Episodic Memory - Scholarpedia

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 7

Episodic memory

Endel Tulving and Karl K. Szpunar (2009), Scholarpedia, 4(8):3332. doi:10.4249/scholarpedia.3332 revision #91236 [link to/cite this article]

Dr. Endel Tulving, Rotman Research Institute of Baycrest, University of Toronto, CANADA

Dr. Karl K. Szpunar, Department of Psychology, Harvard University

Episodic memory is the name given to the capacity to consciously remember personally experienced events
and situations. It is one of the major mental (cognitive) capacities enabled by the brain.

Contents
1 Example
2 Overview
3 Terminology
4 Relations between episodic and semantic memory
4.1 Common features
4.2 Unique features of episodic memory
5 Episodic memory: 2009
6 Open issues
6.1 Autobiographical memory
6.2 Episodic memory in nonhuman animals
6.3 Adaptive value
7 References
8 Recommended readings
9 See also

Example

In the prototypical act of exercising the capacity of episodic memory one may remember a recent trip to Paris,
mentally reliving events that happened there, in the mind’s eye seeing again the places visited, sights seen,
sounds heard, aromas smelled, and people met.

Overview

Memory is an umbrella term that covers a variety of different forms of acquisition, retention, and use of habits,
skills, knowledge, and experience. Those who study memory have found it useful to assume that different forms
of learning and memory are subserved by different memory systems--organized collections of neurocognitive
components that work together to perform functions that other collections of components cannot perform, or
cannot perform as well. An important objective of research has to do with the identification of these memory
systems, specification of their properties, and delineation of the nature of the relations among them.

Historically, the most basic distinction is that between procedural memory (an action system that is
expressed through behavior; e.g., when riding a bicycle) and declarative memory (a cognitive system that is
expressed through propositional knowledge; e.g., when taking a classroom test). Both procedural and declarative
memory are seen as consisting of a number of subdivisions (Eichenbaum & Cohen, 2001; Schacter & Tulving,
1994; Schacter, Wagner, & Buckner, 2000; Squire, 1992; Squire & Kandel, 1999; Squire & Zola, 1998). This
article describes a theory of episodic memory, one of the two assumed subdivisions of declarative memory.
However, because the theory of episodic memory can be only incompletely understood in isolation of the other
assumed subdivision of declarative memory, semantic memory--the system that enables us to acquire and
retain factual knowledge about the world (e.g., knowing that Paris is a nice city to visit in the springtime) and
from which episodic memory is thought to have evolved, much of the discussion will focus on episodic memory
in relation to semantic memory.

Terminology

In this article, the term ‘episodic memory’ refers to a unique memory system (or capacity) of the brain. However,
that is not the only meaning of episodic memory that one will find in the literature. For instance, the term is
often used to describe the specific experience (content) that comes to mind when exercising the capacity of
episodic memory and the accompanying feeling (phenomenology) that one is currently reliving that previous
experience. In the interest of clarity, this article will refer to the contents of episodic memory as ‘remembered
experiences’ and the phenomenological experience as ‘remembering.’ A similar issue exists in relation to the
concept of semantic memory. Presently, the term ‘semantic memory’ also stands for a capacity of the brain. The
structured contents of the semantic memory system are referred to as ‘knowledge’ and the phenomenological
experience as ‘knowing’ (Gardiner & Richardson-Klavehn, 2000).

Relations between episodic and semantic memory

According to the theory of episodic memory, the assumed evolutionary sequence of episodic memory growing
out of semantic memory is reflected in the global, monohierarchical relation between the two. That is, episodic
memory shares with semantic memory many features that distinguish both of them (i.e., all of declarative
memory) from other major subdivisions of memory, yet it also possesses features that it does not share with any
other memory system, including semantic memory (Mishkin, Suzuki, Gadian, & Vargha-Khadem, 1997; Tulving,
1995). The monohierarchical relation also implies that episodic memory depends on semantic memory in its
operations and cannot function without relevant components of semantic memory, whereas semantic memory
does not depend on episodic memory in its operations and can function without episodic memory. This kind of a
relation between the two memory systems mimics many other similar relations in the living world. As a single
example, consider the relation between a visual system that has no sense of color and a visual system that does:
The latter has everything that the former has, plus more.

What makes episodic memory special is that it makes possible mental time travel into the past, as well as into the
future, as will be seen below. No other memory system has the same capacity, at least not in the sense that
episodic memory does.

Common features
Some of the features (or “properties”) that episodic memory shares with semantic memory are:

Both systems allow the organism to know about aspects of its world that are not immediately present.
Encoding of new information [converting perceptual and cognitive input into ‘memory traces’ (engrams)] is
fast and may occur on a single trial.
Encoded information (memory traces) may be multimodal (polymodal).
Storage of encoded information is transmodal: both remembered experiences and knowledge can be stored
independent of the modality through which they were acquired.
Storage of information is highly structured.
Storage of information is highly sensitive to context.
Stored information is representational (isomorphic) with what is or could be in the world.
Access to stored information during retrieval is flexible, within limits.
Behavioral expression of what is retrieved is optional and not obligatory. Thus, it is possible to hold the
retrieved information online, and just contemplate it.
Retrieval of information in both systems requires consciousness. It is not possible to directly retrieve
information from either episodic or semantic memory nonconsciously. Of course, various processes that
underlie the retrieval of remembered experiences and knowledge may take place beyond conscious
awareness.
The operations of neither system depend on language, although language may greatly facilitate them.
The shared features of both systems are present in a wide range of animals; they are highly evolved in
mammals and birds.
The operations of both systems are subserved by shared, widely distributed, cerebral cortical and subcortical
neural networks; especially critical are those in medial temporal lobes and the diencephalon.
Any one of these properties applies equally well to both episodic and semantic memory. It is their conjunction
that allows us sometimes to classify both episodic and semantic memory together under the general label of
declarative (also referred to as cognitive or explicit) memory, without further differentiating between them. In
many situations, both in the laboratory and real life, such generalization is justifiable. In others, however, it is
not, because episodic memory, in addition to the properties listed above, also possesses unique properties that
are shared by neither semantic nor any other memory system.

Unique features of episodic memory


Some of the features (or “properties”) that are unique to episodic memory are:
The key function of episodic memory is to allow the individual to remember personal past happenings as
such; semantic memory is not capable of this function.
This remembering takes the form of mentally “traveling” in subjectively experienced time. Semantic memory
does not have anything special to do with time, other than the (trivial) fact that the knowledge that is brought
to mind in the course of exercising this capacity was once learned in the past.
Episodic memory, unlike semantic memory, is self-centered. The operations of episodic memory are
predicated on one's conscious awareness of oneself as an independent entity that is separate from the rest of
the world. In the absence of such awareness, episodic remembering is not possible.
Episodic remembering expresses itself phenomenally through the medium of a distinctive form of conscious
awareness that is familiar to all people in the sense that they know when they are remembering and not
perceiving, or imagining, or daydreaming, or having any other kind of conscious experience. The conscious
awareness accompanying semantic knowing has a different flavor, clearly distinct from that of remembering.
The two kinds of consciousness involved in episodic remembering and semantic knowing have been named
‘autonoetic’ and ‘noetic,’ respectively (Tulving, 1985; Wheeler, Stuss, & Tulving, 1997).
Episodic remembering requires the activation, by way of voluntary or involuntary processes, of a special kind
of mental state that has been called ‘episodic retrieval mode.’ The operational default memory state is
semantic, characterized by noetic consciousness.
The ontogenetic development of episodic memory is delayed in relation to that of semantic memory: Children
acquire a great deal of knowledge about the world they live in before they are aware of their own past
personal experiences (Nelson & Fivush, 2004).
Episodic memory tends to be more vulnerable to disease, injury, and the ravages of old age than is semantic
memory. Brain damage is more likely to impair episodic remembering than semantic knowing, and in
dementias such as Alzheimer's disease the impairment of episodic memory is frequently the first symptom to
appear (Kitchener, Hodges, & McCarthy, 1998; Klein, Loftus, & Kihlstrom, 2002; Rosenbaum et al., 2005;
Vargha-Khadem et al., 1997).
Episodic memory that all healthy humans possess probably does not exist in other animals, although
‘episodic-like’ memory capacities have already been identified in several species (Clayton, Bussey, &
Dickinson, 2003; Griffiths, Dickinson, & Clayton, 1999; Olton, 1984).
Episodic memory is dependent on neural networks that extend beyond those that subserve the operations of
semantic memory (Aggleton & Pearce, 2001; Nyberg et al., 2000).
Some of these features are more reasonable in light of empirical evidence than others. The whole enterprise of
studying multiple memory systems is in an early stage. Therefore a great deal of further work and thought is
required, and indeed is being spent, on many aspects of the problem (Dere, Easton, Nadel, & Huston, 2008;
Szpunar & McDermott, 2008; Tulving, 2002a).

Today, a thumbnail description of episodic memory can be defined in terms of these unique features, against the
backdrop of the shared features.

Episodic memory: 2009

Episodic memory is a recently evolved, late developing, and early deteriorating brain/mind (neurocognitive)
memory system. It is oriented to the past, more vulnerable than other memory systems to neuronal dysfunction,
and probably unique to humans. It makes possible mental time travel through subjective time--past, present,
and future. This mental time travel allows one, as an “owner” of episodic memory (“self”), through the medium
of autonoetic awareness, to remember one's own previous “thought about” experiences, as well as to “think
about” one's own possible future experiences. The operations of episodic memory require, but go beyond, the
semantic memory system. Retrieving information from episodic memory (“remembering”) requires the
activation, by way of voluntary or involuntary processes, of a special mental set, dubbed episodic “retrieval
mode.” The neural components of episodic memory comprise a widely distributed network of cerebral cortical
and subcortical brain regions that overlap with and extend beyond the networks subserving other memory
systems. The essence of episodic memory lies in the conjunction of three concepts--self, autonoetic awareness,
and subjective time.
The remainder of this article summarizes some of the open issues concerning episodic memory, issues that
remain in the focus of investigators.

Open issues

Autobiographical memory
Episodic memory is closely related to autobiographical memory. That term, however, most often is used in the
sense of significant life experiences, either remembered or known. That is, people typically include facts such as
when and where they were born as an important part of their life story although these are necessarily acquired
through the semantic rather than episodic system. Episodic memory, on the other hand, has to do with
remembered experiences alone (with regard to one's past). The distinction between episodic and semantic
autobiographical memory receives support from relevant neuroimaging studies (Levine et al., 2004; Svoboda,
McKinnon, & Levine, 2006).

Episodic memory in nonhuman animals


There exists essentially universal agreement among all practitioners of the science of memory that many species
other than humans possess highly developed semantic memory systems. These allow them to acquire complex
and intricate knowledge of various sorts about their own ecological niches (as well as other aspects) of the world.
Whether or not species other than humans possess episodic memory depends on how episodic memory is
defined. If the definition is given along the lines of the properties of episodic memory that are “shared” with
semantic memory, then the answer to the question is definitely positive. However, in terms of the extended
definition, including both the “shared” and “unique” lists, the answer is negative--other species probably do not
possess the kind of episodic memory that humans do. At least, we are not aware of any findings that
unequivocally attribute autonoetic consciousness to nonhuman animals (Suddendorf & Corballis, 1997, 2007).

Adaptive value
When it comes to humans, the question as to the survival value of episodic memory arises. Here it is possible to
think of plausible evolutionary drivers that may have played a role in initiating and maintaining the ability to
autonoetically reflect on what has happened in the past. One such thought begins with the assumption that
subjectively apprehended time, a key feature of evolved episodic memory, extends not only backwards to the
past, but also forwards to the future. One’s ability to imagine what the future might bring allows one to prepare
for the various eventualities in a way that a more restricted projection of the past would not. Most specifically, if
one can anticipate possible untoward happenings at a time that has not yet arrived, one can take measures to
ward them off now, in the present (Tulving, 2002b, 2005).

The power of ‘episodic future thinking,’ as the ability has been dubbed, is most clearly visible in the kinds of
cultures and civilizations human beings have created. Many aspects of these would not be possible in the absence
of the ability to mentally envisage the future (Suddendorf & Corballis, 1997). Indeed, evidence continues to
accumulate suggesting that episodic memory and episodic future thinking share similar neural correlates, that
both are similarly impaired in specific cases of brain damage, and that both share similar ontogenetic trajectories
and subsequent decline in aging (Atance & O’Neill, 2001; Schacter & Addis, 2007; Szpunar, in press).

References

Aggleton, J. P., & Pearce, J. M. (2001). Neural systems underlying episodic memory: Insights from animal
research. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 356, 1483 1491.
Atance, C. M., & O’Neill, D. K. (2001). Episodic future thinking. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5, 533-539.
Clayton, N. S., Bussey, T. J., & Dickinson, A. (2003). Can animals recall the past and plan for the future?
Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 4, 685-691.
Dere, E., Easton, A., Nadel, L., & Huston, J. P. (2008). Handbook of episodic memory. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Eichenbaum, H., & Cohen, N. J. (2001). From conditioning to conscious recollection: Memory systems of the
brain. New York: Oxford University Press.
Gardiner, J. M., & Richardson Klavehn, A. (2000). Remembering and knowing. In E. Tulving & F. I. M. Craik
(Eds.), The Oxford handbook of memory (pp. 229 244). New York: Oxford University Press.
Griffiths, D. P., Dickinson, A., & Clayton, N. S. (1999). Declarative and episodic memory: What can animals
remember about their past? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 3, 74 80.
Kitchener, E. G., Hodges, J. R., & McCarthy, R. (1998). Acquisition of post morbid vocabulary and semantic
facts in the absence of episodic memory. Brain, 121, 1313 1327.
Klein, S. B., Loftus, J., & Kihlstrom, J. F. (2002). Memory and temporal experience: The effects of episodic
memory loss on an amnesic patient's ability to remember the past and imagine the future. Social Cognition,
20, 353-379.
Levine, B., Turner, G. R., Tisserand, D., Hevenor, S. J., Graham, S. J., & McIntosh, A. R. (2004). The
functional neuroanatomy of episodic and semantic autobiographical remembering: A prospective functional
MRI study. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 16, 1633-1646.
Mishkin, M., Suzuki, W. A., Gadian, D. G., & Vargha Khadem, F. (1997). Hierarchical organization of
cognitive memory. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 352, 1461 1467.
Nelson, K., & Fivush, R. (2004). The emergence of autobiographical memory: A social-cultural
developmental theory. Psychological Review, 111, 486-511.
Nyberg, L., Habib, R., Tulving, E., Cabeza, R., Houle, S., Persson, J., & McIntosh, A. R. (2000). Large scale
neurocognitive networks underlying episodic memory. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 12, 163-173.
Olton, D. S. Comparative analysis of episodic memory. Behavioral and brain sciences, 7, 250-251.
Rosenbaum, R. S., Kohler, S., Schacter, D. L., Moscovitch, M., Westmacott, R., Black, S. E., Gao, F., &
Tulving, E. (2005). The case of K.C.: Contributions of a memory-impaired person to memory theory.
Neuropsychologia, 43, 989-1021.
Schacter, D. L., & Addis, D. R. (2007). The cognitive neuroscience of constructive memory: Remembering the
past and imagining the future. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B, 362, 773-786.
Schacter, D. L., & Tulving, E. (1994). What are the memory systems of 1994? In D.L. Schacter & E. Tulving
(Eds.), Memory systems 1994 (pp. 1 38). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Schacter, D. L., Wagner, A. D., & Buckner, R. L. (2000). Memory systems of 1999. In E. Tulving & F. I. M.
Craik (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of memory (pp. 627-643). New York: Oxford University Press.
Squire, L. R. (1992). Memory and the hippocampus: a synthesis from findings with rats, monkeys, and
humans. Psychological Review, 99, 195-231.
Squire, L. R., & Kandel, E. R. (1999). Memory: From mind to molecules. New York: Freeman & Co.
Squire, L. R., & Zola, S. M. (1998). Episodic memory, semantic memory, and amnesia. Hippocampus, 8, 205
211.
Suddendorf, T., & Corballis, M. C. (1997). Mental time travel and the evolution of the human mind. Genetic,
Social, and General Psychology Monographs, 123, 133-167.
Suddendorf, T., & Corballis, M. C. (2007). The evolution of foresight: What is mental time travel, and is it
unique to humans? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30, 299-313.
Svoboda, E., McKinnon, M. C., & Levine, B. (2006). The functional neuroanatomy of autobiographical
memory: A meta-analysis. Neuropsychologia, 44, 2189-2208.
Szpunar, K. K. (in press). Episodic future thought: An emerging concept. Perspectives on Psychological
Science.
Szpunar, K. K., & McDermott, K. B. (2008). Episodic memory: An evolving concept. In D. Sweat, R. Menzel,
H. Eichenbaum & H. L. Roediger III (Eds.), Learning and memory: A comprehensive reference (pp. 491-
510). Oxford: Elsevier.
Tulving, E. (1983). Elements of episodic memory. New York: Oxford University Press.
Tulving, E. (1985). Memory and consciousness. Canadian Psychology, 26, 1-12.
Tulving, E. (1995). Organization of memory: Quo vadis? In M.S. Gazzaniga (Ed.), The cognitive
neurosciences (pp. 839-847). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Tulving, E. (2002a). Episodic memory: From mind to brain. Annual Review of Psychology, 53, 1-25.
Tulving, E. (2002b). Chronesthesia: Awareness of subjective time. In D. T. Stuss & R. C. Knight (Eds.),
Principles of Frontal Lobe Function (pp. 311-325). New York: Oxford University Press.
Tulving, E. (2005). Episodic memory and autonoesis: Uniquely human? In H. S. Terrace & J. Metcalfe (Eds.),
The missing link in cognition: Origins of self-reflective consciousness (pp. 3-56). New York: Oxford
University Press.
Vargha Khadem, F., Gadian, D. G., Watkins, K. E., Connelly, A., Van Paesschen, W., & Mishkin, M. (1997).
Differential effects of early hippocampal pathology on episodic and semantic memory. Science, 277, 376 380.
Wheeler, M. A., Stuss, D. T., & Tulving, E. (1997). Toward a theory of episodic memory: The frontal lobes and
autonoetic consciousness. Psychological Bulletin, 121, 331 354.
Internal references

Yael Shrager and Larry R. Squire (2008) Amnesia. Scholarpedia, 3(8):2789.


Valentino Braitenberg (2007) Brain. Scholarpedia, 2(11):2918.
William D. Penny and Karl J. Friston (2007) Functional imaging. Scholarpedia, 2(5):1478.
Howard Eichenbaum (2008) Memory. Scholarpedia, 3(3):1747.
Norman M. White (2007) Multiple memory systems. Scholarpedia, 2(7):2663.

Recommended readings

Dere, E., Easton, A., Nadel, L., & Huston, J. P. (2008). Handbook of episodic memory. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Tulving, E. (1983). Elements of episodic memory. New York: Oxford University Press.

See also

Amnesia, Memory

Sponsored by: Eugene M. Izhikevich, Editor-in-Chief of Scholarpedia, the peer-reviewed open-access


encyclopedia
Reviewed by (http://www.scholarpedia.org/w/index.php?title=Episodic_memory&oldid=63401) : Dr. Lars
Nyberg, Umea University
Reviewed by (http://www.scholarpedia.org/w/index.php?title=Episodic_memory&oldid=65840) : Anonymous
Accepted on: 2009-08-16 20:04:43 GMT (http://www.scholarpedia.org/w/index.php?
title=Episodic_memory&oldid=65840)

Categories: Memory Multiple Curators

This page was last modified on 21


October 2011, at 04:08.
This page has been accessed 106,334
times.
"Episodic memory" by Endel
Tulving and Karl K. Szpunar is
licensed under a Creative Commons
Attribution-NonCommercial-
ShareAlike 3.0 Unported License.
Permissions beyond the scope of this
license are described in the Terms of
Use

You might also like