itself. Thus, the
forms, we can say, out of the successively given nows, time as enduring or "lasting." It
also acts to propel this enduring "from present to present." In this, it is productive of the
ever new now which adds to the quantity of accomplished duration. The nature of this
productive intentionality is given in the next clause. On the one hand, the enduring and
the ever new now are to be regarded as contents "of a fulfillment of the drive" -- i.e., the
intentional drive towards temporalization. On the other hand, they are "intended before
the goal" -- i.e., before they actually exist. What we have here is an intentionality which
produces what it intends. The temporal contents whose presence would fulfill its
intention are intended before they exist and this intending is, in fact, a bringing of these
same contents into objective existence. Husserl, then, is asserting that there is a driving
intentionality directed towards temporalization, one which has as its "goal" new moments
Notes
454
and a consequent increase of the duration which did not yet exist. It is an intentionality
which fulfills itself by bringing into existence and retaining in existence new moments.
In Husserl's words, what we have is the "nucleus of a primal modal intention, one which
simply arises and fulfills itself" (Ibid., p. 594). We confront, in other words, an
intentionality which is responsible for both its intention and its fulfillment.
The teleological conception that here arises becomes apparent once we translate
this into the terms of the dependence of the moment. We then assert that such "driving
present, actually given moment on the abiding wholeness of time. This dependence is
mediate. It occurs through the immediate dependence of the moment on those that
surround it. This means that, as "nothing for itself," a moment's actuality requires the
actuality of the surrounding moments. Its being in the now requires their being in the
now. Their present givenness has, in turn, the same requirement, and so on throughout
the whole of time. Thus, with regard to the future or not yet existent moment, Husserl
can claim that the very being of the presently given moment is one with a driving
intentionality, an intentionality that drives it to appropriate the future moment and bring
it into a present givenness. There is, in other words, a drive in each "original present,"
one which, by virtue of its dependence, "propels it from present to present." Each
present that is brought into existence is a "fulfillment" of this drive, even though it did
not exist when it stood as the drive's goal. The same dependence and resulting
intentional drive also exists with regard to the immediately past moment. This moment,
Husserl elsewhere writes: "Necessarily linked to the consciousness of the [present] now
is the consciousness of the just past which is, again, a now. No experience can cease
without the consciousness of its ceasing and having ceased, and this is a new fulfilled
now" (Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 200). The reason why the consciousness of the now
Notes
455
requires the consciousness of the just past now is that the present now, as "nothing for
itself," cannot be given without the just past now. Thus, the intentional drive which is
based on the now's dependence is one that fulfills itself by reproducing or retaining the
past instant. This is why the givenness of the latter is a "new fulfilled now." Since this
intentional drive also fulfills itself in making the future present, its result is both the
progression of time and the retention of its moments. It progressively realizes the whole
To see the teleological character of this process, we need only repeat our earlier
remarks. The whole of time -- which cannot be actualized in any finite time -- exists as
the telos or goal of the temporal process. But it also determines the process itself by
virtue of its being the ground of the moment's dependence. Thus, as a "not yet," the
whole brings about its own progressive actualization -- this by determining what does
actually exist in the immediate sense -- i.e., by determining the intentionalities of the
Having seen how such a whole can be conceived as the teleological ground of
the temporal process, let us turn to our second question: How can we identify it with the
"timeless now" -- the now that is reached by the last stage of the reduction? For such an
identification, several things are required. As standing at the origin of time, the nunc
stans is pre-objective. Thus, we must be able to say that the whole of time is not actually
objective, but only has a pre-objective existence. We argued that this whole functions as
the ground of every moment by containing all its moments. Accordingly, we must be
able to make the same assertion about the nunc stans. Granting that the whole of time is
pre-objective, we must say that the nunc stans pre-objectively contains all the moments
of time. Finally, we must also see the nunc stans as determining each appearing moment
Notes
456
as dependent. Like the whole of time, it must be seen as grounding the appearing
The first condition is easily satisfied. When we say that the whole of time
determines the temporal process as its "not yet," we are asserting that it does not yet
objectively exist as an accomplished duration. As the process's ground and goal, it is, in
fact posited as pre-objective. Since it cannot be objectively given in any finite time, it
determines the temporal process prior to its being objectively given -- i.e., as that which
What about our second condition -- the condition which requires us to see the
nunc stans as pre-objectively containing all the moments of time? Our last two chapters
touched upon this. Thus, our sixth chapter, speaking of the stationary now which is at
the core of our functioning, asserted that "pre-objectively, the whole of the time required
for every possible synthesis is present in the pre-temporal now ..." (See above, ).
Our fifth chapter made the same point in terms of the notion of unique singularity -- the
very singularity which characterizes the whole of time. We noted that when we bracket
constituted (objective) time, the now that remains is absolutely unique. Once we perform
the reduction, there is no present "beyond" it. This means that this timeless, stationary
now represents in a reduced fashion the whole of successive time. It is the original
presence which each moment of time successively displays in its being now.
For Husserl, this display can be considered an objective exhibition of what the
stationary now implicitly contains. Speaking of "the constant, absolute, concrete self-
... in this -- this is the occurring (Geschenen) of temporalization -- its stationary being
exhibits itself (legt sich aus) in identifiable unities, unities which are one and the same in
the changes of the stream, persisting in their unity, constant in their streaming, but
constantly changing their temporal modes [i.e., their temporal positions vis-a-vis the
Notes
457
now]. The unit (Das Eine) has its temporal unity in these temporal modes; but all the
temporal modes are already present in the simultaneous total now which, as stationary, is
a whole with all these temporal modes as moments ... (Ms. D 13 III, p. 16, July 7, 1933).
Interpreting Husserl, we can say that the constant streaming of objective moments
themselves, exhibit the stationary now at the origin of temporalization. They exhibit the
now whose constant quality makes the temporal process constant. Thus, as exhibitions of
this now, all the temporal modes or moments are "already present" within it. As "parts"
The same point about exhibition was made in our last chapter. As we cited
Husserl, "When the ego is ... finding itself in successive being, it is, in fact, exhibiting its
full present, exhibiting what it actually is now, what actually lies within it as an ego"
(Ms. A V 5 5, p. 10, Jan. 133). In other words, in its production of time, "the present ego
is self-shaping and bears in itself its past self-shapings." Per se, "it has no breadth, no
temporal extension ... But its exhibition necessarily leads to the temporality of
(Ibid., pp. 10-11). The assertion of this passage is that the ego becomes in time what,
pre-objectively, it already is before time. Thus, when the ego is engaged in temporal
ego considers itself to be in time insofar as it "bears within itself its past self-shapings."
retentions form the data on the vertical line of the time diagram, a line which is taken as
attached to the ego's ongoing now. As we said, the vertical line is not, itself, the
"absolutely timeless" origin of the temporal process. Per se, it represents "the quasi-
extension of the ego over time." It is a first exhibition of what the stationary now pre-
Notes
458
temporally contains. A second exhibition is given by the moments which are posited as
departing in time -- this through the constant modification (the "stationary streaming") of
the data on the vertical. With this, we have the actual extension of the ego over time.
To complete this picture, let us recall that not just the totality of time is included
in the stationary now, but also the alphabet of contents -- i.e., the totality of the content
which is required for every possible synthesis. This means that, in regarding the original
which does not have a beginning or an end," one in which "the temporal data of sensation
arise from the non-temporal elements [i.e., the alphabet] of sensation" (Ms. E III 2, p. 49,
1921). With the temporalization of content, the ego can appear as a particular center. In
Husserl's words, it can appear "as the ego-center which gives temporal presence to sense
(sinn), as the center which stands in the presence of time, as the center in relation to
which past and future time have a sense-filled (Sinnhaft) relation" (Ms. C 3 III, p. 35,
Mar. 1931).
If we ask how all the modes of time are "already present" in the ego's now, we
can say that they are present as a goal. This is the first way in which Husserl can speak
finitudes, but [also as] included in the nunc stans" (Ms. E III 9, Nov. 5, 1931, HA XV,
Kern ed., p. 379-8). The whole of infinite time is required to exhibit what is included in
the nunc stans. Thus, the latter remains, throughout this infinite exhibition, the goal of
this process. It is also, however, its ground. To repeat Husserl's remark: "Infinity ... in
the form of temporality" is implicitly "included (beschlossen)" within it. Thus, the nunc
stans is the not yet objectively actual referent of the dependences which stretch from each
actually given moment to the whole of time. As such it is also the ground of the
moments of time in their dependency and,thus, as grounding the very process which
We can secure this last point -- which is our third condition -- by speaking of the
present moment as the appearance of the nunc stans. To call it an appearance of the latter
means, first of all, that it re-presents the latter in its quality of original presence. This
quality is such that "all the modes of time are already present" within the stationary now.
As we cited Husserl, they "dwell within it non-independently." They exist in the non-
exhibited in extended time. The appearing moment thus re-presents its original identity
with all other moments through its being "nothing for itself" -- i.e., its being nothing
apart from the latter. Objectively regarded, it appears as dependent on what precedes and
follows it. It cannot be objectively now -- i.e., be an appearance of the nunc stans --
without its surrounding moments also being borught into the now. Insofar as this
dependence expresses itself in an impulse or drive (Trieb), we can say, with Husserl, that
"in each primordial present, there are transcending impulses ... which reach out into
every other present ..." These impulses "propel" or "drive" our ongoing nowness from
"present to present". Thus, to say as we earlier did, that the appearance in time of the
nunc stans is one with its departure from this appearance is, ultimately, to say that its
being in time is one with its streaming -- i.e., its being the ongoing now. It cannot be in
time without the intentional drive which makes it streamingly appropriate the future and
retain the past. This follows since both "temporal modes" are included in the nunc stans,
the very thing that its appearing is progressively exhibiting. Thus, in its self-exhibition,
the nunc stans is Husserl's "primal present" -- the present that is "primally
as the ground of the ego's temporalization, Husserl can write: "Each ego has something
Notes
460
innate. Within itself, it innately bears the teleological ground of its streaming,
We can describe the relation between the non-temporal nunc stans and its
temporal appearing in ontological terms. Time, we said, represents the "whether it is" of
the object. It is the presence which makes things be present and actual -- this, no matter
what they are. Thus, when we speak of the original unity of time, we are speaking of the
unity of being itself. As embodying this unity, the nunc stans is presence per se -- i.e.,
being per se. It signifies being in its Parmenidean character, the character by which we
tautologically assert, everything that is is. The move to appearances is, as Parmenides
indicates, a move to plurality. In time, the now appears as continuously modifying itself.
This modification is simply the successive, serial display of its original unity. It is a
modification of the original unity of being into the continuity of existence -- a continuity
Let us put this "move to plurality" in terms of Husserl's doctrine that objective
time is constituted out of the continuous modification of what is given in the now.
Diagramatically, the data of the now form the elements of the vertical line. Their
modification is their downward moment along this line. This movement represents the
entrance into the retained of the already appropriated future -- the future which has
already become now. It also represents the increasing "pastness" of the retained. Here,
each retention, in its sinking down, becomes modified into a retention of itself. As such,
it adds a further degree of pastness to the content it retains. Relative to this increasing
pastness, the now of our co-present retentions appears to advance. There is a shift in its
relationship to the extended time which is presented through these retentions; and this
shift gives it its appearance as an ongoing now. We, thus, come to Husserl's doctrine that
temporalization is "a primal functioning ... a constant letting loose of retentions" (Ms. A
V 5, pp. 4-5, Jan. 1933). Diagramatically represented, it is a letting them descend along
Notes
461
the vertical. The key point here is that the presence of "identifiable" moments,
"persisting in their unity" as they depart into pastness, requires the constant sinking down
of the data along the vertical. This, in turn, requires the constant addition to the vertical.
It is in terms of this doctrine that we can speak of the nunc stans' appearing in
moments. For Husserl, the nunc stans cannot appear as a now in time without its
appearing as an ever new now, i.e., as an ongoing nowness vis-a-vis a departing temporal
field. We can explain this modification by pointing to the fact that the nunc stans
surpasses every moment in its containing all moments. It, thus, cannot appear as a
moment without surpassing this appearance. As we earlier put this, it is always "ahead"
of its appearance; it is constantly appearing as what will count as the next moment.
Behind this continuous re-appearance of the nunc stans is the dependence of each of its
appearances. The present moment displays the nunc stans -- i.e., is its objective
appearance -- in the requirement that it cannot appear alone. Its objective presence
ultimately requires the presence of all the moments which are implicit in the nunc stans.
Thus, it displays the nunc stans in its dependence. Mediately dependent on the whole of
time, it is immediately dependent on the next moment -- the next appearance of the nunc
stans. Thus, its very givenness as the appearance of the nunc stans demands the
reappearance of the nunc stans. It requires its reappearance as the next moment. The
present moment, as dependent, must appropriate this next moment in order to be. Given
that this appropriation is one with the moment's own "modification" of sinking into
pastness, the appropriation is, so to speak, the "engine" of the downward movement
along the vertical. It is the engine of the "letting loose" of retentions. Hence, it also
brings about the presentation of the successive time through which our ongoing now
appears to move.
Notes
462
The above, of course, simply translates what we said about the dependence of the
moment on the whole of time into the corresponding terms of the moment and the nunc
stans. The moment's dependence on the whole of time is, pre-objectively, its dependence
on the nunc stans. To reverse this, we can say that its dependence on the nunc stans is a
relation which the moment must objectively exhibit as its dependence on the whole of
time. This follows since such a whole, with its infinity, is the objective counterpart of
the nunc stans -- i.e., the one thing which could completely exhibit it. The point of our
translation is simply to locate the timeless, all-inclusive whole of time within us and to
Before we draw out the implications of the last section, we should guard against a
argued that such experience is constitutive of time. This might lead the reader to suppose
that time is our subjective product. Such a reader would take the retentional process as
constitutive of time and see this process as something occurring as an effect of a given,
individual subject. For Husserl, this is not the case. The individual subject is not a
ground or cause of time. He first appears because time grounds him. Thus, when we
speak of the retentional process as constitutive, this does not mean that this process arises
from a subject who is "there" before its action. The process is rather that from which the
individual can be said to arise or "awaken." Once constituted, the subject appears as a
person who retains and thereby grasps departing time. He also appears as the center of
an already constituted temporal field. He appears as the now from which retentions are
constantly being let loose. As such, he seems to be that in and through which time is
retentionally constituted. Yet, as should be obvious, this appearance has validity only
Notes
463
insofar as we identify the subject with his ground -- i.e., with the now which, in
constantly modifying itself, actually serves as the engine of the retentional process.
The same point can be made by noting that the constitution which is directed to
the abiding totality of time requires an infinite retentional consciousness -- one which
"takes no notice of the limitation of the temporal field" (See above, ). Insofar as
we have a finite lifetime, such a consciousness is not our own. Yet we imply such a
consciousness (or at least its basis) when we admit that we cannot posit a first moment of
time. Here, our time consciousness implies what surpasses our limited retentional
consciousness. More particularly, it implies the duality of our essence -- a duality which
includes both our identity and difference with our ground. Such a duality is implicit in
Husserl's remarks:
Every monad has its immanent temporality. In this temporality, there is a beginning
taken as a beginning of its entering-into-relationship with other monads in its becoming
worldly (Verweltlichung) within objective time. This is also a form of co-existence, (in
the broad sense) a form of communalization. If the monad appears as a new actor in
world time, he also, finally, departs. When being and non-being are real temporal being,
then previously he did not exist and later he will not exist. In the immanence of a
monad, a beginning is a limit of its worldly self-constitution. A "pre"-beginning, does
this have a sense? Can it have one? The limit of self-constitution is the [initial] limit of
the developmental structure of a child, of the whole person in the world. If one could say
that this is not the beginning of being, but rather that of worldly development and of
being in the world, and that, therefore, the co-existence of monads extends beyond that of
the world, so one could try to interpret this as follows: The monad's being is a being in
and for itself in a self-constitution which never begins or ends in immanent temporality.
A particular form of this constitution, which does have a beginning and an end, is the
world accomplishing (verweltichende) constitution in which the monad becomes a
monad living in an environment (eine umweltlich lebende wird) and [as such is a monad
who] consciously, constitutively experiences other monads as worldly realities, entering
into relation with them (Ms. C 8 2, pp. 6-7, Oct. 1929).
Notes
464
Interpreting Husserl, we can say that according to one part of a monad's essence, he does
part of his essence is such that we can say that a monad exists in "a self-constitution
consciousness.
Husserl goes on to express the relation between a monad's finitude and infinitude
in terms of "world time" and transcendental time." In real world time, "only the [finite]
lifetimes of monads are realized." Yet behind them, standing as their ground, is an
(vollkommene geschlossene) infinity." From its vantage point, "the realization [of a
monad's finite lifetime] is not an affair of this monad alone, but rather concerns all the
intentional and teleological causality of monads existing in and for themselves. They
are for each other because they are dependent on each other in their being for each other"
(Ibid., p. 7, italics added). For Husserl, then, there is an unbroken transcendental time
which corresponds to the "self-constitution which never begins or ends." This is the time
which grounds the individual lifetimes of the monads, making them imply each other
insofar as they are parts of one unending time. My finite retentional consciousness refers
to my finite lifetime -- i.e., to a limited segment of "world time." Yet this consciousness
implies more than it actually retains -- i.e., implies Husserl's unending retentional
Several things can be said about this time. To the point that it brings about the
"intentional and teleological causality of monads," it reminds us that "each ego has
something innate. Within itself, it innately bears the teleological ground of its streaming,
Notes
465
constituting, transcendental life" (Ms. E III 9, p. 11, 1929). This ground, as we said, is
the primal present. The constant, unending quality of its constitution is what allows
Husserl to speak of each monad's being as existing "in a self-constitution which never
reminded of Husserl's position that the intentional, subject-objection relation is first given
through the intentionalities of the retentional process. This is another instance of the fact
that the "perfectly continuous" time accomplished by the primal present is, in its
consciousness.
include all the moments of time. As such, it does not just ground his retentional
center -- it also grounds the retentional processes of every individual. This implies that
this finite consciousness. Our point may be put in terms of the last section's assertion
that temporal dependence does not signify that all the moments of time are already given
-- i.e., are "there" before they are retained. Temporal dependence is teleological. It
successively produces its objects which means that it successively results in the moments
on which each present moment is dependent. Objectively speaking, its result is the
"thereness" of such moments in the form of retentions. This "thereness" is also the
which underlies not just my retentional consciousness, but also that of every member of
pastness ..." every experience, in having its temporal position, "... takes its place in an
infinite, filled horizon of time" (Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 198). Implicit in these remarks is
the claim that the horizonality of experiences has its origin in the horizonality of time.
This cannot be otherwise given that time is the form in which our experiences are cast.
Thus, when we abstract from time, what we have is simply the alphabet of contents, an
formative process of temporalization that "the temporal data of sensation arise from the
non-temporal elements of sensation" (Ms. E III 2, p. 49, 1921). Time, we can say, is the
"writing" by which this alphabet is temporally arranged so as to spell out a given world.
For Husserl, as we shall see, the horizonality of the world is an objectification of the
formal necessities involved in this writing -- necessities which can lead to the presence of
subjects.
the notion of horizon. In tracing these back to the temporal process, we will uncover
The notion of horizon is, as we said, that of a series of experiences which have
been connected and, in their connections, determine the further experiences which can
join this series (See above, ). Now, if we ask what first links experiences together
so as to give them the possibility of forming a series, we come to the first of the features
of this notion: that of dependence. Experiences can form themselves into a horizon by
virtue of their dependence. Since this dependence demands their indefinite continuance,
Notes
467
the "internal horizon" of a real object cannot end. This implies that for an experience to
experiences directed to it. Each such experience demands the possibility of a further
experience, an experience of the object from a different perspective or side. Without this
possibility, the object could not be posited as a "real unity" -- i.e., as a perceptual sense
which exhibits itself in an indefinite range of examples. Thus, to say that an object is
experiences. Indeed, insofar as an object's "true being" demands that our experience
mutually confirming experiences. With this, we have a second feature of the notion of
underlying unity, a unity of which they can be said to be experiences. Experiences can
be said to mutually confirm or validate each other insofar as they continue to disclose the
object. A real object's internal horizon is composed of the perspectival appearing which
are grounded in the temporal process. Thus, the indefinite continuance of experiences
points back to the dependence of the moments bearing these experiences. By virtue of
experiences" (Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 198). Like the moment of time, the experiences
which fill it can only exist as part of a greater whole. Dependence is also the temporal
running through our present retentions. It thus results in that merging and re-
enforcement of retained contents which can yield the presence of this sense.
of an apeparing unity. It is not, however, invariably successful. Its synthesis can become
frustrated. What we took to be an object's internal horizon may turn out to be only a
series of "empty anticipations." Failure is possible because positing requires not just
temporal synthesis but also an appropriate content. Thus, a successful positing requires
similar contents. Only these can re-enforce each other in the merging occasioned by
particular contents are not inherently tied to particular moments, the horizon grounded by
the dependence of moments always remains contingent. In other words, a horizon may
fail as a horizon. It may cease to manifest an underlying unity. Thus, even though the
something which must obtain. Throughout our experience of it, the unity remains
Husserl writes: "Everything has its internal and external horizons" (Ms. C 7 II, p.
6, June 1932). We can make the same points about these external horizons that we have
just made with regard to the internal. They also manifest an indefinite continuance and
noted, is not that of a thing but rather that of the world. Thus, to move from the internal
words, its apprehension is joined to the apprehension of the things which surround it.
The apprehension of each of the latter is similarly joined to the apprehensions of its
Notes
469
surrounding objects. For Husserl, the ultimate terminus of this expanding series of
external horizons is "the totality, 'the world as a perceptual world.'" (Krisis, 2nd Biemel
ed., p. 165). This is the world which is posited as "the totality of things" (Ibid., p. 145).
Since an individual can never actually experience this totality, he has to say: "this world
exists for me in a core of experiencibility and [in] a horizon of the unexperienced" (Ms.
C 7 II, p. 6).
The individual, in a certain sense, can also assert this about each of the objects
within the world. Each has its unending, internal horizon of potential experiences. What
distinguishes the world horizon is that we see it as the ultimate ground of the validity of
our individual positings. As we cited Husserl: "To live is always to live in the certainty
of the world." In other words, "I always have the certainty of the world in each and
every thing" (Ms. A VII 1, p. 5, Dec. 1933 - Jan. 1934). This follows from the thing
being posited as something "of" the world. An indivudal experience is "of" a thing only
insofar as it forms part of a series manifesting the thing's underlying unity. Similarly, a
thing is "of" the world only when this set of experiences is part of a greater set -- one
which manifests the perceived world's unity. This means, with regard to particular sets
of experiences directed towards particular things, "... as one takes place, it always
presupposes others having objective validity. It always, thus, presupposes for the
observer the universal ground of the validity of the world" (Krisis, ed. cit., p. 151). In
other words, we cannot posit a thing as something "of" the world -- i.e., as having a
worldly sense -- without also positing the underlying unity which is the sense of the
experiences, each experience presupposing for its validity the presence of further
ultimately ground the validity of any of its elements -- until it embraces "the totality, 'the
world as a perceptual world.'" Here, the objects of the world "... have their actuality for
Notes
470
This "ideal unity" is both the underlying sense of the world and the harmonious
unity of objects in one perceptual world. As the latter, it embraces the totality of an
object's relations to all other objects; and this includes the totality of the ways in which
such objects are implied in any single object's positing as something "of" the world. We
can also say that such relatedness presupposes an underlying unity -- a unity which we
presuppose is saying that an object is something "of" the world. Thus, as we remarked
with regard to an object's internal horizons, our experiences of it are horizonally linked
together -- i.e., form parts of one horizon -- only insofar as they manifest an underlying
unity. The same point obtains when we speak of the external horizons of a thing. It is
only insofar as the experiences composing such horizons manifest the world's "ideal
unity," its unity as a single sense, that we can speak of these experiences as forming parts
of one all embracing world horizon. For Husserl, then: "The world is not constituted as
an individual reality is. It is the original, constantly changing horizon which yet remains
one. It is the unthematic horizon which is present in every individual reality" (Ms. A VII
1, p. 4, italics added). Since the world represents the totality of things, this world
horizon is not just singular, but uniquely singular. Taken as the totality of what we can
experience, it cannot have a beyond. To cite Husserl again: "... the world does not exist
like an existent entity or object. It rather exists in a singularity for which the plural is
senseless. Every plural and singular that can be drawn from it presupposes the horizon of
the world" -- i.e., the world as the totality of our actual and possible experiences (Krisis,
p. 141).
To put this in terms of validity, we can say that to posit a thing as a worldly entity
is to place its internal horizon in the context of the external horizons which give it its
confirm or fail to confirm our theses concerning its being in the world. Defined in terms
of the world, the object receives its sense from its relations to other objects; and the same
can be said about these objects. Thus, the horizons which manifest these relations must
expand until they embrace the whole of experience. For Husserl, it is this whole, taken
such givenness is what results in the horizonality of our experience of the world. In
Husserl's words:
modes." As we said, this horizonality is based upon temporal dependence. For Husserl,
(Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 198). Thus, like the moment of time, the experience which
Notes
472
"fills" it can only exist as part of a greater horizon, i.e., as part of an "all-sided, infinite,
horizon which cannot be complete until it embraces the totality of experience -- i.e., the
whole of the experiential world. Implicit in this notion is the thought that nothing less
than the whole of experience can serve as the grounding condition for each individual
experience. The possibility of the latter is dependent on the former. This means that the
which, in not admitting a beyond, is both self-referring and uniquely singular. To trace
this to the form of time is simply to repeat our assertion that the whole of time is the
dependent on those which surround it, hence each is mediately dependent on the whole of
time. The latter is the ultimate object of the intentionalities which spring from the
moment's dependence. Thus, every moment of time is one with every other in finally
having the same intentional reference. Every moment is a moment "of" the same whole
of time. This whole, then, is completely self-referring. It does not point beyond itself --
but only to itself. Granting this, the unique singularity of time can be said to be the
"primal form" of the unique singularity of the world. It is what makes the world a world
-- i.e., a totality of objects whose experience does not refer beyond itself to yet another
world.
If we take the worldly being of an experience as it being temporally given, i.e., its
being a "datum within the objective order of time," this is also conditioned by the form of
temporal dependence. The intentionalities arising from such dependence are what first
"datum" has its worldly validity as an experience "of" the world, this too can be traced to
these temporal intentionalties. The latter unify our experience and, in so doing, situate it
Notes
473
in a greater whole. In other words, their action is such that just as each moment is "of"
the whole of time, so each experience which fills it is "of" the world which is structured
by this whole.
We can pursue this last point by recalling that experiences are horizonally linked
together only insofar as they manifest an underlying unity. For Husserl, the "ideal unity"
of the world is something aimed at -- i.e., is a goal -- "in the constant movement of
making corrections" and revising validities. It is, in other words, a teleological unity. In
its present state, "the world ... exists, but exists in 'contradiction' with itself. It exists but
does not yet exist insofar as it is always existent in relative true being and relative non-
being" (Ms. E III 9, Nov. 5, 1931; HA XV, Kern ed., pp. 380-81). Neither its true being
nor its non-being (our cancelled positings) are absolute. Both are relative to what we
shall uncover in our expanding horizon of experiences. Now, if we ask why our
experiences are horizonally linked together -- i.e., why they are directed towards
manifesting an ultimate unity, why, in other words, this unity stands as the ideal,
time. By virtue of this horizonality, time is inherently synthetic. No limit can be set to
the diagonal and vertical intentionalities which arise from the dependence of its
moments. This means that its own all-embracing unity as a single time is its inherent,
teleologically determining goal. It is because of this that filled time, i.e., our actual
This does not mean that this world must obtain. For Husserl, "Every fact, and
thus, the fact of the world is, as universally admitted, contingent qua fact. This implies,
assuming that it exists, that it could be different from what it is; [it implies] that it could,
perhaps,even not be" (EP II, Boehm ed., p. 50). Thus, the facticity of the world remains
such that it is possible for the worly horizon to break up into a tumult of sensations. The
teleological determination of our experiences does not dispense with this facticity. It is
Notes
474
rather its temporal compliment. This follows because when we say that the world has a
factual, contingent character, we mean that it cannot be fully determined beforehand. Its
past givenness does not completely determine what will be given. The teleological
perspective does not deny this. It rather speaks of what will be given as helping to
determine what is given. Thus, teleologically speaking, the ideal unity of the world
functions to determine the world as its not-yet. Since the determination by this not-yet
implies a lack of complete determination by the past, the results of already accomplished
syntheses remain contingent. We will return to this point in a later section. For the
present, it is enough to say that teleological determination does not prevent the
content. Such a content, taken as factually given, can disrupt the results of temporal
synthesis -- this, even though the temporal form of synthesis continually structures our
experience.
Husserl's notion of the "ideal unity" of the world can put in terms of a general
claim underlying this and our previous chapters: the world as it exists through time is
self-objectification in time of the nunc stans. As our last section indicated, the nunc stans
is the original, pre-objective unity of the moments of successive time. It manifests itself
in their interdependence and, thus, in the horizonality of filled time. It is because of this
that our experiential world is a world -- i.e., an interdependent whole. Its being a whole
is, in fact, a presupposition for its appearing in contradiction with itself. What is
unrelated is simply other. It is only when it is seen in terms of a unity which should
objectively obtain that its lack of apparent unity -- i.e., its self-contradiction -- can be
claimed.
Husserl's assertion that the world "exists but does not yet exist" has its sense in
the context of this "should." The unity presupposed by his assertion that the world exists
in self-contradiction is an all-embracing unity, one which should obtain but does not do
Notes
475
so. It is taken as a goal of the world's progressive actualization. This goal is inherent in
the temporal process which is teleologically directed towards the realization of the
wholeness of time. As the ultimate referent of every determinate quality of time, this
wholeness is what makes each time a part of the unity of a single time. Each time is "of"
the whole insofar as it is part of a process manifesting this temporal unity. Yet,
objectively speaking, the whole of time is such that it can never manifest itself in any
finite time. The dependence of each time on the whole of time is, then, its dependence
on the not-yet. It is its dependence on a goal -- i.e., on a unity which has not yet been
objectively achieved. Since dependence expresses the relation of grounding, this is also
the dependence of every moment on its pre-objective ground -- i.e., on the nunc stans.
itself through such dependence. When we regard time as filled with content, the same
assertion can be made about the world. For Husserl, the world horizon, in its unique
singularity, grounds the being and validity of every experience taken as an experience
"of" the world. Yet this horizon is, itself, what these experiences themselves collectively
realize. Thus, the ideal unity of the world is both a ground and a goal of the process of
the world's realization as a temporally unfolding structure. The key point here is that the
ideal unity of the world is that of time. It is the unity of the nunc stans objectively
exhibiting itself in the temporal dependence which structures the world horizon.
With this, we may recall why we initially asserted that the horizonality of the
world springs from the necessities involved in temporalization. Our claim was that such
necessities can lead to the presence of individual subjects. To reach this conclusion, we
must focus on one last feature of Husserl's notion of horizon, namely its intersubjective
character. As we mentioned in our third chapter, the givenness of the world in its
horizon (See above, ). This does not mean that the world-horizon is the result of
the constitutive actions of individual subjects. They are rather, as we said, "born" along
with the world in its horizonality and transcendence. They are correlates of the latter.
To merely indicate our arguments in this regard, they start from the premise that
the horizonality of our experience is its perspectival character. The perspectival ordering
of experience is correlated to a defined 0 point in space and time. It, thus, corresponds to
the ego taken as a "pure" center of experience. It is also correlated to this ego's embodied
finitude. A perspectivally experiencing ego has a real component -- i.e., is also a "real"
incapable of being in two places (two "heres") at the same time. The same perspectival
character of experiences is linked to the infinity of the world in which the subject finds
himself. This infinity results from the unending character of the perspectival series
composing the internal and external horizon of objects. With this, we have Husserl's
assertion that "... the life of each transcendental subject is a life of finite being immersed
in infinity" (Ms. A V 10, p. 24, Nov. 9, 1931). His being as a finite center is inherently
correlated to an infinite world horizon. But the latter, in surpassing his finite being, is
correlated to Others. The concept of this horizon includes the possibilities of other
centers -- other finite subjects who are "there" while he remains "here."
The key term of the above is "correlated." Subjects do not ground the world
horizon. As the correlative of such subjects, this horizon is rather the result of what
grounds both itself and such subjects. The ground, in surpassing its finite self-
expressions (i.e., individual subjects), manifests itself in the horizonal structure of their
experiences. It makes such experiences imply infinite, open ended possibilities of being;
Let us put this in terms of Husserl's position that the horizonality of the world is
based on the horizonality of time -- the latter being a result of the necessities involved in
temporalization. The first such necessity is the dependence of the moment. The second
and the third are the resulting diagonal and vertical intentionalities. Now, the reason why
central ego is that both appear through temporal synthesis. Given the proper content,
appearing is the result of the dependence of moment. Its one in many character is given
by the interweaving of time's intentionalities. These are the very same intentionalities
which situate the ego in the ongoing, central now. Temporalization, in fact, involves the
distinguished from the perceived object, and the perceiver of this object appears as the
the horizonal-perspectival character of his perceiving, the perceiver takes himself as "a
finite being immersed in infinity." His finite experience is understood as part of the non-
finite world-horizon, the very horizon which is taken as implying his Others.
Behind this horizon is, of course, the dependence of the moments of content-filled
time. Indeed, temporally considered, the world-horizon is just this dependence. Since
Husserl's all-embracing retentional consciousness has also been identified with such
dependence, we can equate the world-horizon with this non-finite consciousness. This
means that the latter has the same relation to my finite retentional consciousness that the
world-horizon has to its finite part which I call my actual, "lived," experience. In fact,
the relation is the same as that between Husserl's perfectly unbroken "transcendental
time" and the "real time" of my finite lifetime. This relation can be variously
characterized. It is, we can say, a relation between the explicit and the implicit, i.e.,
Notes
478
between that which is explicitly experienced and that which is only anticipated by means
of horizon. It can also be called the relation of the part to the whole, where one takes the
dependence yields the intentionalities which result in the "real time" of a lifetime. The
"life"of this lifetime is the set of experiences which have become unified into a distinct
retentional consciousness. The finitude of this consciousness includes its being spatially,
temporally situated since the very process which grounds it also allows it to experience
the world perspectivally. Yet the dependence of the moment, being inherently unlimited,
stretches beyond this consciousness. It, thus, places it in a horizon context, one which
implies, as equivalent possibilities, other centers of experience, other lives and lifetimes.
This means that I have to say that, by virtue of the dependence of the moment, the
intentionalities which ground me could just as well have grounded Others. I imply these
Others since my own being, as grounded by this dependence, indicates a greater whole --
one capable of "bearing" and "validating" not just myself but also an unending totality of
finite subjects. Such subjects, as we cited Husserl, are both "monads existing in and for
themselves" and "are dependent on each other" (See above, ). The nature of this
their collective existence "in and for themselves." Otherwise put: the whole of time, in
grounding the dependence of its moments, brings about the intentionalities which result
in the existence of monads in and for themselves. In so doing, it brings about its own
progressive actualization as something objective -- i.e., as the time which stands, with the
world, over and against such monads. The dependence of monads on each other is, one
level, their dependence on the world conceived as a ground of being and validity. On
another level, it is their dependence on the temporal wholeness which makes the world a
Notes
479
world. As such, it is also the interdependence of monads since they are, collectively, that
Here, of course, we should reemphasize that we cannot speak of the world, of its
when content is given that a monad can appear as a spatial-temporal center -- i.e., as
there is only the abstract form of temporal synthesis. For Husserl, this form is
particularized through a particular content. Since this content has factual character, the
particular monad which can result must be contingent. So must the world and its
contents through time. In other words, we need the self-surpassing (or "self-
modification") of the nunc stans since this, as we said, is the "engine" of the temporal
of experience, it can result in the monad in the horizonality of its experiential being. It,
thus, can be said to ground its implication of Others through such horizonality. Yet the
very sense of this horizonality implies contingency. It must, if it is based on the self-
surpassing which generates new moments. Each such moment, insofar as it surpasses the
previous apperances of the nunc stans, represents, we asserted, "a new stage for settling
the world's accounts" (See above, ). It represents a newness which surpasses and
Having said this, we must add that this newness which puts the world at risk is
not, ultimately, a sign of the moment's independence. Qua content laden, its factual
character does point to its independence vis-a-vis the past -- i.e., its not being completely
determined by the content of what has already been given. But this independence is
Notes
480
whole of time. Qua content-laden, it is dependent on that "full" absolute which includes
both time and content. Thus, its content filled presence surpasses the already constituted
because it is the manifestation of Husserl's absolute present, the present in which "there
'lies' all time and world in every sense" (Ms. CI, Sept. 21-22, 1932; HA XV, p. 668). In
other words, each content-filled appearance of the absolute surpasses what has been by
being a partial manifestation of all that has ever been or will be. The full manifestation
of the absolute present is nothing less than the world horizon understood as an "all-sided,
infinite, filled horizon of time." The fact that the moment cannot be without this horizon
and yet can disrupt it, points to this horizon's all inclusive character. It is a character
which includes the possibilty of its own dissolution through the very moments which
actualize it. This, as we shall see, involves a corresponding possibility for the monads
who collectively actualize the world horizon. The possibilities of the horizon include the
§7. The Rational and Theological Aspects of the Individual's Relation to Temporal
Constitution
Before we take up the theme of this disruption, two further items need to be
considered: Husserl's positions on reason and God, the latter being taken as reason's
sensations does not form a horizon. Our experiences, we said, are horizonally ordered
when they manifest an underlying unity. Since the latter is the sense of the posited
object, horizonality and positing are correlative notions. The same point holds for the
world-horizon. Our experience of the latter is correlated to our positing the world's
underlying sense or "ideal unity." Each object is "of" the world insofar as its own unity
Notes
481
fits into that of the world. Our perceptions are "worldly" insofar as they posit being as
being-in-the-world. They are "worldly" when they include the sense of the world in the
senses of their particular objects. As Husserl writes, this implies that "every worldly
(Ms. B III 4, p. 39a, Dec. 1932). All-temporality is required because the whole of time is
required to manifest the sense of the world. In itself, the world "... is nothing but the idea
of the infinitely extended, harmonious totality of all experiences, of all momentary living
presents, of all [such subjective presents] that are presently actual or were actual or will
in the future be actual, and of all the possible experiences indicated as co-valid in these
positing act is an "act of reason." As we cited Husserl, "... 'truly existing object' and
'object capable of being rationally posited' are equivalent correlates" (Ideen I, Biemel ed.,
p. 349). At the basis of this equivalence is the fact that positing is essentially a "making
sense" of our experiences. It is a grasping of their one-in-many character where the unity
stands for the one thing of which we are having many experiences. Here, the laws by
which we grasp this unity in multiplicity are taken as the "rational" laws -- i.e., those of
these laws, that of non-contradiction. It states that the same thing cannot, in the same
sense, be and not be. If we take being as being present in time, we can see how this law
may be reinterpreted in terms of the intentionalities constituting the temporal field. Such
intentionalities do not just place contents within self-identical moments, they also unify
these contents into the persisting presence of self-identical objects. Furthermore, they
result in our own identical presence. They help give each of us a distinct "here" and
our objects could both be and not be in the same objective, worldly sense is to disregard
the temporal intentionalities which help establish this sense. It is to assert that such
intentionalities are and are not operative in some specific instance. With this, we can
make the more general point that the formal or "analytic" laws of rationality can be
reinterpreted as laws of positing and the latter can be understood as laws of temporal
synthesis. Here, the a priori character of the formal logical law finds its roots in the a
priori character of such synthesis -- i.e., in the fact that such synthesis must obtain if a
real object is to be given; this, no matter what the object's particular character. Thus, the
universality of the logical law follows once we reinterpret it in terms of the diagonal and
vertical intentionalities which unify our consciousness, the intentionalities which "make
sense" out of our experiences by providing the temporal basis for the positing of an
object as a one-in-many.13
dependence of the moment, they give the necessary conditions for temporalization, thus
grounding the horizonal structure of the world. In serving as the basis for the underying
unity correlated to this structure, they also ground the world's rationality. Thus, given
the equivalence between rationality and positing, the factthat time is inherently synthetic
-- i.e., inherently directed towards positing -- means that it is inherently directed towards
rationality.
developmental motivation" (Ms. E III 4, pp. 28-29, 1934). This is our motivation to
make sense of our experience, i.e., to posit its underlying unity. Behind such motivation
is the fact that we "live in a universal teleological temporality, one in which an inherent
teleological causality has its form ..." (Ms. K III 4, p. 45, 1934-35). The form springs
from the dependence of the moment, a dependence which always links the moment to a
Notes
483
greater whole. The resulting teleological causality is manifested by every whole of time
as it functions as a not-yet for the moments which are its parts. Each moment, in its
dependence, is "of" this greater whole; each is also "of" the object which is synthesized
through the intentionalities springing from this same dependence. The object, then, is
not just a goal of this synthesis. Through its temporal form, it is also its ground. It is a
not-yet which, in a certain sense, "motivates" its own positing. The same thing can be
said about the whole of time and, indeed, about its correlate: the world. To assert that
claim that we are temporally motivated to posit the world's ideal or "rational" unity.
When we speak simply of our motivation, we do not fully capture what Husserl
has in mind. The "teleological temporality" which motivates us to posit the world is also
that which grounds us as positing subjects. Expressed in terms of the correlation between
horizonality and rationality, this means that the temporal grounding of subjects as
the existing world -- is also their grounding as subjects who appear to bear and validate
horizonally grounded, we must also say that it is rationally grounded, both forms of
grounding being ultimately traced to time. In each case, we have an example of the
"teleological causality" of the world -- this, through the temporalization which gives rise
to the world. Let us put this in terms of the equivalence of rationality and positing. For
Husserl, such equivalence signifies that "the world in general (Überhaupt) ... has, in
essential necessity, the form of the logos, of true being ..." This "logos" is the world's
ideal rational unity which is also its "true" posited being. The teleological causality of
the world allows Husserl to fill this out by adding: "In order that there can be the world
and the subjectivity constituting it (the world ... that has ... the form of the logos ...), the
world must, preceding from pre-being to being, also constitute rational persons within
Notes
484
itself. Reason must already exist and must be able to bring itself to a logical [rational]
The point of this passage extends beyond the simple conclusion that world-
constitution, as an affair of reason, requires the presence of rational subjects. Given that
constitution occurs in and through subjects, the self-constitution of the world must
include the constitution of subject as the means through which it can proceed. The
implicit point of this passage is that this relation is teleological. We can put this in terms
of our assertion that the world-horizon grounds both the being and validity of our
experiences and yet is, itself, made actual by such experiences. Here, the same point is
implicitly being made about the world's "logos" -- i.e., the ideal unity which links our
experiences into a world horizon. This logos brings itself about through the positing
activities of individual subjects; and these are subjects which come to be as elements of
its own self-constitution. On the one hand, we must say that "transcendental subjectivity
brings about its own sense of being and that of every worldly reality to the level of the
logos" (Ms. E III 4, p. 31, 1934). On the other hand, we must also claim: "the
part of logical self-constitution ..." In other words, "the logos of the constitution of the
logos includes itself ...," i.e., includes its self-constitution through the rational agency of
Such agency, we can say, is grounded by reason, but grounded by it as its not-yet.
Here, the ongoing constitution of the world's logos is matched by the progressive
development of our reason. To bring our own rational development to the level of the
The lower stage [of rational development] does not yet know anything of the future
stage, the stage which will become intentional on the basis of its intending [i.e., the
Notes
485
intending springing from the lower stage]. Its becoming, however, is a coming to be
which is directed towards reason. Naturally, it does not have any knowledge of true
being. This is the accomplishment of the reason that has [already] come to be. Yet,
precisely the ego which I am in accomplishing this, the ego which I apodictically am and
which I am in my human community, exhibits a coherence in its development, a
development which is necessarily proceeding towards reason. ... Being does not exist
before "human beings" and their reason. It exists rather in and through them. And yet it
does exist in its preliminary stages as the pre-rational becoming rational -- in the course
of which, however, reason is presupposed as existing, as "constituting after the fact"
("nachkonstituierend") both true being as pre-rational and the development [of such pre-
rationall being] through already existing reason. Reason, as ultimately constituting
being, as constituting in an ultimate sense the being of all relativities of being [i.e., of all
relatively "true" beings], is in a way beyond all being. Yet it is, in itself, a level of being,
a level which is "recognized" through already existing reason (Ibid., p. 29).
person and the particular rational world which confronts him. Such a person is, of
course, a member of a "human community" and his world in its full sense is a result of a
collective positing. When Husserl asserts that reason is "beyond all being," he thus
means that it is beyond all constituted being -- i.e., beyond the developmental stages of
our human being and those of the world we posit. Here, it appears as the ground and the
This relation between the ground and the goal is, of course, ultimately temporal.
consciousness of the monad. By virtue of the temporal intentionalties which underlie the
passive constitution of its unity, this consciousness is inherently positing. Its grounding
is such that it "must constitute beings" (Ms. K III I, viii, p. 4, 1935). Thus, given the
its passive synthesis, posit a world which objectifies the rational laws of temporal
synthesis. This, of course, is only half the story. Rationality is not just a matter of
passive synthesis. As involving the correction and harmonization of the elements of our
passively given world, it requires active synthesis (See Ms. B III 7, p. 2, 1933). To
understand this, it is necessary to turn to the nunc stans which is the ultimate ground of
consciousness, the acting ego has a point of identity with the nunc stans. The individual
manifests this identity in his finite freedom -- i.e., in his confronting alterantive
possibilities. Such freedom, we can say, moves him beyond his already constituted
world (on the lowest level, the world of passive synthesis) and allows him to question it.
In other words, by virtue of his freedom, the subject does not just stand in a "this" world
-- a world with no possible alternatives. He can pose the question: "Why this rather than
that?" he can ask why the world is as it appears --i.e., what is the reason for its appearing
as it does?15
Temporality, thus, brings about a double grounding of the ego. It results in the
ego as a center of passive synthesis -- a synthesis which is correlated to its being a center.
It also results in the ego as an active synthesizer. Here, the subject, in its central
egological being, acts out of the freedom which manifests his identity with his ground.
For Husserl, this double grounding allows us to say "passivity [is] always there, always
present as a basis (Grundlage) for freedom ..." It also allows us to assert that the subject,
in his identity with his surpassing ground, surpasses this basis. In Husserl's words, "...
every person is per se autonomous. He freely chooses and decides in a way that
surpasses (überschreitet) the present ..." (Ms. E III 4, p. 23). As a fresh positing, this
surpassing which constitutes reason in its further development in humanity and its
posited world.
reason" (Ibid.) This co-development of our reason and freedom -- i.e., "autonomy" --
follows from the fact that both are grounded in the absolute whose temporal aspect is the
nunc stans. The absolute manifests itself in both our freedom and reason; hence, they
both manifst the identity of ground and goal which is inherent in the absolute's self-
reason which unfolds itself in freedom and reason. They are goals of this development
and are also means for achieving their own realization in us. To cite Husserl again:
Interpreting Husserl, we can say that just as "reason functions in freedom," so freedom
functions in reason. Thus, we cannot be free and be the slaves of ignorance, of irrational
fears and prejudices. The latter bind us to a given world -- a "this" world -- just as surely
Notes
488
as impenetrable physical barriers do. To reverse this, reason functions in freedom insofar
as the latter is the very possibility of questioning this world. Freedom is present from the
start as our possibility to surpass the given and, hence, to question why this world --
initially our practical, every day world -- should be given rather than one of its
alternatives.
To move to a deeper level of analysis, we can say that "the universal being"
mentioned by the passage is that of the world which includes both our freedom and
reason. This world is the objectification of Husserl's absolute, and a number of points
can be drawn from this. The first follows from the absolute's status as our ground and
our goal. Since the absolute manifests itself in freedom and reason, both must be present
from the start. In other words, just as we must already be free to move toward freedom,
so from the beginning, reason grounds its own development. As Husserl writes
concerning reason:
From the beginning, man has knowledge of the world; but in possessing this
knowledge, he must first acquire it -- a telos situated at infinity -- through infinite
work. From the beginning, man is a rational being. From the beginning, he has
reason, but first he must, in the course of his history (in the levels of his historical
modes of being, in his historicity), acquire reason. From the beginning, he is
human and must become human (Ms. E III 10, p. 19, 1934).
The phrase, "from the beginning," refers to our ground -- i.e., to the absolute whose self-
objectification gives us both our passively constituted world and the freedom to develop
and explicate its rational structure. The mention of "infinite work" also points to the
absolute -- this time, however, in its being projected forward as our goal. It refers to a
world and a "knowledge of the world" which would correspond to a full manifestation of
the absolute.
Notes
489
Our second point stems from the fact that the whole of time is required for this
manifestation. This means that the goal is infinitely distant. In Husserl's words:
This teleological ideal, "world," i.e., transcendentally [regarded], this ideal of the
concretely constituting transcendental subjectivity, is not and never will be
temporally given in the sense that a factual, transcendental subjectivity is. It is an
idea, indeed, the idea of an "absolutely perfect" intersubjective community, a
community which does take its origin from us, but one lying completely and
totally at infinity (Ms. E III 1, p. 4, 1931).
As Husserl also expresses this: To both the "streaming, self-confirming world" and its
super-transcendental subjective sense. This is the absolute logos ... lying beyond them
[i.e., beyond both the world and its subjects] as an infinitely distant pole" (Ms. E III 4,
pp. 60-61). As already indicated, such an ideal is that of the full objectification of the
absolute which contains "all time and world in every sense." It is an ideal embracing the
rational unity of the world -- i.e., its logos -- and the rational subjects through which this
The intersubjective character of this ideal leads to our third point. It is that I
imply Others in my rationality. Here, the implication is the same as that which we
considered in discussing the notion of horizon. The world horizon implies Others as
correlates to its infinitude. Since this infinitude is also that of the logos manifested by
the world horizon, the same implication can be drawn from the latter. Other, fellow co-
workers in reason are implied by the notion of the logos since its being "situated at
infinity" means that it can only be realized through an open ended plurality of rationally
"specifically human" telos -- is that which I strive to realize as a rational animal -- and
this telos is, then, my being directed to the open ended community in and through which
it is realized. In other words, to say that "man is already pre-given to himself as man, as
universal horizon, one in which all the co-monads are always implicit" (Ms. A V 20, p. 3,
1934). This horizon is that of reason disclosing itself in rational subjects. Grounded in
reason, such subjects imply Others in their manifesting reason. This cannot be otherwise,
given that the freedom in which reason functions itself implies a plurality of results (See
above, ).
Husserl calls the "absolute logos," taken as a "polar idea," "the one, the true and
the good." "In the striving which encompasses each and every being," it is "that towards
which all finite being is directed; [it is] that towards which all transcendental subjective
being lives as living being, as the being which constitutes truth" (Ms. E III 4, p. 61,
1934). He ascribes to this telos "a surpassing reality (Ueberrealität), a surpassing truth, a
surpassing actuality, a surpassing in-itselfness which first gives true sense to all relative
finite being and all transcendental monadic being" (Ibid., p. 62). He does not stop here,
but identifies this telos with God. Thus, in another manuscript, we read: "God, himself,
is not the monadic totality. He is rather the entelechy lying within it; this, as the infinite
telos of the development of 'mankind' from absolute reason, as the telos necessarily
regulating monadic being and regulating it from its free decisions" (Ms. A V 22, p. 46,
Jan. 1931).
This identification of God with the logos is not just a feature of Husserl's later
philosophy. As Stephen Strasser has written, "Throughout his whole life, both as a
person and a philosopher, Husserl contended with the problem of God."17 Thus, as early
as 1911, he identifies the "idea" of God with that of a telos of "the most perfect
Notes
491
[intersubjective] life in which the most perfect world constitutes itself ..." (Ms. F I 14, p.
43). This view of God develops in parallel with the doctrine of the logos. Indeed, some
A few examples will bring this out. As we cited Husserl, the logos "is beyond all
being and yet is a level of being." Itself unchanging, it requires individual subjects for its
subjects in order to be present as the constituted, rational unity of the world. A similar
point is made about God. Our striving to constitutively bring about the logos is called
The universal, absolute will which lives in all the transcendental subjects and which
makes possible the individual, concrete being of the transcendental totality of subjectivity
is the divine will. This, however, presupposes the whole of intersubjectivity -- not that
this precedes this will, not that this will is impossible without this whole (in the way that
the soul, perhaps, presupposes the living body); rather [it presupposes it] as a structural
level without which this will cannot be made concrete (Ms. E III 9, Nov. 5, 1931; HA
XV, 381, italics added).
rationally constituting subjects. In other words, God achieves his worldly presence
through his "promoting a separation [of himself] into a plurality of individual, unitary
reason or the logos becomes aware of itself through the activities of individual subjects.
In them, reason exists as "a level of being." Constituting and explicating the results of
Notes
492
their constitution, such subjects are not separate from reason itself. Because of this, they
confront the objective presence of reason in one another -- i.e., in their explications (See
Ms. E III 4, p. 27). Similarly, God's objective understanding occurs through us "because
we cognizing humans (erkennende Menschen) are, indeed, egos into which the absolute
ego has split itself ..." (Ms. F I 22, p. 22, Nov. 1917). This means that "God ... is the
eternal, unchanging, uniquely singular being who reveals himself in the ego, and this
implies ... He reflects himsellf, He creates an image (Abild) of himself in the form of a
consciousness, an image which, however, is not separated from God himself" (Ms. F I
22, p. 37). Since individuals are not separate from God, they become the means of his
objective self-consciousness:
God, the absolute being, who is inherently unchanging, who, himself, does not become,
in eternal necessity reveals himself in the form of a pure ego. He, thus, externalizes
himself in an infinite series of self-reflections in which He depicts (abildet) himself in
himself as the formations of consciousness. [He does this] first in an obscure form and
then with increasing purity and lack of concealment, ultimately coming to the purest self-
consciousness. In the process of this development, He splits himself, as it were, into a
plurality of finite human subjects. His freedom, the freedom of his absolute self-
determination, becomes their personal freedom (Ms. F I 22, p. 39). 19
The last three quotes are from Husserl's lectures on Fichte's Menschenheitsideal.
As such, they are part of Husserl's exposition of Fichte's position. Yet, in an appendix to
determined to become a strict theory in the future" (Ms. F I 22, p. 61). With respect to
Husserl's own career, we can say that it forms a leading idea, what Husserl calls a
In the 1930's, this development culminates in the doctrine of the "total absolute."
In a certain sense, Husserl's doctrines of God, freedom, rationality and horizonality are
Notes
493
just different ways of expressing the latter. They all ultimately concern the absolute
which, as "total," grounds both time and its sensuous content. Taken as the goal of its
change insofar as it grounds the development of subjects, the very subjects in and
The temporal component of this absolute is the nunc stans. God, taken as the
nowness by virtue of which each subject is a subject. Thus, as such nowness, God acts in
subjects through the temporal "letting loose" of their acts. He also constitutes the
indivdiual being of subjects by grounding their being as central egos -- i.e., their being as
"split himself" into a pluality of functioning subjects. Here, the original identity between
God and his "reflections" -- i.e., the identity which allows us to say that He is "not
separate" from the latter -- is that of nowness per se. The same point can be made about
the claim God's freedom becomes our "personal freedom." As we said, the root of this
freedom is the surpassing quality of the nowness at the core of our being. This quality
points to the totality of the possibilities pre-objectively present in our anonymous, central
Our teleological relation to God can also be traced to Husserl's "total absolute," in
particular, to its being our ground and our goal. In the following, somewhat obscure
pole":
I with the Others. There are [other] egological subjects, and I am these subjects. Ahead
of them, objectifying them and myself, I [am] the ego pole of [objectifying] acts. I live
directed towards the world and directed towards them as worldly [Others]. I [am] with
them as a pole of life, as a co-accomplisher of objectivities, of the [temporal] streaming.
Notes
494
We [are] never satisfied as goal-directed, as directed in our aiming at relatively finite
goals, as driven beyond such supposedly final goals ... A higher level reflection and a
new aiming (Zielung) beyond all [finite] worldly goals: a free self-determination from
self-understanding and the understanding of humanity, from the understanding of the
absolute as being [present] in all I and we. "Teleology" discovers that God speaks in us.
God speaks in the evidences of the decisions, in the modes of infinity which [course]
through all finite worldliness. I exist -- am on the way (Wege). Where does the path
(Weg) lead? What is my way? My way to the infinite which, at every stage, bears
witness to me that here I am proceeding rightly and, at every false step, witnesses that
here I am proceeding blindly and in error. Here, I am doing my thing -- what is my
concern (Sache); here, I am not. All the right paths lead to myself, but to me through my
co-egos, my co-egos with whom I am inseparately myself, am inseparately this ego.
They lead to God who is nothing other than the pole. The path, beginning with each ego,
proceeds as his path (the ego who begins with me is another ego; just as I, who begin
with him, am another ego); but all these ways lead to God, the same super-worldly
(überweltlich), super-human pole; this, not as separate ways, converging at a point [in the
future], but rather in an indescribable intermingling (Ms. K III 2, pp. 105-06, 1934).
The philosophical doctrine which informs this meditation should be familiar. At its heart
is Husserl's position on the duality of our essence. One part of our essence allows
Husserl to say: "The ego is super-temporal (überzeitlich). It is the pole of the modes of
the egological relations to the temporal" (Ms. E III 2, p. 50, 1934). In other words, when
considered as identical with its ground, "This ego is the only one in an absolute sense. It
does not allow of being meaningfully multiplied. Put more pointedly, it excludes this as
senseless. The implication is: the surpassing being (übersein) of the ego is nothing more
existents (or 'worlds') ..." (Ms. B IV 5, 1932 or 1933; HA XV, 590). Thus, each subject,
identified with the nowness at his core, can claim to objectify both himself and Others.
His action, however, is not his own in any individual sense. As springing from a "super-
temporal" pole, it is rather the action of a common ground. It is the action of the
Notes
495
absolute which is in every "absolute I and we," this being God conceived of as a "super-
teleological character to each ego's constitution. Each ego's "path" begins with God and
has God as its ultimate, ideal terminus because of the identity of ground and goal
exhibited by this temporalization. Thus, God can be taken as the content filled nowness
out of which each ego's path is constituted. He can also be conceived as the goal of
egological paths in their "indescribable intermingling." All the "right paths" lead to God
insofar as they work together to objectively exhibit the pre-objective content of such
nowness.
of ground and goal, the notion of a common ground leads to that of a common goal. If
the ground is non-temporal in the sense of being beyond time -- überzeitlich -- then so is
the goal. The latter is beyond what can be realized in any finite time. The same
inference holds when we say that the action of the "super-temporal" ground is prior, not
humanity "throughout its generations." As we cited Husserl, "the unity of [the ground's]
towards this infinitely distant goal (Ms. E III 4, pp. 28-29). The same inference holds
with regard to the content of this goal. If we assert that the ground pre-objectively
expresses the totality of human possibilities, then this is what humanity strives to realize
in its objective development. Thus, to say that "the absolute totality of monads, or the
totality of monadic primordiality, exists only from temporalization" is also to assert that
"the totality of monadic being exists as being-in-horizonality and [that] infinity pertains
Notes
496
to this -- infinite potentiality, infinite streaming implying the infinities of the stream,
infinity, and iteration of potentialities" (Ms. C I, Sept. 21-22, 1934; HA XV, 670). The
"infinity" refers to the streaming away of the whole of time, an "infinite streaming"
which is required to express the ground of time. The "infinite potentiality" and "iteration
of potentialities" refer to the possibillities inherent in our ground. Their realization is the
goal of the development which increases and actualizes our own potentialities.
To put this in terms of freedom is to say that the freedom inherent in our ground
becomes concretely realized in the development which progressively opens up new ways
of being and behaving for humanity. By this we mean a development which increases
God's freedom can be said to progressively become our own insofar as the possibilities
which form its content begin to define our own possibilities. Freedom, of course, is not
just the choice between alternatives. As action within a teleological context, it has its
specific temporal form. So conceived, its ground is the nowness which inherently
directed towards synthesis. The "primal form" of such temporalization -- and, hence of
synthesis -- is that of what-will-be determining what is. This, however, is the form of the
with the fact that God is both the ground and the goal of our freedom, the following
claim emerges: when freedom is properly directed -- i.e., when it takes as its task the
explication of its ground -- then "God speaks to us in the evidence of our decisions." In
other words, in expressing its ground, human freedom is a freedom for the manifestation
another feature of freedom -- that of the rationality evinced in positing and correcting our
positions so that they can come together to synthetically constitute the world. The
Notes
497
implication, here, is that an improperly directed freedom is one that has cut itself off
from rationality.
Dupré, for example, focuses on the fact that God requires individual subjects for his
"No theism, however, could accept a God who is identical with transcendental
subjectivity or even one who needs it as an essential part of himself. From this point of
view, Husserl's later philosophy is perhaps even further removed from a true
transcendence than his earlier. A strange observation in view of the fact that his personal
convictions became increasingly theistic!" ("Husserl's Thoughts on God and Faith," PPR
XXIX, Dec. 1968, p. 212). Stephen Strasser, on the other hand, focuses on the fact that
God is the "entelechy" of the monad-all. He is the infinitely distant goal of monadic
development. For Strasser, "... God is the principle of development who does not
who forms the absolute idea of a pole [or goal] for developing human reason must
possess an objective being, i.e., one independent of subjective reason" (Ibid., p. 139).
From our perspective, we can say that both interpretations are one-sided; that is,
each emphasizes only half of the relation between God and subjects. To focus on God as
the ground of subjects makes Husserl's position appear pantheistic. God is everywhere
subjects are. Similarly, to focus on Husserl's assertions that God is a goal situated "at
infinity" makes his position appear theistic -- this, at least insofar as it emphasizes the
transcendence which most theistic thinkers ascribe to God. The first focus is Dupre's; the
second Strasser's. For Husserl, however, God is both the ground and goal of subjects.
Notes
498
with subjects. This follows since his transcendence as their goal is also his transcendence
as their ground. As we stressed, the goal is not something which can be realized by any
finite totality of subjects in any finite time. To put this in terms of the ground, we can
say that it, too, surpasses its manifestation by any finitely evolving subjective totality.
The ground's "absolute" status implies that it is capable of grounding, not just the
presently existing totality of subjects, but every possible totality; and this implies that no
finite subjective totality is equivalent to this ground. Thus, when Husserl writes that "the
possible expressions of its ground. Its contingency is its lack of identity with the latter,
i.e., its not being an objective exprsession which is equivalent to its all-embracing and,
As we earlier noted, contingency embraces both the nature -- the "Sosein" -- and
the existence -- the "Dasein" -- of objectively given subjects. Subjects could be other
than what they are. They could also not be. The second follows because subjects
achieve their objective presence by departing from the nowness which is the "to be" of
their being. In Husserl's words, each subject must say, "Present, I exist in continuous
dying as something present ..." (See above, ). This dying is a dying away of the
moments that make up a life. Our worldly life is contingent since the constituting
nowness which results in its objective Dasein is distinct from this. 24 When, with
Husserl, we identify God with such nowness, he cannot be identified with such Dasein.
It is easy to see how facticity and teleology come together in Husserl's thought.
being. Such positing is inherently presumptive -- i.e., factual and fragile. As we cited
Notes
499
Husserl, "... no rational positing is equivalent to the straightforward assertion: 'the thing
is actual' ..., this, in an "incontrovertible" sense (Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 339). This
follows from the distinction of the thing and its appearances. Although its "positing is
rationally motivated only through the appearances (the incompletely filled perceptual
sense)," the thing is not the appearances which motivate its positing (Ibid.). As their
the rational, logical forms which are "transcendentally reinterpreted" as the forms of the
connections which obtain between appearances and which permit positing. Thus, the
thesis of their underlying unity -- the X which is not an appearance -- allows us to say
that the thing is the same in different appearances; but it also makes us say that the
appearances, as not equivalent to the thing, can never finally (or "incontrovertibly")
We can also express this non-equivalence in terms of the fact that appearances are
connected in time. Because of this, the forms of unification are forms of temporal
synthesis; they are forms which establish the unity of a thing as an ongoing, temporal
unity. This is a unity which is actual only in its passage "from present to present." Its
positing as actual thus requires this passage; in other words, it requires its further
appearing. Given this, its actually "can only 'inadequately' appear with an appearance
which is [temporally] finite or limited (Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 339). In other words, its
With this, the theme of teleology appears; for the presumptiveness or facticitiy of
embodied -- i.e., as part of constituted existence -- reason is not given before constitution
or even, in a final sense, with the presence of the ongoing process of constitution. This
Notes
500
follows since its incontrovertible givenness as a structure of "true being" requires the
same "infinite process of appearing" that this "being" does. It is, in other words, the
terminus ad quem, not the terminus a quo of the constitutive process. Thus, if reason or
the logos does determine the constitutive process, it must determine it as a goal -- as a
"term towards which" the process proceeds and not as something given in any final sense.
Husserl expresses this point by saying, "Because the rationality which facticitiy
actualizes is not such as the essence demands, in all this there lies a wonderful teleology"
(Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 139). The essence cannot "demand" such actualization since, as
the rational structure of being, its own incontrovertible givenness is the terminus ad
There is, then, no contradiction in our asserting that the telos or goal of world-
constitution is the concrete embodiment of reason and that, all the same, this
embodiment, at any given time, is controvertible. Viewed in terms of what Husserl calls
"the fact of the world" -- the world as presently posited from already given experience --
one can, indeed, conceive of reason's ending along with this fact. The contingency of the
world -- the possibility that it could be otherwise, that it could, perhaps, even not be -- is
also the contingency of the rationality it embodies. This possibility is also that of the
reduction. The reduction is the suspension of reason taken as the form of the connections
the suspension of reason -- i.e., its end in the realm of constituted existence.
We can uncover the inner connection between facticity and teleology by turning
to their temporal root. The ultimate principle here is the distinction between the ground
and the grounded. Temporally, this appears as the distinction between the nunc stans and
the successive moments which form its appearances. To derive facticity from this
distinction is to note that from the perspective of such moments, being constantly now is
being constantly new. What remains now constantly occupies a new position within
Notes
501
successive time. Thus, the nunc stans appears in time as the flowing or streaming now,
the now whose essential characteristic is facticity. As we said, facts are contingent; their
very meaning as facts is that they could be otherwise. In its streaming, the now which
ever new, ever lapsing into pastness, constantly transcending itself and, hence, constantly
other than itself. As such, it is the pure form of the factual in its contingency.
endured through a whole series of past nows, the newness of each coming moment
formally involves the possibilty of its otherness, i.e., its contingency (See
above, ). Such newness, then, is facticity in its temporal root. Its pure temporal
form is that of the nunc stans which appears constantly new, constantly transcending the
positions of the time that is becoming past even as the nunc stans objectifies itself as a
remaining constantly now and, thus, of slipping away from any fixing or objectification
of it in a definite temporal position. Given this, we can define the temporal origin of
facticity as the placing and, hence, the escape from place of the nunc stans in successive
time. The nunc stans, of course, is what places itself in time. Its relation to its
we confront here is the grounding of constituted existence in both its facticity and
teleological structure. This point may be put by recalling the reason why the nunc stans
cannot appear in time without surpassing its appearances. The reason is its constant
nowness; but this means that it transcends its momentary appearance because it is always
more than this appearance. It is, per se, the original identity of all its appearances -- i.e.,
of all the momentary presents. As we cited Husserl, "all the temporal modes" -- all the
Notes
502
moments composing past present and future -- "are already present" within it. It is their
identity as manifesting nowness or original presence. They manifest the latter insofar as
they are appearances of the nunc stans, and they are such appearances through the
nowness of their existence within the nunc stans. Since such original presence is before
the "apartness" of extended time, such moments, thought of as existing within the nunc
stans, can also be thought of as existing in essential coincidence with one another. For
Husserl, they dwell within it "non-independently." Thus, when the nunc stans places
itself in time, its appearance as a temporal moment must manifest this lack of
future and retain the past. This follows since it only exists as an appearance of the nunc
stans; and the later is an original identity which can only show itself as such through the
dependence of its appearances. To reverse this, we can say that, as dependent, the
momentary appearance can be only by transcending itself and becoming part of a greater
whole.
The result of this is not just the constant self-transcendence of the nunc stans as it
appears in time and, hence, the facticity of the givenness which is constituted through
this process. The argument which proceeds from the original identity of moments to the
dependence of each appearing moment also leads to the teleological structuring of such
givenness. In other words, the dependence of the moment grounds both the "fact of the
world" in its facticity and the inherent movement of this fact towards the "ideal unity" of
the world. It gives us the intentionalities which unify time and structure its process. The
goal of the process is the realization in time of the interdependent totality of moments
which, atemporally, is already present in the nunc stans. We, thus, have the horizonal
Given that this process is teleological, facticity itself is teleological. For Husserl,
to affirm the facticity of the world -- i.e., its "could have been otherwise" -- is also to
affirm its becoming other than what it is. It is to affirm that the process of such
which embodies the logos or reason. Since teleology and facticity have the same root,
we can reverse the order of these assertions. We can say that to affirm teleology is also
to affirm facticity. Here, we assert that the world's teleological becoming involves risk.
Its becoming other than what it is could lead to its dissolution. This follows since the
basis of both is, ultimately, the distinction of the constituting from the constituted. It is
the distinction between the nunc stans and the moments which exemplify its original
identity through their multiplicity and mutual dependence. Resulting in newness, this
There are a number of ways we can express the significance of the above. The
first is to note that Husserl can ask: "Can reason begin or end in constituted existence?
Can the constitutive process which it has ultimately, spontaneously set at work be in
vain?" He answers these questions by asking: "Can it be otherwise than that reason is
super-temporally and all-temporally at work ...?" (Ms. E III 4, p. 30, 1934), all the while
subjects" -- is contingent (Ms. K III 12, p. 39, 1935). Its contingency is part of "the fact
of the world," this even though the world's becoming is structured by the reason "at
work" within it. We can also express this theologically, an expression which involves the
issue of our freedom. Husserl can affirm that God is always at work, that God "speaks in
the evidence of the decisions" of individual monads and that He regulates monadic being
through "its free decisions". Yet this does not prevent the possibilty of the withdrawal of
God. Such a withdrawal can be brought about by our turning away from God -- i.e.,
from the "proper paths" leading to him. This is also a possibility of our "free decisions."
Notes
504
It follows from the nature of our freedom which is our ability to surpass the already
given. As such, it has its temporal root in the surpassing quality of the nunc stans. By
virtue of this grounding, it has its teleological character. The same quality, however, also
gives it its factual, contingency character. Thus, on the one hand, we have the
potentialities. On the other hand, we have the fact that freedom, as the means of its own
development, can turn on itself. Its contingent character signifies that its progressive
advance is not pre-given; it implies that freedom can serve as the means for its regress; it
can suppress itself and even "end" in the realm of constituted existence. *
To speak of the temporal root of this last possibility is to give only half the
picture. Its full context is provided by the formal equivalence of the two aspects of the
absolute: time and content. As an alphabet, the absolute is the totality of contents in a
pre-objective sense. It is such contents before they are synthesized (or "spelled out") into
objective unities. An equivalent assertion holds with regard to the absolute's temporal
aspect. Pre-objectively, the absolute is the totality of moments. As the nunc stans, it is
time's moments before they successively appear in synthesis. The upshot is that time and
content are equally features of the absolute's surpassing quality; indeed, the surpassing
quality of the nunc stans is formally equivalent to that of the alphabet. In both cases, a
determination by the whole -- i.e., by the possibilities of all that can ever be -- surpasses
the determination by the part which has already occurred. As we earlier put this, the
surpassing quality of the absolute follows from its being the possibility of all the
possibilities involving the synthesis of time and content. The absolute, then, may be
called a "fact," but it is not factual in the sense of being contingent. In Husserl's words,
its "fact is not one of the possibilities among which another could just as well be. The
'just as well' concerns only the 'subjective decision' of subjectivity in its state of finite
Notes
505
clarity and in relation to its factual horizon" (Ms. K III 12, p. 41, 1935). Since the
absolute does embrace every possible factual horizon, it cannot be otherwise. It includes
the possibilities of what is given and what could have been given -- i.e., the alternatives
to the given -- and, hence, is characterized as "lying at the basis of all possibilities" (Ms.
C I, Sept. 21-22, 1934, HA XV, p. 669). It thus includes all the possibilities of our
Such possibilities can be seen as "regulating monadic being ... from its free
decisions" (Ms. A V22, p. 46, 1931). Yet, they can also be seen as including the
posssibility of its collapse. Thus, the possibilities of the absolute regulate our being by
appearing as the possibilities of our finite freedom. They are the possibilities which we
confront in our "finite clarity." One of these possibilities does directly involve the
collapse of monadic being. As experience shows, individuals can choose to end their
objective lives. They can commit suicide. In a certain sense, this possibility corresponds
to that of the reduction's dissolution of the connections which give us our objective
world; though here the dissolution is in fact and not just in thought. As we said, the
included in the open endedness or "infinity" of our "life horizon" (Ms. E III 9, Nov. 13,
1931; HA XV, p. 406). Somewhat prophetically, he notes that this horizon also includes
the possibility "of a universal murder of humanity, the murder of the whole of humanity"
-- this, through the action of humanity itself "if it did possess this power" (Ms. E III 4,
ca. July 1930, p. 9). Today, of course, humanity does possess this power. Within the
possibilities encompassed by its freedom is not just that of turning away from the
absolute -- i.e., of not developing its freedom through its freedom. We are also free to
Notes
506
engage in our self-destruction. If the absolute lies at the basis of our possibilities and,
hence, of our freedom, it must, therefore, be seen as grounding this terminal possibility.
practices, eliminate humanity. If we do, our freedom will have eliminated the context in
which self, Others, and the problem of their relations have an applicable sense. This
possibility of the collapse of humanity may be ranged with the possibilities which
involve its regress: the possibilities of freedom suppressing itself. Against these, we
have the possibilities of developing freedom in freedom. These are the possibilities of a
for human being and behaving. To put this in practical terms is to note that two life-
world attitudes correspond to this dichotomy. On the one side, we have tolerance; on the
other, intolerance.
The common meaning of these terms is clear; but to give them their
phenomenological sense, we must locate their meanings in the context of our discussion.
Their general framework is provided by the notion of the absolute as the possibility of all
which such possibilities are actualized. It is in and through humanity that the absolute
objectifies its possibilities. In other words, its temporal self-constitution is our own.
Another general notion determining the concepts of tolerance and intolerance is that of
the goal of this constitution. In Husserl's words, this goal is "the idea of infinite
infinitely distant. Since its realization involves the whole of time, we have "its
Let us explore this last notion further; it will lead us to a corresponding notion of
limit of a process whose stages are conceivable. 25 Here, we may take the limit of a
what it means to be human. For Husserl, our advance towards this goal is an advance
towards our "true being." It is an advance, we can say, which increases the fullness of
our being. Such fullness does not mean completion in a static sense. It does not mean,
for example, that the characteristics which are observed to pertain to humanity are to be
regarded as completely filling out the conception of being human. Since we are dealing
taken as fulfilling the notion of being human and also as an anticipation of further
potentialities for being human. According to such a conception, we can, for example,
say that the accomplishment of human speech opens up a whole range of further
possibilities -- civil society, commerce, etc. -- to the possibility of being actualized. Each
of these, when actualized (or fulfilled) in some particular way, points, in anticipation, to
towards which this horizonally structured process of anticipation and fulfillment tends. It
is also that which we ourselves bring about through our own actions. As we said, the
absolute's self-constitution is our self-constitution. This means that our goal is nothing
less than the synthetic, collective actualization of all the human possibilities inherent in
the absolute. This can also be put by saying that the full self-objectification of the
absolute as an "all embracing intersubjective community" is, itself, the goal which the
involves a recognition of the absolute. We can express this in terms of the distinction we
started with: that between the ground and the grounded. Ontologically, this is the
distinction between being as such and individual beings. The former can be defined
ontological status as a being -- my finitude -- is shown by the fact that I can actualize one
possibility of my being, i.e., can engage in a specific course of action, only by neglecting
this finitude, it is only through a plurality of subjects that possibilities can be collectively
actualized. The conclusion, here, is that my recognition of Others and their possibilities
then, is "the formation according to goals [and, hence, according to a "highest goal"] of
The equivalence of ground and goal allows us to make the same point about the
ground. Our recognition of Others and their possibilities is also a recognition of the
absolute taken as "lying at the basis of all possibilities." This point follows from the
arguments of our previous chapter where we concluded that the presence of Others is a
re-presentation of the absolute -- i.e., of the possibilities inherent in the latter. Since the
ground always contains more than the possibilities of the given existent which is its
particular re-presentation, this existent always implies more than itself. It re-presents the
words: "The fact that something is specifies, at any given time, a realm of co-
possibilities, a totality of that which can or cannot coexist with it" (Ms. E III 2, p. 2,
Notes
509
1921). This means that "beginning with the 'contingency' of the temporal position and of
the ego" occupying this position, a totality of co-possible egos can always be derived.
The totality is "one which the ego, varying its temporal position, itself traces it." Thus,
we can vary the "now" of our here. We can imagine that we are here at an earlier or later
time. We can, correspondingly, vary the "here" of our now, i.e., position our now in a
different "here" by imagining that we are now "there." The result is a view of the
horizon of the possibilities of being now -- i.e., being a temporal center of a particular,
content-filled environment (Ms. K III 2, p. 44, Oct. 10, 1935). As we said, such
recognition of this ground insofar as the first recognition is the secondary objective
component.
Once again the ultimate principle is the distinction between being and beings. An
individual being is such -- i.e., is a definitely given "what" -- by embodying one of the
possibilities whose totality points to being itself. The fact that it is not being itself makes
it contingent. Its contingency, in other words, points back to being itself as the totality of
possibilities, the very totality in terms of which it can be said to be contingent. Thus, as
is contingent signifies one of the possibilities, the very one which actually obtained" (Ms.
C I, Sept. 21-22, 1934; HA XV, p. 670). An individual entity includes this horizon "in
itself" insofar as its presence re-presents its ground. The independence of the latter -- the
fact that, as all-embracing, it could just as well have grounded something else -- is re-
Summing up, we can say that the general framework for the notion of tolerance is
one in which the absolute is both the ground and the goal of my recognition of Others.
perfect intersubjective community. Thus, it does not just provide me with my self-
transcending intentions; it also sets the goal of these intentions. Ultimately, they can
which is required for progress towards this goal. On the most basic level, it is an
openness to the possibilities of the fullness of human being, i.e., to the harmonious
realization of all the possibilities involved in such being. Husserl, in this context, speaks
of the "communalization" of the ideals of being human. This involves the mutual
affirmation of such ideals. I affirm that the Other's ideals are "mine" and he does the
same with regard to my own, though we both do this in a "mediate fashion." Thus, as
Husserl writes, I affirm "his ideals as his, as ideals which I must affirm in him, just as he
must affirm my ideals -- not, indeed, as his ideals of life but as the ideals of my being
and life" (Ms. E III 1, p. 7, 1931). The same point is made with regard to different
societies. Societies are "not egotistical" -- i.e., not intolerant -- if they can affirm one
another's "particular goals and particular accomplishments" (Ms. A V 24, p. 4, fall 1934).
harmony," a case where I can say of the Other: "his existence, his life is as if it were
mine." The "as if" signifies that love is an affirmation of the Other's existence in the
Other. As the opposite of egotism, it is not an identity of the lover and the beloved.
Rather, "it is a particular manner of empathetic congruence" (Ms. E III 2, p. 19, Jan. 1,
1935, italics added). Husserl calls a society formed from such love relationships a "love
realization of this telos (or limit) would be a community in which the intentions of
empathy were fully realized. Each would affirm his Others' existence as if it were his
own, and the objective behavior of his Others would never disappoint him. This means
that within his own primordiality he would find the possibilities which Others objectively
realize; conversely, his own accomplishments would be recognized by his fellows. Their
ideals and goals would be affirmed by him as his own, and vice versa. Such affirmation
inherent in himself whose realization stands not as his own but as another's goal.
For Husserl, the "love" animating such a community "is infinite, absolute and
universal ..." (Ms. E III 4, p. 20, July 1930). Traced to its roots, it is a love of the
absolute conceived as the totality of subjective possibilities. The early lectures on Fichte
interpret this theologically. Human love, is a "desire for the eternal" -- i.e., for God as
He is present in my neighbors (See Ms. F I 22, pp. 42, 53-54, Nov. 1917). It is actually a
love for "the eternal, unchanging, uniquely singular being who reveals himself in the
ego" (Ibid., p. 39). Insofar as God is the "entelechy" or goal of the monad-all, his
presence appears in my and my neighbor's goals. Collectively, his presence is in the goal
of "fullness." He is also, of course, the ground of our progress towards this goal. Here,
his presence is manifested in my own and my Others' freedom. God's "freedom, the
their grounding their worldly being in multiple possibilities (Ibid.). Such freedom, as we
noted at the end of our last chapter, is the ultimate object of the transfer of selfhood
whereby I take the Other as a subject like myself. It is the sine qua non of an empathetic
empathy was fully satisfied would also be a society in which God was "all in all." At this
Notes
512
relations.
all definite content. The notion of "proper ways" leading to God implies that there are
improper ways. Thus, tolerance is not an open acceptance of every possibility of human
the collective realization, the synthetic union of human possibilities. As such, only those
possibilities which do not permanently exclude other possibilities fall within its purview.
This means that, as a positive, practical ideal, it embaces as values to be realized only
certain possibilities: those which permit the actualization of further possibilities within
the horizon of being human. Those whose actualization results in harm, in the narrowing
not forbid them, it would contradict itself. It would include both teleological progression
and its opposite. It would be directed to the goal of fullness of human being and, at the
same time, embrace actions contrary to this goal's realization. If the former lead to God,
the latter lead away; they lead not to his presence, but to his withdrawal.
A few common examples will make this clear. Tolerance, understood negatively
The first, to the point that it is collectively actualized, undermines the possibility of
possibilities, such as civil society, which presuppose this possibility. Theft, when
collectively actualized, has a similar effect on the possibility of possession and, hence, on
the possibilities, such as commerce, springing from this. Insofar as lying and theft cut
off such possibilities, they result in a narrowing of human potentialities and are actually
Because of this, it is never a static notion. Within the schema of anticipation and
fulfillment, its structure at any given time is determined by the stage of our advance
promotes not progress towards our "ought to be," but rather regress. Its result is the
reduction of the possibilities actually available to us. Thus, the thief attempts to limit the
possibilities of possession to himself, cutting them off from Others. Of course, a thief
cannot remain a thief and succeed in this attempt. His action presupposes that Others
will continue to possess the goods he wants, that the possibilities of possession can
always be reinstanted. The case is quite different with intolerance in its extreme form.
Here, it appears as radical evil: the evil that strikes at the root of things. The effect of
this evil is such that it cannot be made good again; that is to say, its effect is a possibility
which is permanently foreclosed to us. Applied to the human community, its result, then,
is the permanent closing off of the possibilities of being human. Such evil may take the
form of the destruction of the historical records of a particular society; it may proceed
beyond this and include the permanent suppression of the society's native language; a
further expression of it would be the wholesale destruction of the members of the society
-- all these actions being intended to eliminate the possibilities of being and behaving
which its members manifest. As the history of our century indicates, radical evil is a
factually given, human possibility. It has actually obtained in our century's destruction of
cultures -- those, e.g., of Turkish Armenians and Eastern European Jews. It most
extreme form would be humanity's wholesale destruction through nuclear war. It would
be Husserl's "intersubjective suicide," i.e., the "murder of the whole of humanity." This
weapons, a humanity divided into two competing systems, each seeking the elimination
continuum with the more common, everyday forms of intoleance: intolerance expressed
our age, intolerance of an ethnic group can precede their destruction. It contains the
germ of radical evil insofar as it manifests the attitude that Others who think and act in a
certain way are not to be accounted as genuinely human. 27 With this attitude, not just
my relation to these Others, but also my tie to the ground of these relations is partially
severed. Such Others are not recognized as human subjects "like myself" -- which
that of the absolute with its surpassing possibilities. When empathy fails, the ground
seems to be no longer available for the action of re-presentation. Insofar as this action is
based on its presence, we can speak of intolerance as a sign of its absence -- i.e., as
The same point can be made about the absolute taken as a goal of human fullness.
Intolerance is an attempt to banish the striving towards this goal. It directs itself against
anticipations springing from these. It, thus, typically takes the form of attempting to
narrow or at least hold static the meaning of being human. In the former case, it attempts
an actual regress from the ideal of human fullness. In the latter, its attempt is to
eliminate the teleological action of this ideal as a goal. Once again, we can speak of a
partial severing of our tie with the absolute. Coincident with our non-recognition of the
Notes
515
This withdrawal of the absolute, as both our ground and goal, can, of course, be
intolerance, this being the lack of recognition which would result in our "intersubjective
suicide."
The question we face in considering the withdrawal brought about by radical evil
is that of the condition for its possibility. What, phenomenologically speaking, is its
we started with: the distinction of the ground and the grounded. Expressed as the
ontological difference between being and beings, this is a principle which is essential to
the inner connection between facticity and teleology. The dependence of the moment
which underlies facticity and teleology is, itself, an elementary expression of this
not being equivalent to being itself -- i.e., my not being the self-actualizing totality of
in embodying one possibility rather than another. As we cited Husserl, this contingency
specific this. My finitude is, thus, concretely shown by the fact that I can permanently
close off possibilities for myself. Indeed, I must since I can actualize one possibility of
as a teleological goal -- one which points to the collective, harmonious realization of all
Others.
Notes
516
Conceived as the totality of factually given subjects, we do not express the totality of
human possibilities. We are not the absolute considered as a telos since the latter
requires the whole of time to achieve its complete factual presence. Thus, the collective
being of presently given subjects is itself something finite. It has its "could have been
contingent." As not yet expressing the totality of possibilities, its subjective decisions
regarding its own development remain contingent. Its finitude is shown by the fact that it
can through its collective actions, permanently foreclose possibilities. In other words,
like the individual, it is finite in the sense that it can, through its actions, close off
possibilities for itself; though, unlike the individual, this cannot be made up by an appeal
to a greater collectivity -- i.e., Others. This follows because it, itself, is this collectivity.
the potentiality for such -- is itself the mark of the collective finitude of humanity. It is
also, we can say, the phenomenological sign that human beings do not equal being itself.
The ontological distinction between the two is shown by the fact that the possibilities
present in the absolute can be permanently lost to humanity. If the ontological difference
did not obtain, humanity could find within itself the potentiality to make good again all
those losses which have made its history calamitous. That it cannot signifies that it is not
its ground, that it can partially or even, in an ultimate catastrophy, be totally cut off from
its ground.
entirety of possibilities. It itself grounds radical evil by including even the possibility of
The attempt to completely foreclose it would involve the very foreclosing of possibilities
which it itself is. It would rather be like attempting to overcome evil by engaging in it in
Notes
517
a radical sense. The fruitlessness of this attempt can be seen in the fact that the very
possibility of such evil is also that of our finitude. It is inherent in the ontological
distinction and, thus, in the transcendence of being itself -- i.e., our ground and our goal
-- from ourselves. In other words, it is because the absolute itself, through its necessarily
finite self-objectifications, grounds the distinction between being and beings that radical
presupposes the ontological difference since, in its most general sense, it is the surpassing
possibilities which surpass those embodied in my given "this." I am free to the point that
I can surpass such given being in my choice between alternate possibilities for its
development. These possibilities form the content of my freedom; they are inherent in
the openness -- the "alphabet" -- of my ground. Projected forward, they become the
openness of my goal. The same thing may be said about the temporal presence of my
ground -- i.e., its presence as the nunc stans. Here, the ontological difference shows
itself in the distinction between my ground's constant nowness and the moments which
form its appearances. Thus, temporally speaking, the surpassing quality of freedom is a
function of the "letting loose" of new acts from this constant nowness. It is a function of
time. Such acts embody the possibilities which are inherent in my pre-objective
nowness, possibilities which surpass those which I have already realized. They can,
however, also contradict the latter. What has been "let loose" can be permanently lost
insofar as what I now bring forth does not fulfill it, but rather closes off its anticipated
horizon.
Notes
518
The content of my freedom, which is that of the presence of my ground, is also the
content of my empathy. This content gives me the transcending intentions which are
essential for the recognition of the Other and his possibilities; it allows me to affirm as
"mine" possibilities which are objectively manifested not in me, but in my Other and his
animating nowness. At its heart, such recognition transfers to the Other the openness, the
freedom, which I find in my own primordiality. So regarded, freedom is essential for the
acts of recognition which result in the web of social relationships. Yet the openness of
freedom also includes the possibility of denying such relationships -- this, through the
possibilities of being and behaving which once were within the compass of freedom.
Here, the fact that we can permanently limit our freedom, that we can foreclose the
possibilities that form its content shows that we are, as constituted entities, not our own
ground. The intolerance which does not recognize the Other and his possibilities, which,
in fact, suppresses the latter results, as we said, in the withdrawal of the ground. This is
also the withdrawal of our freedom insofar as it is the closing off of the possibilities
which form its content. That we are capable of this points once again to the distinction
of being and beings. Our freedom presupposes our finitude -- our status as a being --
i.e., the fact that the possibilities it embodies can not be and, hence, can be permanently
If we ask how freedom can deny freedom without at the same time affirming
duality of our essence -- i.e., in the fact that we are and are not the ground of our finite
being. In our identity with the openness of this ground, we can exercise the freedom
Notes
519
which results in its denial. In our otherness from the ground -- i.e., in our status as finite,
constituted realities, the freedom which we have abandoned can be permanently lost to
us. The openness of the possibilities from which we choose to constitute our "this" can,
in other words, involve a "this" which is closed to such possibilities. It can involve a
"this" which takes itself as already manifesting the totality of possibilities and, thus,
denies the possibility of recognizing alternate ways of being and behaving. Here,
finitude takes itself as infinitude. We deny the ontological difference which is at the
heart of our freedom, i.e., of our ability, qua finite, to surpass ourselves. Now, the
always open to us. In our primordiality, the ontological difference does not yet exist.
Thus, each ego, with an eye to this primordiality, can claim to be "unique." Each can
assert, "I am the only one". It can deny its status as a being by asserting that it is an
"ego ... which does not allow of pluralization in any meaningful sense, which excludes
this as senseless ..." (Ms. B IV 5, 1932 or 1933; HA XV, p. 590). Because of this,
coincidence between ourselves and our ground, we can always confuse the two sides of
our essence -- i.e., our finitude with our infinitude. Our finitude is our existence as a
being -- a "this" -- in the world. Thus, the collapse of the ontological difference in favor
of our finitude is actually the withdrawal of the surpassing quality of infinitude from our
present, worldly being. It is our being fixed in a "this-world" whose horizons have been
continues its action. Yet its action is not such that it can avail itself of the new. The
possibilities of the whole of time are suppressed by the very freedom they engender.
possibilities.30
An important corollary of the foregoing appears when we recall that, for Husserl,
reason functions out of freedom; this, just as much as freedom, in its further
development, functions from reason. This implies that when we speak of a regress, it is
one that includes both freedom and reason. Reason functions "out of freedom" (aus
Freiheit) since its action is that of active synthesis. It involves choice, which means that
the development of humanity towards reason is itself a matter of choice. Thus, just as we
can choose to undermine freedom, we can stop the advance of reason. We can do so by
suppressing the question of reason: "Why this rather than that?" To pose this question is
to call to mind alternate possibilities of being, behaving and thinking. As such, the
suppression of the question pertains to intolerance. When the "that" of the alternate
possibility exists in some social or racial group and yet is not recognized as pertaining to
that of synthesis, no longer has an effect in human affairs. In a certain sense, it has
Our remarks on freedom allow us to specify in a practical and moral way our
relation to the being of beings. The latter is our ground, and its full objectification is our
goal. Thus, as our ground, it manifests itself in our ability to be free (and, hence, in our
ability to pose the question of reason). As our goal, it takes the form of the perfect
each other as embodying the mutually supporting possibilities inherent in our rational
freedom. Now, the ground can never be fully manifest; which means that, as our goal, it
can never be completely realized. This follows from the ontological difference. That
being is not beings signifies that being per se can never be reified; it can never be
Notes
521
us; it is present only as a goal directing our lives. This goal is an inherent one insofar as
reason in the sense that it is rationally explicable in terms of the progressive synthesis of
In the last two features, it is rather like Aristotle's final cause. For Aristotle, the
full grown tree is the goal which the sapling attempts to realize through its biological
activities. The tree rationally combines and expresses the possibilities inherent in the
sapling. What sets apart Husserl's conception of the goal from the Aristotelean with its
biological references is, of course, the ontological difference. This difference does not
just set this goal at infinity, it also transforms the nature of its realization. Expressed as
freedom, the difference signifies a lack of real necessity in the absolute taken as our
ought-to-be. Inherently, the sapling ought to be a tree. Indeed, it can only become this
when the biological conditions for its development are present. As such, this goal is part
of its factually given nature. We, however, need not manifest the absolute. This follows
because the latter can be realized only through the openness of our freedom. Now, an
inherent, rationally explicable goal, which is realized through free activity, is a value. As
such, our practical and moral relationship to the absolute is a relation to value. Here, the
doctrine of the absolute turns into a doctrine of value. It becomes a theory which
grounds the notion of value by showing how it is rooted in the structure of what is.
By the latter we mean the structure of being in its relation to beings. When we
speak about value, our focus is not on what is in the sense of what is factually given. It is
on what ought to be realized through our freedom. For Husserl, we may note, values
form the context in which the question of the ground first arises. He writes: "It is not
facticity per se, but facticity as the source of possible and actual values advancing to
Notes
522
infinity which first compels the question of the 'ground' -- which naturally does not have
the sense of a thinglike, causal source" (Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 139). The ground is not
"thinglike" -- is not a cause as something already existing in nature -- because it, itself, is
not factually given. As the being of beings -- i.e., as lying at the basis of all possibilities,
all relativities, all contingencies -- it is, rather, what grounds nature's facticity. When we
are compelled to raise its question, it is initially in response to prior questions, questions
concerning why the facts permit the realization of values, e.g., those of rationality and
culture (See Ibid.). For Husserl, the general answer to these qustions is that the ground
raise its question. Thus, as already indicated, its practical, moral relation to us is that of
the values or goals which we freely attempt to realize. Husserl's mention of "possible
and actual values advancing to infinity" simply points to the ground's all embracing
character, one which finds expression in the multiplicity of ideals included in the
character of being itself signifies that value remains value. It is something that factually
given subjects can only partially manifset. Thus, the absolute, by virtue of its distinction
from individual beings, must always remain transcendent as a value, i.e., as a goal
The Krisis reflects on the fact that the direction it provides can be lost. Husserl's
much quoted remark, "the dream is over," can be taken as referring to the dream of
inevitable human progress. Since the absolute both draws humanity to itself and includes
the possibility of humanity's turning away and losing its way, this dream is rightly over.
In its stead, we have the awakening of self-responsibility. For Husserl, "A human being
is a human being in his self-responsibility." The same holds for the human community
(Ms. E III 9, p. 81, 1933). The later has, in fact, an all embracing responsibility. Its
"self-responsibility has its domain in the totality of being, the totality of life and ... the
Notes
523
totality of the life-world" (Ibid., p. 82). The negative side of this is that the human
community can, through its actions, cause a breakdown in the life-world. It can disrupt
the web of social relationships which form the life-world's framework. Its responsibility
for the totality of being and life is not just a responsibility for this intersubjective life-
world. It is, as already indicated, a responsibility for the absolute ground of such
totalities. Our own actions are the means by which this ground becomes manifest as the
totality of what is. In other words, the world which progressively manifests the absolute
through its indefinitely extended horizons is something realized through our own
syntheses. Having grounded us, i.e., having given us our basis in passive synthesis, the
absolute exists "regulating [our monadic being] from its free decisions" -- i.e., through its
processes of active synthesis. Its presence, then, is a matter of our taking responsibility
for what we freely choose to value, to constitute and accomplish. This responsibility for
the ground is a self-responsibility since the ground, with its multiple possibilities and
original presence, forms the core of our selfhood. It is the freedom which allows us to
awareness that progress is not inevitable, knows that evil and intolerance can never be
regression. As we have seen, to approach the absolute in teleological and practical terms
is to approach it under the aspect of value. This means taking a moral stance with regard
to the possibilities which are included in our humanity. It also signifies a recognition of
our responsibilities with regard to these possibilities; and this implies a recognition of the
possibility of permanent loss through our actions. Regarded in these terms, the problem
Notes
524
of intersubjectivity becomes eminently practical, one which involves both individual and
value as well those actions of ours which preserve a relation to this ground. It is to value
Thus, intersubjectivity (the world of shared meanings) is not something which we first
must theoretically establish in order, then, to act. In its character as our ought-to-be, i.e.,
which we ourselves must realize through our actions. In this regard, the problem of
intersubjectivity is transformed into that of caring for the factually given (and, hence,
fragile) web of human relations. It is a web, a nexus, into which we are born and which
we ourselves must maintain and expand. Our finitude, then acknowledged, both
necessitates this web and finds its moral expression within it. This expression points
both to Others in their finitude and to the infinitude lying within them waiting to be
expressed.
Notes
525
ENDNOTES
1. Fink's remarks are worth quoting at some length. He writes: "In his late
manuscripts, which were written after Cartesianische Meditationen, Husserl ... sees the
subjects into the transcendental realm. ... he arrives at the curious idea of a primal ego,
some extent, to withdraw the plurality from the dimension of the transcendental ... In the
same context, Husserl also tries to circumvent the difference between essence and fact by
going back to the primal facticity of transcendental life which first constitutes possibility
multiplicities -- also constitutes essence. According to Husserl's ideas in these very late
manuscripts, there is a primal life which is neither one nor many, neither factual nor
essential; rather it is the ultimate ground of all these distinctions: a transcendental primal
life which turns itself into a plurality and which produces in itself the differentiation into
fact and essence" ("Discussion -- Comments by Eugen Fink on Alred Schultz's Essay,
Papers III, ed. I Schutz, Phaenomenologica, No. 22, The Hague, 1966, p. 86). Here, I
must express my gratitude to Dr. Rudolph Bernett of the Husserl Archives in Louvain for
providing me with Fink's indices to the late manuscripts. Dr. Bernett's assistance in
collegiality.
Notes
526
Logische Untersuchungen, 5th ed., 3 Vols. (Tübingen, 1968), I, 15, 228, II/1, 90, 94f.
3. See also Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 115. On the resulting facticity (or
contingency) of the world and its constitution see Iso Kern, Husserl und Kant,
correlation of being to knowability is expressed as follows: "To every object that truly
is, there corresponds (in the a priori of unconditioned essential generality) the idea of a
possible consciousness in which the object itself can be grasped originally and perfectly
adequately. Conversely, if this possibility is guaranteed, eo ipso the object is one that
6. See LU, 1st ed., 2 Vols. (Halle a. S., 1900-1901), II, 249-51, 284, On the
causal determination of the knowing subject, see Ibid., II, 332, 356. The second edition
of the Investigations omits or rewrites these passages in an attempt to make the work's
positions consistent with those of Ideen I which appeared the same year, 1913.
is real is the individual with all its characteristics: it is a here and now. For us,
temporality is sufficient as a characteristic feature of reality" (LU, Tüb. ed., II/1, 123).
accepted by Husserl from a very early period. In the Investigations, it is used to establish
the "ideal" (or "one-in-many") character of the content of knowledge. Such a content
was considered to be ideal insofar as it was the one thing necessarily instantiated in all
valid judgments concerning the object. Husserl writse: "And just as the being or validity
the possible being of empirical instances which fall under these universals, so we say the
same thing here. The assertions, 'the truth is valid,' and, 'there are thinking creatures
possible whose judgments comprehend the relevant contents of meaning,' are equivalent"
LU, Tüb. ed., I, 129). The latter possibility -- i.e., that of the "thinking creatures" -- is in
the Investigations, with its realist stance, simply taken for granted. As such, the securing
securing the possibility of Others. This last, as we note in our text, first becomes an issue
with the adoption of the reduction and the idealism this entails.
9. This "depth of life" involves for Husserl the thought of a "primal ego." As
Fink writes: "... in these late manuscripts, the thought of a primal ego (Ur-Ich) appears,
[it is] an ego that is prior to the distinction, ego -- alter ego, being an ego that first allows
the plural to break forth from itself" ("Die Spätphilosophie Husserls," ed. cit., p. 113).
This ego, as we shall see, expresses the original unity of individual egos before their
phenomenology never argues or demonstrates. It only describes. Prof. Carr, thus, writes
concerning the objection that Husserl commits a petitio principii, "Such an objection
phenomenology never argues), I cannot agree that this objection is valid" ("Comments of
Prof. Mensch's paper, 'Intersubjectivity and the Constitution of time'," Halifax, Nova
Scotia, 1981). To this, we must say that the notion that phenomenology never argues,
when literally applied to Husserl's works, is inaccurate. No reader of Husserl can fail to
This leads us
its use of logical inference and, hence, argumentation. As opposed to being a "mere
collection" of descriptive truths, a theory is a logical unity of these, one which attempts
to deduce certain given truths from other more basic ones. Now, to deny
phenomenology the status of a theory is, for Husserl, to deny from the outset its claim to
be a "rigorous science." Indeed, it is to deny per se its status as a science. This follows,
for as Husserl writes: "The essential unity of the truths of a science is a unity of
explanation. But all explanation points to a theory and ends in the knowledge of the
basic laws, the principles of the explanation" (LU, Tüb. ed., I, 233). This means that
"scientific knowledge is, as such, grounded knowledge (Erkenntnis aus dem Grund). To
know the ground of something is to see the necessity for its being the way it is" (Ibid., I,
231). Granting this, to say that phenomenology cannot argue or deduce is to say that it
Notes
529
has no explanatory power at all. It is to assert that it can never achieve the status of a
science.
Far from
To account for something by means of its constitution is, thus, to attempt to give an
account "aus dem Grund." The goal of this account is that of seeing "the necessity" for
the constituted object's "being the way it is." "Necessity," here, refers to the basic "laws"
aus dem Grund" refers to a knowledge of the grounds of such constitution. What are the
stages of the constitutive process which must be gone through if an entity of a certain
type is to become intuitively present? What are the laws and principles governing the
ordering of such stages? This inquiry is phenomenological insofar as these grounds are
insofar as it attempts to uncover the "rational motivations" for our judgments. Such
motivations are termed "rational" to the point that they spring from the laws of evidence.
assertions by weighing the evidence for their respective claims. Husserl holds that this
evidence is constituted through our constitution of entities -- i.e., the objects with which
our judgments must agree. Thus, a phenomenological account of the laws of evidence --
entities answering to such evidence. Husserl, accordingly, makes the following claim: A
With this, we
can see why Husserl's commission of a petitio principii is fatal to his account of the
constitution of Others. Such a logical error would be of relatively minor importance if,
indeed, Husserl were compiling a simple list of descriptive facts. What he is attempting,
Auslegung.") The petitio, in violating the rules for such an explication, robs the account
of its explanatory, scientific character. More specifically, the petitio assumes the
supposed to be present only at a higher level. It, thus, violates "the basic laws, the
according to Husserl, a fundamental fact of cognitive experience: "The fact, namely, that
all thinking and knowing is directed to states of affairs whose unity relative to a
therefore, of an ideal character" (LU, Halle ed., II, 9). Granting this, we have to explain
"how the same experience can have a content in a twofold manner, how next to its
inherent actual content, there should and can dwell an ideal, intentional content" (Ibid.,
II, 16). The latter is the object's content regarded as a sense -- i.e., as a unity in the
multiplicity of the actual experiences we can have of it. As in the Cartesian Meditations,
(Sinn) and meaning (Bedeutung). Our reasons are essentially the same as Husserl's:
Notes
531
"Meaning and sense count as synonymous for us. On the one hand, it is, precisely with
respect to this concept, very convenient to have parallel terms which one can alternately
use especially in investigations like the previous ones where it is precisely the sense of
the term, meaning, which is under investigation. On the other hand, something else
comes into consideration, namely the deeply rooted practice of using both words as
4. We cannot, for this reason, agree with Schutz's criticism of the "second
epoché" -- the epoché which, for Husserl, brings us to the primary level of constitution.
According to Schutz, the performance of this epoché eliminates not just the sense of
"objective, worldly existing Others," but also the data required for the constitution of this
sense. If we grant this, the primary level is not genuinely primary with respect to Others;
it does not contain elements which, while individually lacking the sense, "Others,"
constitute this sense by coming together. At this point, the sense, "Others," must itself
has no lower level constitutive basis. Here, if we still accept the theory of constitution,
according to which the more primitive level constitutes the less primitive, there is no
more primitive level than that on which the sense of Others first appears. The epoché
which attempts to suspend this sense, thus, overreaches itself. Indeed, insofar as it
attempts to pass beyond the genuinely primary level, it leaves us with nothing at all.
This criticism, however, follows only if we agree with Schutz that there cannot exist data
for the sense, "Others," without this sense itself being present. See Schutz, "The Problem
5. Schutz embraces this conclusion in the following words: "It is to be surmised that
and the we-relationship will be the foundation for all other categories of human
existence. The possibility of reflection on the self, discovery of the ego, capacity
for performing any epoché ... are founded on the primal experience of the we-
What this implies with regard to Schutz's own position is that sociology and not
explicating the 'sense' of the Other, which is already contained implicitly in the very
conception of an objectivity which must be equally valid for all possible subjects, the
theory of intersubjectivity recognizes that the Other must be a 'real' subject, if objectivity
itself is to have any 'sense' at all" (Phenomenology, its Genesis and Prospect, New York,
1965, p. 159). As already noted, David Carr disagrees with this. He claims that the
"task" of such an explication does not involve the question "whether the Other exists as
such" ("The 'Fifth Meditation' ..." ed. cit., p. 19). Such disagreement is all the more
surprising since he himself points out that transcendence is a function "of possible acts
implied in any actual one" -- i.e., any actual act. Thus, if, as he says, there is a
transcendence in which the object is "not only irreducible to any particular acts of mine"
but "is also not reducible to all possible acts of mine," whence does this transcendence
spring from? It cannot arise as a function of the possibilities implicit in my actual acts.
As a function of possibilities which surpass my own, it must refer to the "possible acts"
Notes
533
implied in an actual act which is not my own. It implies, in other words, the act of an
approach to a being in itself that is independent of it. ... When we no longer interpret
transcendental life as receptive, its special character still remains undetermined. It is the
productive creation might sound, at least its opposition is thereby indicated to the
receptive character of the worldly-factual (mental) life of experience, a life which fosters
No. 21, The Hague, 1966, p. 143). Fink's use of the word, Kreation, is especially
significant. When asked by the editors of Kant Studien to review this piece, Husserl
wrote for its "Preface": "... I have thoroughly gone through this article and I am
delighted to be able to say that there is not a sentence within it that I do not make my
own, that I could not expressly acknowledge as my own conclusion" (Studien zur Phän.,
not limited to making sense out of some given presence. The "fullness" of perceived
constitutive activity. Thus, if we say that actual perceptual presence is the sign that some
Notes
534
actuality is given to us, the constitution of this presence is the constitution of its
givenness. In Ricoeur's words, "... one last gap still remains to be filled in between what
we shall henceforth call the 'sense' of the noema and actuality. ... Transcendental
phenomenology aspires to integrate into the noema its own relation to the object, i.e., its
'fullness,' which completes the constitution of the whole noema. ... To constitute
actuality is to refuse to leave its 'presence' outside the 'sense' of the world" ("Introduction
to Ideas I," Husserl: An Analysis of his Phenomenology, trans. E.G. Ballard and L.E.
Evanston, 1967, p. 23). Another way of putting this is to say that the inclusion of
presence in sense makes the constitution of sense the constitution of actuality, once we
identify actuality with sense filled presence or, what is the same, with sense as including
presence.
9. For Fink this means that there is no ultimate "heteronomy" between "sensuous
hyle" and "intentional form," -- i.e., between sensuous data and the interpretive
non-intentional moment of the act is constituted along with the intentional form of
phenomenological time, a self-constitution that does not occur through acts" ("Die
10. De Boer, here, echoes Fink's position. Speaking of the noema (the
objective sense of an entity), Fink writes: "If the psychological noema is the sense of an
actual intentionality, a sense that we distinguish from the being itself to which it refers,
then, in opposition to this, the transcendental noema is the being itself. ... The
manifests and identifies itself in the noema. The transcendental noema cannot ... refer to
an object beyond itself that is independent of it; it is the entity (Seiendes) itself" ("Die
11. For further references in the Krisis to this absolute subjectivity which
objectifies itself in a plurality of human subjects see Ibid., pp. 115f, 1554. See also A V
10, Nov. 5, 1931, pp. 20f, 23f; early references to the same subjectivity include F I 22,
Nov. 1917, pp. 21ff, 37ff. This subjectivity, as we shall see, is that of the "primal ego"
NOTES TO CHAPTER II: ' THE GROUNDING OF THE THING AND THE EGO'
1. The second pagination, indicated by "F.", will be that of Fink's typescript. This
wrote a number of Beilagen for it which have been transcribed by Guy Kirkhoven
at Louvain. Husserl, thus, appears to have taken an active, collaborative part in its
composition.
art gallery. A finite number of colors are used in the paintings, yet each is different. It is
the ordering of the colors on the canvas which makes this so. It makes the colors into
logic. For a summary of the LU's doctrine on this topic, see The Question of Being in
actively explicates the formal relations existing bewteen individually perceivable objects
or features thereof. The claim that the phenomenology of the constitution of being
coincides with the phenomenology of reason (i.e., of categorical thought) signifies, then,
that the forms of unification which are the explicit themes of such thought are implicitly
present in our positing of our world. Categorical thought, in other words, simply makes
positing.
5. We emphasize this point because it is often ignored. Prof. Carr writes, for
example, "That the actual process by which we recognize the other person might
that, given the tie between rationality and positing, this circular, conscious process
would not "work" at all -- i.e., result in an actual positing recognition. As we shall
see, this holds even when we accept Husserl's claim that actual conscious life is not
quality of both.
Notes
537
"It is, accordingly, at once clear how far the logical laws and, in the first instance, the
ideal laws of 'authentic' thinking also claim a psychological meaning and also regulate
the course of factual mental events. Each genuine 'pure' law, which expresses a
Tüb. ed., II/2, 198). The assertion of this passage is that the logical laws necessarily
have a field of applicability. In the Ideen, howver, there is only the assertion of a
conditional necessity. Its position, as we shall see, is: if the course of factual mental
events is to result in the constitution of an objective world, then the logical laws must
7. See Kern, Husserl and Kant, ed. cit., pp. 288ff; also Eduard Marbach, Das
Problem des Ich in der Phänomenologie Husserls, Phaenomenologica, No. 59, The
Hague, 1974, pp. 303ff. Marbach goes so far as to assert that the non-constituted "'pure
ego' ... does not acutally deserve the title of 'ego'" (Ibid., p. 338). In other words, " ... as
8. The notion of the ego as a constituted (or "founded") unity occurs in the
(1893-1917) analyzes in detail the ego's temporal constitution. In Ideen II, written
between 1912 and 1924, the constituted ego reappears under the title of the "personal
ego." This personal ego is a theme of Husserl's writings till the end of his career in the
Notes
538
late 1930's. With respect to the pure, non-constituted ego, its concept is extensively
of the 1920's. In the last decade of Husserl's life, it becomes the subject of an thorough
analysis. The analysis concerns its non-constituted nature as a "nunc stans." Here, it
9. There is a certain ambiguity with regard to the reference of this passage. Does it
Both, as we shall see, require a unity in the posited world for their self-
maintenance.
10. This doctrine first appears in the lectures on internal time consciousness.
11. This statement will have to be modified when we come to speak of the
12. The exact nature of our experience of this non-enduring ego will be the subject of
Chapter V where we will consider Husserl's description of the pure ego as a pre-
13. These examples are from the visual estimate of distance. Corresponding examples
can be taken from the auditory, olfactory and even tactile senses. Thus, a series of
series of tactile sensations -- e.g., those of the muscular effort of focusing our eyes
as objects approach the "here," even those of the "straining" to hear as a sound
diminishes. All of these temporally ordered series play their part in our actual
estimations of distance.
14. The passage in Ideen I (p. 202, Biemel ed.) on which Held in his book (p.
127) bases this interpretation concerns not the pure ego, but rather the personal ego. The
former, as we have stressed, is abstracted from all experiences. The latter, as an ego
made up of acts, is constituted by the experiences whose connections form these acts.
Now, what is called a Kantian idea, in the passage which Held cites, is the stream of
reflectively directed perceptions can grasp it as a whole (See Ideen I, Biemel ed., p. 200).
The thought of it as a unified totality, like the corresponding thought of the world which
is constituted from the stream, is, thus, that of an infinite, Kantian idea. As we have
quoted Husserl, the former thought is that of the personal, as opposed to the pure, ego.
See above, .
15. Marbach's rejection of the pure ego is a rejection of the ego "which cannot
be constituted as a personal ego in Husserl's sense ..." (Das Problem ..., ed. cit., p. 338).
It is, in other words, a rejection of the pure in favor of the personal ego. The difficulty
with Marbach's position is that he tends to identify the personal ego with the idea of the
pure ego which occurs through re-presentation. This second form of availability of the
pure ego -- i.e., its availability in idea -- is, however, not the personal ego. The personal
ego, absolutely considered, is a Kantian idea; Kantian ideas involve the notion of a
progressive advance in the determination of an entity. But the idea of the pure ego, given
Notes
540
that this ego always remains perfectly identical, does not involve any such notion of
progressive advance. The pure ego, as a non-perspectival unity, does not admit of being
"more closely" determined. What this signifies is that the personal ego, qua Kantian
idea, is in contradiction to the pure ego only when we (mistakenly) take it as the idea of
16. These remarks will turn out to have a positive significance when we consider
environment of the ego. The resulting pure now will become an essential
harmony.
1. Apart from sensibility, this synthetic action is limited to the purely logical
employment of thought. The "pure reason" which engages in this employment attempts
to synthesize all the concepts of the understanding into one interrelated whole. In Kant's
words, its attempt is "to combine all the acts of the understanding, in respect to every
object, into an absolute whole" ("Kritik d. r. V.," B 383; Kant's Schriften, III, 253). The
result of this attempt is "metaphysics" with its various propositions and systems of pure
thought.
2. We, thus, do not just have the possibility of different worlds, but also the
possibility of one world varying or passing over into another. In Husserl's words,
exists not only different possibilities [of different natures or worlds] but also the
possibility that factually different 'natures pass over into one another,' the possibility that
factually, in the unity of a factual consciousness, there (intuitively) appears for a period
of time a sensible nature of one sensible form and then again a sensible nature of another
sensible form, the possibility that, by intervals, an exact and then a vague nature or world
constitute themselves as different times, the possibility that there does not exist for
consciousness, once and forever afterwards, a nature which is one and continually self-
3. Thus, Husserl to be consistent must assert that the "ontic unity" or being of
the ego is something acquired, i.e., temporally constituted. He writes, for example, "The
ego is itself constituted as a temporal unity. It is, as a lasting and remaining ego, an
already acquired (and, in constant acquisition, continually acquired) ontical unity" (Ms. C
17, Sept. 20-22, 1931; HA XV, Kern ed., p. 348). The nature of this constitution will
be a subject of Chapter V.
synthesis of such a kind that everything which is presented goes together, as being
mutually valid, in the unity of a world which is the correlate of the constantly becoming
and already accomplished unity of all my presentations, the presentations which I have,
5. We are in agreement with Fink as to the answer to his questions. The absolute or
ultimate subjectivity is, he writes, "... a primal life which is neither one nor many,
neither factual nor essential; rather it is the ultimate ground of all these
distinctions: a transcendental primal life which turns itself into a plurality ..." See
6. It will also follow when we make the reverse reduction and, instead of abstracting
temporal relations, abstract the experiential contents which the latter order -- this
INTERSUBJECTIVITY'
itself and beings. Husserl's later phenomenology takes the stance that "... metaphysics ...
is in need of a new beginning, a new foundation. ... Accordingly, the sense of the
each thing which is given to us as a being ..." ("Die Bedeutung der phanomenologischen
Methode fur die Neubegrunding der Metaphysik," Proceedings of the Tenth International
1949, p. 1219). For Landgrabe, the result of this radical inquiry into the origin or ground
of every individual being is an awareness of the distinction between being and individual
beings. The being of the ground, the being which is ultimately giving, cannot be
grounds. As he expresses this insight: "Being, itself, however, is not a being but rather
Notes
543
that which allows us, at any given time, to say of the beings, the 'things,' 'it exists' and 'it
"associative temporalization" which first results in the ego as a temporal center and
1931).
1905 lectures on time consciousness, "We can no longer speak of a time of the ultimately
absolutely timeless consciousness which is not an object" (Ibid., Beilage VI, p. 112).
Notes
544
3. This remark occurs in the passage: "If, in the primal original stream, we
perform a reduction to the things which are primal-original, if we suspend all re-
are in the original present. Or rather: I do this. But this 'I do,' itself pertains to this. I
see the 'I do' in a reflection, then I see this reflection through a [further] reflection. I am
reflecting." The reflecting ego is the functioning ego; it is not the ego which has been
exist as this reflecting ego [present] in the reflecting acts, while the things previously
apprehended along with the previous ego are objective, are that upon which I function"
(Ms. A V 5, p. 4, Jan. 1933). See also Ms. C III 3, pp. 2-3, Nov. 1931.
4. As Klaus Held puts this point: "The fact that the ego cannot grasp itself in
its active functioning -- its anonymity -- and the fact that it streams away from itself are
one and the same. Could the ego which possesses the intentions which it, itself,
phenomenologically speaking, a non-thought -- then this would signify that it would not,
by its passive streaming, permit the opening up of an original distance in its functioning
present" (Lebendige Gegenwart, Haag, 1966, pp. 128-29). The "non-thought" here is
that of the actively functioning ego being objective to itself by virtue of being fixed in an
objective position of time. So conceived, it would flow with this position into pastness.
It would, thus, never become separate from this position. No original distance between
itself and this position would ever open up; therefore, it would never actually become
objective to itself.
Notes
545
5. See e.g., Ms. C 2 I, pp. 11-12, Aug. 1931, Ms. B I 22, pp. 16-17, May or Aug.,
1931.
metaphysical questioning about the being of the individual being (Sein des Seienden)"
arises when we consider the problem of nothingness. When we do, "nothingness (das
Nichts) does not remain a vague opposite to the individual being (Seiende), rather it
shows itself as pertaining to its being (Sein)" ("Was ist Metaphysik", Wegmarken,
Frankfurt am Main, 1967, pp. 16-17). For both philosophers, nothingness seems to be a
sign of the ontological difference, i.e., of the fact that being (Sein) is not individual
beings (Seienden).
writes: "... we cognizing humans are individual egos nto which the absolute ego has split
himself ..." (Ms. F I 22, p. 22, Nov. 8-17, 1917). This process results in a plurality of
individual egos, but the absolute ego at their origin remains pre-plural. Thus, " ... this
ego cannot be some individual, human ego. Human subjects are members of the world.
They are, in the idealistic sense, quite mediated formations within subjectivity. ... the
pure or absolute ego is nothing other than the subjectivity in which (according to the
ordered play of accomplishing actions) the phenomenal world first comes to be with all
8. The "is" of this last sentence has been marked as inserted by the transcriber.
Notes
546
9. See Aristotle's Physics, II, ch. 11, 218b 21; Hume's Treatise, I, Part I, Sect.
10. It is, thus, not an appeal to a level in which disagreements about worldly
time -- e.g., the Newtonian versus the Einsteinian view of universal simultaneity -- can
occur. Such disagreements are "higher level" because they presuppose the
mathematization of our experience. They also presuppose the existence of Other subjects
and their ability to communicate the results of their experiments. For Husserl, of course,
this is precisely what is at issue. Given his focus, universal time (universale Zeit) must
not, in his texts, be taken on an abstract, theoretical level. It is not to be thought of as the
a space which may be empty of subjects. It is rather the common time of a humanity
which is in active, ongoing contact with itself. Otherwise put: the focus of Husserl's
way. For Husserl, all views of worldly time presuppose this schema.
11. Our final chapter will analyze the particulars of this common style.
12. Aquinas expresses this distinction in terms of the observation that I can
know what something is without knowing whether it is. He writes: "I can know, for
example, what is a man or a phoenix and yet not know whether these may exist among
the things of nature. It is, thus, clear that existence (esse) is other than essence or
whatness" (De Ente et Essentia, ch. 4, ed. Rolland-Gosselin, Kain, 1926, p. 34). If they
were the same, then from knowing the what, I could know the whether, i.e., existence
would be included among "those things which are the components of the essence" (Ibid.).
Notes
547
13. Cf. Aquinas' statement on the essence or nature considered in itself: "It is,
thus, clear that, aboslutely considered, the nature of man abstracts from every sort of
existence (a quolibit esse) ..." (De Ente et Essentia, ch. 3, ed. cit., p. 26). The
corresponding statement by Husserl is: "... the positing and, in the first instance, the
intuitive grasp of an essence implies not the slightest positing of any sort of individual
existence. Pure truths about essence contain not the slightest assertion about facts ..."
(Ideen I, §4, Biemel ed., p. 17). This position can lead to a serious misinterpretation of
of essences, we could conclude from this that phenomenology must be silent about
questions concerning existence and being. This, however, makes unintelligible Husserl's
assertion that "the effort of my phenomenology has always proceeded from the subjective
back to the existent (Seienden)" (Adelgundis Jaegerschmid, "Die Letzten Jahre Edmund
Husserls -- 1936-1938," Stimmen der Zeit, 199, Heft 2, Feb. 1981, p. 134. Entry
recorded March 16-17, 1938). In abstracting from being, one abstracts from the living
present which is the central core of consciousness. In Husserl's words: "One simply
abstracts from being (Sein) and brackets the consciousness in which being first becomes
alive and remains alive (lebendig wird und lebendig bleibt" (Ibid., p. 131, entry recorded
(eine ganz gefährliche Irrlehre)," one which misrepresents the purpose of his
14. Once again, there is a parallel with Thomas, at least if we follow Etienne
Gilson's interpretation. For Thomas, according to Gilson: "Essences may well represent
the balance sheets of so many already fulfilled essential possibilities, but actual
existences are their very fulfilling, and this is why essences are actually becoming in
Notes
548
time, despite the fact that a time-transcending knowledge eternally sees them as already
fulfilled. ... Thus, becoming through esse is the road to fully determined being ..."
(Being and Some Philosphers, 2nd ed., Toronto, 1952, pp. 183-84).
15. This sentence continues: "[They are] its modes of understanding or being able to
understand itself." The point of this seems to be that the absolute cannot
objectively grasp itself without its actually becoming an object -- i.e., without its
16. With this, we have an answer to the question: "Are the worldly events of
monadic mode of being, indices for a passage to a mode of being which, in principle, is
inaccessible to the methods of worldly knowing?" (Ms. A V 20, Nov. 18, 1934). The
"non-worldly ... monadic mode of being" is the being-now which underlies the monad's
being in the world. The now's inaccessibility to the methods of objective "worldly
knowing" is its objective anonymity. Thus, when Husserl asks, "Is birth ... intuitably
conceivable? Is death an event which can be intuitively realizable ...?", his answer is that
they are "per se, precisely non-conceivable ... The 'evidence' is, so to speak, non-
anonymity. It is the evidence of a passage to the now per se, the now apart from those
temporal distances which permit objective appearing and, hence, conceivability. See
individual life is, of course, not answered here. Certainly, after periods of dreamless
sleep, revivification does occur. On awakening, what has been retained from the past is
once again made alive -- i.e., made part of our ongoing life -- by being added to by the
living present. The fact that during such sleep the retained remains and yet is not
consciously grasped indicates that retention, per se, is not a conscious act. Consciousness
occurs with the revivification of the retained. If we follow this line of thought, we can
sketch out the possibility of something akin to a doctrine of personal immortality. The
crucial element of this doctrine is given by Aquinas when he writes: "... once the soul
has acquired its individual being by having been made the form of some particular body,
that being always remains individuated" (De Ente et Essentia, ch. 5, ed. cit., p. 39). For
both Husserl and Aquinas, having a body is having a unique, individuating "here." It is
experience in his "here" -- i.e., its never being equivalent to the Other's experience in the
"there." If, after death, the experience which corresponds to the "here" could be
would occur and, with this, we would have a personal immortality. This, of course, is
only specualtion. In the manuscript A VI 14, written in 1930, Husserl denies the analogy
between waking from "periodic sleep" and waking from the "absolute sleep" of death
(See p. 45). No reason, however, is given for this denial. If it is not his final position,
then we have at least some phenomenological basis for the late Husserl's personal beliefs
INTERSUBJECTIVITY'
ground and the grounded. He writes that the world "is already constructed; its
higher levels in terms of the lower and then view the lower in terms of the higher. In this
way, we reconstruct the constitutive processes which must be assumed if the higher
levels are to be given. Thus, for Husserl, the task of reconstruction is "to reconstruct the
pre-temporal present from the starting point of the accomplished world in which we
constantly have the present and in which we ourselves are present in the same way as
Others; now, upwardly directed, to reconstruct from this [pre-temporal present] the
primordial time of the temporal modalities, to reconstruct primordial experience and the
experiential world; from this (an abstraction since such primordiality is unthinkable
alone), through the consideration of empathy in its levels of validity, to reconstruct the
origin of Others and that of myself as one among many within the objective world ..."
(Ms. K III 4, p. 77, 1936). This procedure, we note, is to be sharply distinguished from
that of Kant's regressive method. The latter ends in what is nouminal and, hence, in
processes which we cannot make visible to ourselves. For Husserl, however, the
Here, the viewing of the higher in terms of the lower is meant to serve as a
Husserl's project is our own. Our last chapter followed him in the reconstruction and
examination of "the pre-temporal present." Our present chapter will concern itself with
empathy and the reconstruction of the simultaneous presents which self and Others
involve.
Notes
551
experience of itself [as functioning], the ultimately functioning transcendental ego must
leave open the possibility of another, unique 'I function.' The peculiar kind of uniqueness
it points to the possibility of co-presents which are just as factual and anonymous"
(Lebendige Gegenwart, ed. cit., p. 163). For Held, the leading idea here is that the
thought of a singular subject or a corresponding plurality. So regarded, "it [i.e., the ego
and, in general, so little be primarily thought of as a unity that, for the most original
understanding of the nunc stans, the thought of an inner plurality, at very least, is
essentially equivalent to the thought of its unity." This inner plurality is "the pre-
temporal, unavoidably anonymous connection between ego and ego" (Ibid., p. 169). It is
the thought of plurality before it is, via objectification, distinguished from unity -- i.e.,
requirements for the co-present now. First, it must be other than the original, pre-
temporal now. Second, it must be identical with it. This second requirement focuses on
the fact that the co-present now must be present. Its actual givenness is its existence in
the constantly present, pre-temporal now. The two conditions are satisfied by seeing co-
presence as the result of a Hegelian "negation of a negation." At the point of its original
welling up, the momentary now is identical with the pre-temporal now. Departing into
negation in a manner which still preserves it. As Hegel describes the logical structure of
Notes
552
this process: "First, I point out the Now and it is aserted to be the truth. I [then] point it
out, however, as something that has been ... But, thirdly, ... I then supersede, cancel, its
having been ... [I] negate thereby the negation of the now and return, thereby, to the first
position: that [the] Now is" (Phenomenology of Mind, tr. Baille, London, 1966, p. 156).
4. The corollary of this is that the stream of impressional moments, each with
its distinct "hyletic" content, is itself constituted. As Husserl observes, the hyletic
content "affects" the subject, it "provokes" (Reize übt) it "and motivates the subject to
activity" -- i.e., the activity of objective synthesis. Yet this does not mean that hyletic
content is prior to all constitutive activity. Rather, "the 'hyletic' is constituted as what is
first 'objective' in the immanent temporal form" (Ms. E III 2, p. 45, 1930's). It is
the original present, pass through it, and stream away. So taken, it is "objective" in the
sense of being placed in the temporal field which stands over and against the subject's
nowness. What we have, here, is a constitution of both acts and content, i.e., a
temporalization "in which all the acts proceeding from the ego and the affections
17 IV, p. 1, 1930). With this, we also have the constitution of the ego understood as the
"middle point" -- i.e., as the active center -- of its temporally extended life. We do not,
however, have the constitution of the source of temporalization. For Husserl, then, "we
must make the distinction: On the one side, we have the temporal stream of
consciousness and the trancendental ego of acts which is related to this temporality ... on
the other side, we have the primal ground of temporalization, the primal ego ..." (Ms. C 2
I, p. 12, Aug. 1931). As the ground of temporalization, the primal ego is the ground of
the hyletic. This means that it is the ground of its "provoking" the central ego since it
Notes
553
makes hyletic content appear to approach the ego from the future and enter into its acts
which along with such content depart into pastness. Since, however, the source of such
we can say is that the hyletic, through its temporalization, displays or exhibits (auslegt)
what the primal ego pre-temporally contains. As such, the hyletic appears as the
impressional content of the transcendental ego of acts and, indeed, appears as something
5. Each subject can therefore say: "I bear (trage) in myself all Others as
selves which are appresented or can be appresented and I bear my [objective] self in the
same way" (Ms. C III 3, p. 33). As Husserl elsewhere put this, "... we have ... monads
which are implied in me as an ego, which are implied in my monadic being and which,
indeed, are implied in every monadic being. Each is a monad among monads, and each
is an ego which of itself inherently implies (von sich aus in sich impliziert) the monadic
world; and as such, each is implied in me, implied in the one primal ego" (Ms. A V 20,
pp. 13-14, 1934). Expressed in terms of co-presence and appresentation, this becomes
the assertion: "As an absolute, streamingly existent, concrete present, I possess [the
a co-present" (Ms. C III 3, p. 33). The point of this is that in acknowledging the Other as
having a living present (the very same present which allows me to function as a "concrete
present"), I also acknowledge the complete reciprocity of our relations. Each ego, qua
primal ego, i.e., qua the living present, takes up the standpoint from which all Others are
appresented as co-presents.
Notes
554
negation of a negation. The assertion that memory and empathy are the same is negated
when subjects are individualized. This assertion that memory is not empathy is itself
negated when I assert that the object of my empathy -- the Other himself -- is the object
negation -- i.e., a negation which overcomes yet preserves what it negates. Thus, the last
assertion does not imply that empathy and memory are the same in the sense that the
object of my empathy is the object of my self-remembering. This would imply that self
and Others are not distinct -- the levels of our first assertion. The last assertion
empathy.
described on pp. . The first pairing links my bodily presence in the "here" and
the "there." The second links its appresented presence in the "there" with the
8. Thus, Husserl follows the sentence we quoted with the question: "But
what kind of potentiality (Potentialität) is this?" Strictly speaking, "the totality of human
teleological being and an ought-to-be (Sein-sollen), and this teleology prevails in each
and every egological action and purpose ..." (Ms. K III 6, p. 253, Aug. 5-8, 1936).
Critique, Leibzig, 1878, which is listed under the Husserl Archive library signature, BQ
3. As Husserl writes, "We can temporally divide, in a certain manner separate into
pieces, a concretely filled duration. This, however, does not mean that these
pieces of time can be considered as concrete individuals or that they can be filled
other words, since past moments imply those that follow them, there are no
4. If our present retentions were concrete individuals (see note 3), they could never
be brought into a real coincidence. Our viewing them together would be the
viewing of a collection. Our present retentions, however, are not individuals, but
into [my retentions'] 'vertical intentionality.'" He immediately adds: "The enduring tone
embracing the primary sensation -- i.e., the sensation of the present tonal now -- [and] the
primary memories of the series of expired tone points ..." (HA X, 82). This unity is
Notes
556
caused by the merging of the tonal contents which, itself, is caused by the merging of the
retentions bearing these contents. The ultimate factor, here, is simply that of the
temporal dependence of the moments that are retained. This is the first cause of the
merging.
extended time. The latter depart into pastness, the constituting phenomena do not per se
7. This means that the moment which is posited as objectively "now" is not
the nunc stans. To reverse this, we can say that to posit the nunc stans as an objective
moment in time is always to lose it. Its objective positing loses it because it assumes its
temporal transcendence, and such transcendence is the departure of the posited into the
"over againstness: of past time. Thus, insofar as it is its limit, the objectively posited
now is part of the continuum of past time. The nunc stans, however, constantly
8. This is the case for the eidh or forms as conceived by both Plato and
Aristotle. For Plato, the forms present "a kind of being which always the same,
uncreated and indestructible" (Timaeus, 52a). They possess "the very actuality of to be"
-- ousia auth tou einai (Phaedo, 78d). For Aristotle, the actuality of the forms is
reality by informing its matter. Aristotle, of course, does equate the formal and final
causes of processes, thus making the form into a goal. As causative, however, such goals
are already achieved. An actual tree actually manifests the form which was the goal of
its development. It is as an already achieved goal -- i.e., as a full grown tree -- that it acts
Notes
557
as a formal and final cause of a process -- the process which, through its seeds, will bring
about another tree bearing its form. For Husserl, however, the goal of a teleological
process does not have to be actually given to be effective. See Ms. F I 14, p. 45, June
1911.
9. To take an example from ordinary life, let us say that a person wants to become a
marathon runner. He is not yet a marathon runner. This goal is a not-yet, i.e., a
by our last footnote, this determination does not depend upon there ever having
been a marathon runner before this person set this as his goal.
[present] now point is characterized as an actual now, i.e., as a new now ..." ( HA X,
11. The ultimate basis of this position is that time is responsible for all
egoogical intentionalities insofar as it is what first brings about "the new awakening
world ..." (Ms. E III 5, Sept. 1933; HA XV, Kern ed., 595).
this "worldly" sense. He writes: "But when we come to the concrete thing, e.g., this
circle, i.e., one of the individual circles, ... of these there is no definition, but they are
known only by the aid of intuitive thinking or of perception" (Meta., VII, ch. 10, 1036a,
Notes
558
2-6, in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. R. McKeon, New York, 1941, p. 807; see also
Meta., 1039a, 15-20). Perception with its intuitive thinking grasps, we can say, the
internal horizons of a thing. The worldly sense of a thing, however, corresponds to its
external horizons. The latter, in linking it to other similar objects give us the "universal"
13. Such a reinterpretation at once gives the logical law a field of applicability
14. This teleological relation is also put by Husserl in the following set of
rhetorical questions: "Can reason begin of end in constituted existence? Can the
constitutive process which it has ultimately, spontaneously set in motion be in vain? ...
the coming to be of real rationality ...?" (Ms. E III 4, p. 30). Here, reason is "at work" in
the same super-temporal, all-temporal sense that time-constitution itself is. The latter is
Frankfurt am Main, 1967, pp. 68-69. Commenting on the principle, "reason is why this
exists rather than another," he asserts, "Freedom is the origin of the principle of reason."
16. Thus, for Husserl, first we have "the absolute in its temporal modalities
temporalizing itself in the absolute streaming ..." Then, "within this," we have "the levels
of the absolute: the absolute as the absolute, 'human' totality of monads, the absolute as
Notes
559
reason and [as existing] in the temporalization of reason, [then] the development of the
rational monadic totality, history in a meaningful sense" (Ms. C I, Sept. 21-22, 1934; HA
XV, 669). All of this, for Husserl, is part of the absolute's progressive temporal
manifestation.
Philosophiches Jahrbuch der Gores-Gesellschaft, vol. 67, 1959, p. 131. The intensity of
Adelgundis Jaegerschmid. She reports that while Husserl claims that phenomenology
"ultimately leads to God, the absolute," he also asserts, "I am attempting ... to reach God
without God" (Gespräche mit Edmund Husserl 1931-36," Stimmen der Zeit, 199, Heft 1,
Jan. 1981, p. 49, p. 56, remarks recorded on April 28, 1931 and Dec. 1935). The
"without God" refers to the practice of the phenomenological epoché on the received
tradition. It involves the withholding of judgment on the assertion of the Bible and on
the "proofs, methods and positions" employed by confessional theology. See also
Jaegerschmid, "Die letzten Jahre Edmund Husserls (1936-1938)," Stimmen der Zeit, 199,
18. Whether or not this is the only way God understands himself is not at issue
here. Husserl's point concerns the fact that God cannot grasp himself as actually
objective without being so -- i.e., without objectifying himself in time through his
functioning.
development of humanity, i.e., of human beings in their development towards the ideal"
(Ms. F I 22, p. 38). As Husserl also puts this: "To write the history of this ego [i.e.,
God], of this absolute intelligence is, therefore, to write the history of the necessary
teleology in which the world as a phenomenal world comes to advancing creation, to its
creation within this intelligence" (Ibid., p. 22). Because this manifestation of God is our
own development, indeed, because we are "egos into which the absolute ego has split
pertains to the pure essence of the ego, of subjectivity, reconstruct the necessary
sequence of the teleological process in which the whole world and ultimately we
ourselves ... have been formed ..." (Ibid.) For Husserl in the 1930's, such
time of the temporal modalities," and from thence to "primordial experience and the
experiential world," ending with the attempt "to reconstruct the origin of Others and that
of myself as one among many with the objective world" (See note 1, ch. VI). The
"intuitive absorption into what pertains to the pure essence of the ego" is taken as an
20. In the language of the appendix, this means that such development is
similar to that of the other "rigorous sciences" which begin with fruitful, if unclarified
insights and whose "whole development is determined as if from a guiding star" (Ms. F I
22, p. 61). For Husserl, Fichte's main insight is "to conceive the world as a teleological
product of the absolute ego ..." (Ibid., p. 23). We should, however, note that certain
features of this view are present in the earlier manuscript F. I 14. Thus, this manuscript
21. "The total absolute is, in advance (im voraus), always what it is; and it
already exists in advance, existing in this manner on all levels, identical simply as what
1931).
single, 'absolute substance,'" Husserl claims: "All essential necessities [e.g., those of the
23. Thus, as Strasser points out, Husserl distinguishes his conception of God
from that of the Aristotelean metaphysics. For the latter, God is the "maker" -- i.e., the
totality of all the informing forms. It, thus, conceives of God "according to the schema
of the full grown tree being the final limit of development" (Ms. E III 10, p. 18). For
Husserl, however, God is never practically realizable. See Strasser, op. cit., p. 142.
the statement, "Socrates in the market-place is other than himself at home," Aquinas
writes that the assertion follows because Socrates varies "according to his existence
(esse), i.e., according the principle that accepts the prior and the posterior" (In I Sent. d.
19, q. 2, a. 2, Solutio; ed. P. Mandonnet, Paris, 1929, I, 470). This means that the
otherness of his esse is the otherness of the now in which he finds himself. The fact that
this now is constantly departing into pastness and, thus, requires constant replacement
distinguishes his esse from that of God. The latter's now is an "eternal now." His now
does not depart, which means that "... the divine being is per se stationary (stans) ..."
Notes
562
(Ibid., d. 11, q. 1, a. 1, Solut., ed. cit., I, 63). In distinction to finite beings, God,
Aquinas asserts, has none of his nowness or existence outside of himself. Speaking of
the "perfection of the divine existence (esse)," he writes: "That of which there is nothing
outside of itself is perfect" -- i.e., complete. "But our existence has something outside of
itself, for it lacks that which presently precedes it and what is future. But in the divine
existence there is nothing past or future. Hence his total existence is perfect; and because
of this, existence more properly pertains to him than others" (Ibid., d. 8, q. 1, a. 1. Solut.,
ed. cit., I, 195). The contingency of a finite being, follows once we admit that esse can
relatively according to the times that are other than the present" (In I Perihermeneias,
lect. 5, no. 22). Thus, our existence outside of the present -- our existence "according to
a past or future time" -- is only existence in a relative sense (Ibid., lect. 3, no. 13). Our
esse simpliciter or actual existence is existence in the present. Since our present does
depart into pastness, making us "outside" of ourselves, this esse or existence is contingent
on our present being renewed. This renewal, we may note, is not something
predetermined by our essence. For Aquinas, our essence, as other than our existence, is
other than our present nowness. Thus, presence or existence in a given time is an
in this or that time is an accidental predicate" (In X Metaph., lect. 3, no. 1982).
How far Husserl was aware of this parallel is not known. He is, however,
reported as saying: "In spite of everything, I once believed -- today , it is more than
belief, today it is the knowledge -- that precisely my phenomenology, and only this, is
the philosophy which the church can use -- this, because it goes together with Thomisim
and extends Thomistic philosophy" ("Gespräche," ed. cit., p. 55, entry recorded on Sept.
4, 1935). This claim of an advance may refer to Husserl's belief that he has provided a
25. The analogy, here, is with calculus. When x = 1, x 2-1/x-1 is not defined;
than as a negative prohibition, that tolerance defines a morality that is different from the
Kantian. Its positive position is, perhaps, closest to the humanism (humanitas) of the
ancient world as exemplified by the statement: "I am human, I deem nothing human
manner of Heidegger's "Brief über den 'Humanismus'." It is not something that demands
following snatch of dialogue from Huckleberry Finn. Huck: It warn't the grounding --
that didn't keep us back but a little. We blowed out a cylinder head. Aunt Sally: Good
gracious! anybody hurt? Huck: No'm. Killed a nigger. Aunt Sally: Well, it's lucky;
because sometimes people do get hurt. Mark Twain, Huckleberry Finn, ch. 32; Signet
28. For Husserl, the "... problematic ... of the irrationality of the transcendal
fact which expresses itself in the constitution of the factual world and factual mental life"
is "metaphysics in a new sense" (EP I, 1923-24, ed. R. Boehm, HA VII, Haag, 1956, p.
188, note). Since radical evil is part of such irrationality, involving as it does a regress of
reason, the question of its ground can be called "metaphysical" in this new sense. What
is new about this metaphysics is its confrontation with irrationality, i.e., with the
transcendence. Hence, the very possibility of radical evil is an argument against Deupre's
position that Husserl envisages "a God who is identical with transcendental subjectivity"
(See above, ). If this were the case, then radical evil would not result in what we
called "the withdrawal of God." This leads us to note the theodicy implicit in Husserl's
position. The question of how God could permit evil to exist is, here, reduced to that of
how He could permit the existence of finitude. In other words, as long as we accept the
necessity of the distinction between God and creatures, we have to accept the possibility
of evil.
30. There is a certain analogy between this state and Heidegger's notion of
"insistence." The latter involves a "forgetting of the totality of being (des Seiendem in
Ganzen)" and an insistence that the part which we already know is this totality. See
"Vom Wesen der Wahrheit," Wegmarken, Frankfurt am Main, 1967, p. 91). A much
in this petty pace from day to day to the last syllable of recorded time ..." ( Macbeth, Act
V, scene v., 11. 18-20). Macbeth has, through intolerance, emptied out his horizons.