The Great Debate - Edmund Burke, Thomas Paine

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 254

Copyright

© 2014 by Yuval Levin Published by Basic Books, A Member of the Perseus Books Group All
rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written
permission except in the case of brief quotations embodied in critical articles and reviews. For information,
address Basic Books, 250 West 57th Street, 15th Floor, New York, NY 10107.

Books published by Basic Books are available at special discounts for bulk purchases in the United States
by corporations, institutions, and other organizations. For more information, please contact the Special
Markets Department at the Perseus Books Group, 2300 Chestnut Street, Suite 200, Philadelphia, PA 19103,
or call (800) 810-4145, ext. 5000, or e-mail special.markets@perseusbooks.com.

Designed by Linda Mark The Library of Congress has catalogued the hardcover as follows: Levin, Yuval.
The great debate : Edmund Burke, Thomas Paine, and the birth of right and left / Yuval Levin.
pages cm Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 978-0-465-04094-0 (e-book) 1. United States--Politics and government. 2. Right and left
(Political science) 3. Political science—Philosophy. 4. Burke, Edmund, 1729–1797—Political and social
views. 5. Paine, Thomas, 1737–1809—Political and social views. I. Title.
JK275.L5 2013
320.50973—dc23

10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
For Cecelia, with love
CONTENTS

Preface
Introduction

ONE TWO LIVES IN THE ARENA


TWO NATURE AND HISTORY
THREE JUSTICE AND ORDER
FOUR CHOICE AND OBLIGATION
FIVE REASON AND PRESCRIPTION
SIX REVOLUTION AND REFORM
SEVEN GENERATIONS AND THE LIVING

Conclusion
Acknowledgments
Notes
Bibliography
Index
PREFACE

N ITS SURFACE, AMERICAN POLITICS THESE DAYS CAN seem

O impossibly complicated. We confront a bewildering array of public


policy problems, each impenetrably convoluted in itself and largely
disconnected from the others. Who could simultaneously understand the
intricacies of our tax code, the inefficiencies of our entitlement system, the
inadequacies of our transportation infrastructure, the moral challenges presented
by the abortion debate, and the ins and outs of the dozens of other prominent
public questions demanding our attention?
I make my living as a combatant in these policy debates. I am the editor of a
quarterly journal about domestic policy and a think-tank scholar who studies
health care, entitlement reform, the federal budget, and similarly wonkish fare. I
have worked on these issues as a policy staffer at the White House (under
George W. Bush) and as a member of the staffs of several Republican members
of Congress. And in doing so, I have found that making sense of these debates
requires more than an immersion in the technical details. It requires a sense of
how the different policy dilemmas that confront our society relate to one another
and why they so frequently divide us as they do.
The way they divide us, after all, is hardly arbitrary. It is not by coincidence
that people who tend to agree with one another on one set of issues (say, how to
deal with the deficit) often also agree on others (like how to reform American
education) that do not seem obviously connected. There are exceptions, to be
sure, but conservatives and liberals—and therefore often Republicans and
Democrats—fairly consistently find themselves on opposite sides of contentious
debates on a very broad range of subjects, from economic policy to social policy
to the environment, the culture, and countless other public questions. The
political right and left often seem to represent genuinely distinct points of view,
and our national life seems almost by design to bring to the surface questions
that divide them.
I have long been intrigued by the sources and nature of those distinct points
of view. And since the thick of the fight is not always the best vantage point for
understanding what moves our politics, the search for some answers at one point
took me away from Washington for a time, to pursue a Ph.D. in political
philosophy at the University of Chicago. In studying the work of the West’s
great political thinkers, I became persuaded that the complicated policy debates
that take place on the surface of our politics are moved not just by partisan
passions or economic interests but by deeper questions that, perhaps ironically,
can be much more accessible to average citizens. These debates pose moral and
philosophical questions regarding what each of us takes to be true and important
about human life and how this influences our expectations of politics. We may
not think about these deeper questions explicitly every time we approach a
contemporary political issue, but how we answer such questions shapes the great
political debates of our day.
That such questions should underlie our political life, however, does not
itself explain why the citizens of our republic should coalesce around two clearly
discernible and fairly coherent sets of answers. Why, then, is there a left and a
right in our politics? This book hopes to offer the beginning of an answer to that
question. That beginning is both historical and philosophical, and so this book is,
too.
It is historical in that it seeks to understand where we are by considering
where we came from. And in our particular political tradition, seeking out where
we came from often means beginning our search in the late eighteenth century—
that extraordinary era of the American Revolution and the French Revolution
that together helped to shape the modern world.
It is philosophical because it contends that what we can learn from that era is
above all a way of thinking about the most basic and timeless dilemmas of
society and politics. This book therefore looks at Anglo-American politics
during the age of America’s founding—a subject of justifiably unending
fascination—from an unusual angle and tries to expose some unfamiliar features
of it.
The historical and the philosophical in this case intersect not in the abstract
but in the real lives of two people whose thoughts and actions helped define the
right and the left at their origins. This book tells the stories of their lives and
times and carefully considers their ideas and arguments. Edmund Burke and
Thomas Paine lived in an era defined by a seemingly interminable succession of
intense political crises, and both men were deeply involved in a great many of
them both as thinkers and as actors. In the process, each laid out a vision of the
world and especially a way of thinking about political change. In some important
ways, Burke and Paine laid out the beginnings of the right and the left,
respectively. The implicit and often explicit debate between them therefore
offers us a glimpse into the origins of our political divisions. This book is thus a
case study in how ideas move history and in where some of the key ideas that
have moved, and still move, our history came from.
To point to the historical and philosophical roots of our political debates is
not to stand apart from or above those debates. On the contrary, I have been
drawn to the questions that animate this book precisely because I have played a
modest part in some political debates myself. I’m a conservative, and I would
not pretend to leave my worldview at the door while I explore the foundations of
our political order. But a conservative must take an interest in his own society’s
traditions, and our political tradition has always contained both the left and the
right—each passionately advancing its understanding of the common good. I am
therefore a conservative who is deeply interested in understanding both the left
and the right as they truly are, and I strive here to tell their stories in a way that
both liberals and conservatives today might recognize as meaningful and true,
and from which both might learn something about themselves and their political
adversaries.
The origins of the left-right divide, of course, are not the same as its current
incarnation. The differences between today’s political divisions and those of
Burke and Paine’s era are at least as fascinating and numerous as their
similarities. I hope to encourage both sides of our political divide to reflect on
the path we have traveled. What might we each learn from our (and our
opponents’) intellectual progenitors, and what crucial insights might we have
forgotten with time but would do well to recall? Above all, though, I hope this
story might help fellow citizens of any political persuasion approach American
politics with greater understanding and confidence. I hope to help the reader see
that although many arguments that boil at the surface are technical and
complicated, they are moved by deep permanent questions that are not only
important but also awfully interesting.
INTRODUCTION

NYONE TRACING THE PEDIGREE OF OUR POLITICAL ideas

A must be struck by the importance, and by the sheer eventfulness, of the


late eighteenth century. Between about 1770 and 1800, many of the
crucial concepts, terms, divisions, and arguments that still define our
political life seemed to burst into the world in fierce and fiery succession.
This was the era of the American Revolution and the French Revolution, and
we have long since fallen into the comfortable habit of attributing the explosion
of political philosophy and drama of that time to those monumental upheavals.
The American Revolution—the first successful colonial revolt in history—gave
birth to a creedal nation embodying the idealism of the Enlightenment, whereas
the French Revolution launched in earnest the modern quest for social progress
through unyielding political action guided by uncompromising philosophical
principle. In these great crucibles of revolution was forged the frame of modern
politics, or so the argument goes.
There is of course much truth to this cliché, but it is a partial, or perhaps a
secondhand, truth. In fact, the late eighteenth century was the scene of a great
Anglo-American debate about the meaning of modern liberalism—a debate that
has since shaped the political life of Britain and America, and by now that of a
great and growing portion of humanity beyond them. The American Revolution
embodied that debate, and the French Revolution intensified it, but the debate
preceded them both and has long outlasted them.
The ideals of the American founding were championed by statesmen-
revolutionaries who disagreed among themselves about the practical significance
of those ideals. The disagreements did not take long to surface and to break the
politics of the new republic into distinct camps that in many ways have endured.
The actual parties to the struggle in France, meanwhile, the Jacobins and
Girondists, monarchists and aristocrats, have no real parallels in contemporary
politics. But the parties to the intense Anglo-American debate about the French
Revolution—a party of justice and a party of order, or a party of progress and a
party of conservation—bear a plain paternal resemblance to the parties that now
compose the politics of many liberal democracies, including our own. In both
cases, the parties to the great debate of the late eighteenth century clearly
prefigured key elements of the left-right divide of our time. The arguments
between them had to do with much more than the particular promise and peril of
the American or French revolutions, and they have lasted because they brought
to the surface a disagreement within liberalism that has never lost its salience.
There are no perfect representatives of the two major parties to the great
debate of that age, but there may well be no better representatives than Edmund
Burke and Thomas Paine. Burke was an Irish-born English politician and writer,
a man of intense opinions with an unrivaled gift for expressing them in political
rhetoric. He was his era’s most devoted and able defender of the inherited
traditions of the English constitution. A patient, gradual reformer of his country’s
institutions, he was among the first and surely the most adamant and effective
critics of the radicalism of the French Revolution in English politics.
Paine, an English-born immigrant to America, became one of the most
eloquent and important voices championing the cause of independence for the
colonies, and then, as revolution brewed in France, he became an influential
advocate of the revolutionaries’ cause as an essayist and activist in Paris and
London. A master of the English language, Paine fervently believed in the
potential of Enlightenment liberalism to advance the cause of justice and peace
by uprooting corrupt and oppressive regimes and replacing them with
governments answerable to the people. He was a brilliant and passionate
advocate for liberty and equality.
Each was both a man of ideas and a man of action—a man of powerful
political rhetoric and of deep and principled commitment to a cause. Each also
saw in the debates of the age far more than the particulars of the events that
launched them. The two men knew each other, met several times, exchanged
letters, and publicly answered one another’s published writings. Their private
and public dispute over the French Revolution has been called “perhaps the most
crucial ideological debate ever carried on in English.”1 But their profound
disagreement extends well beyond their direct confrontations. Each voiced a
worldview deeply at odds with the other over some of the most important
questions of liberal-democratic political thought. While the capacious arguments
of the time surely could not be fully captured in the debate between Burke and
Paine, the important questions at stake can be far better understood by
examining the two men’s views with care. And yet the precise terms and subjects
of their disagreement (especially as it relates to matters other than the French
Revolution itself) remain to a surprising degree underexamined.
This book seeks to examine Burke and Paine’s disagreement and to learn
from it about both their era’s politics and ours. Using not only their dispute about
the French Revolution but also the two men’s larger bodies of writing and
correspondence, the book will explore the themes of the Burke-Paine dispute,
taking apart each man’s views of history, nature, society, reason, political
institutions, freedom, equality, rights, and other key subjects, and seeking the
premises informing each one’s understanding of political life. It will argue that
Burke and Paine each offers a coherent and, for the most part, internally
consistent case about the character of society and politics, and that each man’s
case is greatly illuminated by contrasting it with the other’s. It will demonstrate
that Burke’s and Paine’s diverse arguments are tied together especially by a
disagreement about the authority of the given past in political life—and that
there is much more to this disagreement than a staid and simple dispute between
tradition and progress.
Burke’s reforming conservatism and Paine’s restoring progressivism are both
more complex and more coherent than they first appear. And a careful
consideration of both can clarify the terms of our own debates, especially the
fundamental dividing line of our politics. As Burke and Paine will show us, the
line between progressives and conservatives really divides two kinds of liberals
and two distinct visions of the liberal society.2

IT MAY SEEM STRANGE to seek philosophical arguments in the words of two


men so deeply involved in day-to-day politics. We are not used to political actors
who are also political theorists. Such actors were certainly a bit more common in
Burke’s and Paine’s era—when in both Britain and America we encounter some
politicians who wrote and thought like philosophers—but they were still very
much a rare breed even then. And because nearly all of Burke’s and Paine’s
pamphlets, speeches, letters, and books were written with some immediate
political purpose in mind even as they made larger arguments, scholars of both
men’s views have battled over some very basic questions through the centuries.
In Burke’s case, the leading question has been whether he had a consistent
set of views throughout his life or whether the French Revolution transformed
him somehow. As we will see, Burke spent the first two decades of his political
career championing various sorts of reform: of the British government’s
finances, its treatment of religious minorities, its trade policy, and more. He
spent much of this time pushing against the standing inertia of English politics.
But after the revolution in France, which he was concerned might be imported to
Britain, Burke was above all a staunch defender of Britain’s political traditions.
He strenuously opposed all efforts to weaken the power of the monarch and the
aristocracy and warned against fundamental political reforms (like moves toward
greater democratization) that might unmoor the nation from its long-standing
traditions. He has sometimes been accused, therefore, of changing his most basic
views and turning against his former co-partisans and friends. The charge could
first be heard in his own lifetime (voiced by Paine, among others) and has been
repeated by some of Burke’s biographers and interpreters ever since.
But such a charge miscasts both Burke’s earlier and later views, neglecting
the arguments he offered both as a reformer and as a conserver of Britain’s
political tradition. Those arguments were always about finding a balance
between stability and change—the quest that, as we will see, was at the core of
Burke’s ambitions. In the concluding words of his Reflections on the Revolution
in France, clearly foreseeing the coming charge of inconsistency, Burke
described himself as “one who wishes to preserve consistency, but who would
preserve consistency by varying his means to secure the unity of his end, and,
when the equipoise of the vessel in which he sails may be endangered by
overloading it upon one side, is desirous of carrying the small weight of his
reasons to that which may preserve its equipoise.”3
This image of the man seeking to balance his ship—or to balance his country
in a sea of troubles—against various threats to its cherished equipoise, is fitting,
in light of Burke’s varied causes and arguments throughout his eventful career.
He was a reformer when some elements of the English constitution threatened to
suffocate the whole. He was a preserver when it seemed to him, as David
Bromwich has put it, “that revolution is the ultimate enemy of reform.”4
Equipoise, for Burke, is not stagnation, but rather a way of thinking about
change and reform, and about political life more generally. As we will see, it was
a central metaphor of his political thought.
Regarding Thomas Paine, meanwhile, the leading question that has divided
scholars has run even deeper: Is Paine really a political thinker or just a
particularly passionate pamphleteer and agitator? While his rhetorical skills are
unquestionable, Paine’s seriousness—his contention with genuine political ideas
—has sometimes been brought into doubt. Critics in his own time sought to
dismiss him as a rabid sloganeer or, as Burke himself put it, a man with “not
even a moderate portion of learning of any kind.”5 And some scholars since then
have repeated the charge that Paine brought more heat than light to the subjects
he took up.
But such accusations have always been tinged with a revealing snobbery.
They have been made by political opponents who considered Paine’s philosophy
unserious and who have therefore been inclined to see its champions—especially
those who do not answer to the traditional description of the learned philosopher
—as unserious as well. Certainly, Paine was not the erudite intellectual that
Burke was. His formal education was minimal, and his engagement with the
philosophical tradition of the West bore the telltale rough edges of the
autodidact. One gets the sense that Paine took a sardonic pleasure in his peculiar,
if plainly false, boast that in all his prolific years of writing, “I neither read
books, nor studied other people’s opinions; I thought for myself.”6 (Paine’s
friend Thomas Jefferson repeated a version of this backhanded praise when he
noted that Paine always “thought more than he read.”)7 Paine’s writing is indeed
remarkably (though far from entirely) devoid of explicit references to great
thinkers of the past. Nor did he have the intense and extended exposure to
practical politics that Burke could boast of.
And yet, Paine’s oversized role both in the American Revolution and in the
English-speaking world’s response to the French Revolution was no accident;
nor was it a mere matter of fortunate timing or purely a function of great writing.
On the contrary, Paine’s great rhetorical power came from his ability to bring
even modestly educated readers into contact with profound philosophical
questions and to give those questions an immediacy and intensity that few
political thinkers could match. Paine understood politics as moved by principles,
and he thought that political systems had to answer to the right kinds of
philosophical ideals—especially equality and liberty. However well established
and grand they might be, however deep their roots might reach, all regimes had
to be evaluated by how well they advanced these basic human goods. Thus,
political principles and their instantiation in political actions are key to Paine’s
teaching and present themselves far more prominently in the foreground of his
writing than even in Burke’s. In an 1806 letter, Paine wrote this about himself:
“My motive and object in all my political works, beginning with Common
Sense, the first work I ever published, have been to rescue man from tyranny and
false systems and false principles of government, and enable him to be free and
establish government for himself.”8 Paine sought for the theories and ideas
underlying political life, and argued that only a government that answers to the
right theories and ideas can make any claim to legitimacy.
Precisely because Burke and Paine were both political thinkers and political
actors, their dispute opens a window into the origins of our own political order.
They help us to see how the kinds of arguments made in the heat of a policy
debate relate to the kinds of arguments made in the calm of a philosopher’s
study. And they help us understand how the divisions on display in our everyday
politics came to be.
Burke was always stung by the notion that he and Paine should be
understood together, complaining in one letter to his friend William Elliott of
that bothersome “Citizen Paine, who, they will have it, hunts with me in
couples.”9 But bothered though they might have been by one another, Burke and
Paine may truly be best understood as counterparts. Like the two broad parties to
our own political disputes, they continue to this day to hunt in couples. So let us
join them on the hunt and see what we can learn from them about both their time
and our own.
ONE

TWO LIVES IN THE ARENA

N THE EVENING OF AUGUST 18, 1788, TWO OF THE fiercest

O combatants in the great political debates of the age of revolutions sat


down together for a meal. Although they had given voice to deeply
opposing political ideas for well over a decade, they had not yet quite
grasped the degree of their profound dispute, and their time together, by all
accounts, was pleasant and amicable. “I am just going to dine with the Duke of
Portland, in company with the great American Paine,” Edmund Burke had
written to a friend earlier that day.1 “From the part Mr. Burke took in the
American Revolution,” Thomas Paine would later write, “it was natural that I
should consider him a friend to mankind; and . . . our acquaintance commenced
on that ground.”2 Their acquaintance would end on very different ground, and
their disagreement—which was soon to explode into the open around the French
Revolution—would not only help to define the politics of their age but would
also reverberate through the centuries and around the globe.
It is tempting now to think of those dinner companions that summer evening
as embodiments of the ideas we have come to identify with them, and perhaps to
wonder how they could have tolerated one another’s company, given their
differences. But human beings are more than the sum of their opinions, and
before we can consider what Burke and Paine stood for, we must discover who
they were and get a flavor of the age in which they lived. Doing both will help us
understand how men with such deep differences could at first encounter one
another as fellow travelers of a sort, if not indeed as kindred spirits.
Burke and Paine were both unusual figures in an unusual time. Each was a
man of humble origins who became a celebrated luminary. Each was an outsider
who transformed himself, by force of intellect and personality, into the great
champion of a society in which he was not born. Each was a firebrand and
master of political rhetoric yet was known as much for the force of his
arguments as for the power of his words. And in every sense, Burke and Paine
were men of their time—even if they disagreed vehemently about what their era
represented and where its politics were headed.
In our political imagination, the late eighteenth century is often shrouded in
an almost mystical aura. It was an age teeming with towering political figures
who managed somehow to be simultaneously statesmen and philosophers.
Among his close acquaintances and friends, Thomas Paine could count George
Washington, Thomas Jefferson, James Madison, James Monroe, and many other
legends of the American founding generation. He thought of Benjamin Franklin
as a kind of patron, and Franklin once described Paine as his “adopted political
son.” Burke was well acquainted with Franklin too, having gotten to know him
during Franklin’s time as the representative of the American colonies in London.
And Burke counted among his friends such leading lights of the British
intellectual world as the great writer and moralist Samuel Johnson, the historian
Edward Gibbon, the philosopher and economist Adam Smith, and essentially
every prominent parliamentary and political figure of the day from King George
III on down.
This profusion of philosophical and practical genius did not emerge all at
once by accident. It arose in response to the profound social and political flux of
the age. Even a century after England’s Glorious Revolution had reestablished a
stable Protestant monarchy in London, religious tensions continued to boil just
below the surface throughout the Anglo-American world. And even before the
American and French revolutions shattered the reigning order of Europe, it was
clear to all that the challenge posed to the continent’s political traditions by
Enlightenment ideas about freedom and equality, combined with the challenge
posed to its aristocratic economic arrangements by the gradual emergence of an
industrial manufacturing system, would yield deep and lasting changes on both
sides of the Atlantic.
The nature and character of those changes were at the heart of the debate in
which Burke and Paine would take leading parts. But neither man was by any
means a natural candidate for the part he turned out to play.

“A YOUNG MR. BURKE”

Edmund Burke was born in Dublin, Ireland, most likely in January 1729.3 His
father was a prominent (if never wealthy) attorney and a Protestant, and his
mother was a Catholic from the Nagle family of County Cork. Such mixed
marriages were not unheard of in Ireland in those days, but neither were they
common. His Catholic wife meant that Burke’s father, Richard, could never
reach the pinnacle of Dublin society and that the religious divisions (which
translated, as they still do, to economic and political divisions) in Ireland would
never be far from Edmund’s own view growing up. He was born the same year
that Jonathan Swift described the miserable lot of Ireland’s poor in his Modest
Proposal. While Burke’s family was always reasonably comfortable, he
witnessed real poverty around him. At times, especially during extended visits
with his mother’s rural Catholic relatives, he even observed genuinely grinding
deprivation of a degree barely imaginable to the English aristocrats he would
come to know later in life.
As was the custom in mixed Irish marriages of the time, Burke and his two
brothers were raised in their father’s Anglican faith, while their sister was raised
a Catholic. Burke’s early education was in a Quaker boarding school, where he
showed an early aptitude for poetry and philosophy. In an era of often bitter
divisions (in both England and Ireland) between the official Anglican Church,
Catholicism, and the dissenting Protestant sects (such as the Quakers), Burke
managed in his first fifteen years to travel through all three circles. The
experience of seeing differences of dogma made moot in practice by the bonds
of family affection and neighborly respect was formative for him. It seemed to
leave him with a lasting sense that life was more complicated in practice than in
theory—and that this was a good thing. And his university education, at Dublin’s
renowned Trinity College, grounded this sense of the almost indescribable
complexity of actual living communities in classical learning and a refined
appreciation for philosophy and art.
Although he would spend the great bulk of the rest of his life in England,
these early Irish lessons—along with his distinctive Irish accent—never left
Burke. They helped him always mark a difference between abstract political
ideals and actual life as lived. He retained a sense of how accommodations built
up slowly from reserves of trust, warm sentiment, and moderation could enable
people to live together even in the face of social tension, political oppression,
and economic plight.
His Irish upbringing and education also left Burke with a deep love of
language, the written word in particular. Upon graduation from Trinity, he left
for London, ostensibly to study law at his father’s urging, though he abandoned
his legal studies in short order to pursue his dream of joining the ranks of the
great city’s intellectuals by becoming a writer on large public questions. London
was a hotbed of philosophical and political debates, most often carried on
through pamphlets—lengthy opinion essays (most of which would today qualify
as short books), published and sold very cheaply, often answering one another
and seeking to ground in deeper principles an immediate question of policy.
These pamphlets would swiftly make the rounds of London’s burgeoning café
culture and made for an exhilarating atmosphere of tense engagement with
philosophy and politics.
From his earliest published writing—a lengthy pamphlet called A Vindication
of Natural Society published in 1756—Burke tackled foundational questions of
political life and revealed an inclination to recoil from potentially corrosive
radicalism. The Vindication is a work of satire, lampooning the style of argument
employed by Lord Bolingbroke—an important politician and thinker who had
died a few years earlier, but whose final book, Letters on the Study and Use of
History, had just been published posthumously. The book had been notable for
its criticism of religion, including the official state religion. Bolingbroke had
argued that all organized religions are essentially artificial and therefore
unfounded and that only a simple, natural religion (or Deism) that does not claim
access to revealed truth but merely expresses gratitude to God for the natural
world could be legitimate. He drew a sharp distinction between “natural” and
“artificial” beliefs, championing the former in the name of rational science and
rejecting the latter as groundless dogma. Burke, in his critical satire, emulated
Bolingbroke’s style and case, but applied it to politics, suggesting that all
artificial social institutions should be abandoned. He sought to show where such
ways of arguing would lead if they were allowed to proceed to their logical
conclusions, suggesting that arguments intended to undermine religion by
appealing to a simple notion of nature in opposition to traditional institutions
could also undermine all political authority and social allegiance, dissolving the
bonds that hold societies together.
“What is remarkable in Burke’s first performance,” wrote his great
nineteenth-century biographer John Morley, “is his discernment of the important
fact that behind the intellectual disturbances in the sphere of philosophy, and the
noisier agitations in the sphere of theology, there silently stalked a force that
might shake the whole fabric of civil society itself.”4 A caustic and simplistic
skepticism of all traditional institutions, supposedly grounded in a scientific
rationality that took nothing for granted but in fact willfully ignored the true
complexity of social life, seemed to Burke poorly suited for the study of society,
and even dangerous when applied to it. Burke would warn of, and contend with,
this force for the rest of his life.
The Vindication had displayed Burke’s early tendency to write about
philosophically serious subjects with political and social implications and yet to
do so at some remove from daily politics. This was all the more evident the
following year, 1757, when Burke published his most expressly theoretical work
and his only real book: A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origins of Our Ideas of
the Sublime and the Beautiful. It was an insightful if quirky work of aesthetics—
the study of the human experience of beauty. Burke sought to explain the
distinction between the beautiful (or well formed) and the sublime (or
compelling) as grounded in the difference between love and fear. It was a
surprisingly original contribution to a long-running debate among British
philosophical thinkers about the sources of human perception and experience,
and it opens a door to the young Burke’s emerging political sensibilities. Burke
argues that human nature relies on emotional, not only rational, edification and
instruction—an idea that would become crucial to his insistence that government
must function in accordance with the forms and traditions of a society’s life and
not only abstract principles of justice. “The influence of reason in producing our
passions is nothing near so extensive as it is commonly believed,” Burke
writes.5 We are moved by more than logic, and so politics must answer to more
than cold arguments.
Both of Burke’s works enjoyed moderate success and helped him make a
name for himself in London’s literary world. He was an early member of Samuel
Johnson’s lively circle—which included the famed painter Joshua Reynolds,
Edward Gibbon, the actor David Garrick, the novelist Oliver Goldsmith, James
Boswell (who later famously wrote a biography of Johnson), and other
prominent intellectual figures of the era—and he thought of himself above all as
a writer rather than a political thinker, though his writings always tended toward
political and philosophical questions. The author and politician Horace Walpole
ran across the still-precocious Burke at a dinner party in 1761 and offered a
telling description. Among the guests, Walpole wrote in his private diary, was “a
young Mr. Burke, who wrote a book in the style of Lord Bolingbroke, that is
much admired. He is a sensible man, but has not worn off his authorism yet, and
thinks there is nothing so charming as writers, and to be one. He will know
better one of these days.”6
Burke would come to know better as he ventured into politics, which he did
largely for practical reasons at first. In late 1761, now married and a father of
one, he needed a reliable livelihood and so put aside his writing ambitions. He
took up a position as private secretary to William Gerard Hamilton, an ambitious
member of Parliament who soon became the British government’s chief
secretary to Ireland (and took Burke with him). The post took Burke back to his
birthplace for a time and gave him an even more direct view of the intense
religious tensions that tore at Ireland’s soul. In his many years in English
politics, Burke would always be sensitive to being viewed as too immersed in
the Irish question, given his roots, but he could never let go of it either. His
religiously mixed family, combined with his experience at Hamilton’s side, made
him a devoted defender of the basic rights of Ireland’s Catholics, often to his
own political detriment.
After three years in the post, Burke left Hamilton’s service and, through the
help of mutual acquaintances, became private secretary to the Marquis of
Rockingham, the great Whig leader who would serve briefly as prime minister
and would be Burke’s foremost political patron and friend. Rockingham
immediately grasped Burke’s immense talent and value—his erudition, his
prudence, and his considerable rhetorical skills. He brought Burke into the inner
circle of Whig politics and, in 1765, arranged for him to be elected to a seat in
the House of Commons—Burke’s great arena for the next three decades.
From that point until his death in 1797, Burke would be immersed in the
political life of his country and would devote himself to seeing Britain through
the staggering and seemingly endless succession of crises and other challenges
of that period, taking passionate public views on the great questions of the day:
Ireland’s religious and political troubles, the American Revolution and its
aftermath, Britain’s management and mismanagement of India, contentious
reforms of the British parliamentary and electoral system, the monumental
challenge of the French Revolution, and the European war that followed.
Though Burke would hold no prominent executive position and indeed would
spend the great bulk of his time in Parliament in opposition, his voice would
quickly become among the most prominent and recognizable in British politics,
and his pen would prove crucial to the great events of the age.
As a counselor to the Whig Party’s leaders, Burke established himself as a
chief voice of the party and indeed soon became the leading advocate for the
place of political parties in British public life. In a 1770 pamphlet, Thoughts on
the Causes of the Present Discontents, written in the context of a scandal
involving King George III’s excessive involvement in government appointments
and public jobs, Burke argued that political parties were not, as many people
insisted, factions each contending for its own particular advantage, but rather
were bodies of men each united by a vision of the common good of the whole
nation. Partisanship, he insisted, was not only unavoidable but also beneficial, as
it helped to organize politics into camps defined by different priorities about
what was best for the country. This popular pamphlet, and others like it in that
period, showed unmistakable early signs of Burke’s distinctive political
philosophy, as he argued for prudent statesmanship and an attention to the
sentiments (and not just the material needs) of the people and to the venerated
status of social and political institutions. Political reform, he suggested, must
take account of these and proceed gradually and respectfully regarding them.
The pamphlet also revealed Burke’s immense rhetorical skill—which
expressed itself not only in a talent for captivating epigrams, but also in a
sustained and coherent vision of political life and society laid out with
impressive clarity and consistency. As Burke later put it in describing the talents
required of a statesman, this vision combined “a disposition to preserve and an
ability to improve.”7 And it was always reinforced by powerful and memorable
written words that overwhelm the reader with images and ideas.
Burke also devoted a great deal of his time and energy to parliamentary and
financial reform during this period. Frequent scandals around revelations of
public mismanagement and corruption were undermining the nation’s faith in its
government, and Burke was concerned that an excessive response from his
fellow members of Parliament to the scandals could threaten the integrity of
Britain’s mixed regime. Wasteful spending on the monarchy itself (especially the
king’s enormous staff and costly residences) was a particular concern, and Burke
moved to stem that concern by reorganizing how the system was financed. He
also sought to simplify Britain’s immensely complex criminal law (which, he
believed, assigned vastly excessive punishments for petty crimes) and to soften
the punishment of debtors. Burke was keenly aware that society was always
changing, and its laws needed to change too. But in every case, he advanced
gradual and incremental rather than radical or fundamental reforms and he
always called for respect for existing institutions and forms. Constructive change
requires stability, so reformers always have to be careful. “I advance to it with a
tremor that shakes me to the inmost fiber of my frame,” he told the House of
Commons in reference to his financial reforms. “I feel that I engage in a business
. . . the most completely adverse that can be imagined to the natural turn and
temper of my own mind.”8
No eager democrat, Burke rejected the notion that a member of the
Commons must simply express the views of those who sent him, even telling an
audience of his own constituents in 1774 that he owed them his judgment rather
than his obedience.9 But for all the passionate expression he gave to the cause of
preserving Britain’s cherished institutions, Burke in these early years in
Parliament was, above all, a reformer—of financial policy and trade policy, of
laws restricting the freedom of Catholics and Protestant dissenters, and of the
criminal law. He also opposed the slave trade as inhuman and unjust and resisted
the undue intervention of the Crown in politics.
Burke approached the American crisis, which heated to a boil in the mid-
1770s, with this mix of inclinations toward preservation and reform. As he saw
it, the Tory administration of Lord North had acted imprudently in trying to pay
Britain’s war debts by levying new taxes on the Americans without consulting
them. People who argued about whether Parliament had the right to tax the
American colonies—the question essentially everyone on both sides of the
debate took up—were focused on the wrong subject. Parliament certainly had
that right, Burke suggested, because its legal prerogative to govern the empire
was unquestionable. But having that right did not mean Parliament had to
exercise it or that the government was wise to do so. The government of human
beings, he argued, is a matter not of applying cold rules and principles, but of
tending to warm sentiments and attachments to produce the strongest and best
unified community possible. Surely London could work with the Americans to
yield greater revenues rather than commanding their assent.
“Politics ought to be adjusted not to human reasonings but to human nature,
of which the reason is but a part, and by no means the greatest part,” Burke
said.10 The Americans, he argued in his Speech on Conciliation with the
Colonies, had over time developed robust habits of freedom and an independent
spirit, and if they were to be governed as Englishmen, some reasonable effort
must be made to accommodate their character. In this way, Burke put himself at
odds with the most passionate American advocates of independence (including
Thomas Paine) by denying their most basic claims of rights and principles—
claims he rejected not only as false in that instance but also as inappropriate for
political judgment in general. Burke certainly believed in the central importance
of political rights, but he thought that rights could not be disconnected from
obligations in society and therefore could not quite be understood apart from the
particular circumstances of particular societies in particular moments. The more
radical liberals of his day treated politics as a kind of philosophical geometry, he
thought, applying principles and postulates to come up with the right solution,
but real societies did not work—or at least did not work well—that way. And yet
he put himself on the radicals’ side of the practical question, concluding finally
that if North’s administration could not govern the Americans prudently, it ought
to set them free for the good of the empire.
In these speeches, we begin to get a sense of the richness of Burke’s
understanding of society and politics. Especially evident is his under- standing of
how to properly manage political change to balance the desire for justice and the
need for social stability—a subject that, as we will see, was often foremost on
his mind. In the years that followed the American war, these views continued to
drive Burke to restrain and resist abuses of government power. “Government,”
he wrote, “is deeply interested in every thing which, even through the medium of
some temporary uneasiness, may tend finally to compose the minds of the
subjects, and to conciliate their affections.”11 Excessive and needlessly
aggravating uses of power can undermine these affections, and this idea moved
Burke to worry about the king’s excessive involvement in politics in the early
1760s, the needless irritation of the Americans later in that decade and into the
1770s, and British abuses of the natives of India in the 1780s. Out of the latter
concern, Burke in 1787 even launched a lengthy, albeit ultimately futile,
impeachment effort against Warren Hastings, the chief British administrator of
India. All of this made Burke a prominent reformer, though for reasons other
than those of most of his fellows in that camp. He was never a radical
modernizer, as some of his fellow Whigs were, but he worked with these more
radical elements when he thought their efforts could counterbalance an abuse of
power.
But the abuse of power was not the only solvent of the sentiments essential
to a strong and happy people. The corrosion of public feelings, mutual
attachments, and basic human dignity that resulted from reducing politics to
abstract rights and principles could be no less caustic. Indeed, as Burke had seen
in his earliest published work, such corrosion could be far more dangerous in the
long run because it tended to encourage a radical disposition toward politics.
Politics was first and foremost about particular people living together, rather than
about general rules put into effect. This emphasis caused Burke to oppose the
sort of liberalism expounded by many of the radical reformers of his day. They
argued in the parlance of natural rights drawn from reflections on an
individualist state of nature and sought to apply the principles of that approach
directly to political life. “I do not enter into these metaphysical distinctions,”
Burke said in his Speech on American Taxation. “I hate the very sound of
them.”12
This way of thinking about politics made Burke a reformer of failing
institutions who was wary of radical change and a preserver of venerated
traditions who was wary of the abuse of power. To someone familiar only with
his final positions on particular questions and not with the reasoning he offered
to explain himself, Burke in the late 1780s—when Thomas Paine encountered
him—would have been hard to read and easy to misunderstand. And Paine,
thanks to his own unusual path to prominence, was himself not so easy to grasp.

“AN INGENIOUS WORTHY YOUNG MAN”


Thomas Paine was born in January 1737 in Thetford, in the south of England.
His father, a corset maker by profession, was a Quaker, and his mother was an
Anglican. Paine was baptized in his mother’s church, his parents reasoning that
this might open more doors for him in the future, but his father was the more
religiously observant parent, and the young Thomas often accompanied him to
the Quaker meeting house. Although as an adult Paine would criticize the
austerity of the Quakers (once joking that if God had consulted the Quakers in
the creation, then all the world’s flowers would be gray), it is also clear that their
stark moralism deeply shaped him. He had a lifelong ingrained sense that the
laws of justice are clear and simple, that they embody a preference for the weak
over the strong, and that there can be no excuse for disregarding them.
Whereas Burke’s mixed parentage left him with a sense of the complexity of
society, Paine’s experience seems to have left him thinking that religious
disputes were ultimately pointless, and that it was morality—which he thought
could be distinguished from religion—that truly mattered. “My religion is to do
good,” he later wrote.13
Paine’s father always had steady work, but only enough to keep the family
on the precipice of poverty. Intelligent and bookish, Paine was admitted to a
grammar school at the age of seven. His parents scrimped to keep their only
child in school, but they did not have enough to take him past the five years of
schooling he received there. These years would be his only formal education
(though Paine was a devoted autodidact from then on).14 After apprenticing in
his father’s craft, he spent a brief period in London—working in the trade by day
and enjoying the city’s literary café culture by night—and even made some extra
money by serving for a few months as a privateer on a naval vessel in the Seven
Years’ War. Needing steadier work, he left London, first for Dover and then to
start his own small stay-making business in the town of Sandwich, in the
southeast of England. Paine did not much enjoy his work, but it offered him a
living, and he used every spare moment to read, especially books of poetry,
history, and science. In 1759, he was married to Mary Lambert—who had been
working as a maid in the town.
Paine thus seemed to have begun his life’s journey as a working-class
Englishman. But in 1762, after the tragic death of his wife and child in
childbirth, his world was turned upside down. Overcome with desperate grief, he
abandoned his profession and his now empty home to become an excise officer
—an itinerant collector of taxes on commodities like coffee, tea, and alcohol.
The excise trade was notoriously corrupt. The collectors were paid very
poorly and were expected to carry out the thankless and challenging task of
confronting popular shopkeepers for back taxes and even combatting smuggling
and black-market profiteering. Many of his fellow excise officers took bribes
(and Paine himself was accused of wrongdoing when he rented a room from a
shopkeeper who was under his jurisdiction). The experience left Paine with an
awareness of the potential for government corruption and for the abuse of
workers—a sense that would stay with him.
He did begin to rebuild his life in this work—finding friends among his
colleagues and in 1771 marrying a second time. But the difficult working
conditions proved too much. In 1772, while working in East Sussex, Paine
joined an effort launched by his fellow tax collectors to lobby Parliament for
better pay and treatment. He had made a reputation for himself as an unusually
well-read and well-spoken tax collector, and his fellow officers entrusted him to
put their case in writing and press it before government officials. This was his
first taste of the thrill of political action, and it led to his first political writing: A
roughly twenty-page pamphlet titled The Case of the Officers of Excise was
received with rapt enthusiasm by his colleagues.
Like his more famous later writings, this pamphlet contained a fascinating
mix of careful lawyerly arguments, detailed facts and figures, and passages of
passionate and at times powerfully beautiful rhetoric. It also clearly gave vent to
Paine’s own experience of poverty and even of grief at the loss of his first wife.
Paine’s response to the argument that the excise officers could find ways to make
do with what the government paid them was thunderous: “He who never was
hungered may argue finely on the subjection of his appetite; and he who never
was distressed may harangue as beautifully on the power of principle. But
poverty, like grief, has an incurable deafness, which never hears; the oration
loses all its edge; and ‘to be or not to be’ becomes the only question.”15
Here was the voice that would move history. But it would not move
Parliament on this occasion. In the winter of 1773–1774, Paine spent all his time
(taking leave from his work) in London distributing copies of his pamphlet and
lobbying members of Parliament. The futile effort cost him his job, sent him
deeply into debt, and ultimately became unbearable for his wife, who sought an
end to their marriage.
But Paine’s disastrous monomania did not altogether ruin him. Bankrupt and
living in London, he was introduced by a friend to Benjamin Franklin, then the
representative of the American colonies in Britain. Franklin, ever the talent scout
for his home team, was impressed with Paine’s intelligence and drive and
advised him to seek a new start in America—providing him with a generous
letter of introduction to ease his way. “The bearer,” Franklin wrote, “is very well
recommended to me as an ingenious worthy young man.”16 On November 30,
1774, Paine arrived in Philadelphia. For him, as for so many before and after
him, America offered a new beginning. He was eager to start not where his
working-class roots had placed him by birth but where his lengthy and deeply
impressive philosophical and political self-education could enable him to
operate. The reinvented Paine emerged very quickly into public prominence.
Within weeks he had found a job with Robert Aitken, a Philadelphia printer
and publisher of the Pennsylvania Magazine, and by the spring of 1775, only
half a year into his American journey, Paine was the magazine’s editor and a
regular voice in its pages. He wrote on a wide range of social and political
subjects—from local scandals to international affairs—but always with a
plainspoken moralism intent on protecting the needy and weak. One article in
particular, a powerful denunciation of the slave trade, gained him the attention of
Benjamin Rush—the great physician and statesman and the unofficial organizer
of Philadelphia’s small but deeply impressive intellectual community. Rush
brought Paine into the inner circle of the city’s political and literary elites, where
Paine’s writings gained ever greater prominence.
These early writings hint at both Paine’s considerable rhetorical skills and his
grasp of the reigning Enlightenment-liberal views of his time—a devotion to
individual rights, a theory of government as guardian of these rights, righteous
rage at every violation of them, and an unbending passion for justice for the
weak suffering under the boot of the strong. His sheer rhetorical skill sometimes
overwhelms the reader, just as in Burke’s writing. But where Burke’s
considerable faculty for expression is most often employed to convey the
complexity of social and political life, Paine’s most often conveys a simplicity—
a sense that the just and right way forward can be discerned by a proper
application of key principles and that we are duty-bound to discern and to follow
it. Paine’s views, as they begin to emerge here, are not highly original, but they
are fairly reliably representative of the Enlightenment-liberal (or radical) views
of his day. In these early years, as in his later more prominent work, Paine spoke
for many, but far more effectively than most.
Paine’s magazine mostly steered clear of the great and growing political
question of the day—the prospect of a break with Britain. His publisher feared
antagonizing loyalist subscribers, and Paine himself was not initially sure where
he stood on the question. But as events were giving shape to an American revolt,
Paine came to believe that a reconciliation with Britain could no longer be had
on just and honorable terms, and he began to employ his pen in the cause of
independence. At first, he did so anonymously and outside the pages of the
Pennsylvania Magazine. His first effort, an imagined dialogue between two
British generals, was published in the Pennsylvania Journal in January 1775 and
argued that the British were not interested in reconciliation.17 He followed it
with various essays, observations, and even poems intended to make the
American case—at first gently and with an eye to possible rapprochement with
Britain, but over time with increasing force and a growing emphasis on
independence. In October 1775, he published a brief essay, “A Serious
Thought,” which laid out British violations of the rights of individuals around
their empire, including in America. The piece concluded: “When I reflect on
these, I hesitate not for a moment to believe that the Almighty will finally
separate America from Britain. Call it independence or what you will, if it is the
cause of God and humanity, it will go on.”18
As he published these short writings, Paine had begun to work on a more
extended and sustained case for independence. Spurred on by the early battles
between American and British forces and the appointment of George
Washington to command the army, Paine sought a means of persuading the
people to fight and (perhaps even more so) persuading the colonial elites to
support the move for independence. By the concluding days of 1775, he had
composed an extended pamphlet for that purpose, which he aimed to title Plain
Truth. Paine’s friend Rush, upon reading the draft, encouraged its quick
publication and suggested an improvement to the title—Common Sense.
The fifty-page pamphlet was an all-out assault on the British Crown and
indeed on the notion of hereditary monarchy and the practices and premises of
British politics. It laid out, too, the beginnings of a political philosophy. Paine’s
opening description of the work for his readers, on the title page of the original
printed pamphlet, describes it as taking up four subjects: “The origin and design
of government in general, with concise remarks on the English constitution;
monarchy and hereditary succession; thoughts on the present state of American
affairs; [and] the present ability of America, with some miscellaneous
reflections.” The pamphlet begins by establishing some principles for
distinguishing legitimate from illegitimate rule: that government exists to secure
the freedom and security of its equal citizens and that any government that fails
to do so is not worthy of the name, regardless of its pedigree.
Paine’s case for independence is grounded in these stark and fundamental
principles, and Common Sense asserts that reasoning from such principles and
rights is the only proper way to approach politics. In straightforward language
accessible to every reader, Paine lays out a lengthy and logical case against the
authority of Britain to command the colonies (since the colonists are not
represented in the Parliament they answer to), against the legitimacy of Britain’s
own domestic political institutions (which give the king absolute power over the
citizens his government is supposed to serve), and in favor of a republican
government elected by the people and answerable to them.19 He concludes that
“however strange it may appear to some, or however unwilling they may be to
think so, matters not, but many strong and striking reasons may be given to show
that nothing can settle our affairs so expeditiously as an open and determined
declaration for independence.”20
Paine’s earlier efforts had certainly been noticed, but Common Sense was
simply a sensation. Within a few weeks, it had spread around the colonies,
portions were reprinted in newspapers, and many tens of thousands of copies
were sold.21 It reached its readers at a moment when many thoughtful colonists
were wondering if their leaders had carelessly marched them into a disastrous
blunder by taking on the world’s most powerful military force. Was this conflict
with England all a tax revolt by wealthy elites? Common Sense answered
powerfully in the negative: This was a righteous cause and well worth the
struggle. The pamphlet offered bold, fiery declarations for those already inclined
to independence as well as cool, logical arguments for those on the fence, and it
seemed genuinely to persuade. “By private letters which I have lately received
from Virginia,” George Washington wrote to his friend Joseph Reed in April
1776, “I find that ‘Common Sense’ is working a powerful change there in the
minds of many men.”22
In the months that followed, Paine quickly became the leader of the
rhetorical struggle for independence. He published a series of letters responding
to critics of Common Sense and helped draft a new constitution for
Pennsylvania, seeking to put into practice the principles held out as the impetus
for revolution—a representative government that treated its citizens as free and
equal. Paine also contributed directly to the war effort, working as a secretary for
several officers and traveling with the army to memorialize its efforts. The fall of
1776 was a very difficult time for Washington’s army, and morale among the
advocates of independence was extremely low. In an effort to lift the spirits of
the fighting men and their supporters, Paine, while traveling with the army in
New Jersey, penned an essay that came to be known as “The American Crisis.”
The article would turn out to be the first of a line of Crisis papers. The first paper
opens with what may be Paine’s most famous lines: “These are the times that try
men’s souls. The summer soldier and the sunshine patriot will, in this crisis,
shrink from the service of their country; but he that stands by it now, deserves
the love and thanks of man and woman. Tyranny, like hell, is not easily
conquered; yet we have this consolation with us, that the harder the conflict, the
more glorious the triumph. What we obtain too cheap, we esteem too lightly: it is
dearness only that gives every thing its value.”23
Paine would publish sixteen Crisis papers over the subsequent seven years of
war, each piece intended to address some particular exigency of the moment.
Some of the papers were filled with facts and figures, others were simply pep
talks for the troops, and yet others made large arguments in broad strokes about
the illegitimacy of the British government’s claim on the colonies. But all of the
papers built on the arguments and worldview that Paine had laid out in Common
Sense. Meanwhile, Paine was also actively involved in the administration of the
war—serving as secretary to the Continental Congress’s committee on foreign
affairs and later as the clerk of the Pennsylvania legislature. He also continued to
publish essays and pamphlets on public questions, including calls for a stronger
central government to advance the war effort and arguments for an end to
slavery.
At the end of the war, as compensation for his great service to the cause, the
New York state legislature gave Paine a farm in New Rochelle, which had been
confiscated from a loyalist family. There Paine lived until 1787, devoting
himself largely to scientific pursuits and inventions and most notably to a new
design for an iron bridge with a single large arch that might traverse the width of
a river without obstructing the passage of the large commercial vessels
increasingly found in American and European river traffic. He seemed to put
politics behind him, though as it turned out, he could not keep away for long.
In the spring of 1787, Paine set out to find financing for his bridge design—
financing that he knew could only come from Europe. He thus traveled to France
and Britain in search of support, expecting to be gone for no more than a year.
He did find some English funders, and eventually a bridge employing his design
was built over the Wear River in the north of England. (Another, built decades
later, still stands over the Dunlap Creek in Brownsville, Pennsylvania, to this
day.) But as he surely must have known he would, Paine also encountered
enormous political turmoil on his travels. The prospect of revolution was heavy
in the air in France, and a sense of instability was palpable in Britain too.
As much as anyone on either side of the Atlantic, Paine had always believed
the American Revolution was the beginning of a revolutionary chapter in world
history. Universal principles of equality and liberty could not long be held back:
“The independence of America, considered merely as a separation from
England, would have been a matter but of little importance had it not been
accompanied by a revolution in the principles and practice of governments. She
made a stand not for herself only but for the world, and looked beyond the
advantages herself could receive.”24 He fully expected the ideals of the
revolution to spread to Britain and the continent.
Paine was in France—where his bridge design met with great interest
(though not with financial backing) and where his reputation preceded him in
radical and revolutionary circles—until the late summer of 1787. Paris in that
period felt to him like Philadelphia in the year before the outbreak of war. He
knew a great event was coming, and his hopes for it were high. In the fall, he
traveled to Britain to seek support for his bridge and to meet some of those who
had backed the American cause—among whose number Paine certainly counted
Edmund Burke.
Paine thus approached his meeting with Burke with a sense that Burke and
the other leading English Whigs were kindred spirits, persuaded as he was of the
ideological foundation of the American Revolution and enthused by its potential
to spark popular uprisings elsewhere. He could hardly have been more wrong
about Burke’s essential concerns and priorities. Burke himself, meanwhile, was
certainly aware of Paine’s role and resulting fame, though it is far from clear if
Burke had read Common Sense before encountering its author. In his Letter to
the Sheriffs of Bristol, in 1777, Burke had mentioned in passing “the author of
the celebrated pamphlet which prepared the minds of the people for
independence,” and more or less justified that author as having been driven to
his opinions by the excesses of the British government.25 But he nowhere
contends with the radical views of politics laid out in Common Sense, and it
seems unlikely that Burke would have failed to react badly to those views had he
encountered them.

FIRST ENCOUNTERS

Burke and Paine may have met for the first time, very briefly, in late 1787.26
Then, in the summer of 1788, they not only met for a meal but also spent several
days together at Burke’s home. Burke wrote of hosting “the famous Mr. Paine,
the author of Common Sense, the Crisis, etc. and Secretary to the congress for
foreign affairs,” noting that he “was not sorry to see a man who was active in
such an important scene.”27 Paine was interested mainly in advancing his
bridge, and apparently, the two steered largely away from politics, but got along
reasonably well and remained in contact after the visit. In a January 1789 letter
to Jefferson (who was then still in Paris), Paine wrote of being “in some intimacy
with Mr. Burke.”28
Paine’s time in Paris had exposed him to the leaders of the radical wing of
French politics. His reputation (in a culture that valued writers), his connections,
and his politics made him a natural fit, and Paine was much taken with the spirit
of the hour in Paris—with revolution threatening to erupt. He quickly abandoned
his intention to return to America after a year, concluding that he might play
some role on behalf of America, or of America’s ideals, in France or Britain.
Burke, meanwhile, was much concerned with domestic affairs in Britain. In
November 1788, King George III fell seriously ill, and his condition (which
some modern researchers suggest might have been caused by long-term
exposure to low doses of arsenic in his diet) expressed itself in, among other
things, serious signs of mental imbalance. He would speak unceasingly in
English and German at no one in particular for hours at a time, foaming at the
mouth. And he was thoroughly unable to carry out his duties. Talk of a regency
—or temporary substitute for the king—soon began and set off an explosive
political crisis about the power of the regent.
The most plausible regent was the man who would succeed the king should
his illness prove fatal: his son, the twenty-six-year old Prince George. The prince
was known to harbor deep hostility to the Tory prime minister, William Pitt, and
was indeed a personal friend of Whig leader Charles James Fox. Pitt, in an effort
to prevent his government’s dismissal, introduced a regency bill that would have
placed far-reaching limits on the power of the regent, obliging the regent to keep
the existing government in place and restraining him from exercising most of the
powers of the monarch. Fox, meanwhile, asserted the prince’s complete
hereditary power to take over. The two thus found themselves in an odd reversal
of roles, with the Tory (whose party normally defended the prerogatives of the
monarch) insisting that the Crown must be answerable to Parliament and the
Whig (whose party stood for the rights of Parliament in a limited monarchy)
affirming the hereditary authority of the ruler. Pitt’s bill, which would have
forced a monumental constitutional crisis, was ready to be advanced when, in
March 1788, the king recovered and the crisis was ended.
This Regency Crisis, as it came to be known, left Burke deeply shaken and
alarmed. As described earlier, Burke was an unusual Whig. He was moved most
fundamentally not by reforming inclinations (as most Whigs of his day were),
but by a desire to sustain the stability and unity of his society. He was a Whig
because the Whigs stood for the legacy of Britain’s Glorious Revolution of 1688.
But Burke valued that revolution (in which Parliament overthrew the Catholic
king, James II, and installed William and Mary as joint monarchs to reassert a
Protestant line of succession and avert a disastrous religious war) for preserving
the regime, not, as some more radical Whigs argued, for introducing new
principles of parliamentary supremacy that pointed toward a republican
government. It had been, in Burke’s words, “a revolution not made but
prevented.”29 So although his great concern in the 1760s and early 1770s had
been excessive royal authority, Burke now saw the monarch’s role in the English
system coming under threat, and he reacted with equal concern. That his party
interests were also invested in the regency made him all the more tenacious, to
be sure, but considering Burke’s behavior in the crisis, he clearly began to feel
profound apprehension for the essential stability of the British system. The sight
of the Tories arguing against the authority of the Crown—and of many of his
fellow Whigs being slowly convinced of the merits of their case—aroused a
genuine concern about a ruinous republican revolution in Britain, which would
in every way color his reaction to events in France soon after.
Thomas Paine, with whom Burke had exchanged a few brief and cordial
letters since Paine’s visit, did not help things. He wrote to Burke from France in
the midst of the crisis to suggest that Burke “propose a national convention, to
be fairly elected, for the purpose of taking the state of the nation into
consideration” and essentially reorganizing the regime from scratch.30 Such an
idea could not have been further from Burke’s preservationist inclinations, and
while we have no evidence of a response from Burke, this was probably when
Burke began to discern the true distance between his and Paine’s views of
politics.
Burke’s passionate opposition to the Tory maneuver in the Regency Crisis
had its costs, however. During a regency debate in the House of Commons,
Burke, carried away by the heat of his own arguments, accused Pitt of setting
himself up as a competitor for the Crown against the Prince of Wales. Burke
thereby effectively charged the prime minister with treason on the floor of the
Commons. The remark drew a formal rebuke from the House of Commons and
was a source of great frustration for Burke’s own party leaders, who viewed it as
weakening their position in a key moment. Their frustration was compounded,
moreover, by what many in Burke’s party saw as his excessive concentration on
the impeachment trial of Warren Hastings—the British governor of India, who
Burke believed had grossly abused the local population. Burke’s concentration
on the trial was entirely in keeping with his concern for the integrity of the
British regime, but the trial dragged on longer than the party’s leaders expected
(in fact, it ultimately lasted far longer still, ending with acquittal only in 1794)
and was, they feared, painting the party in a bad light, in no small part because
of Burke’s zeal in its prosecution.
In the summer of 1789, discouraged by these various setbacks and deeply
worried about the commitment of his fellow Whigs to the maintenance of the
English constitution, Burke seriously contemplated retirement from politics. He
wrote to his friend the Earl of Charlemont: “There is a time of life in which, if a
man cannot arrive at a certain degree of authority, derived from a confidence
from the Prince or the people, which may aid him in his operations, and make
him compass useful objects without a perpetual struggle, it becomes him to remit
much of his activity.”31
But retirement was not to be. The dispirited letter to Charlemont was dated
July 10, 1789—four days before the storming of the Bastille and the beginning
of the most celebrated and intense period of Burke’s political life, and the period
that would bring him most directly into conflict with Paine.

THE REVOLUTION IN FRANCE


Events in Paris began with an explosion of pent-up energy. In the course of a
lengthy financial and political crisis, as the mass of the public fell into economic
hardship, resentment against the king and his government had built up, and some
release was inevitable. The second week of July 1789 saw unprecedented riots,
looting, and public confrontations with the military and was capped by the
capture of the Bastille—a prison and fortress that symbolized the power of the
king. Less a paramilitary operation than a mob scene, the taking of the Bastille,
which concluded with the prison’s chief officer being publicly stabbed and
decapitated and the crowd parading his head on a pike through Paris’s main
thoroughfares, set the tone for the early stages of the revolution. But these
displays of rage were always accompanied by calls for justice and for a new
system of government built on enlightened ideals of equality and liberty.
By late August, the leaders of the revolution had regained some control of
events and published a statement of their principles (modeled in part on the
American Declaration of Independence). The statement came to be known as the
Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen and called for representative
government and respect for human dignity. Throughout the West, the mystery of
the character of this upheaval at the very heart of Europe quickly became the
question of the day: Was Paris in the grip of a mad and violent terror or on the
verge of an enlightened and rational new political order?
The British response to these early days of the revolution was
overwhelmingly positive, and Burke’s fellow Whigs in particular believed that
the French were moving to liberalize their government on the model of English
liberty. Charles James Fox, the party’s leader, responded to the storming of the
Bastille with enthusiasm and glee: “How much the greatest event it is that ever
happened in the world! And how much the best!”32 From the outset, Burke’s
own response was far more guarded. He recognized the injustice of the old
regime, but worried about the violent zeal of the revolutionaries. “England is
gazing with astonishment at a French struggle for liberty, and not knowing
whether to blame or to applaud,” he wrote to a friend on August 9:
The spirit it is impossible not to admire; but the old Parisian ferocity has broken out in a shocking
manner. It is true that this may be no more than a sudden explosion; if so, no indication can be
taken from it; but if it should be character rather than accident, then the people are not fit for
liberty and must have a strong hand, like that of their former masters, to coerce them. Men must
have a certain fund of natural moderation to qualify them for freedom, else it becomes noxious to
themselves and a perfect nuisance to every body else. What will be the event it is hard I think still
to say.33

These sentiments would turn out to be Burke’s least negative judgment of the
revolution. With time, as the character (and especially the philosophical
ambitions) of the revolutionaries became clearer, Burke would turn from skeptic
to adamant opponent. The October 1789 assault on Versailles, in which a mob
attacked the young queen and nearly killed her, convinced Burke that the
revolution was not only out of control but also intent on undermining the deep
sentiments and social attachments essential to holding a people together. He
feared that the revolution had become a profound threat not only to France but to
its neighbors as well. This incident would later draw some of the most famous
and eloquent rhetoric in Burke’s writings about the revolution, as we will see,
but his letters of that October clearly show that the emotion expressed later was
not manufactured for effect but genuinely felt. On October 10, Burke wrote to
his son of the latest news from France and concluded that “the elements which
compose human society seem all to be dissolved, and a world of monsters to be
produced in the place of it.”34 On the heels of the Regency Crisis, Burke
watched the French combine mob rule with precisely the kind of stark and cold
political philosophy he had worried about since his earliest public writings.
These observations left him concerned for the fate of the political stability that
he believed was essential to liberty.
Where Burke saw chaos and terror, however, Thomas Paine saw the natural
extension of both America’s own revolution and the empire of rights and
legitimate government. Dispirited by the Regency Crisis, which he believed
revealed that the Whigs, and British society more generally, simply had no
stomach for radical democratization, Paine had turned his ambitions and hopes
to France, where he returned a few months before the outbreak of the French
Revolution. He was by then acquainted with the early leaders of the revolution
(including especially the Marquis de Lafayette, who had taken a crucial part in
the American Revolution), took part in some of their deliberations, and even
played a minor part in drafting the Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the
Citizen. The events of that summer exhilarated Paine, who took it upon himself
to build support for the revolutionaries in the Anglo-American world.
Unaware that Burke’s view of the revolution was very different from his
own, Paine wrote his erstwhile host several letters from France describing the
situation in the hope of gaining in Burke an important friend for the
revolutionaries’ cause in London. In the process, Paine reported all manner of
news that must have greatly alarmed Burke. Most notable was Paine’s final
missive, written January 17, 1790, and passing along a report from Thomas
Jefferson (who had just returned to America, but remained extremely well
informed about events in Paris). The national assembly, Jefferson had written
with enthusiasm, was willing “to set fire to the four Corners of the Kingdom and
to perish with it themselves rather than relinquish one iota from their plan of a
total change of government.” To Jefferson’s evocative description Paine added
that “the assembly is now fixing the boundaries of the division of the nation into
83 parts, latitudinally and longitudinally. It is intended by this arrangement to
lose entirely the name of provinces and consequently of provincial
distinction.”35 Paine clearly believed that this assertive effort to overcome long-
standing local prejudices and attachments and rationally establish a new French
national identity from scratch was both wise and encouraging. It was a sign of
the new government’s commitment to reestablish French society on new and
better principles.
Paine expected this report to please Burke or encourage him to support the
revolutionary cause. But nothing could have been more upsetting to Burke than
news of such extremism and of an intentional effort to erase well-established
local attachments, except perhaps Paine’s ominous promise, delivered in a tenor
of hope, that “the revolution in France is certainly a fore-runner to other
revolutions in Europe.”36 This letter surely played a role in confirming Burke’s
concerns and inciting his worst fears about the revolution in France. What
worried him above all was the combination of philosophical pretensions and
applied savagery of the revolution—mob rule making its case in metaphysical
abstractions. Paine was no advocate of mob rule, to be sure, but his case for the
revolution—that it directly applied the political philosophy of the
Enlightenment, seeking to instantiate the ideals of an individualist egalitarianism
—was precisely the sort Burke feared most for its corrosive effect on people’s
reverence for their society’s political institutions and traditions.
And the prospect of a contagion of such philosophies—of the spread of
revolutionary sentiment into Britain in particular—loomed large in Burke’s mind
after he read a November 1789 speech by Richard Price, a prominent and
respected Unitarian dissenter. Price addressed the Society for Commemorating
the Revolution (that is, the Glorious Revolution, or the English Revolution of
1688) and pointed to the French Revolution as confirming English principles. He
argued that inherent in the English constitution was the people’s right to overturn
their regime if their individual rights—understood in Enlightenment-liberal
terms—were not respected, and that English politics had fallen behind the
French in putting into practice its own principles. In a rush of enthusiasm he told
his audience:
What an eventful period this is! I am thankful that I have lived to see it. . . . I have lived to see 30
MILLIONS of people, indignant and resolute, spurning at slavery, and demanding liberty with an
irresistible voice; their king led in triumph, and an arbitrary monarch surrendering himself to his
subjects.—After sharing in the benefits of one revolution, I have been spared to be witness to two
other revolutions, both glorious. And now methinks I see the love for liberty catching and
spreading.37

The society published Price’s speech as a pamphlet and sent a copy to the
French National Assembly with a letter building on his themes, noting especially
“the glorious example given in France to encourage other nations to assert the
unalienable rights of Mankind, and thereby to introduce a general reformation in
the government of Europe, and to make the world free and happy.”38
Burke would later write, with great understatement, that reading Price’s
sermon and the accompanying letter left him with “a considerable degree of
uneasiness.”39 He was alarmed not only about the celebration of events in
France but especially about Price’s attempt to recast English history in the mold
of the French Revolution. Price had argued that the Glorious Revolution itself
had established the principle that the monarchy was subject to popular choice
(exactly the view Burke opposed in the Regency Crisis) and indeed that the
Glorious Revolution was fought over “unalienable rights.” It was this effort to
commandeer the English constitution for the revolutionary cause that Burke
could see creeping into the thought of his fellow Whigs; he would oppose this
effort most adamantly in his writings about France.
Burke resolved to reply to Price’s lecture and to begin to make the case
against the French Revolution at every opportunity, despite the reigning
sentiment in his own party and in the country at large. A House of Commons
debate about military spending in February 1790 would provide his first
opportunity. The annual debate always involved a general discussion of world
affairs (since the state of world politics would determine the government’s
expectations of its military needs), and Burke knew France would loom large.
The revolution had been proceeding apace, with the government increasingly
moving to confiscate private property and collapse the structures and institutions
of the old regime.
As the debate opened, the Tory prime minister, William Pitt, as well as Fox
and several other fellow Whigs, expressed measured but firm support for the
revolution. Burke’s views were known to his close friends, but were not yet
widely known in Parliament, and as he rose to speak, he knew that his remarks
would cause a stir. By uprooting the foundations of their existing regime and by
confiscating the property of the church, the French had undone both the balance
of their politics and the freedom of their people, Burke argued, and they were
headed for disaster. The trouble, moreover, was not just a matter of bungled
administration and execution—it was rooted in the fundamental ideals of the
revolution. The Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen, he said, was
filled with a foolish “abuse of elementary principles as would have disgraced a
schoolboy.” It was “a sort of institute and digest of anarchy” and contained the
seeds of political catastrophe. “This mad declaration,” Burke said, had caused
France to inflict wounds upon itself normally suffered only by nations at war,
and indeed the declaration “may in the end produce such a war, and perhaps
many such.”40 The revolution was a mortal threat to liberty, and no friend of
liberty should be warm to it.
Burke had laid down his marker and from this point—at great cost to his
standing in his party and to the immense ire of many of his friends—would be an
unbending and very public opponent of the French Revolution. He criticized it in
exceedingly harsh terms on almost every imaginable ground and offered a stern
defense of the English regime against the onslaught of a theoretical politics
intent on uprooting all long-standing social institutions and practices.
After the House of Commons debate, Burke also realized that he needed to
complete his formal response to Price, so that a counterargument could be fully
expounded on Burke’s terms. As he thought about how best to do this, he
remembered a letter he had received in 1789 from a young Frenchman named
Charles-Jean-François Depont seeking his views on the revolution. Depont
clearly expected praise for the revolution, but he instead received a brief, early
version of Burke’s case against it. In his response to Depont, Burke laid out an
argument against radical individualism, arbitrary power, the decimation of social
institutions, and a politics of metaphysical theory: “I must delay my
congratulations on your acquisition of liberty. You may have made a revolution,
but not a reformation. You may have subverted monarchy, but not recovered
freedom.”41
In mid-1790, Burke decided that the best response to Price would take the
form of a second letter to Depont (though, since it would be published, he would
keep his addressee anonymous). The form of a letter would allow him more
freedom in organizing his case and require less formality in presenting it. Burke
spent months composing and editing the letter, which he had decided would be
published and distributed as a long pamphlet under the title Reflections on the
Revolution in France and on the Proceedings of Certain Societies in London
Relative to that Event: In a Letter Intended to Have Been Sent to a Gentleman in
Paris. After numerous drafts and revisions, the pamphlet ever since known
simply as Reflections on the Revolution in France finally emerged on November
1, 1790.
The Reflections was a masterwork of rhetoric. In its style, cadences, images,
and evocative metaphors it was perhaps the best of Burke’s writing. But it was
also a deep and serious work of political thought and the first sustained
assessment and dissection of the claims of liberal radicalism in the age of
revolutions. Burke begins with a defense of the English system from what he
takes to be the distortions of Price and his fellows. By suggesting that the
Glorious Revolution made the British government legitimate because it had put
in place an “elective monarchy,” Burke says Price and others delegitimize all
prior English history.42
He warns his French correspondent that the effort to present the French
Revolution as an extension of English liberalism seeks to deceive both the
French and the English to each accept a dangerous radical novelty as a gift from
the other: “We ought not, on either side of the water, to suffer ourselves to be
imposed upon by the counterfeit wares which some persons, by a double fraud,
export to you in illicit bottoms as raw commodities of British growth, though
wholly alien to our soil.”43
Burke articulates the significance of the hereditary principle in the English
system not only in sustaining the monarchy but in securing the people’s liberties
and allegiance to the laws. And he provides a stirring portrait of Britain’s mixed
regime as justified by the enormous success it has achieved in providing for a
stable and successful national life while gradually evolving to meet the people’s
changing needs. The radicals are angry, he argues, and so they speak more
loudly and forcefully than the rest of the otherwise contented British nation—but
no one should assume therefore that they speak for all: “Because half a dozen
grasshoppers under a fern make the field ring with their importunate chink,
whilst thousands of great cattle, reposed beneath the shadow of the British oak,
chew the cud and are silent, pray do not imagine that those who make the noise
are the only inhabitants of the field.”44
This image of Britain as well served by a kind of deeply rooted calm is
everywhere in Burke’s rhetoric in the Reflections. And he bluntly derides the
attempts of the French to uproot their long-standing social institutions under the
influence of childish theories of social life unworthy of their own great nation.
He dissents from the dominant individualism and state-of-nature theorizing of
the day. And he lays out his own political theory—the theory taken up in this
book—as an answer to the theories of natural rights underlying the revolution.
Burke concludes with an extended comparison of the French and English
systems of government, economies, and social orders. His comparison reflects
very poorly on the wisdom of the French revolutionaries and seeks to highlight
Britain’s relative stability, prosperity, and comfort in an effort to suggest to his
countrymen that emulating France would be disastrous. Praising the gradualism
of the English constitution while mocking the supposedly enlightened radicalism
of the revolutionary French, Burke sums up his sense of the limits of human
reason and power:
A politic caution, a guarded circumspection, a moral rather than a complexional timidity were
among the ruling principles of our forefathers in their most decided conduct. Not being
illuminated with the light of which the gentlemen of France tell us they have got so abundant a
share, they acted under a strong impression of the ignorance and fallibility of mankind. . . . Let us
imitate their caution if we wish to deserve their fortune or to retain their bequests. . . . [L]et us be
satisfied to admire rather than attempt to follow in their desperate flights the aeronauts of
France.45

Burke’s audience in the Reflections was clearly British and not, as his
epistolary mode would have it, a French gentleman. If it were actually a letter to
a Frenchman, the Reflections would have been grossly inappropriate, boasting
and mocking as it does. But as a letter to his countrymen, it sought as much to
remind (or persuade) them of the origins and principles of their own social and
political institutions—to show them what they ought to be by insisting it was
what they already were—as to argue against the French, and all in the cause of
building up a resistance to revolutionary appeals.
The publication of Burke’s missive drew an enormous amount of interest and
debate. “Within our remembrance no publication has excited more anxious
curiosity,” noted the London Chronicle a few days after its release.46 And it
appears to have sold about seven thousand copies in a week, which made it a
massive best-seller for the time.47 It also quickly drew a series of responses
from English radicals, who were aghast at its substance and tone and especially
surprised to see it coming from Burke, whom they had thought of as something
of a fellow traveler.
News of Burke’s vehement opposition to the revolution had reached Paine in
France soon after Burke’s fiery speech in Parliament in February 1790, and
Paine immediately understood that a response was essential. In the heated debate
culture of the era, an attack from so prominent and effective a critic could not be
left to simmer. When he then also heard that Burke would publish a pamphlet
against the revolution, Paine promised his French friends he would write a
response to make their case to the English-speaking world. He planned to turn an
essay he was already writing about the revolution into such a reply once Burke’s
missive arrived.
The resulting book, which Paine titled, with his usual flair, Rights of Man, is
part answer to Burke, part stand-alone defense of the principles of the French
Revolution. It offers a logical, sustained, focused, passionate, and powerful
argument, delivered with often astonishing rhetorical force. Certainly among the
most complete and most widely read elucidations of the basic worldview
underlying the revolution, it is Paine’s most expressly theoretical work. Here,
Paine’s political teaching—the set of views that will pervade the rest of this book
—is most fully put forward. Standing as it did as an answer to Burke’s
Reflections, the book marks the moment when these two giants of the age of
revolutions were set clearly against one another and when the great debate they
launched had truly come into its own.
Published in March 1791, Rights of Man launches vehement attacks against
Burke and his views, even referring to rumors about supposed financial
misconduct by Burke, and describing the Reflections and particularly its
epistolary style as a “wild unsystematical display of paradoxical rhapsodies.”48
Burke completely misunderstood both the causes and the nature of the
revolution, Paine suggests, because he displays no real grasp of French society
and politics: “As wise men are astonished at foolish things and other people at
wise ones, I know not on which ground to account for Mr. Burke’s astonishment;
but certain it is that he does not understand the French Revolution.”49
Paine’s case for the revolution is strikingly philosophical. He spends very
little time on the suffering of the French lower classes under the old regime or
the abuses and excesses of the French aristocracy. Leading with a systematic
attempt to refute or dismiss Burke’s key points, it quickly turns to an enthusiastic
case for human liberty. Paine writes with resolute confidence in the efficacy of
reason in political life. He argues that the revolution is the working out of
inescapable principles of politics and that its success and extension are therefore
essentially inevitable. The objections of its opponents, including Burke’s, merely
mark the alarm of those who see that their old and unjust systems of privilege
and oppression are in danger:
What are the present Governments of Europe but a scene of iniquity and oppression? What is that
of England? Do not its own inhabitants say it is a market where every man has his price, and
where corruption is common traffic at the expense of a deluded people? No wonder, then, that the
French Revolution is traduced. Had it confined itself merely to the destruction of flagrant
despotism perhaps Mr. Burke and some others had been silent. Their cry now is, “It has gone too
far”—that is, it has gone too far for them.50

Paine’s is a politics of applied principle, and he believes the only way to


rescue polities constructed on the wrong principles is to tear them down and
rebuild from scratch. He clearly believes, as he had written in Common Sense
years earlier, that “we have it in our power to begin the world over again.”51 In
Rights of Man, he indeed suggests that this is the only way to construct a just
society. He also offers a thorough and vigorous case against hereditary rule and
aristocracy (a “mere animal system” unsuited to a rational politics) and against
the right of one generation to impose its notions and arrangements on those that
follow. The age of hereditary government has come and gone, he insists:
It is not difficult to perceive, from the enlightened state of mankind, that hereditary Governments
are verging to their decline, and that Revolutions on the broad basis of national sovereignty and
Government by representation, are making their way in Europe.52

Paine lays out his political vision in greater detail in Rights of Man than in
any of his earlier writings: a vision of individualism, natural rights, and equal
justice for all made possible by a government that lives up to true republican
ideals. He is persuaded that all this has become possible in his time. “From what
we now see, nothing of reform on the political world ought to be held
improbable. . . . It is an age of revolutions in which every thing may be looked
for.”53
What emerges is a set of principles consistent with Paine’s writings during
the American war but worked out more thoroughly and philosophically and
therefore now more clearly at odds with Burke’s view of the world. Like Burke,
however, Paine addressed himself to an English audience and used the question
of France to raise the question of the English regime—its past and especially its
future. And Paine certainly succeeded in reaching an English readership. Rights
of Man likely sold tens of thousands of copies and reached a wide audience well
beyond London’s elite (and well beyond Burke’s readership).54

THE BATTLE OF THE BOOKS


The battle lines were now drawn, and the English reading public was very much
engaged in the debate. In America, too, the exchange drew intense attention and
began to sketch political battle lines that would last. John Quincy Adams, son of
the sitting vice president (and himself of course a future president) published a
series of essays in a Boston newspaper under the pen name Publicola, which
offered a kind of running narrative of the Burke-Paine debate (siding far more
with Burke than Paine). In Virginia, Senator James Monroe (a champion of
Paine’s and another future president) noted in a letter to Thomas Jefferson that
“the contest of Burke and Paine . . . is much the subject of discussion in all parts
of this state.”55
Paine’s book was the most significant reply to Burke’s Reflections on the
Revolution in France, though it was by no means the only one. Indeed, dozens of
counter-pamphlets soon appeared, mostly from English radicals and dissenters
accusing Burke of abandoning both Whig principles and his own principles.
They charged him with a profound inconsistency, given his support for the
American Revolution and his earlier assertion (in his 1770 pamphlet Thoughts
on the Causes of the Present Discontents) that the deep disgruntlement of an
entire population is proof that the state requires serious reform. Thomas
Jefferson spoke for many when, upon reading the Reflections, he remarked that
“the Revolution in France does not astonish me so much as the revolution in Mr.
Burke.”56 This theme of inconsistency would follow Burke for the rest of his
life and indeed well beyond his life, among historians.
Burke was stung by such accusations and well aware of the spread of Paine’s
Rights of Man. He was also alert to the growing rift he was causing among the
Whigs by his sharp break with Fox. He therefore decided to make his case in
writing again. In August 1791, he published An Appeal from the New to the Old
Whigs to try to address all these varied challenges at once. The Appeal
articulates many of the same ideas found in the Reflections and earlier writings,
but with more light and less heat, and it grounds them in a deeper contention
with some basic political and philosophical questions. Burke claims for himself
the mantle of the great Whig tradition and describes his opponents in the party as
hungry for radical democracy. He directly addresses a number of Paine’s claims,
using long quotes from Rights of Man and yet never mentioning Paine by name.
Like the Reflections, the Appeal is deeply concerned with the relations among
generations, though, as David Bromwich has astutely noted, it emphasizes the
essential connection between the present and the future, while the Reflections, in
a far more conservative mood, addressed mostly the link between the past and
the present—a subtle but important difference, as we will see.57 More than any
of Burke’s other works, the Appeal presents a robust view of the kind of social
and political life he seeks to defend.
Paine, meanwhile, returned to Britain in July 1791 and was hard at work
spreading his ideas. After the publication of Burke’s Appeal, which Paine
perceived (correctly) as largely a response to him, he set about writing a further
reply, in the form of a second part of Rights of Man, published in February 1792.
This sequel was in many ways more ambitious than the original and in every
way more radical. Burke and Paine had forced one another to get to the core of
their differences: a dispute about what makes a government legitimate, what the
individual’s place is in the larger society, and how each generation should think
about those who came before and those who will come after.
This second part of Rights of Man was, to begin with, an all-out assault on
monarchical government, including quite expressly the British monarchy. It was
also a reflection on the causes of poverty and the plight of the lower classes and
in this sense offers an extremely useful model of how the essential ideas of the
Enlightenment-liberal theorists point to and connect with some later forms of
radical politics. Paine begins to take the next steps on liberalism’s path: He
advocates for a public pension system for the poor, free public education, public
benefits for parents, more parliamentary representation for the lower classes, and
a progressive income tax. He even offers a plan for world peace through the
extension of reason and knowledge: “If men will permit themselves to think as
rational beings ought to think, nothing can appear more ridiculous and absurd”
than to waste public funds on military expenditures.58 Paine denies Burke’s
every premise and raises the stakes of the argument.
But by the time Paine’s second volume was published in February 1792, the
situation in France had begun to look far more ominous to many Englishmen.
The attempt to sustain a constitutional monarchy had failed, and the king had
been imprisoned, while the National Assembly had manifestly failed to keep
order in Paris and to get the country’s finances under control. Its hold on power
was increasingly uncertain as factionalism among the revolutionaries grew.
Paine’s outright calls for overturning the British regime—a risky move in any
climate—turned out to be especially unwise in this moment of growing concern.
In May 1792, Pitt’s Tory government, with significant Whig support (including
Burke’s, although he was notably silent in the debate on the bill, since his fellow
members were well aware of his personal animosity toward Paine), enacted a
proclamation against seditious writings—a move aimed expressly at Paine. The
bill did not mention him by name, but the prime minister was not shy about its
purpose. “Principles had been laid down by Mr. Paine,” Pitt told the House of
Commons, “which struck at the hereditary nobility, and which went to the
destruction of monarchy and religion.”59 Paine, who was in London, was
charged under the new law, and in September he left again for France rather than
face a trial. He was tried and found guilty in absentia and would never again
return to Britain.
As more extreme factions took control in Paris, British public opinion
continued steadily to shift against the French and in favor of Burke’s critical
view of the revolution, which he continued to express in pamphlets and
speeches. The European powers had begun to array themselves against the
revolutionary regime, and war seemed increasingly likely on the continent, while
in France the revolution turned to terror. The execution of the French king in
January 1793 wrought a decisive change of attitudes in London, and the British
public and political leadership alike soon turned sharply anti-French. By the end
of that year, England was officially at war with France, and the reversal of public
sentiment Burke had sought was largely (though, of course, not simply or
entirely) achieved—with much help from the disastrous course of the revolution
itself.
This turn against the French did not, however, resolve the profound questions
brought to the surface by the revolution and taken up with such passion by Burke
and Paine. Was the philosophy of the revolution misguided at its core, or did the
French Revolutionaries merely fail to live up to it? The question of that
philosophy—the question of the character of modern liberal government—was
pressed with special force in the early days of the revolution, but it neither began
with the upheaval in Paris nor ended with it. In the wake of the French
Revolution, this question had clearly become a crucial dividing line of modern
political life.
In a 1796 pamphlet titled Letters on a Regicide Peace, Burke argued that the
old division between a party of royal prerogative and a party of parliamentary
power in British politics was falling away: “These parties, which by their
dissensions have so often distracted the Kingdom, which by their union have
once saved it, and which by their collision and mutual resistance, have preserved
the variety of this Constitution in its unity, [are] nearly extinct by the growth of
new ones.”60 These new parties, which he termed the party of conservation and
the party of Jacobins (the name of the most radical faction in Paris), would be
divided along the new axis revealed in the French Revolution—they would be,
in effect, the parties of Burke and Paine.
In America, too, the French Revolution had sharpened a set of differences
that the American Revolution had tended to blur, and by the mid-1790s, the
politics of the American republic were clearly split into two factions with two
very different views of events in France. With these two views came
corresponding differences on a variety of domestic and international questions.
Here, too, a left and a right were beginning to show themselves, very much
along the lines that Burke and Paine had sketched.
While their ideas gave rise to followers and factions, Burke and Paine did not
remain active on the scene long after this final chapter of their confrontation.
Paine stayed in France through much of the rest of the revolution—all the way
until the fall of 1802. But as the movement’s leaders grew increasingly radical
and his own friends fell increasingly into the background, Paine became
estranged from those in power (even spending several months in prison for
affiliating with moderate rebels deemed insufficiently zealous). He devoted
himself to what he took to be the logical next chapter of his intellectual project: a
book in defense of Deism—the view that God’s existence and work are
accessible to reason without need for revelation or organized religion—and so
against most established religions. This final book of Paine’s made precisely the
argument that Burke’s very first published writing had risen to oppose decades
earlier.
Paine believed that an age of enlightened liberal government would carry
with it an enlightened liberal religious outlook that would discourage the kind of
sectarian conflict that had so long torn Europe apart: “A revolution in the system
of government would be followed by a revolution in the system of religion.”61
But because his book, which he titled The Age of Reason, criticized the
traditional forms of organized religion with the same zealous passion for justice
he had brought to his political writing, it set itself so adamantly in opposition to
Christianity that it was bound to spark controversy and would cast a shadow
over Paine’s reputation, especially in America. “Of all the systems of religion
that ever were invented,” he wrote, “there is none more derogatory to the
Almighty, more unedifying to man, more repugnant to reason, and more
contradictory to itself than this thing called Christianity.”62 Having composed
such lines, how could he have expected anything but the hostile reception his
book swiftly received on both sides of the Atlantic?
When he returned to America in 1802 at the invitation of its new president,
his dear friend Thomas Jefferson, Paine found that his attack on Christianity and
his political radicalism made him something of a lightning rod. He continued to
write, but he was not active in politics and only occasionally offered advice to
Jefferson and his allies. With his health and his finances failing him in time,
Paine spent his last days in relative poverty at a boarding house in New York
City. He died on June 8, 1809, and was buried in New Rochelle, New York.
Burke, too, was completing his political projects by the mid-1790s as his
confrontation with Paine reached its height. The trial of Hastings, which had
dragged on for seven years, came to an end in 1794 with a disappointing
acquittal. Burke had earlier declared his intention to leave Parliament upon the
trial’s completion, and now, sixty-four years old and largely vindicated in his
crusade against the revolution, he did so.
His hopes turned to his son, Richard, who Burke thought might take up his
vacated seat in the Commons. The scene seemed set for this plan to succeed
when, in the summer of 1794, Richard Burke fell seriously ill. He died in August
of that year, leaving his father suddenly broken and despondent. Edmund
Burke’s remaining three years were lived in mourning and were taken up with a
defense of his honor from spurious charges of corruption surrounding his
pension, and a firming up of England’s resolve against the French. Burke died on
July 9, 1797, actively engaged to the last in the war of ideas over England’s
future. Parliament was prepared to have him laid to rest among Britain’s
celebrated men at Westminster Abbey, but in accordance with his will, Burke
was buried near his home at Beaconsfield.

BEYOND BIOGRAPHY
Reviewing these two intensely eventful political and intellectual careers, we
might find it hard not to be struck by the scope and the variety of challenges
confronting the Anglo-American politics of the time. And yet, if we consider the
substance of Burke’s and Paine’s views, what stands out is not the diversity of
subjects taken up, but the consistency of key themes and arguments within each
man’s life work and the overarching unity of their extended disagreement. Their
core concerns, convictions, and arguments remained remarkably stable over
three decades of turmoil. And each contended with essentially the same set of
questions as the other, arriving at starkly different conclusions.
In this respect the historical chronology of their dispute, while crucial to any
understanding of the issues at stake, does not finally reveal the true shape of the
argument. The philosophical contours of the great debate are not fully captured
by its historical contours. We must pursue them instead by carefully drawing the
two men’s deepest arguments out of the intense staccato of day-to-day
intellectual and political combat, putting them into order in a way that allows
their assumptions and reasoning to be considered, and then applying what we
learn back onto the patterns of political life. This is the work not quite of history
but of political philosophy—which allows us to look beneath the mad rush of
events and consider how ideas move politics.
The chapters that follow apply this method to Burke’s and Paine’s profound
debate and seek to peel back the layers of the arguments that still shape our
times. We will begin where Burke and Paine both did: with the question of what
idea of nature and human nature should serve as the backdrop against which
political reasoning and judgment occur, and what place history is to have in such
judgments. We will then consider the two men’s very different ideas about
natural and political right, and then analyze each man’s view of social and
political relations. We will then take up their treatment of the place of reason in
political thought and their views of the proper means and the appropriate ends of
such thought. Only after examining these facets of their deep disagreement will
we approach the subject that generally comes up first in discussions of Burke
and Paine: their views of political change, reform, and revolution. And finally,
looking over these facets of the argument, we will highlight a crucial common
thread in the large and varied debates between Burke and Paine: a dispute about
the status of the past and the meaning of the future in political life—an unusual
and unfamiliar question that to this day often sits silently at the heart of our
politics.
TWO

NATURE AND HISTORY

O UNCOVER THE PHILOSOPHICAL UNDERPINNINGS of political

T debates, we have to first assume that what goes on in politics answers to


more than just people’s passing preferences and material interests. If
political ideas are applications of philosophical ideas—of some
understanding of what is true and good in life—then serious political debates
must be rooted in different philosophical assumptions. And because such
differences involve what lies beneath the level of events and arguments, they
often come down to disputes about what we take to be true by nature about
human beings. That is why debates about political philosophy often begin from
debates about nature and human nature. But the meanings of these terms—nature
and human nature—are not simple or self-evident. They are themselves subject
to intense debate, and that prior debate about what we mean by the natural is
often an indicator of the assumptions that guide our political thinking.
Such differences are powerfully evident in the Burke-Paine debate, and both
men were exceptionally well aware of them. Burke and Paine each sought to
base his arguments—from his very earliest writings on—on an idea of what
nature and human nature were and what they should mean for political life. Their
dispute begins, in effect, with a debate about nature and its relation to history, so
our examination of their views should begin there too.

PAINE’S NATURAL SOCIETY


For the modern-day reader of Thomas Paine’s Common Sense, the pamphlet’s
opening sections cannot help but come as a surprise. Given the immense
influence of Paine’s case for American independence and the author’s reputation
for brilliant and fiery rhetoric, we expect to be greeted with a passionate call to
arms and a catalog of British offenses. But Paine takes his time getting to the
American crisis (which does not really appear until the pamphlet’s third section)
and instead launches into a thought experiment he insists is essential to
grounding any theory of politics: “In order to gain a clear and just idea of the
design and end of government, let us suppose a small number of persons settled
in some sequestered part of the earth, unconnected with the rest, they will then
represent the first peopling of any country, or of the world. In this state of natural
liberty, society will be their first thought.”1
Paine argues for a just resolution of the Anglo-American dispute—as he will
argue for a variety of political causes throughout the long career begun by this
pamphlet—by starting from first and fundamental political principles. When
seeking to understand political and social institutions, he suggests, we must seek
for their earliest origins and deepest roots; we can only truly understand them by
seeing where they came from. “The error of those who reason by precedents
drawn from antiquity respecting the rights of man,” Paine explains in Rights of
Man, “is that they do not go far enough into antiquity. They do not go the whole
way.”2
This “whole way,” as Paine repeatedly makes clear, involves looking not to
history, but beyond history to nature. And by “nature,” he means the condition
that preceded all social and political arrangements and therefore the facts
regarding what every human being is, regardless of social or political
circumstances. Our nature remains just as it was at the beginning of the human
race, since our various social arrangements don’t change what we are by nature
—what every human being always has been and will be. And so our basic nature
must remain the foundation of our political thinking—of our understanding of
what human beings are and how they ought to live together.
Paine begins nearly all of his major writings by restating this basic case, the
key features of which come from Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, and other
political thinkers of the Enlightenment. It is the essential starting point of his
political philosophy: that reflection on politics must begin from permanent
natural facts about human beings, which means it must begin from man himself,
apart from society (and therefore, in essence, before society).3 The only reliable
source of authority is the original source: “If a dispute about the rights of man
had arisen at the distance of an hundred years from the creation, it is to this
source of authority they must have referred, and it is to this same source of
authority that we must now refer.”4 Paine argues that when we look at politics in
this way—as if all of human history had never happened—“we are brought at
once to the point of seeing government begin, as if we had lived in the beginning
of time. The real volume, not of history, but of facts, is directly before us,
unmutilated by contrivance, or the errors of tradition.”5
And just what are these facts that nature offers up? What does Paine see
when he looks past history to our natural beginnings? The very method of
searching after the natural human condition in this way suggests to Paine one
inescapable fact about man first and foremost: At his origin, man is an
individual. And because he has no social relations to start with, he is burdened
by no social distinctions and therefore is equal to all other men. Social
hierarchies have no natural foundation:
Every history of the creation, . . . however they may vary in their opinion or belief of certain
particulars, all agree in establishing one point, the unity of man; by which I mean that men are all
of one degree, and consequently that all men are born equal, and with equal natural right, in the
same manner as if posterity had been continued by creation instead of generation, the latter being
only the mode by which the former is carried forward; and consequently every child born into the
world must be considered as deriving its existence from God. The world is as new to him as it was
to the first man that existed, and his natural right in it is of the same kind.6

Here Paine makes explicit something that other liberal theorists tended not
to. To imagine that we are unchanged since the beginning of time is to believe
that the means of human generation and the procession of generations through
time tell us nothing of great importance about human life. That is, social
relations and distinctions built up over generations have no inherent authority.
And it means, also, that human beings are always most fully understood as
distinct and equal individuals. Society and government involve collections of
such individuals—organized by those individuals for their benefit—but these
groupings of people never fully overwhelm the essentially solitary character of
the human person. “A nation,” Paine writes, “is composed of distinct,
unconnected individuals, [and] . . . public good is not a term opposed to the good
of individuals; on the contrary, it is the good of every individual collected.”7
In pursuit of that good, moreover, individuals begin to assemble into groups.
Just as man is best understood by his origins, so too are society and government,
and for that reason, Paine takes society and government to be two distinct things.
Men originally join together out of necessity and a desire for company. “No one
man is capable,” he writes, “without the aid of society, of supplying his own
wants, and those wants, acting upon every individual, impel the whole of them
into society, as naturally as gravitation acts to a center.” And just as it supplies
the need, nature also supplies the desire for society: “She has not only forced
man into society by a diversity of wants which the reciprocal aid of each other
can supply, but she has implanted in him a system of social affections, which,
though not necessary to his existence, are essential to his happiness.”8 Human
beings are therefore social creatures with needs and wants that reach beyond
themselves. But even for the purpose of assessing their sociality, humans are best
understood as equal and separate individuals.
In his description of this natural human condition, Paine certainly sounds a
lot like the Enlightenment-liberal theorists of his day and like John Locke, on
whom they drew. To make the case for individual rights and social equality,
these thinkers built on theories of how individuals first formed societies. But
more than most, and certainly more than Locke, Paine emphasizes the difference
between the gathering of human beings into society—driven by the need to meet
necessities and by the desire for company—and the establishment of
governments over these societies.
For Paine, there is a crucial middle step between the state of nature and the
political community: the natural society that exists at first without a government.
When humans first gathered into society, the motives and needs that drew them
together naturally governed their cooperation, and they achieved a relatively
sophisticated degree of social life without a need for government as such. But
over time, as they succeeded in overcoming necessity, they relaxed in their
duties, and some form of government became necessary to restrain their vices.
Paine makes more of this distinction between society and government than
do many liberal theorists before him, because it is crucial to his case for
revolution, both in America and in France.9 To the charge (made by Edmund
Burke, among others) that an all-out revolution would bring the dissolution of
society itself and so make any government that followed illegitimate, Paine has
an answer. First, he says, society is older and more important than government.
Second, a revolution consists of a reversion to the natural society for the purpose
of establishing a new government from the same origins as the old one, but
better and more justly formed and organized. “A great part of that order which
reigns among mankind is not the effect of government,” Paine argues in Rights
of Man. “It has its origin in the principles of society and the natural constitution
of man. It existed prior to government, and would exist if the formality of
government was abolished.”10 Paine considers the original society a function of
human nature, while government is an artifice created by human will and
therefore subject to imperfect judgment and especially to corruption by power
and greed.
This natural society, however, remains permanently accessible. Because it is
essentially a function of human nature, we can always revert to it when the
conventional government has failed to carry out its functions or has violated the
rights of its citizens. Such a reversion allows a society to, as Paine puts it, “go
back to nature for information” and “regenerate” itself.11 Thus, as Paine
famously declares, “we have it in our power to begin the world over again.”12
By throwing off our government, we can regenerate our original society and can
“see government begin as if we lived at the beginning of time.”13
This is what a revolution means for Paine—it is, at its core, a return to the
distant past to begin again, and better. “What were formerly called Revolutions,”
he tells us in Rights of Man, “were little more than a change of persons, or an
alteration of local circumstances. . . . But what we now see in the world, from
the Revolutions of America and France, are a renovation of the natural order of
things, a system of principles as universal as truth and the existence of man, and
combining moral with political happiness and national prosperity.”14
The recovery Paine has in mind, however, is not a return to some earlier
period of recorded human history. Rather he seeks a return to the purity of
nature, which, although it ought to inform our political life, has never been
properly put into practice as the organizing principle of a government. In this
respect, Paine’s revolutionary ethic is indeed progressive, even though it looks
back to the very beginning of politics. It understands itself as innovative because
it begins from a knowledge of nature that has never before been achieved.
Nature itself has always been as it is, but Paine believed that it was only
becoming understood for the first time in his own day: “Though it might be
proved that the system of government now called the new is the most ancient in
principle of all that have existed, being founded on the original, inherent Rights
of Man: yet, as tyranny and the sword have suspended the exercise of those
rights for many centuries past, it serves better the purpose of distinction to call it
the new, than to claim the right of calling it the old.”15
Paine considers most of human history until his own enlightened age a
diversion from the effort to understand the proper principles of government:
“[People] have had so few opportunities of making the necessary trials on modes
and principles of government, in order to discover the best, that government is
but now beginning to be known.”16
Government was only in his day beginning to be known, Paine believed,
because nature itself was only then beginning to be properly known. Like most
of his late-Enlightenment contemporaries, Paine drew heavily on the worldview
of the new natural science in formulating his idea of nature. Just half a century
after Isaac Newton’s death, the age in which Paine lived was still very much in
thrall of the revolution in physics—a revolution that seemed to open endless
possibilities for the conquest of nature and the empowerment of man. And the
fundamental principle of this new science was the understanding of nature as
consisting of distinct and separable forces acting on distinct and separable
objects according to rational rules—rather than (as in the ancient science of
Aristotle that it displaced) of organic wholes defined by the ends they were
meant to achieve.
Like many of his contemporaries, Paine considered his political philosophy
an application of this new way of understanding nature. This is one reason he
places such emphasis on tracing things back to their origins, and why when he
speaks of the “facts” of nature, he appears to have in mind principles—rational
laws and rules—that set the boundaries for action, rather than an organic model
of complex wholes interacting. “I draw my idea of the form of government from
a principle in nature which no art can overturn,” Paine writes, “viz. that the more
simple any thing is, the less liable it is to be disordered; and the easier repaired
when disordered.”17
The distinction between nature and “art,” or intentional human action, is
crucial and firm for Paine: Nature is that which is inherent about man, absent all
effort and will, while art is the product of man’s work. Nature is there to be
understood, and the understanding of nature produces a set of rules to guide our
choices. Presenting itself as a set of generalizable laws, nature is thus in most
respects an abstraction.
Nature, in Paine’s view, is therefore the set of facts and axioms about both
man and his world that describes all that man has not himself created. It is
orderly, rational, and governed by abstract rules with general application. We can
best understand nature by breaking it down into its simplest possible parts and
tracing it back to the earliest possible beginnings, where the parts are most
readily discerned.
As Paine defines it, then, society is a function of nature, while government is
a product of art. But the purposes of government are defined by man’s natural
rights and natural limits, so although men create government, they must create it
with the facts of nature in mind, and in such a way as to protect each man’s
natural prerogatives and rights and to secure the natural freedom and best
interest of all. The science of government, therefore, begins from a knowledge of
nature through reason, and government can be judged by how effectively it
respects man’s individual freedom and equality.
Paine believes that the failure to form governments in accordance with this
understanding is responsible for the failures of politics up to his day. “Can we
possibly suppose,” he wonders, “that if governments had originated in a right
principle, and had not an interest in pursuing a wrong one, the world could have
been in the wretched and quarrelsome condition we have seen it?”18
To assess the legitimacy of existing governments, therefore, Paine argues
that we must look to the precepts of nature—the principles especially of human
equality and individuality, which give each man an equal right with every other
to determine the course of government. That means that only power willingly
granted is legitimate, and only a government by consent is just. “All power
exercised over a nation must have some beginning,” Paine writes. “It must either
be delegated or assumed. There are no other sources. All delegated power is
trust, and all assumed power is usurpation. Time does not alter the nature and
quality of either.”19 However far we might be from it, we must look back to the
beginning of our society to determine which sort of society it is, and those who
refuse to look cannot make judgments regarding legitimacy.
At its source, a legitimate government is established by the choice of the
people. When moved by the necessity of creating a regime, they all meet
together, forming a kind of parliament in which every citizen has his own seat
“by natural right.” But over time, as the community grows, it will be impossible
for everyone to attend to public matters personally all the time, so they appoint
representatives “who will act in the same manner as the whole body would were
they present.”20 This representative democracy is the form of government best
in line with nature, according to Paine.
But it was, of course, not the form most commonly found in the world in
Paine’s time. He believed that the more common form at the time, the monarchy,
traced its origins in every instance to some usurper who had established himself
over others by force. There could be no justification in nature for such unequal
power, and so there was no justification in practice. “When men are spoken of as
kings and subjects, or when government is mentioned under the distinct or
combined heads of monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy, what is it that
reasoning man is to understand by these terms?” Paine asks. “If there really
existed in the world two or more distinct and separate elements of human power,
we should then see the several origins to which those terms would descriptively
apply; but as there is but one species of man, there can be but one element of
human power, and that element is man himself.”21 Of kings, he therefore asserts
with plain derision in Common Sense, “as nature knows them not, they know not
her, and although they are beings of our own creating, they know not us and are
become the gods of their creators.”22
Kings and nobles commonly seek to portray themselves as possessed of
elevated origins deep in the mists of history, but Paine will have none of it: “It is
more than probable that, could we take off the dark covering of antiquity, and
trace them to their first rise, we should find the first of them nothing better than
the principal ruffian of some restless gang, whose savage manners, or pre-
eminence in subtlety, obtained him the title of chief among the plunderers.”23
And worse yet, monarchs pass their illegitimate power on to their children,
denying their people’s natural rights beyond their own lives. Because of Paine’s
insistence on the importance of origins, he considers the hereditary principle
near the root of all evil. By compelling men to accept the decisions of prior
generations, it denies them their natural right to self-determination and is
therefore a profoundly unnatural principle of government.
Paine thus consistently asserts the supremacy of nature (understood in terms
of principles accessible to reason) over history (understood as a catalog of
human failures to apply the proper principles to politics). The facts that nature
teaches us about human beings explain why society came to be, and the natural
imperfection of human beings explains why legitimate government is necessary,
while the existence of illegitimate government explains why wars, poverty, and
endless other troubles have occurred. The solution is to replace illegitimate
governments with ones more in line with the emerging understanding of man’s
nature and thereby to advance the cause of natural peace. And the end of a
political revolution, properly understood, is a return to natural society with this
purpose in mind. The great bulk of Paine’s political ideas begin from these
reflections on nature and pursue their implications.

BURKE’S HISTORICAL SOCIETY


Edmund Burke began his own public career by rejecting precisely the view of
nature and its relation to politics that we have just seen Paine lay out. His first
major work, The Vindication of Natural Society, published in 1756, argues in
essence that looking past all conventional institutions and accepting only nature
(narrowly understood as an abstract set of rules) as a source of authority or
insight about human affairs would be deeply corrosive of political and social life.
In the satirical voice of the Vindication, Burke mocks the idea that people
can make any progress by assuming that all of human history has in essence
been a failure because all existing governments have been corruptions of our
original natural condition. While Paine would employ this method to attack
monarchy and aristocracy, Burke in the Vindication and other publications
suggests such a method could just as easily undermine any other form of
government and indeed any other human institution.
Burke believes, first of all, that this method is wrong because it makes far too
much of social and political beginnings. He considers the exposure of origins a
misguided, needless, and potentially destructive enterprise. A government does
not derive its legitimacy by beginning from the proper principles, drawn from
nature. Instead, government develops through time along lines that serve the
needs and well-being of the people and therefore point toward some natural idea
of the good.
The beginnings of any society, Burke writes, are almost certain to involve
some form of barbarism (not to say crime). But over time, by slowly responding
to circumstantial exigencies, societies develop more mature forms—a process
that, as Burke puts it in the Reflections on the Revolution in France, “mellows
into legality governments that were violent in their commencement.”24 A return
to beginnings would thus not offer an opportunity to start anew on proper
principles, but would rather risk a reversion to barbarism. “There is a sacred veil
to be drawn over the beginnings of all governments,” Burke argues, because
there is little to be learned by exposing them, and there is a very real risk of harm
in the exposure itself—especially the risk of weakening the allegiance of the
people to their regime by exposing its imperfect origins.25
This rejection of the importance of beginnings separates Burke from the vast
majority of political thinkers in the Western tradition—from Plato and Aristotle
through Hobbes and Locke and their modern successors. These thinkers have
argued that a founding is a crucial political moment, when the character of a
regime is decisively given shape.26 As detailed in later chapters, Burke argues
instead that a regime takes shape over time and is never in fact “the effect of a
single instantaneous regulation.” Thus, its original shape (let alone the origin of
all political society) is not so crucial as its current shape and function and its
development to this point.27
Paine roundly criticized Burke’s denigration of beginnings, arguing that it is
simply an effort to avoid confronting Britain’s particular illegitimate origins: “A
certain something forbids him to look back to a beginning, lest some robber, or
some Robin Hood, should rise from the long obscurity of time and say, ‘I am the
origin.’”28 Burke does acknowledge a concern of this sort, noting that an
intimate familiarity with the barbarous origins of their regime may undermine
the people’s patriotism. But his greater concern is that in looking past history in
search of nature, people would look past the best available source of wisdom and
instruction to a source of little if any useful knowledge about political life.
Burke never quite bothers to dispute the particular assertions that Paine and
other liberal theorists make about what man’s presocial nature might tell us,
because he thinks it is absurd to think about a presocial man to begin with.29
This does not mean that an understanding of man’s nature is not crucial to an
understanding of society and politics, but Burke argues that to learn about man’s
nature, we need to understand man as he is and, to our knowledge at least, has
always been: a social creature, living together with others in an organized society
with a government. To imagine him as solitary and asocial is to ignore man
himself in pursuit of an abstraction with little to teach us. “I have in my
contemplation the civil social man, and no other,” Burke writes.30
The institutions of society are certainly conventional, he argues. They “are
often the contrivances of deep human wisdom (not the rights of men, as some
people in my opinion not very wisely talk of them).”31 But it is man’s nature to
affect such conventions, and we make a serious mistake if we draw a sharp
distinction between the natural and the artificial in human affairs and thereby
ignore everything that man does in the world as we seek to understand his
nature. “Art is man’s nature,” Burke argues. “We are as much, at least, in a state
of nature in formed manhood, as in immature and helpless infancy . . . the state
of civil society . . . is a state of nature, and much more truly so than a savage and
incoherent mode of life.”32 This blurring of the distinction between nature and
artifice is a crucial move for Burke, distinguishing him sharply from Paine and
other Enlightenment-liberal theorists of his day. Burke shows, in David
Bromwich’s apt phrase, “respect for society and nature as elements of a single
human environment.”33
As we have seen, the distinction between artifice and nature is crucial for
Thomas Paine’s view of the world because he accuses the corrupt regimes—the
aristocracies and monarchies—most especially of raising artificial barriers
between nature and man and therefore denying individual human beings the
rights to which they are entitled by nature. A revolution, as Paine sees it, throws
off all convention and reverts to the original conditions from which regimes
emerge, to regenerate and begin again from the start. By denying the stark
distinction between the natural and artificial or conventional, therefore, Burke
closes off the possibility of such reversion. Regimes, he says, are built primarily
on conventions and are natural in the sense that artistry and artifice are natural to
man. A society cannot be grounded in rights that exist only outside of society.
“The pretended rights of man, which have made this havoc,” Burke writes
regarding the French Revolution in direct response to Paine in 1791, “cannot be
the rights of the people. For to be a people, and to have these rights, are things
incompatible. The one supposes the presence, the other the absence of a state of
civil society.”34 A people therefore cannot revert to a presocial state in which
such rights are in effect, because in doing so, they would cease to be a people.
Burke continues:
The idea of a people is the idea of a corporation. It is wholly artificial; and made like all other
legal fictions by common agreement. . . . When men, therefore, break up the original compact or
agreement which gives its corporate form and capacity to a state, they are no longer a people; they
have no longer a corporate existence; they have no longer a legal coactive force to bind within, nor
a claim to be recognized abroad. They are a number of vague loose individuals, and nothing
more.35

Paine’s idea of revolution, therefore, seems to Burke a recipe for societal


suicide, because it relies on the presumption—which Burke takes to be false—
that by the nature of things, the society will persist when its regime has been
dissolved. In the wake of such a dissolution, Burke argues, there will be no rules
or methods by which a new regime could form: no protections of property or
persons, no reason to follow a leader or adhere to majority rule, no means for
“regenerating.”
In fact, Burke considers the very desire for such a regeneration of one’s own
society appalling. “I cannot conceive how any man can have brought himself to
consider his country as nothing but carte blanche, upon which he may scribble
whatever he pleases,” Burke writes. “A man full of warm speculative
benevolence may wish his society otherwise constituted than he finds it; but a
good patriot, and a true politician, always considers how he shall make the most
of the existing materials of his country.”36 We do not have it in our power to
begin the world over again, Burke suggests.
Building on existing forms using existing materials requires not an abstract
study of nature but a very particular understanding of the history and character
of one’s society. Because the state is conventional, and because the abstract
rights of man do not provide explicit rules for political life directly,
statesmanship is almost always a matter of prudence, an “experimental science,”
as Burke puts it.37 The results of such experiments do not become evident
immediately, so that to learn from them takes time—often more than any single
lifetime. For this reason, history, and not only nature, must inform political life,
and existing political forms should not be abandoned lightly.38 This does not
mean that history is always an honor roll of great and wise accomplishments.
Human history, Burke writes in the Reflections on the Revolution in France,
“consists for the most part of the miseries brought upon the world by pride,
ambition, avarice, revenge, lust, sedition, hypocrisy, ungoverned zeal, and all the
train of disorderly appetites,” but it also consists of efforts to address these vices,
and in both its best and worst manifestations, history offers lessons no statesman
can afford to ignore.39
Burke thus disagrees profoundly with the method of argument and the notion
of nature that informs Paine and the more radical liberal philosophers. But his
inclination to present his views as a critique of others tends to mask the positive
teaching about nature that underlies Burke’s arguments. His sharp rejection of
Paine’s idea of nature begins to point toward his own very different idea.
The Enlightenment philosophers, Burke worries, “are so taken up with their
theories about the rights of man, that they have totally forgotten his nature.”40
Burke is fairly specific as to what they miss about that nature: the part that is not
simply matter in motion or reason in action. A politics oriented to man’s nature
understands man as an animal being, a rational being, and a creature of
sympathies and sentiments.41 Paine and other radical liberal thinkers leave the
human sentiments and the role of the imagination out of their understanding of
human nature. By overemphasizing both the animal and the rational elements of
man, Burke worries, they not only disregard but also undermine the sentiments
that are in fact key to human nature and political order.
The revolutionaries imagined that man was basically a rational animal, so
that if his simple needs (for food and safety) were met, his reason would govern
him.42 Those he disagreed with, including Paine, did not of course deny that
there were other parts to human nature, but Burke believed they had far too
much faith in the ability of reason alone to govern those other elements—and
especially the passions and sentiments.
From a young age, Burke had concerned himself with the place of the
passions in human affairs, and his Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of Our
Ideas of the Sublime and the Beautiful, written just a year after the Vindication of
Natural Society when Burke was only twenty-eight, was devoted to the subject.
He argued especially that the sublime, which draws on man’s simultaneous fear
of and fascination with death, exercises enormous power over the human
imagination. That power can unleash violent torrents of energy into social life if
it is not properly managed by an appeal to man’s simultaneous (if often weaker)
attraction to order and social peace (that is, to the beautiful). The common life of
a community depends a great deal on sentimental attachments and implicit
appeals to this love of the beautiful and the orderly, and in Burke’s view, these
play a vital but generally underappreciated role in the prevention of political
violence and the maintenance of warm and peaceful relations in society. This is
one reason why, for Burke, the stable order of society should not be needlessly
disrupted, and the importance of the rituals, ceremonies, and outright pomp that
often accompany social and political life should not be dismissed.
Burke was not a sentimentalist, however.43 “Leave a man to his passions,”
he wrote, “and you leave a wild beast to a savage and capricious nature.”44
Rather, he argued that while politics does answer to reason, human reason does
not interact directly with the world but is always mediated by our imagination,
which helps us to give order and shape to the data we derive from our senses.
One way or another, reason applies through the sentiments and passions, so it is
crucial to tend to what he calls our “moral imagination” because left untended, it
will direct our reason toward violence and disorder.45
The dark side of our sentiments is mitigated not by pure reason, but by more
beneficent sentiments. We cannot be simply argued out of our vices, but we can
be deterred from indulging them by the trust and love that develops among
neighbors, by deeply established habits of order and peace, and by pride in our
community or country. And part of the statesman’s difficult charge is keeping
this balance together, acting rationally on this understanding of the limits of
reason. “The temper of the people amongst whom he presides ought therefore to
be the first study of a statesman,” Burke asserts.46 It is for Burke another reason
why politics can never be reduced to a simple application of logical axioms. As
Burke’s contemporary William Hazlitt put it: “[Burke] knew that man had
affections and passions and powers of imagination, as well as hunger and thirst
and the sense of heat and cold. . . . He knew that the rules that form the basis of
private morality are not founded in reason, that is, in the abstract properties of
those things which are the subjects of them, but in the nature of man, and his
capacity of being affected by certain things from habit, from imagination, and
sentiment, as well as from reason.”47
This lifelong interest in the natural passions made Burke acutely attuned to
the role of habits and sentiments in political life and to the risks of either
breaking the habits of peace or creating habits of unchecked terror or power. He
thus objected to British actions in America as an affront to the habits and
sentiments of the Americans, even if the actions were not a violation of
Americans’ rights. The same concern caused him to worry about how the young
British men sent to India would be influenced by the unlimited authority they
were given over the locals there. It caused him to fear far earlier than most that
the French revolutionaries, by exploding all the myths that beautified social life,
would unleash a wave of mesmerizing horror that could unmoor everyone
involved from their habits and restraints.
In this respect, Burke argued that the actions of the revolutionaries—by
denying the sentimental aspect of human nature—were profoundly unnatural and
anti-natural. He refused to cede the language of nature in politics to Paine and
the French and English radicals, because he grounded his case for resisting
radical political disruption in a notion of nature quite different from that of the
radicals. In his writings on the French Revolution, Burke repeatedly argued that
the revolutionaries were “at war with nature” or overturning “the order of
nature.”48 But he did not suggest that the particular institutions or arrangements
of prerevolutionary France were themselves natural. That was not the order
being overturned. Rather, the revolutionaries were warring against human nature.
By ignoring or failing to restrain popular passions, they threatened to unleash the
darkest of those passions upon society, utterly desensitizing the people to acts of
terror and violence and so making orderly social life after the revolution
impossible.
This is why Burke placed such heavy emphasis on what he argued was a
natural revulsion to some of the particular actions that characterized the
revolution. The natural revulsion to terrible power is absolutely essential to
Burke’s vision of the functional society. The revolutionaries’ lack of any such
natural reaction had a great deal to do with Burke’s vehemence in opposing
them. He explains what he found so off-putting about Richard Price’s celebration
of the mob violence of the revolution (which was what first moved him to write
the Reflections):
Why do I feel so differently from the Reverend Dr. Price, and those of his lay flock, who will
choose to adopt the sentiments of his discourse? For this plain reason—because it is natural I
should; because we are so made as to be affected at such spectacles with melancholy sentiments
upon the unstable condition of mortal prosperity, and the tremendous uncertainty of human
greatness; because in those natural feelings we learn great lessons; because in events like these our
passions instruct our reason. . . . Some tears might be drawn from me, if such a spectacle were
exhibited on the stage. I should be truly ashamed of finding in myself that superficial, theatric
sense of painted distress, whilst I could exult over it in real life.49

Burke saw in the absence of such a natural reaction to the spectacles of the
revolution a sure sign of trouble—a lack of restraint that could only end in
disaster. This radically unnatural lack of restraint, in his view, had to be taught. A
product of a political theory at odds with nature, it justified violence and
threatened to desensitize the public to violence. “Such must be the consequences
of losing, in the splendor of these triumphs of the rights of men, all natural sense
of wrong and right,” Burke worries.50 A sophisticated theory in the service of
mob violence was nearly the most dangerous thing in the world.
Burke believed that most Englishmen, by contrast, had not yet been educated
out of their habits of peace. His countrymen, he writes, are “generally men of
untaught feelings,” which speak more truly of human nature than the radicalism
of the revolutionaries. In one of the most famous passages of the Reflections,
Burke expounds on the peaceful habits of the English:
In England, we . . . have not yet been completely emboweled of our natural entrails; we still feel
within us, and we cherish and cultivate, . . . those inbred sentiments which are the faithful
guardians, the active monitors of our duty, the true supporters of all liberal and manly morals. We
have not been drawn and trussed, in order that we may be filled, like stuffed birds in a museum,
with chaff and rags, and paltry blurred shreds of paper about the rights of man. . . . We have real
hearts of flesh and blood beating in our bosoms. We fear God; we look up with awe to kings; with
affection to parliaments; with duty to magistrates; with reverence to priests; and with respect to
nobility. Why? Because when such ideas are brought before our minds, it is natural to be so
affected; because all other feelings are false and spurious, and tend to corrupt our minds, to vitiate
our primary morals, to render us unfit for rational liberty.51

In his description, an entire system of morals, habits, and practices had arisen
to support the sentiments friendly to society, and the attempt to overthrow that
system threatens to eviscerate those sentiments and thereby endanger social
peace and individual security.
The system, Burke argues, has generally gone by the old-fashioned name of
“chivalry.” It is the collection of habits intended to pacify and to beautify two
crucial and often dangerous sets of relationships: those between men and women
on the one hand, and those between ruler and ruled on the other. The system of
chivalry ennobled both sets of connections by elevating them with high
sentiments and feelings (gentleness, devotion, and faithfulness in the one case;
obligation, duty, and loyalty in the other).52 But this tradition, which Burke
believed had given its character to modern Europe, was under attack by the
revolutionaries:
All is to be changed. All the pleasing illusions, which made power gentle and obedience liberal,
which harmonized the different shades of life, and which, by a bland assimilation, incorporated
into politics the sentiments which beautify and soften private society, are to be dissolved by this
new conquering empire of light and reason. All the decent drapery of life is to be rudely torn off.
All the superadded ideas, furnished from the wardrobe of a moral imagination, which the heart
owns, and the understanding ratifies, as necessary to cover the defects of our naked, shivering
nature, and to raise it to dignity in our own estimation, are to be exploded as ridiculous, absurd,
and antiquated fashion.53

The radicals’ idea of nature, Burke argues, is only our naked animal nature
and the naked reason that reveals it, and by stripping away the appeal to beauty,
this stark philosophy eradicates every obstacle to radicalism and violence: “On
this scheme of things, a king is but a man; a queen is but a woman; a woman is
but an animal; and an animal not of the highest order.”54 In this sense,
radicalism is truly dehumanizing.
And the absence of chivalry—the failure to respond with outrage to grievous
violations and abuses—has terrible implications for society. This is the context
for one of the most famous and most highly criticized flourishes in Burke’s
writings on France: his grand romantic paean to Marie Antoinette, written in
reaction to the events of October 6, 1789, when a mob attacked the palace of
Louis XVI and nearly killed the queen. Burke begins his reflection by recalling
his once having met the queen while on a semi-official visit to Versailles:
It is now sixteen or seventeen years since I saw the queen of France, then the dauphiness, at
Versailles, and surely never lighted on this orb, which she hardly seemed to touch, a more
delightful vision. I saw her just above the horizon, decorating and cheering the elevated sphere she
just began to move in—glittering like the morning star, full of life and splendor and joy. Oh! what
a revolution! and what a heart must I have to contemplate without emotion that elevation and that
fall! Little did I dream when she added titles of veneration to those of enthusiastic, distant,
respectful love, that she should ever be obliged to carry the sharp antidote against disgrace
concealed in that bosom.

Burke is deeply disturbed that the people of France would not rise to the
defense of their queen when her life was threatened and that they did not even
seem particularly moved by the attack. As he notes in a famously (and almost
painfully) flowery passage of the Reflections:
Little did I dream that I should have lived to see such disasters fallen upon her in a nation of
gallant men, in a nation of men of honor and of cavaliers. I thought ten thousand swords must
have leaped from their scabbards to avenge even a look that threatened her with insult. But the age
of chivalry is gone. That of sophisters, economists, and calculators has succeeded; and the glory of
Europe is extinguished forever. Never, never more shall we behold that generous loyalty to rank
and sex, that proud submission, that dignified obedience, that subordination of the heart which
kept alive, even in servitude itself, the spirit of an exalted freedom. The unbought grace of life, the
cheap defense of nations, the nurse of manly sentiment and heroic enterprise, is gone! It is gone,
that sensibility of principle, that chastity of honor which felt a stain like a wound, which inspired
courage whilst it mitigated ferocity, which ennobled whatever it touched, and under which vice
itself lost half its evil by losing all its grossness.55

The sheer floridity of this passage was bound to draw scorn, and it
immediately did. The very first reader of the Reflections, Burke’s good friend
Philip Francis, was sent an early draft for comment. He wrote to Burke that
while the essay as a whole was very powerful, “in my opinion all that you say of
the queen is pure foppery. If she be a perfect female character you ought to take
your ground upon her virtues. If she be the reverse it is ridiculous in any but a
lover to place her personal charms in opposition to her crimes.”56
Paine’s critique was even more severe, accusing Burke of sketching “tragic
paintings” for his readers to mask the horrors committed by the old regime in
France and describing him as a kind of quixotic knight chasing windmills in
search of a lost age of chivalry.57 And in a sense, this critique is more accurate
than Francis’s. As Burke made clear in his response to Francis, the notion that a
thousand swords should have leaped to protect the queen was not a reflection on
the queen’s character. It reflected on the character of those who lived under a
chivalrous system and who would not let a woman be mistreated. Men should be
so cultured that their natural reaction of pity and reverence is allowed to govern
their actions, rather than being replaced by a sophisticated cynicism. A political
system that gives up on the effort to educate man’s natural sentiments to good
ends would quickly degenerate into despotism, because it would have no hold on
its people’s allegiance except the threat of force. “On the scheme of this
barbarous philosophy,” Burke wrote in the Reflections, “which is the offspring of
cold hearts and muddy understandings, and which is as void of solid wisdom as
it is destitute of all taste and elegance, laws are to be supported only by their
own terrors. . . . In the groves of their academy, at the end of every vista, you see
nothing but the gallows. Nothing is left which engages the affections on the part
of the commonwealth.”58
Burke thus first rejects the radical appeal to nature as potentially ruinous and
then offers the beginning of a positive description of man’s nature by reference
to what exactly he believes might be ruined by the radicals. Man’s reliance on
his imagination to guide even his reason is a natural fact crucially relevant to
political life. A successful political order must protect and sustain the “wardrobe
of our moral imagination” and never lose sight of its importance.
But just how could such a political order be constructed and sustained over
time? Thomas Paine’s model of nature, after all, offered both means and ends for
political action by holding up a particular understanding of nature—taken to be a
set of rational rules that begin from individualism and equality—as the standard
of legitimacy that should give shape to change over time. Burke’s understanding
of human nature offers reasons, including reasons grounded in a positive
teaching about human nature, to worry about the actual consequences of
applying Paine’s model. But what does Burke’s own alternative view have to say
about political change? Here Burke turns most explicitly to nature for an answer.
While he denies that any particular political system is somehow natural to
man, he believes that in thinking about how best to manage and guide political
change over time, we would be wise to look to the model of how change happens
in nature and to follow that model by choice. His model of nature is not Paine’s
system of rational rules akin to modern physics but something more like the
example of biological organisms transmitting their traits through the generations:
a system of inheritance. In an extraordinary passage in the Reflections, Burke
lays out how the natural example is crucial to his larger view of political life:
By a constitutional policy, working after the pattern of nature, we receive, we hold, we transmit
our government and our privileges, in the same manner in which we enjoy and transmit our
property and our lives. The institutions of policy, the goods of fortune, the gifts of providence, are
handed down to us, and from us, in the same course and order. Our political system is placed in a
just correspondence and symmetry with the order of the world, and with the mode of existence
decreed to a permanent body composed of transitory parts; wherein, by the disposition of a
stupendous wisdom, molding together the great mysterious incorporation of the human race, the
whole at one time is never old, or middle-aged, or young, but in a condition of unchangeable
constancy, moves on through the varied tenor of perpetual decay, fall, renovation, and progression.
Thus, by preserving the method of nature in the conduct of the state, in what we improve, we are
never wholly new; in what we retain, we are never wholly obsolete.59

This analogy teaches us a great deal about Burke’s view of nature. It points
to his focus on the facts of birth and death and the need to manage change,
decay, renovation, and progress. He has in mind, too, a kind of model of species,
rather than individuals, so that his appeal to nature, quite unlike Paine’s, does not
yield in individualism but in a case for the implicit and inescapable
embeddedness of every individual in a larger context.
But Burke also clearly asserts that he sees this interpretation only as a model.
This approach to politics is a kind of choice, not a natural fact. Parallels between
nature and politics “rather furnish similitudes to illustrate or adorn, than supply
analogies from which to reason.”60 The English, Burke argues, choose to adhere
to a model of nature—a model of transmission and inheritance that enables
gentle, gradual change—in their political life. They might well have chosen
otherwise. But they wisely follow the model of nature because it draws on some
of the advantages apparent in the natural world for dealing with certain
complicated and inescapable natural obstacles to progress. First and foremost
among these obstacles, people are born and die, and so the human race is always
threatened by discontinuities. By connecting the generations to one another,
rather than sending each all the way back to the first origins of man for
information, Burke’s model secures a means of cultural transmission that takes
account of the life cycle, about which we human beings have no choice.
It also enables responsible change. By always seeing ourselves as carrying
forward and improving on an inheritance, Burke reasons, we need not feel like
the first to do anything, and even new ideas can be fitted into the patterns of old
ones—so that gradual innovations might bring improvements without the usual
impudence of innovators. A sense of age and long-standing also breeds respect
and encourages peaceful and benevolent sentimental attachments to one’s
society: “By this means, our liberty becomes a noble freedom. It carries an
imposing and majestic aspect. It has a pedigree and illustrating ancestors.”61
By treating existing political institutions and practices as an entailed
inheritance, citizens learn to think of them as a kind of charge—a gift from the
past that, preserved and suitably improved upon, is owed to the future—and
therefore learn not to dismiss them lightly. Men are by nature drawn to novelty
and excitement, Burke worries, and only by being stirred by the beauty of the
given can they see its advantages and so be appropriately skeptical and cautious
about overturning it.62 The old and tried model will not always work, of course,
but when it fails, societies would be wise to fix it by gradually building on what
does work about it rather than by starting fresh with an untried idea.
Burke thus offers a model of gradual change—of evolution rather than
revolution. In a sense, he sees tradition as a process with something of the
character that modern biology ascribes to natural evolution. The products of that
process are valuable not because they are old, but because they are advanced—
having developed through years of trial and error and adapted to their
circumstances. The approach to political life built on this model, which Burke
often dubs “prescription,” is a way of adapting well-established practices and
institutions to changing times, rather than starting over and losing the advantages
of age and experience. This model of nature is by no means the whole of Burke’s
idea of prescription, as we will see, but is the foundation of it.
Burke, however, is not arguing for static adherence to past practices. On the
contrary, he believes that contending with constant change is one of the greatest
strengths of the natural world, in ways that human communities would do well to
learn from. “We must all obey the great law of change,” Burke writes. “It is the
most powerful law of nature, and the means perhaps of its conservation. All we
can do, and that human wisdom can do, is to provide that the change shall
proceed by insensible degrees. This has all the benefits which may be in change,
without any of the inconveniences of mutation.”63 And this is achieved by
investing people in the given world, on the model of nature. For Burke,
therefore, nature offers not a source of principles and axioms, but a living model
of change, and one especially well suited to human nature, with its reliance on
imagination and the sentiments, and to the natural facts of man’s life and death.
But Burke’s imperative that change must be made gradual raises a vexing
question that points to another deep division between him and Paine: Is the pace
of change all that matters for social peace and political legitimacy? Does the
substance or direction not matter as well? Is one kind of change as good as
another as long as it is carried out gradually and with respect for precedent?
Paine’s emphasis on nature over history is an appeal to principles of proper
action and therefore an appeal to justice. Burke’s invocation of nature
understood through history calls for a model of thoughtful and gradual change
and is therefore an appeal to order. But does the appeal to justice require a means
of political and social change that is so radical and revolutionary that it must
undermine all hope for political and social order? And does the appeal to order
leave any room for principles of justice as the proper guides to action in the
world? Burke and Paine’s disagreement about the proper model of nature for
politics therefore leads inexorably to a dispute about justice and order.
THREE

JUSTICE AND ORDER

OTH BURKE AND PAINE APPEAL TO MODELS OF NATURE to

B ground their political thought and especially their understanding of


political change. But the differences between their models have huge
implications for how they distinguish good change from bad.
For Paine, the appeal to nature is primarily an appeal to justice. Despite his
rather abstract and theoretical mode of expression, Paine’s passion always comes
from outrage against injustice and human suffering. He detects a moral vacuum
in Burke’s denial of the natural roots of political principle and a marked lack of
compassion for the low and the weak in Burke’s romantic celebration of the
noble and the mighty. It may be easier to paint great tragic pictures when a queen
is threatened by a mob, Paine says, but it is more important to offer help when an
entire people is crushed by a corrupt regime. “He pities the plumage, but forgets
the dying bird,” Paine famously writes of Burke.1 And Paine believes Burke has
been blinded to the injustice done to the French people by precisely his (in
Paine’s view, quite excessive) emphasis on the place of the moral imagination in
politics.
All of Burke’s appeals to beauty and order, to the imposing majesty of the
deeply rooted practices we inherit, strike Paine as excuses for inequality,
indifference, and injustice. He does not think men are innately so vicious as to
require beautiful illusions to restrain them. The illusions, Paine argues, are
necessary only to keep the people from seeing that they have been denied their
rights. In a sense, then, Burke and Paine accuse each other of the same vice:
Each says the other is made cold to human suffering by his theories of nature and
of politics.
In his writings on France, Burke undeniably makes far more of the suffering
of the powerful at the hands of the mob than the suffering of the people at the
hands of their rulers. He insists he does this out of concern not for the property
of the nobles or the priests but for the moral degradation of the mob, which he
takes to be driven to violent radicalism by misguided theories.2 But Burke only
rarely acknowledges the suffering of the French people themselves, and even
then, only when he argues that the leveling philosophies of the revolution will do
the people more harm still and that there were means of addressing their
condition without overturning their society. Burke does not quite defend the old
regime, but he thinks the new one is not an improvement. The revolution, he
writes, involved “the change of one piece of barbarism for another, and a
worse.”3 His concerns are not expressly humanitarian, and the model of nature
he defends is not a model of justice but a model of gradual change.
There is no question, too, that Paine is not only cold to the suffering of those
forcibly deposed from power, but sometimes downright giddy at their downfall
and mistreatment. To Paine, the mob’s actions, which so distress Burke, are not
only justified but also expressly caused by the regime’s extreme despotism and
injustice.4
Each man is therefore partially right to accuse the other of letting his theories
of politics (and, really, his theories of nature) blind him to certain kinds of
injustice. But each also has an answer to the charge. Paine’s answer is loud and
clear: For him, justice is embodied in the rational principles of liberal politics.
Anything short of a government chosen and consented to by the people—a
government that respects their rights and represents their interests—is an unjust
regime and can only survive through brazen crimes. Paine’s politics is firmly
anchored in a moral standard. But the moral grounding of Burke’s politics is a
far more complicated problem.

MORAL ORDER AND MORAL LAW


What might we say of Burke’s idea of justice, especially given his understanding
of nature? He appeals to a model of nature to guide social and political
organization, but does he also appeal to a standard of nature in judging political
action? Does he have a standard of justice at all, or does his emphasis on the
conventional character of political societies mean that he sees no external
measure but the law itself? Burke offers no simple answer to this crucial
question, and scholars of his work have been divided over his view of it for two
centuries.
On one side are those who read Burke as a kind of sophisticated utilitarian or
“procedural conservative,” concerned for social peace and effective government,
worried about the dangers of poorly managed political change, but lacking any
strong moral code to define political life.5 Burke’s vehement objections to the
direct application of abstract theories in political life; his emphasis on
prescription (in which practices and institutions are judged by their effects),
prudence, and expedience in political judgment; and his assertion that political
communities are essentially conventional lead these readers of Burke to see him
as concerned with means to the exclusion of ends and so as a practitioner of
almost pure expediency in political judgment.6 He worries about the pace of
change, but not about its direction.
Some have gone as far as to argue that Burke did not fundamentally disagree
with the substantive aims underlying the rationalism of the French Revolution—
that “he merely wants to further its ends less precipitously.”7 As these readers
see it, his reasons for defending liberty and opposing violations of human dignity
(reasons evident, for instance, in his views of the American conflict and of
British misbehavior in India) have to do with the integrity of Britain’s governing
institutions and social cohesion, not with moral principles that define political
life. He is thus not simply a defender of the given, but he is a defender of the
successful and effective, and his definition of success is highly procedural.
But these readers of Burke face some serious difficulties in his own writing.
Of the idea that the conventional origins of political institutions mean that any
laws made according to a society’s usual procedures are inherently morally
legitimate, Burke offers an unwavering condemnation:
It would be hard to point out any error more truly subversive of all the order and beauty, of all the
peace and happiness, of human society than the position that the body of men have a right to make
what laws they please; or that laws can derive any authority from their institution merely and
independent of the quality of the subject-matter. No arguments of policy, reason of state, or
preservation of the constitution can be pleaded in favor of such a practice. They may in deed
impeach the frame of that constitution; but can never touch this immovable principle. This seems
to be, indeed, the principle which Hobbes broached in the last century, and which was then so
frequently and so ably refuted.8

Clearly, Burke believed there could be unjust laws, and that being effective
doesn’t make a particular policy moral or right. He explicitly denied seeking “to
make the success of villainy the standard of innocence,” and his writings support
this denial.9 “All human laws are, properly speaking, only declaratory; they may
alter the mode and application, but have no power over the substance of original
justice,” he writes.10 Nor does he refute the notion that political life fulfills
some inclinations impressed upon man by his nature, or his maker. Although
Burke could be exceedingly vague when taking up these questions, he clearly
sees himself vindicating a moral vision in his political crusades.
Indeed, his (at least tonal) moralism has led some Burke scholars to argue
that not only was Burke not a utilitarian or pure proceduralist, but he was in fact
a natural-law philosopher—that is, a believer in a clear moral standard, made
evident in nature or made accessible through revelation, that serves as a model
and standard for human life.11 Burke, they insist, “conceived of statecraft as the
practical application in concrete human affairs of primary moral principles,
clearly evident to man’s right reason.”12 To support this view, they point to
Burke’s repeated references to God, religion, and the order of nature, especially
in his writings on India and Ireland.
And it is true that in taking up those last two subjects, Burke most explicitly
asserts that the standards of judgment in politics must go beyond efficacy to
some idea of justice. In 1787, after word had reached London of gross
mistreatment of the natives of India by the East India Company (which
represented the government’s interests in that important part of the empire),
Burke launched an impeachment proceeding against Warren Hastings—the
British governor general of India. Burke considered the case crucial to setting
the character of the growing empire, and although Hastings was ultimately
acquitted by the House of Lords, Burke later described his own part in the trial
as among his most significant accomplishments.13 Because he had very little
positive law to appeal to in making his case, he grounded his passionate and
powerful appeal in a higher law. “I impeach him,” Burke told the lords regarding
Hastings, “in the name and by virtue of those eternal laws of justice which he
has violated. I impeach him in the name of human nature itself, which he has
cruelly outraged, injured, and oppressed, in both sexes, at every age, rank,
situation, and condition of life.”14
Similarly, in the case of laws restricting the rights and privileges of Catholics
in his native Ireland, Burke argued that the policy amounted to “a deprivation of
all the rights of human nature.”15 In a private letter, he described a bill to outlaw
intermarriage between Irish Catholics and Protestants (a subject that was, of
course, quite personal for Burke) as filled with “outrages on the rights of
humanity and laws of nature.”16 And in the Irish context, in fact, he comes
closest to defining his understanding of the explicit purpose of government and
political life: “Everybody is satisfied that a conservation and secure enjoyment
of our natural rights is the great and ultimate purpose of civil society; and that
therefore all forms whatsoever of government are only good as they are
subservient to that purpose to which they are entirely subordinate.”17
This language sounds a lot like Paine’s and that of the French
Revolutionaries and seems on its face to contradict Burke’s frequent denial of
the direct relevance of natural rights to life in civil society. It is not hard to see
why some readers would take such declarations as evidence that Burke sees an
accessible natural law above the positive law. But this view is no less
problematic than the charge that Burke is a utilitarian. It falls apart especially
when we consider the very subject that the natural-law readers of Burke point to
above all: his frequent references to religion.
Burke’s view of the appropriate place of religion in public life, made most
extensively in the Reflections on the Revolution in France, is in fact strikingly
utilitarian. In his first take on the subject—in the Vindication of Natural Society
—Burke worried that people who attacked religious institutions and practices as
merely “artificial” or conventional risked undermining civil society. The case
against organized religion, he argues, could easily become a case against all
social institutions grounded in tradition. In the Reflections, he offers much the
same point in a positive sense: Just as attacks on religion could be harmful to
social peace, so could the public elevation and endorsement of religious practice
and belief reinforce social harmony and civil society. Religion, then, is an
element in the larger system of chivalry, ennobling the use of political power and
moderating its users. “When they are habitually convinced that no evil can be
acceptable, either in the act or the permission, to him whose essence is good,”
Burke writes of citizens living under an established church, “they will be better
able to extirpate out of the minds of all magistrates, civil, ecclesiastical, or
military, any thing that bears the least resemblance to a proud and lawless
domination.”18
Moreover, religion, by “consecrating” the state, gives the people an added
impetus to respect and regard their regime.19 Religion, and especially an
established church, helps to give people the kind of sentimental attachments and
peaceful habits necessary to sustain a political order grounded in generational
continuity and prescription.20 Covering the state in sacred garb also helps to
shield its origins and protect it from rash and extreme reform or revolution.21
And finally, religion also helps the poor deal with their condition. To deprive
them of this source of consolation is to make oneself “the cruel oppressor, the
merciless enemy of the poor and wretched.”22
Burke therefore writes about religion almost exclusively in terms of its use to
society and the state rather than as a path to divine truth. He invokes the power
and beauty of religious ceremony as means of building popular allegiance and
solidarity.23 The majesty and pomp of a great cathedral, in this view, can
strengthen social bonds, whether or not they celebrate a true revealed divine
justice. “We know and it is our pride to know,” Burke writes, “that man is by his
constitution a religious animal,” and for this reason, atheism seems to him a
recipe for social unrest, and religion a necessary prop for peace.24 But it is as
such a prop, and not explicitly as the particular and ultimate standard of
judgment, that religion is accorded a central place in Burke’s political thought.
He does not deny the truth of Christianity—and in his private life and letters
offers reason to think he was a relatively orthodox believer—but he does not
think politics can be directly grounded in Christian moral claims. Instead, he
says, politics can be based only on the piety these claims yield in the believer.
Indeed, Burke is remarkably forthright in denying a necessary connection
between the social value of religious piety and the theological truth underlying
it. Of French Catholics, he writes that some of their beliefs are surely simple
superstition, but that this being their ancient religion, it nonetheless plays a
crucial role in sustaining social and political life.25 Even in England, he argues,
it makes sense for statesmen to follow the code and the forms of the established
religion regardless of their own sense of its ultimate truth: “If by their conduct
(the only language that rarely lies) they seemed to regard the great ruling
principle of the moral and the natural world as a mere invention to keep the
vulgar in obedience, they apprehend that by such a conduct they would defeat
the politic purpose they have in view. They would find it difficult to make others
to believe in a system to which they manifestly gave no credit themselves.”26
This is a case for a consecrated state religion, but not truly for a politics that
answers finally to a divine standard. Indeed, another element of Burke’s larger
political teaching undermines even further the case for natural law as the essence
of his philosophy. Although he does insist on a standard outside the positive law
by which political action should be measured, his rejection of beginnings as the
ultimate source of authority and understanding suggests he would not search for
that standard at the beginning of human history, where natural law ultimately
points. As we have seen, Burke argues that beginnings should be shrouded in a
veil, and that the results of the long chain of tradition and practice—results like
stability, prosperity, allegiance, patriotism, and nobility—are what we must seek
to protect. Thus, the long chain itself is to be guarded, but not because its origins
were perfect; he says plainly that he does not believe they were. This is not
Christian traditionalism. It is prescription, a very different and quite innovative
way of thinking about social development.
Burke turns out, therefore, to be neither a utilitarian proceduralist nor a
natural-law philosopher. He does not believe that man-made law is the final
authority and that only consequences matter. Nor does he believe that political
life is an expression of unchanging Christian truths. The regime, he suggests,
does not owe its legitimacy directly to God, and neither is every whim of the
sovereign legitimate. He proposes, rather, a novel notion of political change that
emerges from precisely his model of nature and his (again, rather novel) idea of
prescription. And yet over time, this idea points us toward a standard of justice
and judgment beyond pure utility.
Burke does not differ with Paine’s or the natural-law school’s view that a
standard of justice must guide political life. He differs, rather, in his view of our
ability to know and discover that standard. Paine argues that we can know the
standard by rational deduction from the premises of our understanding of nature.
So, for instance, our knowledge of presocial man tells us that all men are equal
—an understanding that must define political life. The natural-law tradition
argues that we can know the standard through philosophical reflection on
theological or philosophical premises (many of them evident in the functioning
of nature). Burke, however, is far more skeptical of our ability to discover and
apply directly this higher standard of justice in politics. The higher standard is
not directly accessible to reason, he argues, because human beings generally
cannot reason directly about abstract ideas without some imaginative context,
and because social life is not the simple playing out of presocial natural
premises. Burke’s view of nature and of human nature suggests to him that the
standards of justice that are to guide political life are rather discoverable—to the
extent we can know them at all—implicitly through the experience of political
life itself.
Burke believes, therefore, that the traditions embodied in England’s social
and political institutions (what he describes as “the English constitution”), built
as they are on the model of natural generation, are the best means available for
his countrymen to reach a transcendent standard for government. He
acknowledges that the constitutional tradition does not speak with one voice and
cannot be traced back to a simple set of original principles that rely on man’s
beginnings to define his rights. But it does offer, in the norms it builds up,
though always with exceptions, an approach by degrees to a real standard
beyond mere convention. This view is neither natural-law philosophy nor a
standard-less utilitarianism. Grounded in Burke’s natural model of change, this
approach respects traditional practices not because they began a long time ago
but because they have survived and evolved, through a process of trial and error,
for a long time.
Prescription—which improves society by building upon its strengths—with
its analogy of nature, makes this trial and error possible and helps us distinguish
error from success. It is indeed a model of change, but one suited to help us
discern the general shape of some permanent underlying principles of justice.
The historical experience of social and political life consists in essence of a kind
of rubbing up against the principles of natural justice, and the institutions and
practices that survive the experience thereby take on something of the shape of
those principles, because only those that have this shape do survive. Over time,
therefore, provided they develop in accordance with the model of prescription,
societies come to express in their institutions, their charters, their traditions, and
their habits a simulacrum of the standard of justice. Society, as it exists after
such long experience, therefore offers an approximation of society as it should
exist. Social and political change can help to bring a society slowly closer to the
standard, if only by degrees. But such progress is likely to happen only if the
change is in keeping with the spirit of society’s preexisting modes and orders,
since they offer the only real sense we can have of what the sought-after
standard looks like. We should seek to emulate our ancestors, Burke argues,
“who, by looking backward as well as forward . . . went on, insensibly drawing
this constitution nearer and nearer to its perfection by never departing from its
fundamental principles, nor introducing any amendment which had not a
subsisting root in the laws, constitution, and usages of the kingdom.”27 Burke in
this sense is not a backward-looking but a forward-looking traditionalist; he
believes that the present is better than the past, and he is committed to sustaining
the means by which it has become better, to facilitate further improvement.
The best kind of political change, in Burke’s view, builds on what is best
about the given world to improve what is worst about it, and leaves society as it
was but more so. This is the best sort of change not because our conventional
institutions define the standards of our politics, but because the conventions that
have survived the test of time are those that somehow answer to that standard.
“This great law does not arise from our conventions or compacts; on the
contrary, it gives to our conventions and compacts all the force and sanction they
can have.”28 This is the reason prescription is such an effective model of
change; over time, it “mellows into legality governments that were violent in
their commencement.”29
Social change can thus be generally ameliorative if it is properly managed,
though it is not simply progressive: it does not move in only one direction.
Burke’s idea of a just society is not an end state that is the ultimate goal of all
political change. Rather, a just society provides space for thriving private lives
and a thriving national life within the bounds of the constitution by allowing for
some balance of order and freedom. Political life occurs within that space, and
political change sustains and defends that space and therefore moves in various
directions as events warrant—sometimes restraining or strengthening one
element of the constitution, and sometimes another. Political change helps to
slowly draw the constitution toward its perfection, but the change is far from
linear and never simple. Precisely because of the generational character of
human societies, political change cannot achieve a genuine perfection. Thus,
societies are always contending with the most basic flaws of human nature.
Those cannot be overcome, because we humans are always human, even as our
social institutions improve with time as we learn from experience.30 The
statesman’s task is therefore not to drive society toward some particular ultimate
and just condition but to create and constantly sustain a space in which the
people may exercise their freedom and enjoy the benefits of life in society.
Successful political change in Burke’s view is thus utterly continuous with a
society’s past and character. To plan, manage, judge, and carry off such
successful change therefore requires a profound understanding of the history, the
spirit, the norms, the practices, and the traditions of one’s society, and a
successful politics is guided by this kind of understanding—which goes by the
name of prudence. Prudence is not the opposite of either principle or theory.
Prudence, rather, is the application of general experience to particular practical
problems. In Burke’s view, the prudent person believes that the experience of our
society generally points to underlying principles of justice (and of nature) and so
offers more reliable, if less specific, guidance than do abstract theories like the
natural-rights liberalism that Paine would import wholesale into practical
politics.
“History is a preceptor of prudence, not of principles,” Burke writes; it does
not offer us direct knowledge of precise or abstract rules.31 But it does give us
general rules, which are certainly good enough most of the time. In an early
pamphlet, Burke argues that there are no exact formulas for civil or political
wisdom:
They are a matter incapable of exact definition. But, though no man can draw a stroke between the
confines of day and night, yet light and darkness are upon the whole tolerably distinguishable. Nor
will it be impossible for a Prince to find out such a mode of government, and such persons to
administer it, as will give a great degree of content to his people, without any curious and anxious
research for that abstract, universal, perfect harmony, which, while he is seeking, he abandons
those means of ordinary tranquility which are in his power without any research at all.32

That well-functioning societies approach the standard of justice over time


does not mean that all societies will gravitate toward the same institutions and
forms, however. Precisely because we can never access it directly and in full,
there are many ways to approach the standard of justice by degrees. “Liberty
inheres in some sensible object,” Burke writes, “and every nation has formed to
itself some favorite point, which by way of eminence becomes the criterion of
their happiness.”33 Not only do different nations in Europe approach this ideal
in different ways, but even distinct communities of Englishmen take different
approaches. Burke points to the American colonists as examples. Living apart
from Britain for several generations, the Americans, he says, have developed a
powerful attachment to personal liberty and an insatiable entrepreneurialism,
which their political institutions will inevitably reflect, while the British at home
are more attached to firm and stable authority.34
But each of these criteria of happiness, if it has resulted in societies that
allow for liberty, dignity, prosperity, and honor, makes for a legitimate standard
of judgment and change for the nation in question, and each is expressed in that
nation’s political tradition. “If the people are happy, united, wealthy, and
powerful, we presume the rest,” Burke writes. “We conclude that to be good
from whence good is derived. In old establishments various correctives have
been found for their aberrations from theory. Indeed they are the results of
various necessities and expediencies. They are not often constructed after any
theory; theories are rather drawn from them.”35
Most political questions present themselves within the bounds established by
the constitution and so do not raise essential questions of natural justice but
rather challenges to prudence. They ought therefore to be settled by expedient
judgment guided by constitutional precedent, and if they are found to have been
made incorrectly, they can be corrected, again by prudent statesmanship. Most of
the political life of a reasonably functional society, therefore, is a matter of
straightforward prudence, which is “in politics, the first of virtues,” Burke
writes.36 But there are two crucial exceptions to this expediency.
First, sometimes a particular policy is so starkly at odds with the
constitutional tradition and therefore so likely to be at odds with the standards of
justice that guide political life, it must be opposed by direct recourse to justice
and right, and not only on prudential grounds. “Justice is itself the great standing
policy of civil society; and any eminent departure from it, under any
circumstances, lies under the suspicion of being no policy at all,” Burke
writes.37 Most policy questions do not rise to the level of fundamental matters
of justice. But those that do will require special attention and urgency because
they present something of an unprecedented challenge, for which the
constitutional tradition is not well suited. British conduct in India and Ireland so
obviously violated the pattern of English history, in Burke’s view, that it was
equally clear that they violated natural justice. Burke contrasts the East India
Company’s charter with what he calls the great charters of English history,
starting with the Magna Carta, which laid out the rights of Englishmen in 1215.
“Magna Carta is a charter to restrain power, and to destroy monopoly,” he
writes. “The East India charter is a charter to establish monopoly, and to create
power. Political power and commercial monopoly are not the rights of men.”38
Burke opposed the slave trade on similar grounds.
The second exception to the reign of pure prudence challenges not the
traditions of the constitution but the mode of change that has made the
development of the constitution possible. The prospect of total revolution, which
is the prospect Burke perceived in France, threatens to throw off all that has been
laboriously built up over generations by prescription and start over from scratch.
It is the deepest and most dangerous threat to Burke’s nature-inspired model of
change. He believed that the French Revolution threatened to cut society off not
only from the institutions it had built up over countless generations but (as a
result) from the standard of justice itself, leaving no other standard by which to
judge politics than naked power masquerading as philosophy. This is what he
perceived in the mobs of Paris. The intensity and the very early awakening of
Burke’s opposition to the revolution are much easier to understand when we
realize just what he believed was threatened and why.
For Burke therefore, nature, history, justice, and order are inextricably
connected. In his view, we can know the standard of nature only generally and
only through the experience of history, whereas in Paine’s view we can know it
precisely but only by liberating ourselves from the burdens of history and
seeking for direct rational understanding of natural principles. For Burke the
resort to history is the model of nature. For Paine, nature waits for us behind the
distractions of history, which is merely a sorry tale of errors, crimes, and
misunderstandings. Paine’s model of nature is a model of permanent justice that
offers us principles for the proper arrangement of political life; Burke’s model of
nature is a model of gradual change that stands a chance of pointing society in
the right direction.

NATURAL EQUALITY AND THE ORDER OF SOCIETY


Only now, having gotten a sense of what both Paine and Burke mean by nature
and its consequences for justice and political life, can we begin to understand the
deep differences that divide them. As we have begun to see, their disagreements
about nature, history, and justice bear heavily on their other, more prominent
disagreements about political change. But the most direct implications of their
views of nature and justice have to do with Burke’s and Paine’s understanding of
social relations and connections—and perhaps most notably the two men’s very
different notions of equality.
Burke’s model of nature does not point to social equality. In a society
sustained by inheritance, social eminence and great wealth will tend to stay in
certain families and beyond the reach of others. Not that change and reform
cannot happen, or that those who are able to rise in society are somehow
unworthy of it, but equality itself should not be a primary goal of politics. Social
peace, prosperity, and stability are more important for everyone, and are often
not well served by the pursuit of equality—especially because true social
equality is ultimately an unachievable goal.
“The idea of forcing every thing to an artificial equality has something, at
first view, very captivating in it,” Burke writes. “It has all the appearance
imaginable of justice and good order; and very many persons, without any sort
of partial purposes, have been led to adopt such schemes and to pursue them
with great earnestness and warmth.”39 But it is ultimately both misguided and
impractical. “Believe me, sir,” he writes in the Reflections, “those who attempt to
level never equalize. In all societies consisting of various descriptions of
citizens, some description must be uppermost.”40 The only question is which
element will predominate, and in a society that makes leveling and equalizing its
central principle, the great middle will tend to predominate, overpowering both
the rich and the poor. But this middle, especially in a society focused on
equalizing, will tend to be badly suited to rule. “The levelers therefore only
change and pervert the natural order of things. They load the edifice of society
by setting up in the air what the solidity of the structure requires to be on the
ground. The association of tailors and carpenters, of which the republic (of Paris,
for instance) is composed, cannot be equal to the situation into which, by the
worst usurpations, an usurpation of the prerogatives of nature, you attempt to
force them.”41
As this passage demonstrates, for Burke the question of political equality—
or of who has the right to rule—is even more important than that of social or
economic equality. In a society with an egalitarian idea of rule, there will not be
true equality, but rather a disorderly rule by the unfit. Because it will organize
itself around an idea of equality that it can never truly achieve, such a society
will also always be in disarray and flux. The idea of eliminating all social
distinctions in society, Burke argues, is a “monstrous fiction, which by inspiring
false ideas and vain expectations into men destined to travel in the obscure walk
of laborious life, serves only to aggravate and embitter that real inequality, which
it can never remove; and which the order of civil life establishes as much for the
benefit of those whom it must leave in an humble state as those whom it is able
to exalt to a condition more splendid, but not more happy.”42
Burke certainly isn’t defending a simple social status quo, where those born
to privilege and those born to toil must remain where they are. He makes clear
that he does not intend “to confine power, authority, and distinction to blood and
names and titles.”43 Rather, distinction should go to those who are best suited
for power, and Burke believes one important component of that suitability has to
do with property and leisure, which tend to be inherited. It should be possible,
but not too easy, for others to break in to the ruling class if they prove
themselves (as indeed Burke himself had done). But as a general matter, he
writes, “some decent, regulated preeminence, some preference (not exclusive
appropriation) given to birth is neither unnatural, nor unjust, nor impolitic.”44
Why should this preference be given, if (as Burke asserts) natural ability is
not itself inherited? One chief reason has to do with the importance Burke
attributes to prudence in political life. Put simply, governing is very difficult, and
not everyone can do it. And in a society shaped by prescription, governing
requires not so much raw intelligence as knowledge of history and tradition, a
sense of the people, and clear-eyed prudence in making decisions. Because it is
more than the expression of public preferences or the application of geometrical
principles, governing requires quality more than quantity—a quality that is
developed through experience and study that build judgment and so is harder to
come by for people in some professions and ways of life than others.45
“Rational and experienced men tolerably well know, and have always known,
how to distinguish between true and false liberty and between the genuine
adherence and the false pretence to what is true,” Burke writes in An Appeal
from the New to the Old Whigs. “But none, except those who are profoundly
studied, can comprehend the elaborate contrivance of a fabric fitted to unite
private and public liberty with public force, with order, with peace, with justice,
and, above all, with the institutions formed for bestowing permanence and
stability through ages, upon this invaluable whole.”46
Men have these abilities in differing degrees not because some are born more
prudent than others but because prudence is a function of experience and
education. Indeed, this case for political inequality seems motivated precisely by
a belief in natural equality. “The savage hath within him the seeds of the
logician, of the man of taste and breeding, the orator, the statesman, the man of
virtue, and the saint,” Burke writes, “which seeds, though planted in his mind by
nature, yet, through want of culture, and exercise, must lie for ever buried, and
be hardly perceivable by himself or others.”47 To cultivate these seeds requires a
certain type of life. Those who live it and who benefit by it are a kind of natural
aristocracy, entitled to rule because they possess the requisite judgment. In an
extraordinary passage in the Appeal, Burke sets forth a list of more than fifteen
qualities or abilities (e.g., “To see nothing low and sordid from one’s infancy”;
“To be taught to despise danger in the pursuit of honor and duty”; “To have
leisure to read, to reflect, to converse”; “To be a professor of high science, or of
liberal and ingenuous art”) that might help constitute a member of the natural
aristocracy.48
Such people, of course, can be formed only under particular social
conditions. And there is no shame or injustice in preferring for rule those who
are better formed for making judgments, Burke argues. Societies should seek to
be well governed, rather than to merely play out the implications of an abstract
ideal of political equality, and to be well governed requires giving more authority
to those better able to govern.49 Societies whose core concern is social equality
not only will tend to fail to elevate the worthy, but will even tend to elevate and
celebrate those most poorly qualified to govern.50
For this reason, as society sustains itself through inheritance, it will sustain
certain social and political inequalities, too, for its own good. And these
inequalities have a crucial added benefit, beyond elevating the best qualified.
They also offer means for containing and resisting abuses of power, by requiring
power to flow through the deep-cut channels that compose the uneven social
topography. The division of citizens into distinct groups and classes, Burke
writes, “composes a strong barrier against the excesses of despotism,” by
establishing habits and obligations of restraint in ruler and ruled alike grounded
in the relations of groups or classes in society.51 To remove these traditional
restraints, which hold in check both the individual and the state, would mean
empowering only the state to restrain the individual, and in turn restraining the
state with only principles and rules, or parchment barriers. Neither, Burke
thought, could be stronger or more effective than the restraints of habit and
custom that grow out of group identity and loyalty. Burke’s famous reference to
the little platoon—“To be attached to the subdivision, to love the little platoon
we belong to in society, is the first principle (the germ as it were) of public
affections”—is often cited as an example of a case for local government or
allegiance to place, but in its context in the Reflections, the passage is very
clearly a reference to social class.52
Breaking apart all the connections that stand between the individual and the
state and leaving equal but separate individuals alone would expose them all to
the raw power of the state directly. The people would also have no protection
from one another or from the mass of citizens, in such a situation. Burke worries
that this would leave them unable to defend their freedoms and subject to even
more brutal and dangerous abuses of power than the ancient despotisms could
have been capable of. The social institutions that stand between the individual
and the government are crucial barriers to the ruthlessness of public officials and
the occasional cruelty of majorities. They are essential to liberty.53
Meanwhile, Burke believes that the very process of stripping the high and
the mighty of power and stature threatens to unleash forces that could easily
destroy the structured peace of society. He attributes the disloyalty and mutiny of
French soldiers, for instance, to their having seen the nobles humiliated.54 The
effect of the experience of leveling, Burke worries, is to eliminate all sense of
respect and obligation and leave the people ill suited for peace and order, even in
civil society, let alone in political life. As noted in Chapter 2, Burke famously
lamented that “on this scheme of things, a king is but a man; a queen is but a
woman; a woman is but an animal; and an animal not of the highest order.”55
The descent to barbarism begins by demoting kings and queens to mere men and
women.
And yet, for all his opposition to social and political leveling, Burke does not
deny the natural equality of man.56 It is precisely because he thinks human
beings are more or less equal in natural abilities that he wants only those who
have been properly formed and trained to govern. Thus, natural equality not only
does not necessitate social equality (as Paine would insist it does), but also
makes necessary some social inequality. Society is natural to man, and the
people living in it are inevitably unequal in some material and social respects.
But society makes possible a deeper kind of equality, which is one of the ideals
toward which he sees the model of nature pointing. “The inequality which grows
out of the nature of things by time, custom, succession, accumulation,
permutation, and improvement of property, is much nearer that true equality,
which is the foundation of equity and just policy, than any thing which can be
contrived by the tricks and devices of human skill,” Burke writes.57 This “true
equality,” which he describes as a “moral equality,” does not take the form of an
equal right to rule but is something more like an equal right to one’s station in
life: “All men have equal rights, but not to equal things.”58
This moral equality, derived from ancient chivalry and its appeal to the
peaceful sentiments, distinguishes modern European civilization from all others
and even from the greatest civilizations of the past. “It was this,” Burke writes,
“which without confounding ranks had produced a noble equality, and handed it
down through all the gradations of social life.”59 A mode of politics ordered to
support the sentiments of social peace and sustained by a prescriptive model of
change will tend to elevate the low and bring the high to submission without
actually eradicating all social distinctions or atomizing society into mere
disparate individuals. It composes a whole of which all are equally parts, even if
not equal parts. And through it, all are better able, Burke writes, “to seek and to
recognize the happiness that is to be found by virtue in all conditions; in which
consists the true moral equality of mankind.”60 Such happiness is only possible
in a well-governed society, and such a society in turn is made possible only by
certain kinds of social and political inequalities.
Thomas Paine, of course, could hardly disagree more with Burke than he did
on this point. Paine’s work was the very embodiment of the radical
egalitarianism that Burke feared. Paine believed that every man stands in an
equal relation to his origin with every other, and therefore that none is somehow
entitled to reign supreme. “Where there are not distinctions there can be no
superiority,” Paine writes in Common Sense.61 And since “all men [are]
originally equals, no one by birth could have a right to set up his own family in
perpetual preference to all others for ever.”62 Because it violates the rights of
every new generation, inherited social status is a recipe for an unjust society that
could never be well governed. There is “no truly natural or religious reason” for
the distinction between kings and subjects, he argues. “Male and female are
distinctions of nature, good and bad the distinctions of heaven, but how a race of
men came into the world so exalted above the rest and distinguished like some
new species, is worth inquiring into, and whether they are the means of
happiness or misery to mankind.”63 In other words, a king quite obviously is but
a man. The idea that social standing or the right to rule, like property, should
somehow be transmitted through the generations therefore strikes Paine as a
profound misunderstanding of the nature of man and of political life.
“What is government more than the management of the affairs of a Nation?”
Paine asks in Rights of Man. “It is not, and from its nature cannot be, the
property of any particular man or family, but of the whole community, at whose
expense it is supported; and though by force and contrivance it has been usurped
into an inheritance, the usurpation cannot alter the right of things.”64
Paine well understood Burke’s contention that noble families’ ruling
privilege stemmed not from any natural right to rule but from the education in
prudence and statesmanship that their inherited access to leisure allowed. But
Paine’s very different view of the relation of politics to nature and human nature
persuaded him that government is not as complicated as Burke suggests, and
therefore does not require a life of leisure and learning. “Notwithstanding the
mystery with which the science of government has been enveloped for the
purpose of enslaving, plundering, and imposing upon mankind, it is of all things
the least mysterious and the most easy to be understood,” he writes in his
Dissertation on First Principles in Government.65 Those who call it
complicated do so only to protect their interests, like magicians sheltering their
tricks. In the Rights of Man, he accuses the old regime in France of this
dishonest tactic. “In all cases they took care to represent government as a thing
made up of mysteries, which only themselves understood; and they hid from the
understanding of the nation the only thing that was beneficial to know, namely,
that government is nothing more than a national association acting on the
principles of society.”66 These principles, accessible by reflection upon nature,
do not require a deep study of history and do not change from one time and place
to another.67
Paine argues that government is ultimately a kind of intellectual exercise
requiring raw intelligence, not a knowledge of history or philosophy, and raw
intelligence is more or less randomly distributed by nature. Interestingly, Burke
bases his case against social equality on the roughly equal natural distribution of
abilities, which require leisure and education—advantages not equally available
—if they are to be honed and developed, whereas Paine bases his case for social
equality on the unequal but random distribution of natural abilities. “It is
impossible to control Nature in her distribution of mental powers,” Paine writes.
“She gives them as she pleases. I smile to myself when I contemplate the
ridiculous insignificance into which literature and all the sciences would sink,
were they made hereditary; and I carry the same idea into governments.”68
Political rule, according to Paine, is thus like artistic or scientific
achievement—it takes a natural talent, in this case, “mental powers,” which
enable the possessor to best understand the laws and rights of nature and apply
them. No class of men is uniquely gifted with such abilities, and those who have
them will not necessarily pass them down to their children. Only an egalitarian
society could allow them to emerge and serve the interests of the polity. The
equal right to rule is thus essential to the success and prosperity of society. Paine
is not a leveler of property, as Burke sometimes accuses him of being, but he is a
leveler of authority.69

ALTHOUGH THEIR DIFFERING VIEWS about nature and justice do not


finally explain their larger dispute in full, both Burke and Paine begin from these
questions, and their views of the subject begin to lay open their larger political
philosophies. Paine argues for revolution in the cause of recovering natural
liberties (which he believes have been trampled by governments). Burke argues
against revolution in the cause of defending the natural order of things (which he
believes is expressed in political life). Part of their dispute is about whether
nature provides underlying principles for judging political institutions or
provides the order and structure that those institutions constitute. Both men point
to something permanent about nature, but for Burke, what is permanent is
change (birth, growth, and death, as well as their political counterparts), while
for Paine, what is permanent is unchanging principle. In this sense, Burke
operates from an expectation of constant change, and Paine’s radical liberalism
is timeless. But from his reflections on change, Burke concludes that stability
and continuity are essential to a sustainable society. Paine, in contrast, concludes
from his reflections on timelessness that total and radical transformation is
always an option.
Burke also draws from his reflections a sense that human beings are
connected in the midst of change, that some links bind us inescapably across
society and time; while for Paine the encounter with timeless principles is
individual and direct. In considering the Burke-Paine dispute as a whole,
therefore, the question of nature and its consequences for order and justice points
us inevitably toward the question of social and political relations and
commitments—that is, toward the question of choice and obligation.
FOUR

CHOICE AND OBLIGATION

URKE AND PAINE’S DISPUTE ABOUT NATURE AND justice sets

B the scene for a profound disagreement about the very purpose of politics.
For Paine, the natural equality of all human beings translates to complete
political equality and therefore to a right to self-determination. The
formation of society was itself a choice made by free individuals, so the natural
rights that people bring with them into society are rights to act as one chooses,
free of coercion. Each person should have the right to do as he chooses unless
his choices interfere with the equal rights and freedoms of others. And when that
happens—when society as a whole must act through its government to restrict
the freedom of some of its members—government can only act in accordance
with the wishes of the majority, aggregated through a political process. Politics,
in this view, is fundamentally an arena for the exercise of choice, and our only
real political obligations are to respect the freedoms and choices of others.
For Burke, human nature can only be understood within society and
therefore within the complex web of relations in which every person is
embedded. None of us chooses the nation, community, or family into which we
are born, and while we can choose to change our circumstances to some degree
as we get older, we are always defined by some crucial obligations and
relationships not of our own choosing. A just and healthy politics must recognize
these obligations and relationships and respond to society as it exists, before
politics can enable us to make changes for the better. In this view, politics must
reinforce the bonds that hold people together, enabling us to be free within
society rather than defining freedom to the exclusion of society and allowing us
to meet our obligations to past and future generations, too. Meeting obligations
is as essential to our happiness and our nature as making choices.
Paine’s formulation of the purpose of politics is, on the surface, much more
familiar to us Americans today. It is perhaps the most familiar of all the elements
of Enlightenment liberalism’s view of the world—but we rarely think about its
premises and consequences. Burke’s notion, while barely known to us at all as a
theory of government, speaks in some important ways to how we actually live.
Both views are more complex and problematic than we might expect—and take
us toward the heart of the debate that defines modern liberal democracy.

A POLITICS OF CHOICE
The idea of rights sits at the core of Thomas Paine’s political philosophy. Rights
are the organizing principle of his thought and the prime concern of all his
writings about government. But the clearest and most accessible elucidation of
Paine’s idea of rights comes not in any of his essays on political questions,
which all take a certain notion of political and natural rights for granted, but in
an extraordinary letter he wrote to Thomas Jefferson in the momentous year
1789.
The note, apparently a follow-up to a discussion between the two men,
summarizes Paine’s own views on the question of rights in the midst of the chaos
and excitement of the revolution in France. The revolutionaries said they were
dedicated to the “rights of man,” but what exactly did that mean? Paine begins,
in the great Enlightenment-liberal tradition, by imagining a founding:
Suppose twenty persons, strangers to each other, to meet in a country not before inhabited. Each
would be a Sovereign in his own natural right. His will would be his law, but his power, in many
cases, inadequate to his right; and the consequence would be that each might be exposed, not only
to each other, but to the other nineteen. It would then occur to them that their condition would be
much improved if a way could be devised to exchange that quantity of danger into so much
protection; so that each individual should possess the strength of the whole number.

In this situation, he suggests, the people would trade freedom for protection,
but they would not quite give up their basic presocial rights. Instead, they would
build on them:
As all their rights in the first case are natural rights, and the exercise of those rights supported only
by their own natural individual power, they would begin by distinguishing between those rights
they could individually exercise, fully and perfectly, and those they could not. Of the first kind are
the rights of thinking, speaking, forming and giving opinions, and perhaps are those which can be
fully exercised by the individual without the aid of exterior assistance; or in other words, rights of
personal competency. Of the second kind are those of personal protection, of acquiring and
possessing property, in the exercise of which the individual power is less than the natural right. . . .
These I consider to be civil rights, or rights of compact, and are distinguishable from natural rights
because in the one we act wholly in our own person, in the other we agree not to do so, but act
under the guarantee of society.1

This cogent description grounds rights in a highly individualistic


understanding of the citizen. It sees social and political bonds as the products of
individual choices driven by calculations of utility and need. Every citizen has
the right to freedom of action, and when an individual right cannot be exercised
individually, citizens draw on the power of the state to put their rights into
practice. This power is not a gift of society; it is an entitlement—access to it is
the reason we enter into society. We form societies to protect and vindicate
preexisting natural rights, and what we call our civil rights are means of drawing
upon the common capital of society so that natural rights can be given effect. As
Paine puts it in Rights of Man, “society grants [the citizen] nothing. Every man is
a proprietor in society, and draws on the capital as a matter of right.”2
This means that the rights we have in society and the rights we have by
nature are in essence rights to the same things—and especially to freedom of
choice. “Man did not enter into society to become worse than he was before, nor
to have fewer rights than he had before, but to have those rights better secured,”
Paine writes. He thus sees men in their natural state transformed into citizens for
the protection of their rights, and he describes society explicitly as the product of
this utilitarian arrangement. In Rights of Man, he offers this description in the
form of three essential premises of his political thought:
First, That every civil right grows out of a natural right; or, in other words, is a natural right
exchanged. Secondly, That civil power properly considered as such is made up of the aggregate of
that class of the natural rights of man, which becomes defective in the individual in point of
power, and answers not his purpose, but when collected to a focus becomes competent to the
Purpose of every one. Thirdly, That the power produced from the aggregate of natural rights,
imperfect in power in the individual, cannot be applied to invade the natural rights which are
retained in the individual, and in which the power to execute is as perfect as the right itself. We
have now, in a few words, traced man from a natural individual to a member of society, and
shown, or endeavored to show, the quality of the natural rights retained, and of those which are
exchanged for civil rights.3

Society is therefore a means to accomplish what each individual has the right
but not the ability to accomplish. For Paine, this means it is above all a means to
enable choice, or the freedom to shape our own future uncoerced—a means to
the radical liberation of the individual from the burdens of his circumstances, his
given nature, and his fellow man. Equality, individualism, and natural rights
(some transformed into civil rights) are descriptive and prescriptive facts
regarding the human condition, but personal liberty—the right to choose—is the
end toward which we aim in politics. Societies exist to protect acts of choice, by
meeting animal necessities on the one hand and by protecting individuals from
coercion on the other. This means that government itself, in protecting and
giving effect to the rights of individuals, must be understood as a chosen
arrangement defined by clear contractual rules.
Like most political thinkers of his day, Paine often refers to society as a
contract, though he is always sure to insist that he means a contract not between
the people and the sovereign power, but rather among the people themselves. “It
has been thought a considerable advance towards establishing the principles of
Freedom to say that Government is a compact between those who govern and
those who are governed,” Paine notes in Rights of Man, “but this cannot be true,
because it is putting the effect before the cause; for as man must have existed
before governments existed, there necessarily was a time when governments did
not exist, and consequently there could originally exist no governors to form
such a compact with.”4 Reaching back as always to beginnings for his
reasoning, Paine thus describes the social contract in starkly individualist terms:
“The fact therefore must be that the individuals themselves, each in his own
personal and sovereign right, entered into a compact with each other to produce
a government: and this is the only mode in which governments have a right to
arise, and the only principle on which they have a right to exist.”5
Only the founding generation of any regime can truly exercise consent in this
explicit sense, but Paine argues that implicit consent, as expressed in the
decisions of subsequent generations to refrain from overturning the laws, is the
only source of legitimacy any regime ever possesses.6 Every legitimate political
society, therefore, is a contract among its living members, and not an agreement
between them and their government or an agreement among their forefathers that
somehow binds them.
As a contract, society not only provides benefits to its members but also
requires of them certain obligations in return. Yet even these obligations come
down to making room for choice. Paine puts it succinctly: “The right which I
enjoy becomes my duty to guarantee it to another, and he to me, and those who
violate the duty justly incur a forfeiture of the right.”7 Our social duties,
therefore, amount to respecting the rights of others as they respect our own, so
that the obligations that define society are obligations to the freedom of choice
of its individual members. They are chosen obligations intended to protect
choice.
And how is this society to be led? Paine’s answer—that popular sovereignty
and the election of leaders are essential features of any legitimate regime—flows
directly from his belief in individual choice. Hereditary government violates the
rights of the governed, even if at its origin, generations ago, such a government
was installed by the choice of the public. People can choose to be governed by a
king with broad powers, but they cannot choose to empower that king’s children
and grandchildren permanently over their own. “If the present generation, or any
other, are disposed to be slaves, it does not lessen the right of the succeeding
generation to be free,” Paine argues.8
Paine spends a great deal of time in Rights of Man arguing this point, and he
does so in direct response to Edmund Burke’s writings on the French
Revolution. Burke argued not only that the French had removed their
government in an illegitimate way but also that the very notion that people
always have a right to remove their government and select their own rulers was
in error. The idea that choice sits at the center of all political thought struck him
as a mistake. It is upon this matter of the rights of the people to choose their own
regime and their own rulers, more than upon any other subject, that Paine
addresses himself squarely to Burke, and upon this matter, too, that Burke most
expressly offers an answer to Paine in his own subsequent writings. Their very
different views about the nature of social obligation and individual rights come
to a head on the question of consent—of just how central choice really is in
political life.

AN ETHIC OF OBLIGATION
Burke’s views on consent were bound to be provocative for Paine. Any modern
friend of democracy reading the Reflections on the Revolution in France must be
struck by the vehemence with which Burke rejects the general proposition that
the people have a fundamental right to choose their own rulers. The Reflections
is known as an anti-revolutionary work, an attack on the extremism Burke
believed was on display in France, and a defense of established practices and
forms. But the work in fact begins with a concerted assault against claims made
by the prominent dissenting Protestant minister Richard Price regarding the
English Revolution of 1688. Price had insisted that the Glorious Revolution had
established the English regime upon three fundamental rights: “to choose our
own governors, to cashier them for misconduct, [and] to frame a government for
ourselves.”9 What was happening in France, Price contended, was an effort to
catch up with these English liberties. Burke devotes the opening portion of his
essay to a savage attack against these claims: “This new and hitherto unheard-of
bill of rights, though made in the name of the whole people, belongs to those
gentlemen and their faction only. The body of the people of England have no
share in it. They utterly disclaim it. They will resist the practical assertion of it
with their lives and fortunes.”10 Burke thus fears not just the specter of the
frenzied Paris mob but also the theory of rule by consent at the heart of
Enlightenment liberalism.
This stark denial of the people’s right to choose their leaders appears at first
to be primarily a defense of the English constitution, since if Price’s (and
Paine’s) principles are valid, then most of English history has consisted of
illegitimate rule. “Do they mean to invalidate, annul, or to call into question,
together with the titles of the whole line of our kings, that great body of our
statute law which passed under those whom they now treat as usurpers?” Burke
asks.11 In 1784, in a speech on parliamentary reform, Burke had argued that the
principles of the radical reformers simply could not coexist with the British
system of government: “It is ridiculous to talk to them of the British Constitution
upon any or all of its bases; for they lay it down that every man ought to govern
himself, and that where he cannot go himself he must send his representative;
that all other government is usurpation. . . . If this claim be founded, it is clear to
what it goes.”12 It goes, Burke worried, to a complete rejection of the English
constitution, and it opens the door to sedition and revolution.
English champions of republican principles, like Richard Price, answered
this charge of sedition by pointing precisely to the revolution of 1688, which,
they argued, established the monarchy by the choice of the people. Though most
monarchs around the world were indeed illegitimate, as they governed without
the consent of their people, the English monarchy had been reestablished as an
act of choice by the 1688 Parliament and so governed in accordance with the
principle that the people could establish and remove their rulers at will. Burke
adamantly rejects this defense: The Glorious Revolution, he argues, was a
moment of extreme crisis, but the Englishmen who saw their country through it
(the “old Whigs” to whom Burke appeals) chose precisely to avoid turning that
crisis into an opportunity to establish an English republic, by finding a monarch
descended from their ancient line and continuing their regime on its established
foundations. “The Revolution was made to preserve our ancient indisputable
laws and liberties, and that ancient constitution of government which is our only
security for law and liberty,” Burke argues. “The very idea of the fabrication of a
new government is enough to fill us with disgust and horror. We wished at the
period of the Revolution, and do now wish, to derive all we possess as an
inheritance from our forefathers.”13
This inheritance surely does contain an element of choice and popular
sovereignty, along with other elements. Even in his day, Burke’s treasured House
of Commons was, after all, a relatively democratic element in a mixed regime,
and Burke does not object to popular elections and democratic politics. He has
often been accused, by critics from Paine himself to scholars in the twenty-first
century, of being just that: an antidemocratic defender of old privileges. But this
charge requires a rather crude reading of his views on consent, elections, and
representation. He frequently defends representative institutions, which he
argues are necessary counterweights to the excesses of the monarch and the
aristocracy. But representative institutions are not the purpose of the regime,
only one of its parts. A good government should take its cue from the proclivities
of its people. “In effect, to follow, not to force the public inclination; to give a
direction, a form, a technical dress, and a specific sanction, to the general sense
of the community, is the true end of legislature,” he writes, and this requires both
a means of letting the people have a voice and a means of subjecting the public
will to prudent leadership and wise restraint.14 The problem comes, Burke
argues, in thinking of consent as the essential defining principle of a regime. “I
reprobate no form of government merely upon abstract principles,” Burke writes,
and democracy certainly can be part of a legitimate government. But pure
democracy, a regime formed to serve choice above all, seems to him a recipe for
disaster, in theory and in practice, as it carries no clear principle of restraint.15
A long philosophical tradition, from Plato to Montesquieu and right to
Burke’s own day, had noted the dangerous excesses of absolute democracy, and
in pointing to these dangers, Burke makes an unusually explicit appeal to
philosophy: “Not being wholly unread in the authors who had seen the most of
[democratic] constitutions, and who best understood them, I cannot help
concurring with their opinion, that an absolute democracy, no more than absolute
monarchy, is to be reckoned among the legitimate forms of government. . . . If I
recollect rightly, Aristotle observes that a democracy has many striking points of
resemblance with a tyranny.”16 This notion of tyranny, a tyranny of the
unchecked majority over the minority, much alive in Burke’s mind at the time of
the French Revolution, would underlie his critique of unchecked democracy. As
he put it in the Reflections:
Of this I am certain, that in a democracy, the majority of the citizens is capable of exercising the
most cruel oppressions upon the minority, whenever strong divisions prevail in that kind of polity,
as they often must; and that oppression of the minority will extend to far greater numbers, and will
be carried on with much greater fury, than can almost ever be apprehended from the dominion of a
single scepter. In such a popular persecution, individual sufferers are in a much more deplorable
condition than in any other.

Under a cruel king, Burke argues, members of an oppressed minority “have


the balmy compassion of mankind to assuage the smart of their wounds.” But
under a tyrannical democracy, the public as a whole is against them. “They seem
deserted by mankind, overpowered by a conspiracy of their whole species.”17
Their oppression seems somehow legitimated.
On top of this tyranny of the majority, and perhaps an even greater threat to
legitimate government, is the danger of arbitrary rule in a democracy—of the
government never having to answer for its actions, because they are carried out
in the name of the people. In his Appeal from the New Whigs to the Old, Burke
quotes at length Paine’s case that election is the only legitimate source of
authority, and then paraphrases the attitude he sees in it: “Discuss any of their
schemes—their answer is—It is the act of the people, and that is sufficient. Are
we to deny to a majority of the people the right of altering even the whole frame
of their society, if such should be their pleasure? They may change it, say they,
from a monarchy to a republic to-day, and to-morrow back again from a republic
to a monarchy; and so backward and forward as often as they like.”18
If there is no source of authority but this moment’s popular will, then no
arrangements or institutions of society can be expected to remain in place one
moment longer than the majority wishes them there. This, Burke argues, is not
only impractical (as it would lead to a debilitating uncertainty and make it
impossible for any citizen to plan his future), but also an error in principle.
“Neither the few nor the many have a right to act merely by their will, in any
matter connected with duty, trust, engagement, or obligation.” It makes no
difference if a majority chooses it or not, “as no one of us men can dispense with
public or private faith, or with any other tie of moral obligation, so neither can
any number of us.”19 There are crucial instances when choice is simply not an
option.
And here we come to the heart of Burke’s trouble with consent. While the
threats to the English constitution and the risk of majority tyranny worry him,
the more profound and fundamental problem, Burke argues, is that the focus on
choice amounts to a fundamental misunderstanding of the human condition. A
politics of choice begins in error.
As Burke sees it, each man is in society not by choice but by birth. And the
facts of his birth—the family, the station, and the nation he is born into—exert
inescapable demands on him, while also granting him some privileges and
protections that the newborn has, of course, done nothing to earn. Men can
change their circumstances and can garner or lose privileges and obligations in
the course of their lives, but even when they do so, they take on in their new
stations new obligations that are not simply chosen and cannot simply be
discarded at will: “The place of every man determines his duty.”20 The most
essential human obligations and relations—especially those involving the family
but also many of those involving community, the nation, and one’s religious faith
—are not chosen and could never really be chosen, and political and social life
begins from these, not from an act of will. “We have obligations to mankind at
large, which are not in consequence of any special voluntary pact,” Burke writes.
“They arise from the relation of man to man, and the relation of man to God,
which relations are not matters of choice. On the contrary, the force of all the
pacts which we enter into with any particular person or number of persons
amongst mankind, depends upon those prior obligations. In some cases the
subordinate relations are voluntary, in others they are necessary—but the duties
are all compulsive.”21 Only by beginning one’s theory of politics from a highly
implausible thought experiment about perfectly independent people founding a
society by choice can one imagine a society in which choice is utterly central.
When one looks at how human beings actually live, it is impossible to ignore the
centrality and the value of compulsory obligations.
Perhaps the most perfectly inescapable fact about how we live is that all
human beings enter a world that already exists—a world in which they belong to
a particular family and community that are responsible for them and toward
which they in turn have obligations. Paine’s error, Burke suggests, begins with a
flawed notion of original freedom and independence. In the Appeal from the New
to the Old Whigs, in direct response to Paine, Burke reveals the heart of his own
anthropology with an extraordinary depiction of human relations. It is quite
possibly the most important paragraph in Burke’s decades of writing, and so is
worth quoting at length:
Dark and inscrutable are the ways by which we come into the world. The instincts which give rise
to this mysterious process of nature are not of our making. But out of physical causes, unknown to
us, perhaps unknowable, arise moral duties, which, as we are able perfectly to comprehend, we are
bound indispensably to perform. Parents may not be consenting to their moral relation; but
consenting or not, they are bound to a long train of burthensome duties towards those with whom
they have never made a convention of any sort. Children are not consenting to their relation, but
their relation, without their actual consent, binds them to its duties; or rather it implies their
consent because the presumed consent of every rational creature is in unison with the predisposed
order of things. Men come in that manner into a community with the social state of their parents,
endowed with all the benefits, loaded with all the duties of their situation. If the social ties and
ligaments, spun out of those physical relations which are the elements of the commonwealth, in
most cases begin, and always continue, independently of our will, so without any stipulation, on
our part, are we bound by that relation called our country, which comprehends (as it has been well
said) “all the charities of all.” Nor are we left without powerful instincts to make this duty as dear
and grateful to us, as it is awful and coercive.22

Just as Paine’s understanding of rights and choice sits at the heart of his
political thought, so this vision of obligations not chosen but nevertheless
binding forms the very core of Edmund Burke’s moral and political philosophy.
An enormous portion of Burke’s (and the conservative) worldview becomes
clearer in light of the importance he places on the basic facts and character of
human procreation, and an enormous portion of Paine’s (and the progressive)
worldview becomes clearer in light of the desire he evinces to be liberated from
the implications of those facts and that character. Almost all of what we loosely
call the “the social issues” have to do with the dispute about whether such
liberation is possible and desirable and, because it raises the question of the
relation between generations (as we will see in Chapter 7), that dispute also
shapes a surprising portion of our other prominent debates. Burke takes the
human person to be embedded in a web of obligations that give shape to our
lives.
The role of consent in this view of society is secondary at best. Social
relations flow out of natural relations, and consent is assumed where it cannot be
expressed, not because the individual chooses to accept his obligations, but
because the consent of every rational creature is assumed to be in line with “the
predisposed order of things.” This vision of society begins with the family—not
the individual—and moves up toward society.
Burke believes that the French revolutionaries deliberately and explicitly
wanted to weaken these bonds of obligation—to weaken the family, to begin
with, and so to weaken the deepest source of resistance to the revolutionary
ethic. In his Letter to a Member of the National Assembly, written in 1791,
Burke argues that the revolutionaries, following Rousseau, seek to reject the
duties of the family “as not founded in the social compact, and not binding
according to the rights of men; because the relation is not, of course, the result of
free election—never on the side of the children, not always on the part of the
parents.”23 The family is the primary obstacle to an ethic of choice and so a
primary target of genuinely radical liberal revolutionaries.
If Paine saw government’s primary obligation as the protection of individual
choice and the enabling of popular will, the obligations that emerge from
Burke’s natural relations are those of the care and protection of the web of social
relations and of society’s patrimony. Occasionally, choice will be the best means
of meeting these obligations, as when the elected House of Commons restrains
the king’s excessive intrusion into local affairs, but choice is, for Burke, never
the essence of the obligation itself or the end being served. The ends are defined
by the social relations and duties created by the nature and the shape of the
social order and can be better understood and better served by a political system
grounded in prescription—one modeled on the nature of society itself and so
best suited for continual and gradual improvement. Prescription, Burke argues, is
a type of cross-generational choice preferable to individual choice. It is what
allows him, he believes, to deny the principle of consent without abiding
despotism:
This is a choice not of one day, or one set of people, not a tumultuary and giddy choice; it is a
deliberate election of ages and of generations; it is a constitution made by what is ten thousand
times better than choice, it is made by the peculiar circumstances, occasions, tempers,
dispositions, and moral, civil, and social habitudes of the people, which disclose themselves only
in a long space of time. It is a vestment which accommodates itself to the body. Nor is prescription
of government formed upon blind, unmeaning prejudices—for man is a most unwise and a most
wise being. The individual is foolish; the multitude, for the moment, is foolish, when they act
without deliberation; but the species is wise, and when time is given to it, as a species it always
acts right.24

While Burke acknowledges that a particular civil order may begin


historically in a voluntary act and that some constitutions may be explicit
compacts between rulers and ruled, he believes that such origins are not nearly
as important as the Enlightenment liberals assumed. Society does not depend for
its legitimacy on such a source, and political life cannot make everything a
matter of choice, because the most important facts about human societies are not
the result of anyone’s choice and cannot be changed by anyone’s choice.
A great many of the deepest differences between Burke and Paine become
apparent in the light of this very different idea of how social relations work.
Burke’s view begins from the “dark and inscrutable” biological origins of every
new generation and so assumes a limit to our ability to explicitly understand and
articulate the character of political life. Because politics does not begin in
choice, it is not entirely ours to make. We have to build our politics around our
society rather than building society on the principles of our theory of politics. As
the great Burke biographer John Morley put it, “To Burke there was an element
of mystery in the cohesion of men in societies, in political obedience, in the
sanctity of contract; in all that fabric of law and charter and obligation, whether
written or unwritten, which is the sheltering bulwark between civilization and
barbarism. When reason and history had contributed all they could to the
explanation, it seemed to him as if the vital force, the secret of organization, the
binding framework, must still come from the impenetrable regions beyond
reasoning and beyond history.”25
In other words, Burke’s description of society can never make for the kind of
hard and total explanation that Paine and other radicals believed could be had
through their theories of rights and liberties. No calculation of individual rights,
interests, obligations, choices, and actions adds up to a sum of the whole in
Burke’s politics, but only a kind of picture of relations. His social relations flow
and roll out of personal ones and are sustained by sentimental attachments and
habits of affection. “We begin our public affections in our families,” Burke
writes. “We pass on to our neighbourhoods, and our habitual provincial
connections. These are inns and resting-places. Such divisions of our country as
have been formed by habit, and not by a sudden jerk of authority, were so many
little images of the great country in which the heart found something which it
could fill.”26
From Burke’s Reflections, Paine well understood that this notion of society
as an array of layered obligations marked a critical difference between his view
and Burke’s. To Paine’s mind, social relations were best understood by studying
individuals (as society was the sum of its parts), and the layers of social relations
that Burke put between individual men and mankind’s original rights were
needless distractions or intentional obstructions used to justify oppressive
traditions. In the Rights of Man, Paine puts it this way:
It is not among the least of the evils of the present existing governments in all parts of Europe that
man, considered as man, is thrown back to a vast distance from his Maker, and the artificial chasm
filled up with a succession of barriers, or sort of turnpike gates, through which he has to pass. I
will quote Mr. Burke’s catalogue of barriers that he has set up between man and his Maker. Putting
himself in the character of a herald, he says, “We fear God; we look with awe to kings; with
affection to Parliaments with duty to magistrates; with reverence to priests; and with respect to
nobility.” Mr. Burke has forgotten to put in “chivalry.” He has also forgotten to put in Peter. The
duty of man is not a wilderness of turnpike gates, through which he is to pass by tickets from one
to the other. It is plain and simple, and consists but of two points: His duty to God, which every
man must feel; and with respect to his neighbor, to do as he would be done by.27

But to Burke’s mind, these barriers and “turnpike gates”—the layers of


relations and institutions between the individual and the state—are the social
order. There is thus more to society than the “regime” or the formal institutions
of government, and a political and social order cannot be undone and redone at
will without badly damaging society.
For Burke, therefore, the “social contract” is not an agreement made among
the people—an agreement that prescribes the shape of their political
arrangements—but rather a description of binding relations. In his writings of
the 1790s, Burke was increasingly clear on this point. Spurred especially by
Paine’s critique and others, he came to see that this dispute about the meaning of
consent, contract, and social relations was among the deepest points of
separation between him and his adversaries on the question of France. “I cannot
too often recommend it to the serious consideration of all men who think civil
society to be within the province of moral jurisdiction,” he wrote in 1791,
that if we owe to it any duty, it is not subject to our will. Duties are not voluntary. Duty and will
are even contradictory terms. Now though civil society might be at first a voluntary act (which in
many cases it undoubtedly was) its continuance is under a permanent standing covenant,
coexisting with the society; and it attaches upon every individual of that society, without any
formal act of his own. . . . Men without their choice derive benefits from that association; without
their choice they are subjected to duties in consequence of these benefits; and without their choice
they enter into a virtual obligation as binding as any that is actual. Look through the whole of life
and the whole system of duties. Much the strongest moral obligations are such as were never the
results of our option.28

Burke thus seeks to redefine the concept of the social contract to suit it to his
own picture of politics.
His contract is not a set of quid pro quos, with rights exchanged for
obligations by free people making choices about what is best for them, but a
description of relations that are inescapable and binding. Society is not an
agreement, but an arrangement (a “great arrangement of mankind,” as he puts it),
and the contract lays it out for us to see, not to choose.29 Burke’s notion of the
social contract is thus distinct from Paine’s and from the common
Enlightenment-liberal social-contract teaching. He puts it most clearly in a
justifiably famous passage in the Reflections:
Society is indeed a contract. Subordinate contracts, for objects of mere occasional interest, may be
dissolved at pleasure; but the state ought not to be considered as nothing better than a partnership
agreement in a trade of pepper and coffee . . . or some other such low concern, . . . to be dissolved
by the fancy of the parties. It is to be looked on with other reverence. . . . It is a partnership in all
science; a partnership in all art; a partnership in every virtue, and in all perfection. As the ends of
such a partnership cannot be obtained in many generations, it becomes a partnership not only
between those who are living, but between those who are living, those who are dead, and those
who are to be born. . . . The municipal corporations of that universal kingdom are not morally at
liberty . . . to dissolve it into an unsocial, uncivil, unconnected chaos of elementary principles. It is
the first and supreme necessity only, a necessity that is not chosen but chooses, a necessity
paramount to deliberation, that admits no discussion, and demands no evidence, which alone can
justify a resort to anarchy.30

Burke thus employs the concept of the social contract to a purpose almost the
opposite of Paine’s. And Burke’s discussions of contract almost never touch on
the subject generally of greatest interest to Enlightenment-liberal contract
theorists (and, for that matter, to political philosophers in general): the structure
of the regime and its institutions. He lays out the proper functions of government
in terms of the services it ought to render to society, but he contends that “the
circumstances and habits of every country . . . decide upon the form of its
government,” and this form can gradually change with time as circumstances
require.31
Nor does Burke think that describing the nature of society means describing
the history of society—as the usual modern (perhaps scientific) approach to
political life would seek to do. He is instead seeking something more like the
essential character of social life and so looks at society as he believes it is, rather
than trying to understand the chronology of its development. And because
Burke’s contract is a description, the contract does not establish the grounds on
which society may be dissolved or may continue, but rather presents the relation
between its parts. Burke argues that the Enlightenment-liberal social-contract
theorists apply their contract only to extreme situations, grounding it in the
moment of founding and drawing from it rules for when revolution may be
appropriate. “But the very habit of stating these extreme cases is not very
laudable or safe,” he writes, “because in general it is not right to turn our duties
into doubts. They are imposed to govern our conduct, not to exercise our
ingenuity; and therefore, our opinions about them ought not to be in a state of
fluctuation, but steady, sure, and resolved.”32 Burke’s contract describes the
everyday life of his society.
To deny the centrality of consent is surely to deny as well the importance of
rights, as Enlightenment-liberal theory understands them. And Thomas Paine
argues fervently that Burke’s unusual twist on the social contract leaves him
incapable of any case for rights. “Does Mr. Burke mean to deny that man has
any rights?” he asks in Rights of Man. “If he does, then he must mean that there
are no such things as rights anywhere, and that he has none himself; for who is
there in the world but man? But if Mr. Burke means to admit that man has rights,
the question then will be: What are those rights, and how man came by them
originally?”33
But Burke refuses to allow his opponents to own the idea of rights. As he
does with the concept of the social contract (and as we will see him do as well
with the idea of liberty), he invokes the vocabulary of the Enlightenment
radicals, but with different meanings in mind: “In denying their false claims of
right, I do not mean to injure those which are real, and are such as their
pretended rights would totally destroy.”34 And just what are these real claims of
right? Burke offers his fullest answer in the Reflections:
If civil society be made for the advantage of man, all the advantages for which it is made become
his right. It is an institution of beneficence; and law itself is only beneficence acting by a rule.
Men have a right to live by that rule; they have a right to justice; as between their fellows, whether
their fellows are in politic function or in ordinary occupation. They have a right to the fruits of
their industry; and to the means of making their industry fruitful. They have a right to the
acquisitions of their parents; to the nourishment and improvement of their offspring; to instruction
in life, and to consolation in death. Whatever each man can separately do, without trespassing
upon others, he has a right to do for himself; and he has a right to a fair portion of all which
society, with all its combinations of skill and force, can do in his favor.35

Burke essentially denies the relevance (though not necessarily the existence)
of abstract, individual, natural rights. He defines instead some practical rights to
the benefits of society. And these benefits do not amount to freedom or power. In
fact, some of the benefits of society to which men have a right involve restraints
on their freedoms and their passions. Burke writes:
Government is not made in virtue of natural rights, which may and do exist in total independence
of it; and exist in much greater clearness, and in a much greater degree of abstract perfection: but
their abstract perfection is their practical defect. By having a right to every thing they want every
thing. Government is a contrivance of human wisdom to provide for human wants. Men have a
right that these wants should be provided for by this wisdom. Among these wants is to be
reckoned the want, out of civil society, of a sufficient restraint upon their passions.

Society’s ability to limit the range of our choices is thus an important


advantage:
Society requires not only that the passions of individuals should be subjected, but that even in the
mass and body as well as in the individuals, the inclinations of men should frequently be thwarted,
their will controlled, and their passions brought into subjection. This can only be done by a power
out of themselves; and not, in the exercise of its function, subject to that will and to those passions
which it is its office to bridle and subdue. In this sense the restraints on men, as well as their
liberties, are to be reckoned among their rights. But as the liberties and the restrictions vary with
times and circumstances, and admit of infinite modifications, they cannot be settled upon any
abstract rule; and nothing is so foolish as to discuss them upon that principle.36

Human beings cannot live in society if they follow their wants and passions
unrestrained, and so one of the rights of citizens is to have their passions brought
under some control. Thus society guarantees some liberties and some restraints,
and precisely how these are balanced is in normal times a matter of prudence,
not absolute principle. The calculus of prudence aims not to maximize choice,
but to meet the true wants of the people, as these emerge from the complex and
layered society that Burke describes. His rights are therefore relations, not
individual entitlements—they describe a person’s place in the large scheme of
obligations and privileges and offer the protection and benefits of that scheme
and that place.
Since choice is not central to Burke’s understanding of rights, he rather
readily dismisses the right to self-government—that “share of power, authority,
and direction which each individual ought to have in the management of the
state.”37 The state, as Burke sees it, owes certain advantages to its people, and
whatever means can best achieve these while retaining the loyalty of the people
ought to be pursued. The key is not that each man should have his views
expressed through the actions of the state, but that each man should have his
needs served by the actions of the state. The people’s desires and their interests
can conflict, Burke says, and the able statesman must seek to serve their true
interests. The nation, therefore, ought to be understood as guided by a purpose,
and not by a duty to its origins or to man’s natural rights. The state proves itself
by achieving its purpose, which is the benefit of its citizens.
Even in the democratic element of the British regime, Burke believes, the
role of each member of Parliament was not to stand in for his constituents but to
apply his wisdom to advance their interests and needs and those of the entire
nation. In 1774, just after winning election to the House of Commons from
Bristol—England’s second largest city at the time—Burke told his new
constituents that he would not see his role as merely the representative of their
views: “Your representative owes you, not his industry only, but his judgment;
and he betrays, instead of serving you, if he sacrifices it to your opinion.”38
Even the Commons, in other words, is not a fully representative institution, and
Burke acknowledges no inherent right to take part in self-government.
Government is not the counting of heads, but an application of prudence to
circumstances, and in Burke’s view, there is no reason to imagine that every man
is entitled to a part in it—direct or indirect. Under some circumstances,
democratic institutions may best serve the interests of the whole, and in these
situations, they ought to be employed, but not as a matter of absolute right.
This denial of the right to self-government, the most stark expression of
Burke’s denial of the centrality of choice in political life, was sure to set off
Paine, for whom the right to rule is the essential civil right from which all others
flow. Paine has no patience for Burke’s complex meanderings around the basic
question of self-government. He sees in Burke’s reconception of rights an empty
mysticism aimed at defending illegitimate rule:
He puts the nation as fools on one side, and places his government of wisdom, all wise men of
Gotham, on the other side, and he then proclaims, and says that “Men have a RIGHT that their
WANTS should be provided for by this wisdom.” Having thus made proclamation, he next
proceeds to explain to them what their wants are, and also what their rights are. . . . [I]n order to
impress them with a solemn reverence for this monopoly-government of wisdom, and of its vast
capacity for all purposes, possible or impossible, right or wrong, he proceeds with astrological
mysterious importance, to tell to them its powers.

This, Paine suggests, is just a way to keep Burke’s readers from seeing
through Burke’s denial of the basic principles of liberty: “As the wondering
audience, whom Mr. Burke supposes himself talking to, may not understand all
this learned jargon, I will undertake to be its interpreter. The meaning, then, good
people, of all this, is: That government is governed by no principle whatever;
that it can make evil good, or good evil, just as it pleases. In short, that
government is arbitrary power.”39
Burke’s notion of government, Paine worries, provides no protections of
liberty, because it does not define in advance the precise rights of man that no
government may intrude upon and because it does not lay out the limits of
government. It substitutes vague and varying notions of advantages and relations
for a clear idea of the protection of every individual’s freedom to choose.
Without question, Burke’s reimagining of the social contract deprives him of
one great advantage of the Enlightenment-liberal contract theorists: a clear
principle by which to limit the scope of government action to oppose coercion.
Government, in Burke’s view, is limited by the complex obligations, relations,
and distinctions that compose every society. Paine seeks to flatten these
distinctions but impose in their place explicit limits on the state in defense of
individual liberty. Paine thinks the principles of liberty will better protect
individual freedom than the institutions of society. Where Paine imposes on
government the obligation to respect the freedom of action of each of its citizens,
Burke imposes on government a much less exacting (if somewhat more
demanding) obligation to meet the wants of the people and advance the interests
of the complex social whole. Order and interest, more than individual liberty and
choice, is the end of Burke’s notion of government. And he thinks the nation’s
social topography will be a better guardian of the people’s liberty in practice
than a set of abstract rules, however exacting they might be.
But here again, Burke attempts to employ the rhetoric and vocabulary of the
more radical liberals to his own rather different purposes. He will not let the
Enlightenment liberals own the term liberty, either. “The effects of the incapacity
shown by the popular leaders in all the great members of the commonwealth are
to be covered with the ‘all-atoning name’ of liberty,” he writes of events in
France. “But what is liberty without wisdom, and without virtue? It is the
greatest of all possible evils; for it is folly, vice, and madness, without tuition or
restraint. Those who know what virtuous liberty is, cannot bear to see it
disgraced by incapable heads, on account of their having high-sounding words in
their mouths.”40
And just what is this “virtuous liberty”? How does it differ from the notion
that Paine or the French revolutionaries have in mind? Burke offers an answer in
a 1789 letter to a young Frenchman named Charles-Jean-François Depont, who
had suggested to him that the revolution then unfolding in Paris was a great
example of liberty in action. The French surely deserved liberty, Burke
responded, but they had mistaken the meaning of the term. True liberty “is not
solitary, unconnected, individual, selfish liberty, as if every man was to regulate
the whole of his conduct by his own will. The liberty I mean is social freedom. It
is that state of things in which liberty is assured by the equality of restraint. . . .
This kind of liberty is indeed but another name for justice; ascertained by wise
laws, and secured by well-constructed institutions.”41
This is perhaps the boldest and most forthright of Burke’s redefinitions of
liberal terminology. He suggests that radical individualism is the opposite of
justice and, in that sense, also the opposite of genuine liberty. He offers “social
freedom” as a kind of counterpart to “individual liberty,” a term much favored
by Paine and by many Enlightenment liberals of the day, and suggests such
freedom is the deepest source of Britain’s strength.42
This interplay of liberty and restraint is key to Burke’s understanding of both
government and the challenges of statesmanship. “Men are qualified for civil
liberty in exact proportion to their disposition to put moral chains upon their own
appetites,” he writes. “Society cannot exist, unless a controlling power upon will
and appetite be placed somewhere; and the less of it there is within, the more
there must be without. It is ordained in the eternal constitution of things, that
men of intemperate minds cannot be free. Their passions forge their fetters.”43
Thus an intemperate people, including a people pushed toward intemperance
by a radical political philosophy, will be less capable of liberty and thus more
likely to find themselves oppressed by their regime, regardless of how noble the
philosophy expounded in their declarations of rights might be.
Finding the balance between freedom and restraint is an immensely difficult
challenge, which the revolutionaries, certain of their ability to establish a regime
from scratch, are too likely to ignore. “To make a government requires no great
prudence,” Burke writes in the Reflections. “Settle the seat of power; teach
obedience; and the work is done. To give freedom is still more easy. It is not
necessary to guide; it only requires to let go of the rein. But to form a free
government: that is, to temper together these opposite elements of liberty and
restraint in one consistent work, requires much thought, deep reflection, a
sagacious, powerful, and combining mind.”44 Liberty and restraint cannot be
balanced by a stark application of Enlightenment-liberal syllogisms drawing on
the natural rights of every individual, because the balance must always occur in
the complicated context of social life and therefore must consider the numerous
obligations, privileges, and habits that shape a society. Liberty in practice is a
compromise between restraint and freedom. In a letter to some prominent
constituents in Bristol, Burke lays out his case against the Enlightenment-liberal
notion of freedom:
Far from any resemblance to those propositions in geometry and metaphysics, which admit no
medium, but must be true or false in all their latitude; social and civil freedom, like all other things
in common life, are variously mixed and modified, enjoyed in very different degrees, and shaped
into an infinite diversity of forms, according to the temper and circumstances of every community.
The EXTREME of liberty (which is its abstract perfection, but its real fault) obtains nowhere, nor
ought to obtain anywhere. Because extremes, as we all know, in every point which relates either to
our duties or satisfactions in life, are destructive both to virtue and enjoyment.45

The only genuine liberty, Burke argued in 1774, “is a liberty connected with
order: that not only exists along with order and virtue but which cannot exist at
all without them. It inheres in good and steady government, as in its substance
and vital principle.”46 This ordered liberty, Burke argues, is the essence of what
a good government owes its people. It is what the social contract protects, what
the rights of men properly understood involve, and what freedom really means.
It is secured by prudent statesmen, alert to the non-voluntary social relations that
shape society, and to the unique history, habits, and mores their people have
developed to meet their obligations and pursue gradual and incremental political
and social progress.
Burke and Paine therefore approach the question of social relations—of
choice and obligation as ends of society—in profoundly different ways, moved
by their different premises about the character of human life and especially by
their deep divergence on the question of context: the importance of the given
world to shaping our options and defining our duties. Their general views on this
question shape many of their particular opinions and instincts on the immense
array of issues both men take up in their writings. But these opinions take shape
in complicated and often surprising ways.
To see these complications in more detail, we can examine the two men’s
views on two sets of issues in particular: patriotism (or duty to country) and
social-welfare policy (or obligation to one’s fellow citizens).

THE NATION AND THE POOR


Thomas Paine seeks to put universal principles into practice. In basing man’s
rights and liberties on nature, not on history, he understands them as equally true
and applicable everywhere and therefore not rooted in any particular nation’s
circumstances or ideals. His writings are therefore remarkably devoid of appeals
to patriotism and duty to homeland. Even in his Revolutionary War writings in
America, including the Crisis papers, which were intended to strengthen the
resolve of the populace, Paine almost always appeals to the universal cause of
freedom and not to the particular love of America.
As R. R. Fennessy has put it, “Paine’s only loyalty was, in fact, to his own
principles. When America adopted them, he was to be an American citizen. . . .
When, later, he thought that France was about to follow America’s example, he
was happy to accept French citizenship—and he was just as happy to relinquish
it when he found that the French, after all, did not understand political
principles.”47 Paine often described himself in the same terms. “My country is
the world, and my religion is to do good,” he wrote on several occasions.48
In his writings, Paine clearly asserts that his principles require him to put
himself above mere national identity in this way. Contrasting the old and the new
ways of thinking about government in Rights of Man, Paine notes that “the one
encourages national prejudices; the other promotes universal society.”49 He sees
social obligations as obligations to one’s fellow man. They may flow through
one’s community or country, but they are not obligations to the community or
country. Paine finds it difficult to justify a pure regard for one’s own, and for
him, love of country is not a substitute for clearheaded judgment of the
legitimacy of the government.
Edmund Burke, of course, placed a far greater emphasis on the social and
generational context of politics, arguing that the intermediaries between each
man and mankind at large were crucial to political order and that the nation was
especially crucial. The nation is the means by which order is made and kept, and
by which order is made beautiful. A nation builds upon its past accomplishments
through prescription by looking to its common history and finding in this history
both sources of pride and principles for reform and improvement. Family
affections become community affections and, finally, national ties. Every
individual thus finds himself enmeshed in multiple communities—his
geographic neighbors, his fellow workers or merchants or nobles—and all of
these point up toward the nation, and only from the nation and through it toward
mankind as a whole.50
This does not mean that we must simply accept everything about our
country, right or wrong. But we must begin from a disposition of gratitude for
what it provides us. And the statesman must sustain the attachments of the
people to their country. “To make us love our country, our country ought to be
lovely,” Burke writes in the Reflections.51 But whether it is lovely or in need of
reform, our country is not simply one instance of universal principles in action.
As Paine describes it, every country would be more or less the same if all were
to abide by the principles of freedom and justice, but Burke thinks the historical
experience of each nation defines its forward path. Each society has its own
traditional institutions and trajectories and gives its people something unique of
their own to love. “Our country is not a thing of mere physical locality,” Burke
writes. “It consists, in a great measure, in the ancient order into which we are
born.”52
But if their differences about the nature of public obligations led Burke and
Paine to divergent views on patriotism, the very same differences ironically led
them to quite similar views on economic relations and the then-emerging
theories of capitalism. The right and left both began with high hopes for
capitalism, but for very different reasons and with very different notions of what
it would mean for society and its members—and especially what material
obligations citizens had toward one another.
Paine several times makes it clear that he is a believer in commerce because
he believes open trade and free economics will advance his radical causes by
uprooting traditional social and political arrangements.53 It would do this by
focusing men on their material needs and showing them a rational means of
meeting those needs. The system of the old European governments, Paine
argues, was held in place by deceptions and distractions (including especially the
nearly permanent specter of war) that could be, and were already beginning to
be, dissipated by a rational economics. “The condition of the world being
materially changed by the influence of science and commerce, it is put into a
fitness not only to admit of, but to desire, an extension of civilization,” Paine
writes. “The principal and almost only remaining enemy it now has to encounter
is prejudice.”54
Burke’s support for largely unimpeded trade and industry began from
roughly the opposite corner. He argued that government manipulation of the
economy could be profoundly disruptive to the social order because it involved
gross manipulation of very complicated economic and social forces that are
almost inevitably beyond the understanding of legislators. Even in its own
material terms, he argues, the economy functions best when left to itself,
referring in one essay to “the laws of commerce, which are the laws of nature,
and consequently the laws of God.”55 A free economy, as Burke saw it, would
help sustain the stability of society and therefore its wealth—some of which
could (and should) then be used by the wealthy to help the poor.
The passion for wealth was by no means an unmitigated good, but trying to
mitigate it through policy would be a mistake, Burke argued. It would have to be
counteracted by the culture, not by politics, which should just seek whatever
good could be drawn from it. “The love of lucre, though sometimes carried to a
ridiculous, sometimes to a vicious excess, is the grand cause of prosperity to all
States. In this natural, this reasonable, this powerful, this prolific principle, it is
for the satirist to expose the ridiculous; it is for the moralist to censure the
vicious; it is for the sympathetic heart to reprobate the hard and cruel; it is for the
Judge to animadvert on the fraud, the extortion, and the oppression: but it is for
the Statesman to employ it as he finds it; with all its concomitant excellencies,
with all its imperfections on its head.”56
Legislators are always tempted to employ the weight of government to undo
economic inequalities, but such attempts always produce more harm than good,
in Burke’s view. He recognizes that the modern economy does relegate some
people to desperate poverty or to demeaning occupations, and he frets about “the
innumerable servile, degrading, unseemly, unmanly, and often most
unwholesome and pestiferous occupations, to which by the social economy so
many wretches are inevitably doomed.”57 But the costs of remedying their
situation, not only to society as a whole but even to the particular wretches
involved, would be far worse than their current suffering, Burke argues, because
these people are the most vulnerable to economic dislocations, which are made
more likely by clumsy government manipulations of prices or wages.
In a short essay titled Thoughts and Details on Scarcity (much of it written in
1795, the last year of his life, to advise the prime minister against an attempt to
manage the pay of farm laborers through legislation), Burke expresses a
profound mistrust of government interference in the economy, especially on
behalf of the poor: “My opinion is against an over-doing of any sort of
administration, and more especially against this most momentous of all
meddling on the part of authority; the meddling with the subsistence of the
people.”58 The needs of the poor are of the utmost importance, he argues, but
they should be addressed by charities, which should be amply supported by the
wealthy and the noble. Government cannot take that care upon itself, as doing so
would never work and, in the process, would disrupt the social order. Care of the
poor is not in this sense a public obligation, but a private one.
Burke’s ardent capitalism was noticed by no less an authority on the subject
than his contemporary, Adam Smith, who wrote that “Mr. Burke is the only man
I ever knew who thinks on economic subjects exactly as I do, without any
previous communications having passed between us.”59 But ironically, Paine
criticizes Burke’s economic thinking precisely by citing Smith. “Had Mr. Burke
possessed talents similar to the author of ‘On the Wealth of Nations,’ he would
have comprehended all the parts which enter into, and, by assemblage, form a
constitution,” Paine writes in Rights of Man, when dismissing Burke’s
complaints about the revolutionaries’ supposed mismanagement of the French
economy.60
Paine was undoubtedly right about some of the social consequences of free-
market economics, and Burke was surely mistaken to argue that free trade and
capitalism would keep the elements of society in their place and aid stability.
Few forces in the modern West have been as disruptive (for good and for bad) of
established order. But the two men’s deeper difference, it turns out, was not
about the consequences of capitalism but about the community’s obligation to
the poor. While the often communitarian Burke argues that care for the needy
ought to remain a private function in large part for the sake of the needy, the
often libertarian Paine makes a forceful case for something like a modern
welfare system. In so doing, Paine helps show how the modern left developed
from Enlightenment liberalism toward embryonic forms of welfare-state
liberalism as its utopian political hopes seemed dashed by the grim realities of
the industrial revolution.
Paine’s views in this regard offer a rare instance of his clearly changing his
position in the course of his career. In his earlier writings, Paine describes a very
limited scope for government: “Government is no farther necessary than to
supply the few cases to which society and civilization are not conveniently
competent, and instances are not wanting to show, that every thing which
government can usefully add thereto has been performed by the common
consent of society, without government.”61 But by 1791, having witnessed in
Paris and London the early effects of the approaching industrial economy and
having thought through the implications of his views about the origins of the
social order, Paine was writing with eloquent passion of “the moral obligation of
providing for old age, helpless infancy, and poverty.”62 Meeting this obligation,
he argues in the second part of Rights of Man, is a key purpose of government.
“Civil government does not exist in executions; but in making such provision for
the instruction of youth and the support of age, as to exclude, as much as
possible, profligacy from the one and despair from the other.”63 He calls for
provisions for poor parents when a child is born, for government support in
paying for elementary education, for pensions to the elderly who cannot work,
and even for public help with funeral expenses for those who cannot afford
them.64 “This support,” he then argues, “is not of the nature of a charity but of a
right.”65 Public assistance to the poor turns out to be a true social obligation.
In 1797, Paine devoted a short pamphlet titled Agrarian Justice to laying out
more fully his case for this proto–welfare state and for why it should be viewed
as a right of those in need. The case, it turns out, draws on Paine’s usual method
of reasoning from human origins:
The earth, in its natural, cultivated state was, and ever would have continued to be, the common
property of the human race. In that state every man would have been born to property. . . . But the
earth in its natural state, as before said, is capable of supporting but a small number of inhabitants
compared with what it is capable of doing in a cultivated state. And as it is impossible to separate
the improvement made by cultivation from the earth itself, upon which that improvement is made,
the idea of landed property arose from that parable connection; but it is nevertheless true, that it is
the value of the improvement, only, and not the earth itself, that is individual property. Every
proprietor, therefore, of cultivated lands, owes to the community ground-rent (for I know of no
better term to express the idea) for the land which he holds; and it is from this ground-rent that the
fund in this plan is to issue.66

Since the first human generation had a right to all the earth, and since
subsequent ones have denied that right to most, it is only proper that
compensation should be paid, drawn from a tax on property and made available
to all. He is very clear on this last point: Not only the poor but all (including
landowners themselves) would receive payment from this common fund. He
writes, “It is proposed that the payments, as already stated, be made to every
person, rich or poor. It is best to make it so, to prevent invidious distinctions. It is
also right it should be so, because it is in lieu of the natural inheritance, which,
as a right, belongs to every man, over and above property he may have created,
or inherited from those who did. Such persons as do not choose to receive it can
throw it into the common fund.”67
Paine expressly disagrees with Burke’s notion that charities can take care of
the poor:
There are, in every country, some magnificent charities established by individuals. It is, however,
but little that any individual can do, when the whole extent of the misery to be relieved is
considered. He may satisfy his conscience, but not his heart. He may give all that he has, and that
all will relieve but little. It is only by organizing civilization upon such principles as to act like a
system of pulleys, that the whole weight of misery can be removed. . . . In all great cases it is
necessary to have a principle more universally active than charity; and, with respect to justice, it
ought not to be left to the choice of detached individuals whether they will do justice or not.68

Poverty, it seems, is taken by Paine to be one of those coercive realities that


constrain the people’s freedom, from which the state ought to protect the people,
so as to allow their will and choice free rein. “The rugged face of society,
checkered with the extremes of affluence and want, proves that some
extraordinary violence has been committed upon it, and calls on justice for
redress,” Paine writes. “The great mass of the poor in countries are become an
hereditary race, and it is next to impossible for them to get out of that state of
themselves.”69 This persistent poverty creates a social obligation upon others—
poverty is a threat to freedom that yields in a right to be liberated from poverty.
To Burke’s mind, meanwhile, poverty is one of the realities that always
exists and is part of the larger human condition, not a departure from it. Wealthy
individuals have a moral and religious duty to help ameliorate poverty, but it
could never be eradicated by the government. Poverty is surely a constraint on
choice, but not a failure of government, since the protection of choice is not a
fundamental purpose of government, in Burke’s view.
Paine thus looks to politics to overcome impediments to our freedom to live
as we choose, which leads him in time to look to the state to ameliorate severe
material deprivation. He argues that such deprivation originates from the
(sometimes necessary, sometimes avoidable) distortions of mankind’s equal right
to the fruits of the earth and is exacerbated over time by regimes that neglect or
ignore the rights of their people. To correct for this error, he argues, government
has a role in alleviating the misery of the most miserable and giving all
something closer to an equal chance of rising by their own merits. In this way,
again, Paine understands social obligations as arising primarily out of the
importance of individual freedom and choice. Government exists to address
violations of rights to freedom and choice, and it must occasionally do so by a
modest redistribution of material resources to keep the poorest from falling
beneath even the minimal standard of human dignity. Paine is thus an ardent
capitalist but one alert to some of the effects of capitalism on the poor. Before
the full emergence of the industrial revolution, Paine understood that economic
progress would not eliminate poverty and, on the contrary, might create
circumstances that could necessitate unprecedented public action.
Burke, meanwhile, believed our obligations are functions not of our right to
choose but of our deeply embedded place in the social order. Each of us lives in
a particular relation to society, which carries with it both duties and privileges,
and society will only function well if all its members meet their particular
obligations. The care of the poor is surely among these obligations, but the duty
falls to the rich, not to the state acting on behalf of all, because it is not
something the state could do without causing even greater harm. Precisely
because Burke draws a less stark distinction between society and government—
treating both as described by the social contract, which is a partnership in all
things—he also has a more limited notion of the role of the government. Paine
makes a great deal of the difference between government and society, but in
practice this difference often means that duties that are taken to be public
obligations are all assigned to the government, while private life is kept
conceptually separate from politics.
Burke’s and Paine’s understandings of social relations, therefore, differ
dramatically, and along lines similar to (and rooted in) those of their
disagreement over nature and history. Edmund Burke begins from the given
world and seeks to strengthen social and political life as a means of contending
with circumstances we did not choose. Thomas Paine begins from the principles
of liberty, equality, and natural rights and builds political institutions on those
grounds to defend the prerogatives of the individual. The two men differ sharply
on just how much what has been done before matters and just how pliable
human relations will be to philosophically inspired efforts at fundamental
reconstruction.
In their differing views, we also find echoes of their more general approaches
toward effecting political change. The thinker, who works primarily with ideas
and principles, looks at circumstances not of people’s choosing and considers
them consequences of past applications of principle. Such a person sees in
circumstances that are less than ideal the imprint of principles that are less than
correct. He therefore seeks to improve on circumstances by offering a new
beginning in principles that are more correct. The statesman, who works with
political circumstances, begins necessarily from his (mostly given rather than
chosen) affiliations with and obligations to his particular community and its
various subdivisions and so starts from what exists and seeks within it ways to
improve on it. In this way, the distinction between choice and obligation finds its
match in the distinction between reason and prescription, as the former
distinction applies to the ends of politics and the latter to its means. We therefore
turn next to Burke’s and Paine’s profound disagreement on the relative merits of
reason and prescription and, with them, of theory and practice.
FIVE

REASON AND PRESCRIPTION

F NATURAL EQUALITY IS THE CRUCIAL PREMISE OF

I Enlightenment-liberal politics, and government by consent its essential form,


then human reason is its great moving force. Reason cuts through the pious
platitudes of the old order, demonstrates the truth and consequences of our
rights, and helps us to shape a new order built to serve justice. The age of
revolutions understood itself as advancing the cause of reason in political life.
In America, the revolutionary leaders assumed that “a decent respect to the
opinions of mankind requires that they should declare the causes which impel”
their actions for inspection under the searing light of reason. In France, the most
ardent revolutionaries considered themselves a kind of “cult of reason,” as the
revolutionary leader Jacques Hebert put it. And for a great many Europeans who
described their time as an age of enlightenment, it was human reason unleashed
(especially by the new natural sciences and their methods) that shed new light on
old quandaries.
Given how central the idea of a truly rational politics was to the self-
understanding of the champions of Enlightenment liberalism, this ideal was, not
surprisingly, a point of great contention between Burke and Paine. Paine
understood his own time as “The Age of Reason” (as he dubbed it in the title of
his last book). He thought that the combination of new insights into the science
of politics and greater freedom for citizens to exercise their own individual
reason upon public questions would free liberal societies of countless ancient
prejudices and open the way to a new politics of liberty. Burke thought the
governing of human communities was much too complex a task to be simplified
into a series of pseudoscientific questions and resolved by logical exercises. It
required, in his view, a degree of knowledge and wisdom about human affairs
that could only be gathered from the experience of society itself. Their views, in
other words, were direct extensions of the broader worldviews presented thus far
and offer a deeper understanding of the foundational political questions of
modern politics. Their dispute therefore deepens as it moves from the ends to the
means of political thought.

BURKE’S PRESCRIPTION AND THE LIMITS OF REASON


Edmund Burke’s belief in the complexity of human nature and the insufficiency
of choice leads him to be far more skeptical than most of his peers about
reason’s potential for guiding political action. Burke routinely mocks the idea
that the radicals’ rationalism had unleashed a great enlightenment upon a hitherto
dark world. Having read, as he puts it, “more than he can justify to any thing but
the spirit of curiosity of the works of these illuminators of the world,” Burke
reports himself perplexed at their claims to a new path to wisdom. “Where the
old authors whom he has read, and the old men whom he has conversed with,
have left him in the dark, he is in the dark still.”1
There is more to this than a sarcastic jab at self-appointed beacons of reason.
Burke believes that Enlightenment liberals’ and radicals’ emphasis on human
reason begins from a misunderstanding of human nature—the mistaking of a
part for the whole: “Politics ought to be adjusted not to human reasonings but to
human nature, of which the reason is but a part, and by no means the greatest
part.”2 By ignoring the greater parts—especially the sentiments and attachments
that move people in politics—one misses the most important factors behind
political actions and social attachments. Many of the greatest challenges a
statesman must confront arise from the less rational elements of the human
character.
Governing is, of course, a rational activity, and political thought must
certainly be guided by some general principles, but it’s a mistake to assume that
effective principles can be drawn from abstract premises rather than actual
experience. The general must be derived from the particular, not the other way
around. “It seems to me a preposterous way of reasoning, and a perfect
confusion of ideas, to take the theories which learned and speculative men have
made from [the practice of] government, and then, supposing it made on those
theories which were made from it, to accuse government as not corresponding
with them.”3
This confusion of the relationship between theory and practice in politics can
have dangerous consequences, Burke warns, because as political life becomes an
enactment of a theory rather than a response to particular social needs and wants,
it becomes unmoored both from the ends that should guide politics and from the
limits that should restrain it. He believes that the importation of theory too
directly into political life is among the foremost errors both of the British
government in its dealings with America in the late 1770s and of the
revolutionaries in France a decade later. Again and again he warns against
mistaking politics for metaphysics, and he describes his concerns in terms of
three distinct but closely related worries.
First, Burke believes that the attempt to apply what he calls metaphysical
methods in politics confuses politicians and citizens about the purpose of politics
—leading them to think that governing is about proving a point rather than
advancing the interests and happiness of a nation. The trouble is not that
principles do not belong in politics. On the contrary, Burke writes, “I do not put
abstract ideas wholly out of any question; because I well know that under that
name I should dismiss principles, and that without the guide and light of sound
well understood principles, all reasonings in politics, as in everything else,
would be only a confused jumble of particular facts and details, without the
means of drawing out any sort of theoretical or practical conclusion.”4 Rather,
the problem is the insistence on abstract precision in political questions and thus
on measuring practice by fine theoretical metrics. This insistence can confuse us
about what the purpose of politics actually is. Government is “a practical thing,
made for the happiness of mankind,” Burke writes, not “to gratify the schemes
of visionary politicians.” It runs into trouble, therefore, when statesmen “split
and anatomiz[e] the doctrine of free government, as if it were an abstract
question concerning metaphysical liberty and necessity and not a matter of moral
prudence and natural feeling.”5
Burke’s objection is in essence methodological. Politics cannot be
understood by a method too exacting and abstract for the subject. Since “man
acts from adequate motives relative to his interest, and not on metaphysical
speculations,” politics must be attuned to his motives and interests.6 This does
not mean that no distinctions can be made in politics, but it does mean that
hairsplitting, speculative distinctions are often far too fine to be of service. “No
lines can be laid down for civil or political wisdom. They are a matter incapable
of exact definition. But, though no man can draw a stroke between the confines
of day and night, yet light and darkness are upon the whole tolerably
distinguishable.”7
Practitioners of politics therefore should not expect precise knowledge and
must accustom themselves to making prudential and uncertain judgments.
“Every political question I have ever known has had so much of the pro and con
in it that nothing but the success could decide which proposition was to have
been adopted,” Burke confesses to a friend.8 In the moment, a politician cannot
avail himself of scientific certitude, and in seeking it, he corrupts his practice,
which must consist of informed approximations. “It is, I own, not uncommon to
be wrong in theory and right in practice,” Burke notes.9 And the success of
policy must be measured in practice, not by its adherence to a speculative theory.
“A statesman differs from a professor in [a] university,” Burke remarked in a
1781 speech, “the latter has only the general view of society; the former, the
statesman, has a number of circumstances to combine with these general ideas,
and to take into his consideration.”10
This difference points to Burke’s second great concern about theory in
politics, which is that theory often ignores circumstances and particulars crucial
to the success of policy and the happiness of society. Theory is general and
universal, but politics must always be very particular. “Circumstances (which
with some gentlemen pass for nothing) give in reality to every political principle
its distinguishing color and discriminating effect. The circumstances are what
render every civil and political scheme beneficial or noxious to mankind.”11 In
this respect politics is more, not less, precise than theory: It is concrete and
particular. And Burke believes that concrete characteristics, needs, and interests
are undermined when politics is turned into a kind of applied metaphysics. In a
letter to constituents in Bristol, Burke assured his voters: “I never ventured to put
your solid interests upon speculative grounds.”12 It is absurd to make political
judgments in the abstract, he writes in another letter: “I must see the thing, I
must see the men.”13 It is impossible to govern well without taking heed of
these distinctions and differences. “The legislators who framed the ancient
republics,” Burke writes in the Reflections,
knew that their business was too arduous to be accomplished with no better apparatus than the
metaphysics of an undergraduate, and the mathematics and arithmetic of an exciseman. They had
to do with men, and they were obliged to study human nature. They had to do with citizens, and
they were obliged to study the effects of those habits which are communicated by the
circumstances of civil life. They were sensible that the operation of this second nature on the first
produced a new combination; and thence arose many diversities amongst men, according to their
birth, their education, their professions, the periods of their lives, their residence in towns or in the
country, their several ways of acquiring and of fixing property, and according to the quality of the
property itself, all which rendered them as it were so many different species of animals. . . . For
the legislator would have been ashamed, that the coarse husband-man should well know how to
assort and to use his sheep, horses, and oxen, and should have enough of common sense not to
abstract and equalize them all into animals, without providing for each kind an appropriate food,
care, and employment; whilst he, the oeconomist, disposer, and shepherd of his own kindred,
subliming himself into an airy metaphysician, was resolved to know nothing of his flocks, but as
men in general.14

When statesmen practice such egalitarian abstraction, they fail to know their
people. And this failure translates into practice as a failure to account for crucial
differences and attachments, which Burke deemed essential to political life.
Rather than govern the people through their native or organically emergent
categories and distinctions, Burke writes, the radicals in France seek “to
confound all sorts of citizens, as well as they could, into one homogeneous mass;
and then they divided this their amalgama into a number of incoherent
republics.”15 He has in mind a decision of the revolutionary assembly to divide
France into perfect square districts, rather than govern its traditional regions. The
eradication of traditional attachments and practices that would follow such a
move (and that indeed was its purpose) would not eliminate prejudices and
attach the people to their national identity, as the revolutionaries hoped. Instead,
Burke argues, it would crush all attachment to community and leave an
unrestrained Paris government in charge of a greatly weakened nation.
In these protestations against the rational eradication of traditional
distinctions, we find a hint of Burke’s essential moderation, which rejected not
only chaos but also an excess of order. Reductive theories of politics seemed to
him an almost despotic force in society. They first undid all existing
arrangements, weakening the people beyond repair, and then imposed an
artificial order unconnected and ill suited to the character of those being
governed. And in this radical rearrangement, he feared, were the seeds of an
unrestrained political extremism, employing society as a kind of metaphysical
laboratory.
That very fear points to the third concern Burke has about theory in politics.
He is concerned that an overreliance on theory may unleash extremism and
immoderation by unmooring politics from the polity. “Their principles always go
to the extreme,” Burke writes of the radicals of his day.16 Because they pursue
the vindication of a principle, they cannot stop short of total success. Even when
their aims are well conceived, the radicals will not accept a good thing if it “does
not come up to the full perfection of the abstract idea,” and instead, they will
“push for the more perfect, which cannot be attained without tearing to pieces
the whole contexture of the commonwealth.”17 Burke believed that when the
perfect is thus made the enemy of the good, political life can never be
satisfactory, since there is no perfection in politics.
The quest for theoretical perfection is thus in practice a pursuit of extremes.
And precisely because the pursuit is empowered by sophisticated theories, its
extremism resists restraint. Old-fashioned grievances—moved by local or
national loyalties or material necessities—have their natural bounds. Old-
fashioned despotism—moved by a naked desire for power on the part of a
charismatic tyrant—cannot readily mask its excesses. But a mob moved by a
theory has no natural stopping point and cannot easily be assuaged, and leaders
claiming to advance a truth obtained by philosophical speculation do not fit the
familiar profile of the tyrant. The ancient tyrants could only wish to get away
with what the modern speculative revolutionaries can achieve.18
In the pursuit of such extremes, moreover, the fidelity of the people to
society is always in question. “Those vexatious questions, which in truth rather
belong to metaphysics than politics,” Burke writes, “can never be moved without
shaking the foundations of the best governments that have ever been constituted
by human wisdom.”19 When politics becomes a means of playing out
speculative premises, every political practice, institution, and allegiance must
explain itself in philosophical terms, so that no long-standing tradition,
institution, or cherished habit can resist the searing light of speculative analysis.
A politics built on modern reason inevitably becomes a self-fulfilling prophecy:
rejecting all that cannot explain itself in terms of modern reason and therefore
leaving in place only those elements of political life that meet its standards—
regardless of what society may actually need or what has proven capable of
serving the community in years gone by. By seeking a generalized theoretical
precision in politics, ignoring circumstances and particulars, and unleashing a
spirit of extremism, the speculative method of the Enlightenment radicals
threatens to break the links between human nature and political life, as Burke
understands them. And it does all this on the back of a notion of human reason
that vastly exaggerates the capacity of the individual mind to discern political
truths directly.
Beyond his concern about importing the methods of speculative philosophy
into politics, therefore, Burke expresses profound concern about the concept of
reason at the heart of these methods: an individual rational faculty that on its
own, drawing upon evident principles derived from reflections on nature, can
assess the truth or falsehood of any proposition and apply general rules to every
circumstance. This modern ideal of reason, Burke fears, partakes far too much in
the modern myth of individualism, suggesting that every truth must be
demonstrable to the rational individual. On the contrary, Burke argues, human
reason, important as it is, is far more limited than this ideal suggests, and those
limits point human beings rather to their mutual dependence than to a radical
individualism. The nature of reason, including its limits, is crucial to
understanding the proper means of political thought and action.
From his very earliest writings, Burke was deeply impressed with the limits
of human reason and its inability to resolve very basic philosophical questions.
In his Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of Our Ideas of the Sublime and the
Beautiful, Burke notes that “on the whole one may observe that there is rather
less difference upon matters of taste among mankind than upon most of those
which depend upon the naked reason.”20 We are, he argues, far more likely to
agree on the quality of a poetic passage in Virgil than on whether one of
Aristotle’s theories is true. And this implies that there are limits to what reason
can fully resolve.
The persistence of these limits over centuries of disputation by brilliant
philosophers suggested to Burke that some limits on our rational capacity are
simply permanent—there is only so much we could know for sure. “That man
thinks much too highly, and therefore he thinks weakly and delusively, of any
contrivance of human wisdom, who believes that it can make any sort of
approach to perfection,” Burke writes.21 And it is not our unwillingness to
follow our reason that accounts for these permanent imperfections, but the limits
of reason itself. “It is true indeed that enthusiasm often misleads us,” Burke
writes, but “so does reason too. Such is the condition of our nature; and we
cannot help it.”22 This means that we must balance our reason against our
passions and vice versa, but even such a balance can offer little confidence. No
person has within him the capacity to overcome the radical infirmity and
imperfection of man. No individual is up to it, regardless of his intelligence or
his grasp of the principles of science or the facts of nature. Rather, we must learn
from the combined experience of many, and particularly from the lives of those
who lived before us.
“We are afraid to put men to live and trade each on his own private stock of
reason, because we suspect that the stock in each man is small, and that the
individuals would do better to avail themselves of the general bank and capital
of nations and of ages,” Burke writes in the Reflections.23 Even when we as
individuals cannot readily perceive the significance of the wisdom inherent in
our cultural capital, the very fact of its having come down to us with the
reverence and regard of previous generations should cause us to take it seriously
as a standard to guide our actions and inquiries, or at least to give it a very
significant benefit of the doubt. In a particularly revealing passage in the Appeal
from the New Whigs to the Old, Burke writes: “If ever we should find ourselves
disposed not to admire those writers or artists, Livy and Virgil for instance,
Raphael or Michael Angelo, whom all the learned had admired, [we ought] not
to follow our own fancies, but to study them until we know how and what we
ought to admire; and if we cannot arrive at this combination of admiration with
knowledge, rather to believe that we are dull, than that the rest of the world has
been imposed on.”24
We should in this sense be open to allowing some questions to be prejudged
for us by the collective wisdom of past generations and to accept—if not quite
blindly, then surely faithfully—the weight and gravity of their combined reason
as greater than our own individual capacity. Those past generations were
engaged in the same pursuits that we pursue—seeking fulfilling lives as
individuals and societies and making the most of their imperfect human nature—
and the fact that they found certain tools especially helpful should mean
something to us.
Burke employs the word prejudice, a loaded term even in his own day, to
describe such received wisdom. A prejudice, he argues, can obviously be a very
bad thing when it is a mere individual bias without evidence or reason. But it can
be a very good thing when it is a habit of opinion or action formed by long social
usage and communicated by tradition. Since no individual can hope to
reconsider every question from scratch, there must be some received opinions,
but the best of these are formed by large communities over time. The
revolutionaries, in seeking to uproot all the prejudices of their countrymen, in
fact just work to replace the product of generations of reasoning with a set of far
lesser prejudices of their own, based on ill-considered premises about human
nature and politics. The friends of the English constitution, Burke contends, act
differently: “Many of our men of speculation, instead of exploding general
prejudices, employ their sagacity to discover the latent wisdom which prevails in
them. If they find what they seek (and they seldom fail), they think it more wise
to continue the prejudice, with the reason involved, than to cast away the coat of
prejudice and to leave nothing but the naked reason; because prejudice, with its
reason, has a motive to give action to that reason, and an affection which will
give it permanence.”25
The misguided explosion of prejudice would leave men unable to act in
politics, Burke worries. Properly aged and developed prejudices, on the other
hand, allow men to act on proven principles without the need to reason to them
from scratch, and support the moral sentiments required for social peace.26
And when such age-old prejudice is not available, other means of drawing on
the wisdom of many must be employed. The absence of clear guidance from the
past is not a reason to rely on the unaided reason of the individual alone or to
look to naked theory for standards. Instead, it is a reason to desire collective
deliberation and collective action in politics. “Political arrangement, as it is a
work for social ends, is to be only wrought by social means. There mind must
conspire with mind,” Burke writes.27 The point of such cooperation is not to
determine the will of the majority, however. Indeed, Burke argues that not will
but precisely reason (in light of its limits, as he understands them) must underlie
political action. His radical opponents, he argues, misguidedly employ an
individualist reason to rationalize their way to the case for politics as the
expression of sheer majority will. “If government were a matter of will upon any
side,” he tells his voters in Bristol, “yours, without question, ought to be
superior. But government and legislation are matters of reason and judgment.”28
His is merely a different and less individualist notion of reason and judgment. “I
have known, and, according to my measure, have cooperated with great men,”
Burke writes of his political career, “and I have never yet seen any plan which
has not been mended by the observations of those who were much inferior in
understanding to the person who took the lead in the business.”29 Politics is not
a matter of individual genius, but is a matter of joint activity directed to common
benefit.
This sense of the limits of individual human reason and the importance of
joint deliberation and action made Burke a forthright champion of political
partisanship—a most unusual view in his time, even more so than in ours.
Parties have long been thought incommensurate with good government, because
they represent particular interests rather than the good of the whole. The
Enlightenment radicals argued that if reason were properly brought to bear on
politics, individuals could—through rational thought, persuasion, and the
application of the proper principles—arrive at the conclusions necessary for
good government. Parties have no role in this process; they would only obscure
the truth. Paine certainly held this view and suggested that party dispute was a
distraction from governing: “I wish with all the devotion of a Christian that the
names of Whig and Tory may never more be mentioned.”30
Burke wholeheartedly disagrees and grounds his case precisely in the views
discussed above: a sense of the limits of reason and theory, and a sense that men
need to work together to be wise and effective. First, he thinks, it is a gross
mistake to imagine that reason could resolve all partisan political disputes,
because these disputes result precisely from the permanent imperfections of
human knowledge and human reason. Participants in politics, he suggests,
pursue their understanding of what is best for the whole, not just for themselves.
But we are not equipped by nature to know the whole or to completely
understand what is best, and the theoretical methods of the Enlightenment
liberals do not in fact overcome this limitation. We can know only parts, and
different people are shaped by their life experiences, moved by study, or perhaps
just persuaded by arguments, to emphasize different parts. For some, the danger
of disorder may be paramount; for others, the injustice of arbitrary power,
respect for the will of God, the traditions of our ancestors, the promise of
progress, or other priorities may be at play. Politics in a free society is a
competition among the “partisans” of these different parts. Statesmen confront
options for action, and what they emphasize about human nature, politics, or the
circumstances of a situation—the parts of human knowledge they possess or
deem most crucial—will shape the choices they make.
Partisans make their case by offering reasons for emphasizing the parts of
human knowledge they deem most important, but these reasons will never be
persuasive to everyone, because different people are shaped differently by their
experiences and circumstances and are thus inclined to emphasize different parts.
Partisanship will therefore never be argued out of existence. We can never know
enough to stand above it, and no party could ever persuade everyone to stand
with it. Each of the different parties has part of the truth, but none has all of it.
For this reason, Burke writes, “we know that parties must ever exist in a free
country.”31 Knowing this does not make the knower a nonpartisan or put him
above the partisan fray. He still has his views and thinks it is his obligation to
participate avidly in the great partisan debates of the day.
The opponents of party, Burke argues, too easily mistake it for faction. But
large political parties in Britain are not private factions. Rather, as he uses the
term, “party is a body of men united for promoting by their joint endeavor the
national interest upon some principle in which they are all agreed.”32
Politics is a negotiation of these principled differences in response to
particular needs and events, and in that process, the participants benefit
immensely from common action both in formulating their views and in putting
them into effect—in both cases because no man’s individual reason and ability
are up to the task. Party politics should not be looked down upon as unseemly,
Burke argues. On the contrary, it is the means by which well-intentioned
politicians join together as honorable compatriots to advance what they see as
the best course for their country. The effort to espouse common views and bring
people who hold them into power is a noble pursuit, “easily distinguished from
the mean and interested struggle for place and emolument.”33 This does not
mean a blind preference for one’s party. The views that drive a statesman to join
with others ought to be what motivate him, and if the party ceases to advance
them, he is right to abandon it. Indeed, for all his championing of partisanship,
Burke himself very publicly broke with his party over the French Revolution, at
great cost to both him and his party.
But as long as one’s views are, in general, shared by co-partisans, and
especially if opposing views are represented by parties of their own, it is
incumbent upon any serious politician to hitch his wagon to a party and to work
in concert with others. “No man,” Burke writes, “who is not inflamed by
vainglory into enthusiasm, can flatter himself that his single, unsupported,
desultory, unsystematic endeavors, are of power to defeat the subtle designs and
united cabals of ambitious citizens. When bad men combine, the good must
associate; else they will fall, one by one, an unpitied sacrifice in a contemptible
struggle. It is not enough, in a situation of trust in the commonwealth, that a man
means well to his country.” A statesman must find the means to turn his good
intentions into effective action, and most of the time, only party politics offers
that means.34 It is not the partisan but rather the politician who claims to put
himself above party who must be suspected of advancing only private
interests.35
But partisanship is not the most significant consequence of the limits of
individual reason for Burke. It offers a means of organizing political activity
given those limits, but it does not itself offer an alternative guide to political
judgment and action. If the premises of Enlightenment liberalism are inadequate,
and if the resulting faith in modern reason is unjustified, what is the alternative
organizing principle of, and the appropriate means for thinking about, political
change? Burke’s answer draws on all that we have seen of his critique of
speculative politics, his emphasis on the given, and his understanding of human
nature. It is prescription—Burke’s great anti-innovationist innovation.
The term prescription originated in Roman property law, where it referred to
ownership by virtue of long-term use, rather than by formal deed. Burke uses the
term to describe the means by which practices and institutions that have long
served society well are given the benefit of the doubt against innovations that
might undermine them and are used as patterns and models for political life. In
this way, reforms and innovations are judged by their conformity to, and
continuity with, existing political forms.
Burke’s case for this novel concept is firmly grounded in his sense of the
limits of individual reason. Generations of statesmen have dealt with the kinds of
challenges the present age must face, and “if we do not take to our aid the
foregone studies of men reputed intelligent and learned, we shall be always
beginners.”36 Humility before the wisdom of the past, however, does not mean
just learning from the arguments that great men of prior generations made in
writing and speech. Their legacy is the nation itself—its institutions, practices,
and forms, all of which are “the result of the thoughts of many minds, in many
ages.”37 Prescription therefore means, above all, respecting and preserving the
political order as it has been handed down and even according it reverence.
Prescription thus begins in a kind of humble gratitude. Because building a
working political arrangement is extremely difficult, we who inherit one such
arrangement should be grateful for it even when we cannot fully understand the
sources of its success. In any effort at reform, Burke writes, “I set out with a
perfect distrust of my own abilities; a total renunciation of every speculation of
my own; and with a profound reverence for the wisdom of our ancestors, who
have left us the inheritance of so happy a constitution and so flourishing an
empire.”38 To approach the constitution as the radicals do, with an eye to
measuring it against a speculative theory and no inherent regard for its
established forms, is to prefer one’s own reason over the collective wisdom of
generations of one’s countrymen.39 The French revolutionaries made precisely
this mistake, Burke argues. Addressing himself to them in the Reflections, he
writes that while the old regime had terrible flaws, it also contained the seeds of
possible improvement:
You began ill, because you began by despising everything that belonged to you. You set up your
trade without a capital. If the last generations of your country appeared without much luster in
your eyes, you might have passed them by, and derived your claims from a more early race of
ancestors. Under a pious predilection for those ancestors, your imaginations would have realized
in them a standard of virtue and wisdom, beyond the vulgar practice of the hour: and you would
have risen with the example to whose imitation you aspired. Respecting your forefathers, you
would have been taught to respect yourselves.40

Burke thus does not argue that the English constitution itself is an ideal
regime for all, but rather that each society ought to draw on the best of its own
tradition in addressing challenges and problems. The French should appreciate
the past successes of their own fathers rather than abandon their ancestors’
accomplishments in favor of a theoretical ideal.
The temptation to do otherwise is great, Burke acknowledges. It is human
nature to lose sight of the value of what we possess and be taken instead with the
potential of what we imagine possible. It is therefore necessary to awaken in the
people an appreciation for what they have and should not take for granted, and
even to build up some pride in resisting reckless innovation.41
Burke thus seeks to describe his fellow Britons as uniquely and admirably
sensible about the dangers of abandoning the achievements of their ancestors.
“Thanks to our sullen resistance to innovation, thanks to the cold sluggishness of
our national character, we still bear the stamp of our forefathers,” he writes.42
“From the Magna Charta to the Declaration of Right, it has been the uniform
policy of our constitution to claim and assert our liberties as an entailed
inheritance derived to us from our forefathers, and to be transmitted to our
posterity; as an estate specially belonging to the people of this kingdom, without
any reference whatever to any other more general or prior right.”43 In a private
letter to the poet Richard Cumberland (who had written to Burke praising the
Reflections but wondering if their countrymen were really worthy of Burke’s
praise), Burke is remarkably up-front about his rhetorical purposes and methods:
“Whether I have described our countrymen properly, time is to show; I hope I
have, but at any rate it is perhaps the best way to persuade them to be right by
supposing that they are so. Great bodies, like great men, must be instructed in
the way in which they will be best pleased to receive instruction; flattery itself
may be converted into a mode of counsel.”44
Such flattery aims to suggest to the English that they already possess the
materials needed to address the many challenges they confront. And this means
they are able not only to stand their ground against ill-conceived innovation but
also to respond effectively to changing circumstances by building on what they
have.
Burke’s foremost fear, particularly in the period of the French Revolution but
also in the incessantly eventful preceding decade and a half, was that in crisis
conditions, the English would be tempted to seek after what he derided as
speculative metaphysical politics. He therefore first of all offers prescription as a
means of resistance. Long before the French Revolution and speaking of the
dangers of British overreaction in the American crisis in 1775, Burke offered this
advice to the House of Commons:
If you apprehend that on a concession you shall be pushed by metaphysical process to the extreme
lines, and argued out of your whole authority, my advice is this; when you have recovered your
old, your strong, your tenable position, then face about—stop short—do nothing more—reason
not at all—oppose the ancient policy and practice of the empire as a rampart against the
speculations of innovators on both sides of the question; and you will stand on great, manly, and
sure ground. On this solid basis fix your machines, and they will draw worlds toward you.45

Long-held assumptions and time-tested prejudices, too, are useful in a crisis.


“Prejudice is of ready application in the emergency; it previously engages the
mind in a steady course of wisdom and virtue, and does not leave the man
hesitating in the moment of decision, skeptical, puzzled, and unresolved.
Prejudice renders a man’s virtue his habit; and not a series of unconnected acts.
Through just prejudice, his duty becomes a part of his nature.”46
But the essence of Burke’s teaching on prescription is not directed to
resistance in a crisis. Rather, prescription is above all a means of controlled and
gradual modification in response to felt public needs—not to oppose all change,
but rather to pursue change carefully, preferring changes to substance over
changes to form where possible, and incremental over radical reform where
necessary.47 Burke was by no means a radical traditionalist opposed to all
reform. Far from it; he was a leading (in some respects the leading) reformer in
Parliament in his time (see Chapter 6). But he believed that successful reform
must begin from existing circumstances, not from theoretical speculations. The
maxim of the English, Burke writes, is “never entirely nor at once to depart from
antiquity.”48 That does not mean no departure may be attempted, but rather
means that departures must be partial and incremental—aimed at improving or
correcting, not beginning anew.
Indeed, Burke argues that change, understood in this way as “a principle of
growth,” is not only permissible but essential, and essential precisely to the task
of preserving the existing order.49 “A state without the means of some change is
without the means of its conservation,” he writes.50 Such a principle of growth
or means of change is intended to be a permanent feature of the regime, not just
a path to an ultimate and correct arrangement that would not change further.
In this sense, Burke’s approach is actually more open to change than that of
many of his radical opponents, including Paine. They were looking to establish
the right permanent principles to guide the work of government. Burke argues
that change is itself a permanent principle, and that while the ends of
government do not change, the means to those ends must be altered as needed,
and these sometimes must include even the details of the form of the
government.
The preservation of the overall political order, which is among Burke’s chief
concerns, requires and must be suited to accommodate constant change and must
ensure that any change is continuous and gradual rather than disruptive and
sudden.51 This precisely is what prescription aims to do: to ground the new in
the old, to make change into extension, and so to provide for continuity and
stability so that problems are addressed while the overall order is not unduly
disturbed. Burke wants political judgments even in extreme situations to be
guided by the pattern of the normal and the usual, not the other way around. He
argues that such an approach, drawing as we have seen on the model of
inheritance, “furnishes a sure principle of conservation and a sure principle of
transmission; without at all excluding a principle of improvement. . . . [I]t leaves
acquisition free; but it secures what it acquires. Whatever advantages are
obtained by a state proceeding on these maxims, are locked fast as in a sort of
family settlement.”52
Burke’s model for such careful gradualism is the legal profession, which he
deeply admires. Lawyers, he says, always seek for precedents and always
present innovations as modest enlargements of precedent. He acknowledges that
these efforts sometimes strain credulity and misrepresent the nature of the
precedent to obscure the degree of genuine innovation in question, but he
actually praises this practice as an indication of the lawyers’ desire to minimize
social disruption—suggesting perhaps that his own efforts include such
obscuring of real disruption.53 Lawyers understand that the authority of the law
depends on its stability and that people build their lives around certain
assumptions that should not be disrupted needlessly. This is all the more true
when the disruption in question is more profound than in most legal cases—
when the form or function of the regime itself is in question. Gradual change that
carefully builds on existing materials allows society to adjust and to employ its
strengths to address its weaknesses.
This reliance on precedent does not mean that Burke believed that all
circumstances had analogies in prior historical events. There were surely
unprecedented political challenges. When confronting the government’s failure
to contain the colonial revolt in America, Burke told his parliamentary
colleagues that Britain’s long history offered nothing like it to consider.54 Of the
European war he saw emerging in the wake of the French Revolution in the last
years of his life he said, “I cannot persuade myself that this war bears any the
least resemblance (other than that it is a war) to any that has ever existed in the
world—I cannot persuade myself that any examples or any reasonings drawn
from other wars and other politics are at all applicable to it—and I truly and
sincerely think that all other wars and all other politics have been the games of
children.”55 But precisely in the face of such unprecedented difficulties and
crises that called for new thinking, Burke believed the nation had to call on the
strength and stability of its ancient constitution, adapted as it had been over
centuries to address a broad variety of challenges. It was valuable not because it
had dealt with crises just like those of his day, but because it had dealt
effectively with a bewildering array of different and novel kinds of problems.
The constitution is valued, after all, not because it is old but because it has
been developing and evolving for a long time and so is well suited to the nation,
its character, and its needs. The constitution is in this sense very up to date and is
adapted and adaptable to real-world circumstances. It is therefore likely to be far
better than any theory at contending with novel circumstances since theory has
high expectations and is very rigid while a long-standing regime is accustomed
to adjusting itself as things change.
The changes and reforms the constitution undergoes, moreover, do not all
point in any one direction, but are responses to events that seek to bring the
system into equilibrium. Sometimes, the appropriate response is to enlarge the
scope of representative institutions, as the theories of the Enlightenment liberals
would suggest should always happen, but at other times, the appropriate
response is to enlarge the prerogative of the monarch or the aristocracy.
As we have seen in Chapter 3, Burke believed that the structure of the
constitution and the regular practices of preceding generations offered the only
available means of reaching for standards of measure beyond utility, and he does
argue that politics should answer to, and be shaped in accord with, these
standards. But these standards are discovered through gradual improvements
tried by the test of time. History, Burke suggests, is not an unfolding, but rather a
process of clarification through experience, and political change is among its
constant features. No particular change sets a single direction for future
development. All are prudential modifications in response to unique
circumstances and demands. “These exceptions and modifications are made not
by the process of logic, but by the rules of prudence,” Burke writes. “Prudence is
not only first in rank of the virtues, political and moral, but she is the director,
the regulator, the standard of them all.”56 The rules of prudence are applied, and
therefore developed, in response to events, not in advance of them, and their
validity is measured by their practical success or failure in keeping the people
safe, happy, and free.
Institutions that have grown in this organic way may not be tidy, but they are
strong and functional, and the attempt to force them into accord with a theory
foreign to their development will not end well. “The old building stands well
enough, though part gothic, part Grecian, and part Chinese, until an attempt is
made to square it into uniformity. Then it may come down upon our heads
altogether, in much uniformity of ruin.”57 Rather than pursue such uniformity,
Burke argues, we ought to see how well the evolved institutions serve the
public’s needs and desires.
This organic approach establishes for Burke a different and more practical
standard not only for policy but also for political principles. “The practical
consequences of any political tenet go a great way in deciding upon its value,”
he writes. “Political problems do not primarily concern truth or falsehood. They
relate to good or evil. What in the result is likely to produce evil, is politically
false: that which is productive of good, politically is true.”58 Thus within the
bounds of the constitution, politics is not a branch of philosophy, in an express
search for truth or its application, but is rather in the business of producing good
practical outcomes, which help point to higher truth but not directly. Burke
makes this point exceptionally explicit several times in his career, perhaps most
notably in reference to the American crisis: “I will not enter into the question of
how much truth is preferable to peace. Perhaps truth may be far better. But as we
have scarcely ever the same certainty in the one that we have in the other, I
would, unless the truth were evident indeed, hold fast to peace.”59
Thus Burke returns to the limits of reason. Our ability to know the practical
consequences of a particular policy far exceeds our ability to ascertain the truth
of a philosophical claim. In politics, therefore, we almost always ought to judge
by effects and not by speculation.
Burke understands that because his alternative to modern reason begins from
a rejection of modern reason, his approach would prove to be exceedingly
vulnerable to attempted applications of such reason. For prescription to serve its
purpose, it must be accepted implicitly, not argued for or about.60 He hopes that
its practical success will protect its roots from undue curiosity. “The bulk of
mankind on their part are not excessively curious concerning any theories whilst
they are really happy,” he writes, “and one sure symptom of an ill-conducted
state is the propensity of the people to resort to them.”61 But Burke also sees
that the Enlightenment radicals want to investigate the regime in their theoretical
terms regardless of its practical success, and he understands the danger this
scrutiny can pose to a prescriptive regime. “It has been the misfortune, not as
these gentlemen think it, the glory, of this age, that every thing is to be
discussed,” he writes, “as if the constitution of our country were to be always a
subject rather of altercation than enjoyment.”62 Once the foundation of the
regime becomes a subject of argument, the implicit fidelity of the people may
well be lost forever.
It is not that no argument could be made in defense of the English
constitution. Far from it, Burke believes. But no argument could achieve the
force of attachment that prescription creates by habit, enjoyment, and untroubled
loyalty. Through legalistic arguments, a statesman can show that his regime is
legitimate, but he cannot make his fellow citizens love the country through such
arguments, or make sacrifices for it in a crisis, and indeed he could easily
undermine such patriotism by making the country a subject of such impudent
investigation.63 A working regime, with roots deep in the past and a history of
incremental development that has suited it well to the needs of its people, should
have the benefit of the doubt, in Burke’s view, and should not be subjected to the
searing light of the Enlightenment philosopher’s misguided investigation, driven
as it is by an exaggerated notion of the power of reason. The radicals and their
schemes must bear the burden of proof, and their ideas should be subjected to
extreme scrutiny. “The arrogance of their pretensions in a manner provokes and
challenges us to an enquiry into their foundation,” Burke writes.64 This is why
Burke goes to such lengths to examine the revolutionary regime and its claims,
methods, actions, and results in the Reflections. While prescriptive regimes
should enjoy some immunity from such prosecution on the basis of their proven
success, novel revolutionary regimes should expect to be scrutinized.
Burke’s case regarding the limits of human reason in politics can easily be
taken as an anti-intellectual case against the use of reason in politics, or the use
of reason at all, and it very often has been. But it is better understood as an
argument about the particular character of the political sphere. Burke clearly
does not deny the value of the contemplative life in its own terms, and indeed at
times he argues that the contemplative virtues are superior to the active ones. In
June 1777, Burke received a letter from William Richardson, a Scottish
professor of the humanities, together with a copy of a book Richardson had
written analyzing the philosophical underpinnings of some of Shakespeare’s
plays. In his letter (which does not survive), Richardson apparently praised with
great humility Burke’s political vocation as superior to his own more speculative
life. Burke in his response vehemently disagreed with the characterization:
“How could you think I could be indifferent to the opinions of a gentleman in
your honorable and happy situation, secluded though you conceive it to be from
the importance of political occupation? . . . The contemplative virtue is in the
order of things above the active; . . . the other, at best, is but a very gross and
concrete body, constantly dependent, frequently defeated, always obstructed.”65
And yet, the superiority of the contemplative virtue does not entitle it to
supplant the active virtue in its proper sphere. Political life, Burke suggests, is
the realm of the active virtue, since politics governs human action and not
human thought. To pretend otherwise and import a speculative theorizing frame
of mind into politics is both to distort the character and purpose of politics and to
exaggerate the nature and the power of reason. Enlightenment liberalism does so
as a result of the premises from which it begins regarding human nature,
individualism, choice, reason, and the given world. Burke’s sullen resistance to
these premises shapes his vehement rejection of the rationalist politics of the
radicals of his day and shapes his innovative alternative: prescription as a mode
of change and preservation.
Burke thus offers his case for prescription as a response to the elevation of
reason at the heart of both Enlightenment thought and Thomas Paine’s political
philosophy. But Paine, almost alone among the Enlightenment liberals and
radicals of his day, not only advances the vision of reason that Burke opposes,
but also responds directly to Burke’s alternative and reaffirms a faith in reason.

PAINE’S RATIONALISM AND THE AGE OF REASON


Thomas Paine viewed reason as a profoundly liberating force that can help man
learn his rights and establish governments equipped to guard and champion
those rights. “There is a morning of reason rising upon man on the subject of
government, that has not appeared before,” Paine writes. “As the barbarism of
the present old governments expires, the moral conditions of nations with respect
to each other will be changed.”66 Paine’s self-declared purpose is to advance the
cause of this rational politics. “It is time that nations should be rational, and not
be governed like animals, for the pleasure of their riders.”67 Making nations
rational was in one way or another his goal in every political exertion.
Paine argues plainly that political principles must precede political
institutions, rather than, as Burke would have it, be derived from them. In Rights
of Man, he asserts that his aim is “to establish a system of principles as a basis
on which governments ought to be erected.”68 And this was his goal not only in
his time in France. In an 1806 letter to John Inskeep, the mayor of Philadelphia,
Paine reflects on his eventful career: “My motive and object in all my political
works, beginning with Common Sense, the first work I ever published, have been
to rescue man from tyranny and false systems and false principles of
government, and enable him to be free and establish government for himself.”69
These false systems and unreasonable principles are central to all of Paine’s
descriptions of the world, especially as the chief causes of war and despotism.
“Man is not the enemy of man, but through the medium of a false system of
Government,” he writes.70 If only regimes were established on the proper
principles, in line with reason, mankind would flourish as never before.
Building on the Enlightenment-liberal view of human nature and the polity,
Paine argues that the crucial premise of Enlightenment thought—the natural
equality of man—inescapably leads to a politics of individualism and individual
reason. If men are equal, then none can simply command the assent of another
and none will accept on faith the superior wisdom of others. The equality of man
dictates that in a legitimate government, everything must be open for discussion
and analysis by all. And this is a great virtue, not, as Burke had argued, a vice of
modern politics. “In the representative system,” Paine writes, “the reason for
everything must publicly appear. Every man is a proprietor in government, and
considers it a necessary part of his business to understand. It concerns his
interest, because it affects his property. He examines the cost, and compares it
with the advantages; and above all, he does not adopt the slavish custom of
following what in other governments are called leaders.”71 Burke’s insistence
that the core of the regime must not be questioned or open to inspection seems to
Paine like a self-interested reaction of those who “are called leaders” against this
new rational politics. They defend their prerogatives by clothing them in fancy
names, and they assert the danger of unaided reason in politics because “they
tremble at the approach of principles, and dread the precedent that threatens their
overthrow.”72
To avert that overthrow, Paine writes, they make government seem far too
subtle and fragile for citizens to approach, “blinding the understanding of man
and making him believe that government is some wonderful mysterious
thing.”73 But understood in the proper, rational terms, government is not a
mystery at all.74 The science of government ought therefore to be a science of
principles, not of single instances, and these principles are accessible to the
reason of every rational individual. The French Revolution, Paine argues, should
be understood in this context. What matters most about it is not that it is a sharp
break from the patterns of the past, but that it is a replacement of wrong with
right principles.
Burke, in Paine’s view, seeks to obscure the question of principle by focusing
instead on historical particularities: on persons and the details of institutions. It is
difficult to discern anything clearly “when circumstances are put for arguments,
which is frequently the case with Mr. Burke,” he writes.75 Burke’s case that
abstract principle is foreign to political life therefore strikes Paine as simply an
excuse to avoid the question of the principles of his beloved English
constitution, which causes Burke in turn to excuse appalling injustice in France
on similar grounds. In Rights of Man Paine writes:
Mr. Burke appears to have no idea of principles, when he is contemplating government. “Ten
years ago,” says he, “I could have felicitated France on her having a government without
enquiring what the nature of that government was, or how it was administered.” Is this the
language of a rational man? Is it the language of a heart feeling as it ought to feel for the rights
and happiness of the human race? On this ground, Mr. Burke must compliment every government
in the world, while the victims who suffer under them, whether sold into slavery, or tortured out of
existence, are wholly forgotten. It is power, and not principles, that Mr. Burke venerates; and
under this abominable depravity, he is disqualified to judge between them.76

Precisely this kind of confusion of persons for principles and power for
reason is behind the defense of hereditary government, Paine argues. “Mr. Burke
does not attend to the distinction between men and principles.”77 Hereditary rule
is “a mere animal system,” with no rational component attached. Its advocates
could never persuade the people to establish such a system were it not already in
place (having gotten there illegitimately long ago).78
And the fact that the system has been there for ages is hardly a case for its
persistence. To argue that long usage transforms an unjust practice into a just one
is absurd, Paine writes, “for either it is putting time in the place of principle, or
making it superior to principle; whereas time has no more connection with, or
influence upon principle than principle has upon time.”79 An institution or
practice must prove itself before the bar of reason. Laws cannot derive authority
from age, but only from “the justness of their principles.”80
Throughout his writing Paine rejects appeals to authority and demands
instead appeals to reason as a standard of judgment. He even prides himself in
his own work on avoiding making points by quotation of familiar and learned
authorities—a practice Burke engages in frequently. “I scarcely ever quote; the
reason is, I always think,” Paine writes.81 Even when others pointed to places in
which his work clearly drew on noted authorities, Paine staunchly resisted the
implication. There is certainly something odd in an obviously learned man’s
insisting he is not conversant with the great writers of his age and of the Western
canon, but for Paine the substantive point is worth more than the biographical
one: Direct reference to original principles is more important than a
demonstrated grasp of precedents. The emphasis on individual and unaided
reason is crucial for the case he seeks to make. He argues that every individual is
capable of employing his own reason to discern the truth or falsehood of a
political question, so that no reliance on the past or on collective reasoning is
required. In this way, again, Paine believes that every individual has the capacity
to begin from scratch, rather than beginning where others have left off.
On the question of reason, as on others we have seen, this assertion of self-
sufficiency starkly divides Burke and Paine. Paine seeks to demonstrate the
capacity of the individual for self-rule by holding every individual separate from
a larger whole—both social and temporal. In order to follow the dictates of
reason, we must put aside all the context and authority of the given world and
pursue the abstract and universal truth directly. And the reason unleashed by the
Enlightenment allows us (and indeed requires us) to do just that. This unaided
modern reason is our means of knowing the truth, and we need not take any
claims to truth on the authority of others.
Reason can take the place of authority even in the realm of religion—indeed
perhaps especially in that realm, which for so long had been the domain of
authority and faith. Paine’s most express and outright claims for the power of
unaided reason appear in his writings on religion and especially his two-volume
case for Enlightenment Deism, titled (not coincidentally) The Age of Reason.
The Age of Reason is in some respects an astonishingly intemperate book and
may therefore unduly distract its readers from Paine’s case for reason. He
launches blistering attacks on all forms of organized Christianity and works his
way through the Bible pointing out inconsistencies and implausibilities. “The
most detestable wickedness, the most horrible cruelties, and the greatest miseries
that have afflicted the human race have had their origin in this thing called
revelation, or revealed religion,” Paine writes.82 It is absurd and insulting to
God himself, he contends regarding the origins of Jesus, “to believe that the
Almighty committed debauchery with a woman engaged to be married.”83
But beyond his attacks on the particular dogmas and consequences of
organized religion, Paine’s final book contains his most extensive and assertive
case for the centrality of individual human reason. His rejection of organized
religion is an elevation of individual reason: “I do not believe in the creed
professed by the Jewish Church, by the Roman Church, by the Greek Church, by
the Turkish Church, by the Protestant Church, nor by any church that I know of.
My own mind is my own church.”84 He rejects any religious authority’s claims
that cannot be independently verified by every rational person. “A thing which
everybody is required to believe requires that proof and evidence of it should be
equal to all, and universal.”85 We simply cannot be expected to take on authority
what we have not seen ourselves, even in the case of revelation. “When it is
revealed to me, I will believe it to be a revelation,” Paine writes, “but it is not,
and cannot be incumbent upon me to believe it to be revelation before.”86
Rather than in books claiming the authority of revelation, human beings ought to
search for God in his creation, which is available to all through their unaided
senses and reasoning faculty:
The creation is the Bible of the deist. He there reads, in the handwriting of the creator himself, the
certainty of His existence and the immutability of His power, and all other Bibles and testaments
are to him forgeries. . . .
. . . We can know God only through His works. We cannot have a conception of any one
attribute but by following some principle that leads to it. We have only a confused idea of His
power, if we have not the means of comprehending something of its immensity. We can have no
idea of His wisdom but by knowing the order and manner in which it acts. The principles of
science lead to this knowledge; for the Creator of man is the Creator of science, and it is through
that medium that man can see God, as it were, face to face.87

Thus modern science, employing modern reason, offers us the path to


authoritative and verifiable truth, even about God. “That which is now called
natural philosophy, embracing the whole circle of science, of which astronomy
occupies the chief place, is the study of the works of God, and of the power and
wisdom of God in His works, and is the true theology.”88
Paine thus argues that the unleashing of reason through science and its
further refinement and employment in the political revolutions of the day would
inevitably unleash new modes of knowing God and his works, too, and so would
inspire a revolution in religion. “Soon after I published the pamphlet Common
Sense in America,” Paine writes, “I saw the exceeding probability that a
revolution in the system of government would be followed by a revolution in the
system of religion.”89 Reason, conceived in Enlightenment terms as an
individual analytical faculty, is the means to knowing the truth. No claim of
authority or seniority has standing to assert itself over reason. If this is true of
people’s knowledge of God and so of morality, it is surely all the more true of
their knowledge of political things. Politics, no less than theology and morals,
must be an application of unaided reason and must be designed and managed to
facilitate its operation.
And indeed, politics as Paine describes it is an exceptionally intellectual
undertaking—almost purely an exercise in reason. Again and again, he
distinguishes a properly functioning regime (by which he means something like
a representative republic) from the despotism of the aristocracy on the grounds
of their differing relations to the exercise of reason:
Those two distinct and opposite forms erect themselves on the two distinct and opposite bases of
Reason and Ignorance. As the exercise of Government requires talents and abilities, and as talents
and abilities cannot have hereditary descent, it is evident that hereditary succession requires a
belief from man to which his reason cannot subscribe, and which can only be established upon his
ignorance; and the more ignorant any country is, the better it is fitted for this species of
Government. On the contrary, Government, in a well-constituted republic, requires no belief from
man beyond what his reason can give. He sees the rationale of the whole system, its origin and its
operation; and as it is best supported when best understood, the human faculties act with boldness,
and acquire, under this form of government, a gigantic manliness.90

Paine actually raises Burke’s own words in defense of this position,


particularly Burke’s assertion in the Reflections on the Revolution in France:
“Government is a contrivance of human wisdom” (see Chapter 4).91 In that
passage, Burke is arguing that political institutions are not works of nature but
creations of man (though he downplays the difference between the two). But
Paine rather deftly employs the reference to suggest that governing is an act of
raw intellect. In Rights of Man, Paine argues: “Admitting that government is a
contrivance of human wisdom, it must necessarily follow, that hereditary
succession, and hereditary rights (as they are called), can make no part of it,
because it is impossible to make wisdom hereditary.”92
This is a crucial part of Paine’s case against monarchy—that since governing
is intellectual work, there is no reason to expect that the ability to govern well
will be hereditary, and in any case no one could possibly be wise enough to be
given as much power and privilege as a king is granted. “For a man to merit a
million sterling a year from a nation, he ought to have a mind capable of
comprehending from an atom to a universe, which, if he had, he would be above
receiving the pay,” Paine writes.93 For this reason, the very fact of monarchy
demonstrates, in Paine’s view, an intentional rejection of a politics of reason.
“Hereditary succession is a burlesque upon monarchy. It puts it in the most
ridiculous light, by presenting it as an office which any child or idiot may fill. . .
. This sort of superstition may last a few years more, but it cannot long resist the
awakened reason and interest of man.”94 In a society that properly understands
the fully rational character of politics, no such practice could make sense.
Such a politics of rational assessment, of course, relies on the premise that if
reason is allowed free rein, the right choices will be made. Paine’s republicanism
rests on the view that reason is well (though not equally) distributed across
society, and if left to its own devices, it will move the majority to both elect to
power those with the greatest mental gifts and make the correct kinds of choices
directly. “It is always the interest of a far greater number of people in a nation to
have things right, than to let them remain wrong; and when public matters are
open to debate, and the public judgment free, it will not decide wrong, unless it
decides too hastily.”95
Paine therefore flatly disagrees with Burke’s view that political judgment
requires more wisdom than the unaided reason can muster and that therefore
long-standing and successful prejudices should be given some weight: “No man
is prejudiced in favor of a thing, knowing it to be wrong. He is attached to it on
the belief of its being right; and when he sees it is not so, the prejudice will be
gone.”96
Long-standing use provides no exemption. “The question is not whether
those principles are new or old, but whether they are right or wrong.”97 And a
refusal to directly confront that question leads society to accept many wrongs
and persist in much injustice—and especially in needless wars. In the emerging
age of reason, “the objects for war are exceedingly diminished, and there is now
left scarcely anything to quarrel about, but what arises from that demon of
society, prejudice, and the consequent sullenness and untractableness of the
temper,” Paine writes in 1782.98
One crucial reason why society cannot easily overcome that demon of
prejudice, Paine argues, is precisely the reliance on precedent that Burke values
so highly. “Government by precedent, without any regard to the principle of the
precedent, is one of the vilest systems that can be set up,” Paine writes.
By associating those precedents with a superstitious reverence for ancient things, as monks show
relics and call them holy, the generality of mankind are deceived into the design. Governments
now act as if they were afraid to awaken a single reflection in man. They are softly leading him to
the sepulcher of precedents, to deaden his faculties and call attention from the scene of
revolutions. They feel that he is arriving at knowledge faster than they wish, and their policy of
precedents is the barometer of their fears.99

Moreover, because the oldest precedents are valued most highly, the doctrine
of precedents suggests that human history is a decline, “that wisdom degenerates
in governments as governments increase in age, and can only hobble along by
the stilts and crutches of precedents.”100 Paine thus rejects the view at the core
of Burke’s doctrine of prescription: that practices that have passed the test of
time deserve respect and have gradually evolved to best meet the needs of the
present. In fact, he argues, the practices of the past were not built upon reasoned
knowledge and so do not provide a model of politics. Paine even objects to the
employment of precedent not only in political life but also in the law courts.101
And for the same reasons, he thinks the wisdom of many has no special
standing over that of one—all must pass the same test of reason, as employed by
every individual. Paine thus flatly rejects the idea that party politics allows for
many minds to work together and that the limits of reason mean that parties are
inevitable in a free society, as different people emphasize different parts of the
truth in different ways. For Paine, the truth is knowable by reason and should be
persuasive to all, and therefore parties in politics can only be factions in search
of private ends over the public good. His ideal of a republican legislature “was
always founded on a hope that whatever personal parties there might be in the
state, they would all unite and agree in the general principles of good
government—that these party differences would be dropped at the threshold of
the statehouse, and that the public good, or the good of the whole, would be the
governing principle of the legislature within it.”102 A politics freed from
prejudice and enlightened by reason need not be a politics of partisanship. Just as
Burke’s case for party emerges from his understanding of human nature and the
limits of reason, so Paine’s case against it is grounded in his own understanding
of human nature and of the power of reason.
Similarly, Paine dismisses the notion that each nation should follow the
patterns of its own history and that no universal principles of political form or
function can speak to all. Such a view, he argues, begins by assuming that
politics has nothing to do with reason and knowledge and so does not answer to
principles of any kind but only to contingent experience. If there is a case for
monarchy, for instance, surely one group of Englishmen in Britain should be
able to explain it to another in America, even if they live in different
circumstances. “If there is anything in monarchy which we people of America
do not understand, I wish Mr. Burke would be so kind as to inform us,” Paine
writes.103 But in fact the opposite is the case:
I see in America a government extending over a country ten times as large as England, and
conducted with regularity, for a fortieth part of the expense which Government costs in England.
If I ask a man in America if he wants a King, he retorts, and asks me if I take him for an idiot?
How is it that this difference happens? Are we more or less wise than others? I see in America the
generality of people living in a style of plenty unknown in monarchical countries; and I see that
the principle of its government, which is that of the equal Rights of Man, is making a rapid
progress in the world.104

Surely if it is good for America, it will be good for others, too, because it is
verifiably grounded in accessible arguments.
For all these reasons, Paine believes that Burke’s concerns about the danger
of uprooting long-standing prejudices and practices are misplaced and that his
politics (based as it is on the limits of reason) is misguided. It is not at all a
misfortune that everything is to be discussed, Paine argues. Discussing
everything openly is the means of rationalizing politics and, by so doing, the
way to properly define, guide, and implement political change. Once basic
principles like the equality of man and the necessity of consent are laid out, the
kinds of gross injustice evident in so many of the regimes of the world become
untenable. “It is impossible that such governments as have hitherto existed in the
world, could have commenced by any other means than a total violation of every
principle sacred and moral,” Paine writes.105 He argues against Burke’s
assertion that these governments do most things well and we should therefore
not focus on the few things they fail to do. The truth is the opposite, Paine says:
These governments’ most basic forms are wrong, and the few things that do
work are merely exceptions that prove the rule.106
A legitimate and working government, therefore, will combine the proper
principles with their attendant forms. In this sense, politics really does answer to
abstract principles for Paine, but it does so out of the conviction that the right
principles are inescapable prerequisites for the right practices, and that once
reason and proper principles are unleashed in political life, a course is
irrevocably set that will lead to a fairer and more effective government. The
revolution Paine has in mind is thus primarily one of knowledge, enabled by
reason, and those who oppose it are essentially agents of willful ignorance. Paine
writes: “The Revolutions of America and France have thrown a beam of light
over the world, which reaches into man. The enormous expense of governments
has provoked people to think, by making them feel; and when once the veil
begins to rend, it admits not of repair. Ignorance is of a peculiar nature: once
dispelled, it is impossible to re-establish it. . . . Mr. Burke is laboring in vain to
stop the progress of knowledge.”107
A government founded on such advances in knowledge therefore argues for
itself in rational terms in its very forms and functions. It makes its case explicitly
so that every citizen can consider the case, and it wears its principles on its
sleeve. This means, for one thing, that the government must explicitly present its
principles and forms to the world through a written constitution. Such a
document, Paine argues, must give expression to the proper origin of
government in a contract among the people and is in effect the actual legal form
of that contract. Such a constitution thus embodies what is known by reason
about the origins of government and the nature of man, and it speaks in plain
terms to the reason of every reasonable person, so that no one can question its
legitimacy. What Burke calls the English constitution—which is not a document
but the actual forms and structures of the English government—is to Paine not a
constitution at all, but just the accumulated practices of an essentially unjust
regime.
Their definitions of a constitution embody Burke’s and Paine’s views on
reason and political change. For Burke the constitution is the product of
prescription, and its defense is the aim of prescription. Paine believes that the
constitution is the product of explicit reasoning on abstract principles and is
defended by reasoned argument. Burke’s constitution is a regime, if not a nation.
Paine’s constitution is a legal document. A constitution, Paine writes, “is not a
thing in name only, but in fact. It has not an ideal, but a real existence; and
wherever it cannot be produced in a visible form, there is none. Can, then, Mr.
Burke produce the English Constitution? If he cannot, we may fairly conclude
that though it has been so much talked about, no such thing as a constitution
exists, or ever did exist, and consequently that the people have yet a constitution
to form.”108
Such a straightforward constitution, which in plain black-and-white
describes the government in rational terms and in its entirety, also greatly
simplifies the function of government and avoids the enormous and needless
complexity and inefficiency of the English system, with its countless vestigial
limbs retained out of pure inertia and unwillingness to change. This complexity
is itself a mark of the unreasonable character of the British regime.
Rationalization translates to simplification. “I draw my idea of the form of
government from a principle in nature, which no art can overturn, viz. that the
more simple any thing is, the less liable it is to be disordered; and the easier
repaired when disordered,” Paine writes in Common Sense.109
This point again stands in for Paine’s larger disagreement with Burke about
the relation of political life to reason and science, as understood by the
Enlightenment philosophers. Burke explicitly rejects the notion that simplicity in
government is a virtue. Complicated institutions built up over time are far more
likely to work well because they have developed to balance competing pressures
and ambitions against one another. Human beings are not simple, and their
governments cannot be, either. “When I hear the simplicity of contrivance aimed
at and boasted of in any new political constitutions, I am at no loss to decide that
the artificers are grossly ignorant of their trade, or totally negligent of their duty.
The simple governments are fundamentally defective, to say no worse of them,”
Burke writes.110
But to practice politics by balancing countervailing excesses, Paine says,
“amounts to an accusation upon Providence, as if she had left to man no other
choice with respect to government than between two evils.”111 Since he does
not believe that is the case, he rejects the kind of checks-and-balances approach
to institutional design that characterizes even most liberal political philosophers
and argues that mixed government is unacceptable. Paine is in this respect a true
Enlightenment radical, more like the French Revolutionaries than the American.
Burke’s various defenses of the aristocracy and the prerogatives of the king
always defend the whole mixed regime—the king, the nobles, and the common
people balancing each other’s interests to achieve a stable political life. “I hold
[the Lords] to be of absolute necessity in the constitution, but I think they are
only good when kept within their proper bounds,” Burke writes.112 This, as he
explains it, is why he defended Parliament against royal power grabs in the
1760s but then become a staunch defender of the royal prerogative against the
advocates of republicanism in the 1780s.113
But Paine believes that such instability and irregularity result from a failure
to apply the proper principles to government. A mixed regime is a jumbled mess
and falls short of legitimacy to the extent it falls short of true republicanism.114
For similar reasons, Paine does not generally advocate checks and balances
within a republican regime. He does not argue that a very specific arrangement
of the representative system is a necessary function of republican principles; it is
a matter of preference as long as the representative principle is adhered to.115
But Paine’s own preference is for simplicity and minimalism in institutional
design.
In Common Sense, he offers an idea of what he believes should be the shape
of American self-government after the British are expelled. He calls for annually
elected unicameral state assemblies with no state executives (or governors). The
assemblies are to be empowered over all domestic questions but subject to the
authority of the Continental Congress in foreign affairs. At the federal level, he
wants the different states divided into equal districts that would each send a large
number (perhaps thirty each) of representatives to the national congress, which
would also be a unicameral body. All votes in the congress should require a
three-fifths majority; the congress would choose its president by drawing the
states by lot, and each state in turn would have its chance to preside. Little to no
discord could arise in such a structure, Paine suggests, as it would best represent
the true will of the people while allowing for the rational assessment of political
problems.116 The structure is aimed at facilitating rational decision making and
ignores almost entirely the role of ambition, interest, and passion in human
affairs—all of which Paine takes to be avoidable by a proper attention to the
correct principles of government.
Paine’s rejection of bicameralism (which he modified a little in the 1790s but
never rejected during his career) is particularly telling in this regard. In Rights of
Man, he argues that “two houses arbitrarily checking or controlling each other is
inconsistent; because it cannot be proved on the principles of just representation,
that either should be wiser or better than the other.”117 These words were
published in 1792 and probably written in late 1791, well after the adoption of
the U.S. Constitution, which, of course, involved a very different institutional
structure. Though Paine never says so explicitly, his constitutional writings of
the 1790s strongly suggest he had serious principled objections to the design of
the American constitutional system, with its complicated efforts to corral
ambition and channel envy and the hunger for power through counteracting
institutions.
For Paine, simplicity in government is the appropriate expression of the
simple and accessible truths that underlie it. Thus, he not only opposes intricate
designs in the constitution but also rejects the kind of pomp and circumstance
that often attaches to the power of the state. While Burke argues that elevating
the institutions and great persons of the state “with majesty and sober pomp”
helps form the crucial sentimental attachments and ennoble the whole enterprise
of politics, Paine calls it all a means to disguise the fundamental injustice and
unreasonableness of the regime. He seeks to desentimentalize politics. The
haughty pretensions of the aristocracy are ridiculous, he says. “Titles are but
nicknames, and every nickname is a title.”118 And the self-importance of the
monarchy is ludicrous: “I compare it to something kept behind a curtain, about
which there is a great deal of bustle and fuss, and a wonderful air of seeming
solemnity; but when, by any accident, the curtain happens to be open and the
company see what it is, they burst into laughter.”119
Burke does not disagree with the notion that exposing the monarchy to
ridicule would weaken it, but for him this is precisely the reason for treating it
solemnly—the seeming solemnity is truer and more valuable to human nature
than the laughter. But Paine rejects this as an insult to human nature. “As to Mr.
Burke,” he writes, “he is a stickler for monarchy. . . . He has taken up a
contemptible opinion of mankind, who, in their turn, are taking up the same of
him. He considers them as a herd of beings that must be governed by fraud,
effigy, and show; and an idol would be as good a figure of monarchy with him,
as a man.”120 The revolutionaries express their higher views of man by putting
aside these demeaning displays. “The patriots of France have discovered in good
time that rank and dignity in society must take a new ground. The old one has
fallen through. It must now take the substantial ground of character, instead of
the chimerical ground of titles; and they have brought their titles to the altar, and
made of them a burnt-offering to Reason,” Paine writes.121
If all the pretensions and chimeras of the aristocracy were dropped, and if the
political principles laid bare by reason were allowed to govern, Paine believed
that the concerns to which Burke’s correctives were directed would prove
unfounded. A politics of reason, Paine argues, will largely resolve what may
appear to be inherent tensions in human nature. Mistaken principles of
government and the regimes built on them were the essential causes of human
problems like poverty and war. If reason were unleashed, it would first
demonstrate to the people that the principles are false and so the systems are
illegitimate. “I do not believe that monarchy and aristocracy will continue seven
years longer in any of the enlightened countries in Europe,” Paine wrote in 1792.
“If better reasons can be shown for them than against them, they will stand; if
the contrary, they will not.”122 And once the reasons have been arrayed and the
old governments brought down, new regimes better founded in reason will
resolve what have always seemed intractable problems. The existence of
desperate poverty in many countries, Paine writes, “lies not in any natural defect
in the principles of civilization, but in preventing those principles having a
universal operation; the consequence of which is, a perpetual system of war and
expense, that drains the country, and defeats the general felicity of which
civilization is capable.”123 He later argues:
If men will permit themselves to think as rational beings ought to think, nothing can appear more
ridiculous and absurd, exclusive of all moral reflections, than to be at the expense of building
navies, filling them with men, and then hauling them into the ocean, to try which can sink each
other fastest. Peace, which costs nothing, is attended with infinitely more advantage, than any
victory with all its expense. But this, though it best answers the purpose of nations, does not that
of court governments, whose habited policy is pretence for taxation, places, and offices. . . . When
all the governments of Europe shall be established on the representative system, nations will
become acquainted, and the animosities and prejudices fomented by the intrigue and artifice of
courts, will cease. The oppressed soldier will become a freeman; and the tortured sailor, no longer
dragged through the streets like a felon, will pursue his mercantile voyage in safety.124

Paine believed fervently that war was grounded in the consequences of error
and of intentional denial of the truth. In an age of reason, war will become a
thing of the past. Once the proper political principles are put into effect, there
will remain only questions of opinion and preference. These questions will range
from the more minor details of the institutions of the regime (the more major
ones being in fact questions of principle) to other, less significant momentary
questions of policy and will. They may not be answered by direct recourse to
abstract principle, but in a system designed in line with such principles, these
questions of opinion will be resolved very efficiently by rational democratic
deliberation and swift trial and error. No error will continue long, Paine
writes.125
“It will sometimes happen that the minority are right and the majority are
wrong,” Paine writes, “but as soon as experience proves this to be the case, the
minority will increase to a majority, and the error will reform itself by the
tranquil operation of freedom of opinion and equality of rights.”126 As long as
the broad structure and principle of the regime is properly established and reason
is free to reign, the people will choose well.
Paine realizes, of course, that no system will be perfect. He acknowledges,
too, that changing circumstances will require changes in the law, even when the
government is founded on the right principles. He approves of the provisions in
the U.S. and French constitutions allowing for amendment on these grounds.
Though he believes that reasoned principles should shape the regime, the subject
to which that reason is applied changes with time, so the laws must too. “It is
perhaps impossible to establish anything that combines principles with opinions
and practice, which the progress of circumstances, through a length of years, will
not in some measure derange, or render inconsistent,” Paine writes.127 But these
deficiencies will be modest and will be quickly noticed and corrected, provided
that the overall system of government is established on the principles of equality
and representation and that the people are left free to employ their reason to
political problems without deception or oppression. When prejudice and habit
are replaced with rational examination and the application of principle in
politics, the age of reason, though not a perfectly untroubled paradise, will enjoy
peace, prosperity, and progress.
Indeed, the progressive character of the transformation Paine envisions is
crucial to his larger case. He believes that the Enlightenment project will unleash
human reason long kept in chains. It will unseat the institutions and practices
that have caused the most profound human problems and replace them with
institutions and practices that will further empower reason over human affairs.
Moreover, Paine believes that once empowered, human reason will allow for a
continuing series of good judgments and choices. These positive developments,
Paine believes, represent the outset of a great forward motion in history—a
future that will get better and better as improvements build on one another.
This view informs Paine’s openness to the possibility of improvement in
political institutions, even over those he himself proposes. “The best constitution
that could now be devised, consistent with the condition of the present moment,
may be far short of that excellence which a few years may afford,” he writes.
The age of reason is only dawning.128 And because knowledge once learned
cannot be unlearned, this type of political transformation will not be reversed,
but will advance with time. Guided by reason, the new free republican
institutions will champion the cause of rights, justice, commerce, science, and
knowledge, and these will each build upon the others. It is truly an
unprecedented time. Rather than look back for guidance, Paine argues we must
look to reason and, with its help, move forward.
Paine rejects Burke’s charge that because he, Paine, always looks forward,
his cause will always lack for concrete proof of its effectiveness. Paine, too,
wants to prove his political philosophy by its effects, not just by speculation:
“When it shall be said in any country in the world, my poor are happy; neither
ignorance nor distress is to be found among them; my jails are empty of
prisoners, my streets of beggars; the aged are not in want, the taxes are not
oppressive; the rational world is my friend, because I am the friend of its
happiness: when these things can be said, then may that country boast its
constitution and its government.”129 His claim to be able to bring about such
effects must be largely prospective, since he champions an untried innovation,
while Burke speaks for a long-established constitution. Paine therefore seeks to
prove by reason that what he advocates will bring about a progressive
transformation of social life. But in the debate over the French Revolution, when
Paine’s heralding of reason was at its height, he did also point to a crucial and
prominent practical success of his principles: He pointed to America.
Both during and after the American Revolution, Paine understood and
explained the revolution in terms of universal principles and the march of reason
and rights. It therefore served for him as the first example of an enactment of his
kind of Enlightenment vision of politics and as the model for what he hoped
might happen in France and beyond. And yet for Burke, the same American
crisis offered a case study in a nearly opposite view of human reason and its
place in public affairs.

THE MEANING OF AMERICA


Burke and Paine were in effect on the same side of the American question, the
side (eventually) of independence for the colonies. But, as becomes most clear in
light of their differences about reason in politics, they were moved by starkly
opposed analyses of the events in question and their significance.
“The independence of America, considered merely as a separation from
England, would have been a matter of but little importance, had it not been
accompanied by a revolution in the principles and practice of governments,”
Paine asserted a decade after the American Revolution in Rights of Man. “She
made a stand, not for herself only, but for the world, and looked beyond the
advantages herself could receive.”130 For Paine, from his very earliest public
writings about America until the very end of his life, the American story was a
story of the vindication of Enlightenment reason and the principles it helps to
uncover. As we have seen, he began his call for American independence in
Common Sense with a case for Enlightenment-liberal equality and liberty, and
Paine was always keen to make clear that the essence of the cause was a matter
of principle, not mere practical exigency. “The cause of America is, in the
greatest measure, the cause of all mankind,” he declares.131
When in 1782 the Abbé Raynal, a French priest and scholar, wrote a short
book on the (still ongoing) American Revolutionary War, accusing the
Americans of revolting over nothing greater than a petty tax complaint, Paine
responded with a heated public letter to the abbot, asserting the essentially
principled character of the struggle. The American Revolution, he argued, was
an utterly novel political act, unlike any seen before in history: “Here the value
and quality of liberty, the nature of government, and the dignity of man were
known and understood, and the attachment of the Americans to these principles
produced the Revolution as a natural and unavoidable consequence. They had no
particular family to set up or pull down. Nothing of personality was incorporated
with their cause.” At issue instead was the vindication of reason and
principle.132 “The true idea of a great nation is that which extends and promotes
the principles of universal society,” Paine writes.
What the Americans had begun, far from a mere petty squabble among
Englishmen, would “be distinguished by opening a new system of extended
civilization.”133 By their claim to authority over the colonies without the
extension of voting rights and other protections, the English had opened the
question of rational liberty, and the people of America were uniquely well suited
to understand the question and its proper answer and to act on that
understanding. Once independent, they would establish a model of
republicanism that undoubtedly would attract the attention and the emulation of
others and would demonstrate that the principles of enlightenment rationalism
could offer solid foundations for a thriving political community.
Over the subsequent two decades, as (albeit not without obstacles and
hiccups) the American experiment did indeed appear to have been well
launched, Paine resorted constantly to the model of America as an example of
the potential of his revolutionary principles. The Americans succeeded not for
reasons specific or local to them—on the contrary, circumstances were much
arrayed against them. They succeeded because they had employed the proper
principles for founding a new regime. In 1792 Paine put it this way:
If there is a country in the world where concord, according to common calculation, would be least
expected, it is America. Made up as it is of people from different nations, accustomed to different
forms and habits of government, speaking different languages, and more different in their modes
of worship, it would appear that the union of such a people was impracticable; but by the simple
operation of constructing government on the principles of society and the rights of man, every
difficulty retires, and all the parts are brought into cordial unison. There the poor are not
oppressed, the rich are not privileged. Industry is not mortified by the splendid extravagance of a
court rioting at its expense. Their taxes are few, because their government is just: and as there is
nothing to render them wretched, there is nothing to engender riots and tumults.134

America is the very thing that Burke insists is lacking in Paine’s argument:
concrete proof in the life of a real community that Paine’s principles of
government can work in practice. This evidence allows him to turn the tables
and accuse Burke of ignoring actual circumstances in favor of abstract worries.
With characteristic flourish, Paine argues in Rights of Man that “a metaphysical
man, like Mr. Burke, would have tortured his invention to discover how [the
Americans] could be governed. He would have supposed that some must be
managed by fraud, others by force, and all by some contrivance; that genius
must be hired to impose upon ignorance, and show and parade to fascinate the
vulgar.”135 Instead of all this sound and fury, Paine argues, the Americans chose
the simplicity of reason and Enlightenment liberal principles and have shown by
their success that nothing more is needed and that other regimes, founded on
other principles, are needlessly oppressive and unjust. “One of the great
advantages of the American Revolution has been that it led to a discovery of the
principles, and laid open the imposition, of governments. All the revolutions till
then had been worked within the atmosphere of a court, and never on the great
floor of a nation.” The American Revolution was a practical experiment in the
new science of government and one that proved the efficacy of its principles and
its understanding of human reason in politics.136
But Edmund Burke drew more or less the opposite lesson from the story of
American independence. He was deeply involved in the British debate over
America and was quite possibly the most prominent and vocal of the friends of
America in Parliament. But Burke never attributes a philosophical character to
the views and actions of the Americans. Not once in his public or known private
writings on the subject does he refer to the events in America as a revolution,
referring always to the American crisis, the American war, or even describing
the events as a civil war. In his view, it was the English, not the Americans, who
had broken with prescription in the name of merely speculative theoretical
claims about government by imposing an unprecedented regime of taxation and
limits on commerce in America on the premise that Parliament had an unlimited
authority to govern colonial affairs directly.
The Americans, in his view, merely sought to continue and preserve the
traditions of the English constitution and the privileges they had always enjoyed.
Burke does worry that the example of the Americans so ably pursuing their
independence and seemingly suffering so little for it might move others around
the world to attempt it, but he does not attribute the appeal of their example to
any philosophical underpinnings of their cause, and he blames only the British
for provoking it.137 The Americans were defending their long-standing implicit
rights and the nature of their past relationship with London—they wanted
continuity, and Parliament would not allow it. Burke in effect reads the second
half of the Declaration of Independence (a document he surely knew but
scrupulously avoids mentioning) and not the first, while Paine does the opposite.
In fact, Burke’s case against the actions of the British government involved
some of his clearest and most adamant defenses of prescription against abstract
reason, all directed against the English, not the Americans. The move to tax the
colonies for revenue rather than merely to control Britain’s international trade
(that is, the move from customs and tariffs to internal taxation of consumption)
was utterly unprecedented, and it was this novelty, not the cost of the tax, that
alarmed the Americans and moved them to resist, he argued. “Whatever the right
might have been, this mode of using it was absolutely new in policy and
practice.”138
The move was defended by Lord North’s administration on the grounds that
Parliament has every right to tax the colonies in any way it wished. The
principles of sovereignty and the charters of the colonies permitted it. Burke
never denied this point; he only argued that politics must take account of more
than abstract principles. “The question with me is not whether you have a right
to render your people miserable,” Burke told the Parliament, “but whether it is
not in your interest to make them happy. It is not what a lawyer tells me I may
do; but what humanity, reason, and justice tell me I ought to do.”139 The
Americans had lived for many years essentially as Englishmen, with the
apparatus of self-rule and a developed sense of independence. When Parliament
decided, without involving them in consultation, to alter the scheme of their
taxation, it rudely reminded them of the limits of their independence, in what
amounted to a needless provocation. “People must be governed in a manner
agreeable to their temper and disposition,” Burke writes, “and men of free
character and spirit must be ruled with at least some condescension to this spirit
and this character.”140 Rather than break so harshly with the grain of American
sentiments, Parliament could instead have increased the levies on trade and
thereby improved its revenue without disturbing the Americans. Burke insisted
they would have stood for it, because they were used to it. “Men do bear the
inevitable constitution of their original nature with all its infirmities,” he argued.
“The act of navigation [of 1660] attended the colonies from their infancy, grew
with their growth, and strengthened with their strength. They were confirmed in
obedience to it even more by usage than by law.”141
Being right in principle was no excuse for being wrong in practice, and
Burke warned Parliament that forgetting this truth would carry heavy costs,
because it would move the Americans to question their entire relationship with
London. Precisely because he did not believe the Americans were making a case
against prescription or raising genuine threats to the regime (as he believed did
occur in France in the following decade), Burke thought it terribly unwise for the
English to break with the patterns of their past practices.142
Again and again in 1775 and early 1776, Burke implored the Commons to
pay attention to “the true nature and the peculiar circumstances” of the conflict,
because, he argued, “whether we will or not, we must govern America according
to that nature, and to those circumstances; and not according to our own
imaginations; not according to abstract ideas of right; by no means according to
mere general theories of government, the resort to which appears to me, in our
present situation, no better than arrant trifling.”143 In time, this line of argument
caused Burke to conclude that the Americans should be allowed to go their
separate way, as Parliament had pushed too hard against the grain of the
American character and the English constitution, and left no hope of
reconciliation. Human affections, he argued on this front as on others, were the
key to any functional society, and once disaffection takes hold, social and
political bonds have little hope of surviving.
Burke said and wrote remarkably little about America after the end of the
war in 1783. Unlike Paine, he did not resort to the American crisis for an
example in later political struggles. His only extended reference to it was in a
passage of the Appeal from the New to the Old Whigs in 1791. In this discussion,
he essentially restates his case against the government’s policy in the American
crisis and his belief (affirmed, he says, by conversations with Benjamin Franklin
in London) that the Americans did not want independence or pursue affirmation
of philosophical principles, but rather reacted understandably to an unwise
provocation. The Americans stood at that time “in the same relation to England
as England did to King James the Second in 1688,” Burke writes.144
For both Burke and Paine, the American crisis served as proof of their very
different understandings of reason and political change. Paine’s case for
American independence is a case for a politics of Enlightenment reason and
rational principle. Burke’s case for American independence is a case for
prudence and prescription. In championing opposing sides of the question of the
French Revolution a decade later, each man made almost exactly the same case
he had argued about America. Their agreement over America reflected quite
different understandings of events there, while their disagreement over France
reflected a general agreement over what the French revolutionaries were up to.
In both cases, Burke and Paine disagreed profoundly about human nature,
political change, and the proper relation of reason and politics.

DEBATING REASON
Throughout his public and private writings on a range of political subjects over
several decades, Thomas Paine offers an extensive and determined case for the
supremacy of unaided, individual human reason as understood by Enlightenment
liberalism over habit and tradition. With this assertion comes the need to subject
every political institution, practice, question, and ideal to the rational inspection
of every individual. Because society and politics answer to rational and universal
principles, they must be answerable to the reason of one and all, he argues.
Throughout his own many political writings, speeches, and letters in the
same period, Edmund Burke offers vigorous objections to this mode of thinking
about politics. These objections are grounded in his very different view of
human nature, political life, and the limits of reason. Burke offers a case for
political action guided by prescription and aimed at gradual change in response
to particular felt needs. This approach to politics makes up for limited
knowledge and the permanent limits of reason through a reliance on past
precedents and an aggregation of individual views in (inevitably partisan)
politics.
This dispute between universal principles and historical precedents—
between a politics of explicit knowledge and a politics of implicit knowledge—
cuts to the core of the debate that still defines our politics. To this day,
progressive voices argue that our political system must empower expertise to
directly address social and political problems with technical prowess. And
today’s conservatives argue that we must empower institutions (like families,
churches, and markets) that channel the implicit knowledge of many individuals
and generations and that have passed some test of time and contain in their very
forms more wisdom than any person could possess. This dispute, which Burke
and Paine made so explicit, is another version of the disagreement about whether
political thought must consider abstract, solitary, rational individuals or must
take up particular human societies in their social and historical settings. The
question forms a unifying thread throughout the Burke-Paine debate. As they
argue about reason, Burke and Paine disagree about the given past and its
relation to the present—about whether the circumstances that greet us when we
enter the world can legitimately make demands on the way we think about
politics.
These disagreements combine into a deep difference over the nature of
political change and improvement. Their differing assessments of the nature of
events in America masks this dispute somewhat, but as the age of revolutions
approached its climax in France, Burke’s and Paine’s differences rose swiftly to
the surface and shaped a heated public debate between them. The disagreement
over reason and prescription is at its core an argument about the theoretical or
conceptual foundations of politics. But Burke’s and Paine’s two positions have
very practical consequences when applied to political change. From reason and
prescription, and from the views of human nature and society on which they
draw, Paine and Burke arrive at the arguments for which they are best known:
the arguments for revolution and reform.
SIX

REVOLUTION AND REFORM

BURKE AND PAINE WERE KEENLY AWARE THAT POLITICAL ideas


pointed to political action. Both men were writers and thinkers, but both were
also deeply involved in political affairs at a time when the links between ideas
and action were unusually clear. Their political ideas therefore point toward two
views of political action and change—with Burke drawing on his vision of
prescription to make the case for slow, incremental reform and Paine building on
his case for a rational politics to argue that only a wholly new beginning from
first principles can redeem an illegitimate government.
These views were evident in Burke’s and Paine’s writings from their earliest
political engagements and follow plainly, as we have seen, from their reflections
on society and man. But they came to the fore most forcefully in the period of
the French Revolution, when the question of just how the means and the ends of
political change were related became suddenly urgent and prominent. Burke and
Paine were better prepared than most of their contemporaries to take up these
questions, and the passion and intensity with which they did so have ever since
defined their legacies.

PAINE’S REVOLUTION FOR JUSTICE


Thomas Paine was a self-declared and unabashed revolutionary. “To have a
share in two revolutions is living to some purpose,” he proudly wrote to George
Washington.1 That purpose, from Paine’s earliest political exploits to the end of
his life, was the cause of justice, pursued by an application of reason and
principle to government. And as we have seen, Paine believed that such an
application must begin from the beginning, so that a profoundly corrupt or
broken regime needs to be replaced rather than mended.
Again and again, he expresses disgust with the excuses illegitimate
governments make for their mistreatment of their people in an effort to hold on
to power. “As time obliterated the history of their beginning,” he writes of the
despots who founded every old nation, “their successors assumed new
appearances, to cut off the entail of their disgrace, but their principles and
objects remained the same.”2 It is simply not possible to fix discrete problems in
regimes of this sort, because the principle of despotism has soaked through into
every corner and crevice. “When despotism has established itself for ages in a
country, as in France,” Paine writes, “the original hereditary despotism resident
in the person of the king divides and sub-divides itself into a thousand shapes
and forms, till at last the whole of it is acted by deputation.”3
Nothing short of a total remedy can address such a profound corruption of
government. To speak of revolution, therefore, is for Paine to speak of
overthrow, of the lifting up of the burden of generations of misrule and iniquity,
leaving only the society itself, essentially in its natural state.
Paine was under no illusion that such a general revolution would be easy; nor
did he take lightly the risks and problems it entailed. “Mischief is more easily
begun than ended,” he writes, and revolutions will always carry behind them a
train of mischief.4 He insists therefore that he is not enamored of revolutions for
their own sake. As a general matter, he writes, “it is better to obey a bad law,
making use at the same time of every argument to show its errors and procure its
repeal, than forcibly to violate it.”5 Only when the regime is so fundamentally
corrupt as to make the very idea of a good law impossible is more extreme
action required. Paine is careful to emphasize this caveat because he wants to be
perfectly clear that a government established on the proper principles, not the
revolution required to get to such a government, is the goal of his efforts: “It is in
the first place necessary that we distinguish between the means made use of to
overthrow despotism in order to prepare the way for the establishment of liberty
and the means to be used after the despotism is overthrown.”6
The aim of the revolution is to establish a new order, not a permanent
revolutionary state, and only the promise of that new order, together with the
abuses of the old one, justifies the revolution. It is an insurrection that aims at
the establishment of some stable political arrangement. “The authority of the
present Assembly is different from what the authority of future Assemblies will
be,” Paine writes of the French parliament in the early stages of the revolution.
“The authority of the present one is to form a constitution; the authority of future
assemblies will be to legislate according to the principles and forms prescribed
in that constitution; and if experience should hereafter show that alterations,
amendments, or additions are necessary, the constitution will point out the mode
by which such things shall be done, and not leave it to the discretionary power of
the future government.”7
But for all these caveats, the mandate Paine describes for revolution is
exceptionally broad because he faults the very idea of “monarchical and
hereditary government,” and not just the particular abuses of particular regimes,
for leaving man in a wretched condition.8 In some writings (particularly in the
first part of Rights of Man, written while some of the French revolutionaries,
including Paine’s friend the Marquis de Lafayette, were still trying to retain
some symbolic role for the king in the new regime, and therefore written with
some caution) Paine reluctantly acknowledges the right of the people to choose a
monarch. But by the height of the French Revolution, and very clearly by the
second part of Rights of Man, which was written a little over a year after the
first, he declares himself an uncompromising republican. “All hereditary
government is in its nature tyranny,” Paine writes, and passionately attacks the
very notion of monarchy and hereditary aristocracy.9
When legitimate governments are established around the world, revolutions
should be scarce and citizens should seek to redress grievances by persuasion
and legislation. But as long as that is not the case (which it was not in his time in
any country except America and revolutionary France, Paine believed), the only
remedy at hand was to begin again. The old European regimes were simply no
longer adequate in the era of modern knowledge about politics. “Whether the
forms and maxims of Governments which are still in practice were adapted to
the condition of the world at the period they were established is not in this case
the question,” Paine writes. “The older they are, the less correspondence can
they have with the present state of things. Time, and change of circumstances
and opinions, have the same progressive effect in rendering modes of
Government obsolete as they have upon customs and manners.”10 The advance
of knowledge and civilization, themselves aided by the advance of modern
reason and science, make the inadequacy and illegitimacy of old regimes
increasingly acute, and the illegitimacy itself can only be addressed by total
revolution.
In practice, therefore, Paine argues that the moment requires a complete and
utterly new political beginning. People in every nation must throw off the old
governments that burden them and must begin again from their social
foundations, this time constructing political institutions in accord with the
principles of equality, choice, and representation made evident by reason. Paine’s
idea of revolution is thus less a remedy to a particular set of social and political
grievances and more a response to the absence of proper political foundations.
He wants to see a return to the natural society that he believes precedes the
formation of government and, from that point, the construction of entirely new
institutions and practices, unconnected to any that have existed in the old regime.
This requires the design and implementation of thoroughly novel social and
political forms. Continuity with the old regimes would itself be proof of the
inadequacy of reform. A constitution, in order to work well, “must be a novelty,
and that which is not a novelty must be defective,” Paine writes.11 Nothing of
the prior regime should be retained, and it makes very little sense to look at even
more ancient models, like those of Greece and Rome, in establishing a new
regime. “Mankind have lived to very little purpose if, at this period of the world,
they must go two or three thousand years back for lessons and examples.”12
Instead, we must look not to history but to our new understanding of nature and
of the principles of justice and society and begin nothing less than a rebirth.
Clearly, given both his enthusiasm for revolution and his caveats regarding
the limited circumstances under which it could be called for, Paine believed that
what matters most is what the revolution builds, not what it tears down, and he
was careful to make this point explicit too. “In contemplating revolutions,” he
notes in Rights of Man, “it is easy to perceive that they may arise from two
distinct causes; the one, to avoid or get rid of some great calamity; the other, to
obtain some great and positive good.” He continues:
In those which proceed from the former cause, the temper becomes incensed and soured; and the
redress, obtained by danger, is too often sullied by revenge. But in those which proceed from the
latter, the heart, rather animated than agitated, enters serenely upon the subject. Reason and
discussion, persuasion and conviction, become the weapons in the contest, and it is only when
those are attempted to be suppressed that recourse is had to violence. When men unite in agreeing
that a thing is good could it be obtained, such for instance as relief from a burden of taxes and “the
extinction” of corruption, the object is more than half accomplished. What they approve as the
end, they will promote in the means.13

Yet even in this very passage, Paine betrays the difficulty of distinguishing
destruction and construction in his view of the world. The positive goods he calls
upon as examples are “relief” from burdensome taxes and “the extinction” of
corruption—both of which are in fact negative goods. Because he believes a
legitimate government can fall into line with the rational and natural order of
things, he considers injustice a kind of imposition. Therefore, the enactment of
justice is the removal of a burden; the good is the elimination of the bad. For this
reason, Paine’s revolutionary writing is in fact almost entirely devoted to the
enterprise of bringing down despots and tyrants. Revolution is the elimination of
impositions and burdens, which in practice requires the total elimination of the
governments responsible for them.
Paine believes that since governing is essentially intellectual work, people
have the ability to build a proper government from scratch provided they respect
the principles of individual equality and liberty. But the necessary prior task of
dismantling a despotic regime is a much more difficult challenge that requires
immense political exertion, courage, and commitment. He sees himself above all
called to contribute to meeting this challenge, an effort that requires the best and
the brightest in an oppressed society—“all that extent of capacity which never
fails to appear in revolutions”—to help the people see their way to understanding
the failings of their government and to argue for a return to beginnings for the
construction of an alternative.14
Paine believed his particular talent for political argument was especially well
suited to the nature of the challenge, which required a kind of awakening. The
forms and habits of the old regime can easily disguise its fundamental injustice
from the people, since people after all tend to love their country and its symbols
and forms and so will bear a lot of pain out of habit. But, Paine writes, “it is,
however, curious to observe how soon this spell can be dissolved. A single
expression, boldly conceived and uttered, will sometimes put a whole company
into their proper feelings: and whole nations are acted on in the same manner.”15
Properly disillusioned and then instructed in the proper principles of
government, every nation has the capacity to liberate itself through revolution
and replace a decrepit despotism with a free regime. It is in this sense that Paine
famously assures his fellow Americans in 1776 that they can choose to
effectively to begin the world anew.16 We have it in our power to shake loose of
old presumptions, begin from the correct first principles, and so construct a
proper government.
Put this way, Paine’s revolutionary ethic turns out to be (in its means, as well
as its ends) an applied form of his theory of political life. He seeks to institute
change by starting over from scratch, just as he seeks to assess political
arrangements by looking back to first origins. He wants to take the method of
reasoning about politics employed by Enlightenment liberalism and turn it into a
method of acting on politics.
Because his idea of revolution is grounded in principle in this way and
involves a kind of liberation of man’s nature from the oppression of false ideas
and tyrannical government, Paine believes that its progress will be essentially
unstoppable once the obstacles of the old regimes are properly removed.
“Government founded on a moral theory, on a system of universal peace, on the
indefeasible hereditary Rights of Man, is now revolving from west to east by a
stronger impulse than the government of the sword revolved from east to west,”
he writes. “It interests not particular individuals, but nations in its progress, and
promises a new era to the human race.”17 This is a revolution concerned not
with the replacement of one leader with another. It is moved not by hatred of one
king or preference for another, but by the desire for justice enabled by a search
for the truth.
Even as things turned sour in France and Paine found himself imprisoned for
nearly a year by the revolutionary regime for associating with insufficiently
radical factions, he continued to argue that the proper principles were there to be
applied, and that any failures of the revolution were merely failures to apply
them fully and properly. “All the disorders that have arisen in France during the
progress of the revolution have had their origin not in the principle of equal
rights, but in the violation of that principle,” he wrote in 1795.18 Nine years
later, having seen the collapse of his great dream and the rise of Napoleon, Paine
told a group of French-speaking inhabitants of Louisiana: “You see what
mischief ensued in France by the possession of power before they understood
principles. They earned liberty in words, but not in fact. The writer of this was in
France through the whole of the Revolution, and knows the truth of what he
speaks; for after endeavoring to give it principle, he had nearly fallen victim to
its rage.”19 To the extent the revolution did not fully succeed, Paine concludes,
it was because it was incomplete, not, as Burke might suggest, because it sought
a complete enactment of an inadequate and excessively speculative vision.
This view makes Paine a thoroughgoing revolutionary, well before the idea
of the revolutionary as a political character or type had come into vogue.
Believing that political change must be total and uncompromising, he is excited
by the prospect of overthrowing the existing order so that a new and more
rational one may sprout in its place. Paine was exceptionally frank about his
advocacy for total revolution, especially once he was ensconced in France. He
saw all resistance to a complete new beginning as an expression of corruption or
of some invidious private motive and believed that during the exceptional period
of the revolution, resistance and opposition must be squashed for the good of the
cause.
It is important to understand how far beyond the liberalism of most English
Whigs Paine went by espousing these views. By rejecting monarchy in principle,
he allied himself with the fringe of the English radicals of the day, but even most
of those radicals never went as far as to suggest the abolition of the monarchy in
Britain itself. For Paine, despotism was the result of a failure to fully apply the
principles of liberty in practice, and so the liberal principles that had emerged
from the Whig worldview necessitated an unbending republicanism. It was in
this context that in his final letter to Burke, on January 17, 1790, Paine wrote of
the zeal of the revolutionaries and their determination to destroy themselves or
their country rather than abandon their revolutionary plan.20
It is easy to see why Paine was excited. The events he described, in the
opening months of the French Revolution, perfectly embodied his view of how
meaningful political change must occur and how a regime properly grounded in
Enlightenment rationalism ought to replace an ancient monarchy. The very same
events, however, also gave perfect expression to his correspondent’s worst fears
and deepest worries. Burke’s and Paine’s sharp differences were never clearer
than at the outset of the revolution in France.

BURKE’S COUNTERREVOLUTIONARY REFORM


“There was a time when it was impossible to make Mr. Burke believe there
would be any revolution in France,” Paine explains in Rights of Man. He was
referring to his discussions with Burke just a year before the revolution broke
out.21 Total revolution in the very heart of Europe seemed to Burke too radical a
prospect to believe. And for that very reason, when the revolution did come,
Burke could hardly contain his worry about its consequences. The revolution
embodied every concern Burke had spent his political life trying to address. It
was an outbreak of philosophically inspired radicalism driven by the very
theories of human nature and politics Burke had criticized for decades, it sought
to cut off a society’s links to its past, and it proceeded by acts of mob violence
and extremism.
Not surprisingly, therefore, Burke’s response, from the moment he became
aware of the scale of the violence in Paris until the end of his life about seven
years later, was an intense and fiery opposition to developments in France. He
had an unswerving dedication to opening the eyes of his countrymen to what he
took to be a profound and unprecedented peril. The French regime, Burke writes,
“is not a new power of an old kind. It is a new power of a new species.”22
Nothing like it had been seen before on the European scene, but it expressed in
real-world form the dangers that had for some time been building in the
intellectual world. “Never before this time was a set of literary men converted
into a gang of robbers and assassins; never before did a den of bravoes and
banditti assume the garb and tone of an academy of philosophers,” Burke writes
in one characteristic flourish of disconcertion.23
In the American crisis, which he never called a revolution, Burke believed
the colonies rebelled against British misrule. But the French were rebelling, he
thought, out of zeal for a new theory of man and society and in the process were
overturning far more than political structures. In this sense, it was precisely
because the revolution was about pursuing a new order, rather than just rejecting
a particular policy or ruler, that Burke thought it went too far. Paine’s
justification was identical to Burke’s indictment. “It is not a revolution in
government,” Burke writes. “It is not the victory of party over party. It is a
destruction and decomposition of the whole society; which never can be made of
right by any faction, however powerful, nor without terrible consequences to all
about it, both in the act and in the example.”24
France after its revolution, according to Burke, was not so much a nation
with a different government as a party in an intellectual dispute that spanned
borders and had ambitions to reach into every European state. “My ideas and my
principles led me in this contest to encounter France not as a state but as a
faction,” Burke writes in the Letters on a Regicide Peace.25 “It is a war between
the partisans of the ancient, civil, moral, and political order of Europe against a
sect of fanatical and ambitious atheists which means to change them all. It is not
France extending a foreign empire over other nations: it is a sect aiming at
universal empire, and beginning with the conquest of France.”26
And Burke’s vehement opposition was clearly motivated by the concern that
the revolutionary sect’s next conquest would be Britain and indeed that
England’s own political radicals were avidly working to set the scene for a new
English revolution to follow the French. He was worried that the agitations of
such radicals in Britain would give the people, as well as foreigners, the
impression that the nation as a whole was about to rebel. And in the Reflections,
he worked to dispel this notion while reminding his countrymen of the principles
of their regime and making the case against revolution as a mode of political
change.27
Burke did not deny that the need for serious political change sometimes
arose; nor did he deny that the old regime in France had serious faults (though he
surely did play these down at times).28 “I am no stranger to the faults and
defects of the subverted government of France,” he writes, “and I think I am not
inclined by nature or policy to make a panegyric upon anything which is a just
and natural object of censure. But the question is not now of the vices of that
monarchy, but of its existence. Is it then true, that the French government was
such as to be incapable or undeserving of reform; so that it was of absolute
necessity that the whole fabric should be at once pulled down, and the area
cleared for the erection of a theoretic, experimental edifice in its place?”29
Burke did not object to the desire for political change, but objected to throwing
out the entire regime, and with it, he believed, the political tradition of France, to
realize such change.
Some of the particular policies of the new regime could well improve the lot
of the people in the short run, he notes, as “they who destroy every thing
certainly will remove some grievance” and “they who make every thing new,
have a chance that they may establish something beneficial.” But to excuse the
violence and radicalism of the revolution by pointing to some particular benefit
of it, a person would have to prove that the benefit could not have been achieved
through less radical reform, and this, Burke argued, was simply false. And more
important, the harm done by the means and ends of the revolution was far
greater than these modest benefits. “The improvements of the national assembly
are superficial; their errors, fundamental.”30 The old regime may have been
barbaric, Burke writes, but the violent revolution has merely unleashed on the
world another no less barbaric regime.31
Surely these are not the only options. “Have these gentlemen never heard, in
the whole circle of the worlds of theory and practice, of anything between the
despotism of the monarch and the despotism of the multitude?” he asks.32 “It is
with them a war or a revolution, or it is nothing.”33 Burke argues that the failure
to see or pursue a middle ground is not an oversight but a prominent feature of
the radical worldview of the revolutionaries: “Their despair of curing common
distempers by regular methods, arises not only from defect of comprehension,
but, I fear, from some malignity of disposition.”34
The overthrow of a government is of course not unprecedented, even in the
history of Britain. But for the British as for most civilized nations, Burke claims,
revolution has been considered justifiable only as a matter of absolutely
unavoidable necessity. “Revolution will be the very last resource of the thinking
and the good.”35 The French, however, have made it a rule. “Their idea of their
powers is always taken at the utmost stretch of legislative competency, and their
examples for common cases from the exceptions of the most urgent
necessity.”36 This kind of extremism is very poorly suited to political life. “He
that sets his house on fire because his fingers are frostbitten can never be a fit
instructor in the method of providing our habitations with a cheerful and salutary
warmth,” Burke writes.37
Moreover, necessary revolutions in Britain have generally been undertaken
to return the constitution to some balance. They have not sought to completely
replace the system of government. Such total revolution, Burke argues, cannot
be justified even by necessity, because its consequences are so dire and grave
that there must always be a better option. By cutting off political life from all
prescription and instituting Enlightenment radicalism as a kind of state religion,
the revolution goes beyond the bounds of any necessity and puts in place an
incorrigible system—a government so riddled with fundamental problems it can
never be made good.38
Why should the revolutionary regime be so thoroughly (and permanently)
unsalvageable? Burke sees the regime as the instantiation of the radical views of
nature, choice, and Enlightenment reason described thus far, and he believes that
when all these are combined and put into action, the result is an unmitigated
political disaster, and one that closes off the path to its own improvement.
To begin with, the revolution undoes checks and incentives for moderation
and sets wild spirits loose. Its leaders treat France like a conquered country,
erasing all vestiges of prior identity and strength.39 They turn the people against
one another to weaken every part of society except the new government and seek
in particular “to subvert the whole frame and order of the best constructed states
by corrupting the common people with the spoil of the superior classes.”40 They
turn the talents of the nation’s best and brightest against the wealth of its great
families.41 All of this creates new habits of action and thought that powerfully
undermine all political order. These habits began before the revolution itself and
were essential to it. “A silent revolution in the moral world preceded the
political, and prepared it.”42 And once connected with the spectacles of an
actual revolution, these habits create a hunger for radical political action—a
hunger that leaves people dissatisfied with normal life and thus disinclined to
seek stability. “A cheap, bloodless reformation, a guiltless liberty, appear flat and
vapid to their taste. There must be a great change of scene; there must be a
magnificent stage effect; there must be a grand spectacle to rouse the
imagination.”43
Once roused, Burke argues, the imagination will remain so and will seek a
target for further spectacles and stage effects. Burke fears the unleashing of
political zealotry and fanaticism. A regime built on such theories with a public
moved to fanaticism, he writes, will quickly become a “tyranny of a licentious,
ferocious, and savage multitude, without laws, manners, or morals, and which so
far from respecting the general sense of mankind, insolently endeavors to alter
all the principles and opinions which have hitherto guided and contained the
world, and to force them into a conformity to their views and actions.”44
Setting loose these forces, Burke argues, not only undermines social stability,
but also sets the people and the state on a collision course, because the public
will soon enough grow tired of its new regime and its unavoidable restrictions on
individual liberty just as it was taught to grow tired of the old regime. And the
state is certain to overwhelm the populace in such a clash. A revolution driven
by a faith in choice and individualism will in time therefore yield a regime that
crushes choice and individualism. The political ideas behind the revolution
encourage disloyalty to one’s country in favor of Enlightenment principles. But
when that disloyalty extends to the new regime itself, the regime will have far
fewer resources than its predecessor to call upon in exerting its authority, since it
will have crushed the people’s natural calm. Having leveled society, the regime
will have only force at its disposal and will find itself compelled to crush dissent.
“Kings will be tyrants from policy when subjects are rebels from principle,”
Burke writes.45 And in that crisis, Burke predicts, the only recourse will be to a
military regime and, with it, the end of all the lovely talk about the rights of man.
In the Reflections, Burke predicts the rise of a charismatic general to power in
such a crisis—a prediction that eerily prefigures the coming of Napoleon.46
Indeed, it is precisely because the new regime is built upon a rational plan
that it has the potential to wield immense and previously inconceivable power
and overrun the individual. “France differs essentially from all those
Governments which are formed without system, which exist by habit, and which
are confused with the multitude, and with the complexity of their pursuits,”
Burke writes.
It is systematic; it is simple in its principle; it has unity and consistency in perfection. In that
country entirely to cut off a branch of commerce, to extinguish a manufacture, to destroy the
circulation of money, to violate credit, to suspend the course of agriculture, even to burn a city, or
to lay waste a province of their own, does not cost them a moment’s anxiety. To them, the will, the
wish, the want, the liberty, the toil, the blood of individuals is as nothing. Individuality is left out
of their scheme of Government. The state is all in all.47

Ironically, the regime built explicitly upon the rights of man stands to
trample those rights more effectively than any ancient despotism, Burke
believes. The revolutionaries have mistaken the external signs of despotism (like
nobles and priests) for the causes of it and so, as often happens in history, have
fought the wrong enemy and may turn out to embody the very evil they seek to
combat. “It is thus with all those, who, attending only to the shell and husk of
history, think they are waging war with intolerance, pride, and cruelty, whilst,
under color of abhorring the ill principles of antiquated parties, they are
authorizing and feeding the same odious vices in different factions, and perhaps
in worse.”48
Here again, Burke argues that the effort to rationalize politics, to eliminate
those sentimental attachments and seemingly vestigial organs, will end up
liberating not reason and justice but the passion for power. His difference with
Paine regarding human nature leads to very different expectations of the age of
revolutions. Political ideas have consequences, Burke writes, and these should
be understood in light of both the permanent limitations of human nature and the
successes and the failures of the past. Revolution, he argues, is an inappropriate
means of political change because it is not well suited for capitalizing on the
implicit lessons of the past or for leaving room for the permanent imperfection
of all human undertakings. The challenges of governing are simply too subtle
and complex to allow for such blunt force.
The French revolutionaries, as he understood them, simply ignored this
complexity. “An ignorant man, who is not fool enough to meddle with his clock,
is however sufficiently confident to think he can safely take to pieces, and put
together at his pleasure, a moral machine of another guise, importance and
complexity, composed of far other wheels, and springs, and balances, and
counteracting and co-operating powers,” Burke writes. “Men little think how
immorally they act in rashly meddling with what they do not understand. Their
delusive good intention is no sort of excuse for their presumption.”49
The pleasure that the revolutionaries seemed to take in such destruction of
long-standing arrangements only further confirms Burke in his worries. “It is a
sour, malignant, envious disposition, without taste for the reality, or for any
image or representation of virtue, that sees with joy the unmerited fall of what
had long flourished in splendor and in honor,” he writes. “I do not like to see any
thing destroyed; any void produced in society; any ruin on the face of the
land.”50 He believes that this hunger for ruin is a function of a lack of
appreciation for the given world. “Ingratitude is indeed their four cardinal virtues
compacted and amalgamated into one,” he writes in the Letter to a Noble
Lord.51
Thus again, Burke’s deepest objections to the revolutionaries and their
approach to political change have to do with their attitudes about the past and
their relation to it—their assertion that political change must overcome the past,
rather than build on it. Burke argues that this view, together with the closely
related assumptions of the revolutionaries regarding nature, choice, and reason,
leads to a profoundly misguided approach to political action and political
change. What’s more, the resulting revolutionary regime not only stands to do
terrible damage to society, but would also close off the paths to correcting its
own mistakes.
For all these reasons, Burke considers it absolutely crucial to resist the
revolution, both by opposing its extension and growth in France and, more
importantly, by preventing its importation into Britain. If it is not firmly resisted
at the outset and is allowed to seep into the political bloodstream of the British,
its effects could be irreversible, he worries. In a famous passage at the
conclusion of the Thoughts on French Affairs, Burke highlights the difficulty and
the danger that counterrevolutionaries since his day have always faced: “If a
great change is to be made in human affairs, the minds of men will be fitted to it,
the general opinions and feelings will draw that way. Every fear, every hope, will
forward it; and then they, who persist in opposing the mighty current of human
affairs, will appear rather to resist the decrees of Providence itself, than the mere
designs of men. They will not be resolute and firm, but perverse and
obstinate.”52 Burke clearly worries that the intellectual and almost spiritual
appeal of the revolution’s call for justice will overwhelm its great practical
deficiencies in the minds of the people and that once the revolution has taken
firm root, it will be essentially impossible to undo its effects or to remind the
people of what it has cost.
He is alert, as well, to the danger of appearing to be merely opposed to
change—of seeming to defend the status quo for no other reason than that it is
the way things are. On the contrary, Burke argues, he is not defending the status
quo but is rather defending an effective means of reform against an ineffective
one that threatens to cut society off from the possibility of real improvement.
In light of his vehement opposition to the French Revolution, we are today
too easily inclined to dismiss this assertion and to see Burke as merely a
defender of the established order. But the facts of his career and the nature of his
case against the revolution plainly argue otherwise. Burke was a leader in almost
every reform effort undertaken in Parliament during his three decades in elected
office. He sought (often but not always successfully) to reform the nation’s
finances, trade, and restrictions on Catholics and dissenters. He sought to
moderate the excesses (especially the excessive punishments) of the criminal
law, to rein in the East India Company, and to bring the gradual end of the slave
trade. And he effectively backed the American Revolution. But he always
approached the reform of existing institutions from a regard for their pedigree
and their worth, seeking to build on what worked to correct what did not, rather
than to overturn the foundations of the regime and begin again.
In this sense, Burke’s opposition to the French Revolution, especially as laid
out in the Reflections, involves a contrast between two modes of political
change, rather than between two types of regime or views of politics. The
contrast Burke draws in the Reflections between France and Britain is really a
contrast between revolution and reform. The French, he argues, have cut
themselves off from their glorious traditions and so, in an effort to correct the
faults of their former regime, have introduced worse faults than anyone could
have imagined. Their parliament is filled with inexperienced miscreants, their
economy in shambles, their population declining, their bureaucracy inept, their
laws ill-formed, their credit gone, their money worthless, their coffers empty,
their king a slave, their judges fools, and their army falling apart. Meanwhile,
England in his telling is basking in the glorious warmth of its old and revered
constitution—safe, sound, free, orderly, wealthy, and comfortably munching on
crumpets.
There is no question, as Thomas Paine frequently seeks to show, that Burke
is exaggerating in both accounts. The details of his descriptions of the
revolutionary regime and the events surrounding its emergence are often
inaccurate, and his description of the prior two centuries of English history
(when his countrymen had, after all, beheaded one king and deposed another) is,
to put it mildly, sanitized to make a point.
The point is not that whatever exists must be good, but that reform must
proceed gradually for practical, political, social, and moral reasons. In one
especially striking passage of the Reflections, Burke works through a long
discussion of the achievements and glories of the French throughout the
centuries of the Bourbon monarchy. He wonders how the beneficiaries of it all,
even in light of the many abuses and other faults of the later years of the regime,
could have determined that nothing but total revolution could improve it: “I do
not recognize, in this view of things, the despotism of Turkey. Nor do I discern
the character of a government, that has been, on the whole, so oppressive, or so
corrupt, or so negligent, as to be utterly unfit for all reformation. I must think
such a government well deserved to have its excellencies heightened; its faults
corrected; and its capacities improved into a British constitution.”53
When he speaks of the British constitution in this context, Burke means the
model of slowly enlarged precedent, not the model of the Lords and the
Commons in particular. Reformers should build on their national traditions.
The fundamental insight of his positive case for reform is that a statesman
ought to begin from gratitude for what works in his society, rather than from
outrage at what does not work. He must begin from a sense of what he has and
what is worth preserving and from there build toward what he wants and what is
worth achieving. But without question, change is not only inevitable but
desirable. And without developing an effective means of change, a nation “might
even risk the loss of that part of the constitution which it wished the most
religiously to preserve.”54
This difficult task of preservative improvement is, to Burke’s mind, the most
demanding and most important of the challenges of political life:
When the useful parts of an old establishment are kept, and what is superadded is to be fitted to
what is retained, a vigorous mind, steady persevering attention, various powers of comparison and
combination, and the resources of an understanding fruitful in expedients are to be exercised; they
are to be exercised in a continued conflict with the combined force of opposite vices; with the
obstinacy that rejects all improvement, and the levity that is fatigued and disgusted with every
thing of which it is in possession.55

Thus, as he famously put it, “a disposition to preserve, and an ability to


improve, taken together, would be my standard of a statesman.”56 And a key to
that disposition is that what Burke considers reform must be addressed to
specific, discrete problems. “The change is to be confined to the peccant part
only; to the part which produced the necessary deviation.”57 Rather than see the
whole state as a problem, he seeks to discern the good from the bad in it. This
inclination speaks to his understanding of the character of regimes in general. As
we have seen, Burke believes governments exist for very broad reasons, not to
advance one particular set of views or rights, but to account for the general
welfare of the people and to serve the needs of a complicated society. Rather
than see the whole of the system as one success or one failure, he thus sees it as
a patchwork of accumulated institutions that may require reform now and then as
difficulties present themselves, but that for the most part ought to be left to
function.
Unlike the planned regime of the revolutionaries, “the States of the Christian
World have grown up to their present magnitude in a great length of time, and by
a great variety of accidents. They have been improved to what we see them with
greater or less degrees of felicity and skill. Not one of them has been formed
upon a regular plan or with any unity of design,” Burke writes in the Letters on a
Regicide Peace.58 When something goes awry in this kind of complex
organism, the treatment required is more like medicine than engineering: a
process of healing that seeks to preserve by correcting.
There is a real art to knowing just how to pull off such a balancing act. And
when it is done well, a timely and gradual reform can avert public disaffection
and thus avert more disruptive or wholesale changes. “Early reformations are
amicable arrangements with a friend in power; late reformations are made under
a state of inflammation. In that state of things the people behold in government
nothing that is respectable. They see the abuse and they will see nothing else.
They fall into the temper of a furious populace provoked at the disorder of a
house of ill-fame; they never attempt to correct or regulate; they go to work by
the shortest way: to abate the nuisance, they pull down the house.”59
A decade before the French Revolution, Burke led an effort at just such an
artful and preventive reform, intended to curb waste and abuse in the
appropriation of public money, especially money spent on the lavish upkeep of
the royal family and assorted official jobs in the royal residences. These plum
jobs often involved no real work and simply rewarded the friends and relatives
of the politically well-connected. Seeing the potential for public disaffection
with the larger system of government over such waste and abuse, Burke led a
successful initiative to clean up public expenditures by painstakingly reviewing
every expense on the royal households. Toward the end of his life, he reflected
back upon this reform effort, employing terms drawn from medicine to describe
the statesman’s task: “I found a great distemper in the commonwealth; and,
according to the nature of evil and of the object, I treated it. The malady was
deep; it was complicated, in the causes and in the symptoms. Throughout it was
full of contra-indicants.” And his mode of treatment was motivated by an
understanding of the difference between fixing and replacing an established
system that works but that has some problems:
I knew that there is a manifest marked distinction, which ill men, with ill designs, or weak men
incapable of any design, will constantly be confounding, that is, a marked distinction between
Change and Reformation. The former alters the substance of the objects themselves; and gets rid
of all their essential good, as well as of all the accidental evil annexed to them. Change is novelty;
and whether it is to operate any one of the effects of reformation at all, or whether it may not
contradict the very principle upon which reformation is desired, cannot be certainly known
beforehand. Reform is, not a change in the substance, or in the primary modification of the object,
but a direct application of a remedy to the grievance complained of. So far as that is removed, all
is sure. It stops there; and if it fails, the substance which underwent the operation, at the very
worst, is but where it was.60

The challenge, of course, is to tell the difference between what must be


preserved and what must be reformed, and Burke acknowledged to the
Commons that he could not be entirely certain he had done so correctly in his
economic proposals. He could state with confidence only that he had based his
proposals on the specifics of the situation rather than a speculative theory of how
the royal households should work.61 And above all, he pursued his reform with
a sense of the risks of altering the institutions of the state.62 But it was
necessary, he says, to avoid public disaffection and to rescue the good name and
opinion of Parliament and the monarchy, and so he set out not to innovate but
quite literally to re-form, to bring the regime back to health by addressing its
particular ailment.
Wholesale innovation, Burke argues, is not a means of progress but rather
undercuts the prerequisites for progress by breaking with the past and thus
regressing to beginnings. It disrupts a long-standing political order and therefore
makes improvements vastly more difficult, as “good order is the foundation of
all good things.”63 Instead, statesmen must begin from what they have.
The British have long understood this crucial point, Burke argues. True
English principles—true Whig principles—militate against reckless innovation
and argue instead for the importance of continuity and stability. Even when they
were forced to resort to a kind of revolution themselves, the old Whigs who are
his models did so with an eye to preservation. Burke describes how they
accomplished this:
The two principles of conservation and correction operated strongly at the two critical periods of
the Restoration and Revolution, when England found itself without a king. At both those periods
the nation had lost the bond of union in their ancient edifice; they did not, however, dissolve the
whole fabric. On the contrary, in both cases they regenerated the deficient part of the old
constitution through the parts which were not impaired. They kept these old parts exactly as they
were, that the part recovered might be suited to them.64

The failure of the French to do the same meant that their revolution would
tear down the old but not build up the new.

THE EMERGENCE OF RIGHT AND LEFT


Because he understood the old Whigs in these terms, Burke reacted with
particular resistance and alarm to the attempt by some radicals to portray the
Glorious Revolution of 1688 as a kind of preface to the French Revolution. The
idea that the Whigs of 1688 had turned their ancient monarchy into merely an
elected kingship was central to the case made by the British defenders of the
French Revolution, and his alarm at such an argument drove Burke to compose
the Reflections.
He thus devotes the opening of the Reflections and the great bulk of the
Appeal from the New to the Old Whigs to answering this argument. In these
tellings, the Whigs of 1688, as defenders of the ancient English order, sought to
address a severe crisis of legitimacy by finding a means of preserving the
structure of the regime and the line of succession despite gross misbehavior by
the monarch, rather than starting anew on novel principles. The revolution of
1688, Burke argues, was a necessary exception, but the Whigs of the day made
sure it did not become the rule. It was decidedly “not a nursery of future
revolutions.”65 Indeed, he argues in the Appeal, 1688 was “a revolution not
made but prevented.”66
The debates of his own time, Burke thought, bore no real resemblance to
those of 1688, and the simplistic notion that Whigs should be in favor of
revolution and that to be against the French radicals made one a Tory mistook
the meaning of the crisis. In the early years of the French Revolution, a great
many of Burke’s Whig co-partisans disagreed and charged him with betraying
the principles of the party. Burke at first brushed off such charges, but as the
French Revolution wore on, he came to think that his own differences with his
fellow Whigs contained an important lesson about what the French Revolution
meant to the politics of Britain. The British debate about the French Revolution,
he concluded, was in a certain sense a debate among Whigs. Or at least it was
detached from the debate between parliamentary and royal power—a debate
long understood as the distinction between Whigs and Tories. The revolution had
wrought a profound transformation of the political landscape and created two
new parties divided along a new question.
In the Letters on a Regicide Peace, Burke argues that it simply no longer
made sense to speak of Whigs and Tories as those terms had once been used.
“These parties, which by their dissensions have so often distracted the Kingdom,
which by their union have once saved it, and which by their collision and mutual
resistance, have preserved the variety of this Constitution in its unity, be (as I
believe they are) nearly extinct by the growth of new ones, which have their
roots in the present circumstances of the times.” And what are these new parties?
One party, Burke says, is filled with men who “consider the conservation in
England of the ancient order of things, as necessary to preserve order every
where else, and who regard the general conservation of order in other countries,
as reciprocally necessary to preserve the same state of things in these Islands.”
And opposing this party of conservation is “the other party which demands great
changes here, and is so pleased to see them every where else, which party I call
Jacobin.”67
In the wake of the French Revolution, Burke suggests, the Whigs and Tories
have been replaced by a party of conservation and a Jacobin party. The question
between them is no longer about the prerogatives of the king versus those of
Parliament, but is rather about the prerogatives of the existing given regime
versus a revolutionary republicanism that would wash it away. In other words,
the question that now defined British politics was the question of revolution and
reform.
On this point, Burke and Paine largely agreed. Although Burke cites Paine at
length as the chief example of the republican arguments he attributes to the
radical Whigs, Paine in fact never claims the mantle of the Whigs. Far from
attempting to appropriate the authority of 1688, as many English radicals did,
Paine disparages the Glorious Revolution, which he says had been “exalted
beyond its value.” He even openly mocks the old Whigs who undertook it.
“Mankind will then scarcely believe that a country calling itself free would send
to Holland for a man, and clothe him with power on purpose to put themselves in
fear of him, and give him almost a million sterling a year for leave to submit
themselves and their posterity, like bondmen and bondwomen, for ever.”68 The
influence and appeal of the Glorious Revolution, he argues, “is already on the
wane, eclipsed by the enlarging orb of reason, and the luminous revolutions of
America and France. In less than another century it will go, as well as Mr.
Burke’s labors, ‘to the family vault of all the Capulets.’”69 Of William and Mary
themselves, long venerated by Whig champions of the rights of 1688, Paine says
they “have always appeared to me detestable; the one seeking to destroy his
uncle, and the other her father, to get possession of power themselves.”70
Paine effectively makes Burke’s point that the French Revolution, properly
understood, does not seek to advance the Whig principles of 1688, but rather
sees them as sorely inadequate to the task of correcting unjust regimes. To alter a
fundamentally unjust regime in order to preserve it strikes Paine as both
illegitimate and pointless. No government has “a right to alter itself, either in
whole or in part,” he writes, so that reform without recourse to an original
condition or a national convention can only be either inadequate or illicit.71 In
fact, a partial reform strikes him as no better than no improvement at all. “It will
always happen when a thing is originally wrong that amendments do not make it
right, and it often happens that they do as much mischief one way as good the
other.”72 In an ill-founded society, the principles of injustice become “too
deeply rooted to be removed, and the Augean stables of parasites and plunderers
too abominably filthy to be cleansed by anything short of a complete and
universal Revolution.”73 Such universal revolution is in fact the only effective
means of reform, Paine argues, and he utterly dismisses the distinction Burke
insists upon between revolution and reform: “Reforms, or revolutions, call them
which you please.”74
For his own reasons, therefore, Paine concludes just as Burke does that the
familiar political divide in Britain has lost its salience and been replaced by a
new question. “It is not whether this or that party shall be in or not, or Whig or
Tory, high or low shall prevail; but whether man shall inherit his rights, and
universal civilization take place. Whether the fruits of his labors shall be enjoyed
by himself or consumed by the profligacy of governments. Whether robbery
shall be banished from courts, and wretchedness from countries.”75
This new question now pressed upon Europe with great urgency and made
for a moment of political transformation. In Paine’s view, the advancement of
reason and science made his own time a moment of profound change unlike any
prior era and set the tone for a far brighter future: an age of reform, by which he
means an age of revolutions, as he puts it in the final words of the first volume of
Rights of Man:
From what we now see, nothing of reform in the political world ought to be held improbable. It is
an age of Revolutions, in which everything may be looked for. The intrigue of Courts, by which
the system of war is kept up, may provoke a confederation of Nations to abolish it: and an
European Congress to patronize the progress of free Government, and promote the civilization of
Nations with each other, is an event nearer in probability, than once were the revolutions and
alliance of France and America.76

“The iron is becoming hot all over Europe,” Paine then writes in the second
volume. “The insulted German and the enslaved Spaniard, the Russ and the Pole,
are beginning to think. The present age will hereafter merit to be called the Age
of Reason, and the present generation will appear to the future as the Adam of a
new world.”77 This period will be remembered as the moment of
transformation, he argues: “The farce of monarchy and aristocracy, in all
countries, is following that of chivalry, and Mr. Burke is dressing for the funeral.
Let it then pass quietly to the tomb of all other follies, and the mourners be
comforted.”78
But in Burke’s view, his time differed from the past not because some new
truth had been learned or great advance achieved, but simply because the
excesses and corruptions of the revolution itself had distorted and transformed
English politics: “The present time differs from any other only by the
circumstances of what is doing in France.”79 The basic realities of human nature
and of politics have not changed at all, except inasmuch as they must now
confront a political force that seeks to ignore or undermine them. And politics
seeks in particular to ignore the obligations of the present to the past, and
therefore to the future, as Burke sees it.
In this sense, Burke’s and Paine’s disparate ideas about revolution and
reform—a difference that both men suggested was quickly becoming their era’s
defining disagreement in European politics—can be understood as a
disagreement about the relation of the present to the past and about the
obligation of every generation to sustain and improve what it was given and to
pass it along to those who follow. The dispute over political change concerns the
relations of generations in politics. Burke’s objection to total revolution draws on
his horror at the prospect of abandoning all that has been arduously gained over
centuries of slow, incremental reform and improvement. He sees it as a betrayal
of the trust of past generations and of the obligation to future ones. Paine’s
objection to such plodding reform, meanwhile, is that it gives credence to
despotism and is moved more by the desire to sustain iniquity than by the desire
to address injustice.
Burke believes that human nature and the rest of nature make themselves
known in politics through long experience, that human beings are born into a
web of obligations, and that the social problems we confront do not lend
themselves to detached scientific analysis. For all these reasons, he believes that
improvements in politics must be achieved by cumulative reform—by building
on success to address failure and by containing the effects of innovation within a
broader context of continuity.
Paine, on the other hand, believes that nature reveals itself in the form of
abstract principles discovered by rational analysis, that human beings are entitled
to choose their government freely, that government in turn exists to protect their
other choices, and that reason can help people see beyond the superstitions that
have long sustained unjust regimes. For all these reasons, he believes that
improvements in politics must be achieved by thoroughgoing revolution—by
throwing off the accumulated burdens of the past and starting fresh and properly.
Their assorted disagreements therefore repeatedly point to a confrontation
over the authority of the past and the prerogatives of the present in political life.
That profound and unusual terrain of dispute is where we now turn.
SEVEN

GENERATIONS AND THE LIVING

HAT IS THE PROPER RELATION BETWEEN GENER Ations in a

W society? Just because our parents’ generation did something a certain


way, should we do the same, or can we put aside their practices and
blaze our own path? Do we owe it to our children to preserve the
social and political institutions that we ourselves inherited so our descendants
can live as we did, or do we owe them the freedom to find their own way? Is it
even possible to understand our civic life in terms of consent and freedom of
choice if it involves a political order we inherited at birth and so had no real part
in choosing? Do both the society we happened to inherit and our place in that
society have any legitimate authority over how we ought to live our lives?
As we have already begun to see, the Burke-Paine debate has a great deal to
tell us about both why and how we ought to think about these vexing questions.
The dilemma of the generations in a liberal society looms exceptionally large in
their political thought and is present just below the surface of many of the
disputes that divide them. Paine and Burke bring up the subject frequently and in
a wide variety of contexts, so that more than just another theme of their dispute,
it forms a kind of unifying thread among the themes we have discussed.
Paine seeks to understand man apart from his social setting, while Burke
thinks man is incomprehensible apart from the circumstances into which he is
born—circumstances largely the making of prior generations. Burke describes a
densely layered social whole that defines the place of each of its members, while
Paine thinks each person is born with an equal right to shape his destiny. Paine’s
case for a politics of reason argues for direct recourse to principle in the face of
long-established but unreasonable practices. Burke’s case for prescription is
based on generational continuity. This argument leads Burke to prefer gradual
reforms that preserve what has come down from the past, while Paine pursues a
revolutionary break as the only way to escape the heavy burden of long-standing
injustice.
The question of the generations recurs so frequently in their discussions
because the Burke-Paine debate is about Enlightenment liberalism, whose
underlying worldview unavoidably raises the problem of the generations.
Enlightenment liberalism emphasizes government by consent, individualism,
and social equality, all of which are in tension with some rather glaring facts of
the human condition: that we are born into a society that already exists, that we
enter this society without consenting to it, that we enter it with social
connections and not as isolated individuals, and that these connections help
define our place in society and therefore often raise barriers to equality.
These facts suggest either that Enlightenment liberalism is in some important
ways unworkable in practice given the relations between generations or that
those relations must be transformed to make such liberalism possible. Because
they took up the question of Enlightenment liberalism at the moment when it
was becoming a question of practice, Burke and Paine were unusually attentive
to these problems and approached the matter of generational relations as a
genuinely practical and open question.

PAINE’S ETERNAL NOW


Thomas Paine’s view of political life points toward a politics of timelessness. An
individual’s rights and place in society should have nothing to do with what
preceded his birth. Every human individual in every generation has the same
relation to society as every other person in every other generation, so that the
political actions, decisions, rules, and achievements of past generations do not
constrain the present or define it. The present is defined instead in direct relation
to original principles, which are just as plain and true today as they were at the
beginning of human history. They are equally true for different generations just
as for different individuals. Therefore, Paine insists, “every generation is equal
in rights to generations which preceded it, by the same rule that every individual
is born equal in rights with his contemporary.”1
This equality among the generations does not mean, however, that past and
present generations have an equal claim on present political judgments. The past
had its chance, and now the present generation is entitled to its own, as future
generations someday will be. “Every age and generation must be as free to act
for itself in all cases as the ages and generations which preceded it.”2 The
movement of generations is in this sense less cumulative than repetitive. “All
men are born equal, and with equal natural right, in the same manner as if
posterity had been continued by creation instead of generation,” Paine argues,
“the latter being only the mode by which the former is carried forward; and
consequently every child born into the world must be considered as deriving its
existence from God. The world is as new to him as it was to the first man that
existed, and his natural right in it is of the same kind.”3
This desire for a direct connection to original principles can make it difficult
to contend with the consequences of the passing of generations—indeed with the
very fact that people are born at all. Consent requires that every generation see
the world as fully open before it, rather than taking as given what existed when it
arrived. Free men must be able to live freely in the present, and they cannot do
so if they are obliged to obey the edicts of their predecessors. Paine makes this
point remarkably explicit in essentially all of his political writings—before,
during, and after the French Revolution. It is perhaps put most starkly in his
1795 Dissertation on First Principles of Government: “Time with respect to
principles is an eternal NOW: it has no operation upon them; it changes nothing
of their nature and qualities. But what have we to do with a thousand years? Our
lifetime is but a short portion of time, and if we find the wrong in existence as
soon as we begin to live, that is the point of time at which it begins to us; and our
right to resist it is the same as if it never existed before.”4 This extraordinary
notion of the eternal now powerfully clarifies Paine’s understanding of time in
political life. His is a politics of the present. As he puts it in Rights of Man, “it is
the living, and not the dead, that are to be accommodated” in political life.5
Paine does not deny the fact of generations of course, but rather the authority of
the accumulated practices of the past. Indeed, he takes the constant movement of
nations through generations to be itself an argument for the eternal now in
politics:
A nation, though continually existing, is continually in a state of renewal and succession. It is
never stationary. Every day produces new births, carries minors forward to maturity, and old
persons from the stage. In this ever running flood of generations there is no part superior in
authority to another. Could we conceive an idea of superiority in any, at what point in time, or in
what century of the world, are we to fix it? To what cause are we to ascribe it? By what evidence
are we to prove it? By what criterion are we to know it?6
Precisely because life itself is not timeless, Paine insists that politics must be
timeless—for why would the past be inherently better or worse than the present
or the future? And precisely because Paine does believe in progress, in a
movement of political life toward a better understanding of the timeless
principles of justice, he argues that this progress points toward a politics of
permanent principle in which truth rather than habit reigns supreme. He thus
understands hereditary monarchy and aristocracy not only as unjust impositions
on the liberty of the individual but as unjust impositions by the past upon the
present.
Paine particularly presses this point in his response to Burke’s assertion of
the permanent allegiance of the British people to the monarchy. In the
Reflections on the Revolution in France, in an effort to refute the claim of
Richard Price that the Glorious Revolution had created a right to choose the
monarch, Burke notes that the Parliament of 1688 pledges to William and Mary
that “we do most humbly and faithfully submit ourselves, our heirs and
posterities, for ever.” Paine quotes this passage in the opening of Rights of Man
and accuses Burke of arguing that this submission by one particular generation
of legislators is inexorably binding on all future Englishmen.7 “The English
Parliament of 1688 did a certain thing, which, for themselves and their
constituents, they had a right to do,” but which they had no right to do for
subsequent generations.8
There never did, there never will, and there never can, exist a Parliament, or any description of
men, or any generation of men, in any country, possessed of the right or the power of binding and
controlling posterity to the “end of time,” or of commanding for ever how the world shall be
governed, or who shall govern it. The vanity and presumption of governing beyond the grave is
the most ridiculous and insolent of all tyrannies. Man has no property in man; neither has any
generation a property in the generations which are to follow. . . . Every generation is, and must be,
competent to all the purposes which its occasions require.9

The deep connection between Paine’s individualism and his rejection of the
authority of the past is powerfully evident in this passage. Paine thinks of
different generations as essentially distinct and unconnected—not as extensions
of one another. In effect, he suggests that we who are alive today, the people who
once inhabited our country, and the people who will inhabit it in the future are
simply not one people in any meaningful political sense. “That every nation, for
the time being, has a right to govern itself as it pleases must always be admitted;
but government by hereditary succession is government for another race of
people, and not for itself.”10
Hereditary government is always imposed and never chosen, Paine explains,
because it is not hereditary government until the second generation of its rule,
and that generation of the ruled could not have chosen its rulers. If human beings
lived forever, there might be such a thing as a legitimate monarchy, but since
they do not live forever, every hereditary regime becomes tyrannical by
definition after one generation.11 This next generation is forced to be governed
by the descendant of the person chosen to govern in the prior generation. Force
thus replaces choice, and the regime ceases to be legitimate. “The Parliament of
1688 might as well have passed an act to have authorized themselves to live for
ever, as to make their authority live for ever.”12
The right to rule is a matter of consent, which ideally is earned by a display
of virtue or merit. “Whenever we are planning for posterity,” Paine writes in
Common Sense, “we ought to remember that virtue is not hereditary.”13 And as
virtue is not hereditary, neither can political power be hereditary. For this reason,
no man can claim the authority to govern by virtue of his link to those who have
governed in the past.
Indeed, Paine’s individualism, and his resulting egalitarianism, drives him to
suggest that essentially nothing of any relevance is hereditary, and he minimizes
the importance of the links between generations in society more generally.
Human beings should be governed by their own choices and actions, rather than
those of others, and the social relations one happens to have inherited upon
arriving in this world ought not to be the decisive factor in the trajectory of one’s
life.
For much the same reason, the political arrangements and practices of the
past do not possess any inherent authority over the present or the future simply
for having been in effect for a time. Writing of the English constitution, Paine
remarks:
In speaking on this subject (or on any other) on the pure ground of principle, antiquity and
precedent cease to be authority, and hoary- headed error loses its effect. The reasonableness and
propriety of things must be examined abstractedly from custom and usage; and, in this point of
view, the right which grows into practice today is as much a right, and as old in principle and
theory, as if it had the customary sanction of a thousand ages. Principles have no connection with
time, nor characters with names.14

The just and right paths do not need the blessing of long custom to be
adopted—in a politics attuned to proper principles and guided by reason, they
will be adopted on their own merits: “That which is worth following will be
followed for the sake of its worth; and it is in this that its security lies, and not in
any conditions with which it may be encumbered.”15
In a regime premised on inheritance, there is no guarantee that what is worth
following will be followed, not only because custom can be blind, but because
nature can be quite haphazard in its distribution of gifts, and the child of an able
monarch may easily be a fool. The flood of generations disburses natural gifts,
and the march of time means that even the ablest leader must eventually depart
the stage. A successful political system must be able to contend with both
problems, even as it holds to timeless ideals and treats every individual and
every generation equally. For Paine, the key to such a system is a republican
character, the essence of which is that an able person from any part of society
may rise to elected power by proving his worth. Only a republic can keep the
generations from trampling on one another and keep the loss of an able leader
from ruining the state. “As the republic of letters brings forward the best literary
productions, by giving to genius a fair and universal chance; so the
representative system of government is calculated to produce the wisest laws, by
collecting wisdom from where it can be found,” Paine writes.16
The republic is a kind of solution to the cycle of generations in politics. By
putting into practice liberal premises, it creates a state in which the assumptions
of Enlightenment liberalism apply, and by reshaping the traditional relationship
of the generations, it ensures that everyone has rights of consent and equality,
despite everyone’s being born into a preexisting society. It also offers a practical
solution to the serious practical deficiencies of an inherited order. A monarchy
not only is an unjust imposition by the past, but is also constantly interrupted by
the facts of birth and death and the deficiencies of both youth and old age. “To
render monarchy consistent with government, the next in succession should not
be born a child, but a man at once, and that man a Solomon. It is ridiculous that
nations are to wait and government be interrupted till boys grow to be men,”
Paine writes.17 A republic avoids that problem. “It places government in a state
of constant maturity. It is, as has already been observed, never young, never old.
It is subject neither to nonage, nor dotage. It is never in the cradle, nor on
crutches.”18
A crucial part of Paine’s enthusiasm for republicanism has to do with this
character of the republic as he sees it: its ability to offer an escape from the
ravages of time, a permanence denied to any institution that follows the life
cycle, yet at the same time a legitimacy denied to any institution that denies the
equality of all generations. “It is the nature of man to die, and he will continue to
die as long as he continues to be born,” Paine writes, but politics need not be
shaped or debilitated by this fact about mankind.19 The problematic political
consequences of human mortality are overcome by a regime of choice and
consent.
In this sense, modern liberal politics as Paine sees it is part and parcel of a
larger project to overcome the limitations placed on mankind by his natural
condition, especially his birth and death. Enlightenment liberalism both requires
and (through republicanism) makes possible a state of constant maturity—an
eternal now. It averts the effects, and thereby denies the importance, of the
passing of generations and of the links between them. As noted earlier, Paine
expressly denies that these links exercise any authority, even when laws extend
across generations: “A law not repealed continues in force, not because it cannot
be repealed, but because it is not repealed; and the non-repealing passes for
consent.”20
Nothing of consequence passes between the generations, Paine insists. In
Agrarian Justice, he argues that an inheritance tax is the most just means by
which to draw government revenue for the welfare system he envisions, because
at the moment of inheritance—the nexus of generations—no transaction worth
protecting occurs.21 The links between generations therefore cannot serve as the
foundation for political institutions or even for property. Rather, politics must
focus on the present, not on the dead or those yet to be born. “Those who have
quitted the world, and those who have not yet arrived in it, are as remote from
each other as the utmost stretch of moral imagination can conceive. What
possible obligation, then, can exist between them?”22 Because it is impossible to
legislate on behalf of those who can no longer or not yet exercise consent,
legislators must focus on those who can.
Paine is not ignoring the needs of future generations, but he argues that their
greatest need will be like that of the present generation: the need for freedom in
accord with their natural rights. Paine rarely speaks of inheritance in a positive
sense, but speaks of it only in a negative sense—that is, as an obligation not to
impose on our descendants. The present should live in such a way that it does
not bind the future.
Political institutions last beyond one generation, of course, but they must be
designed to require continuing consent. And legislation passed by one generation
should not overly burden the next—each age should legislate only for itself
when possible. “As the generations of the world are every day both commencing
and expiring,” Paine writes, “therefore when any public act of this sort is done, it
naturally supposes the age of that generation to be then beginning, and the time
contained between coming of age and the natural end of life is the extent of time
it has the right to go to, which may be about thirty years; for though many may
die before, others will live beyond; and the mean time is equally fair for all
generations.”23 Beyond that roughly thirty-year span, a law is no longer in effect
primarily upon those who enacted it, and so it should be cleared away, Paine
argues.24
Requiring all laws to expire after a generation would also help avoid the
suffocating clutter of the British constitution. “The British, from the want of
some general regulation of this kind, have a great number of obsolete laws;
which, though out of use and forgotten are not out of force, and are occasionally
brought up for particular purposes.”25 By establishing time limits on legislation,
wise lawmakers would enable every age to govern itself and so would actually
reinforce the laws that deserve to endure (by having them reaffirmed), while
systematically filtering out those that do not. There is no sense in legislating as if
legislators’ reason will discern the desires and needs of all future generations
forever. “The term ‘forever’ is an absurdity that would have no effect,” Paine
writes. “The next age will think for itself, by the same rule of right that we have
done, and not admit any assumed authority of ours to encroach upon the system
of their day. Our forever ends where their forever begins.”26
Essentially nothing, therefore, legitimately spans generations. Because Paine
believes that the rights and freedoms of the individual are at the core of political
life, he argues that positive inheritance is almost entirely burdensome. What we
owe the future is freedom, which is also what we must demand from the past.
Politics in this sense exists for the sake of the present. It allows present citizens
to legislate for themselves, free of impositions from their ancestors, and it will
allow future citizens to do the same. This temporal individualism is at the heart
of Paine’s liberalism.

BURKE’S ETERNAL ORDER


Beginning from a very different premise, Edmund Burke comes to an entirely
different view of the appropriate relations between the generations. His own
understanding of politics puts not abstract natural freedom but concrete
inheritance at the very core and emphasizes obligation over choice. Burke
believes that what we owe the future above all is not freedom but rather the
accumulated wisdom and work of the past: The task of any generation is to
preserve and, where necessary and possible, improve what that generation has
been given by its predecessors, with the aim of passing the benefit along to its
successors. Each generation must live with a sense of its own time as transitory
—more or less the opposite of an eternal now.
As noted, Burke sees society as a relationship not just between the living, but
also between the living, the dead, and the people of the future.27 Society exists
not to facilitate individual choice but to meet the needs of the people, and to do
so, it must draw on the wisdom of the past and be guided by the imperative to
make that wisdom available to future generations as well, supplemented by
lessons learned by the current generation along the way. “I attest the retiring, I
attest the advancing generations, between which, as a link in the great chain of
eternal order, we stand,” Burke told the House of Lords in the course of the
impeachment trial of Hastings.28
A great deal of Burke’s work is built on this sense that the present is fleeting
and best understood as a link in a chain, and his focus on this question grows
especially pronounced in the years of the French Revolution. Burke believes that
the present generation has profound obligations both to the past and to the future
and that these obligations offer an important benefit to the present generation, by
imposing crucial constraints upon its ambitions and its reach. Society can thrive
only within such constraints and therefore with a sense of itself as linked to the
past and the future. Without these constraints, all the lessons of history would be
denied to the present and the future, and “personal self-sufficiency and
arrogance, the certain attendants upon all those who have never experienced a
wisdom greater than their own, would usurp the tribunal.”29
29Burke expressly denies that we can look out for the needs of the future
even as we reject the lessons and achievements of the past. Access to those
lessons and achievements is one of the most crucial needs of the future, as he
sees it, so the present-centered vision of the revolutionaries must involve
betraying the future as much as the past: “People will not look forward to
posterity, who never look backward to their ancestors.”30 A free and ordered
society will look to both, Burke argues:
One of the first and most leading principles on which the commonwealth and the laws are
consecrated, is lest the temporary possessors and life renters in it, unmindful of what they have
received from their ancestors, or of what is due to their posterity, should act as if they were the
entire masters; that they should not think it amongst their rights to cut off the entail or commit
waste on the inheritance, by destroying at their pleasure the whole original fabric of their society;
hazarding to leave to those who come after them a ruin instead of a habitation, and teaching these
successors as little respect to their contrivances as they had themselves respected the institutions
of their forefathers.31

In order to build anything lasting, Burke suggests, we must respect what has
been built in the past and how it has come down to us.
The idea of inheritance for Burke explains not only the descent of property and
title, but also the descent of rights and obligations, which Paine takes to derive
directly from the individual but which Burke believes are a function of one’s
relation to the past. Burke stresses that because men are born into civil society
without their own consent, their rights in that society are a function not of their
agreeing to certain arrangements but of their inheritance from their forefathers,
who had worked to defend those rights just as members of this new generation
should for themselves and their posterity. In defending the accumulated
achievements of the past, however, Burke defends not only social relations and
ordered freedom but also precisely the kind of inherited property and privileges
that Paine so opposes. Burke argues that the noble families of Britain are
essential to the nation’s stability and success and provide a source of strength
that a fully democratic republic could never attain. In an extraordinary letter to
the Duke of Richmond in 1772, Burke writes:
You people of great families and hereditary trusts and fortunes are not like such as I am, who,
whatever may be the rapidity of our growth, and even by the fruit we bear, and flatter ourselves a
little that, while we creep on the ground, we belly into melons that are exquisite for size and
flavor, yet still we are but annual plants that perish with our season, and leave no sort of traces
behind us. You, if you are what you ought to be, are in my eye the great oaks that shade a country,
and perpetuate your benefits from generation to generation.32

Though not blind to the dark side of the aristocracy, Burke rejects Paine’s
assertion that nothing of much consequence transpires at the junction of the
generations. He argues that the strength and stability made possible by the
aristocracy are worth the cost—and that in any case, no plausible alternative
exists as a means of perpetuation.
Burke also expressly disagrees with Paine’s assertion that a republic allows
for institutions that reach beyond the lifespans of individuals. Republican
institutions are never secure, Burke argues, because they accept no authority but
the present. “They conceive, very systematically, that all things which give
perpetuity are mischievous, and therefore they are at inexpiable war with all
establishments,” Burke writes of the revolutionaries.33 No one can ever plan
ahead securely in a republic, Burke argues, because the rules could change at any
point on the momentary whim of today’s majority. Only cross-generational
institutions and the great aristocratic families offer a real solution to the
challenge of establishing arrangements that will outlive their founders. “This
nobility forms the chain that connects the ages of a nation which otherwise (with
Mr. Paine) would soon be taught that no one generation can bind another,” Burke
argues.34 Whereas individuals come and go, the commonwealth is more
permanent. Precisely because of this difference, laws and practices that span
generations are essential, so that society as a whole may persist as a body which,
“in juridical construction, never dies; and in fact never loses its members at once
by death.”35 Or as Burke puts it in the Reflections:
Our political system is placed in a just correspondence and symmetry with the order of the world,
and with the mode of existence decreed to a permanent body composed of transitory parts;
wherein, by the disposition of a stupendous wisdom, moulding together the great mysterious
incorporation of the human race, the whole at one time is never old, or middle-aged, or young, but
in a condition of unchangeable constancy, moves on through the varied tenor of perpetual decay,
fall, renovation, and progression.36

Burke and Paine thus employ very similar language—the language of a


regime always in its prime—to argue for thoroughly opposite notions of the
relations between the generations in the design of political institutions. For
Burke it is not by separating the generations but by joining them that we ensure
that society is not debilitated by human mortality. Society flourishes not by
freeing every generation from those that precede and succeed it so that it might
have direct recourse to permanent principles, but by linking the generations
tightly together so that they might form a permanent body. If “the whole chain
and continuity of the commonwealth would be broken and no one generation
could link with the other,” Burke worries, then “men would become little better
than the flies of a summer.”37
The commonwealth, as a work of many generations intended to last for many
more, requires an explicitly intergenerational character. It exists not in an eternal
now but rather as the product of a lengthy and still ongoing process—one in
which time is of very great significance and therefore in which the generations
must take part together. “Where the great interests of mankind are concerned
through a long succession of generations,” Burke writes, “that succession ought
to be admitted into some share in the councils which are so deeply to affect
them. If justice requires this, the work itself requires the aid of more minds than
one age can furnish.”38
Thomas Paine, as we have seen, believes that this view subordinates the
interests of the present and the future to those of the past, as it would deny every
generation but the first a full share in self-government. But Burke argues that far
from sacrificing the present and the future, he is defending both from being
robbed of their inheritance. It is the revolutionaries who would sacrifice the
interests of the present (by subjecting the present generation to the instability and
danger of the revolution itself) and risk the inheritance of the future on a gamble.
“In political arrangements, men have no right to put the well-being of the present
generation wholly out of the question,” he writes. “Perhaps the only moral trust
with any certainty in our hands is the care of our own time. With regard to
futurity, we are to treat it like a ward. We are not so to attempt an improvement
of his fortune, as to put the capital of his estate to any hazard.”39
That capital, to which the present and the future are entitled, is the
accumulated knowledge and practice of their forefathers. The radicals, Burke
argues, seek “to deprive men of the benefit of the collected wisdom of mankind,
and to make them blind disciples of their own particular presumption.”40 He
therefore sees himself as a defender of the present, not the past, and sees the
revolutionaries as a threat to present happiness as well as to future order. “Our
first trust is the happiness of our own time.”41
Even if their plans had some chance of succeeding, Burke suggests, the
revolutionaries’ treatment of the present generation is therefore a dereliction of
the statesman’s foremost duty. And of course, for the very same reason, he also
thinks their plans will fail: Because the revolutionaries do not grasp the actual
character of human society, they direct themselves to the wrong ends altogether.
In rejecting the accumulated achievements of the past, they reject an entire
approach to political life and an entire view of the nature of man and society.
Their other errors—as Burke sees it, errors about human nature and justice,
human obligations and freedom, human reason and knowledge, and political
change and reform—result from (and also describe) the same underlying view.

THE POLITICS OF THE GIVEN WORLD


Anyone exploring the views of Burke and Paine will repeatedly encounter, as we
have, the question of context—both social and generational. Again and again,
Paine defends the prerogatives of the individual and derides all that presses upon
his freedom of action. Again and again, Burke insists that no man is an island
and no individual exists apart from society.
Two sets of concerns—those regarding the individual and the community,
and those regarding the present and the past—are therefore constant themes of
both Burke’s and Paine’s political thought. Paine believes that human beings are
best understood apart from the community and the past, as complete and
sufficient individuals endowed with natural rights whose interactions are
functions of their individual choices and actions. Both tradition and society
should be put aside when contemplating questions of political principle and
action, because both are consequences of politics, not sources of it. Burke
believes that human beings are best understood in their social and historical
settings, as members of their communities with obligations to each other and as
the recipients of a valuable inheritance from the past—an inheritance that they
are charged to improve and pass along.
But as we review the particulars of the Burke-Paine debate laid out in the
previous chapters, these two sets of concerns—about tradition and community—
appear to collapse into one. The argument over tradition and the past
encompasses the dispute over community for both Burke and Paine. It is the
given world—those conditions we are born into without choice—that to Burke’s
eyes make the theory of individualism inadequate. Because human generations
are not independent of one another, human individuals are not independent of
one another, either. The facts of human birth and death and the social institutions
built around them link individuals, families, and communities inexorably, and to
pretend otherwise (let alone to sever their links) would be disastrous for political
life.
For Paine, meanwhile, the theory of individualism relies on an explanatory
device (the “state of nature”) that takes the first human generation as its model—
a generation for whom there was no given past. To apply a theory based on that
premise is to deny the authority and significance of human generations and thus
of tradition—and Paine is not shy about making that clear. The independence of
individuals from their neighbors is a function of the independence of generations
from their predecessors; this independence in the first generation is the essence
of the theory of Enlightenment liberalism, which applies its timeless principles
to all subsequent generations as well.
Thus, a crucial common thread in the large and varied debates between
Burke and Paine is apparently a dispute about the status of the past in political
life. And both Burke and Paine are exceptionally explicit about its significance
and take up the question of the meaning of the past in an uncommonly overt
way. Paine’s abhorrence of inherited government is the core of his political
philosophy, for he sees inherited government as essentially opposed to nature,
choice, reason, and justice. He wants to look past history and tradition to nature,
and therefore to look past given obligations to created choices, beyond received
wisdom to pure reason, and beyond mere cumulative reforms to total revolution.
Burke, meanwhile, says the model of inheritance is the model of nature, the
appropriate means of understanding and meeting our obligations, the core of
prescription, and the key to reform.
Both men are students of political change, and in a certain respect all of the
themes taken up in this book are aspects of a dispute about change: its purpose,
its character, its means, and its ends. But Burke’s and Paine’s views of the matter
always clearly draw on this deep disagreement about the nature and meaning of
the relations between generations. For Paine, the disjunction between the
permanent principles of politics and the inherited realities of social and political
life demands a revolutionary transformation—a break with the past to bring the
real into alignment with the ideal made known by reason. For Burke, the evolved
forms of political life, which are a valued inheritance, offer both the means and
the ends of political change. When problems arise, society can employ its
political institutions to address them, as those institutions have developed slowly
over time to serve that purpose. But when a problem is too large for those
institutions to contend with and thereby threatens their survival, statesmen must
reform the institutions in an effort to strengthen and preserve them, so that these
institutions might be passed down to future generations who will use them in the
same way. This arrangement calls for gradual change in response to discrete
needs and problems, informed by a profound respect for the given order—
because for Burke the real is the only reliable means of grasping the ideal.

HERE WE FIND THE TRUE BOTTOM of the Burke-Paine debate, and from
here we can begin to appreciate how their differences have helped to shape our
own. They disagreed about whether some basic aspects of the human condition,
especially the facts that we are all born and that we all die, should decisively
shape human societies. Paine’s assertive, confident, rationalist, technocratic, and
progressive outlook held that through the right kinds of political arrangements,
man could overcome the limits that these facts might impose and he could
therefore reshape his world to his preferences and even end the long-standing
scourges of injustice, war, and suffering. Burke’s grateful, protective, cautious,
pious, gradualist, and reformist outlook held that man could only hope to
improve his circumstances if he understood his own limits, built on the
achievements of those who came before him to repair their errors, and realized
that some profound human miseries and vices are permanent functions of our
nature—and that pretending otherwise would only make them worse.
Both are modern attitudes, and both are liberal too, but they disagree about
just what modernity and liberalism mean. Indeed, that very disagreement has
ultimately come to define modern liberalism.
CONCLUSION

DMUND BURKE AND THOMAS PAINE KNEW THAT THE heated

E controversies that had shaped their public lives would not end with their
deaths. In fact, both of them worried that they might not be allowed to
rest in peace, quite literally.
As he lay ill in 1797, Burke expressed his dread that should the French
radicals and their allies in Britain succeed in spreading their revolution across
the channel, they would exhume his body from its resting place to make an
example of their staunch opponent. He gave instructions that he should be buried
in an unmarked grave kept apart from that of his son and from the plot reserved
for his wife, so that his fate need not be theirs. In the end, Burke’s family and
friends decided to follow the guidance of his written will instead of this fevered
deathbed plea, and he was buried alongside his son in a grave bearing the family
name in a Beaconsfield churchyard, where his wife joined them some fifteen
years later.1
Paine, too, found himself uneasy about the fate of his earthly remains and
reasoned that his enemies (whom he assumed would be motivated by his
writings against biblical religion) would be deterred only by the sanctity of a
Christian cemetery. The adamant Deist (if not atheist) therefore ironically sought
ultimate protection under the religion of his fathers, leaving this request in his
will: “I know not if the Society of people called Quakers admit a person to be
buried in their burying ground who does not belong to their Society, but if they
do, or will admit me, I would prefer being buried there; my father belonged to
that profession, and I was partly brought up in it. But if it is not consistent with
their rules to do this, I desire to be buried on my own farm at New Rochelle.”2
The Quakers in the end did not allow it, and Paine was indeed buried on his
farm. His fears, moreover, turned out to be better founded than Burke’s, if not
quite for the reasons he expected. Ten years after his death, Paine’s remains were
surreptitiously removed from his New Rochelle grave by William Cobbett, an
English radical who sought to take the body to Britain and erect a glorious
memorial to his hero. But Paine’s antimonarchical views had not been forgotten
in Britain, and the government refused to permit a monument. Cobbett’s gambit
turned into a fiasco and made him a national laughingstock. Worse yet, Paine’s
remains were eventually lost. Their final disposition remains unknown to this
day.
Burke’s and Paine’s exceptional concerns about their legacies should not
surprise us. They were right to assume that their names and their words, if not
their mortal remains, would not be left to rest but would continue to play key
roles in the great debate they had helped launch. Throughout the nineteenth and
twentieth centuries and into the twenty-first, both have been frequently appealed
to by various political movements. Assorted radical leaders the world over—
from the American abolitionist firebrand John Brown to Uruguayan liberator
José Gervasio Artigas and countless others in between—laid claim to the legacy
of Thomas Paine, as did the mainstream labor and progressive movements in the
Anglo-American world. Conservative cultural and political movements—from
Romantic poets to reforming Tories to the conservative movement that emerged
in America in the middle of the last century—have laid claim to Edmund
Burke’s name and ideas.
Ironically, our understanding of the Burke-Paine debate has actually suffered
some from such persistent political attention to both men. The revolutionaries
who adopted Paine as their own would too often infuse his historical memory
with socialist sensibilities that would have been largely foreign to Paine himself.
And a great deal of the commentary (and even the scholarship) regarding Burke,
particularly over the past century, has seemed to want to make him (even) more
temperamentally conservative than he was, in the process overlooking important
strains in his thinking.
There has been some modest tempering of these tendencies in both cases, if
sometimes through equal and opposite distortions: Paine’s role in the American
Revolution, for instance, has caused some American conservatives to give him a
serious look and to emphasize elements of his worldview they find agreeable.
No less an icon of the American right than Ronald Reagan accepted the
Republican Party’s nomination for president in 1980 by reminding his supporters
of Paine’s call for transforming failed governing institutions. Burke’s emphasis
on gradualism, meanwhile, has appealed to some contemporary liberals eager to
resist dramatic transformations of the welfare state. No less an icon of the
American left than Barack Obama has reportedly described himself as a Burkean
eager to avoid sudden change.3
But it is not in these uses and abuses of Burke’s and Paine’s own names and
reputations that we can find the lasting legacy of their debate. By considering the
arguments as each man first made them, and not as assorted partisans across two
centuries have sought to use them, we can see how the worldviews Burke and
Paine laid out still describe two broad and fundamental dispositions toward
political life and political change in our liberal age.
The tension between those two dispositions comes down to some very basic
questions: Should our society be made to answer to the demands of stark and
abstract commitments to ideals like social equality or to the patterns of its own
concrete political traditions and foundations? Should the citizen’s relationship to
his society be defined above all by the individual right of free choice or by a web
of obligations and conventions not entirely of our own choosing? Are great
public problems best addressed through institutions designed to apply the
explicit technical knowledge of experts or by those designed to channel the
implicit social knowledge of the community? Should we see each of our
society’s failings as one large problem to be solved by comprehensive
transformation or as a set of discrete imperfections to be addressed by building
on what works tolerably well to address what does not? What authority should
the character of the given world exercise over our sense of what we would like it
to be?
These questions build on one another, and step by subtle step, they add up to
quite distinct ways of thinking about politics. Every person looks upon his
country and sees a mix of good things and bad. But which strike us more
powerfully? In confronting the society around us, are we first grateful for what
works well about it and moved to reinforce and build on that, or are we first
outraged by what works poorly and moved to uproot and transform it?
Our answers will tend to shape how we think about particular political
questions. Do we want to fix our health-care system by empowering expert
panels armed with the latest effectiveness data to manage the system from the
center or by arranging economic incentives to channel consumer knowledge and
preferences and address some of the system’s discrete problems? Do we want to
alleviate poverty through large national programs that use public dollars to
supplement the incomes of the poor or through efforts to build on the social
infrastructure of local civil-society institutions to help the poor build the skills
and habits to rise? Do we want problems addressed through the most
comprehensive and broadest possible means or through the most minimal and
targeted ones? People’s answers to such questions likely fall into a pattern. And
the answers depend not only on our opinion of the state of our particular society
at this moment but also on our assumptions about how much knowledge and
power social reformers can really expect to have, and of what sort.
Ultimately, the answers depend as well on people’s implicit notion of what
our political order—what modern liberalism—really is, exactly. Is it a set of
principles that were discovered by Enlightenment philosophers and that should
be put more and more completely into practice so that our society can
increasingly resemble those philosophers’ ideal mix of egalitarianism and
liberty? Or is it a living culture built up over countless generations of social trial
and error so that by the time of the Enlightenment, especially in Britain, society
had taken a form that allowed for an exceptional mix of egalitarianism and
liberty? Is liberalism, in other words, a theoretical discovery to be put into effect
or a practical achievement to be reinforced and perfected? These two
possibilities suggest two rather different sorts of liberal politics: a politics of
vigorous progress toward an ideal goal or a politics of preservation and
perfection of a precious inheritance. They suggest, in other words, a progressive
liberalism and a conservative liberalism.

THE TWO PARTIES TO our political debates still very often answer to these
general descriptions. But of course, they do not answer to them perfectly or quite
consistently. Burke and Paine offer us a window into the birth of the right and
the left, but to see the birth of an idea is not to see its developed state. How both
the right and the left have changed from the views laid out by Burke and Paine is
at least as interesting as how their views have persisted. This book can, of
course, barely scratch the surface of that complex evolution, but even the very
broadest outlines can help us see how Burke and Paine remain deeply relevant
both as instructive points of origin and as useful correctives for today’s right and
left.
The fundamental utopian goal at the core of Paine’s thinking—the goal of
liberating the individual from the constraints of the obligations imposed upon
him by his time, his place, and his relations to others—remains essential to the
left in America. But the failure of Enlightenment-liberal principles and the
institutions built upon them to deliver on that bold ambition and therefore on
Paine’s hopes of eradicating prejudice, poverty, and war seemed to force the left
into a choice between the natural-rights theories that Paine thought would offer
means of attaining his goal and the goal itself. In time, the utopian goal was
given preference, and a vision of the state as a direct provider of basic
necessities and largely unencumbered by the restraints of Paine’s Enlightenment
liberalism arose to advance it.
We can begin to discern the earliest roots of this way of thinking in Paine’s
own later revolutionary writings, when he proposes a primordial welfare state.
But it advanced a fair bit from Paine’s views as over time, some American
progressives, influenced by European social-democratic thinking, came to
believe in an assertive national government. They thought such a government
could both provide some material benefits and clear away some of the social and
civic institutions that stood between the individual and the state (institutions that
they considered, as Paine did, carriers of backwardness and prejudice). In this
way, the government could free people simultaneously from material want and
from direct moral obligations to those immediately around them. Such a
government would make people more equal to one another and freer of one
another, and thus better able to exercise their individual choices.
Today’s left plainly exhibits this combination of material collectivism and
moral individualism. The role it affords to the government and its links to
European social thought might at first suggest that this attitude leans toward
communitarianism. But its American form is actually a radical form of
individualism, moved by much the same passion for justice that Paine had and
by much the same desire to free people of the fetters of tradition, religion, and
the moral or social expectations of those around them.
The deep commitment to generational continuity and to the institutions of
implicit social knowledge that we have found at the core of Burke’s thought
remains essential to today’s American right, meanwhile. But as Burke himself
noted, different societies form such institutions differently, and Americans in
particular have always been “men of free character and spirit” to an exceptional
degree.4 This, and the simple fact that American conservatives are conserving a
political tradition begun in a revolution (even if it was not as radical a revolution
as Paine insists), has long made the American right more inclined both to resort
to theory and to appeal to individualism than Burke was. And the two tendencies
are connected: The theory of American political thought most often and most
readily at hand for today’s conservatives is an adaptation of the very same
natural-rights theories that Paine, Jefferson, and other Enlightenment-liberal
founders of America had championed, but which the left eventually abandoned.
The tradition of conservative liberalism—the gradual accumulation of practices
and institutions of freedom and order that Burke celebrated as the English
constitution and that in many important respects the American revolution sought
to preserve (not to reject) on this side of the Atlantic—has only rarely been
articulated in American terms. For this reason, it is not often heard on the lips of
today’s conservatives.
And yet, this very same conservative liberalism is very frequently the vision
they pursue in practice. It is the vision conservatives advance when they defend
traditional social institutions and the family, seek to make our culture more
hospitable to children, and rail against attempts at technocratic expert
government. It is the vision they uphold when they insist on an allegiance to our
forefathers’ constitutional forms, warn of the dangers of burdening our children
with debt to fund our own consumption, or insist that the sheer scope and
ambition of our government makes it untenable.
Today’s left, therefore, shares a great portion of Paine’s basic disposition, but
seeks to liberate the individual in a rather less quixotic and more technocratic
way than Paine did, if also in a way that lacks his grounding in principle and
natural right. Thus today’s liberals are left philosophically adrift and far too open
to the cold logic of utilitarianism—they could learn from Paine’s insistence on
limits to the use of power and the role of government. Today’s right, meanwhile,
shares a great deal of Burke’s basic disposition, but seeks to protect our cultural
inheritance in a less aristocratic and (naturally, for Americans) more populist
way than he did, if also in a way that lacks his emphasis on community and on
the sentiments. Today’s conservatives are thus too rhetorically strident and far
too open to the siren song of hyperindividualism, and they generally lack a
nonradical theory of the liberal society. They could benefit by adopting Burke’s
focus on the social character of man, from Burke’s thoroughgoing gradualism,
and from his innovative liberal alternative to Enlightenment radicalism.
Both sides of our politics therefore exhibit in practice deep continuities to their
intellectual forerunners, despite being barely aware of these connections, and
would be well served by better understanding them. Each group might find some
of its worst excesses alleviated a bit by carefully considering the Burke-Paine
debate.
One peculiar feature of some prominent contemporary policy debates can
make this historical continuity of the left-right divide particularly difficult to see
and so is worth a further word. As the great economic debate of the last century
has loosened its grip on our politics with the fall of communism and the waning
of socialist ideas, American political life has come to be defined by the social-
democratic welfare state and its mounting difficulties. Today’s progressives are
thus often engaged in a struggle to preserve a set of public entitlement programs
that their predecessors built over the past century (often employing arguments
that, in the cause of preservation, sound downright Burkean). Meanwhile,
today’s conservatives seek to transform some key governing institutions (often
resorting to arguments from classical-liberal principles that ring of Paine). The
rhetoric of some key domestic debates therefore sometimes seems almost like a
mirror image of the original left-right debate.
But this is a kind of second-order argument about political change—a debate
about reforming a set of welfare-state institutions that are themselves intended to
advance a certain vision of change. The vision is a progressive archetype that
Paine would certainly have recognized: an egalitarian ideal of justice advanced
through the application of technical expertise regarding society within a liberal
framework. Opposing it is a more conservative ideal that Burke would have
found familiar: a case for addressing social problems through evolved
institutions (like the family, civil society, religious groups, and markets) that
tacitly contain and convey implicit knowledge within a liberal framework. It is
very much another instance of the general pattern of ideological division that we
have traced back to Burke and Paine’s era.
For all that they have certainly evolved over two centuries, the two sides of
our politics still often express the basic underlying dispositions—toward
progress and tradition, choice and obligation, technocratic prowess and a worldly
skepticism—evident in Paine and Burke. When it is most itself, each of our
parties rather plainly fits the profile that emerges from our study of the great
debate of the age of revolutions.

IT MAY BE STRANGE TO THINK that just a few layers beneath our bubbling
and contentious political debates there still lurk such profound questions of
political philosophy. But as both the lives and the arguments of Burke and Paine
help show us, political events are always tied up with political ideas, and seeing
those ties can shed a bright light on both the events and the ideas. Philosophy
moves history, especially in times of profound social change. And ours, like
Burke and Paine’s, is surely such a time.
Burke and Paine agreed that politics is always in flux and that the challenge
of the statesman is to govern change for the benefit of society. The practical
questions that divided them and shaped their assorted theoretical explorations
and arguments began from this basic reality. But to what ends, and by what
means, should people alter their political and cultural arrangements? Burke and
Paine’s debate may not provide an ultimate answer, but it offers an unusually
deep and serious engagement with a question we must still confront.
In our day-to-day political arguments, we hear echoes of a deeper debate that
we easily mistake for remnants of an argument between capitalism and
socialism, or for faint precursors of a long-predicted ultimate clash between
religious traditionalism and secular cosmopolitanism. But more likely, these
echoes are in fact reminders of the defining disagreement of the political order of
modern liberalism. That disagreement was given early and unusually clear voice
by Edmund Burke and Thomas Paine, and becomes far easier to comprehend
when we pay careful attention to what they have to teach us.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

HIS BOOK HAS BEEN LONG IN COMING, AND SO HAS left me

T with enormous debts to many people whose support, guidance, good will,
and (in no small measure) patience have made it possible.
It began in the Committee on Social Thought at the University of
Chicago, where I found to my amazement teachers and students engaged in a
genuine search for understanding and committed to a kind of scholarship that,
had I not witnessed it myself, I might have easily imagined was entirely a thing
of the past. I owe special thanks to Ralph Lerner, whose generous spirit,
enthusiasm, astonishing breadth of knowledge, and abiding good humor helped
make this work a joy. Nathan Tarcov, too, offered a model of deep and devoted
engagement with texts. And Leon Kass, who was the first reader of this book,
has been far more than a teacher but a mentor and model—both professional and
personal. My debt to him is greater than I could hope to repay.
Although my research began in Chicago, this book was written almost
entirely in Washington, where I have built up debts to many other scholars and
friends. Alan Levine of American University and Patrick Deneen (then of
Georgetown University and now of the University of Notre Dame) were
particularly helpful. And Adam Keiper, in this as in so much else, has been
beyond invaluable—for among his countless talents he is a superb editor. More
important, he is a treasured friend.
Since 2007, I have been privileged to hang my hat at the Ethics and Public
Policy Center in Washington, and much of my work on this book was done
there. It is an island of collegiality and intellectual engagement in a city where
both are too often lacking, and for that I am grateful to its president, Ed Whelan,
and to my colleagues. Since 2009, I have also been lucky enough to serve as
editor of National Affairs magazine, and my wonderful team of colleagues there
has made it a joy—my thanks to them all. Neither this book nor my other work
in recent years could have been possible without the generous support,
encouragement, and guidance of Roger Hertog, for which I am deeply grateful.
I am grateful, also, to a variety of colleagues, advisors, and friends who read
parts or all of this manuscript and offered their wisdom and guidance. They
include especially Adam White, George Weigel, Hillel Ofek, Michael Aronson,
Scott Galupo, Peter Wehner, my brother Yariv Levin, and (the late) Daniel Bell. I
was also privileged to have a series of conversations about Thomas Paine with
the late Christopher Hitchens in what turned out to be the last year of his life,
which deeply shaped my thinking about Paine and his ambitions.
In any project like this, one inevitably also accumulates debts to librarians,
who have only become more important in the age of the internet. For me, this
was especially the case with Thomas Paine’s writings, which still cry out for an
authoritative scholarly collection. The librarians of the Regenstein Library at the
University of Chicago, the manuscripts collection of the Library of Congress, the
British Library, and the library of the American Philosophical Society in
Philadelphia offered invaluable help, in some cases remotely under
circumstances that could not have been convenient for them. And I am of course
much indebted to the many scholars cited in the bibliography and throughout the
text, for their work and in some cases for personal conversations and guidance
beyond.
At Basic Books, I have been very fortunate to work with Tim Bartlett—a
learned and gifted editor who understood precisely what my manuscript was,
what this book should be, and how to turn the former into the latter. Kaitlyn
Zafonte managed to keep both Tim and me (and always a great deal more, it
seemed) on track; Collin Tracy and Patty Boyd showed the kind of meticulous
care every writer hopes for in a production and editing team; and Nicole Caputo
made the final product look its best. I am very grateful to them all.
My greatest debt, however, is as always to my family. I am grateful to my
parents for more than I could ever say. I am grateful to my children, Maya and
Sam, for the profound joy they bring to our lives.
But above all, I am grateful to, and grateful for, my wonderful wife, Cecelia,
who is the embodiment of that “unbought grace of life” that we are privileged to
enjoy though we could never truly deserve. Aside from an inexplicable failure of
judgment in her selection of a spouse, she has always seemed to me just perfect.
I dedicate this book to her with love, because it is from her that I have learned
what love and dedication really mean.
NOTES

INTRODUCTION
1. Copeland, Our Eminent Friend Edmund Burke, 148.
2. As we will see, because the term liberal is itself a matter of significant
contention between Burke and Paine, the term will usually be modified when it
appears in this book. Enlightenment liberalism will refer to the political ideas
(drawn especially from John Locke but refined and at times also altered by some
of his intellectual successors) at the heart of the thinking of many English
Whigs. With some important differences, the term also refers to the ideals of
many revolutionaries in America and France—especially government by the
consent of the governed, and natural rights underlying political association.
Radical liberalism will describe more extreme variants of the same approach to
politics—variants that insisted on a thoroughly republican form of government
and entertained the notion of overthrowing the monarchy. Classical-liberal, used
just once in the book, describes a more moderate (and later) variant of liberalism
greatly influenced by the British reaction against the French Revolution, and by
Edmund Burke. In the conclusion, I will also use conservative liberalism to
describe an element of the political thought of Edmund Burke—which viewed
liberalism as a practical achievement of the English legal and political tradition,
rather than as a discovery of principles against which that tradition (and others)
should be measured. These definitions will be further refined in later chapters,
but the terms are, of course, necessarily shorthand and therefore somewhat
anachronistic (indeed, while the word liberal was commonly used in Burke’s and
Paine’s time, the word liberalism did not emerge until the second decade of the
nineteenth century). Nevertheless, the terms are used here with the same
meanings they are widely given in modern scholarship regarding the period.
3. Edmund Burke, The Writings and Speeches of Edmund Burke, ed. Paul
Langford (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1981–) (hereinafter cited as Burke,
Writings), 8: 293. This collection, once completed, will include all of Burke’s
available speeches and writings with the exception of personal correspondence.
Two crucial volumes in the collection still remain to be published, so that a
significant number of Burke’s writings, especially of the early 1790s, will be
cited from other collections and noted as such.
4. Burke, On Empire, Liberty, and Reform: Speeches and Letters of Edmund
Burke, 11.
5. Edmund Burke, The Correspondence of Edmund Burke, ed. Thomas
Copeland (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1967) (hereinafter cited as
Burke, Correspondence), 6: 303. This collection includes all of Burke’s available
personal correspondence.
6. Thomas Paine, Life and Writings of Thomas Paine, ed. Daniel Wheeler
(New York: Vincent Parke & Company, 1915) (hereinafter cited as Paine,
Writings), 5: 18n. This ten-volume collection includes all of Paine’s publications
and the bulk of his personal correspondence. Unless otherwise noted, all
references to Paine’s writings are drawn from this collection. In a few instances,
cited personal letters that are available only in other, and otherwise less
complete, collections will be noted individually.
7. Jefferson, The Political Writings of Thomas Jefferson, 207.
8. This letter to John Inskeep, mayor of Philadelphia, is included in Paine,
The Complete Writings of Thomas Paine, 2: 1480, but not in Paine, Life and
Writings of Thomas Paine, which is used for most other Paine citations.
9. Burke, Writings, 9: 31.

CHAPTER 1: TWO LIVES IN THE ARENA


1. Burke, Correspondence, 5: 412.
2. Paine, Writings, 4: xv.
3. Some recent historical detective work by historian F. P. Lock suggests
Burke might have actually been born in January 1730 (Lock, Edmund Burke, 1:
16–17). In fact, the date (and especially the year) of his birth has been a subject
of a long-standing scholarly dispute dating back at least to Dixon Wecter’s 1937
essay “Burke’s Birthday” (though, with lesser scholarly probity, really all the
way back to his earliest biographers), with plausible claims placing it anywhere
from 1728 to 1730. Lock’s 1998 analysis of the evidence is compelling but
hardly conclusive, especially because the case for 1729 is buttressed by
contemporary accounts. Having no new evidence in this controversy, I have
simply followed the substantial majority of modern Burke scholars who place
his birth in January 1729.
4. Morley, Burke, 24–25.
5. Burke, Writings, 1: 221.
6. Walpole, Horace Walpole’s Correspondence, 9: 380.
7. Burke, Writings, 8: 206.
8. Burke, Writings, 3: 483.
9. Burke, Writings, 3: 64–70.
10. Burke, Writings, 2: 196.
11. Ibid., 252.
12. Ibid., 458. As we will see in some detail in Chapter 2, however, this does
not mean that Burke rejected all applications of theory to politics.
13. Paine, Writings, 5: 32–33.
14. Robbins, “The Lifelong Education of Thomas Paine,” 135–142.
15. Cited in Nelson, Thomas Paine, 44.
16. Franklin, The Works of Benjamin Franklin, 361.
17. Paine, Writings, 2: 113–118.
18. Ibid., 196.
19. Paine frequently uses the term republican, which he defines rather
carefully in the second part of his Rights of Man, as discussed in a later chapter.
My use of it throughout follows his definition (which also mirrors Burke’s
understanding of the term). Thus, republican refers not to a specific system of
government but to an approach to government. This approach begins from a
thoroughgoing rejection of hereditary monarchy and then seeks to establish on
rational principles of utility a system of government that is maximally
answerable to the people.
20. Paine, Writings, 2: 75.
21. Exact sales and readership figures for this period are of course
unobtainable. Kaye, Thomas Paine, 56–57, notes that about 150,000 copies of
the pamphlet were apparently distributed by printers and publishers—an
immense number for the time. Conway, Life of Thomas Paine, 25, reports a
similar number from several contemporary sources. Paine himself, with his
customary modesty, states in Rights of Man that Common Sense was an utterly
unprecedented literary event and “the success it met with was beyond anything
since the invention of printing” (Paine, Writings, 5: 18n). This, of course, is a
rather less reliable report.
22. Washington, The Writings of George Washington, 3: 347.
23. Paine, Writings, 3:1.
24. Paine, Writings, 4: 220.
25. Burke, Writings, 3: 305–306.
26. Burke’s earliest biographer, Robert Bisset, plainly asserts such a meeting
occurred, but Thomas Copeland, after poring over the evidence, argues that it
appears unlikely to have happened and that the two men met for the first time
only in 1788. (Copeland, Our Eminent Friend Edmund Burke, 155–156.)
Subsequent biographers have concurred with Copeland’s view, while
acknowledging that it cannot be proven conclusively.
27. Burke, Correspondence, 5: 415.
28. Quoted in Copeland, Our Eminent Friend Edmund Burke, 160.
29. Edmund Burke, “An Appeal from the New to the Old Whigs,” in Further
Reflections on the Revolution in France, ed. Daniel Ritchie (Indianapolis:
Liberty Fund, 1992) (hereinafter cited as Burke, Appeal), 136n. I have used this
Ritchie collection for the Appeal throughout this book, as the volume of the
Oxford collection of Burke’s writings that will include that essay has yet to be
published.
30. Paine, Writings, 5: 106–107.
31. Burke, Correspondence, 6: 1.
32. Fox made the remark in a letter on July 30, 1789. It is quoted and
discussed in Evans, Debating the Revolution, 12.
33. Burke, Correspondence, 6: 10.
34. Ibid., 30.
35. Burke, Correspondence, 6: 70.
36. Ibid.
37. MacCoby, ed., The English Radical Tradition, 54.
38. Price, The Correspondence of Richard Price, 260.
39. Burke, Writings, 8: 59.
40. Edmund Burke, The Writings and Speeches of Edmund Burke (Boston:
Little, Brown & Co., 1901) (hereinafter cited as Burke, Writings and Speeches),
3: 221. (A partial text of this speech, which Burke did not set down himself but
which was published in the parliamentary record, is made available in this older
edition of Burke’s writings and speeches, but not in the contemporary academic
edition otherwise used for most references.) 41. Burke, Correspondence, 6: 46.
42. Burke, Writings, 8: 116.
43. Ibid., 108.
44. Ibid., 136.
45. Ibid., 293.
46. Fennessy, Burke, Paine, and the Rights of Man, 1.
47. For details of its circulation, see W. B. Todd’s meticulously researched
study “The Bibliographical History of Burke’s Reflections on the Revolution in
France,” 100–108.
48. Paine, Writings, 4: 69.
49. Ibid., 104.
50. Ibid., 143.
51. Paine, Writings, 2: 90.
52. Paine, Writings, 4: 200.
53. Ibid., 201.
54. Paine himself, in a letter to John Hall, claimed the book sold more than
fifty–six thousand copies, but he offers no evidence and scholars generally
express serious doubts about that figure (Paine, The Complete Writings of
Thomas Paine, 2: 1,321–1,322). In any case, Paine’s book clearly sold far more
copies than Burke’s. (Conway, The Life of Thomas Paine, 343).
55. Jefferson, The Papers of Thomas Jefferson, 20: 304.
56. Ibid., 17:671.
57. David Bromwich, “Burke and the Argument from Human Nature,” in
Crowe, ed., An Imaginative Whig, 54–55.
58. Paine, Writings, 5: 97.
59. The episode is ably discussed in Nelson, Thomas Paine, 228.
60. Burke, Writings, 9: 326–327.
61. Paine, Writings, 6: 3.
62. Ibid., 275.

CHAPTER 2: NATURE AND HISTORY


1. Paine, Writings, 2:1.
2. Paine, Writings, 4: 52.
3. As it was the common practice in Burke and Paine’s time and would be
difficult to avoid in discussing their thinking, I will use the singular male “man”
to refer to human beings in general throughout this book.
4. Paine, Writings, 4: 53.
5. Ibid., 266.
6. Ibid., 54.
7. Paine, Writings, 8: 294–295.
8. Paine, Writings, 4: 227.
9. Claeys, Thomas Paine, 94, argues that this emphasis on the distinction
between society and government and the antistatist implications of this
distinction are among Paine’s most significant original contributions to political
thought.
10. Paine, Writings, 4: 226.
11. Ibid., 221.
12. Paine, Writings, 2: 90.
13. Paine, Writings, 4: 255–256.
14. Ibid., 197.
15. Ibid., 240.
16. Ibid., 291. Paine also uses the identical formulation later in the same
chapter of the Rights of Man (ibid., 305).
17. Paine, Writings, 2: 5–6.
18. Ibid., 237–238.
19. Ibid., 265.
20. Ibid., 4.
21. Paine, Writings, 4: 193–194.
22. Paine, Writings, 2: 79.
23. Ibid., 20–21.
24. Burke, Writings, 8: 213. Similarly, Burke writes in a 1790 letter to
Thomas Mercer that over the course of centuries, “that which might be wrong in
the beginning is consecrated by time and becomes lawful” (Burke,
Correspondence, 6: 95).
25. Burke, Writings, 6: 316–317.
26. There are, of course, other exceptions to this rule, including most notably
Machiavelli on numerous occasions in his descriptions of Rome in the
Discourses on Livy
27. Burke, Writings, 8: 331.
28. Paine, Writings, 4: 150.
29. Burke, Writings, 8: 112.
30. Ibid.
31. Burke, Correspondence, 6: 48.
32. Burke, Appeal, 168–169.
33. Bromwich, “Burke and the Argument from Human Nature,” in Crowe,
ed., An Imaginative Whig, 48.
34. Burke, Appeal, 179. Emphasis in original.
35. Ibid., 163–164.
36. Burke, Writings, 8: 206.
37. Ibid., 111.
38. Ibid., 112.
39. Ibid., 189.
40. Ibid., 115.
41. Burke, Writings, 1: 198.
42. Burke, Writings, 2: 196.
43. See especially Burke’s adamant rejection of Rousseau’s sentimentalism
in his 1791 “Letter to a Member of the National Assembly” (Burke, Writings,
8:312–317).
44. Burke, Writings and Speeches, 11: 237.
45. Burke, Writings, 8: 128.
46. Burke, Writings, 2: 252.
47. “Character of Mr. Burke,” in Hazlitt, The Collected Works of William
Hazlitt, 7: 306.
48. Burke, Writings, 8: 101, and 3: 396.
49. Burke, Writings, 8:131 (emphasis in original).
50. Ibid., 133.
51. Ibid., 137.
52. This case is nicely outlined in Fennessy, Burke, Paine, and the Rights of
Man, 121–123.
53. Burke, Writings, 8: 128.
54. Ibid.
55. Ibid., 126–127.
56. Burke, Correspondence, 6: 86–87.
57. Paine, Writings, 4: 24.
58. Burke, Writings, 8: 128.
59. Ibid., 84.
60. Burke, Writings, 9: 188.
61. Ibid.
62. Burke, Appeal, 87–88.
63. Burke, Writings, 9: 634.

CHAPTER 3: JUSTICE AND ORDER


1. Paine, Writings, 4: 26.
2. Burke makes this clearest in a letter to his friend Phillip Francis in 1791
(Burke, Correspondence, 6: 90–91).
3. Burke, Appeal, 89.
4. Paine, Writings, 4: 40.
5. The term “procedural conservative” is used especially in Hampsher-Monk,
The Political Philosophy of Edmund Burke.
6. Charles Vaughn, one of the great twentieth-century readers of Burke,
argued that Burke “stood side by side with Hume and Bentham in their assault
upon abstract ideas of right, in their constant reference of everything to
expediency” (Vaughan, Studies in the History of Political Philosophy Before and
After Rousseau, 2: 19). John Morley, perhaps Burke’s best nineteenth-century
biographer, called himself “a Burkean and a Benthamite,” on similar grounds
(Morley, Recollections, 1: 232–233). The majority of Burke’s twentieth-century
interpreters took him at least to be dramatically deemphasizing the significance
of a moral standard in politics. Burkeanism, in this sense, is considered a
disposition, not a theory, of politics, and mostly a disposition about change,
which, as Hampsher-Monk, The Political Philosophy of Edmund Burke, 28, has
put it recently, “claims to identify no ideal.”
7. Mansfield, Statesmanship and Party Government, 245.
8. Burke, Writings, 9: 455.
9. Burke, Appeal, 176–177.
10. Burke, Writings, 9: 456.
11. This school of Burke scholars was exemplified by Peter Stanlis and his
important 1958 book Edmund Burke and the Natural Law.
12. Ibid., 84.
13. “If I were to call for a reward,” Burke wrote when reflecting on his
career in his final year of life, “it would be for the services in which for fourteen
years, without intermission, I showed the most industry and had the least
success. I mean the affairs of India; they are those on which I value myself the
most; most for the importance; most for the labor; most for the judgment; most
for constancy and perseverance in the pursuit” (Burke, Writings, 9: 159).
14. Burke, Writings, 6: 459.
15. Burke, Writings, 9: 572.
16. Burke, Correspondence, 4: 416.
17. Burke, Writings, 9: 463.
18. Burke, Writings, 8: 145.
19. Ibid.
20. Ibid., 142–143.
21. Ibid., 146.
22. Ibid., 290.
23. Ibid., 148.
24. Ibid., 142. At several periods in his career, and especially in the early
1770s and again in the wake of the French Revolution, Burke was exceptionally
hostile to all forms of atheism, employing a tone and vehemence rarely found in
even in his most passionate writings on other subjects. “The most horrid and
cruel blow that can be offered to civil society is through atheism,” he argues in
his Speech on the Relief of Protestant Dissenters in 1773. “These are the people
against whom you ought to aim the shaft of law; these are the men to whom,
arrayed in all the terrors of government, I would say ’you shall not degrade us
into brutes’. . . the infidels are outlaws of the constitution not of this country but
of the human race. They are never, never, never to be supported, never to be
tolerated. Under the systematic attacks of these people, I see some of the props
of good government already begin to fail; I see propagated principles which will
not leave to religion even a toleration. I see myself sinking every day under the
attacks of these wretched people” (Burke, Writings, 2: 88).
25. “The institutions savour of superstition in their very principle; and they
nourish it by a permanent and standing influence,” Burke writes of French
Catholic priests. “This I do not mean to dispute; but this ought not to hinder you
from deriving from superstition itself any resources which may thence be
furnished for the public advantage” (Burke, Writings, 8: 207–208).
26. Ibid., 151.
27. Burke, Appeal, 199.
28. Burke, Writings, 6: 350.
29. Burke, Writings, 8: 213.
30. “We cannot change the nature of things, and of men, but must act upon
them the best we can,” Burke writes (Burke, Correspondence, 6: 392).
31. Burke, Correspondence, 2: 281–282. He makes a nearly identical point in
Burke, Writings, 9: 269.
32. Burke, Writings, 2: 282.
33. Burke, Writings, 3: 120.
34. Burke, Writings, 2: 196.
35. Burke, Writings, 8: 220.
36. Burke, Correspondence, 6: 48.
37. Burke, Writings, 8: 205.
38. Burke, Writings, 5: 382.
39. Burke, Correspondence, 3: 403.
40. Burke, Writings, 8: 100.
41. Ibid.
42. Ibid., 88.
43. Ibid., 101.
44. Ibid., 103. Or as he puts it earlier in the Reflections, “I do not hesitate to
say that the road to eminence and power from obscure condition ought not to be
made too easy, nor a thing too much of course. If rare merit be the rarest of all
rare things, it ought to pass through some sort of probation. The temple of honor
ought to be seated on an eminence. If it be opened through virtue, let it be
remembered, too, that virtue is never tried but by some difficulty and some
struggle. . . . Everything ought to be open—but not indifferently to every man”
(Ibid. 101).
45. Ibid., 95.
46. Burke, Appeal, 198.
47. Stanlis, Edmund Burke and the Natural Law, 186.
48. Burke, Appeal, 168.
49. “Men qualified in the manner I have just described, form in nature, as she
operates in the common modification of society, the leading, guiding, and
governing part. It is the soul to the body, without which the man does not exist.
To give therefore no more importance, in the social order, to such descriptions of
men, than that of so many units, is an horrible usurpation” (Burke, Appeal, 168–
169).
50. Burke, Writings, 8: 100–101.
51. Ibid., 233.
52. Ibid., 97.
53. Ibid., 174.
54. Ibid., 259.
55. Ibid., 128.
56. David Bromwich, in Crowe, ed., An Imaginative Whig, 46, notes Burke’s
several allusions to “the natural equality of all mankind” and suggests that
“Burke must have meant, above all, equality before the law.” But in the context
in which these references appear, especially the context of Hastings’s actions in
India, this explanation seems implausible. Burke appears, rather, to refer to a
general equality of material nature, which he does not, however, take simply to
imply a political or social equality.
57. Burke, Correspondence, 3: 403.
58. Burke, Writings, 8: 110.
59. Ibid., 127.
60. Ibid., 87.
61. Paine, Writings, 2: 50.
62. Ibid., 19.
63. Ibid., 12.
64. Ibid., 195.
65. Paine, Writings, 9: 243.
66. Paine, Writings, 4: 234.
67. Ibid., 297–298.
68. Ibid., 247.
69. “That property will ever be unequal is certain,” Paine writes in his
Dissertations on First Principles of Government in 1795. “Industry, superiority
of talents, dexterity of management, extreme frugality, fortunate opportunities, or
the opposite, or the means of those things, will ever produce that effect, without
having recourse to the harsh, ill-sounding names of avarice and oppression”
(Paine, Writings, 9: 262).

CHAPTER 4: CHOICE AND OBLIGATION


1. Paine, The Complete Writings of Thomas Paine, 2: 1,298–1,299.
2. Paine, Writings, 4: 59.
3. Ibid., 59–60.
4. Ibid., 62.
5. Ibid.
6. Ibid., 12.
7. Paine, Writings, 9: 260.
8. Ibid., 161.
9. Burke, Writings, 8: 66.
10. Ibid.
11. Ibid., 73.
12. Burke, Writings and Speeches, 7: 93.
13. Burke, Writings, 8: 81 (emphasis in original).
14. Burke, Writings, 3: 315.
15. Burke, Writings, 8: 174.
16. Ibid. Burke is describing the case made by Aristotle in The Politics,
1.319a–1.320a.
17. Burke, Writings, 8: 174.
18. Burke, Appeal, 157.
19. Ibid., 157–158.
20. Ibid., 162.
21. Ibid., 160.
22. Ibid., 161.
23. Burke, Writings, 8: 316.
24. Burke, Writings and Speeches, 7: 95.
25. Morley, Burke, 239.
26. Burke, Writings, 8: 244.
27. Paine, Writings, 4: 56.
28. Burke, Appeal, 159–160.
29. Burke, Writings, 8: 229.
30. Ibid., 8: 147.
31. Burke, Appeal, 114.
32. Ibid., 163.
33. Paine, Writings, 4: 52.
34. Burke, Writings, 8: 109.
35. Ibid., 109–110.
36. Ibid., 110–111.
37. Ibid., 110.
38. Burke, Writings, 3: 69.
39. Paine, Writings, 4: 148–149.
40. Burke, Writings, 8: 290–291.
41. Burke, Correspondence, 6: 42.
42. Burke, Writings, 3: 59.
43. Burke, Writings, 8: 332.
44. Ibid., 291.
45. Burke, Writings, 3: 318.
46. Ibid., 59.
47. Fennessy, Burke, Paine and the Rights of Man, 38.
48. Paine, Writings, 5: 32–33. Nearly identical sentiments are expressed in
Paine, Writings, 8: 269, and 3: 191.
49. Paine, Writings, 4: 239.
50. Burke, Writings, 8: 97.
51. Ibid., 129.
52. Burke, Appeal, 161.
53. Paine, Writings, 5: 6.
54. Paine, Writings, 8: 240.
55. Burke, Writings, 9: 137.
56. Burke, Writings, 9: 180.
57. Burke, Writings, 8: 209.
58. Burke, Writings, 9: 145.
59. West, Adam Smith, 201.
60. Paine, Writings, 4: 71.
61. Ibid., 227–228.
62. Paine, Writings, 9: 84.
63. Paine, Writings, 5:15.
64. Ibid., 57–58.
65. Ibid., 58.
66. Paine, Writings, 10: 11–12.
67. Ibid., 16–17.
68. Ibid., 25–26.
69. Ibid., 28.

CHAPTER 5: REASON AND PRESCRIPTION


1. Burke, Appeal, 147–148.
2. Burke, Writings, 2: 196.
3. Burke, Writings and Speeches, 7: 97.
4. Ibid., 41.
5. Burke, Writings, 3: 317.
6. Ibid., 157.
7. Burke, Writings, 2: 282.
8. Burke, Correspondence, 2: 372–373.
9. Burke, Writings, 1: 228.
10. Burke, Writings and Speeches, 7: 41.
11. Burke, Writings, 8: 58.
12. Burke, Writings, 3: 313.
13. Burke, Writings, 8: 326. Note, however, that in his writings about
America, India, and France, Burke always worked from his desk and never
traveled to the scene of the action. Paine, meanwhile, although he surely valued
abstract principles of justice more highly, wrote of America from Philadelphia
and of the French Revolution from the heart of the action in Paris. Almost
without exception, he wrote of events in which he was a participant.
14. Ibid., 231–232.
15. Ibid., 232.
16. Ibid., 193.
17. Burke, Correspondence, 6: 46.
18. Burke, Writings, 8: 165.
19. Burke, Writings, 2: 188.
20. Burke, Writings, 1: 207.
21. Burke, Writings, 3: 589.
22. Burke, A Note-Book of Edmund Burke, 68.
23. Burke, Writings, 8: 138.
24. Burke, Appeal, 199.
25. Burke, Writings, 8: 138.
26. Burke, Appeal, 192–193.
27. Burke, Writings, 8: 217.
28. Burke, Writings, 3: 69.
29. Burke, Writings, 8: 217.
30. Paine, Writings, 3: 10.
31. Burke, Writings, 3: 163.
32. Burke, Writings, 2: 317.
33. Ibid., 318.
34. Ibid., 315.
35. Ibid., 320; and Burke, Correspondence, 4: 79.
36. Burke, Appeal, 197.
37. Ibid., 196.
38. Burke, Writings, 3: 139.
39. Burke, Writings and Speeches, 7: 104.
40. Burke, Writings, 8: 86.
41. Burke, Writings and Speeches, 7: 104.
42. Burke, Writings, 8: 137.
43. Ibid., 83.
44. Burke, Correspondence, 6: 158.
45. Burke, Writings, 2: 456.
46. Burke, Writings, 8: 138.
47. Burke, Correspondence, 4: 295.
48. Burke, Writings, 8: 150.
49. Burke, Writings, 3: 492.
50. Burke, Writings, 8: 72.
51. Toward the end of his life, Burke indeed describes that preservation as
his very chief concern. In his final year in Parliament, at a time when he was
persuaded that the radicals would overwhelm the English constitution, he wrote
to Lord Loughborough, “I am heartily sick of politics, and would give any thing
for the means of burying myself in a quiet obscurity, until the Jacobins shall pull
me, with others much my betters, out of it. However, my views are very single;
my principles are very much fixed; my time of political service and natural
existence are very short. With those things strong before my eyes I have but one
idea, in which I wish to be serviceable as long as I live and can serve, which is to
preserve the order of things into which I was born” (Burke, Correspondence, 7:
518–519).
52. Burke, Writings, 8: 83–84.
53. Ibid., 82.
54. Burke, Writings, 2: 194.
55. Burke, Correspondence, 7: 521–522.
56. Burke, Appeal, 91.
57. Burke, Writings, 2: 175.
58. Burke, Appeal, 163.
59. Burke, Writings and Speeches, 7: 14.
60. Of course, Burke himself argues a great deal for and about prescription
—a paradox of which he sometimes seems aware but which he could not avoid
or resolve.
61. Burke, Writings, 3: 319.
62. Burke, Writings, 8: 142.
63. Burke, Appeal, 190–191.
64. Burke, Writings, 8: 214.
65. Burke, Correspondence, 3: 355.
66. Paine, Writings, 4: 306.
67. Paine, Writings, 5: 45.
68. Ibid., 1.
69. Paine, The Complete Writings of Thomas Paine, 2: 1,480.
70. Paine, Writings, 4: 199–200.
71. Ibid., 263.
72. Ibid., 188.
73. Ibid., 263.
74. Ibid., 234.
75. Ibid., 156.
76. Ibid., 21–22. Paine here uncharacteristically (and therefore quite possibly
intentionally) distorts the quotation he offers. In the relevant passage from the
Reflections on the Revolution in France, Burke is making a case against judging
governments in the abstract: “Abstractly speaking, government as well as liberty,
is good; yet could I, in common sense, ten years ago have felicitated France on
her enjoyment of a government (for she then had a government) without inquiry
what the nature of that government was, or how it was administered? Can I now
congratulate the same nation upon its freedom? Is it because liberty in the
abstract may be classed amongst the blessings of mankind that I am seriously to
felicitate a madman who has escaped from the protecting restraint and
wholesome darkness of his cell, on his restoration to the enjoyment of light and
liberty?” (Burke, Writings, 8: 58). In other words, Burke asks a rhetorical
question to which he clearly intends a negative answer, but Paine presents the
remark (having altered the grammar and removed the question mark) as though
it were a positive assertion. It is an extraordinary fact of the literature regarding
Paine’s Rights of Man and the Burke-Paine debate that this distortion is very
rarely noticed.
77. Paine, Writings, 4: 17.
78. Paine, Writings, 5: 211–112.
79. Paine, Writings, 9: 248.
80. Paine, Writings, 4: 291.
81. Paine, Writings, 2: 235. Though he does largely avoid quotations, Paine
does at various places in his writings quote and refer approvingly to Locke,
Montesquieu, Rousseau, Grotius, Adam Smith, and others.
82. Paine, Writings, 6: 267.
83. Ibid., 268.
84. Ibid, 2.
85. Ibid., 10.
86. Ibid., 265.
87. Ibid., 273 and 277.
88. Ibid., 47.
89. Ibid., 3.
90. Paine, Writings, 4: 189–190.
91. Burke, Writings, 8: 110.
92. Paine, Writings, 4: 147.
93. Paine, Writings, 5: 103n.
94. Paine, Writings, 4: 244–245.
95. Ibid., 276.
96. Ibid., 215–216.
97. Paine, Writings, 5: 107.
98. Paine, Writings, 8: 240.
99. Paine, Writings, 4: 286.
100. Ibid., 286–287.
101. Paine, Writings, 10: 275–276.
102. Paine, Writings, 8: 371.
103. Paine, Writings, 4: 164.
104. Ibid., 164–165.
105. Ibid., 234.
106. Ibid., 103.
107. Ibid., 150–151.
108. Ibid., 63–64.
109. Paine, Writings, 2: 5–6.
110. Burke, Writings, 8: 112.
111. Paine, Writings, 4: 244.
112. Burke, Writings and Speeches, 7: 133.
113. Burke, Writings, 8: 293.
114. Paine, Writings, 4: 258.
115. Paine, Writings, 9: 273.
116. Paine, Writings, 2: 52.
117. Paine, Writings, 4: 293.
118. Ibid., 80–81.
119. Ibid., 260.
120. Ibid., 245.
121. Ibid., 83.
122. Ibid., 214.
123. Paine, Writings, 5: 2–3.
124. Ibid., 97–98.
125. Paine, Writings, 9: 270–271.
126. Ibid., 272.
127. Paine, Writings, 4: 306.
128. Ibid.
129. Paine, Writings, 5: 92–93.
130. Paine, Writings, 4: 220.
131. Paine, Writings, 2: xx.
132. Paine, Writings, 8: 195.
133. Ibid., 269.
134. Paine, Writings, 5: 232–233.
135. Ibid., 233.
136. Ibid., 234.
137. Burke, Writings, 3: 126–127.
138. Burke, Writings, 2: 428.
139. Burke, Writings, 3: 135.
140. Burke, Writings, 2: 194.
141. Ibid., 428.
142. Ibid., 428 and 461.
143. Ibid., 111.
144. Burke, Appeal, 106–108.

CHAPTER 6: REVOLUTION AND REFORM


1. Cited in Foner, Tom Paine and Revolutionary America, 270.
2. Ibid., 236–237.
3. Ibid., 19–20.
4. Ibid., 46.
5. Paine, Writings, 4: 212.
6. Paine, Writings, 9: 276.
7. Paine, Writings, 4: 66.
8. Ibid., 232.
9. Ibid., 241.
10. Ibid., 200.
11. Paine, The Complete Writings of Thomas Paine, 2: 281.
12. Paine, Writings, 3: 146.
13. Paine, Writings, 5: 100–101.
14. Paine, Writings, 4: 249.
15. Paine, Writings, 5: 46.
16. Paine, Writings, 2: 90.
17. Ibid., 224.
18. Paine, Writings, 9: 271–272.
19. Paine, Writings, 10: 173–174.
20. Burke, Correspondence, 6: 70.
21. Paine, Writings, 4: 3.
22. Burke, Writings, 9: 277.
23. Ibid., 174.
24. Ibid., 253.
25. Ibid., 264.
26. Ibid., 267.
27. Burke, Writings, 8: 136.
28. Most notoriously in the Reflections; see especially ibid., 89.
29. Ibid., 175–176.
30. Ibid., 292.
31. Burke, Appeal, 89.
32. Burke, Writings, 8: 173.
33. Ibid., 114.
34. Ibid., 218.
35. Ibid., 81.
36. Ibid., 245.
37. Burke, Appeal, 195–196.
38. Ibid., 83.
39. Burke, Writings, 8: 230.
40. Burke, Correspondence, 7: 388.
41. At one point in the Letters on a Regicide Peace, Burke actually defines
Jacobinism (a term he uses often in his French writings) by pointing to this
practice: “Jacobinism is the revolt of the enterprising talents of a country against
its property” (Burke, Writings, 9: 241).
42. Ibid., 291.
43. Burke, Writings, 8: 115.
44. Burke, Appeal, 89.
45. Burke, Writings, 8: 129.
46. Ibid., 266.
47. Burke, Writings, 9: 288.
48. Burke, Writings, 8: 190.
49. Burke, Appeal, 196.
50. Burke, Writings, 8: 188.
51. Burke, Writings, 9: 173–174.
52. Ibid., 386. This passage has been the subject of a great deal of scholarly
controversy. Some readers (following especially Matthew Arnold) see it as self-
criticism on Burke’s part, arguing that he is essentially championing a cause he
knows is lost. Others see it as a clarion call for early resistance to the revolution,
lest it establish itself too firmly in European politics, and a warning to those
inclined to think that if the revolution fails, its evident faults will necessarily
persuade people of the essential error of its ways, and so no great effort is
required to combat it. I am mostly of the latter view, as the context of the essay
strongly suggests that Burke is arguing that the struggle against the revolution
must be won at the level of ideas, because once the ideas have sunk in, no
amount of practical failure will persuade its adherents of its falsehood. But
Burke’s remark certainly contains something of a melancholy reflection on the
difficulty of his own cause. (See also Leo Strauss, Natural Right and History,
318.) 53. Burke, Writings, 8: 180 (emphasis in original).
54. Ibid., 72.
55. Ibid., 216.
56. Ibid., 206.
57. Ibid., 72.
58. Burke, Writings, 9: 287.
59. Burke, Writings, 3: 492.
60. Burke, Writings, 9: 154–155.
61. Ibid., 545.
62. Ibid., 483.
63. Burke, Writings, 8: 290.
64. Ibid., 72.
65. Ibid., 77.
66. Burke, Appeal, 136n.
67. Burke, Writings, 9: 326–327.
68. Paine, Writings, 4: 101.
69. Ibid.
70. Paine, Writings, 5: 43n.
71. Ibid., 245.
72. Paine, Writings, 4: 77.
73. Ibid., 17.
74. Paine, Writings, 5: 103.
75. Ibid., 15.
76. Paine, Writings, 4: 201.
77. Paine, Writings, 5: 99.
78. Ibid., 92.
79. Burke, Writings, 8: 105.

CHAPTER 7: GENERATIONS AND THE LIVING


1. Paine, Writings, 4: 54.
2. Ibid., 7.
3. Ibid., 55.
4. Paine, Writings, 9: 248.
5. Paine, Writings, 4: 8.
6. Paine, Writings, 9: 251.
7. In fact, Burke appears to be arguing only that the Parliament of 1688 did
not do the opposite, that is, Parliament did not decree that the people owed no
allegiance to the royal family and have a permanent right to elect their own
monarch (Burke, Writings, 8: 70).
8. Paine, Writings, 4: 6.
9. Ibid., 7–8.
10. Ibid.
11. Paine, Writings, 9: 255.
12. Ibid., 13.
13. Paine, Writings, 2: 74.
14. Paine, Writings, 5: 212.
15. Paine, Writings, 4: 306.
16. Ibid., 248.
17. Ibid., 259.
18. Ibid., 257–258.
19. Ibid., 12.
20. Ibid.
21. Paine, Writings, 10: 17–18.
22. Paine, Writings, 4: 9.
23. Paine, Writings, 8: 342.
24. Ibid., 342–343. Three years after Paine’s proposal quoted here, Thomas
Jefferson made a similar suggestion on similar grounds in a letter to James
Madison, on September 6, 1789. His letter came complete with actuarial
calculations that placed the length of one generation at nineteen years and thus
made for somewhat shorter-lived laws than Paine had envisioned. “The earth
belongs always to the living generation,” Jefferson wrote, and “one generation is
to another as one independent nation to another” (Jefferson, Writings, 959).
25. Paine, Writings, 8: 343.
26. Ibid., 345.
27. Burke, Writings, 3: 147.
28. Burke, Writings, 7:692.
29. Burke, Writings, 8: 146.
30. Ibid., 83.
31. Ibid., 145.
32. Burke, Correspondence, 2: 377.
33. Burke, Writings, 8: 138–139.
34. Burke, Writings, 9: 183.
35. Burke, Appeal, 133–134.
36. Burke, Writings, 8: 84.
37. Ibid., 145.
38. Ibid., 217–218.
39. Burke, Appeal, 90–91.
40. Ibid., 197.
41. Burke, Correspondence, 6: 109.

CONCLUSION
1. Lambert, Edmund Burke of Beaconsfield, 168–169, offers a concise
summary of the facts surrounding this request (which was recorded in writing by
several of those involved).
2. Paine, Writings, 10: 369.
3. Obama’s self-description is reported by New York Times columnist David
Brooks in Gabriel Sherman, “The Courtship,” The New Republic, August 31,
2009.
4. Burke, Writings, 2: 194.
BIBLIOGRAPHY

Aldridge, Alfred. Man of Reason: The Life of Thomas Paine. London: Cresset Press, 1960.
———. Thomas Paine’s American Ideology. Wilmington: University of Delaware Press, 1984.
Ayer, A. J. Thomas Paine. New York: Atheneum, 1988.
Ayling, Stanley. Edmund Burke: His Life and Opinions. New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1988.
Baumann, Arthur. Burke: The Founder of Conservatism. London: Eyre and Spottiswoode, 1929.
Berthold, S. M. Thomas Paine: America’s First Liberal. Boston: Meador Publishing Company, 1938.
Best, Mary. Thomas Paine: Prophet and Martyr of Democracy. New York: Harcourt, Brace and Co., 1927.
Bisset, Robert. Life of Edmund Burke. 2 vols. London: G. Cawthorn, 1800.
Blakemore, Steven. Intertextual War: Edmund Burke and the French Revolution in the Writings of Mary
Wollstonecraft, Thomas Paine, and James Mackintosh. Madison, NJ: Fairleigh Dickinson University
Press, 1997.
Bogus, Carl. “Rescuing Burke.” Missouri Law Review 72, no. 2 (spring 2007): 387–476.
Bolingbroke, Viscount Henry. The Philosophical Writings of the Late Henry St. John, Viscount of
Bolingbroke. London: David Mallet, 1754.
Boswell, James. The Hypochondriak. Edited by Margery Bailey. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press,
1928.
Brooke, John. The Chatham Administration. London: MacMillan & Co., 1956.
Browne, Ray. The Burke-Paine Controversy: Texts and Criticism. New York: Harcourt, Brace and Co., 1963.
Browne, Stephen. Edmund Burke and the Discourse of Virtue. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press,
1993.
Burke, Edmund. The Correspondence of Edmund Burke. 10 vols. Edited by Thomas Copeland. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1958–1978.
———. Further Reflections on the Revolution in France. Edited by Daniel Ritchie. Indianapolis: Liberty
Fund, 1992.
———. A Note-Book of Edmund Burke. Edited by H. V. F. Somerset. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1957.
———. On Empire, Liberty, and Reform: Speeches and Letters of Edmund Burke. Edited by David
Bromwich. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2000.
———. Reflections on the Revolution in France. Edited by Frank M. Turner. New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press, 2004.
———. Selected Letters of Edmund Burke. Edited by Harvey Mansfield. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1984.
———. A Vindication of Natural Society. Edited by Frank Pagano. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1982.
———. The Writings and Speeches of Edmund Burke. 12 vols. Boston: Little, Brown, & Co., 1901.
———. The Writings and Speeches of Edmund Burke. Edited by Paul Lang-ford. 9 vols. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1991–.
Bury, J. B. The Idea of Progress. New York: Kessinger, 2004.
Butler, Marilyn, ed. Burke, Paine, Godwin and the Revolution Controversy. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1984.
Butterfield, Herbert. George III and the Historians. London: Collins, 1957.
Cameron, David. The Social Thought of Rousseau and Burke: A Comparative Study. London: Weidenfeld
and Nicolson, 1973.
Canavan, Francis. Edmund Burke: Prescription and Providence. Durham, NC: Carolina Academic Press,
1987.
———. The Political Economy of Edmund Burke. New York: Fordham University Press, 1995.
———. The Political Reason of Edmund Burke. Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1960.
———. “The Relevance of the Burke-Paine Controversy to American Political Thought.” Review of Politics
49, no. 2 (spring 1987): 163–176.
Carnes, Mark. Rousseau, Burke, and the Revolution in France. New York: Pearson Longman, 2005.
Chalmers, George. The life of Thomas Pain, the Author of Rights of Man: With a Defense of his Writings.
London: John Stockdale, 1791 (in the collections of the Library of Congress, Washington DC).
Chapman, Gerald. Edmund Burke: The Practical Imagination. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
1967.
Churchill, Winston. Thoughts and Adventures. London: Butterworth, 1932.
Claeys, Gregory. The French Revolution Debate in Britain. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2007.
———. Thomas Paine: Social and Political Thought. Boston: Unwin Hyman, 1989.
Cobban, Alfred. Edmund Burke and the Revolt Against the Eighteenth Century: A Study of the Political and
Social Thinking of Burke, Wordsworth, Coleridge, and Southey. New York: Barnes & Noble, 1960.
Cone, Carl. Burke and the Nature of Politics. 2 vols. Lexington: University of Kentucky Press, 1954.
———. The English Jacobins. New York: Scribner, 1968.
Conniff, James. The Useful Cobbler: Edmund Burke and the Politics of Progress. Albany: SUNY Press,
1994.
Conway, Moncure. The Life of Thomas Paine. New York: B. Blom, 1970.
Copeland, Thomas. Our Eminent Friend Edmund Burke: Six Essays. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press,
1949.
———. “The Reputation of Edmund Burke.” Journal of British Studies 1, no. 2 (1962): 78–90.
Courtney, Ceceil. Montesquieu and Burke. Oxford: Blackwell, 1963.
Creel, George. Tom Paine: Liberty Bell. New York: Sears Publishing Company, 1932.
Crowe, Ian, ed. Edmund Burke: His Life and Legacy. Dublin: Four Courts Press, 1997.
———. An Imaginative Whig: Reassessing the Life and Thought of Edmund Burke. Columbia: University of
Missouri Press, 2005.
Del Vecchio, Thomas. Tom Paine: American. New York: Whittier Books, 1956.
Descartes, Rene. Discourse on Method. Translated by Richard Kennington. Newburyport, MA: Focus
Publishing, 2007.
Dishman, Robert, ed. Burke and Paine on Revolution and the Rights of Man. New York: Charles Scribner’s
Sons, 1971.
Dreyer, Frederick. Burke’s Politics: A Study in Whig Orthodoxy. Waterloo: Wilfrid Laurier University Press,
1979.
Dyck, Ian, ed. Citizen of the World: Essays on Thomas Paine. New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1988.
Edwards, Samuel. Rebel! A Biography of Tom Paine. New York: Praeger, 1974.
Elder, Dominic. The Common Man Philosophy of Thomas Paine. Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame Press, 1951.
Evans, Christopher. Debating the Revolution: Britain in the 1790s. London: I.B. Tauris & Co., 2006.
Fasel, George. Edmund Burke. Boston: Twayne Publishers, 1983.
Fennessy, R. R. Burke, Paine, and the Rights of Man: A Difference of Political Opinion. The Hague: M.
Nijhoff, 1963.
Fidler, David, and Jennifer Welsh, eds. Empire and Community: Edmund Burke’s Writings and Speeches on
International Relations. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 2001.
Foner, Eric. Tom Paine and Revolutionary America. New York: Oxford University Press, 2005.
Ford, Karen, ed. Property, Welfare, and Freedom in the Thought of Thomas Paine. Lewiston, NY: Edwin
Mellen Press, 2001.
Ford, Karen. “Can a Democracy Bind Itself in Perpetuity: Paine, the Bank Crisis and the Concept of
Economic Freedom.” Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 142, no. 4 (1998): 557–577.
Franklin, Benjamin. The Works of Benjamin Franklin. Edited by John Bigelow New York: Putnam’s Sons,
1904.
Freeman, Michael. Edmund Burke and the Critique of Political Radicalism. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1980.
Frohnen, Bruce. Virtue and the Promise of Conservatism: The Legacy of Burke and Tocqueville. Lawrence:
University of Kansas Press, 1993.
Fruchtman, Jack. Thomas Paine and the Religion of Nature. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press,
1993.
Godwin, William. Memoirs of Mary Wollstonecraft. New York: Haskel House, 1927.
Halevy, Elie. The Growth of Philosophic Radicalism. New York: Beacon Press, 1966.
Hampsher-Monk, Iain. The Political Philosophy of Edmund Burke. New York: Longman, 1987.
Hawke, David. Paine. New York: Harper and Rowe, 1974.
Hazlitt, William. The Collected Works of William Hazlitt. Edited by A. R. Waller and Arnold Glover.
London: J.M. Dent, 1902.
Herzog, Don. “Puzzling Through Burke.” Political Theory 19, no. 3 (August 1991): 336–363.
Hitchens, Christopher. Thomas Paine’s Rights of Man: A Biography. Boston: Atlantic Monthly Press, 2007.
Hobbes, Thomas. Leviathan. Edited by Michael Oakshott. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1997.
Hoffman, Steven, and Paul Levack, eds. Burke’s Politics. New York: Knopf, 1949.
Insole, Christopher. “Two Conceptions of Liberalism: Theology, Creation, and Politics in the Thought of
Immanuel Kant and Edmund Burke.” Journal of Religious Ethics 36, no. 3 (2008): 447–489.
Jefferson, Thomas. The Papers of Thomas Jefferson. 10 vols. Edited by Julian Boyd. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 1950.
———. The Political Writings of Thomas Jefferson. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1993.
———. Writings. New York: Library of America, 1984.
Kant, Immanuel. First Introduction to the Critique of Judgment. New York: Bobbs-Merril, 1965.
Kaye, Harvey. Thomas Paine: Firebrand of the Revolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000.
Keane, John. Tom Paine: A Political Life. New York: Grove Press, 2003.
Kirk, Russell. The Conservative Mind. Chicago: Regnery, 1953.
———. Edmund Burke: A Genius Reconsidered. New Rochelle, NY: Arlington House, 1967.
Kramnick, Isaac. Edmund Burke. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1974.
———. The Rage of Edmund Burke: Portrait of an Ambivalent Conservative. New York: Basic Books,
1977.
Lambert, Elizabeth. Edmund Burke of Beaconsfield. Newark: University of Delaware Press, 2003.
Leffmann, Henry. The Real Thomas Paine: A Philosopher Misunderstood. Philadelphia: University of
Pennsylvania, 1922.
Lock, F. P. Edmund Burke. 2 vols. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998 and 2006.
Locke, John. Second Treatise of Government. Edited by C. B. Macpherson. New York: Hackett, 1980.
MacCoby, Simon, ed. The English Radical Tradition. New York: Kessinger, 2006.
MacCunn, John. The Political Philosophy of Burke. New York: Russell & Russell, 1965.
Macpherson, C. B. Burke. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980.
Mansfield, Harvey. “Burke and Machiavelli on Principles in Politics.” Chap. 3 in Machiavelli’s Virtue.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996.
———. Statesmanship and Party Government: A Study of Burke and Bolingbroke. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press: 1965.
McCue, Jim. Edmund Burke and Our Present Discontents. London: Claridge Press, 1997.
Meng, John. “The Constitutional Theories of Thomas Paine.” Review of Politics 8, no. 3 (July 1946): 283–
306.
Morley, John. Burke. New York: Harper and Brothers, 1887.
———. Recollections. 10 vols. New York: Macmillan, 1917.
Murphey, Dwight. Burkean Conservatism and Classical Liberalism. Wichita, KS: New Liberal Library,
1979.
Namier, Lewis. The Structure and Politics of the Accession of George III. London: MacMillan & Co., 1929.
Nelson, Craig. Thomas Paine: Enlightenment, Revolution, and the Birth of Modern Nations. New York:
Viking, 2006.
Newman, Bertram. Edmund Burke. London: G. Bell & Sons, 1927.
O’Brien, Conor C. The Great Melody. London: Minerva, 1993.
O’Gorman, Frank. Edmund Burke. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1973.
Osborn, Annie. Rousseau and Burke: A Study of the Idea of Liberty in Eighteenth-Century Political Thought.
New York: Russell & Russell, 1964.
Paine, Thomas. The Complete Writings of Thomas Paine. 2 vols. Edited by Philip Foner. New York: Citadel
Press, 1945.
———. Essential Writings of Thomas Paine. New York: Signet Classics, 2003.
———. Life and Writings of Thomas Paine. 10 vols. Edited by Daniel Wheeler. New York: Vincent Parke
and Co., 1915.
———. Paine: Political Writings. Edited by Bruce Kuklick. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.
Pappin, Joseph. The Metaphysics of Edmund Burke. New York: Fordham University Press, 1993.
Parkin, Charles. The Moral Basis of Burke’s Political Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1956.
Philip, Mark. Thomas Paine. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007.
Price, Richard. The Correspondence of Richard Price. Edited by Bernard Peach. Durham, NC: Duke
University Press, 1991.
Purdy, Strother. “A Note on the Burke-Paine Controversy.” American Literature 39, no. 3 (November 1967):
373–375.
Ritchie, Daniel, ed. Edmund Burke: Appraisals and Applications. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction
Publishers, 1990.
Robbins, Caroline. “The Lifelong Education of Thomas Paine: Some Reflections upon His Acquaintance
Among Books.” Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 127, no. 3 (1983): 135–142.
Rogers, Samuel. Recollections of the Table Talk of Samuel Rogers. London: Edward Moxon, 1856.
Rothbard, Murray. “A Note on Burke’s A Vindication of Natural Society.” Journal of the History of Ideas 19
(June 1958): 114–118.
Sloan, Herbert. Principle and Interest: Thomas Jefferson and the Problem of Debt. Charlottesville:
University of Virginia Press, 2001.
Stanlis, Peter. Edmund Burke and the Natural Law. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1958.
———. The Relevance of Edmund Burke. New York: P.J. Kennedy, 1964.
———, ed. Edmund Burke, the Enlightenment, and the Modern World. Detroit: University of Detroit Press,
1967.
Strauss, Leo. Natural Right and History. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953.
Strauss, Leo, and Joseph Cropsey, eds. History of Political Philosophy. 3rd ed. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1987.
Taylor-Wilkins, Burleigh. The Problem of Burke’s Political Philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1967.
Todd, W. B. “The Bibliographical History of Burke’s Reflections on the Revolution in France.” Library 6
(1951): 100–108.
Turner, John. “Burke, Paine, and the Nature of Language.” Yearbook of English Studies 19 (1989): 36–53.
Vaughan, Charles. Studies in the History of Political Philosophy Before and After Rousseau. 2 vols. New
York: Russell & Russell, 1925.
Vickers, Vikki. Thomas Paine and the American Revolution. New York: Rout-ledge, 2006.
Walpole, Horace. Horace Walpole’s Correspondence. 48 vols. Edited by W. S. Lewis. New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press, 1937.
Washington, George. The Writings of George Washington. Edited by Jared Sparks. Boston: Little, Brown &
Co., 1855.
Welsh, Cheryl. Edmund Burke and International Relations. New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1995.
Wecter, Dixon. “Burke’s Birthday.” Notes and Queries 172 (1937): 441.
West, E. G. Adam Smith. New York: Arlington House, 1969.
Williams, Gwyn. Artisans and Sans-Culottes: Popular Movements in France and Britain During the French
Revolution. New York: Norton, 1969.
Williamson, Audrey. Thomas Paine: His Life, Work, and Times. London: Allen and Unwin, 1973.
Woll, Walter. Thomas Paine: Motives for Rebellion. New York: P. Lang, 1992.
INDEX

Adams, John Quincy, 35


Age of Reason, The (Thomas Paine) zealous character of, 39, 154
and rationalism in politics, 128, 154–155
Agrarian Justice (Thomas Paine), 121–212
“American Crisis, The” (Thomas Paine), 18, 20, 116
American Declaration of Independence, 24, 127, 171
American Constitution
Paine’s thoughts on, 163–164, 166
and Burke’s constitutionalism, 171–173
American Revolution, 38
Burke on, 1, 7, 9–12, 20, 59, 135, 168, 171–174, 185–6, 193
Paine on, 1, 17–20, 25–26, 168–174, 182–183, 225
Anglican Church, 4, 12
Appeal from the New to the Old Whigs, An (Edmund Burke) as response to Paine, 35–36
on prudence, 84–85
on legitimate government, 100
on unchosen obligations, 102–103
on wisdom in past, 135–136
on American crisis, 173
on Glorious Revolution, 198
Aristocracy
Burke’s partial defense of, 85, 99, 146, 162, 217
Burke’s “natural aristocracy,” 85
Paine’s criticism of, 33–34, 53, 55, 164–165, 180, 208–209
Aristotle, 53, 99, 135
and ancient science, 49

Bastille, storming of, 23–24


Beaconsfield, 40, 223
Bolingbroke, Lord, 5, 7
See also Vindication of Natural Society, A (Edmund Burke)
Boswell, James, 6
Bristol, England
Letter to sheriffs, 20
and Burke’s understanding of representation, 111, 115, 131, 137 (see also Representation) British
constitution. See English constitution
Bromwich, David, xvii, 36, 55
Brownsville, Pennsylvania, 19
Burke, Edmund
meetings and correspondence with Paine, 1, 20–23, 26
writings contrasted with Paine, 15, 40–41
alleged inconsistency of, 35
notable acquaintances and friends, 2, 6
early life, 3–4
education, 4
family, 3–4, 7
early writings, 5–6
literary career, 6–7
political career, 7–12
secretary to William Gerard Hamilton, 7
secretary to Marquis of Rockingham, 7
death of, 40
Burke, Richard (Edmund Burke’s father), 3–4
Burke, Richard (Edmund Burke’s son), 25, 223
death of, 40

Capitalism, 118, 231


and Burke, 120
and Paine, 123
Case of the Officers of Excise, The (Thomas Paine), 14
Catholics, 22
Burke’s family, 3–4
Burke’s sympathy for Catholic minorities, 7, 9, 73, 193
Burke on French Catholics, 75
Charlemont, Earl of, 23
Chivalry
Burke on, 61–64, 74, 87
Paine on, 106, 201
Common Sense (Thomas Paine), 44
reasons for writing, 16, 150
impact of, 17
launches Paine to fame, 18
whether Burke read, 20
radical rationalism, 34, 161, 169–170
rational political institutions, 163
egalitarianism, 51, 88, 210
as preparation for revolution in religion, 155
Commons, House of, 9, 40
character of, 98–99, 103, 111, 194
Burke elected to seat, 7, 111
Burke’s speeches in, 9, 22–23, 28–29, 143, 173, 197
Consent, 160, 205–207
Burke’s ethic of obligation, 97–116, 97–99, 101, 104, 106–108, 121, 216
Paine’s politics of choice, 50, 71, 92–97, 120–121, 210–213
Conservatism, 36
Burke as “procedural conservative,” 71–72, 76
See also Partisanship
Continental Congress, 18, 163
Crisis papers. See “American Crisis, The”
Cumberland, Richard, 142

Declaration of Independence. See American Declaration of Independence


Declaration of Right, 142
Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen, 24, 26, 29
Deism, 5, 39, 154, 223
Democracy. See Representation
Depont, Charles-Jean-François, 29, 113
Dissertation on First Principles in Government (Thomas Paine), 89, 208
Dover, England, 13
Dublin, Ireland
Edmund Burke’s birthplace, 3
Burke attends Trinity College, 4
Dunlap Creek, 19

East India Company, 73, 81, 193. See also India; Warren Hastings
East Sussex, England, 13
Economics
Paine’s support of free economics, 118–124
Paine’s understanding of poverty, 14, 36, 52, 75, 118–125, 165, 227
Paine’s support of welfare system, 120–122, 213–14
Burke’s support of free economics, 118–124
Burke’s thoughts on class privilege, 82–88, 99
See also Poverty; Property
English constitution
as Burke’s model, 77–81, 97–98, 141–142, 145–148, 171–173, 193–194
Paine’s criticism of, 152, 160–161, 167–168, 210–213
Equality, 3, 16, 127
and Burke’s thought, 82–90, 119, 132
Burke’s thoughts on class privilege, 82–88, 99
and Paine’s thought, 45–47, 82–91, 123–124, 151, 180–183
and equality of generations (Paine), 206–207
relation to republican government, 211–213 (see also Representation) Fennessy, R.R., 116
Fox, Charles James, 21, 24, 28, 35
Francis, Philip, 63
Freedom. See Liberty
French Revolution, 23–34
Burke’s view of, 24–26, 27–32, 35–38, 70–71 . . .
Burke’s view of its unprecedented nature, 185
Burke’s acknowledgment that France needs reform, 186–187, 193–194
Paine’s view of, 21, 25–26, 32–34, 70–71, 183–184
Paine’s acknowledge of revolutionary failures, 183–184
Franklin, Benjamin, 2, 14, 173
French National Assembly, 27, 37, 103, 179

Garrick, David, 6
George III, King, 2, 8, 21
George, Prince, 21
Gibbon, Edward, 2, 6.
Glorious Revolution, 3
Burke on, 22, 27–28, 30, 98, 173, 187–188, 198–200, 209
Richard Price on, 27–28, 97–98
Paine on, 199–200, 209–210
Goldsmith, Oliver, 6
Greek Church, 154

Hamilton, William Gerard, 7


Hastings, Warren, 11, 23, 39–40, 73, 215. See also India; East India Company
Hazlitt, William, 58
Hebert, Jacques, 127
Hobbes, Thomas, 53, 72
and Paine’s theories, 45

India, Burke’s involvement in British policy to, 7, 11, 23, 39–40, 59, 71, 73, 81, 193, 215
Individualism,
and Paine’s understanding of social relations, 93–97, 105–106
contrasted with Burke’s understanding of social relations, 97–116
See also Consent; Social contract
Inskeep, John, 150
Ireland, 73, 81
Edmund Burke’s birthplace, 3
and Burke’s family, 4
and Burke’s career with William Gerard Hamilton, 7
Jacobins, Party of, 38, 199
James II, King, 22, 173. See also Glorious Revolution
Jefferson, Thomas, 229
and Paine, 2, 20, 39, 92
on French Revolution, 26
on Edmund Burke, 35
Jewish Church, 154
Johnson, Samuel, 2, 6

Lafayette, Marquis de, 26, 179


Lambert, Mary, 13–14
Letter to a Member of the National Assembly (Edmund Burke), 103
Letter to the Sheriffs of Bristol (Edmund Burke), 20
Letters on the Regicide Peace (Edmund Burke), 38, 186, 195, 199
Letters on the Study and Use of History (Lord Bolingbroke), 5
Lawyers, Burke’s view on, 145
Liberalism. See Partisanship
Liberty
Paine’s understanding of, 90–96, 112
Burke’s understanding of, 90, 98, 109–110, 112–116
poverty as a constraint on, 122–124
Livy, 135
Locke, John, 53
and Paine’s theories, 45, 47
London, England
Burke’s life in, 2–6
Paine’s life in, 13–14, 37, 121
London Chronicle, 32
Lords, House of, 73, 162, 194
Louis XVI, King, 37, 62

Magna Carta, 81, 142


Madison, James, 2
Marie Antoinette, Queen of France, 25, 69
Burke’s paean to, 62–64
Michael Angelo, 135
Modest Proposal (Jonathan Swift), 3
Monarchy
Paine’s assault on the British Crown and hereditary rule, 16–20, 51–52, 96, 152, 156–157, 164
Paine’s shift to uncompromising republicanism, 179–180
and Burke’s understanding of British monarchy, 30, 98
See also Regency Crisis; English constitution
Monroe, James, 2, 35
Morley, John, 5, 105
Montesquieu, 99
Natural law
whether Burke was a natural-law theorist, 72–77
New Rochelle, New York, 19, 39, 224
New York
legislature gives Paine farm, 19
Paine’s last days in, 39
Newton, Isaac, 49
North, Lord, 9–10

Paine, Thomas
meetings and correspondence with Burke, 1, 20–23, 26
writings contrasted with Burke, 15, 40–41
close acquaintances and friends, 2
early life, 12
poverty of, 12, 14, 52
religious beliefs, 12, 39 (see also Age of Reason) as working-class Englishman, 12–13
short marriage to Mary Lambert, 13–14
enters the excise trade, 13–14
early pamphleteering efforts, 14
introduced to Benjamin Franklin, 14
early writings on British abuses of rights, 15–16
becomes editor of Pennsylvania Magazine, 15–16
becomes advocate and administrator of American war of independence, 18
drafts a new Pennsylvania constitution, 18
designs and seeks financing for an iron bridge, 19–20
travels to France and Britain, 19–21
imprisoned in France, 183
death of, 39
Paris, France, 30
Paine resides in, 19–21, 24
revolutionary activities, 23–24, 26, 37–38, 82–83, 185
Partisanship,
emergence of in Burke-Paine debate, 118, 198–203, 223–231
Burke on, 8, 137–140, 174, 186
Paine on, 158–159
Patriotism,
Burke on, 54, 76, 116–118, 148, 189
Paine on, 116–118
Pennsylvania, 15–16, 18–19
Paine helps draft Pennsylvania constitution, 18
Pennsylvania Journal, 16
Pennsylvania Magazine, 15–16
Philadelphia, Pennsylvania, 14–15, 19, 150
Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of Our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful, A (Edmund Burke), 6, 57–
58, 134–135
Pitt, William, 21–22, 28, 37
Plain Truth (Thomas Paine), 16 (see Common Sense) Plato, 53, 86, 99
Political parties. See Partisanship
Portland, Duke of, 1
Poverty, 226
Burke’s experience with, 3
Burke’s understanding of, 75, 119, 123–124
Paine’s experience with, 12, 39
Paine’s understanding of, 14, 36, 52, 118–124, 165, 227
See also Economics; Property
Prejudice
Burke’s defense of, 132, 136–137, 143
and prescription, 104, 143
Paine’s opposition to, 26, 117–118, 128, 157–159
Prescription, 128–150, definition of, 67, 77
and denial of consent, 104
grounded in limits of reason, 140–142, 147, 158
and English constitution, 77–81, 141–142, 171–173
as mode of prudent reform, 84, 143–150
commonality with prejudice, 104, 143
reliance on precedence, 145
Paine’s opposition to, 158
Price, Richard, 27–30, 59–60, 209
Progress, 138
Paine’s view of, 48, 159–160, 167–168, 180, 183, 208, 222
Burke’s view of, 64–66, 78–79, 115, 197, 138. See also Prescription; Reform
contemporary progressives, 175, 224, 227–228, 230
Property
confiscation of by revolutionary regime, 28
Burke’s views on private property, 28, 56, 70, 87, 132
Burke’s understanding of inherited property, 65, 84, 216 (see also Prescription) Burke’s thoughts on class
privilege, 82–88, 99
Paine’s views on private property, 90, 93, 121, 209, 213
Paine’s view of state as common property, 88, 122, 151 (see also Representation) See also Economics;
Poverty
Protestants, 3–4, 9, 22, 73, 97, 154
Prudence, Burke’s understanding of, 8, 56, 71, 81, 84–85, 99, 110–111, 115, 128–150
definition of, 79
organic approach to institutions, 146–147
Contrasted with Paine’s rationalism, 88–89, 157–158
See also Sentiments; Statesmanship, Burke’s understanding of
Publicola. See John Quincy Adams

Quakers, 4, 224
influence on Paine, 12

Raphael, 135
Rationalism,
and Burke’s response to Bolingbroke, 5 (see also A Vindication of Natural Society)
Burke on limits to reason, 56, 65, 108, 128–150, 130–131, 134–135, 162, 190–191, 202 (see also
Prudence; Prescription) Burke’s criticism of abstractions and speculations, 56, 74, 109–110, 129–132,
172
Burke’s view of importance of sentiments, 8, 10, 57–61, 64, 66–67, 105, 129, 173, 190–191
Paine’s confidence in reason, 50, 89, 128, 150–168, 171
Raynal, The Abbé, 169
Reed, Joseph, 17
Reflections on the Revolution in France (Edmund Burke) audience, 31–32
reception, 32–33, 35, 142
predicts French tyranny, 190–191
Regency Crisis, 21–23, 25, 28
Reform
Burke’s history as policy reformer, 7–12, 21–22, 35 7–12, 21–22, 35, 116–124, 143–144, 185–198
Burke’s understanding of, 8–9, 140–146, 185–198, 202 (see also Prudence; Prescription)
Paine on insufficiency of reform, 181, 200–202 (see also Rationalism; Revolution) Religion,
in Burke’s life, 3–4, 7
in Paine’s life, 12, 39, 153–5
Burke’s defense of, 5, 73–76, 101, 123. See also Catholics; A Vindication of Natural Society
Paine’s views of, 12, 39, 153–155. See also Deism; Age of Reason
Representation
Burke’s understanding of, 9, 86, 98–99, 111–112, 115, 131–132, 137, 146
Paine’s understanding of, 51, 151, 163–6, 211
and Paine’s assistance in drafting Pennsylvania constitution draft, 18
Paine’s criticism of the English constitution, 152, 160–161, 167–168, 210–213
See also Consent; Social contract
Revolution
Paine’s view of, 47–49, 55–56, 70–71, 90, 151, 178–185
Paine’s view of proper goal of revolutions, 181–182
contrasted with Burke’s view of change, 8–9, 140–146, 185–198, 202 (see also Prescription; Prudence)
Reynolds, Joshua, 6
Richardson, William, 149
Rights
Burke’s view of equal rights, 87
Burke’s denial of relevance of abstract rights, 56, 74, 109
and Paine’s view of consent, 92–97
Rights of Man (Thomas Paine) reception to, 34–35
aim of book, 150
and politics of choice, 94–96
on social obligations 116–117
on Burke’s case against abstract principles, 153
American revolution as revolution in principles, 168
on Burke’s skepticism that there would be a revolution in France, 185
Rockingham, Marquis of, 7
Roman Church, 154
Roman property law. See Prescription
Rousseau, 103
Rush, Benjamin, 15–16, Sandwich, England, 13
Science
Burke’s parody of scientific rationalism, 5 (see also A Vindication of Natural Society) Burke’s
understanding of political science, 56–67, 108, 128, 130–131, 134–135, 162, 202 (see also Prudence;
Prescription) Paine’s science of government, 50, 89, 128, 151, 155, 171 (see also Rationalism) Paine’s
scientific pursuits, 19–20
natural science, 49, 50, 127, 155
ancient science, 49
Sentiments, Burke’s view of importance of, 8, 10, 57–61, 64, 66–67, 105, 129, 173, 190–191 (see also
Prudence; Rationalism; Science) “Serious Thought, A” (Thomas Paine), 16
Seven Years’ War, 13
Shakespeare, William, 149
Smith, Adam, 2, 120
Burke’s likeminded economic thought, 120
Social contract
Burke’s understanding of, 106–109, 113–115, 124
Paine’s understanding of, 92–97, 109
See also Consent; Representation
Society for Commemorating the Revolution, 27. See also Price, Richard.
Speech on Conciliation with the Colonies (Edmund Burke), 10
Speech on American Taxation (Edmund Burke), 11–12
Statesmanship, Burke’s understanding of theory vs. practice, 128–132
and partisanship, 138–140
and reform, 194–197
See also Prudence; Sentiments; Science
Swift, Jonathan, 3
Taxation
Burke’s views on British tax policy, 9–11, 171–172
Paine’s view on British tax policy, 17, 169
Paine’s support of progressive income tax, 36
Paine’s support of inheritance tax, 122, 213–214
Paine’s experience as an excise officer, 13–14
Thetford, England, 12
Thoughts on the Causes of the Present Discontents (Edmund Burke), 8, 35
Thoughts and Details on Scarcity (Edmund Burke), 119–120
Tories, 224
Burke’s opposition to policy on America, 9–10
and Regency Crisis, 21–22
reaction to French Revolution, 37, 138, 201
distinguished from Whigs, 198–199, 201 (see also Partisanship) Trinity College, 4
Turkey, 194
Turkish Church, 154

Utilitarianism,
Burke’s supposed utilitarianism, 72–77
Paine’s society as utilitarian arrangement, 94
and contemporary liberals, 229

Versailles, 25, 62
Vindication of Natural Society, A (Edmund Burke), 5–7, 52–53, 57, 74.
Horace Walpole on, 6–7
Virgil, 135

Walpole, Horace, 6
War, Paine’s promise of world free of, 36, 165–166
Washington, George, 2, 16–18, 178
reacts to Paine’s Common Sense, 17
Wealth of Nations, On the (Adam Smith), 12
Wear River, England, 19
Welfare system. See Poverty
Westminster Abbey, 40
Whigs,
Paine on, 20, 25, 184, 199–201
Burke’s membership, 7–8, 11, 21–24, 28, 35
Burke on true Whig principles, 98, 197–199 (see also An Appeal from the New to the Old Whigs) William
and Mary, 22, 200, 209. See also Glorious Revolution

You might also like