2.5 Pistas para Criatividade
2.5 Pistas para Criatividade
2.5 Pistas para Criatividade
MAURITA HARNEY
Swinburne University a/Technology
To some, the topic of AI and Creativity (like the topic of 'machine thinking')
might sound like a contradiction in terms. For creativity in thinking and other activ-
ities, as commonly understood, requires us to withdraw the constraints implicit in
rules and rational appraisal. But what could be more rational or rule-bound than the
model of the mind and cognition on which AI is founded? The implicit connection
here, between creativity and 'irrationalism', owes something to Sigmund Freud,
who saw creativity as the link between art and play. Both are activities pursued
for their own sake, and both involve the suspension of rational principles: "The
creative writer does much the same as the child at play. He creates a world of phan-
tasy which he takes very seriously-that is, which he invests with large amounts of
emotion-while separating it sharply from reality.',1 There is no reason to suppose
that creativity in science is any different. It is identified as that initial phase in
scientific inquiry when the principles of rational evaluation and assessment are sus-
pended and a bold conjecture or intuitive guess is made. It is that phase prior to the
process of testing by means of the rational principles of deduction and induction.
When creativity is identified with thinking which is intuitive, conjectural or
hypothetical, rather than rule-governed or rational, it is tempting to dismiss it as
'irrational'-as something mysterious, ineffable, resistant to attempts to analyse it
or appraise it in any way. However, I prefer to dispense with the dubious dichotomy
of rationaVirrational, and focus instead on the kinds of inquiry which might be called
conjectural, creative, or intuitive. I will be suggesting that conjectural knowledge of
this kind constitutes an epistemological paradigm (in Kuhn's (1970) sense 2 ) which
is different from, but complementary to, the paradigm of scientific knowledge
(which is governed by considerations relating to rational explanation, and notions
of evidence, truth, and justification). It is a paradigm more easily recognisable in
the study of cultural meanings than in standard approaches to the study of scientific
phenomena. For this reason I will be suggesting that we tum to the domain of
cultural inquiry to seek the conceptual tools for analysing the creative component
in scientific discovery. More specifically, I propose to explore some ideas drawn
from recent developments in literary theory and studies in rhetoric. It is here that I
think we might find some valuable insights for conceptual ising the creative process.
Such an exploration is itself an exercise in creativity, for it requires us to transgress
1 Freud, S.: 1959, Creative Writers and Day-Dreaming, standard edn, Vol. IX, Hogarth Press and
the Instirute of Psychoanalysis, London, p. 144, quoted in Storr (1972: 113). Margaret Boden (1990:
46) similatly points out that "creativity has much in common with play".
2 The notion of a conjectural paradigm, however, is derived from Carlo Ginzburg in Eco and
Sebeok (1983).
195
T. Dartnall (ed.). Artificial Intelligence and Creativity, 195-208.
© 1994 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
196 MAURITA HARNEY
the traditional boundaries which demarcate and dichotomise the arts versus the
sciences, the factual versus the mythical, the rational versus the poetic.
The American philosopher C. S. Peirce (1901 ff.) provides us with a useful starting
point for talking about knowledge which is conjectural, creative, or intuitive. He
coined the tenn 'abduction' (variously called 'retroduction' and 'hypothesis') to
describe that initial phase in scientific inquiry when a bold hypothesis is fonned to
explain some surprising fact or observation.
Peirce regarded Kepler's discovery of the elliptical orbit of Mars to be a classic
case of abduction. Kepler's reasoning was as follows: First, the surprising fact of
certain irregularities in the path of Mars is observed. But, if the orbit of Mars were
elliptical, then these movements would be a matter of course. So, hypothetically,
Mars travels in an elliptical orbit:
Or, schematically:
C
If A then C
So, A
If A then C
A
So,C
3 See Tursman (1987) for a detailed discussion of Peirce's logic.
CLUES TO CREATIVITY 197
the process of discovery is not separated from the process of hypothesis evaluation,
the sense in which abduction might be called 'creative' is, to say the least, both
philosophically and computationally uninteresting. Paul Thagard (1988) has used
abduction as a computational mechanism in developing a model of the process of
knowledge-acquisition. He describes a program which uses abduction (along with
analogy and generalisation) to generate the concept 'sound-wave'. This has not been
greeted with enormous enthusiasm-possibly because of the very restricted sense
of creativity that it involves. It works by matching preselected concepts so that its
'creativity' ranking, in the eyes of one reviewer (Schagrin, 1991), is equivalent to
that of completing a multiple-choice test. Moreover, as Thagard himself admits, his
program doesn't take into sufficient account the background knowledge to scientific
conjecture.
Peirce himself did not develop a single unified or consistent theory of abduction.
Nevertheless he presented us with an enormously rich and fertile notion which
others have subsequently developed more fully in a vast range of cognitive domains
dealing with human inquiry. It has, for example, been identified with the mode
of reasoning used by fictional detectives like Sherlock Holmes (notwithstanding
Conan Doyle's claim that the method was one of observation and deduction).
It is a notion which has figured prominently in the writings-both fictional and
philosophical-of Umberto Eco. Eco has an impressive record of scholarship in
the philosophy of language and rhetoric. He is, of course, popularly known for his
fictional works and screen writing as well.
Anyone who is familiar with Umberto Eco's mediaeval detective story, The
Name of the Rose, may have recognised in its opening pages a variation on ano):her
piece of fiction-Voltaire's fairy tale of Zadig. This story tells how Zadig, a very
astute observer of 'the book of nature', was walking in the forest one day when
he met two bands of very agitated men. They were the queen's courtiers and they
were anxiously searching for the queen's horse and her pet dog which had recently
escaped. They asked Zadig if he had seen them. Zadig asked if the horse was a
stallion with a perfect gallop and small hoofs, so many hands high, with a three and
a half foot tail, a gold studded bit and silver shoes. He went on to ask if the dog
was a spaniel bitch which had long ears and an injured left foreleg, and which had
recently given birth to pups. His descriptions were so accurate that the courtiers
exclaimed that he must have seen the horse and the dog. When Zadig denied this,
and said that he had never set eyes on them, the courtiers understandably refused
to believe him. Not only that, they presumed that he must have stolen the beasts,
and promptly dragged him off to prison.
Later, Zadig was able to tell his story. Being a sharp observer of his natural
surroundings, he had perceived several signs-imprints in the soil, a broken branch
and dust on the leaves at a certain height, a trace of gold on a rock, furrows in
the dust, and so forth-and from these had built up a general picture of what had
CLUES 10 CREATIVITY 199
passed by. He had, in other words, formed a hypothesis about what had occurred
on the basis of keenly observed signs.
This same kind of reasoning from observed signs to a general picture of what
caused those signs is the method of investigation used by fictional crime detectives
like Sherlock Holmes, and indeed by Umberto Eco's own fictional sleuth in his
novel, The Name a/the Rose. Here again, in detective fiction, we have the careful
observation of signs or 'clues'-a footprint, a forced lock, a blood-smeared poker,
etc.-from which the detective formulates a hypothesis or general picture of the
possible origins of those clues. In crime detection, this general picture is very
complex, and includes things like motives, intentions, etc.
evidence of this method in the work of Mesopotamian diviners, for whom animals'
innards, stars, drops of oil in water, etc., were read as signs of the future. Ginzburg
(1983: 110) remarks:
It's a matter of kinds of knowledge which tend to be unspoken, whose rules
... do not easily lend themselves to being formally articulated or even spoken
aloud. Nobody learns to be a connoisseur or a diagnostician simply by applying
the rules. With this kind of knowledge there are factors in play which cannot
be measured-a whiff, a glance, an intuition ... 5
The suggestion is that conjectural knowledge constitutes an epistemological
paradigm different from that of scientific knowledge. Scientific knowledge is gov-
erned by considerations of justification, testing, evidence, and notions of truth and
proof. The conjectural paradigm gives primacy to processes of discovery rather
than justification or evaluation, and consists of knowledge that is often regarded as
pre-scientific or even pseudo-scientific. Within this paradigm, the discovery process
is cast as a theory about interpreting signs. Abduction is the underlying method of
interpretation and for this reason constitutes, in Eco's words, a semiotic mechanism.
Semiotics means the science of interpreting signs. Like cognitive science, it has
emerged as an interdisciplinary field of study in recent years. Its focus of inquiry
is cultural meanings. All cultural phenomena (institutions, mythS, dress, sport,
film, advertising, media, etc.) are seen as signs or sign systems whereby meaning
is communicated. Semiotics draws on linguistics, philosophy, literary theory, and
studies in rhetoric for the methods and techniques for 'decoding' or 'deciphering'
these signs.
As a way of re-conceptualising the process of forming bold hypotheses, I will
be suggesting that the abductive phase in scientific inquiry be re-located within
the alternative epistemological paradigm described by Ginzburg as the 'conjectural
paradigm'. Within this context, abduction can be theorised as a semiotic mechanism,
that is, a device used in the interpretation of signs. This might, incidentally, be
regarded as an extension of Peirce's own insights, as Peirce himself is one of the
acknowledged founders of semiotics.
Quoting Peirce's own words, Eco (1984) describes a sign as "something by
knowing which we know something else".6 Eco's notion of 'sign' is articulated
through a careful historical analysis of the notion beginning with Hippocrates'
idea of a sign as a symptom. It is this notion of sign which is operative when
we recognise smoke as a sign of fire. This recognition is abductive in structure.
Smoke only becomes a sign when the interpreter sees the phenomenon/event as
5 Ginzburg's examples of 'conjectural' knowledge are reminiscent of Polanyi's (1962) 'tacit
knowledge'. The conceptual frameworks in each case are different, however.
6 The reference is to Peirce's Collected Papers, 8.332.
CLUES TO CREATIVITY 201
the antecedent of a hypothetical inference of the fonn ifp then q. Understanding
linguistic meaning has precisely the same structure. Our understanding of the
utterance /man/ as meaning rational, mortal animal is not modelled on equivalence
or identity. (It is not of the fonn p if and only if q).7 It is not a function of
substitutability of synonymous tenns. Rather, it is based on hypothesis in the same
way that' Smoke means fire' is. My understanding assumes first that the utterance
/man/ is an utterance (token) of a type of English word: "To recognise a given
phenomenon as the token of a given type presupposes some hypothesis about the
context of utterance and the discursive co-text" (Eco, 1983: 206).
Eco's abductive analyses of such commonplace phenomena are quite consistent
with Peirce's own views. Peirce believed that abduction pervades all of our mental
life, from the most commonplace identifications through to truly revolutionary
scientific discoveries. Perception is a case in point. If certain perceptual data are
present then there is perhaps an inkwell, "as long as other contextual elements
authorise me to think that the perceptual interpretation is appropriate" (Eco, 1984:
35). Taking up Peirce's notion that perception is 'presumptive evidence', Eco (1984)
says: "Perception is always interrogative and conditional and is invariably based
(even if we do not realise it) on a bet ... Perception is ... a source of potential semiosis.
The fact that perception takes place without effort does not invalidate its inferential
mechanism."8 Such inferences are, of course, so commonplace as to be quasi-
automatic. They are what Eco calls 'overcoded abductions', in which the rule (the
'if... then... ' clause) is 'already coded'. This kind of abduction lies at one end of a
spectrum. At the other end are what Eco calls the 'creative abductions' exemplified
in revolutionary scientific discovery like Einstein's Theory of Relativity. Here, the
abduction involves a rule which is invented ex novo. In between are abductions
exemplified by what might be called 'creative problem solving'. Here the rule
is selected from a number of equiprobable rules at our disposal. They are called
'undercoded abductions', and include the kind of inquiry undertaken by fictional
detectives when they reason from observed clues to a hypothesis about 'whodunit',
or the reasoning in routine medical diagnosis.
The further we move along this spectrum, the more creative the hypothesis; the
more creative the hypothesis, the riskier it is.
The process of reasoning which leads to a conjecture or hypothesis has been likened
to the construction of a narrative or plot. A plot, unlike a chronicle or mere list of
events, is a coherent, schematic whole (polkinghome, 1988: 19):9
T Bco's insistence on reserving the hypothetical (if. .. then ... ) relation as the model for sign·
inteIpretation, and distancing it from the equivalence (... if and only if. .. ) relation (represented by
synonymy) preserves Peirce's important logical distinction between abduction and deduction.
8 Bco's reference is Peirce's CoUected Papers, 5.266-68.
9 Polkinghome's work includes a study of ways in which narrative is treated as a cognitive structure.
See 1988, chapter 5.
202 MAURITA HARNEY
10 Polkinghome's own approach is not semiotic. However, his approach is consistent with the more
general project of drawing on the insights ofliterary theory to make sense of the nature of knowledge
and inquiry in other, seemingly unrelated, domains.
CLUES TO CREATNITY 203
11 Schank (1990) uncritically conflates the ability "to connect together experiences which are not
obviously connectable" with "generalisation", claiming that the latter is essential to creativity.
12 There are differences amongst semioticians as to the application of these distinctions. These
differences need not concern us here.
204 MAURITA HARNEY
1
~ _,~,,~ ,.~._"., .~,,~"
metonymy
1
boats traversed the water
13 Jakobson's 'structuralist' approach to the relationship between cognition, linguistics and rhetoric
has established his reputation as a forefather of modem semiotics. 'Non-structuralist' approaches to
the study of metaphor and its relation to cognition include the work of Lakoff (1987), and Lakoff and
Johnson (1980).
CLUES TO CREATIVITY 207
References
Achinstein, P.: 1971, Law and Explanation: An Essay in the Philosophy o/Science, Clarendon Press,
Oxford.
Boden, M.: 1990, The Creative Mind: Myths and Mechanisms, Weidenfeld and Nicolson, London.
CUller, J.: 1981, The Pursuit o/Signs: Semiotics, Literature, Deconstruction, Routledge and Kegan
Paul, London.
Eco, U.: 1976, A Theory o/Semiotics, lndiana University Press, Bloomington.
Eco, U.: 1979, The Role o/the Reader, Indiana University Press, Bloomington.
Eco, U.: 1983, Horns, hooves, insteps, in, Eco, U. and Sebeok, T. A. (eds), The Sign o/Three: Dupin,
Holmes, Peirce, Indiana University Press, Bloomington.
Eco, U.: 1984, Semiotics and the Philosophy o/Language, lndiana University Press, Bloomington.
Eco, U. and Sebeok, T. A. (eds): 1983, The Sign of-Three: Dupin, Holmes, Peirce, lndiana University
Press, Bloomington.
Eco, U.: 1990, The Limits 0/ Interpretation, lndiana University Press, Bloomington.
Eco, U., Santambrogio, M. and Violi, P. (eds): 1988, Meaning and Mental Representation, University
of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Fiske,J.: 1982, Introduction to Communication Studies, Methuen, London.
Ginzburg, C.: 1983, Morelli, Freud and Sherlock Holmes, in Eco, U. and Sebeok, T. A. (eds), The
Sign o/Three: Dupin, Holmes, Pdrce, lndiana University Press, Bloomington, pp. 81-118.
Harman, G.: 1965,lnference to the best explanation, Philosophical Review, 64: 88-95.
Hawkes, T.: 1977, Structuralism and Semiotics, Methuen, London.
Hofstadter, D. R: 1985, Metamagical Themas: Questingfor the Essence 0/ Mind and Pattern, Basic
Books, New York.
Jakobson, R: 1956, Two aspects of language and two types of linguistic disturbances, in Jakobson,
R. and Halle, M. (eds), Fundamentals o/Languages, Mouton, The Hague.
Jakobson, R. and Halle, M. (eds): 1956, Fundamentals o/Language, Mouton, The Hague.
Johnson-Laird, P. N.: 1988, The Computer and the Mind, Fontana, London.
Kuhn, T.: 1970, The Structure 0/ Scientific Revolutions, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Lakoft', G.: 1987, Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Lakoft', G. and Johnson, M.: 1980, Metaphors We Live By, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Lodge, D.: 1977, The Modes 0/ Madern Writing: Metaphor, Metonymy, and the Typology 0/ Madern
Literature, Edward Arnold, London.
O'Rorke, P. (ed.): 1990, Working Notes of the 1990 Spring Symposium on Automated Abduction,
Technical Report 90-32, University of California, Irvine.
Partridge, D. and Wilks, Y. (eds.): 1990, The Foundations 0/ Arrijicial Intelligence: A Sourcebook,
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Peirce, C. S.: 1878, Deduction, induction, and hypothesis, in Cohen, M. R (ed.), 1923, Chance, Love,
and Logic, Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner, pp. 131-153.
Peirce, C. S.: 1901, Abduction, induction and deduction, in Burks, A. W. (ed.), 1966, Collected
paperso/Charles Sanders Peirce, Vol. VII, BelKnap Press, Cambridge Mass.
Peirce, C. S.: 1901ft'., Abduction and induction, combining selections from mss of 1901, 1903, 1896
and 1908, in Buchler, J. (ed.), The Philosophy 0/ Peirce. Selected Writings, Routledge & Kegan
Paul, London, 1940, pp. 150-56.
Polanyi, M.: 1962, Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-critical Philosophy, Routledge & Kegan
Paul, London, corrected version 1962.
Polkinghorne, D. E.: 1988, Narrative Knowing and the Human Sciences, State University of New
York Press, Albany.
Punch, W. F., Tanner, M. C., Josephson, J. R, and Smith, J. W.: 1990, Peirce: A toolfor experimenting
with abduction, IEEE Expert, October: 34-44.
208 MAURITA HARNEY
Schagrin, M. L.: 1991, Review of Paul Thagard, Computational Philosophy of Science, Minds and
Machines, 1(1): 121-124.
Schank, R.: 1990, What is AI anyway'! in Partridge, D. and Wilks, Y. (eds), The Foundations of
Artificial Intelligence: A Sourcebook, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 3-13.
Storr, A.: 1972, The Dynamics of Creation, Seker and Warburg, London.
Thagard, P.: 1988, A Computational Philosophy of Science, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Tursman, R.: 1987, Peirce's Theory of Scientific Discovery, Indiana University Press, Bloomington.