Does Culture Evolve (Fracchia & Lewontin, 1999)
Does Culture Evolve (Fracchia & Lewontin, 1999)
Does Culture Evolve (Fracchia & Lewontin, 1999)
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Wiley and Wesleyan University are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to History
and Theory.
http://www.jstor.org
JOSEPHFRACCHIAAND R. C. LEWONTIN
ABSTRACT
In his well-known "Two Cultures" essay C. P. Snow reported a gap between the
literary and natural-scientific cultures. Acknowledging that "a good deal of the
scientific feeling" is shared by some of his "American sociological friends,"
Snow was well aware that there was a degree of artificiality in limiting the num-
ber of cultures to the "very dangerous" one of two. Yet, he based his binarist
decision largely on the cohesion of the natural-scientific and literary communi-
ties that made of them cultures "not only in an intellectual but also in an anthro-
pological sense."' The intellectual division of labor and the development of dis-
ciplinary languages certainly seem to substantiate his reference to two incom-
mensurate cultures. Anyone who has sat on a university committee reviewing
grant proposals from, and consisting of citizens of, each of the cultures must have
observed the pattern of who accuses whom of using jargon and be convinced that
at least the academic version of Snow's gap, that between the humanities and the
natural sciences, has widened into a seemingly unbridgeable abyss. It has
become commonplace that the two cultures have nothing in common.
Perhaps, however, too much has been made of this abyss. Members of the lit-
erary culture, and of the humanities in general, may be appalled at the thought of
1. C. P. Snow, The Two Culturesand a Second Look (Cambridge,Eng., 1964), 8-9.
4. Leslie White, Preface to Evolutionand Culture,ed. MarshallSahlins and Elman Service (Ann
Arbor, 1960), v.
5. Ibid., vii.
for."Against all claims for their uniquenesshe insists that the traditionalsocial
sciences have been "superseded"by, and will only become truly scientific when
subsumedunder,sociobiology.10
More recently, anthropologistJohn Tooby and psychologist Leda Cosmides
have also chastised the social sciences for their "self-conscious stance of intel-
lectual autarky";their "disconnectionfrom the rest of science has left a hole in
the fabricof our organizedknowledge where the humansciences shouldbe." The
lack of progressin the social sciences has been caused by their"failureto explore
or accept their logical connections to the rest of the body of science-that is, to
causally locate their objects of study inside the larger network of scientific
knowledge."11
This desideratum is the cornerstone of the journal Politics and the Life
Sciences whose editors and contributorsinsist that the social sciences must be
nested within the life sciences. The hopes for a synthesis implicit in thejournal's
name were expressed by Richard Shelly Hartigan in a flattering review of
RichardD. Alexander's The Biology of Moral Systems (1987). Predictingmari-
tal bliss, Hartiganconfidently asserts that "the lengthy divorce of the natural
from the humansciences is aboutto end with reunion.Though the nuptialsmay
be delayed awhile, the partiesare at least getting to know each other again more
intimately."12The reunionconsists of articles devoted to the "Darwinian"expla-
nationof such topics as social alienation,the nucleararmsrace, the legal process,
social stratification,oral argumentin the supreme court, the relation between
humanintelligence and nationalpower, and even feminism.'3
These examples could be multiplied,but as this brief overview indicates, the
biggest engineeringprojectattemptingto bridgethe gap at least between the cul-
tures of the naturaland the human sciences over the last few decades has been
initiatedby naturalscientists, anxious perhapsabouthaving wageredtheirraison
d'etre on the success of their imperialistventure;and it has quickly drawn the
participationof those social scientists optimistic about overcoming their inferi-
ority complex and gaining respectabilityby groundingtheir own disciplines in
the natural sciences. The bridge itself is the concept of "culturalevolution"
whose scientific girders are the categories and explanatorylaws either directly
borrowedor derived from a narrowlyselectionist approachto the study of bio-
logical evolution.
10. Ibid., 4, 158.
11. Leda Cosmides and JohnTooby, "ThePsychological Foundationsof Culture,"in TheAdapted
Mind, ed. JeromeH. Barkow,Leda Cosmides, and John Tooby (Oxford, 1992), 22-23.
12. Richard Shelly Hartigan, "A Review of The Biology of Moral Systems" by Richard D.
Alexander,in Politics and the Life Sciences 7, no. 1 (1988), 96.
13. See for example the following essays, all from Politics and the Life Sciences: Elliot White,
"Self-selection and Social Life: The Neuropolitics of Alienation-The Trapped and the Over-
whelmed" (vol. 7, no. 1, 1989); John H. Beckstrom, "EvolutonaryJurisprudence:Prospects and
Limitationson the Use of Modern DarwinismThroughoutthe Legal Process" (vol. 9, no. 2, 1991);
Lee Ellis, "A Biosocial Theoryof Social StratificationDerived from the Conceptsof Pro/Anti-social-
ity and r/K Selection" (vol. 10, no. 1, 1991); Hames N. Schubertet al., "ObservingSupremeCourt
Oral Argument: A Biosocial Approach" (vol. 11, no. 1, 1992); Larry Arnhart, "Feminism,
Primatology,and Ethical Naturalism"(vol. 11, no. 2, 1992).
At the outset we must make clear what the issue of culturalevolution is not
about.First, there is no question that cultureas a phenomenonhas evolved from
the absence of culture as a consequence of biological change. Whether or not
otherprimateshave cultureon some definition,the insectivores, from which the
primates evolved, do not, so at some stage in biological evolution culture
appearedas a novelty. Second, no one challenges the evident fact thathumancul-
tureshave changed since the first appearanceof Homo sapiens, but not even the
most biologistic theory proposes that majorchanges within the phenomenonof
culture-say the inventionof an alphabetor of settled agriculture-was a conse-
quenceof genetic evolution of the humancentralnervoussystem. Humanculture
has had a history,but to say that cultureis a consequence of a historicalprocess
is not the same as saying that it evolves. What constitutes an evolutionary
process as opposed to a "merely"historicalone? What explanatorywork is done
by claiming that culturehas evolved?
Leslie White's cri de coeur accusing the Boasians of aligning themselves with
anti-evolutionistcreationismconfoundstwo quite differentissues. The mid-nine-
teenth-centurystruggle against evolution, mirroredin modern Christian cre-
ationism,was not over whetherthe succession of life forms from earliertimes to
the present has some law-like propertiesthat give some shape to that history.
Ratherit was, and remains,a denial that organismicforms have had a history at
all, that there has been significant change in species and that present-daylife
forms arosefrom othersquite unlike them. But no one denies thatculturehas had
a history,that industrialproductionarose from societies that were at a previous
time pastoralistand agricultural.Not even the most literal of fundamentalists
thinks that God createdthe motor car on the sixth day. Ironicallyit is a form of
traditional Christianity that simultaneously denies an intelligible history to
organic life as a whole, while asserting a directionalityto human history, the
ascent towardfinal redemptionfrom the depths of the Fall.
White's identificationof the struggleover culturalevolution with the struggle
over organic evolution, if it is more than a deliberatepiece of propagandain a
battle for academic legitimacy, is really a struggle over the natureof historical
processes.At base, it is meantto be a rejectionof the propositionthathumancul-
turalhistory is just one damn thing after another,claiming that, on the contrary,
thereis an underlyingnomotheticprocess. But in assertingthe claim thatculture
evolves White claimed more than what was necessary. History may indeed be
law-like in some sense, but does that make a historical process evolutionary?
There may be law-like constraintson historical change like Ibn Khaldun'srule
that "Bedouinscan gain control only over flat territory,"but we do not therefore
characterizethe Muqaddimahas providing an "evolutionary"theory of history,
any more thanHegel's thirdkind of history,the Philosophical,is claimed to be a
theory of evolution.'4
It might be assertedthatfor theoriesto qualify as evolutionarythey must con-
sist of more than mere constraintsand prohibitions;ratherthey must be charac-
14. Ibn Khaldun,The Muqaddimah(Princeton,1958), chapter2:24.
previous step of transformationto provide the initial state for the next change. It
is not necessarythat the complete unfolding be predictablefrom the very origin
of the system because successive steps may be contingent.There may be more
than one local unfolding possible from a given state, and these alternativesmay
be chosen, contingenton variousexternalcircumstances.Transformationaltheo-
ries, nevertheless, usually assume a very restricted contingency, putting very
strong constraintson which states may succeed each other, and in what order.
Indeed the standard theory of embryonic development which provides a
metaphoricalbasis for developmentaltheories of evolution assumes that there is
one and only one possible succession of states.Thus, there is one direction,or at
most a few alternativepossible directions of change immanentin the natureof
the objects.Directionalitydoes not in itself imply thatchangeis monotoneor that
there is a repeatedcycling among states along some simple axis, yet again and
again transformationaltheoriestake the form of a "Lawof Increaseof . . .," com-
plexity, efficiency, control over resources or energy, of Progressitself. The task
of filling in the blanks we leave to later pages. A variationaltheory,in contrast,
does not have directionalitybuilt into it because the variationon which the sort-
ing process operatesis not intrinsicallydirectional,and changes in the statistical
distributionof types in the ensemble are assumedto be the consequenceof exter-
nal circumstancesthat are causally independentof the variation.Nevertheless,
one-way directionalityhas penetratedDarwinismby means of a claim aboutnat-
ural selection. If the differentialnumericalrepresentationof differenttypes in a
species occurs not by chance events of life and death,but because the properties
of some organismsconfer on them greaterability to survive and reproducein the
environmentin which they find themselves, might there not be some properties
thatwould confer a generaladvantageover most or all environments?Such prop-
erties, then, ought to increase across the broadsweep of organismsand over the
long durationof evolutionaryhistory,puttingaside any particularitiesof history.
So, for example, it has been claimed thatcomplexity has increasedduringorgan-
ic evolution, since complex organismsare supposed somehow to be able to sur-
vive betterthe vagaries of an uncertainworld. Unfortunatelyno agreementcan
be reachedon how to measurecomplexity independentof the explanatorywork
it is supposed to do. It is, in fact, characteristicof directionalitytheories that
organismsare first arrayedalong an axis from lower to higher and then a search
is institutedfor some propertythat can be arguedto show a similar ordering.
From directionalityit is only a short step to a theory of stages. Transfor-
mationaldevelopmentaltheories are usually describedas a movement from one
stage to the next in the sequence,from savageryto barbarismto civilization, from
artisanalproductionto competitive industrialcapitalism to monopoly capital.
Development begins by some triggering,startingthe process from its germ, but
there are thoughtto be a succession of orderedstages throughwhich each entity
must pass, the successful passage throughone stage being the conditionfor mov-
ing on to the next. Variationamong individualentities then arises because there
is some variation in the speed of these transitions, but primarily because of
vation that offspring had some general resemblance to their parents, neither
Darwin nor Lamarckhad the benefit of a coherenttheory of inheritance,so they
had to content themselves with a variety of ad hoc notions about the passage of
characteristics,all of which had in common that the properties of individual
organismswere somehow directly influencedby the propertiesof their biologi-
cal parentsat the time of conception. Theorists of culturalevolution, conscious
of the need for a theory of inheritance,yet deprivedof any compelling evidence
for particularlaw-like mechanismsfor the transgenerationalpassage of cultural
change, are in a much more difficultposition, althoughthey do not seem to have
realizedit, because they do not even know whetheran actor-to-actor,not to speak
of a parent-to-offspring,model of the passage of culturehas any general applic-
ability.
19. Evolutionand Cultureis the work of four authors,each of whom contributeda chapterto the
volume: Thomas Harding,David Kaplin, MarshallSahlins, and Elman Service. The most influential
of these has been Sahlins's "Evolution:Specific and General."Sahlins's approachto culturehas, of
course, evolved considerablysince 1960.
20. M. Sahlins, "Evolution: Specific and General," in Evolution and Cuture, ed. Sahlins and
Service, 20.
ever full of sound and fury, this debate is essentially an intramuralaffair. For
beneath all the differences in details, there is a paradigmaticunity among
Darwiniantheories of culturalevolution based on the assumptionthat cultural
evolution can and must be explained in terms isomorphicwith the three princi-
ples of Darwin's variationalscheme. Before they can proceed with that explana-
tion, however, culturalevolutionists undertakea clean-upproject, accomplished
throughsleights of conceptualhand,thatclears away anythingbetween the "bio-
logical" and the "cultural"thatmight have a constitutiveeffect in the production
and"evolution"of culturalforms.This entails firstof all the disappearanceof the
social or, at least, deprivingthe social of causal efficacy, and then the neutraliz-
ing of culture.
The easiest way to make society disappearis simply to dissolve it by defini-
tionalfiat into a mere population.E. 0. Wilson, for example, writes:"Whensoci-
eties are viewed strictly as populations, the relationshipbetween culture and
hereditycan be definedmore precisely."23RobertBoyd and PeterRichersonstate
rathercategorically that "culturalevolution, like genetic evolution in a sexual
species, is always a group or population phenomenon";and in a later work:
"because cultural change is a population process, it can be studied using
Darwinianmethods."24A more nuancedway of dissolving society into a collec-
tion of atomistic individualsis to create a choice between two extreme alterna-
tives. Melvin Konner, for example, correctly rejects the society-as-organism
metaphorby contrastingthe cell that is devoted "entirely to the survival and
reproductionof the organism"with "thepurposesof the individualhuman [that]
are wedded to the survival and reproductionof the society only transientlyand
skeptically."But he overdrawsthe consequencesof this obvious insight and con-
cludes that evolution "has designed the individual with a full complement of
independenceand a canny ability to subvert,or at least try to subvert,the pur-
poses of society to its own. Every time a humanbeing gets fed up with his or her
society or churchor club or even family, and voluntarilychanges affiliation,we
have anotherfactual disproof of the centralmetaphorof social and political sci-
ence."25Here he assumes thatthe repudiationof the obviously false metaphorof
society as organismis a justificationfor an equally obviously false atomisticindi-
vidualism that renderssociety a mere population.
However accomplished,the dissolution of societies into populationsor, as in
more nuancedapproaches,the reductionof differentialsocial power to the status
of a subordinatevariable,26precludes the possibility that social systems might
have propertiesuniqueto them as organizedsystems, thatis, that social relations
might be characterizedby structuresof unequal power that affect individual
social behaviorand the fitness of culturaltraits.This dissolution means, in turn,
that social hierarchyand inequalityare explained as just the consequence of the
differentialculturalfitness of individualsor of the culturaltraitsthey bear,rather
than, say, as a consequenceof antagonisticand exploitative social relations.27
25. Melvin Konner,The Tangled Wing:Biological Constraintson the Human Spirit (New York,
1982), 414.
26. Unawareof the implicationsof theirreductionof societies to populations,Boyd and Richerson,
muchto theirsurprise,foundthemselvescriticizedby David Rindos("TheEvolutionof the Capacityfor
Culture:Sociobiology,Structuralism, andCulturalSelectionism,"CurrentAnthropology27 [1986], 315-
316) andWilliamDurham(Coevolution,179ff.) for not havingadequatelyaddressedthe social. In their
directresponseto Rindos(includedin Rindos,327), Boyd andRichersonclaim, correctly,thatthey spent
an entirechapterof theirCultureand the EvolutionaryProcess on "thescale of humansocial organiza-
tion,"implying,incorrectly,thattherewiththe matterwas resolved.Thatchapterfirstdevelops a taxono-
my of biases (direct,indirect,and frequencydependent)and then constructsmodels to analyzehow the
frequencyof these biases affects the transmissionof culture.Thoughsuch biases certainlyaffect social
behavior,theiroriginsandpersistencearenowherediscussed.Consequently,they end up explaininghow
social biases affect individualchoice by transformingcliches into explanatoryprinciples:"When in
Rome,do as the Romansdo"becomesthe law of "frequency-dependent bias"(286) and"keepingup with
the Joneses"the law of "indirectbias"(287). The questionsof whetherall Romansdo as some Romans
do or of whetherkeepingup with the Jonesesmakessense in societies not basedon commodityproduc-
tion andexchangeare crucialquestionsthatdisappearin theirbiases.
Durhammakes perhapsthe most concertedeffort to considerasymmetriesof social power and the
"imposition"of group values on individual"choice"(Coevolution,198-199). He identifies "reference
groups"withina given population,therebyacknowledging"thesimple fact thatculturalevolutionis an
intrinsicallypoliticalprocess"(211). Because he does not ask the essentialquestionsof why particular
"referencegroups"exist andwhatis the distinctlyanddiscretesocial logic behindparticularasymmetries
in grouppower,Durhamcan only treatany particularset of referencegroupsand social asymmetriesof
poweras arbitraryandsubordinatevariablefactorsaffectingindividualchoice, ratherthanas constitutive
factorsof social and culturalformsand their"evolution."
27. The most perspicaciouscriticof theoriesthatreducesocieties to populationswas KarlMarx.The
hallmarkof politicaleconomy and the sourceof its errors,Marx argued,was that it took as its starting
point the populationwithouthaving determinedthe componentsof the populations,its "subgroups"or
classes and the logic of theirinternalrelations.Such an approachwould producenot "a rich totalityof
many determinationsand relations,"but "ever thinnerabstractions"and "a chaotic conceptionof the
whole"(Marx-EngelsReader,ed. RobertTucker[New York, 1978], 237). Or as he latersummarizedit
more succinctly:societyey does not consist of individuals,but expressesthe sum of interrelations,the
relationswithin which these individualsstand"(247). The analysis of a society reveals much aboutits
population,but the converseis not necessarilytrue.
Having taken the crucial preliminarystep of dissolving society, the next step
is, perhaps surprisingly,to neutralizeculture as well. In order to qualify as an
instanceof a variationaltheoryof evolution, culturemust be provento consist of
isolatable, individualentities, and to be only the sum of its parts. It is thus nec-
essary to refute any and all claims thatcultureshave unique and discreteproper-
ties and a system-specificlogic thatrequirethem to be analyzedeach on its own
terms. This is sometimes done by definitionalfiat aimed at anothersuperorgan-
ismic strawman. E. 0. Wilson, for example, insists that "culturesare not super-
organismsthatevolve by theirown dynamics."Culture,concursJeromeBarkow,
"is not a 'thing,' not a concrete, tangible object. It isn't a cause of anything.To
describebehaviouras 'cultural'tells us only that the action and its meaning are
sharedand not a matterof individualidiosyncrasy."28
The definitionalfiats thatposited population-likemodels of culturereceived at
least two slight challenges. Discontentwith an excessively atomisticview of cul-
ture, Bernardo Bernardi, for example, constructs a constellation of "anthro-
pemes" consisting of "ethnemes,"themselves subdivided into "idioethnemes"
and "socioethnemes";and Martin Stuart-Foxdivides memes into mentemes.29
Though these attemptsappearto reject the notion of isolated, individualmemes
and to aim at systematiccomplexity, they fall short.Tellingly, in suggesting the
division of the meme into mentemes, Stuart-Foxquite consciously attemptedto
constructa categorialanalogywith modernlinguistic terminology.But he did not
follow up this overtureand consider Saussure's fundamentalinsight on which
modem linguistics is based, namely that meaning is system-specific, that each
term (sign) acquiresits historically-specificmeaning by virtue of its place with-
in a discreteset of differentialrelations.By neglecting this insight, attemptssuch
as Stuart-Fox'sand Bernardi'sfocus only on the aggregateratherthan the sys-
temic. Only additive in method, they treatmemes as aggregatesof smallerenti-
ties, as cultural molecules composed of cultural atoms-which effects only a
slight displacementof their ontological individualism,reproducingit at the level
of compounds.
Coevolutionistshave also made overturesto the systemic characterof culture
by removing it from a tight genetic leash and insisting that cultureevolves rela-
tively autonomouslyon its own culturaltrack. But regardlessof the numberof
evolutionarytracksadvocated,all theories of culturalevolution pay only lip ser-
vice to the complexity of culture:because they persistin treatingcultureas mere-
ly the sum total of individual cultural units at a given stage in the selection
process, as a kind of "stateof the 'memes"' at a given point in time, they deny
cultureany system-specificcharacteristics;and this, in turn,allows all culturesto
be explained according to the same (transhistoricaland therefore ahistorical)
selectionist logic.
28. E. 0. Wilson, On Human Nature, 78; Jerome Barkow, Darwin, Sex, and Status: Biological
Approachesto Mind and Culture(Toronto,1989), 142.
29. Bernardo Bernardi, "The Concept of Culture:A New Presentation"in The Concepts and
Dynamics of Culture,ed. BernardoBernardi(The Hague, 1977); Martin Stuart-Fox,"The Unit of
Replicationin Socio-culturalEvolution,"Journalof Social and Biological Structures9 (1986), 67-90.