Chicago Unbound Chicago Unbound
Chicago Unbound Chicago Unbound
Chicago Unbound Chicago Unbound
Chicago Unbound
1996
Recommended Citation
Richard A. Epstein, "The Tort/Crime Distinction: A Generation Later," 76 Boston University Law Review 1
(1996).
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Chicago Unbound. It has been
accepted for inclusion in Journal Articles by an authorized administrator of Chicago Unbound. For more
information, please contact unbound@law.uchicago.edu.
SYMPOSIUM
THE TORTICRIME DISTINCTION:
A GENERATION LATER
RICHARD A. EPSTEIN*
tions of property. The tort law should seek to protect these same inter-
ests against all other external deprivations, including many that are
strictly accidental, by awarding money damages to the victim from the
wrongdoer. In some cases of imminent danger injunctive relief could be
appropriate as well, although the issue of prospective3 relief injects a mass
of complications to which I shall briefly refer later.
Over the years, I have remained quite content with the basic substan-
tive orientation of the tort/crime distinction, but have become more un-
easy about its intellectual foundations. My ideal government is not quite
as small as the above theory suggests, but it is still much smaller than the
massive government in place today. The shifts in basic intellectual out-
look are perhaps more substantial. On the political theory side, a robust
libertarian theory is vulnerable to the charge that it fails to account for
the coordination, public goods, and holdout problems4 of such great con-
cern in the organization of social affairs. Thus it is not sufficient to as-
sume that the only forms of conduct accompanied by undesirable social
consequences are those involving the use of force or fraud. The libertari-
an posture seeks to minimize the use of force and fraud and their conse-
quences. However, a more comprehensive social statement seeks to max-
imize social welfare, embracing the libertarian prohibitions, but going
beyond them to allow certain forms of regulation and taxation to over-
come these otherwise intractable coordination problems. The set of
forced exactions that are totally barred under a libertarian approach have
a limited, but secure place in the larger system of social controls.
Similarly, on questions of method, I believe that the deontological ap-
proach is wrong insofar as it claims that its normative conclusions can be
denied only on pain of self-contradiction. Today many writers believe
that the protection of individual autonomy is not a primary goal of legal
rules, but that, to the contrary, any "natural" distribution of talents is
determined largely by luck and hence morally arbitrary.' Given this per-
spective, it follows that legal rules should introduce certain measures of
sharing across individuals, if not by forced labor, then by systems of taxa-
tion and regulation that redistribute the fruits of individual labor.' One
can argue against these views, but hardly on the ground that they are self-
contradictory, or even that they are morally suspect in their effort to raise
the level of the least fortunate closer to the level enjoyed by those who
have a greater share of natural abilities and endowments. A defense of
the older regime of individual liberties and properties cannot rest on a
simple assertion that people have rights and that other individuals are not
allowed to do actions that violate those rights.7 One has to show why
any given configuration of rights is superior to its rival conceptions, an
undertaking that typically requires an appeal to consequences, less for
particular cases, and more for some overall assessment of how alternative
legal regimes play out in the long run. In a word, one has to become a
utilitarian of some stripe to justify rules in terms of the consequences they
bring about.'
A utilitarian approach is frequently attacked on the ground that the
critical outcomes needed to fuel the system are invariably indeterminate.
In many legal contexts, the choice of legal rules is hard to make, but the
inferences we can draw from a select set of difficult legal cases are far
from obvious. More concretely, it is only when individuals look to some
of the hardest questions within the legal system-whether we choose neg-
ligence or strict liability as the basic principle of tort law-that we find
both our moral instincts and our utilitarian calculations coming up short.
But those hard cases are not the ones we should chose initially to test the
moral limits of a legal rule. Rather the operative inquiry steps back a
long way and asks: Why, of all the possible tort rules that could organize
the system of tort law, do those two survive in constant tension with each
other? At this level it is not difficult to imagine the adverse consequences
of a rule requiring the victim of harm to pay damages equal to the harm
that he sustained to the party that inflicted the harm. This rule might be
ingeniously justified on the ground that it induces a high degree of victim
precaution. But don't bet on its social appeal. It takes little temerity to
say that no legal system will ever adopt so odd a position, given the mas-
sive insecurity generated by subsidizing individuals to maim or kill their
fellow human beings. Likewise a rule declaring that all promises are pre-
sumptively criminal acts would not sit well either: it is simply too costly
for the legal system to declare war on the mutual gains arising from ordi-
nary exchanges. Sometimes these presumptive gains are overridden by
9 THOMAS HOBBES, LEVIATHAN 86-96 (A.R. Walker ed., Cambridge Univ. Press
1935) (1651).
10 JOHN LOCKE, SECOND TREATISE OF GOVERNMENT 3-10 (Richard H. Cox ed.,
Harlan Davidson, Inc. 1982) (1689).
11 HOBBES, supra note 9, at 115-19.
12 The ex ante constraint is surely decisive because any system that imposes crimi-
nal sanctions on aggressors will not leave violators well off ex post. Indeed, one of the
greatest perils to any system of contract-voluntary or hypothetical-is the institu-
tionalization of a general principle of ex post regret, whereby those who do not like
the observed outcomes can undo the entire arrangement. When that regret contin-
gency is Imown in advance, the initial deal will not get off the ground because no one
will regard himself as a potential winner.
are subject to either civil or criminal liability. The same has surely been
true with respect to nuisances, such as the discharge of pollutants on land,
water, or air. Yet the potential liabilities accompanying the newer envi-
ronmental restrictions go far beyond those associated with traditional
wrongs such as nuisance or pollution. Today it is wrong to place a railway
tie on the side of a critical dune unless one first receives a permit from the
state,' 4 and it is a criminal offense to modify the habitat of any endan-
gered species located on private property.'" It hardly matters what dan-
gerous conditions are corrected or what collateral benefits are created.
Because there is rarely a particular harm to any one person, the set of
sanctions tends to be criminal in nature. But the core objection to this
form of criminal liability does not rest on the observation that these of-
fenses are strict liability offenses, although that is sometimes the case.
Nor does it rest on the possibility that individuals may not receive suffi-
cient notice that the law deems the designated conduct criminal. They
often receive an abundance of notice; public officials are always willing to
proclaim their commands from the mountain tops in order to satisfy the
most exacting due process requirements. And surely the statutes could
incorporate, explicitly or by implication, a narrow exception for cases of
abject necessity, which would seem pointless if the crime in question is
removing a rubber tire from a wetland under the jurisdiction of the Army
Corps of Engineers.
No, the objection to the criminal sanction quite simply comes from the
deep and passionate belief that government should not undertake these
exercises at control at all, or at the very least, that if it intrudes on the
lives of its individual citizens, then it should compensate them for the
losses it imposes.16 This position follows the argument on state control
outlined above.' 7 Start with a world in which disputes between neighbors
are regulated by the law of nuisance and ask whether the further regula-
tion works on balance to the joint improvement of the parties. Certain
rule adjustments surely make sense, which helps explain why privately
planned unit developments usually adopt covenants more extensive than
those required under the law of nuisance. Yet the legal restrictions men-
tioned above are more intrusive still, but their gains to affected parties
are small or nonexistent. As between the parties, we may describe the
transactions as Pareto Pessimal, meaning that both neighbors end up
worse off than before, without any enormous positive external gains to
put aside the entire issue of drug offenses. 21 The first step in the argu-
ment is to show why traditional tort law will no longer do the job. Quite
simply, the answer is that there are no victims to whom a tort remedy
could be sensibly assigned. Consider once again the issues of land use
control and worker safety regulation. Turning first to land use regulation,
precisely who is hurt if an individual owner decides to turn over some soil
or build a stairway up the side of a hill? Clearly it is not the neighbors,
most of whom have engaged in similar conduct (before the restriction was
imposed) or who currently chafe under like restrictions. To be sure,
neighbors do not always get along in this or any other world, so that at
least some neighbors might well be inclined to report violators to public
officials in order to exact a fair measure of vengeance against them. But
those sorts of indirect unhappiness do not count as compensable or pro-
tectable interests under either the tort or the criminal law. So, too, with
harms to the "environment:" no private plaintiffs stand ready and avail-
able to police them. Consequently, it falls to the government by default
to fill the void said to exist. Further, in this case the government sues
only as the government, rather than in its capacity (analogous to the pri-
vate landowner) as steward or owner of public lands and waters. The
utter want of a definable, focused wrong thus propels these cases into a
large and unstructured public arena.
The second stage of the argument is more difficult. The government
can proceed in its own name to remedy the perceived wrong with either
civil fines or criminal actions. In principle it would seem that when tort
law normally remedies the relevant harm, civil fines should be the pre-
ferred public response. We utilize public officials to decrease enforce-
ment costs rather than to escalate conflicts with individual defendants.
To be sure, most regulatory statutes provide for civil penalties.
Yet enforcement rarely stops there. Instead, such statutes allow the
state-at its option-to pursue the criminal route, either by way of fine
or imprisonment. The expansion of power is often justified in part by the
fact that most of the prohibited acts are done intentionally, and hence fit
more easily in the criminal camp. We expand the scope of the actus reus
without any offsetting contraction of the relevant mens rea.
This "double whammy" is hardly defensible when the underlying con-
duct should not be subject to any sanctions at all. But once we take the
first step, the second comes easily. After all, ordinary criminal prosecu-
tions do not allow a defense for ignorance of law. It is quite enough to
intend to do the act that the law has declared harmful. The approach has
great merit as a means to dispose of false pleas of ignorance for conven-
21 On which I am tempted by a standard that eliminates all punishment for use, all
public aid for illegal drug users, and all defenses of diminished responsibility based on
drug use. See Richard A. Epstein, The Moral and Practical Dilemmas of an Under-
ground Economy, 103 YALu L.J. 2157, 2175-76 (1994).
22 For a recent anecdotal indictment of the follies of OSHA, see PHILIP K. How-
ARD, THE DEATH OF COMMON SENSE 12-15 (1994) (commenting on the scope and
specificity of OSHA regulations and the massive expenditures made by employers to
reach mandated compliance levels).
23 E.g., id.
Some actions still remain illegal even under standard libertarian theo-
ry, aided perhaps by a limited assist from the antitrust laws. How should
control of these wrongs be divided between tort and criminal law? In
principle, the utilitarian overlay24 looks to maximize some social welfare
function. The upshot is to use criminal and tort law to optimize the net
gain from productive activities, less the sum of the costs of harmful ones
and the costs of their prevention. The dialogue then switches to the fa-
miliar litany of optimal deterrence, which envisions harm from both
under- and over-enforcement of the law (criminal and tort) and hopes to
steer a path between the two.25 Questions of individual rights, so conge-
nial to the traditional deontological approach, are swept away by a set of
instrumental and technical concerns. The connection between the ordi-
nary expectations of citizens is washed away in a sea of jargon. The com-
prehensibility and legitimacy of the law, both criminal and civil, are sorely
tested. Or so the standard story goes.
Lest we despair, I believe that we can make the jargon intelligible. Just
as the techniques of social contract theory are equal to the task of defin-
ing individual rights, they can also explain why the traditional view of the
26 See H.L.A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW 181 (1961) (observing that the devel-
opment of law has been "profoundly influenced" by moral discourse, but that legal
validity need not be explicitly tied to morality).
27 See, e.g., POSNER, supra note 4, at 119-77.
28 See J.H. BAKER, AN INTRODUCTION TO ENGLISH LEGAL HISTORY 571 (3d ed.
1990) ("In early societies there is no concept of the 'state.' Both compensation and
retribution for wrongdoing are exacted at the instance of the wronged individual and
his kin.").
pie accident cases. But through it all, the basic intuition remains true: For
accidental harms at least, a system that puts the full burden of enforce-
ment on the injured plaintiff works better than a system of state prosecu-
tion for harms to discrete individuals. The private plaintiff has good
knowledge of the facts-or at least better knowledge than anyone else-
and strong incentives to prosecute the matter to judgment. So as a first
approximation the traditional tort system looks optimal despite its imper-
fections. Thus we can take some comfort in the older cases that stressed
the dominance of tort in cases of accidental harms.29
The same view seems to flow from liberal political theory. It is easy to
forget that one of the major issues in the classical treatments of political
philosophy concerned the scope of tort and crime, and setting the appro-
priate limits to the doctrine of self-defense, whose contours are of great
importance in the state of nature, that is, prior to the effective introduc-
tion of police forces. In this regard, it is useful to note that the Lockean
view draws a similar distinction between tortious and criminal behavior.
It is worth quoting the familiar and illuminating passages:
10. Besides the crime which consists in violating the law, and vary-
ing from the right rule of reason, whereby a man so far becomes
degenerate, and declares himself to quite the principles of human
nature and to be a noxious creature, there is commonly injury done
to some person or other, and some other man receives damage by his
transgression, in which case he who hath received any damage, has
besides the right of punishment common to him with other men, a
particular right to seek reparation from him that has done it. And
any other person who finds it just, may also join with him that is
injured, and assist him in recovering from the offender, so much as
may make satisfaction for the harm he has suffered.
11. From these two distinct rights, the one of punishing the crime
for restraint, and preventing the like offence, which right of punish-
ing is in everybody; the other taking reparation,which belongs only
to the injured party, comes it to pass that the magistrate, who by
being magistrate hath the common right of punishing put into his
hands, can often, where the public good demands not the execution
of the law, remit the punishment of criminal offenses by his own au-
29E.g., Hulle v. Orynge, Mich. 6 Edw. 4, fol. 7, pl. 18 (1466), reprinted in J.H.
BAKER & S.F.C. MILsOM, SOURCES OF ENGLISH LEGAL HISTORY 327, 330 (1986). A
participant in that case observed:
[I]f a man is shooting at the butts and his bow swerves in his hand and [the arrow]
kills a man, against his will, this (as has been said) is not a felony. If, however, he
injures a man by his archery, the man shall have a good action of trespass against
him: and yet the archery was lawful, and the injury which the other suffered was
against his will.
Id.; see also Weaver v. Ward, 80 Eng. Rep. 284 (K.B. 1616) (applying a similar distinc-
tion to the insanity defense that, although irrelevant in tort, is critical in criminal law).
30 LOCKE, supra note 10, at 6-7. The references to the transition from collective
punishment by individuals to collective punishment by magistrates marks the transi-
tion from a state of nature. Of course noxious beasts could be killed with impunity,
and the parallel Locke draws between such conduct and private enforcement of one's
interests in the state of nature is an intentional one. Id. at 7. Further, the deadly
punishments are allowed for lesser offenses, if such is needed for public safety. Id.
("[E]ach transgression may be punished to that degree, and with so much severity as
will suffice to make it an ill bargain to the offender ...
31 Id. (emphasis omitted).
32 E.g., RICHARD A. EPSTEIN, CASES AND MATERIALS ON TORTS 35-39 (6th ed.
1995).
aa See Kenneth Mann, Punitive Civil Sanctions: The Middle Ground Between Crim-
inal and Civil Law, 101 YALE L.J. 1795, 1861-71 (1992) (assessing the impact of the
expansion of civil punitive damages on the tort/criminal law distinction).
37 A similar issue arises in the tort law. Compensation in cases with a less than
50% chance that the defendant causes the harm in question depends on our treatment
of cases where the likelihood of causation by a defendant is greater than 50%. If
there is full compensation in the 50%-plus cases, then there should be no enforcement
in the 50%-minus cases, at least if deterrence is the goal of the civil system. But if we
utilize partial compensation for the 50%-plus cases, then we should use it across the
board. Whether that response is appropriate depends on the distribution of cases
around the 50% point. If all individual cases are below the 50% level, the result will
be underdeterrence unless we effect some adjustment. However, complications of
this sort are hard to work into popular morals.
have been guilty in this short Paper. Notwithstanding the rise of law and
economics in the academy, most people are more or less where I was on
legal thinking when I first addressed the tort/crime distinction in 1977.
They accept a strong categorical distinction between accidental and delib-
erate harms, and recognize that the latter are dangerous enough to re-
quire public control.
A major challenge to this distinction lies in the endless number of tort
suits against institutional defendants, all claiming that something more
than accidental harm is at stake. The most expensive words in the tort
lexicon are "send them a message," with its attendant invitation to puni-
tive damages as well as hefty compensatory damages. Although overused
and misused on particular occasions, the phrase has at least one saving
grace: it reminds us that most people have some sense of the deterrence
value associated with imposing both tort and criminal liability. It reminds
us that, for firms as well as individuals, reputational loss-that ubiquitous
stigma-delivers a large part of the total sanction. Once we have in-
voked "the message," it becomes increasingly difficult to defend the posi-
tion that social consequences and social utility-real or perceived-have
no bearing on popular views about civil and criminal liability.
Can these impulses be folded into a model that assigns to the criminal
law an expressive or condemnatory role missing from tort law? At one
level, the looming threat of punitive damages in tort settings constantly
blurs the distinction between the two systems. Many tort cases give rise
to expressive or condemnatory actions as well. But for these purposes, a
more vexing inquiry is whether the criminal law-even at its core-truly
reflects a social effort to regenerate fundamental norms by publicly con-
demning those who violate them. At some level, every society has to face
the task of reaffirming its values and beliefs during times of crisis. Funer-
al services that remind us of the sacrifices by those who have fallen victim
to senseless violence surely fill this role, as does the ultimate conviction of
an assailant.
But my own hunch is that the centrality of the criminal law to these
functions is limited. The enormous amount of self-examination and re-
crimination in Israel following the assassination of Prime Minister Yitzak
Rabin began at the instant of his untimely death and continued unabated
through the funeral services. It reached a fever pitch long before the be-
ginning of the trial of his assailant, Yigal Amir. Of course, this trial will
fall into the public spotlight. Yet there is little reason to think that its
inevitable outcome will shape Israeli or world opinion on the central
question of whether, and if so how, the harsh debate over peace with
Palestine induced-or drove?-Amir to commit cold-blooded murder.
Most criminal trials are not show trials. Often they involve acts of vio-
lence that ordinary people down on their luck commit on their fellow
citizens. In most cases the criminal system strains to keep up with the
inflow of business. Under these circumstances, the instrumental role of
criminal trials-locking people up-necessarily comes to dominate any