0% found this document useful (0 votes)
32 views6 pages

Diagrammatic Reasoning

Diagrammatic reasoning involves using visual representations like diagrams instead of linguistic means to understand concepts and ideas. Diagrams show abstract relationships and information through shapes connected by lines and arrows. Charles Sanders Peirce developed several graphical systems for logic including existential graphs, conceptual graphs, and entitative graphs that use visual structures to represent logical expressions and reasoning.

Uploaded by

noah676
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
32 views6 pages

Diagrammatic Reasoning

Diagrammatic reasoning involves using visual representations like diagrams instead of linguistic means to understand concepts and ideas. Diagrams show abstract relationships and information through shapes connected by lines and arrows. Charles Sanders Peirce developed several graphical systems for logic including existential graphs, conceptual graphs, and entitative graphs that use visual structures to represent logical expressions and reasoning.

Uploaded by

noah676
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 6

Diagrammatic reasoning

Diagrammatic reasoning is reasoning by means of visual representations. The study of diagrammatic


reasoning is about the understanding of concepts and ideas, visualized with the use of diagrams and
imagery instead of by linguistic or algebraic means.

Diagram
A diagram is a 2D geometric symbolic representation of information according to some visualization
technique. Sometimes, the technique uses a 3D visualization which is then projected onto the 2D surface.
The term diagram in common sense can have two meanings.

visual information device: Like the term "illustration"


the diagram is used as a collective term standing for
the whole class of technical genres, including
graphs, technical drawings and tables.[1]
specific kind of visual display: This is only the genre,
that shows qualitative data with shapes that are
connected by lines, arrows, or other visual links.

In science the term is used in both ways. For example,


Anderson (1997) stated more general "diagrams are pictorial,
yet abstract, representations of information, and maps, line
graphs, bar charts, engineering blueprints, and architects'
sketches are all examples of diagrams, whereas photographs
Sample flowchart representing the
and video are not".[2] On the other hand, Lowe (1993) defined
decision process to add a new article to
diagrams as specifically "abstract graphic portrayals of the
Wikipedia.
subject matter they represent".[3]

In the specific sense diagrams and charts contrast computer


graphics, technical illustrations, infographics, maps, and technical drawings, by showing "abstract rather
than literal representations of information".[1] The essences of a diagram can be seen as:[1]

a form of visual formatting devices


a display that does not show quantitative data, but rather relationships and abstract
information
with building blocks such as geometrical shapes that are connected by lines, arrows, or
other visual links.

Or as Bert S. Hall wrote, "diagrams are simplified figures, caricatures in a way, intended to convey
essential meaning".[4] According to Jan V. White (1984) "the characteristics of a good diagram are
elegance, clarity, ease, pattern, simplicity, and validity".[1] Elegance for White means that what you are
seeing in the diagram is "the simplest and most fitting solution to a problem".[5]

Logical graph
A logical graph is a special type of graph-theoretic structure in any one of several systems of graphical
syntax that Charles Sanders Peirce developed for logic.

In his papers on qualitative logic, entitative graphs, and existential graphs, Peirce developed several
versions of a graphical formalism, or a graph-theoretic formal language, designed to be interpreted for logic.

In the century since Peirce initiated this line of development, a variety of formal systems have branched out
from what is abstractly the same formal base of graph-theoretic structures.

Conceptual graph

A conceptual graph (CG) is a notation for logic based on the existential graphs of Charles Sanders Peirce
and the semantic networks of artificial intelligence. In the first published paper on conceptual graphs, John
F. Sowa used them to represent the conceptual schemas used in database systems. His first book[6] applied
them to a wide range of topics in artificial intelligence, computer science, and cognitive science. A linear
notation, called the Conceptual Graph Interchange Format (CGIF), has been standardized in the ISO
standard for Common Logic.

The diagram on the right is an example of the display form for


a conceptual graph. Each box is called a concept node, and
each oval is called a relation node. In CGIF, this CG would be
represented by the following statement:
Elsie the cat is sitting on a mat
[Cat Elsie] [Sitting *x] [Mat *y] (agent ?x
Elsie) (location ?x ?y)

In CGIF, brackets enclose the information inside the concept nodes, and parentheses enclose the
information inside the relation nodes. The letters x and y, which are called coreference labels, show how
the concept and relation nodes are connected. In the Common Logic Interchange Format (CLIF), those
letters are mapped to variables, as in the following statement:

(exists ((x Sitting) (y Mat)) (and (Cat Elsie) (agent x Elsie) (location x y)))

As this example shows, the asterisks on the coreference labels *x and *y in CGIF map to existentially
quantified variables in CLIF, and the question marks on ?x and ?y map to bound variables in CLIF. A
universal quantifier, represented @every*z in CGIF, would be represented forall (z) in CLIF.

Entitative graph

An entitative graph is an element of the graphical syntax for logic that Charles Sanders Peirce developed
under the name of qualitative logic beginning in the 1880s, taking the coverage of the formalism only as far
as the propositional or sentential aspects of logic are concerned.[7]

The syntax is:

The blank page;


Single letters, phrases;
Objects (subgraphs) enclosed by a simple closed curve called a cut. A cut can be empty.

The semantics are:


The blank page denotes False;
Letters, phrases, subgraphs, and entire graphs can be True' or False;
To surround objects with a cut is equivalent to Boolean complementation. Hence an empty
cut denotes Truth;
All objects within a given cut are tacitly joined by disjunction.

A "proof" manipulates a graph, using a short list of rules, until the graph is reduced to an empty cut or the
blank page. A graph that can be so reduced is what is now called a tautology (or the complement thereof).
Graphs that cannot be simplified beyond a certain point are analogues of the satisfiable formulas of first-
order logic.

Existential graph

An existential graph is a type of diagrammatic or visual notation for logical expressions, proposed by
Charles Sanders Peirce, who wrote his first paper on graphical logic in 1882 and continued to develop the
method until his death in 1914. Peirce proposed three systems of existential graphs:

alpha – isomorphic to sentential logic and the two-element Boolean algebra;


beta – isomorphic to first-order logic with identity, with all formulas closed;
gamma – (nearly) isomorphic to normal modal logic.

Alpha nests in beta and gamma. Beta does not nest in gamma, quantified modal logic being more than
even Peirce could envisage.

In alpha the syntax is:

The blank page;


Single letters or phrases written anywhere on the
page;
Any graph may be enclosed by a simple closed
curve called a cut or sep. A cut can be empty. Cuts
can nest and concatenate at will, but must never
intersect.

Any well-formed part of a graph is a subgraph.

The semantics are:


Alpha Graphs
The blank page denotes Truth;
Letters, phrases, subgraphs, and entire graphs may be True or False;
To enclose a subgraph with a cut is equivalent to logical negation or Boolean
complementation. Hence an empty cut denotes False;
All subgraphs within a given cut are tacitly conjoined.

Hence the alpha graphs are a minimalist notation for sentential logic, grounded in the expressive adequacy
of And and Not. The alpha graphs constitute a radical simplification of the two-element Boolean algebra
and the truth functors.

Characteristica universalis
Characteristica universalis, commonly interpreted as universal characteristic, or universal character in
English, is a universal and formal language imagined by the German philosopher Gottfried Leibniz able to
express mathematical, scientific, and metaphysical concepts. Leibniz thus hoped to create a language usable
within the framework of a universal logical calculation or calculus ratiocinator.

Since the characteristica universalis is diagrammatic and


employs pictograms (below left), the diagrams in Leibniz's
work warrant close study. On at least two occasions, Leibniz
illustrated his philosophical reasoning with diagrams. One
diagram, the frontispiece to his 1666 De Arte Combinatoria
(On the Art of Combinations), represents the Aristotelian
theory of how all material things are formed from combinations
of the elements earth, water, air, and fire.

Basic elements of Leibniz's


pictograms.
Leibniz's diagrammatic reasoning.

These four elements make up the four corners of a diamond


(see picture to right). Opposing pairs of these are joined by a bar labeled "contraries" (earth-air, fire-water).
At the four corners of the superimposed square are the four qualities defining the elements. Each adjacent
pair of these is joined by a bar labeled "possible combination"; the diagonals joining them are labeled
"impossible combination." Starting from the top, fire is formed from the combination of dryness and heat;
air from wetness and heat; water from coldness and wetness; earth from coldness and dryness.[8]

The Venn-II reasoning system


In the early 1990s Sun-Joo Shin presented an extension of Existential Graphs called Venn-II.[9] Syntax and
semantics are given formally, together with a set of Rules of Transformation which are shown to be sound
and complete. Proofs proceed by applying the rules (which remove or add syntactic elements to or from
diagrams) sequentially. Venn-II is equivalent in expressive power to a first-order monadic language.

See also
Heuristics
How to Solve It by George Pólya
Natural deduction
Propositional calculus
Spatial-temporal reasoning
Trikonic
Visual reasoning

References
1. Brasseur, Lee E. (2003). Visualizing technical information: a cultural critique. Amityville, N.Y.:
Baywood Pub. ISBN 0-89503-240-6.
2. Michael Anderson (1997). "Introduction to Diagrammatic Reasoning" (http://zeus.cs.hartford.
edu/~anderson/intro.html) Archived (https://web.archive.org/web/20080915135208/http://zeu
s.cs.hartford.edu/~anderson/intro.html) 2008-09-15 at the Wayback Machine. Retrieved 21
July 2008.
3. Lowe, Richard K. (1993). "Diagrammatic information: techniques for exploring its mental
representation and processing". Information Design Journal. 7 (1): 3–18.
doi:10.1075/idj.7.1.01low (https://doi.org/10.1075%2Fidj.7.1.01low).
4. Bert S. Hall (1996). "The Didactic and the Elegant: Some Thoughts on Scientific and
Technological Illustrations in the Middle Ages and Renaissance (https://books.google.com/b
ooks?id=DzgBU0-Y7a0C&dq=%22The+Didactic+and+the+Elegant%3A+Some+Thoughts+
on+Scientific+and+Technological+Illustrations+in+the+Middle+Ages+and+Renaissance%2
2&pg=PA3)". in: B. Braigie (ed.) Picturing knowledge: historical and philosophical problems
concerning the use of art in science. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. p.9
5. White, Jan V. (1984). Using charts and graphs: 1000 ideas for visual persuasion (https://arch
ive.org/details/usingchartsgraph00janv). New York: Bowker. ISBN 0-8352-1894-5.
6. John F. Sowa (1984). Conceptual Structures: Information Processing in Mind and Machine.
Addison-Wesley, Reading, MA, 1984.
7. See 3.468, 4.434, and 4.564 in Peirce's Collected Papers.
8. This diagram is reproduced in several texts including Saemtliche Schriften und Briefe,
Reihe VI, Band 1: 166, Loemker 1969: 83, 366, Karl Popp and Erwin Stein 2000: 33.
9. Shin, Sun-Joo. 1994. The Logical Status of Diagrams. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.

Further reading
Gerard Allwein and Jon Barwise (ed.) (1996). Logical Reasoning with Diagrams (https://boo
ks.google.com/books?id=a8sBKy8wFXkC&dq=Logical+Reasoning+with+Diagrams&pg=P
P1). Oxford University Press.
Michael Anderson, Peter Cheng, Volker Haarslev (Eds.) (2000). Theory and Application of
Diagrams: First International Conference, Diagrams 2000 (https://books.google.com/books?i
d=b_lqCQAAQBAJ). Edinburgh, Scotland, UK, September 1–3, 2000. Proceedings.
Micheal Anderson and R. McCartney (2003). Diagram Processing: Computing with
Diagrams (http://www.cs.hartford.edu/~anderson/personal/diagramprocessing.pdf). In:
Artificial Intelligence, Volume 145, Issue 1–2, April, 2003.
James Robert Brown (1999). Philosophy of Mathematics: An Introduction to the World of
Proofs and Pictures (https://www.amazon.com/dp/0415122740). Routledge.
James Franklin (2000). Diagrammatic reasoning and modelling in the imagination: the
secret weapons of the Scientific Revolution (http://web.maths.unsw.edu.au/~jim/imagin.pdf),
in 1543 and All That: Image and Word, Change and Continuity in the Proto-Scientific
Revolution, ed. G. Freeland & A. Corones (Kluwer, Dordrecht), pp. 53-115.
Janice Glasgow, N. Hari Narayanan, and B. Chandrasekaran (ed) (1995). Diagrammatic
Reasoning: Cognitive and Computational Perspectives (https://www.amazon.com/dp/02625
71129). AAAI Press.
Kulpa, Zenon. "Diagrammatic representation and reasoning (https://web.archive.org/web/20
130426004234/http://www.ippt.gov.pl/~zkulpa/diagrams/Diagres.pap.pdf)." Machine
GRAPHICS & VISION 3 (1/2. 1994.
Gem Stapleton A Survey of Reasoning Systems Based on Euler Diagrams (http://www.com
p.it.bton.ac.uk/Research/vmg/papers/ED04Survey.pdf). Electronic Notes in Theoretical
Computer Science. 2005.

External links
Diagrammatic Reasoning Site (http://zeus.cs.hartford.edu/~anderson/) Archived (https://web.
archive.org/web/20090619082112/http://zeus.cs.hartford.edu/~anderson/) 2009-06-19 at the
Wayback Machine from the University of Hartford, Connecticut, USA
Lecture (http://math.ucr.edu/home/baez/universal/) about Universal Algebra and
Diagrammatic Reasoning by John Baez, 3 Feb 2006.
Homepage of Sun-Joo Shin (http://www.yale.edu/philos/people/shin_sun-joo.html).
Visual Modelling Group (http://www.cmis.brighton.ac.uk/Research/vmg/) at the University of
Brighton, UK.
Marlo diagrams online to solve syllogisms (https://fersoler.github.io/MarloDiagrams/).

Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Diagrammatic_reasoning&oldid=1147202924"

You might also like