When Must We Interfere
When Must We Interfere
When Must We Interfere
Complete all sections of this form and ensure it is the first page of the document you submit.
Failure to attach the coversheet as required may result in your work not being accepted for
assessment.
DECLARATION BY STUDENT
This assignment is entirely my own work. Quotations from secondary literature are indicated by the
use of inverted commas around ALL such quotations AND by reference in the text or notes to the
author concerned. I confirm that no sources have been used other than those stated.
I understand what is meant by ‘plagiarism’ and have signed at enrolment the declaration
concerning the avoidance of plagiarism.
I understand that plagiarism is a serious academic offence that may result in disciplinary
action being taken.
I understand that I must submit all written work BY the deadline.
Module Code:
7FFLF906
(e.g. 7FFLA001)
Your assignment may be used as an example of good practice for other students to refer to in
future. If selected, your assignment will be presented anonymously and may include feedback
comments or the specific grade awarded. Participation is optional and will not affect your grade.
Do you consent to your assignment being used in this way? Please tick the appropriate box below.
YES NO
X
When not only may we interfere in others’ lives, but must we?
I. Introduction
When we may or must interfere can refer both to concrete and to general conditions under
which these are the case. Concrete conditions are along the lines of the following example:
imagine that you are a physically strong person and you see that a child is physically
threatened by a drunk stranger. What must you do? Since this approach would basically
produce a list of situation such as these (X 1, X2, … Xn) with morally correct responses (Y1, Y2,
impossible.
Instead, I focus on general and procedural conditions. My main argument is that deciding
when one may and must interfere is context-specific and requires certain competences and
qualities, we can come to similar conclusions as these idealized individuals. The answer I
To elaborate, these competences and virtues belong to idealized individuals which are (1)
mentally calm and reflective, (2) rational and reasonable, and (3) critical of own and
surrounding values. The deliberations of such a person should, in other words, be decisive
when deciding under which circumstances one may or must interfere with another person
The question points to the tension between the several values we might hold. This essay
suggests that the question presumes a triadic relationship, including (1) aspects of the negative
autonomy of the interferee, (2) aspects of the positive autonomy of the interferer, and (3) a
value that trumps both. The procedural account helps to decide what the values of (3) ought to
be.
2
It should by now be clear that the essay will not delve into thorny metaphysical and
theological questions on the fundaments and methods of realist morality. Instead I utilize a
pragmatic psychological account to arrive at moralities which can be respected by those who
suggest them and the communities and societies these individuals belong to.
In order to explain my argument, I first look into what the relevant terms in the question mean
and how they interact with the other terms of the question. From these interactions, I derive a
triadic relationship that exposes the field of tension between several relevant values. Third, I
argue why when deciding which values are relevant and should trump other values, a
psychological and pragmatic account is reasonable. Fourth, this account shapes my decision
to look at an idealized individual account that provides the procedure from which we ought to
attain moral judgements. Fifth, I explain how this account is to interact with priorly held
values and the values that surround someone. Finally, I anticipate a reasonable
counterargument, after which I show how such a context-specific morality is more robust than
their logical connections. In this case these are: interference, may, and must. The first concept
refers to the intentional obstruction of future action or the disruption of current action through
force, e.g. physical. The second word, may, refers to the moral permission to do certain
actions, while must refers to the obligation to do so. In the question, we are asked when we are
both allowed and obliged to interfere. I take when to refer to the set of circumstances or
When these words are combined, they get more complex meanings. When person R is
morally allowed to interfere with person Q this means that the negative freedom of Q is
3
morally limited by the positive freedom of interferer R. However, if R is both allowed and
obliged to interfere with Q, this means that R is morally limited in his positive freedom by an
external obligation, while Q is morally limited, again, in his negative freedom. In my usage,
morally limited means that we ought to believe they ought to be physically limited given the
circumstances they are in. We generally believe that rapists and murderers are morally limited
Underlying these considerations is another important term: autonomy. The conditions under
which one is allowed and obliged to interfere with another person correspond to when certain
aspects of autonomy are trumped by other values. With autonomy – Greek for ‘self-rule’ –
1. The ability to deliberate freely about one’s values, identity, and interests without
2. The ability to attempt to effectuate these values, interests, desires in the real world.
Coming back to the main question, we can notice that it holds the following premise: there are
certain circumstances under which permission and obligation to interfere are conceivable or
possible. Given our conceptual analysis, we can display this premise through a triadic
relationship:
This relationship holds when the first part (A n) and the second part (Ap) are trumped by
another value or values (V). We can express this as follows: ‘An < V > Ap.’
4
In this section, I have set up the general logical structure of the question. Much revolves
around how to find the relative value of the autonomy-trumping value or values. In the next
section, I will set the first step towards answering this question.
the psychology of humans, we can look at the sorts of things they respect, find important,
worth protecting, and motivating. I imagine these autonomy-trumping values not to exist as
part of a list of other commitments but rather as part of a complex web of values that
individuals hold.1 What we find important, in general terms, are related to the creation,
preservation, and attainment of things necessary, useful, good, and beautiful – while
distancing ourselves from what we find repulsive and disgusting. Relatedly, autonomy is
generally considered either inherently good or a useful means to other ends. In many cultures,
it holds a certain self-evident weight. In particular, when our actions do not directly harm
others, we expect others to respect our space of action. However, other values might be
What we consider in a positive or a negative light is not only part of the human condition, but
also varies across individual genes, temperaments, and cultures. 2 For most of the benefits of
the world, we need to cooperate with others and we need systems that guarantee our basic
interests. This is along the lines of a Hobbesian contractarianism. 3 Scanlon (2000), on the
other hand, suggests that our moral compass is not only egoistic and self-directed but also
aims to respect others. At any rate, morality also needs to be social in order to make sense
1
Exemplified by the holism of Neurath’s boat. (Neurath 1983, 92)
2
Regarding disgust and morality, social scientist Jonathan Haidt et al., (1994) have done research that shows a
5
given our basic psychological properties. We can derive the following moral psychological
1. Morality is a means to attain and secure positive goods while removing negative ones,
2. motivates us (to some extent) or makes us feel some shame or guilt when we fail to
adhere to them,
This listing finishes our discussion between the inherent relationship between human
psychology and morality. The next two sections will highlight the importance of respect for
judgements as mentioned in this section. In particular, I discuss how our selective respect for
rules.4
institutions such as the judiciary. 5 However, when a soldier of expensive lawyers win a court
from a poor defendant, we may feel there is something fishy about this ruling. Similarly,
when courts of banana republics find all political opponents of the dictator guilty of a crime,
we do not necessarily respect this ruling. This is, in simple terms, what is meant with our
selectiveness of respect for judgements. We do this for our own individual judgements as
well. During calm times, we would not trust our judgement to our future angry, frustrated, or
4
This notion is inspired by the Griffinian informed-desire account which states that ‘utility is the fulfilment of
desires that persons would have if they appreciated the true nature of their objects.’ (Griffin 1989, 11)
5
Primatologist Frans de Waal (2005) explains in Our Inner Ape how our early phylogenetic ancestors such as
chimps, bonobos, but also macaque monkeys have primitive moral dispositions: they care about fairness,
6
manic self. This division between the different states of an individual is not new and is echoed
“[Is justice] truth-telling and paying back what one has received from anyone, or may
these very actions sometimes be just and sometimes unjust? I mean, for example, as
everyone I presume would admit, if one took over weapons from a friend who was in his
right mind and then the lender should go mad and demand them back, that we ought not
to return them in that case and that he who did so return them would not be acting justly
—nor yet would he who chose to speak nothing but the truth to one who was in that
state.”
Plato thought that our souls existed of three parts: the wise, the passionate, and the desirous.
Some modern psychologists have theories that are not too unsimilar to the ancients.
According to them, thinking occurs either through automatic unconscious processes and
explicit and controlled conscious processes.6 This conception of a divided self can also be
found in our usage of the rational and the emotional as separate elements of our being. This
apparent division prompts the question which part of our embodiment gets to decide what we
My assumption is that even though we value our emotions and desires, we do not like to
identify ourselves with our instincts or uncontrollable desires. Tobacco addicts might agree
that they smoke too often, but often add that they want to stop. In other words: the addiction is
conceptualized as external. Moreover, when we are angry, we might temporarily hold other
norms than when we are not. When we are in love, we might let another person mistreat us
6
Part of the dual process theory of thought, argued for psychologists like Daniel Levitt and Daniel Kahneman
(2011).
7
We often either regret or try to forget these actions or omissions. This means that even though
these nonrational states are parts of us, their sole judgements enjoy less respect than our calm,
conscious, and reflective self.7 To be sure, this does not mean that desires and emotions
should be cancelled out or considered void and unimportant for us to respect our judgements.
What is more, implying the psychological primacy of rationality and reflectiveness or its
independence from other dispositions might be seriously misguided. The point is that a certain
peace of mind necessitates some level of prudence that we cannot conjure up when we are
To end, if our selective respectability of judgements, as proposed in this section, is true, what
we believe are our core values cannot be satisfactorily decided or cancelled when we are, for
instance, in an emotional storm, suffer great pains, or are tired and sleepy.
V. Idealized account
The previous section discussed the many ways in which we are in suboptimal states. Given
the ambitious claim of our idealized account, we are more often than not in this deficient
state. This means that proper moral judgement needs either some exertion on the side of the
person who is to judge and criticism of his or her day-to-day judgements. We can, indeed,
either try to approximate this idealized state or use it as a thought experiment: what would our
idealized account decide under these circumstances? So far we have only pointed out one of
the three characteristics of my idealized account: peace of mind versus being overwhelmed
7
Immanuel Kant (1781) referred to this respect for the rational as Achtung (Ak 4:401), which he deemed to be a
guiding motivating principle of human cognition. My account allows for a compassionate or desirous
8
Two other considerations also have a reasonable claim to be part of this account. I now dis-
cuss the second. Imagine, for instance, that someone has a certain peace of mind but does not
have certain other virtues, capacities, and competences. Think of people who are uncareful
when formulating their thoughts leading to frequent contradictions or people who are not soci-
able but have strictly egoistic, narcissistic, or, sociopathic tendencies. To start with a simple
example, an 8-year old might argue that (1) he ought to have full autonomy, while (2) he be-
lieves adults should interfere as much as they want. Regardless of a certain peace of mind,
these two propositions do not allow for a workable ethics. Other problems occur when people
with sociopathic tendencies completely discard sociability, making them lack both impartial-
ity and consistency. The second set of characteristic are therefore: the virtue and competence
But the problems of partiality and inconsistency might require more explanation. In the next
section, I will propose that the antonyms of these two terms (impartiality and consistency) are
the necessary building blocks of moral thinking and should therefore guide much of our moral
reasoning.
In short, this section explored how the idealized subject allows for a procedure of value
assertion which are, upon proper reflection, respected. This procedure will prove useful when
trying to answer what the relative value of other (candidate) values (V) in relationship to
autonomy (A) is. In other words, idealized subjects are part of the procedure to decide when
one may and must interfere with another person and when others are able to do the same.
The next section dives into the question why preventing contradictions, partiality, and
9
VI. Primacy of coherence, impartiality, and consistency
Taking a closer look at the second characteristic of our idealized account, we find certain vir-
tues and competences. These, in turn, lead to the prevention of contradictions, partiality, and,
ular, imply that whatever moral judgements we have in general, should also apply to
ourselves and without exceptions given similar circumstances. That is, we cannot be capri-
cious when a moral judgement risks affecting a member of our family or ourselves, nor can
we decide to have a stronger moral judgement because we have had a bad day. Thus, so far, I
have conceived morality as both socially constructed and both self and other-directed, but
have not yet completely argued why this is a reasonable pragmatic assumption.
I mentioned the Hobbesian contractarianism and the Scanlonian contractualism. The first ar-
gues that we agree to moral norms for our self-protection, the second adds that we also care
about others. In both cases, we have to realize that in order to create a harmonious together-
ness, we need moral systems that guarantee that others respect our rights when we are being
judged and that the caprices of individuals do not become a fear for us. A small minority of
individuals might not feel that others deserve their consideration, they might agree with
Glaucon’s rebuttal from The Republic that ‘it seems best to be have the reputation of being
just, while benefiting from being unjust.’ (Book II) But even they should know that if every-
one would believe this, they would be in a dangerous place. Therefore it is better to instil a
certain level of conscience and virtue in others. In our times, we value inclusiveness and
might not want to discard this egocentric point of view. However, I suggest that living to-
gether in communities and societies require certain basic competences and attitudes that a
small minority of people might simply not hold. Aristotle put this most harshly when he said:
10
“Society is something that precedes the individual. Man is by nature a social
animal; an individual who is unsocial naturally and not accidentally or cannot lead
the common life is either a beast or a god.” (Aristotle, paraphr. Politics 1253a)
Coming back to my previous point, allowing inconsistencies would beat the very purpose of
moral systems, which is to prevent arbitrary and illegitimate interference in our lives and the
lives of others. At any rate, moral systems and attitudes that are partial and inconsistent would
be threats to our basic needs. This intuition is so strong that we do not know of a normative
ethical tradition in our canons that does not emphasise these two conditions. The Kantian
deontologists are sceptical and dismissive of anything that reeks of partiality and
inconsistency when deciding one’s duties, the utilitarians (at least in its standard form)
emphasise impartiality to the point that they remove the special obligations to family
members and loved ones and merely look at happiness creation and pain prevention. The
social contract theorists Hobbes and Locke found such contracts to be necessary or useful to
live in harmony with others without the caprice, arbitrariness, and thus inconsistency and
partiality of other people. Hobbes, admittedly, does allow the Leviathan to be capricious, but
only to prevent the bigger evil: the all-against-all perennial and unpredictable conflicts that,
according to him, are in the nature of pre-society. Much of our ethical canon therefore seems
to look for ways to reduce social anxiety caused by the potential whim of others.
To be sure, this does not mean that impartiality and consistency amount to normative equality
since, for instance, individuals in more authority-oriented societies might expect or want their
leaders to have certain powers they do not have. But even they would agree that he should act
within the bounds of his role e.g. support his people and punish transgression.
To summarize, this section discussed the idealized account in two of the three conditions:
1. Mental calmness
11
2. Reasonableness and virtue preventing failures of moral judgement such as
The next section discusses how these properties ought to interact with our individual context,
the values that we hold, and the cultures that surround us. This discussion will make way to
the assertion of the third and final characteristic of our idealized account which amounts to a
certain critical attitude towards our current values, attitudes, and culture.
VII. Context-specificity
An important part of this argument is that morality is and should be taken as context-specific.
Individual temperament, sex and gender, age and socioeconomic class, family and personal
interests are among contextual factors that can affect the reasoning of the idealized individual.
Especially upbringing and early childhood values might turn out to be the most influential. As
was stated before, our values are connected to the web of other values that we have internal-
ized over time. Remember also the triadic relationship that we had suggested. How much we
value autonomy and what we believe trumps autonomy and under which circumstances do not
occur in voids. They are the products of the embodied history of individuals.
One might therefore ask: since moral judgements are contingent, why do we not hold that all
morality is relative and that, as such, morality is nothing more than one’s expression of norm-
ativity at a given point in time? I reject this for two reasons. First of all, the idealized subject
account of moral judgement does not consider all dispositions, opinions, instincts, or desires
as morally valid. Some people may lack basic rational skills, others might lack the sociability
to form a useful and respectable moral system. Secondly, our idealized account forces us to
reject a naïve absorption of cultural, political, or even legal norms. From time to time, partial
interests and feelings of resentment and hate – think of Nazi Germany – might shift the dis-
12
course of a people towards attitudes they would never have promoted in their children in calm
times.
Another example is how egalitarianism, freedom, and brotherhood mentality can be found in
the canonization of French Revolution thought. The possibility that modern policies of France
(indirectly) promote segregation does not change this paradigmatic value. Nor does it, for in-
stance, change the framework of Christianity that clerics throughout history have been corrupt
e.g. promised heaven in exchange of money or that they were, in more recent times, involved
Finally, the context-specificity does mean that criticisms from one context might not apply to
other contexts. What one group might consider exalted morality, does not have to be
represented by another group of people to be called moral. Cultures are complex systems that
cannot be analysed by viewing a small set of interactions or roles. One might simultaneously
reject the moral validity of patriarchy in one’s own context, while holding that in such
systems fathers ought to take care of the material needs of their wife and children (i.e. are
VIII. Conclusion
With this final part being added, the idealized account can be summarised to hold three
conditions:
2. Reject basic errors through reasonableness and virtue: contradiction, partiality, and
consistency,
3. Aim towards paradigmatic values rather than morality supported by the fashion of the
day.
13
When we approximate or imagine this idealized account, we are most apt to make moral
claims about the moral limit of others. This way, we answer the question when we may and
abortion, or capital punishment are provided. However, this account pushes us to make sure
we are in the right psychological state and that our conventions follow paradigmatic
guidelines. In this way, we provide a procedure based solution that respects the context-
specificity of morality and can demand a higher form of moral discourse that rejects relativist
Bibliography
Aristotle. Aristotle’s Politics. Oxford : Clarendon Press, 1905., 1905. https://search.librar-
y.wisc.edu/catalog/999495662302121.
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/autonomy-moral/.
Griffin, James. Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement, and Moral Importance. Reprint.
Haidt, Jonathan, Clark McCauley, and Paul Rozin. ‘Individual Differences in Sensitivity to
Disgust: A Scale Sampling Seven Domains of Disgust Elicitors’. Personality and Individual
Kahneman, Daniel. Thinking, Fast and Slow. 1st ed. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux,
2011.
14
Kant, Immanuel. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Riga, 1785.
Bibliography of Neurath in English, edited by Otto Neurath, Robert Sonné Cohen, and Marie
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-6995-7_7.
Scanlon, Thomas. What We Owe to Each Other. Nachdr. Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press of
Waal, Frans B. M. de. Our Inner Ape: A Leading Primatologist Explains Why We Are Who
15