EC - Bonazzi 2020 - The Sophists - GRE - IgrKsr
EC - Bonazzi 2020 - The Sophists - GRE - IgrKsr
EC - Bonazzi 2020 - The Sophists - GRE - IgrKsr
BY Mauro Bonazzi
From Socrates and Plato onwards, the Sophists were often targeted by the authoritative
philosophical tradition as being mere charlatans and poor teachers. This book, translated
and significantly updated from its most recent Italian version (2nd edition, 2013), challenges
The Sophists
these criticisms by offering an overall interpretation of their thought, and by assessing the
specific contributions of thinkers like Protagoras, Gorgias and Antiphon. A new vision of the
Sophists emerges: they are protagonists and agents of fundamental change in the history of
Ancient Philosophy, who questioned the grounds of morality and politics, as well as the nature
of knowledge and language. By shifting the focus from the cosmos to man, the Sophists
inaugurate an alternative form of philosophy, whose importance is only now becoming clear.
To place an order from within the United States, Canada and Mexico For information on subscribing or submitting to the journal, please visit
please contact Cambridge Customer Services toll free via +1 800 872 7423 journals.cambridge.org/gar
or by email via information@cup.org/. For orders outside of North America
please call + 44 (0)1223 325566 or email via ukcustserve@cambridge.org/.
THE SOPHISTS
BY
MAURO BONAZZI
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781108706216
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library
ISBN 9781108706216
Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of URLs for
external or third-party websites referred to in this publication, and does not guarantee that any
content on such websites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate.
Foreword v
I The Sophists: History of a Name and Prejudice 1
II Being and Truth, Humanity and Reality 11
III A World of Words: The Sophists at the Crossroads
Between Grammar, Rhetoric, Poetry, and Philosophy 43
IV Justice and Law 65
V Teaching Virtue: The Sophists on Happiness and Success 96
VI The Gods and Religion 111
Appendix 1: The Protagonists 125
Appendix 2: The Sophists and Specialist Forms of Knowledge
(Technai) 138
Bibliography 141
Index 153
translations are Freeman 1948, Kent Sprague 1972, and Dillon and
Gergel 2003. With regard to Plato and Aristotle, our two most import-
ant testimonies regarding the sophists, the translations are taken from
Cooper 1997 and Barnes 1984, respectively. For all the other authors,
the translations are from the Loeb Classical Texts (with minor
changes).
This book, a revised and updated version of my previous book, I
sofisti (Rome, 2010), would never have seen the light without the sup-
port and the competence of the editor of the New Surveys series, Phillip
Horky. My warmest thanks are due to him, and also to Sergio Knipe for
his help with the translation.
One day around the year 430 BC, before dawn, a young and promising
Athenian, Hippocrates, son of Apollodorus, hastens to Socrates’ house
to rouse him from his sleep. The reason for this bizarre behaviour soon
becomes clear: Protagoras is in Athens! With a knowing smile, Socrates
answers that he is already aware of this, as though he could not really
understand the reason for all this excitement. But Hippocrates shows
no hesitation: Protagoras, the great sophist, he who ‘makes people
wise’, is in Athens – an opportunity not to be missed! The two of
them must leave immediately, and Socrates must help Hippocrates
gain access to Callias’ house, where the sophist is staying. However,
Socrates insists on enquiring about the reason for Hippocrates’ excite-
ment: does he wish to become a sophist?
‘And if somebody asks you what do you expect to become in going to Protagoras?’
He blushed in response – there was just enough daylight now to show him up – and
said, ‘If this is all like the previous cases, then, obviously, to become a sophist.’
‘What? You? Wouldn’t you be ashamed to present yourself to the Greek world as a
sophist?’
‘Yes, I would, Socrates, to be perfectly honest.’ (Plato, Protagoras, 310a–312a)
This famous page from Plato – the prologue of the Protagoras – prob-
ably constitutes the most compelling example of the ambiguous fame
attached to the name of the sophists. That fame has not changed
much over the centuries: the sophists have always been the object of
violent polemics and passionate vindication. After centuries of criti-
cism, in the modern age the sophists received the support of some
most distinguished philosophers: first from Hegel, who regarded
them as the masters of Greece, then from some English liberals (in par-
ticular George Grote), and finally – and even more staunchly – from
Nietzsche, who saw them as the most genuine representatives of the
Greek spirit.1 Later, Popper was to go so far as to speak of a ‘great gen-
eration’, while other scholars have even suggested that ours is the age of
the Third Sophistic.2 At the same time, however, ‘sophist’ and
1
On the importance and limits of the interpretations put forward by Hegel and English liberals,
see Kerferd 1981a: 4–14; on Nietzsche, see Consigny 1994.
2
Popper 1971: 162. One author who describes the contemporary age as a ‘Third Sophistic’ is
Vitanza 1997; see also Fowler 2014. See too Rorty 1979: 157. The expression ‘Second Sophistic’
is used to describe the revival in the Imperial age of certain elements introduced by the sophists in
the fifth century BC. The focus in this case was on rhetorical and literary themes, while the more
strictly philosophical aspect was largely overlooked. For this reason, I will not be discussing the
phenomenon here (for an interesting attempt to link the fifth-century sophistic and the Second
Sophistic, see Cassin 1995).
3
It may be worth noting that, in the surviving testimonies, the only sophist to describe himself as
such is Protagoras in the Platonic dialogue that bears his name (Protagoras, 317b = 80A5 D.-K. =
31P13a L.-M.).
4
Kerferd 1981a.
5
Naturally, this list, while perfectly reasonable, is not decisive. To give just one example of how
difficult it is to precisely identify the sophists: in his writings, Aristotle applies this label to four
authors alone, namely Lycophron, Polyeidos, Bryson, and Aristippus. Only the first of these is
reckoned among the sophists today (Polyeidos appears to have been a poet and literary critic,
while Bryson and Aristippus are possibly to be associated with the milieu of the Socratic schools).
All four are called sophists in relation to language and ethico-political issues, which – as we shall
see – constituted the privileged object of reflection for the sophists.
history, we can identify some key features.6 Other clues may then be
inferred through an engagement with the ancient sources. The word
sophistês is based on the root *soph-, which we also find in sophos
(knowledgeable, wise) and sophia (knowledge, wisdom), two terms
commonly used from early Greece to express the notion of skill in
some field or craft. Starting from this general meaning, sophos gradually
came to describe individuals who were knowledgeable and accom-
plished in intellectual pursuits. These ‘wise men’ (sophoi in the plural),
usually poets or soothsayers, possessed a kind of knowledge that was
unattainable by other men and which could have beneficial effects.
From the fifth century BC onwards, sophistês entered into use as a syno-
nym of sophos: to be more precise, sophistês is formed from the verb
sophizesthai, which is to say ‘to exercise sophia’. A ‘sophist’, therefore,
is someone who acts as a sophos, someone who possesses intellectual
knowledge either in a general sense or in a specific discipline.
Sophistês, originally a synonym of sophos, thus came to describe some-
thing more narrow, something more suited to the needs of an increas-
ingly sophisticated society: the exercise of knowledge in practice is
teaching, as a profession; hence, a sophist is a teacher, and educator.
This is an initial defining feature, from which others follow.
The professionalizing of the sophist’s role helps to explain another
crucial characteristic that further distinguishes his social position,
namely his salary. Insofar as the sophist imparts some teachings, he
expects some payment in return – a request that is only natural for
us, but which was very unusual for the ancient Greeks, who regarded
the idea of teaching wisdom or virtue to anyone for a fee as something
quite shocking.7 Secondly, what also distinguishes the activity of the
sophist – albeit to a lesser degree than the demand for pay – is his itin-
erant character. The sophists are teachers who share their knowledge in
exchange for a fee in the many cities they visit. This is hardly surprising,
given that almost all sophists were born far away from the major cultural
6
On the meaning of sophistês and its history, see the following analyses: Untersteiner 1949–62:
i.xvi–xxiii; Guthrie 1971: 27–35; and Kerferd 1981a: 24–41. An alternative reconstruction is put
forward by Edmunds 2006, according to whom sophistês only entered into use as a technical term
in the fourth century BC, whereas in the fifth it described a gamut of intellectual figures, including
soothsayers, dithyrambic poets, scientists, and orators. This study confirms the importance played
by Plato and Aristotle in the definition of the sophists’ identity; still, it does not rule out that by the
fifth century the term ‘sophist’ had already come to be associated with the practice of teaching,
which is perhaps the most distinguishing feature of the sophists’ activity; on this, see also Tell
2011.
7
Blank 1985.
and political centres of their day, such as Athens: travelling for them
was practically a requirement.8 The itinerant character of the sophists’
teaching may seem like a trivial fact, but actually has some important
implications – as we shall see – that at least partly account for the degree
of hostility they incurred.
These three criteria (teaching, the charging of a fee, and travel) allow
us to narrow down the field of our enquiry, insofar as they help us dis-
tinguish a ‘sophist’ such as Protagoras from a ‘sophist’ such as
Prometheus. Protagoras was a teacher who visited many cities of the
Greek world, exercising his profession for a fee; by contrast, when
Aeschylus calls Prometheus a sophist, he is only highlighting his knowl-
edge and commitment to help people (Prometheus Bound, 944). What is
even more interesting is the case of Solon, who had also travelled the
known world: Herodotus (1.29) calls him both sophistês and philosophos,
not because he wishes to portray him as a forerunner of the sophists and
philosophers, but to praise his desire for knowledge (the literal meaning
of philo-sophia being ‘love of wisdom’) and the experience he had
acquired through his travels – two virtues which are certainly note-
worthy, but which do not distinguish the sophists’ teaching activity.
8
To get an idea of the extent of the sophists’ travels, see the profiles in Appendix 1. It is import-
ant to bear in mind that many sophists also travelled for political reasons, acting as ambassadors of
their cities: see esp. Plato, Hippias, 282b–c, on Gorgias, Prodicus, and Hippias. One may recall
Gorgias’ famous embassy to Athens in 427 BC. Similar embassies have been suggested in relation
to Thrasymachus, albeit on less certain grounds: see White 1995 and Yunis 1997. It is also worth
mentioning Antiphon’s famous embassy to Sparta after the coup of 411 BC – assuming that the
hypothesis that identifies the sophist with the orator by that name is correct.
and more generally the experts in all other disciplines.9 As has often
been noted, competition plays a central role in ancient Greece, a society
lacking ‘official’ types of authority: each teacher was required to provide
concrete proof of his superiority over other aspiring ‘wise men’.10 The
sophists offer a striking example of this polemical spirit. Their teaching
constitutes a remarkable challenge to the claims to truth made by other
experts in the polis, and betrays the sophists’ desire to establish them-
selves as the new intellectual masters in Greece.11
From the point of view of their opponents, the sophists’ claim to be
capable of taking the place of experts amounted to the promotion of a
strictly verbal kind of knowledge: the sophists do not really know what
they are talking about; they are only brilliant speakers who conceal their
shortcomings behind linguistic tricks; their only concern is how to win
an argument. Accusations of this sort may be found in many texts by
Hippocratic physicians, who label the sophists ‘professional defamers’
(see Appendix 2). No less eloquent are Aristotle’s observations, which
convey a further and more serious criticism. Aristotle is less drastic
than other detractors and grants the sophists a few merits: it is true –
he states – that the sophists have chiefly focused on language and
argumentative techniques; yet their analyses are still worth discussing,
if only to highlight their errors and fallacies. In Aristotle’s perspective,
however, the real problem is this: the sophists’ exclusive interest in lan-
guage implies that they do not examine reality, causes, and principles,
which is to say that they are not genuine philosophers at all. At best they
are dialecticians, grammarians, and orators, even though it is tempting
9
See Fait 2007: xl–xliv.
10
Lloyd 1979.
11
The sophists’ ambition explains why their activity entailed not only private lessons but also
public performances (epideixis): see Guthrie 1971: 41–4. Privately, the teacher was chiefly con-
cerned with presenting certain argumentative schemes that the pupil could then make use of for
his own benefit (see Natali 1986; it is possible that these arguments were subsequently brought
together to form genuine discourses that might serve as a model for students). Public performance
was a privileged avenue for sophists to promote themselves and their wisdom even before an exten-
sive audience (for instance, during solemn celebrations such as the Olympic Games). For a vivid
description of these performances, see Lloyd 1987: 79–102; for analyses of the possible circulation
of these discourses in written form, see O’Sullivan 1996 and Thomas 2003. While bearing this
distinction in mind, we should not overemphasize the break between public and private, since
even the teaching of arguments could take place in open contexts: this is the case, for instance,
in Plato’s Euthydemus, where Euthydemus and Dionysodorus, mocking their interlocutors, present
argumentative schemes that their pupils can apply to new cases. The truly enduring feature of the
sophists’ activity is its agonistic-competitive character. Interesting points on the historical and cul-
tural context may also be found in Soverini 1998.
12
Significantly, in the first book of the Metaphysics, the treatise that is usually regarded as the
first history of philosophy, no mention is made of the sophists, whereas their theses are widely dis-
cussed in the treatises of the Organon – in particular, in the Sophistical Refutations. On Aristotle and
the sophists, see the observations made by Classen 1981, who notes that, although Aristotle does
not regard the sophists as genuine philosophers, he does not simply despise them either. Aristotle’s
interpretation was especially influential among the great Latin orators, from Cicero to Quintilian,
who only dealt with the sophists in relation to their rhetorical studies. Among modern scholars, a
similar interpretation has been upheld by Gomperz 1912 and, more recently, in a completely dif-
ferent context, by several American scholars interested in a reassessment of rhetoric (see e.g.
Schiappa 1991 on Protagoras and Consigny 2001 on Gorgias). Along much the same lines,
Michael Gagarin, who is the author of some of the most enlightening contributions on the ancient
sophists, has stressed the central importance of logos (which can mean ‘word’, ‘speech’, or ‘rea-
son’) as the cornerstone of the sophists’ investigations (see, for example, Gagarin 2002 and
2008). While the importance assigned to logos is indisputable, it does not imply a lack of interest
in ethical and political issues, as we shall see.
13
Goldhill 1986: 222–7.
the discourse which with unjust arguments overturns the better dis-
course and contradicts the laws in such a way as to make injustice tri-
umph (lines 882–4).14 Naturally, their teaching is not an innocuous
abstraction, but has concrete effects, which affect society to its very
core – or, rather, subvert it: Aristophanes’ comedy ends with a son
beating his father, a gesture which constitutes the most eloquent evi-
dence of the overturning of traditional values.15 The sophists are repre-
sented as the bad teachers of Athens (and the whole of Greece), those
responsible for its moral and political crisis.
I will assess the soundness of these charges at different stages in the
course of the present investigation, in order expose their limits and
prejudiced character. For the moment, I only wish to note that both
accusations in a way depend on what may be regarded as the sophists’
most important contribution: their acknowledgement of the fact that
reality is ‘problematic’.16 It is this awareness which leads the sophists
to investigate new issues and to question established values, as was
already observed by Plato himself – the sophists’ fiercest opponent in
a way, but also the philosopher who had most clearly grasped the philo-
sophical and political significance of the challenge they posed.17 This
not only acquits the sophists of the charge of promoting immorality,
but assigns them a prominent place in the history of philosophy – a
point I will be discussing at length in the following chapters.18 For
the time being, it is important to note that these two accusations
allow us to better define the primary aim of the sophists’ research
and teaching: the charge of playing with words may be explained by
considering the sophists’ utmost interest in the issue of language,
while the accusation of promoting immorality is due to their interest
in practical, ethical, and political problems. The sophists’ favourite
object of enquiry was the art of speech (logos), and in particular its prac-
tical and political applications. Language and politics, then, are two of
14
The thinly veiled allusion here is to Protagoras, who promised to ‘make the weaker argument
the stronger’ (80B6b D.-K.): a provocative claim in its ambiguity, given that ‘weaker’ might also
mean less just.
15
Besides, the sophists had touched upon this theme too in a provocative fashion: see Antiphon
87B44B, 5.4-8 D.-K. = 37D38 L.-M.
16
Paci 1957: 126.
17
See now Corey 2015.
18
Significantly enough, aside from a few exceptions, the dominant view today is precisely that
the sophists’ activity entailed an engagement with ontological and political issues. This may be
inferred from the most authoritative studies on the subject, which, while disagreeing on many
points, agree at least on this one – from Untersteiner 1954 (first published in Italian 1949) to
Kerferd 1981a, from Guthrie 1971 (first published 1969) to Cassin 1995.
19
Gagarin 2008: 23.
In order to understand the meaning and scope of the challenge that the
sophists present to us, we must clear the field of all ambiguities and
prejudices. All too often the sophist is only taken into consideration as a
polemical target, as a counterpart to the philosopher: whereas the philoso-
pher argues in order to seek the truth, the sophist only tries to win an argu-
ment; and whereas the philosopher concerns himself with problems in all
of their complexity, the sophist instrumentally focuses on fashionable
topics that might interest his public of potential pupils (in other words,
people willing to pay him). These contrasts are repeated not only in
relation to the future, which is to say to Plato and Aristotle, but also, retro-
spectively, in relation to the so-called ‘Presocratic philosophers’. As a
consequence, the sophists find themselves in a sort of no man’s land,
and their activities appear to mark a break in the history of philosophy,
interrupting its toilsome and earnest progression from myth to reason.
Like all schematic reconstructions, the one just provided gives rise to
some serious misunderstandings. One initial misunderstanding concerns
the very concept of ‘philosophy’: up until the end of the fifth century there
was no discipline of ‘philosophy’, possessing a distinctive epistemological
status and opposed to other literary genres such as history or rhetoric.
Heraclitus – to quote but one figure among those whom we regard as phi-
losophers – uses the term to mock Pythagoras and Hesiod, accusing them
of knowing many things without really understanding any at all (22B35
D.-K. = Her. 40D L.-M.). As a non-polemical term of praise, the historian
Herodotus calls the poet and politician Solon a ‘philosopher’, commend-
ing his thirst for knowledge (1.30.2); along much the same lines, Pericles
goes so far as to claim that all Athenians are philosophers (Thuc. 2.40.1).
Philosophy, as we understand it, which is to say as an independent discip-
line, is a later invention by Plato and Aristotle: what we find in the fifth
century, rather, are many prose writers (including the sophists) and
poets engaging in an all-round debate that touches upon authors ranging
from Homer to Parmenides, from Anaxagoras to Simonides. (It is import-
ant to remind ourselves that the same kind of openness is also displayed by
Plato, Aristotle, and many other ancient philosophers.)
Only by setting out from a correct historical contextualization can we
address the delicate question of the sophists’ contribution to the history
of ancient thought. The sophists were no doubt interested in language
and all the issues related to the problem of language (argumentative
techniques, rhetoric, poetry, and literary criticism), since this was the
topic which most interested their public, especially in democratic
Athens. However, this is not to say that they did not also deal with
other ‘philosophical’ problems which the Presocratics had investigated
and which Plato and Aristotle were to take up again – quite the contrary.
The vagueness of the concept of ‘Presocratic’ has often led to the
misguided attempt to draw a clear-cut distinction between natural
philosophers and sophists, spawning the cliché that the former only
discussed nature, and the latter the human world. Like all clichés,
this one contains both an element of truth and an element of falsehood.
It is true that the Presocratics’ investigations chiefly focused on physis
(nature), while the sophists concerned themselves with what more spe-
cifically pertains to humanity. But it is just as true that the Presocratics
made some very important contributions to the study of language and
human psychology, and that the sophists also dealt with the problems of
physis and human’s relationship with the world. In other words, what
changes is the perspective, not the topics discussed: the Presocratics
searched for the elements of continuity between human beings and
reality, while the sophists were interested in the issue of what distin-
guishes humankind. The change of perspective, however, does not
depend on any lack of interest of the latter towards the former: it is
the consequence of a critical engagement.
Ancient sources repeatedly bear witness to the sophists’ interest in
the Presocratics’ physis. The most significant example is provided by
Gorgias’ treatise On Nature or On Not-Being, which from its very title
sets out to overthrow the theses of Melissus and Parmenides
(Gorgias, after all, was a pupil of Empedocles: see 82A3, 10 D.-K. =
32P4–5 L.-M., and Kerferd 1985). Protagoras (80B2 D.-K. = 31D7,
R2 L.-M.), Lycophron (83.2 D.-K. = 38D1 L.-M.), and probably
Xeniades (81.1 = 39R1 L.-M.) also polemicized against Parmenides
and Zeno. Cicero states – unfortunately, in a very succinct way – that
Prodicus and Thrasymachus, too, investigated the nature of things
(De natura rerum, 84B3 D.-K. = 34D2 L.-M.; and 85A9 D.-K. =
35D4 L.-M.); and Aristophanes describes Prodicus (and the sophist
Socrates) as a ‘meteorosophist’ (which is to say, an ‘expert on celestial
phenomena’: 84A5 D.-K. = Dram.T22–4 L.-M.).1 Finally, recent studies
1
Other testimonies about Prodicus’ naturalistic interests – in particular, that of Galen – have
been collected by Mayhew 2011: T 61–9 (see also Mayhew 2011: 171–5, on Aristotle’s testimony
as a source for reconstructing Prodicus’ cosmology).
2
Hourcade 2001. Within the same context, we may also mention those testimonies apparently
concerning a ‘sophistic theory of perception’ (Ioli 2010: 56–9, following in the footsteps of
Monique Dixsaut). Indeed, Platonic passages such as Theaetetus, 153e–154a, and Meno, 76d,
may be taken to suggest that Protagoras and Gorgias had somehow adopted the Presocratic theor-
ies envisaging sense-perception in terms of the flow of particles.
3
Detienne 2006.
not’ (80B1 D.-K. = 32D9 L.-M.; for the sake of convenience, in the
following pages this sentence will be abbreviated as ‘man-measure’).4
‘Man-measure’ is one of the few authentic Protagoras fragments to
have been preserved, and many ancient sources confirm that the state-
ment was originally formulated precisely in these terms. The problem,
however, is its opacity: even in antiquity there was intense debate con-
cerning what Protagoras really meant, and modern readings have only
increased doubts about its content. As a matter of fact, it cannot be
ruled out that a certain degree of ambiguity was intentional. Truth
was not a scientific treatise but, in all likelihood, an epideixis, the text
of a public performance. In opening his speech, Protagoras sought to
capture the attention of his audience (or reader) by making a striking
and allusive claim – at the expense of exactness and precision – and
putting aside all caution and hesitation (which are hardly the most valu-
able qualities for a public performance). There is nothing strange in any
of this, since a desire to capture the audience’s attention was quite
typical of the sophists, as is confirmed by many other sources.5
This is not to say that the ‘man-measure’ thesis had no specific
meaning. Simply, it is a matter of dealing with potentially ambiguous
elements. In particular, it is necessary to clarify the notion of man:
that is, whether ‘man’ refers to each individual or to humanity in gen-
eral; in discussing this issue, the meaning of the other terms that make
up the sentence will also become clearer. In turn, this will help us assess
the underlying meaning of Protagoras’ statement and its field of applic-
ability, so as to determine whether it is an epistemological thesis (a the-
sis concerning knowledge) or whether it also carries practical or
political implications. By way of anticipating my argument, I note
here that the sentence can be read on different levels, in line with the
archaic logic according to which there is no need to clearly distinguish
the different meanings possessed by a term.
There are three main sources for the ‘man-measure’ thesis: Plato,
Aristotle, and Sextus Empiricus (a second-century CE sceptic). All
4
The sceptic Sextus Empiricus, one of our most important sources, attributes this sentence to a
work entitled Kataballontes logoi (The Overthrower Arguments or, better, The Knockdown Arguments;
on this translation, see Appendix 2): one possible solution may be that Truth was one of the dis-
courses in the Antilogies, which were also known with the (sub)title of Kataballontes logoi: see
Decleva Caizzi 1999: 317. Among the most important studies, see Vlastos 1956; Decleva Caizzi
1978; Barnes 1979: ii.541–53; Mansfeld 1981; Farrar 1988.
5
The sentence introducing the treatise on the gods was just as provocative: see Chapter 6,
p. 112.
but more generally all opinions and judgements (and especially value
judgements). ‘Man is the measure of all things’ means that each indi-
vidual is the ultimate arbiter of all of his or her own judgements –
that the wind is warm or cold, but also that performing a given action
is right or wrong.6
The point just made is crucial in order to reconstruct the overall
meaning of Protagoras’ position. The transition to a broader concep-
tion of human activities (not only sense-perceptions but human judge-
ments as a whole) brings out one aspect of the thesis that scholars have
all too often overlooked. Usually it is taken for granted that Protagoras’
thesis concerned problems related to human knowledge and that these
problems were addressed in abstract terms, by examining the general
ways in which the process of knowledge acquisition unfolds – in
other words, by investigating what happens to a subject X who at a
given moment t experiences sensation f (let us think of the example
of the wind). Yet this is not correct. It is certainly true that
Protagoras’ thesis was concerned with human knowledge. However,
it is not true that it focused on it in an ‘abstract’ way, as though humans
were ‘automata’ that can be stimulated from the outside so as to study
their reactions at given moments and in specific circumstances. This
approach might work in the case of the wind, but not in that of judge-
ments concerning what is good or bad. ‘Man’ refers to the individual,
yet not to an abstract subject: Protagoras has concrete, historically well-
defined people in mind, with their ideas and prejudices. What is meant
by ‘man’, therefore, is each person with his or her own personal history,
experiences, and expectations: that is, people for whom some options
are possible while others are not, and whose judgements largely reflect
their individual experience – people who are responsible for the opi-
nions they have and for what they do. When I claim that a certain
thing or action is good (or beautiful or unjust), I do so on the basis
of a series of ideas and opinions that I have acquired over the course
of my life and that I have continued to put to the test through my
engagement with facts – in other words, on the basis of my experience,
which is different from that of other people. The true measure, then,
is not ‘man’ in the abstract sense but rather each individual’s
6
To be more precise, it must be noted that Protagoras, like many thinkers of his day, does not
distinguish between the mind and sense-perceptions as though they concerned two completely dif-
ferent domains (i.e. the intelligible world and the sensible one): cf. 80A1 D.-K = 31R13 L.-M. on
the soul.
7
Mansfeld 1981: 44–6.
are what surrounds a person, what happens to him or her. What matters
is the way in which we relate to them: each individual, according to his
or her experience, is the judge of these facts, insofar as he or she assigns
them a degree of consistency or value.
This initial reconstruction also enables us to evaluate Protagoras’
position with respect to the previous intellectual tradition: ‘man-
measure’ emerges as a polemical response to the enquiries on physis
conducted by many Presocratics, and in particular to Parmenides’
monism.8 Protagoras’ interest in critically engaging with the Eleatic
school is confirmed by other sources: in particular, Porphyry (a
third–fourth-century CE Neoplatonist) informs us that Protagoras
wrote a treatise On Being (regrettably lost) against those who ‘uphold
the uniqueness of being’ – clearly, Parmenides and his disciples
(80B2 D.-K. = 31D7, R2 L.-M.); a polemic with Zeno is also attested.9
The same polemical intentions are suggested by Plato’s Theaetetus,
which presents Protagoras and Parmenides as the leading exponents
of two opposite ways of conceiving reality, namely as becoming and
as being.
Once again, although Plato’s testimony is crucial, it must be exam-
ined with great caution, so as to avoid pushing our interpretation
of Protagoras too far. The Theaetetus ascribes a sort of radical
Heracliteanism to Protagoras that presents reality as the constant flow
of all things, a flow so incessant that we should speak not of ‘being’
8
Farrar 1988: 48–50.
See 29A29 D.-K. = Zen. D12b L.-M.: ‘For he [Zeno] said: “Tell me, Protagoras, does one
9
grain of millet make a sound when it falls or does the thousandth part of the grain of millet?”
When the other answered that it did not, he said, “Does a medimnus of grains of millet make a
sound or not when it falls?” When the other answered that it did make a noise, Zeno said,
“Well then, is there not a proportion between a medimnus of grains of millet and a single grain
and the thousandth part of that one grain?” And when the other answered that there was one,
Zeno said, “Well then, will there not be the same proportions between the sounds with regard
to one another? For just as the things are that make a sound, so too are their sounds; and since
that is so, if a medimnus of millet makes a sound, a single grain of millet will make a sound
too, and so too the thousandth part of that grain”’. While not impossible in chronological
terms, it seems unlikely that the meeting between the two thinkers really occurred. However,
this passage may still be seen to provide further evidence of the polemical exchanges that the soph-
ist entertained with the Eleatic school. The text in question has sometimes been interpreted as
proof of the fact that Protagoras denied infinite divisibility; but this seems like an incorrect conclu-
sion, since Protagoras – at least in theory – does not deny the possibility of a division into increas-
ingly small parts. What he denies is rather that the sound produced by these portions of millet is
audible. Once again, we may note that the sophist examined things from the point of view of sens-
ible experience, against the abstractions of the natural philosophers: just as sight does not perceive
the touching of a sphere and a tangent at a given point (see 80B7 D.-K. =31D33 L.-M.), so hear-
ing can only perceive sounds up to a certain point. Even from this perspective, man is the measure
of all things.
10
On this passage, see Zilioli 2013: 239–43, arguing that Plato’s text attributes to Protagoras
not so much a radical version of a Heraclitean theory of flux as a theory of ontological indetermin-
acy; and Corradi 2012: 79–89.
11
This does not rule out the possibility that Protagoras’ conception of material reality may have
been similar to that of other Presocratics, but it is important to stress once again that this was not
the sophist’s chief interest. In brief, and without delving into the details, it cannot be ruled out that
Protagoras viewed physical reality as something that contains all opposites. If this is the case, the
sophist was only taking up a thesis that was common among natural philosophers and typical of the
polarizing thought of the Presocratics, who were used to envisaging nature in terms of contrasting
or harmonizing opposites (let us think here of the Pythagoreans or of Heraclitus). This is Sextus
Empiricus’ interpretation (Outlines of Pyrrhonism, 1.216–19 = 80A14 D.-K. = 31R21 L.-M.), cf.
Woodruff 1999: 303–4.
The things we are concerned with are chremata, i.e. things we are decisively related to;
thus there is no point in speaking in a grand manner about what things may or may not
be in themselves; what we have to take into account and concentrate on is what they are
for us, in the world we live in, in a world in which our relationship to things, our living
in the world, is decisive.12
12
Versenyi 1962: 181.
13
More recently, see also the ‘pluralist’ reading developed by Apfel 2011: 45–78.
The thesis that man is the measure of his own judgements faces two ser-
ious objections: the charge that it is self-refuting and the charge of sol-
ipsism. Protagoras was at least partly aware of these two difficulties, and
clarifying them will help us bring out the richness and significance of
his thesis.
The charge of being self-refuting (or peritrope, as the ancients called
it: literally, the charge of ‘tripping up’) was apparently formulated for
the first time by Democritus (80A15 D.-K. = 68A114 D.-K. = 31R22
L.-M.) and then further developed by Plato (in the Theaetetus and
Euthydemus) and Aristotle (in the fourth book of the Metaphysics). In
brief, this accusation states that, if all judgements are true (this being
the implicit meaning of the ‘man-measure’ thesis), then the judgement
that ‘man-measure’ is false is also true; hence, ‘man-measure’ is false.
Protagoras had further claimed that ‘it is not possible to contradict’
(80A19 D.-K. = 31R10 L.-M.) and this led Plato and Aristotle to
add that the sophist denied the principle of non-contradiction, suggest-
ing another version of the peritrope charge: Protagoras claims that all
judgements are true (let us call this thesis P) and his opponent that
Protagoras’ claim is false (non-P); but, according to Protagoras, contra-
diction is impossible and therefore non-P is compatible with P. But in
this case, non-P is true; hence, P is false.15
14
See Woodruff 1999: 300–4; Lee 2005: 30–45; Zilioli 2013. On the adoption of this category
with reference to Protagoras and the sophists, consider the cautious note sounded by Bett 1989.
15
Barnes 1979: ii.548.
The soundness of this criticism has been the object of a heated schol-
arly debate, yet no shared solution has been reached.16 Protagoras could
nonetheless resort to a few arguments to defend his views. The accus-
ation omits the qualifiers ‘for me’ and ‘for you’, which are crucial to the
‘man-measure’ thesis. By introducing these qualifiers, Protagoras could
reformulate the peritrope charge in such a way as to neutralize it: if what
I judge is true and I judge that Protagoras’ thesis is false, it does
not follow from this that Protagoras’ thesis is false in an absolute
sense, but only that it is false ‘for me’. And the fact that it is
false ‘for me’ does not prevent it from being true for other people: it
remains true, for instance, for Protagoras, who can thus avoid the
charge that he is tripping himself up (as well as denying the principle
of non-contradiction).
This defensive strategy, however, is potentially open to an even more
serious charge, that of solipsism. This risk is clearly present in the afore-
mentioned thesis that it is ‘impossible to contradict’. The thesis in
question is fully compatible with ‘man-measure’, for if each individual
is the measure of his or her own world of sensations and judgements,
contradiction can only be apparent: each individual entertains a
relationship with things whose truth-reality cannot be contradicted or
disputed by others. Still, it is just as evident that people differ, since
some maintain what others deny. But how can we deal with these diver-
gences and oppositions, if everyone is right? If this is how things stand,
what follows is a radical (and intolerable) form or solipsism, whereby
the fact that each person is his or her own judge makes it impossible
to decide things with others. The price that Protagoras must pay in
order to defend the consistency of his doctrines seems far too high.17
In this case, too, Protagoras has a number of good arguments on his
side. Up until this point, the discussion has centred on the problem of
‘truth’, a concept the importance of which can hardly be disputed.
However, no matter how central it may be, truth is not the only criter-
ion that governs human thoughts and actions. Alongside truth there are
other, equally important criteria. One is ‘what is useful’: all judgements
are true, but some are more expedient than others. And this is what
matters the most for Protagoras. To exploit a compelling formula,
Marcel Detienne described the Presocratic thinkers as ‘masters of
16
Burnyeat 1976; Lee 2005: 46–76; and especially Castagnoli 2010.
17
Woodruff 1999: 303.
truth’; Protagoras (along with all sophists) might instead be called the
‘master of usefulness’.
Once more, with regard to what is useful, the most important testi-
mony comes from Plato.18 As we have seen, the main object of the
Theaetetus is knowledge, and it is in relation to this problem that
Plato introduces, discusses, and criticizes Protagoras’ thesis.
However, the dialogue also features a lengthy digression that, while it
does not directly touch upon epistemological problems, nonetheless
helps to clarify Protagoras’ perspective in all of its complexity: this is
the so-called ‘Apology of Protagoras’ (166a–168c), a lengthy speech
that Protagoras would have delivered, had he had the opportunity to
take part in the dialogue (the dialogue of the Theaetetus takes place in
399 BC, the year of Socrates’ trial, by which time Protagoras had already
died). In his fictional reply, Protagoras accuses Socrates of playing the
sophist and of intentionally deceiving his interlocutors by playing on
the affinity between the words ‘to know’/‘to have knowledge’ and ‘to
be wise’/‘to have wisdom’. But, the sophist continues, the truth-value
of a type of wisdom is one thing, the value of its contents another: if
we are to reason correctly, we must not confuse these two things.
Unlike the former, which is changeless, the latter varies: from the
point of view of knowledge and truth, every individual is a measure,
and the fact that each person is a measure depends on his or her rela-
tionship with the things that surrounds him or her – this is a fact. But
from the point of view of the value of the contents (of wisdom), it can-
not be ruled out that some people are capable of showing the individual
how to establish a more expedient relationship with reality.
Socrates puts the following words into Protagoras’ mouth:
For I myself say that the truth is just as I wrote it: each of us is the measure of the things
that are and of those that are not, but one person differs enormously from another pre-
cisely inasmuch as things exist and appear to be something for one person, something
else for another. As for wisdom (sophia) and the wise man (sophos), I am very far from
saying that they do not exist; but I also call the man wise who, by transforming things,
makes them appear to be good and be good for someone to whom they appeared to be
bad and were bad.
(Theaetetus, 166d = 80A21 D.-K. = 31D38 L.-M.; transl. after L.-M.)
18
Very interesting considerations regarding the problem of what is useful and its relativity may
be found in Guthrie 1971: 164–75. De facto, the relativity of what is useful may be understood
both in an objective sense (the usefulness of a thing varies depending on the people or circum-
stances) and in a subjective sense (nothing is good or bad in itself: it is we who establish this).
The first sense best expresses Protagoras’ position.
Thus, to a sick person food will appear bad and be bad: it would be
meaningless to argue that the sick person is wrong to say that food
tastes bitter to him or her. However, there is someone, namely the doc-
tor, who can help the sick person build a more expedient relationship
with reality, by ensuring that food will taste sweet, not bitter, to
them. Protagoras’ aim is not merely to abolish the idea of truth,
which is shattered into an endless number of private truths; his aim is
to replace this criterion with another, more effective criterion – that
of what is useful. It is by reflecting on the issue of what is useful that
the sophist, while respecting everybody’s opinion, shows his wisdom.
For, ultimately, what is useful varies from one situation to the next
(80A22 D.-K.), and the sophist’s task is to identify what is truly expe-
dient in each case. Therefore, just as the doctor helps the patient’s
body, so the sophist can help his patient build a better, more expedient
relationship with reality: relying on his experience, the sophist can help
his pupil evaluate his or her beliefs and whether he or she regards them
as being truly important, or whether they are merely values that he or
she has passively inherited from tradition. The sophist can verify
whether the pupil’s system of values is consistent, or whether it includes
contrasting beliefs. Finally, the sophist can give the pupil advice on how
to set out to achieve his or her goals. In brief, we may conclude that
Protagoras teaches only one, fundamental thing: how to judge well
on the basis of the existing circumstances.19
By focusing on the criterion of what is useful, Protagoras can thus
justify his teaching within a context in which the space for truth has
been substantially limited: the wisdom he claims to possess does not
stem from any privileged access to an imaginary higher realm of ultim-
ate truths from which other people are barred. Rather, his wisdom is
based on his experience and his capacity to master arguments and pro-
blems: it is a human form of knowledge that is never conclusive but
nonetheless has its usefulness, insofar as it can help the pupil under-
stand what is best for him or her and how to achieve it. Protagoras’
teaching takes the form not of a transmission of data and information,
but of a means to establish a more effective relationship with reality.
The significance of Protagoras’ wisdom emerges even more clearly in
relation to political problems, the field in which he most flaunted his
competences. In a famous passage from another Platonic dialogue,
19
Woodruff 1999: 309; Woodruff 2013.
the Protagoras, the sophist claims that what he teaches is essentially how
to make the best decisions with respect not only to private matters but
also (and especially) to the affairs of the city, noting immediately after-
wards that this is the ‘political art’ ( politike techne).20 The object of pol-
itics is the contrast between the potentially conflictual values of
different people: everyone has his or her own ideas, values, and aims.
However, these values and aims often differ or even clash, and this cre-
ates the premises for conflict. Here is where the opportunity arises for
the sophist to intervene. Like everyone else, Protagoras cannot claim to
objectively know what is good or expedient in absolute terms. But,
unlike many other people, he possesses certain practical competences
and knows how to foster a critical reflection among citizens to help
them reach an agreement on what is best for everyone – to help them
identify those values (which are not absolute values, but ones that
can always be reappraised) that make it possible to establish a better
relation among the individuals of the community, as well as with reality.
The sophist can do so not only in those rare cases in which he can dir-
ectly participate in the political life of a city, but also indirectly, by
teaching his pupils to become good politicians, which is to say politi-
cians capable of building a consensus that will defuse the risk of con-
flict. In both cases, Protagoras’ wisdom proves crucial for the life of
the polis, and in particular for that of a democratic polis such as
Athens.21 Protagoras’ wisdom is not divine but human and, most
importantly, political.
To conclude, we can reappraise the overall meaning of the ‘man-
measure’ thesis. The introduction of the criterion of what is useful
entails a significant shift of perspective. The thesis undoubtedly con-
cerns the problem of knowledge, but it is important to stress that it is
not limited to epistemological issues; rather, one might argue that
Protagoras is chiefly concerned with the problem of knowledge in rela-
tion to its practical consequences. The problem of truth is not just an
epistemological problem, but also a practical one. Consequently, the
term ‘man’ acquires a different meaning as well. The object of ‘man-
measure’ is not just individuals but humans in their mutual relations.
20
‘The object of my instruction is good deliberation about household matters, to know how to
manage one’s own household in the best way possible, and about those of the city, so as to be most
capable of acting and speaking in the city’s interests’ (Protagoras, 318e–319a). Reference to the
political craft is made immediately afterwards, at 319a (both passages are included in the
Diels-Kranz edition as testimony 80A5 = 31D37 L.-M.).
21
Guthrie 1971: 174–5.
22
The question of titles is always a thorny one for archaic and classical authors. However, as
rightly noted by Palmer 2009: 205 n. 25, the peculiarity of Melissus’ and Gorgias’ titles would
seem to suggest that they are authentic and that the latter was probably drawing upon the former.
On the possible dating of the text to the mid-fifth century BC (or, more precisely, to the years 444–
441 BC, the date of the eighty-fourth Olympic Games: 82B2 D.-K. = 32P4 L.-M.), see the cautious
remarks by Mansfeld 1985: 247 and Ioli 2010: 15–18.
23
Wardy 1996: 15.
24
Cassin 1995: 27.
25
We have two main sources: an anonymous treatise devoted to a critical discussion of the
thought of Melissus, Xenophanes, and Gorgias (On Melissus, Xenophanes, and Gorgias, usually
abbreviated to M.X.G.; on the identity of this author, see Ioli 2010: 23–8); and Sextus
Empiricus, Against the Mathematicians, 7.65–87. Despite the evident similarities, these two texts
arrange Gorgias’ writing in different ways: the more reliable source is probably M.X.G. (which
I will be following); Sextus’ discussion (the only one published in the Diels-Kranz edition) appears
instead to reflect a desire to reshape Gorgias’ arguments by lending them a sceptical twist.
Particularly crucial are the analyses provided by Calogero 1932; Newiger 1973; and Mansfeld
1985. Among other modern editions, I shall refer to Cassin 1980; Buchheim 1989; and Ioli
2010 and 2013.
is.26 In order to reach this goal, Gorgias develops his argument in two
stages: first he establishes the identity between being and not-being,
demonstrating that even not-being is; from this he derives two conse-
quences that lead to the impossibility of both being and not-being,
and hence to the conclusion that nothing is. The argumentative struc-
ture is always the same: (a) first Gorgias establishes a starting assump-
tion; (b) then he explicates what follows from it; (c) he explains the
reasons for this consequence; and finally (d) he draws his conclusions.
Here is a schematic reconstruction of the whole passage:
I. Identify being with not-being
(a) starting assumption: if not-being is not-being;
(b) consequence: what is not is no less than what is is;
(c) explanation: for what is not is what it is not, and what is is what
it is;
(d) conclusion: hence, not-being is as much as being.27
This conclusion raises two distinct problems (not-being is; not-being is
in a similar way to being), which are analysed as follows:
II.1. First consequence
(a) starting assumption: if not-being is;
(b) consequence: being, its opposite, is not;
(c) explanation: for if not-being is, then being, its opposite, is not;
(d) conclusion: hence, nothing is.
II.2. Second consequence
(a) starting assumption: if being and not-being are the same thing;
(b) consequence: being is not;
(c) explanation: for what is not is not-being, and hence even what is is
not-being;
(d) conclusion: hence, nothing is.
26
The most convincing analyses are found in Calogero 1932: 189–268; Mansfeld 1985; Striker
1996: 11–14; Palmer 1999: 66–74; Curd 2006; and Ioli 2010: 28–40.
27
The text of the anonymous M.X.G. literally states: ‘so that things ( pragmata) are not more
(ouden mallon) than they are not’. However, we should not rule out the possibility that the choice
of the expression ouden mallon and the use of pragma may depend on the vocabulary (and
Pyrrhonian inclinations) of the source rather than on Gorgias himself: see Mansfeld 1988: 258,
followed by Curd 2006: 187 n. 8; contra, see Ioli 2010: 34–36.
28
Curd 2006: 186.
29
Palmer 1999: 72.
30
See Striker 1996: 12. This reasoning is also referred to by Plato in the Parmenides (162a–b:
see Mansfeld 1985: 258–62; Palmer 1999: 109–17) and Aristotle in the Metaphysics (see 1003b10:
‘It is for this reason that we say even of non-being that it is non-being’).
existential meaning (if not-being is, being, its opposite, is not), in the
second one the focus is on the predicative meaning (being is not-being:
if being is identical to not-being, then being too is not-being, and hence
is not). Certainly, this undue transition from one meaning of the verb
‘to be’ to the other risks to invalidate the formal correctness of
Gorgias’ refutation. But Gorgias might have objected to this that
what he was doing was merely reproducing an ambiguity already to
be found in Parmenides, simply applying it to not-being rather than
being.31 In this respect at least, insofar as he successfully combined
being and not-being, Gorgias could have effectively defended his thesis
that nothing is: for Parmenides himself had observed that the equating
of being and not-being ‘simply reduces both to the negative level of
non-existence’.32
In the ‘dialectical argument’, Gorgias targets the speculative activ-
ities of all the Presocratics, and not just the theses of the Eleatics. Yet
in this case, too, the Eleatics are Gorgias’ privileged point of reference,
as may be inferred from the discussion on the generated or ungenerated
character of being, which probably represents the most successful
example of Gorgias’ way of arguing.33 Gorgias accepts the arguments
put forward by the Eleatic school regarding the impossibility for
being to be generated, and adopts the thesis that being could neither
be generated from what is (for, in changing, what is would no longer
be what is), nor from what is not (for nothing can be generated from
what is not: nihil ex nihilo). Hence, being is not generated. The prob-
lem, however, is that being is not ungenerated either, contrary to
what the Eleatics liked to claim: Gorgias refutes the Eleatics on
the basis of their very own theses, by leading the arguments that
Melissus and Zeno had produced into contradiction. According to
Melissus, if being were ungenerated, it would also have to be infinite.
This leap from the temporal level to the spatial one might seem
31
Calogero 1932: 197.
32
Ioli 2010: 31; cf. 28B6, 8–9 D.-K. = Parm. D8, 8–9 L.-M. Another objection to Gorgias’ rea-
soning is put forth by the anonymous author of M.X.G., who observes that Gorgias’ thesis also
implies the opposite conclusion: given that being and not-being coincide, one might conclude
not that nothing is, but that everything is. Yet, once again, the anti-Parmenidean polemical back-
drop is enough to show that this is not a real objection at all for Gorgias, given that his primary aim
is to conflate being and not-being: for Parmenides, claiming that everything is – both what is and
what is not – is no more acceptable than the thesis that nothing is.
33
On Gorgias’ argumentative strategy, which often arranges his opponents’ theses into con-
trasting pairs or multiple sets of arguments (e.g. Encomium of Helen, 13), see Mansfeld 1985
and 1986 and the observations made in Chapter 3, pp. 57–62.
34
Briefly put, Gorgias’ argument would run as follows: if P, then X or Y; but neither X nor Y;
hence, not P either. A similar argumentative structure also underpins the second discussion, focus-
ing on the issue of whether being is one or many: if being were one, it would be bodiless; but what
is bodiless has no magnitude, and with no magnitude it would be nothing, as Zeno observed. On
the other hand, if there is no unity, there cannot be any multiplicity either, since this depends on
unity. Therefore, if being is neither one nor many, it is not: nothing is. In M.X.G. we then find a
discussion on movement, but the fragmentary state of the text does not allow us to determine
whether it constituted a further development of the reflection on unity/multiplicity or whether it
instead marked the beginning of the discussion on the motion/rest pair. In support of the first
(and more reasonable) hypothesis, see Ioli 2010: 46–8.
35
Caston 2002.
36
This point might also be raised against Protagoras, who had upheld a sort of infallibilism by
denying the possibility of error: see Di Benedetto 1955 (according to whom Protagoras is actually
the chief polemical target of the whole treatise); Mansfeld 1985: 249–58; Caston 2002: 217–18;
Ioli 2010: 50–60.
what is true and what is false, which is to say to choose one mental state
over another. This marks the beginning of the second argument, which
introduces sense-perceptions by assimilating them to judgements (the
introduction of sense-perceptions once again shows that Gorgias did
not have the Eleatics alone in mind; rather, this second part of the rea-
soning seems to run against ordinary assumptions about knowledge).
For, ultimately, sense-perceptions also concern thoughts: if I see a
thing, that thing is in my mind. But, as has just been noted, if a
thing is in my mind, that thing is, which leads to absurd results;
hence, not even sense-perceptions are always reliable. However, if nei-
ther judgements nor sense-perceptions correctly represent reality, we
are no longer capable of grasping the truth – we no longer have any
way of understanding which of the things we think truly exist. The
truth might exist and it might even be thinkable, but we will never
know whether we have thought it. And this is tantamount to saying
that, even if being is, it is unknowable.
In the transition from the second to the third thesis, Gorgias con-
cedes what he had first denied: after having established that being is
unknowable, he allows that it might be knowable; but even if it might
be knowable, it cannot be communicated to other people. Besides,
we may grant that reality exists, and that we know reality, but we cannot
grant that we can communicate our knowledge. This, as we shall see, is
the most important point for Gorgias, a point that is never disputed in
the treatise. He appears to adduce three arguments in defence of the
third thesis (in this case, too, the text is corrupt – the most convincing
analysis remains that of Mourelatos 1985). The first argument rests on
the assumption of the heterogeneity of logos (understood as thought and
discourse) with respect to reality. Just as sight does not see sound, and
hearing does not hear colours, so logos does not speak things, but
words: the only possible experience is direct, first-hand experience.
But this is off-limits for logos, which always represents a translation of
such experience, a failed translation insofar as it proves incapable of
taking the place of its object.37 The other two arguments merely reassert
the isolation of logos, showing that there is no way of confirming
whether what A has communicated has been received by B as A
37
An alternative reconstruction that is worth mentioning is the one suggested by Wardy 1996:
14–21, who justifies the impossibility of transmitting logos on the basis of a physicalist interpret-
ation of it: logoi are not symbols but physical objects; as such, they can only occur in one place
at any one moment; clearly, this makes the transmission of the same logos impossible.
understands it; indeed, not even A can be sure of this, given the diver-
gence between his own perceptions and feelings at different times. An
unbridgeable gulf thus separates things from thoughts and words: even
assuming that being is knowable, it cannot be communicated.38
Now that we have reached the end of this analysis, it is time to evalu-
ate Gorgias’ treatise in all of its complexity. What are the aims of this
treatise and what is its underlying meaning? Certainly, the treatise con-
tains a fair dose of irony and provocation, both in the theses it defends
and in the way in which it defends them. The problem, then, is to
understand the meaning of these provocations. Scholars in the past
fluctuated between two radical interpretations of Gorgias: the first dis-
missed his text as a mere divertissement of no real philosophical inter-
est;39 the second interpretation emphasized its ‘nihilism’.40 It is all
too evident, however, that both theses are one-sided, and that they
fail to adequately account for the challenge launched by Gorgias. A cer-
tain playfulness, which frequently manifests itself in the author’s desire
to dazzle his public with bold arguments, no doubt constitutes a defin-
ing feature of Gorgias’ practice (and of the sophists’ more in general).41
Yet this does not justify the conclusion that there is nothing of philo-
sophical relevance in the treatise (and that the treatise is merely an
example of sophistry – of arguments that are only apparently true42).
On the contrary, we only need to think of the discussions on the verb
‘to be’ or of the problem of communicability to realize that Gorgias
is raising questions of the utmost importance, which all great philoso-
phers – from Plato to those of our own day – have felt compelled to
address.43 As for the ‘nihilist’ reading, even leaving aside the problem
of what ‘nihilist’ means, it is clear that this is a doubly selective inter-
pretation. First, it de facto only considers the first thesis – that nothing
38
Kerferd 1984: 218–21; Palmer 2009: 87–8.
39
See Gomperz 1912: 28.
40
One notable example of this interpretation is furnished by Diels 1884, which reconstructs
Gorgias’ spiritual history in three stages: after initially subscribing to Empedocles’ theses,
Gorgias discovered Eleatic dialectic, which marked the beginning of a ‘period of doubt, or rather
of despair’, culminating with the nihilism of the treatise on not-being; Gorgias then emerged from
this nihilism through a new interest in rhetoric. The nihilistic interpretation crops up again and
again in the literature (see the list in Caston 2002: 205 n. 1) and has recently been taken up
again by Hourcade 2006.
41
Consider too fragment 82B12 D.-K. = 32D18 L.-M.: ‘Gorgias said that we should destroy
our opponents’ seriousness by laughter, and their laughter by seriousness.’
42
See J. Robinson 1973.
43
Besides, as rightly noted by Kerferd 1955–6: 3, Gorgias’ treatise is just as playful as Plato’s
Parmenides (see Parm. 137b).
through our senses and via correct reasoning, with no need to yield to
the abstract truths of philosophy.
No doubt, these interpretations have the merit of identifying some of
the key aspects of Gorgias’ thought, from his interest in the problem of
language to his focus on logical arguments. However, both of them risk
assigning too much to Gorgias: for – and this is a crucial point – what
authorizes us to take everything that Gorgias says as his own personal
doctrine? On the contrary, what clearly emerges from a reading of his
treatise is a dialectical position:44 his arguments appear to reflect a
desire to show to what absurd conclusions the theses or beliefs of his
opponents lead, and not to convey any personal theories; Gorgias is
arguing against, not in defence of. In other words, his treatise constitutes
an apparently playful reflection on a series of far from playful problems
in human life. Yet, we are not justified in turning these reflections and
the arguments developed by Gorgias into a holistic theory, as the afore-
mentioned scholars have sought to do. Gorgias’ aim is to invite his
interlocutors to acknowledge the complexity of these problems, and
to challenge them to come up with the most satisfactory solutions.
We know nothing at all of his own answers, assuming that he had
any to offer: ‘There isn’t any difficulty in appreciating Gorgias’ argu-
ments, once we see them dialectically – once, that is, we stop thinking
that the only way to be serious is to be dogmatic.’45 It is essential to clar-
ify this point in order to appreciate Gorgias’ teaching. His whole reflec-
tion takes the form of an all-out attack against the foundationalist
claims of philosophy and common sense: what Gorgias questions is
not so much reality itself, as the foundationalist claim that reality
possesses some invariant structures and that humans are capable of
discerning and communicating such structures.46 Whether the target
is Parmenides or the ‘two-headed men’, the polemical aim is this
alleged correspondence between being, thought, and language, along
with everything which this thesis implies: (1) the belief that reality is
something ontologically, logically, and temporally independent of us;
(2) the idea that knowledge coincides with the objective apprehension
44
This is suggested, e.g., by Striker 1996: 11–14; Woodruff 1999: 305–6; Caston 2002: 207–8.
See also Wardy 1996: 9–24.
45
Caston 2002: 208.
46
The main champions of this thesis are Mourelatos 1985, Wardy 1996, and Consigny 2001:
60–73 et passim. Cassin 1995 adopts a similar position, with a markedly idiosyncratic reading.
of this independent structure; and (3) trust in the fact that the purpose
of language is simply to convey this knowledge.
But – Gorgias asks – are things really so? Can we really speak of an iso-
lated reality, removed from the contingencies of human culture and lan-
guage? And even assuming that an independent reality exists, does
knowledge simply coincide with the correspondence of thought to things?
Rather, is it not the case that our opinions, prejudices, expectations, and
desires condition our approach to reality? Ultimately, these are the pro-
blems that Gorgias is most concerned with. They are substantial problems.
Finally, the anti-foundationalist interpretation just outlined has the
merit of explaining what is probably Gorgias’ chief contribution,
namely his acknowledgement of the importance of language in
human experience. As already noted, his whole treatise highlights the
complexity of the linguistic phenomenon, and this awareness – as we
shall see – also finds significant parallels in the other surviving works
by the same author. What makes Gorgias’ reflections so interesting is
the fact that he freed language (and logos more generally) from all onto-
logical implications, all alleged metaphysical correspondences with
reality: logos is not a reflection of things or the natural means by
which to objectively and impartially describe reality.47 On the contrary,
Gorgias asserts the independence of discourse, with its limits and
potential. As we shall see, a more in-depth investigation of this problem
reveals that his theses constitute a genuine challenge to philosophy.
47
Segal 1962: 110.
48
Brunschwig 2002.
49
Pradeau 2009b: 327.
50
See Themistius, Paraphrase of Metaphysics, 6.25–7.2; Philoponus, Commentary on Physics,
43.9–13; Simplicius, Commentary on Physics, 93.29–30 (these passages are not included in the
D.-K. edition). It seems that a passage from Plato’s Sophist (251b) can also be traced back to dis-
cussions of this kind, albeit not necessarily to Lycophron.
51
Bonazzi and Pradeau 2009: 335.
Antiphon was certainly among the most prominent sophists, and argu-
ably one of the most fascinating. However, two obstacles have ham-
pered the full appreciation of his merits, unjustly removing him from
the centre stage. The first is the problem of his identity, which has
added to the complexity of interpreting his ethical and political frag-
ments. A second and just as insidious hindrance has been the prejudice
according to which the sophists were only interested in the human
world, which is to say rhetorical and political problems. Thus the
many fragments of Antiphon’s writings that deal with cosmological,
biological, meteorological, geometrical, and medical topics have been
neglected, in the belief that they constitute a confused mass of informa-
tion collected from disparate sources. No doubt, Antiphon’s analyses
are largely indebted to the research conducted by natural philosophers
such as Anaxagoras and Democritus or by the Hippocratic physicians.
However, the conclusions drawn by Antiphon are far from obvious or
banal: on the contrary, the picture of physis, of reality, that emerges
from his writing is highly original and, as we shall see, constitutes the
foundation for even more interesting political considerations. The
case of Antiphon also shows that there is no radical break between
the sophists and the Presocratic natural philosophers: in their analyses,
the sophists did not overlook their predecessors’ theses.
Antiphon’s main work was entitled Truth. This title was not ran-
domly chosen, since it perfectly reflects the context in which its author
sought to operate. The title is also significant in relation to Protagoras,
since Antiphon’s theses, particularly in the political sphere, are very
much indebted to and react against the work of the sophist of
52
See Diogenes Laertius, 6.1; Guthrie 1971: 216–18.
Abdera. One focus of the treatise – perhaps the chief focus – was physis,
which was investigated from a wide range of perspectives. The most
stimulating, and best-known, section of the work concerns human
nature; but the author’s analysis of humankind was based on a more
general analysis of reality, fragments of which also survive.
The following testimony from Aristotle helps clarify the possible
meaning of Antiphon’s position:
Some people think that the nature and substance of the things that are by nature is what
is present first of all in each thing, without possessing configuration (arrhuthmistos) in
itself, as the nature of a bed is the wood, and that of a statue the bronze. Antiphon
says that evidence of this is the fact that if one were to bury a bed and the rotting
could acquire the power of sending up a shoot, it would not become a bed, but
wood, which shows that the arrangement in accordance with the rules of the art is
merely an accidental attribute, whereas the substance is the other, which, further, per-
sists continuously through the process.
(87B15 D.-K. = partially reproduced in 37D8 L.-M.)
The above claim is far less banal than it seems. The passage establishes
an opposition between what – using the Aristotelian terminology – we
might call accidental characteristics, and what truly counts, namely the
essence, that which subsists continuously. This opposition between
convention and reality, couched in terms of the opposition between
nomos and physis, was to play a decisive role in Antiphon’s thought.
Here it is interesting to note the way in which physis, understood as
the ultimate material constituent, is presented: according to
Aristotle’s testimony, the term which Antiphon used to describe nature
is arrythmiston, ‘without configuration’, a rare adjective that may be
traced back to the Democritean tradition. Physis, then, is the unconfi-
gured material substrate that resists all external attempts to lend it
order.53 Other fragments too – unfortunately, very short ones – confirm
this picture (87B10, 12, 22–5 D.-K. = 37D9, 37, 18–21 L.-M.), sug-
gesting that Antiphon championed an organic, dynamic, and material-
ist view of reality. Physis is something living and ever-changing that
obeys its own rhythm, not one imposed from the outside: the natural
constituents of the universe (such as the sun and planets) are the prod-
uct of a chain of causal relations which do not stem from any intelligent
or finalistic plan, but only from the accidental combination of the ele-
ments (87B28–32 D.-K. = 37D24–7 L.-M.).
53
See Romeyer-Dherbey 1985: 96–103.
The implications of these views are far from negligible, when exam-
ined against the background of their cultural context: Antiphon’s
defence of the idea of a universe governed by necessity but not provi-
dence reflects an attempt on his part to clearly distance himself from
all mythical or religious explanations of reality. Moreover, he distances
himself not just from religious traditions but also from most of the
Presocratics, who – while emancipating themselves from the world of
myth – had assigned the ultimate principle or principles a series of posi-
tive attributes usually assigned to the gods: for Antiphon, the nature of
the all is not divine. Finally, from the opposite perspective, we cannot
rule out a criticism of Protagoras and Gorgias, who, by placing humans
at the centre of everything, had denied the priority of physis. Antiphon
succeeds in the delicate task of striking a middle ground, emphasizing
the centrality of nature while at the same time denying any axiological
superiority to this priority: his nature, true reality, is something neutral,
devoid of any meaning or value that might direct human choices.
Reality is indifferent: the importance of these theses will become
clear once the discussion focuses on humankind.54
Someone who had fully realized the significance of the kind of theses
put forward by Antiphon was Plato, who in the Laws – which is to say in
the last years of his life, at a fair distance from the debates and cultural
climate of the fifth century – felt the need to newly address the same
problems in order to decry their dangers. In Book 10, the Athenian
Stranger sets out to inform his two friends, the Spartan Megillus and
the Cretan Clinias, about those theses which were then circulating in
Athens concerning nature and the gods. Although the thinkers referred
to by Plato are unnamed, it is more than likely that, among others, he
was targeting Anaxagoras (who had denied the divine nature of the sun,
arguing that it was only a fiery rock – a thesis at the root of all problems:
886d–e), Democritus, and even Antiphon. The last, as has been sug-
gested, may in fact be Plato’s chief polemical target.55
The thesis put forward by the anonymous thinkers is that the universe
is the necessary outcome of the accidental combination of its material
constituents, which ‘moved at random, each impelled by virtue of its
own inherent properties’ (889b). While the combination of necessity
and chance, two apparently contrasting concepts, may seem odd at
54
See Gagarin 2002: 69–71.
55
Untersteiner 1949–62: iv.178–95; Decleva Caizzi 1986a; Neschke Hentske 1995: 140–9;
Bonazzi 2012. See also Sedley 2013.
natural world and not on the human world is the thesis that the sophists
had no interest in physis and only focused on humanity. Rather, what
the sophists appear to have polemically engaged with is the fascination
with what is obscure, with the hidden nature of things.56 However, phy-
sis as such remains the starting point of all enquiries. To be more pre-
cise, reality remains the central problem that cannot be overlooked: the
common denominator in all these disparate theories, often developed
in polemical contrast to one another, is the acknowledgement of the
problematic nature of reality.57
And yet, the sophists are responsible for a fundamental turn in the
history of philosophy, a turn the importance of which can hardly be
ignored: a shift of focus from nature to the human world. Of course,
as has been noted, this does not mean that the Presocratics had not
focused on the human world; but they had done so starting from
their study of physis, by considering human beings as part of the
whole. The sophists adopted a completely new perspective, by setting
out from the belief that things must be turned round, that it is reductive
to consider humans simply as a part of the whole. On the contrary, in
their view it is necessary to set out from human beings and their
uniqueness with respect to other entities. In other words, the sophists
follow in the trail of the Presocratic philosophical tradition and con-
tinue to investigate problems related to nature, the city, and human-
kind, but following an opposite hierarchy, based on a decisive
philosophical intuition that no subsequent thinkers could afford to
ignore: the idea that the relation between reality and human beings is
problematic and cannot be taken for granted, but must rather be con-
structed. And it is on the basis of this acknowledgement that the soph-
ists discussed human beings and their problems: for if nature in itself is
ambiguous, neutral, or devoid of meaning, one must turn elsewhere in
order to discover the meaning of humanity’s experience and life. The
attention shifts from cosmology to epistemology, from the study of real-
ity in itself to that of how we can know reality and relate to it – from
physis to logos.
56
Woodruff 1999: 309.
57
Paci 1957: 126.
1
Pernot 2006: 15–22.
2
Gagarin 2008.
3
Brancacci 1996: 116–17.
4
Classen 1976: 223–5.
5
The distinction between these two expressions is unclear: see Guthrie 1971: 205.
6
Guthrie 1971: 220.
7
Momigliano 1930. It is difficult to determine on what basis Prodicus drew his distinctions: in
some cases he would appear to rely on the traditional use of terms (e.g. 84A18 D.-K., partially
reproduced in 34D24 L.-M.), while elsewhere he seems to suggest radical innovations based on
their etymology (84B4 D.-K. = 34D9 L.-M.; see Pfeiffer 1968: 40–1). The small number of testi-
monies makes it difficult to come up with a definite answer to these questions: see Classen 1976:
232–7. As rightly noted by Dorion 2009b: 531 n. 22 in relation to 84A16 D.-K., Prodicus also
investigated the problem of homonymy, which is to say the phenomenon of the semantic ambiguity
of a term (the term in this particular case being manthano, which in Greek means both ‘to under-
stand’ and ‘to learn’).
often associate the two8), the main difference being that, whereas
Prodicus appear to proceed by asking ‘how does x differ from y’,
Socrates focuses more directly on individual entities, asking ‘what is
x?’9 In Prodicus’ case, this interest in names and synonyms has
favoured a particular interpretation of his thought, which has empha-
sized his specificity compared to other sophists. It has been noted
that his distinctions usually (but not always: see 84B4 D.-K. = 34D9
L.-M.) refer to terms and concepts pertaining to the field of ethics or
moral psychology.10 This has led some scholars to set Prodicus in con-
trast ‘to people the likes of Callicles and Thrasymachus’, as an oppon-
ent of the relativism typical of these authors and the upholder of a
certain foundation for the moral principles that are to govern people’s
lives.11 Provided that we bear in mind the rhetorical purposes of this
kind of research in Prodicus’ case as well, the reconstruction in ques-
tion is largely valid (we will be returning to it in Chapter 5).12
Prodicus’ positive ethical orientation, however, does not entail such a
radical contrast with the other sophists, as may be inferred from a com-
parison with Protagoras.
Plato’s Phaedrus suggests that one of Protagoras’ works was entitled
Orthoepeia (The Correctness of Language; Phdr. 267c = 80A26 D.-K. =
31D22a L.-M.). Regrettably, the content of this book is completely
unknown; but different sources confirm that Protagoras had an interest
in the problem of the correctness of language at different levels.13
Mention has already been made of Protagoras’ grammatical interests
and criticism of Homer, which implied the thesis of linguistic correct-
ness. On another level, the notion of orthos is used as a criterion of ana-
lysis for poetry: correctness in this case concerns not points of
grammar, but the consistency of a composition, its statements, and
its moral teaching (80A25 D.-K. = 31D31 and 42 L.-M.; we will be
returning to this testimony in the following section). Finally, the
same notion could also be applied in an even more general sense:
8
See Guthrie 1971: 275.
9
Classen 1976: 232.
10
Dumont 1986; Wolfsdorf 2008b.
11
In this respect, it is interesting to note that, in the Euthydemus, Plato mentions Prodicus twice
as a potential opponent of sophists and eristic debaters such as Euthydemus and Dionysodorus:
see Euth. 277e and 305c.
12
Cole 1991: 100.
13
Gagarin 2008: 28–30. More in general, see Rademaker 2013.
14
Significantly, Antiphon’s second Tetralogy discusses the same problem. See also Antiphon’s
fr. 87B44, 4.10 (= 37D38 L.-M.), where the criterion of ‘correct reasoning’ is used to establish
what causes pain and what pleasure. Another interesting occurrence of the criterion of correctness
is to be found in the Encomium of Helen, where Gorgias sets out ‘to say correctly what is necessary’
in order to preserve Helen’s honour (82B11, 2 D.-K. = 32D24 L.-M.).
15
Untersteiner 1954: 30–2 and 66.
16
Gagarin 2008: 30.
17
This doctrine also shows that Protagoras was not endorsing a conventionalist theory of
names, as one might well expect (see Pl. Crat. 391b–d and the observations rightly made by
Corradi 2006: 54–5). A conventionalist position is possibly to be found in Euthydemus and
Dionysodorus’ thesis, as presented in Plato’s Euthydemus, and has also been attributed to
Antiphon by Guthrie 1971: 204 on the basis of the pseudo-Hippocratic treatise On Art that
Diels published as an appendix to 87B1 D.-K. (= Med. T2 L.-M.). In this passage, however,
the author’s silence as regards his polemical aims makes it difficult to prove Guthrie’s thesis. In
the same period, in close proximity to the sophists, Democritus appears to have upheld a similarly
conventionalist thesis: see Barnes 1979: i.164–9.
18
The same conception also explains the statement that ‘it is not possible to contradict’ (80A19
D.-K. = 31R 10 L.-M.): to the extent that each individual entertains a relationship with things
whose reality and truth cannot be disputed or contradicted, the opposition here is only apparent.
It is interesting to note that in a recently republished papyrus, the same thesis is also attributed to
Prodicus, only on the basis of different arguments: see PToura III 16, 9–18, reprinted in Bonazzi
2007: 261 (= 34R14 L.-M.).
19
See Corradi 2007b.
20
Classen 1976: 222–5.
21
Brancacci 2002b: 183–90.
the human beings and the importance of logos, understood as the cap-
acity to reason and to express oneself – as thought and speech. An
increased awareness of the chasm between human beings and reality
goes hand in hand with a belief that, through logos, humans can become
the measure of all things. This is what Protagoras’ thesis ultimately
amounts to, and it is easy to see that Prodicus and the other sophists
had reached the same conclusion, by different routes.
22
See Pfeiffer 1968: 16–17; Soverini 1998: 6–12. Very interesting reflections are also to be
found in Most 1986, who stresses the importance of the interpretation of literary texts as a distinct-
ive feature of the sophists. Indeed, the sophists’ penchant for the written word constitutes a distin-
guishing element with respect to the oral culture in which poets found themselves operating: see
again Pfeiffer 1968: 24–30. It is worth recalling the fact that several sophists were also the authors
of poetical works: this is the case with Hippias (86A12 and B1 D.-K. = 36D2 and D4 L.-M.),
Critias, and possibly Antiphon (see 87A6 a 9 D.-K. = 37P8 L.-M.).
23
Goldhill 1986: 222–43; Morgan 2000: 89–94.
24
Brancacci 1996: 111. The likely polemical target of this method of literal exegesis is the alle-
gorical exegesis developed by Theagenes of Rhegium in the sixth century BC and later taken up in
Athens by another great intellectual of the period, Anaxagoras of Clazomenae, and by his pupil
Metrodorus of Lampsacus (on these authors, see Rocca-Serra 1990 and Morgan 2000: 98–
101). Evidence of a polemic between Protagoras and the champions of the allegorical method is
possibly to be found in testimony 80A30 D.-K. (= 31D32 L.-M.), in which Protagoras focuses
on a theomachy, a theme dear to Homeric interpreters of the allegorical tradition (who were
wont to interpret theomachies as symbolizing the oppositions between natural elements, such as
hot and cold, or dry and moist): see Brancacci 1996: 118. On Protagoras and Homer see, more
recently, Capra 2005 and Corradi 2006: 56–63.
grow familiar with the works of the poets and hence with traditional
values – values that the individual will then be free to engage with, by
either approving or rejecting them.25 Similar conclusions are suggested
by other sources I have mentioned, namely the (regrettably) very suc-
cinct texts in which Protagoras analyses and criticizes some Homeric
verses (80A28–30 D.-K. = 31D24–5, 30 L.-M.): by showing his ability
to discuss the great Homer, while at the same time taking the liberty of
criticizing him, Protagoras justifies his claim to be the new teacher that
the city needs.
The importance of an engagement with the poetic tradition finds
confirmation that is only apparently unexpected in the ‘man-measure’
fragment. In the previous chapter we saw how one of Protagoras’
polemical targets was Parmenides and the philosophical tradition of
the ‘teachers of the truth’. Yet these were not the only ‘teachers
of the truth’ attacked by the sophists, since much the same holds true
of the poets, who had often drawn upon the idea of ‘measure’ to assert
their importance: a poet – to quote some famous verses – is someone
who, by grace of the Muses, knows the ‘measure’ of loving wisdom
(Solon, fr. 1, 51–2 Gentili-Prato) and possesses the ‘measure’ of wis-
dom (Theognis, 873–6).26 A poet, in other words, is someone who,
by virtue of the divine protection he enjoys, is capable of speaking
the truth and distinguishing it from falsehood; he is the custodian of
the order of reality and this justifies his prominent role in society.27
Everything changes with Protagoras: the ‘man-measure’ thesis under-
mines the poets’ claim to truth, just as it does with the truth referred
to by philosophers such as Parmenides (who ultimately were operating
within the same context as the tradition of poetic lore: he too wrote in
verse). The truth is no longer guaranteed by gods and inspired poets,
since humans are now the measure of all things, each according to
their own perspective. And Protagoras is the new teacher, and the
only one who can help others find their bearings in the ambiguous
world that surrounds them, in which contrasting opinions take the
place of absolute truth and falsehood. We can thus appreciate the pro-
grammatic importance of Protagoras’ introductory speech at the begin-
ning of Plato’s Protagoras, where he proclaims himself to be the heir to
an authoritative, centuries-old tradition:
25
Morgan 2000: 94.
26
See Corradi 2007a.
27
Arrighetti 1998: xv–xxi; Detienne 2006: 113–24.
I say that the sophistic art is ancient, but that those ancient men who practiced it,
because they feared the annoyance it caused, employed a screen and disguised it,
some using poetry, like Homer, Hesiod, and Simonides, and others initiatory rites
and oracles, the followers of Orpheus and Musaeus; and certain ones, I have heard,
under gymnastic too, like Iccus of Tarentum and another one, still alive, as much a
sophist as anyone: Herodicus of Selymbria, originally a Megarian colony. And music
was the screen employed by your fellow citizen Agathocles, a great sophist,
Pythoclides of Ceos, and many others.28
(Pl. Prot. 316d–317c)
This claim is not merely designed to place Protagoras under the aegis of
a well-rooted tradition; rather, it contributes to a more complex strategy
of appropriation, which, through an apparently slavish adherence,
brings about a radical reversal.
While Protagoras seems to focus entirely on the rational and ration-
ally analysable aspects of poetic language, Gorgias also shows an inter-
est in its psychagogic and creative aspects (without overlooking the
importance of rational arguments, as we will see in the following sec-
tion). The assumptions and aims, however, are the same: the centrality
of logos and the ambition to establish oneself as Greece’s true teacher.
In particular, Gorgias’ reflection is marked by an acknowledgement of
the power of words and by the notion of deception. In this respect, the
most interesting text is his declamation Encomium of Helen, which was
apparently composed to defend the memory of Homer’s famous hero-
ine, guilty of having fled with Paris, bringing about the Trojan War.
Among the various reasons that may have led Helen to flee to Troy,
Gorgias considers the arguments by which Paris might have persuaded
her, and this allows him to embark on a famous digression on the power
of logos and what constitutes it, namely words:
Speech (logos) is a great potentate that by means of an extremely tiny and entirely invis-
ible body performs the most divine deeds. For it is able to stop fear, to remove grief, to
instil joy, and to increase pity. (82B11, 8 D.-K. = 32D24, 8 L.-M.)
28
Only part of this passage is included in the Diels-Kranz edition, as 80A5 D.-K. (the whole
text appears in Bonazzi 2009b as T6 and L.-M. as Soph. R11). On its importance, see
Brancacci 2002a.
29
See Rosenmeyer 1955; Verdenius 1981; Horky 2006.
30
As regards Parmenides, see fr. 28B, 56 D.-K. (= Parm. 19D8.57 L.-M.) and Verdenius
1981: 124. On the poetic tradition, see de Romilly 1975: 1–22 and de Romilly 1973, who also
notes that this conception of poetry as something magical and illusionary (see e.g. 82B11,
9 D.-K. = 32D24, 9 L.-M.) might reflect an influence from Empedocles (whose disciple
Gorgias may have been: 82A3, 10 D.-K. = 32P4–5 L.-M., and Kerferd 1985).
31
Segal 1962: 124.
32
Casertano 2004: 83
33
This idea is also taken up in the Dissoi logoi, 89, 3, 10–12 D.-K. (= 40, 3, 10–12 L.-M.),
which quotes verses by the poets Cleoboulina and Aeschylus.
34
Segal 1962: 102; Poulakos 1983.
35
In Gorgias’ case, appropriation also entails an attempt to adapt the poetic style to the kind of
prose declamations typical of his oeuvre: see 82A29 D.-K. (= 32D21b L.-M.) and de Romilly
1975: 8–11.
36
Detienne 2006: 191.
37
Detienne 2006: 192.
38
Besides, it is worth noting that Hippias’ ‘antiquarian’ interests were not limited to poetic
quotes, since he also made lists of the winners at the Olympics, so as to establish a reliable chron-
ology of Greek history (86B3 D.-K. = 36D7 L.-M.), of the founding of cities, and of human
genealogies (86A2 and B2 D.-K. = 36D14b and D30 L.-M.), and of many other topics pertaining
to mythological, ethnographic, geographical, and philosophical traditions (86B6–9, 12 D.-K. =
36D22–3, 26–8 L.-M.). On Hippias’ pursuits as a polymath, see Brunschwig 1984; A. Patzer
1986; Pfeiffer 1968: 51–4; Mansfeld 1986; and Balaudé 2006.
39
Pfeiffer 1968: 54–5.
40
See Brisson 2009: 395.
41
Another text that might help us further clarify the nature of the sophists’ interest in literary
criticism and poetry is an anonymous papyrus (POxy. III 414) that Giuliano 1998 has hypothet-
ically assigned to Antiphon. In his collection of fragments of the sophists, moreover, Untersteiner
had published an anonymous treatise On Music, which deals with similar issues (Untersteiner
1949–62: iii.208–11).
42
The traditional reconstruction identified a first Sicilian stage, represented by two almost
unknown figures, Tisias and Corax. From Sicily, rhetoric would then have reached Athens thanks
to Gorgias (who famously visited Athens as an ambassador in 427 BC); in turn, Gorgias would have
influenced other sophists such as Antiphon (assuming, of course, that the rhetor and the sophist of
this name are one and the same person: see p. 128) and Thrasymachus. Among the modern cham-
pions of this view, see Kennedy 1963 and, more recently, Pernot 2006.
43
See esp. Cole 1991: 71–112, and Gagarin 2007. Besides, the very adjective rhetorike, which
has given us the term ‘rhetoric’, may have been coined by Plato: see Schiappa 1991: 40–9, along
with the reservations voiced by Pernot 2006: 34–5.
44
See, for example, Lloyd 1979: 79–86.
45
One variation of this argument is what we might call the ‘counter-probability’ argument: see
e.g. Antiphon, Tetral. 1.2.2.3 and 2.2.6. A classic example is the case of a fight between a weak
man and a strong one: in order to defend himself, the former argues that, being weak, it is unlikely
that he wished to pick a fight with someone stronger. In turn, the latter replies by turning this rea-
soning on its head: it is unlikely that he was the one to start the fight because, being the stronger, he
would immediately have been blamed for it. In other words, something is claimed to be unlikely
precisely because it is likely: see Aristotle, Rhetoric, 2.24.12 (this argument was apparently
‘invented’ by Corax). The sophists’ interest in the notion of ‘probability’ or ‘likelihood’, however,
does not justify the criticism levelled by Plato, who in Phaedrus, 267a, accuses the sophists of
choosing what is probable over what is true: for one only speaks of probability when the truth is
unclear, which is often the case (unfortunately), but not always. See Gagarin 1994.
46
The most complete analysis is provided by Spatharas 2001; see too Mazzara 1999 and Long
1984. On Antiphon, see the analysis by Gagarin 2007 (who quite rightly reacts to Solmsen 1931,
according to whom all of Antiphon’s orations were marked by the adoption of irrational argumen-
tative schemes, such as the use of oaths and ordeals, which were typical of the archaic age).
Thrasymachus was by contrast famous for his ability to play with the audience’s feelings; see
Macé 2008. For an overview, see also Tinsdale 2010.
47
Natali 1986; see also above, Chapter 1, n. 11.
If Gorgias were really trying to persuade his audience of Helen’s innocence, he could
have chosen a different strategy with a much greater chance of success.48 But if his
48
For example, he could have exploited an alternative version of the myth, according to which
Helen never went to Troy (this is the version followed by the poet Stesichorus, among others: see
Plato, Phaedrus, 243a–b; see too Herodotus 2.113–20 and Euripides’ Helen). The argument that
Helen was innocent, despite the fact that she went to Troy, instead betrays a desire to provoke
the audience with a thesis that at first sight seems utterly implausible.
purpose was rather to enhance his reputation and demonstrate his intellectual virtuos-
ity, then he may have felt that the more implausible the case appears initially, the more
chance he has to show his skill in arguing for it as well as to develop novel perspective
on the issues involved. . . .It does not matter whether anyone is persuaded of Helen’s
innocence; the important thing is that Gorgias’ arguments open up new ways in
which to think about language, emotion, causation, and responsibility. His case may
be shocking, even perverse; it may be completely unconvincing; but his logos remains
one of the most interesting and intellectually stimulating works of the sophistic
period.49
Besides, all of this does not apply to Gorgias alone. For instance, a
cursory reading of the Dissoi logoi is enough to show that the primary
aim of its anonymous author is not simply to persuade his audience,
for example when he notes that, in a race or war, victory is good for
the winner but bad for the loser: the purpose of a claim of this sort is
certainly not to persuade anyone that good and bad are the same
thing. From Protagoras onwards, antilogy became the typical scheme
of sophistic discussions, with opposing arguments being used as a
means to examine a question in all of its complexity and ambiguity.
When properly employed, this method could be of use for winning
arguments; yet it was just as useful as a means to discuss problematic
cases, investigate or develop different types of arguments, entertain
the public or capture its interest, and showcase one’s skills.50 We
here get to the very heart of the sophists’ conceptualization: the analysis
of logos served not just to develop rigorous and cogent arguments, but
also to investigate various other aspects of human experience.51
This helps to clear up a third misunderstanding. The sophists have
often been accused of being somewhat incoherent and unsystematic.
Now, if no philosophy can exist without a system – that is, without a sys-
tematic and organized exposition of all the problems under scrutiny – it
is legitimate to claim that there is no room for the sophists in this field.
But such a rigid conception hardly does any justice to the richness
of philosophy, which also includes enquiry and critical analysis as
constitutive elements. According to this second, and more reasonable,
definition, the sophists, too, have a place in philosophy, since, in order
for it to truly work, the analysis of logos cannot be reduced to an
investigation of argumentative techniques, but must also take into
49
Gagarin 2001: 285–6.
50
Gagarin 2001: 289.
51
See Solmsen 1975.
52
Segal 1962; Long 2015: 97–103. Along with logos and eros, another phenomenon to which
Gorgias pays particular attention both in the Encomium of Helen and elsewhere (cf. 82B4
D.-K. =32D45a L.-M.) is sight. This has an intermediate function, so to speak, insofar as it transmits
purely physical stimuli to the soul, engendering emotional states such as fear and joy, which in turn elicit
certain behaviours according to the sequence: physical stimulus – emotional response – physical stimu-
lus. In addition to the crucial study of Segal 1962: 105–7, see Casertano 1986 and Ioli 2010: 56–60,
exploring a possible ‘sophistic theory of perception’.
53
See Barnes 1979: ii.524–30; Tordesillas 2008.
Ontology: discourse celebrates being, its function is to speak it. Logology: discourse
makes being, being is an effect of speaking. In the former case, the exterior imposes
itself, and requires that we speak it; in the latter case, discourse produces the exterior.55
As repeatedly noted over the course of this chapter, the sophists can
truly make a claim to being specialists of logos. Clearly, this is such
an important term that it can hardly be made the exclusive preserve
54
Ioli 2010: 90. On the function of language in Gorgias, see also Calogero 1932: 262 and esp.
Mourelatos 1985: 627–30.
55
Cassin 1995: 73.
of the sophists: the concept of logos, with all that it entails, was just as
important for the Presocratics, as well as for Plato, Aristotle, and all
other Greek philosophers. Still, the sophists’ contribution here remains
crucial. It was thanks to them that an awareness of the fact that logos is
the distinctive feature of humankind emerged. Whereas for many pre-
vious thinkers, logos is what enables us to get in touch with an objective
and well-ordered reality, since logos is also the ordering principle of
reality, for the sophists it is a tool that a human can – and must – use
to give meaning to things, a meaning that things do not necessarily pos-
sess in themselves. The problem, in other words, is to build a relation-
ship with an ever-elusive reality and to adapt to changing situations,
finding the right measure in each case. Thus the problem of logos is
the problem of kairos, the right moment: the problem of finding the
best possible solution in each circumstance and of knowing how to
express it.56
In themselves, when viewed in abstract terms, however, logos and
kairos are not enough to describe the sophists’ position. The attempt
to give meaning to reality cannot be confined to the theoretical level
of words, but must concretely manifest itself in the shaping of a
human world: in order to possess any real value, the sophists’ logos
must engage with the ambiguous world of politics, where nothing is
fixed and duplicity is the norm. It is hardly a coincidence that the
first people to be referred to as sophists were politicians such as
Mnesiphilus, who had helped Themistocles:
Who was neither an orator nor one of the so-called ‘natural philosophers’, but who,
practicing something that at that time was called ‘wisdom’ (sophia) but was really clev-
erness in political matters and pragmatic shrewdness, made this his profession and pre-
served it intact like a sect transmitted to him in succession from Solon. But those
people who followed him mixed this with forensic arts and transferred its sphere of
56
Scholars have long been debating the importance of the notion of kairos for the sophists – a
notion that was widespread in the archaic Greek world. The problem is twofold: first, to determine
whether the sophists developed a rhetorical theory of kairos (thereby acknowledging the import-
ance of improvisation); and second, to determine whether they also assigned kairos a more general
value, which might make it the notion that best expresses the specific nature of sophistic knowl-
edge. The few surviving sources allow us to give a positive answer to the first problem (in
82B13 D.K. = 32D12 L.-M., Gorgias is even credited with a kairou techne; cf. 82A1a, A24 and
B13 D.-K. [= 32D11–12 L.-M.]; 80A1 D.-K. [= 31D20DL.-M.] on Protagoras and
Alcidamas’ speech On Those Who Write Written Speeches, or On the Sophists). As regards the second
problem, the existence of a general doctrine of kairos (a ‘Kairos-Lehre’, to quote Guthrie 1971: 272
n. 4) seems like a projection on the part of modern scholars – a fascinating, yet at least partly ana-
chronistic, view; see Tortora 1985 and Tordesillas 1986.
As is well known – and as one would expect in the historical and cul-
tural context of the fifth century – the sophists extensively dealt with
practical and political matters. It is important to note that this was
not a self-contained interest, but the direct consequence of their enqui-
ries into physis and logos:
to put it in even more provocative terms, the blueprint for the sophists’ politics is pro-
vided by the treatise On Not-Being. . . .Ultimately, being is but a consequence of saying.
Given this, it is clear that the presence of Being, the immediacy of Nature, and the
evidence of a speech designed to adequately express these things, all vanish together:
the natural philosopher who discovers speech gives way to the politician who creates
discourse.58
57
See also Detienne 2006: 205.
58
Cassin 1995: 152.
1
Ostwald 1969.
2
De Romilly 2005: 49–66.
3
Heinimann 1945.
4
Hoffmann 1997.
5
See now Gavray 2017.
6
Neschke-Hentske 1995: 56–9.
foundations for – and lends legitimacy to – the law (and hence justice)
is precisely the concept of what is advantageous and useful for the par-
ties who are striking an agreement. Naturally, in this case too we cannot
think of what is useful as an objective good: as people’s interests vary
depending on the situation, it is not something which one must con-
form to, but rather something to be constructed out of different points
of view. It is precisely this capacity to promote an agreement based on
what is useful that reveals the importance of the sophist or his pupil, the
politician.7 Their duty is to help the city establish rules and values,
which will then take the concrete form of a body of laws (nomoi) allow-
ing the city to prosper: ‘the clever and competent orators [i.e. those
who publicly discuss political matters, hence politicians and sophists]
make good things seem to be just to cities instead of bad ones’ (A21a
D.-K. = 31D38 L.-M.).8
Similar conclusions are suggested by an analysis of the famous myth
that Plato puts into Protagoras’ mouth in the other dialogue devoted to
the sophist, the Protagoras (80C1 D.-K. = 31D40 L.-M.). Some scho-
lars have questioned the reliability of this testimony, arguing that it is
due more to Plato’s genius than Protagoras’ pen. No doubt, this is a
reasonable observation, because it would be too much to assume that
Plato simply incorporated a long extract from an opponent’s work
into his own text. Yet the reasonableness of this observation does not
justify the opposite – and equally radical – hypothesis that the myth is
simply Plato’s own invention and has nothing to do with Protagoras.
This assumption, too, conflicts with Plato’s way of working, since –
as we have seen in relation to the ‘man-measure’ thesis, for instance
– Plato always sets out from his opponents’ theses in order to criticize
them. The myth (like the speech that follows it) certainly offers some
information on Protagoras’ thought; to what extent, it is difficult to
determine.9
The myth retraces the key stages in the history of humankind, start-
ing from the well-known story of Prometheus, the beneficent daemon.
When the time had come to generate mortal animals (including
humans), the gods entrusted Prometheus with assigning each species
7
See also Denyer 2013: 167.
It is worth noting once more that, obviously, the laws will apply ‘so long as the city thinks [or:
8
adopts this law, nomizein]’: as a human product, no law can claim to have absolute and everlasting
validity.
9
For an analysis of these problems, see Bonazzi 2011 and Manuwald 2013.
10
For an in-depth investigation of these topics and further bibliographical references, see Farrar
1988: 81–99; Bonazzi 2004; Balla 2018: 91–101.
human beings are political and rational animals: they are political in the
sense that they cannot live in isolation, but need one another and are
forced to live together (‘political’ is to be understood etymologically
starting from the polis – the city, community, and state); and they are
rational because they have the means to engage with one another in
order to find possible solutions.
As we have seen, these solutions are only possible through the shar-
ing of collective values: in the myth, justice and shame are not a per-
manent possession of humankind, but rather predispositions that
must be actualized, which is to say that they must take the concrete
form of nomos, to ensure the development of a harmonious commu-
nity.11 In order to clarify Protagoras’ position, it is worth referring
again to the conceptual pair nomos/physis: for Protagoras, human physis,
unlike that of other animals, is not a given or something invariable;
rather, it can only be fully realized through nomos, which actualizes
the specific potential of humanity – a political potential.12 Whereas ani-
mals will always behave in the same way, humans can decide how to
comport themselves: whether to plunge back into the violence of the
animal world or to fashion a world of values for themselves. Nomos –
which is to say, the development of a political society – does not
stand in contrast to physis, but rather constitutes its ‘fulfilment’13 and
ensures the existence of individuals. Moreover, nomos is not only
what ensures survival, but also – and most importantly – the precondi-
tion for humans to fully express their potential. The individual – every
individual human being – is the product of society and attains fulfil-
ment in society: hence, his or her ultimate fulfilment depends on the
existence of a well-ordered society.
Again, this explains the social function of the sophist, a master of pol-
itical virtue: the sophist, just like the politician and any good citizen,
exercises a fundamental function for the community, insofar as he pro-
motes this collective awareness, thereby contributing to perfecting his
community, which can and must be improved.14 In other words, it is
11
Moreover, we should not overlook the fact that, while Zeus is the one who bestows these two
virtues on humanity, he does not concretely define what comprises them by making their content
explicit: in other words, justice is not a divine revelation, but something that humans must achieve
together. In this sense, the mythological framework does not conflict with the agnosticism of frag-
ment 80B4 D.-K. (= 31D10 L.-M.).
12
Later in the dialogue, Protagoras speaks of political virtue as human virtue (andros arete) tout
court (Prot. 325a); on this issue see also Beresford 2013.
13
Casertano 1971: 124.
14
Decleva Caizzi 1999: 319.
The thesis found in Hesiod is essentially the same as the one later
adopted by Protagoras, and the reference to this text is intended pre-
cisely to emphasize such a convergence: what is typical of human
beings, and what distinguishes them from animals, is their possession
of justice, which is to say their political capacity. Plato’s Protagoras
makes a brilliant attempt to reclaim the tradition, by highlighting the
continuity between his own theses and its precepts.17 However, this
attempt does not amount to an uncritical borrowing, because
Protagoras’ appropriation is also a deformation, and the differences
with respect to Hesiod are no less significant than the similarities.
According to Hesiod, Justice is divine: it is a deity, the daughter and
15
Pl. Prot. 325c5–326e5. See also Vegetti 1989: 51.
16
See Bonazzi 2011.
17
Sihvola 1989: 39–48.
protégée of Zeus, who intervenes when he sees that men fail to respect
her (Works and Days, 257, 265; Theogony, 901–3). All mythological
imagery aside, this means that justice exists regardless of human beings;
human justice is not independent of this order of divine values, but
must rather conform to it. The situation radically changes with
Protagoras: the innovation consists in his emphasis on the human
rather than the divine, and the relative, rather than absolute, character
of justice.18 There is no place for divinity: justice is something human –
it is not what brings us close to the gods but what fulfils our natural
potential. Protagoras’, then, is a radical humanism; and it is in the
light of this humanism that the way in which he modifies Hesiod’s pos-
ition becomes clear. Whereas in Hesiod the present age (the Age of
Iron) is characterized precisely by the flight of Justice and Shame
(Works and Days, 190–201), in Protagoras the association of the
human community, polis, and justice also suggests that some form of
justice and shame is always to be found – as long as there are human
beings. In turn, this strengthens the reasonable belief that acting in
view of justice is in everyone’s interests. Whereas Hesiod defines
human history in terms of decadence (since it is difficult to imitate
the gods), Protagoras presents it as the history of a possible progress.
The engagement with Hesiod, which constitutes the real subtext of
the myth, confirms the underlying aim of Plato’s presentation: to high-
light the great ambition of Protagoras, who had not so much sought to
engage in erudite debate with other wise men, as to present himself as
an heir to the Greek paideia, as one of the great masters or, rather, as the
great master of Greek culture, capable of imparting a teaching that drew
upon tradition but that could also meet the needs of the new times
(consider the observations already made on pp. 51–52).
That this was Protagoras’ aim becomes even clearer when we con-
sider another of the great topics discussed in fifth-century Athens: dem-
ocracy. Generally speaking, Protagorean humanism was well suited to
Athenian democracy, so much so that it has been argued that his theses
18
In all likelihood, another implicit polemical aim of Protagoras’ thesis is to be found in those
‘unwritten and unfailing ordinances (nomima) of the gods, which have life, not simply today and
yesterday, but for ever’ (Sophocles, Antigone, 453–5) – on which see e.g. De Romilly 2005: 27–48.
Nor can it be ruled out that, in emphasizing the importance of these unwritten laws, fifth-century
authors such as Sophocles were precisely targeting positivists such as Protagoras and Pericles: see
Bonazzi 2017: 112–24, in the footsteps of Ehrenberg 1957.
19
Kerferd 1981a: 144. A particularly important study on this topic is Farrar 1988. In order to
better evaluate Protagoras’ thesis – and, more generally, those of Athenian democracy – we must
distinguish between the theoretical level and that of concrete praxis. The reason for this is that
Athenian democracy has often been accused of being anything but a ‘democracy’, given that
roughly three-quarters of the population (women, slaves, and foreigners resident in Attica) were
barred from political participation. These are undeniable historical facts. Yet in no way do they
weaken the interest of theories such as those of Protagoras or Pericles, who promote an important
elaboration of the concept of democracy, understood as the government of the community. Ideas
of this sort still preserve all their importance today, regardless of the inconsistent way in which they
were applied in fifth-century Athens.
20
What proves crucial in this respect is the testimony of Thucydides, who, when discussing the
democratic ideology, repeatedly adopts the same perspective as Protagoras. The most clear-cut
stance is expressed in Athenagoras’ speech in Book 6: ‘democracy (demos) is the name for all, oli-
garchy for only a part’ (Thuc. 6.39). No less important is Pericles’ famous funerary speech for the
fallen of the first year of war, in which democracy is described as the government not of ‘the few’
but of ‘the many’ for ‘everyone’ (on this climax, see Musti 1995: 3–13).
must hold together the city’s interest and the individual’s, where the
former is the precondition for the latter.21 Protagoras, in other words,
emerges as a democratic political thinker: he is a political thinker
because he has shown that the social (or political – from polis)
dimension is fundamental; he is democratic insofar as he suggests
that political action is a collective and shared kind of action.
The new democratic political order is not imposed from above, but is
immanent and structured on two levels – those of competency and
excellence. As citizens, all people have a basic political competence,
which some people know how to make use of more than others
(the sophist here marks out a special area in which he can apply his
expertise); but all this invariably takes place through a mutual
engagement.22 Presenting democracy, the form of government for the
new times, as the heir and culmination of the Greek political tradition,
is certainly a brilliant achievement, which legitimizes Protagoras’
aspirations and ambitions. It is hardly a coincidence that the main
ancient reflections on democracy were often set in relation to
Protagoras’ ideas.23
In Protagoras, therefore, we find a first, vigorous defence of nomos,
an idea of which the fifth-century Greeks were particularly proud.
Protagoras was not completely isolated, as other authors and texts asso-
ciated with sophistry appear to have shared his positive evaluation of
law. The text closest to Protagoras’ views is arguably the so-called
Anonymous of Iamblichus, an anonymous treatise quoted at length
in the Neoplatonist Iamblichus’ Protrepticus. No less interesting are
some extracts from an oration, Against Aristogeiton, falsely attributed
to Demosthenes but more likely dating from the late fifth century. Its
author once again emphasizes the thesis that law and justice are what
allow humans to distinguish themselves from animals, by transcending
the world of violence: nature is disorderly and a source of injustice,
whereas the law ensures what is right, good, and beneficial (anon. On
the Laws, 15–20). Finally, Aristotle credits Lycophron with a ‘protec-
tionist’ conception of law (‘law is. . .the guarantor for each other of
21
For some interesting parallels, see Thuc. 2.40.2 and 2.60.2–4 (Pericles’ speech), and Hdt.
5.78.
22
Farrar 1988: 81–7.
23
In particular, in addition to the aforementioned passages by Thucydides, it is worth mention-
ing the famous comparison between the various forms of government found in Herodotus 3.80–2.
Finally, it is worth recalling that the seventh section of the Dissoi logoi also discussed democracy
and how best to safeguard it.
what is just’, 83.3 D.-K. = 38D3 L.-M.), which can probably be under-
stood as one of the first attestations of contractualist theories (of which
there is a compelling formulation in Glaucon’s speech at the beginning
of the second book of Plato’s Republic): the idea that laws guarantee
rights evidently implies a ‘disorderly’ conception of human nature.
Laws are designed to protect people, which is why they must be
respected: at least in this sense, the ‘protectionist’ and the contractual-
ist theories converge.24
Unfortunately, the dearth of information about these authors makes
it impossible to reconstruct in any detail the relation between them and
Protagoras, whose theses certainly attracted much attention in Athens
and Greece; but it is not unreasonable to hypothesize that they drew
upon his work in some way. Besides, the fact that Protagoras consti-
tuted an important point of reference in the debates on such matters
may also be inferred from the theses of sophists opposed to nomos,
whose arguments – as we shall now see – appear to have had precisely
the thinker of Abdera as their target.
The other great sophist, Gorgias, does not appear to have devoted any
special attention to justice and other political issues. Here it is possible
to register a substantial difference compared to Protagoras: whereas the
latter attributed the utmost importance to the teaching of political vir-
tue, the former apparently even went so far as to claim that he did not
teach virtue at all:
What I admire most of all in Gorgias, Socrates, is that you would never hear him prom-
ise this [sc. to be a teacher of virtue]. Instead he laughs at other people when he hears
them make this promise. No, he thinks that one should make people clever at speaking.
(82A21 D.-K. = 32D47 L.-M.)
24
More generally, on the possible circulation of contractualist theories in the fifth century, see
Guthrie 1971: 135–47 and Kahn 1981.
In this case, too, the mythological scheme (the reference to the super-
iority of gods over humans – but let us not forget that ultimately the
gods are equated with destiny) conceals a far from obvious idea,
which de facto constitutes a first justification of strength as the criterion
guiding human actions:
the form still conforms to traditional patterns, but the principle is now used to justify
the general law of the supremacy of the stronger, which, within the framework of the
mythological example and scheme, is geared towards the acknowledgement of a truth
that de facto operates in the world of human beings.26
25
Note the importance of this concept: see Chapter 3, p. 48.
26
Isnardi Parente 1969: 172.
27
Dodds 1959: 12–15.
truth. The key word in Callicles’ speech, his truth, is pleonexia, literally
the drive ‘to have more’; and it is this unsuppressible instinct to over-
power others, this will and desire to increase one’s own power, that is
the hallmark of all things – of humans, of animals, and indeed of the
whole universe (cf. Gorgias, 508a).
Callicles’ claims are certainly intriguing, as is shown for instance by
the fact that Friedrich Nietzsche drew upon them in some famous
pages of his Genealogy of Morals.28 However, it is easy to show that
they are weak theses. The main difficulty lies in the conflating of the
descriptive and prescriptive aspects of the concept of nomos, or law.
To clarify the problem, we can consider the modern distinction of
the term in the scientific field and in the legal one: scientific laws,
which describe the behaviour of a given object (be it a lion or a planet),
are one thing; the laws issued by legislators, which prescribe a certain
type of action (such as the paying of taxes or the avoidance of murder),
are another. In other words, to state how things are is different from
stating how they should be.
Callicles’ thesis ultimately boils down to an attempt to make these
two aspects coincide, but it falls short of its mark. Like a scientist, he
sets out from the descriptive aspect, yet, unlike the scientist, he also
assigns it axiological value. Thus, it is an objective fact that reality reg-
ulates itself according to power relations, but this is not understood as
something neutral, but rather as something good and just: to use
Callicles’ own words, there is a natural justice, and this is pleonexia,
which is to say the law of the strongest. But herein lies the problem.
The fact that reality axiologically regulates itself according to power rela-
tions means that the one who prevails is the strongest and hence the
most just. But given that Callicles’ world is dominated by those whom
he contemptuously refers to as the mass of weaklings, it follows that
the weak are actually the strong and hence the just: the democratic
nomos of equality is therefore just and beautiful, whereas the ‘strong’
(that is, those regarded as strong and best by Callicles, the aristocrats)
are de facto losers and weaklings.29 In other words, establishing strength
as the criterion of value implies an acceptance of reality, and not its
rejection, which is what Callicles opts for when he calls for the overthrow
of the tyranny of the weak. Significantly, later on in the dialogue,
28
See Dodds 1959: 387–91.
29
A similar reasoning, intended to show the weakness of the strong, is also to be found in the
Anonymus Iamblichi (89.6 D.-K. = 40.6 L.-M.).
30
Fussi 2006: 203–20.
31
Vegetti 2018: 198.
32
The most significant text, not least because of the numerous affinities it has with the sophists,
is the anonymous Constitution of the Athenians, with regard to which I will refer to Lapini 1997 and
Gray 2007; also very interesting is Xenophon, Memorabilia, 1.2.40–6.
33
For a reconstruction of the different hypotheses that have been put forward (to show either
the coherence or the incoherence between the two theses, and to favour one or the other), see
at least partly resolved if we consider the fact that the first thesis refers
to more specifically political issues, while the second one concerns indi-
vidual choices and hence ‘ethical’ problems (although we should not
forget that, prior to Aristotle, the distinction between ethics and politics
was not explicitly theorized). Consequently, it is worth focusing here on
the first thesis, while the importance of the second thesis – namely,
what its polemical target is – will become clear in the next chapter,
where we will be discussing happiness.
In arguing with Socrates, or rather in countering his defence of just-
ice, Thrasymachus claims of justice that it is ‘what is advantageous for
the person who is stronger’ (Republic, 338c = 85B6a D.-K. = 35D21
L.-M.), noting immediately afterwards that the stronger is to be under-
stood in the sense of ‘the established rule’ (arche): hence, justice ‘is the
advantage of the stronger’, that is of the established rule (Republic,
338d–e). This thesis has often been compared to Callicles’, but this
is a misleading comparison: while it is true that both of them pay
much attention to strength, Thrasymachus clearly understands strength
in the sense of power, and his emphasis on the theme of power allows
him to avoid the conflation between the descriptive and prescriptive
aspects that had proven so fatal to Callicles. Thrasymachus’ thesis is
merely descriptive, insofar as it does not pass any judgement but only
records a fact: namely that strength and power constitute a fundamental
aspect of human relations. Power is where the strength lies, and both
justice and law are subordinate to it: those who are in a position of
strength – that is, those who wield power – establish rules and laws,
the only purpose of which is to ensure that those in a position of
strength preserve their power and hence pursue their own advantage.34
Despite the apparent similarities, the theses of Callicles and
Thrasymachus differ in some crucial respects. First of all,
Thrasymachus’ thesis acquires a universal value that Callicles’ lacks: it
can be used to describe all the political relations that govern human
lives, without the need to draw any arbitrary distinctions between
good and bad governments. Furthermore – and this is the most
significant divergence – Thrasymachus and Callicles have two different
conceptions of justice. For Callicles, justice is something real, some-
thing that objectively exists and is embedded within reality ( physis): its
Macé 2009: 159–62 and, most recently, with further bibliography, Barney 2017, Wedgwood 2017,
and El Murr 2019.
34
Vegetti 1998: 240–7.
35
Vegetti 1998: 240–2.
36
This juxtaposition might seem even more surprising if we consider the fact that most scholars
tend to interpret Antiphon not just as a champion of physis but as the first spokesman for natural
justice. However, this reading is based on an erroneous reconstruction of the papyrus transmitting
87B44 D.-K. (=37D38b L.-M.), as may be inferred from the recent discovery of another part of
the same papyrus: see the edition of Bastianini and Caizzi 1989 (which I follow for the column
order) and the point made by Narcy 1996.
37
In my analysis of this fragment, I am partly drawing upon Bonazzi 2020, which I refer to for
further bibliographical references. Ostwald 1990 remains the most useful introduction.
If the laws provided some help for those who submit to such situations, and loss for
those who do not submit to them but who oppose them, [col. 6] it would not be useless
to obey the laws. But as it is, it is evident that, for those who submit to such situations, a
just outcome deriving from a law is not enough to provide them help. First, it permits
the sufferer to suffer and the doer to do. And just as, at that time [i.e. before the crime]
it did not prevent either the sufferer from suffering or the doer from doing, so too when
reference is made to it for the purpose of punishment, it is not more on the side of the
one who has suffered than on that of the one who has done. For it is necessary that
he persuade those people who will exact punishment that he has suffered, or that he
be capable of obtaining justice by deceit. But the doer too is permitted to deny
the same things [col. 7]. . .exactly as much of a defence is available to the defendant,
as the accusation that is available to the accuser, and persuasiveness is balanced for
the one who has suffered and for the one who has done.
(87B44B, 5.25–7.14 D.-K. = 37D38a, 5.25–7.14 L.-M.)
Let us keep to the example of stealing. Those who accept the injunction
not to steal will not steal, even in a situation in which stealing might ful-
fil a need (as in the case of those who are hungry and steal food). This is
one disadvantage; but, what is more, respecting the law does not pro-
tect one from the possibility of being in turn robbed by those who do
not respect this law. Consequently, one risks suffering an additional
drawback, which adds insult to injury, considering that the law courts
assign equal rights to the victim and to the guilty party, and that the
outcome of a trial depends more on the capacity to persuade than on
the ascertainment of the truth.
No less interesting are the analyses devoted to the practice of bearing
witness in relation to the problem of justice (87B44C D.-K. = 37D38c
L.-M.).38 People usually believe that it is unjust to commit injustices
against those who have not committed any injustice; and that it is
just to testify to the truth in a court case. But, according to
Antiphon, these two beliefs are mutually incompatible when a truthful
witness leads to the sentencing of a criminal who had not done that wit-
ness any wrong. Moreover, Antiphon observes, in doing so the witness
puts themself at risk, since he antagonizes someone – the criminal –
who will sooner or later seek revenge. All this brings out the limits of
nomos, which not only prevents people from fulfilling their primary
needs, but is even incapable of protecting those who yield to its rule.
It is as though physis and nomos are applied at two parallel levels: the
level of truth and that of opinion, the level of concreteness and that
of abstraction, without these levels ever really meeting. While through
his or her action the witness has upheld the nomos of an abstract
38
See Furley 1981.
community, he or she has caused, and has incurred, concrete and per-
sonal damages.
Antiphon’s analyses are important in several respects. First of all, it is
worth noting that they constitute an eloquent example of the sophists’
wide range of interests. It is generally assumed that the sophists had no
interest whatsoever in the research conducted by natural philosophers
and scientists, and that they only dealt with politics. Antiphon’s case
instead presents us with a more nuanced situation: the originality and
importance of the sophists rather lies in their ability to bring together
the two spheres, and to put scientific research to the service of political
aims. This is a matter of method as well as content: the adoption of a
detached and scientific, descriptive and non-judgemental attitude is
what lends shape to the ‘realistic’ approach, which constitutes one of
the most significant contributions offered by the sophists’ political
reflection.
It is crucial to take account of this ‘realistic’ and detached attitude if
we are to fully understand Antiphon’s position: the text clearly suggests
that Antiphon did not wish to present his own conception of justice in
opposition to conventional ones, as Callicles does in the Gorgias.
Rather, his primary aim is to closely engage with the theories of justice
that were then circulating in Athens and in the Greek world more
widely. In particular, the opening lines of the fragment show that the
sophist was particularly interested in addressing the positivist thesis,
which had been developed in particularly compelling terms by
Protagoras: the definition of justice as obedience to the laws of the com-
munity of which one is a citizen (87B44B, 1.6–11 D.-K. = 37D38a,
1.6–11 L.-M.) clearly captures the cornerstone of this thesis, namely
the identification of law with justice (what is just is what the laws
decree).
As we have just seen, the critique of positivism is common to many
sophists. However, Antiphon is the one who best grasps the underlying
crux of the matter by raising the vital question of the foundation of the
law (and hence of justice): if justice is a human convention, meaning
that it simply consists of the laws established by people, what authorita-
tiveness or foundation can it have? Protagoras’ answer, as we have seen,
is the idea of what is useful. The authority and legitimacy of nomos
depend on its capacity to ensure everyone’s interests: this is the reason
why nomos must be respected. Nevertheless, a concrete analysis of how
society works shows the flimsiness of Protagoras’ answer, which is an
abstract one, insofar as he refers to a (ideal) community of citizens
group), Antiphon analyses the life of humans in society to show that his
interests are individual and hence anti-social – in other words, they
concern the human as an individual and not as a citizen. This explains
the limits of Protagoras’ defence of nomos: the only reality is each indi-
vidual,39 whereas the laws of the polis, directed as they are at an abstract
citizen community, at most express an external and artificial consensus,
incapable of safeguarding the natural and hence real interests of
individuals.40
Such is the ‘truth’ that Antiphon reaches through an impartial ana-
lysis of reality, and it is a truth that affords few illusions as to the pos-
sibility of building a just and close-knit society. The dominant tone of
his analysis suggests an acknowledgement of the difficult condition of
humanity, caught between natural needs and social constrictions.41
However, this is not to say that it is impossible to live in a satisfying
way. After all, the human being has a most valuable means to make
up for the limits of politics and nomos, a means which unfortunately
he or she rarely resorts to: intelligence. As we shall see in the next chap-
ter, it is by using one’s intelligence that it is possible to find a balance
both within oneself and with others.
39
Hourcade 2001: 115.
40
Farrar 1988: 115–18. In passing, it goes without saying that these conclusions have anti-
democratic implications. Naturally, by this I do not mean to say that it is possible to infer from
the surviving fragments of Antiphon’s On Truth that he openly sided against democracy: on the
contrary, what makes Antiphon’s analyses so intriguing is his claim that he is not taking any
stand himself, but wishes the dynamics of natural and social reality to emerge on their own.
Still, it must be noted that his analyses of humans and society, his systematic emphasis on the
essentially anti-social character of human beings, and hence his privileging of the needs of the indi-
vidual over the collective rights of citizens constitute one of the most dangerous attacks on
Athenian democracy, which was founded on the identification of the common good with the inter-
ests of individuals. The ‘atomization’ of common interest into many private and mutually conflict-
ing interests amounts to the de facto impossibility of finding the kind of common good which, in
the eyes of Protagoras and Pericles, was the distinguishing trait of democracy.
41
Decleva Caizzi 1999: 327.
42
See H. Patzer 1974. Critias’ aims are quite clear: an unrelenting struggle against democracy,
in an attempt to import into Athens the values of the oligarchic ideology of Sparta. On this, see
Bultrighini 1999 and Iannucci 2002.
43
See Chapter 6, p. 119.
44
Ostwald 1986: 282.
Another strongly debated topic was equality. Once again, the political
context – the ups and downs of Athenian democracy – helps us to
understand the interest in this issue: two of the catchwords of the
democratic regime, those which best represented this form of govern-
ment, were isegoria and isonomia, which is to say everyone’s right to
express themselves and everyone’s equality before the law (notwith-
standing the fact that ‘everyone’ excluded a considerable section of
society47). Moreover, the importance of the topic is confirmed by the
fact that discussions about equality extended to broader fields, touching
upon social, racial, and economic questions.48 Naturally, as in the case
of justice, the topic was addressed by many different authors, and not
just sophists, but the latter’s contribution was often highly original
45
Untersteiner 1954: 278–83.
46
Decleva Caizzi 1985: 203–8, has hypothesized that Socrates’ thesis specifically has Antiphon
as its polemical target.
47
See p. 73, n. 19.
48
Guthrie 1971: 148–63.
49
Decleva Caizzi 1986b. Antiphon’s polemic becomes even more significant if, as seems likely,
the sophist and the oligarchical rhetor were one and the same person: in this case, Antiphon would
have criticized slavery not on humanitarian grounds, but in order to once again highlight the limits
‘of the lame egalitarianism of the democratic polis’ (Canfora 2001: 215).
50
Isnardi Parente 1977: 32–3.
at length the trophies won from the Medes, telling them that ‘trophies won from the
barbarians demand hymns, those from the Greeks dirges’.
(82A1 D.-K. = 32D27 and R19 L.-M.)
51
Bonazzi 2008: 66–8.
52
Guthrie 1971: 160.
53
Nietzsche 1964: 249.
‘value’ derives from their natural endowments, which they need to cul-
tivate by following their ancestors’ example,1 in the fifth century, with
the rise of democracy, the belief took root that anyone could attain vir-
tue. This made the problem of education and teaching an even more
pressing one. Everyone could become ‘virtuous’, which is to say
develop qualities that would propel them to the summit of the commu-
nity; the problem, then, was to learn how to attain virtue. And this is
precisely what the sophists promised to teach, starting from
Protagoras, who claimed that what people could learn from him was
‘good deliberation about household matters, to know how to manage
one’s own household in the best way possible, and about those of the
city, so as to be most capable of acting and speaking in the city’s inter-
ests’ (Protagoras, 318b = 80A5 D.-K. = 31D37 L.-M.). In other words,
Protagoras promised to teach people virtue (Protagoras, 319b; see also
349a and Meno, 91a). Plato reports that Gorgias instead mocked
those who promised to teach others virtue (Meno, 95b = 82A21
D.-K. = 32D47 L.-M., quoted above, p. 75). Yet the purpose of his
teaching was much the same (see e.g. Plato, Gorgias, 452d–e).2 No
less significantly, even one of the Dissoi logoi, the sixth, is entirely
devoted to refuting the thesis that ‘wisdom and virtue can neither be
taught nor learned’ (90.6.1 D.-K. = 40.6.1 L.-M.). Once again, then,
the sophists prove capable of grasping and addressing the most import-
ant problems of the life of the city, eliciting opposite reactions – enthu-
siasm or aversion – through their bold claims.
Generally speaking, a defining feature of the sophists’ reflection is
the affirmation of the priority of the individual over the community.
The sources we have all appear to go in this direction, with one signifi-
cant exception: Protagoras. Unlike the other sophists, Protagoras seems
to be striving to reconcile the interests of the individual with those of
the public sphere, by emphasizing the eminently political dimension
of human nature. In this he once again shows significant affinities
with the democratic ideology of Pericles, and I will therefore refer
back to the previous chapter for a more detailed exposition of his
ideas. In all other cases, what makes the sophists’ analyses interesting
1
See, for example, Theognis, lines 27 ff.; Pindar, Olympian Odes, 2.86, 9.100, 10.20.
2
Also revealing, in this respect, is an epigram from Olympia that was written in his honour: ‘No
mortal ever invented a finer art than Gorgias / To exercise the soul in competition of excellence. /
And it is of him that, in Apollo’s hollows, the statue is dedicated, / A paradigm not of wealth, but of
the piety of his character’ (82A8 D.-K. = 32P34b L.-M.).
The immoralists
3
See Bett 2002.
4
A detailed overview of these testimonies may be found in De Romilly 1988: 194–231; see also
Chapter 1, pp. 8–9.
5
Ostwald 1986: 229–50.
6
See also Trabattoni 2000: 19–21.
7
In the Gorgias, a character who is presented in much the same light as Meno is Polus of
Acragas, historically another pupil of Gorgias and the author of a treatise on rhetoric. See, for
instance, Nails 2002: 252.
8
See Chapter 4, pp. 77–80.
9
Hobbs 2000: 137–74.
10
See Kerferd 1981a: 123.
marketplace and advertised that he was able to treat grief-stricken people by means of
his speeches. And he inquired into the causes and thereby consoled those people who
were suffering. But then, considering that this art was beneath him, he turned to rhet-
oric.
(87A6 D.-K. = 37P10 L.-M.)11
At first sight, these bitter descriptions of human life might seem like yet
another variation on the classic theme of human unhappiness, which
Antiphon presents through brilliant and evocative images. Upon closer
inspection, however, some original insights emerge. In particular, it is
worth noting that the undeniable pessimism of the fragments is con-
stantly associated with the theme of intelligence: according to
Antiphon, the true cause of distress, in general, is not the wretchedness
of the human condition, but the poor use to which people put their intel-
ligence, making things even more difficult instead of solving their pro-
blems.12 Life is complicated and the choices we have to make – when
it comes to things such as marriages, children, money, and friendship
(87B49, 53–8 D.-K. = 37D57, 52–3, 59, 47a–b, 54–5 L.-M.) – are diffi-
cult ones. Unfortunately, instead of using their intelligence to deal with
these thorny problems, humans often allow themselves to be driven by
impulses and passions to commit acts they will soon regret, but which
11
Cf. also 87A6 D.-K. (= 37P9 L.-M.): ‘When Antiphon had attained a great degree of per-
suasive power and was nicknamed “Nestor” because he could succeed in persuading people
when he spoke about anything, he announced that he would give lectures capable of eliminating
pain, as he supposed that no one could name to him a grief so terrible that he could not banish
it from that man’s thought.’
12
Gagarin 2002: 95.
cannot be erased, since ‘it is not possible to retract one’s life like a move
in checkers’ (87B52 D.-K. = 37D48 L.-M.); and ‘the time that they are
neglecting is gone’ (87B53a D.-K. = 37D53 L.-M.).
What is most striking about Antiphon’s distress is the lack of any
moralistic overtones and the lucid realism of his observations. Take
the example of wealth, a conventional good whose importance
Antiphon does not wish to dispute, and which constitutes a recurrent
theme in surviving testimonies (87A3, B53–4 D.-K. = 37D83, 52, 59
L.-M.).13 It is difficult to deny the importance of wealth, and this
view had been memorably expressed by Aristodemus, one of the
seven wise men: ‘Surely no witless word was this of the Spartan, I
deem, “Wealth is the worth of a man (chremat’aner); a poverty void of
esteem”’ (Alceus, fr. 49 Lobel-Page = D.L. 1.31). Whether we like it
or not, wealth is not something that can be ignored: to reject it com-
pletely, as though it served no purpose, is to adopt a fruitless position
that is of little use in everyday life. Instead, we should address various
concrete questions: if wealth marks the social value of a person, we
should also be concerned to ensure that it is acquired in an honest
and correct way; in turn, the problem of the acquisition of wealth
requires us to more deeply investigate its actual management, preserva-
tion, increase, circulation, and so on – and these spawned the first ‘eco-
nomic’ reflections. These are only some of the problems that Antiphon
dealt with, favouring the ‘mercantilistic’ view – a minority view at the
time – according to which the circulation of money was a legitimate
way to gain wealth, in opposition both to the traditional practice of saving
money and to those philosophers who merely criticized wealth, without
making any significant contributions to the debate (Xenophon informs
us of a polemic of Antiphon against Socrates on the matter, although it
is difficult to tell just how reliable this testimony is from a historical per-
spective14). Wealth was a concrete problem for which Antiphon suggests
concrete solutions, capable of making life’ more free and pleasant’
(Xenophon, Memorabilia, 1.6 = 87A3.3 D.-K. = 37D83.3 L.-M.). It is
easy to imagine that he may have formulated similar arguments concern-
ing other everyday problems, from marriage to work and friendship.
13
Predictably, given the importance of the problem for an expanding society such as
fifth-century Athens, Antiphon was not the only sophist to deal with the issue of wealth: see
Gorgias 82B20 D.-K. (= 32D40 L.-M.), Prodicus 84B8–9 D.-K. (=34R4 andP6 L.-M.), and
Anon. Iambl. 89.7.1 and 7.8 (40.7.1 and 8 L.-M.); see too Soverini 1998: 45–65 and 81–9;
Demont 1993; Bonazzi 2009a: 28–31 and 2016; Gavray 2016.
14
See Bonazzi 2009a.
The outcome of all this is concord, the inner balance that can be cre-
ated between the different driving forces of reason and desire that
guide human actions (see, for example, 87B44a D.-K. = 37R7 L.-M.,
whose attribution to Antiphon, however, is uncertain). Moreover, this
concord is the precondition for the enjoyment of genuine pleasure
(or at any rate for the avoidance of pain): Antiphon’s pessimism does
not rule hedonism out, but rather leads to it.16
Just as in On Truth, in On Concord Antiphon’s privileged object of
reflection would appear to be the single individual, who is different
from the ‘citizen’ of the polis or from the abstract ‘human being’ of
which philosophers all too often speak. Ultimately, the argument
expounded in On Concord seems to offer a positive counterpart to the
analyses of On Truth: Antiphon offers what we might describe as an eth-
ical solution to political problems, which is consistent with his emphasis
on the priority of the individual over the community (without ever for-
getting, however, that the distinction between ethics and politics had
not yet been systematized in the sophists’ day). As we have seen, On
15
Bonazzi 2006b.
16
Capra 1997: 298–303.
Truth had dispelled the illusion that nomos can solve the problems
which physis poses to individuals; for its part, On Concord shows that
only the individual can find a solution to their problems, to the extent
that they succeeds in striking a balance with themselves and with their
own needs and desires. In other words, by contrast to the positive
assessment of the social and collective dimension of human experience,
Antiphon focuses on the limits of coexistence and finds a way out, not
in the existence of shared rules, but in the individual’s capacity to face
life’s concrete problems in such a way as to derive the greatest benefit
and enjoyment. In opposition to the exterior consensus of nomos,
Antiphon thus invokes inner concord, which does not require any
legal approval in order to remain in force and which each person can
establish within him- or herself, by making intelligence prevail over
the destructive impulses of the passions. Through moderation and tem-
perance it is possible to restore the right balance with ourselves and
with the things that surround us: it is not the laws that ensure security
and happiness, but intelligence and the use that people make of it.17
Undoubtedly, Antiphon’s fragments contain none of the sort of revo-
lutionary truths expounded by those figures who sought to overthrow
the whole system of values of their community (let us think of
Callicles); but nor do they simply pander to widespread prejudices of
the sort that guide many people’s actions. Rather, we might speak
here of an intention to provoke, designed to drive people to become
17
Although it chiefly applies to ethical issues, it cannot be ruled out that this ‘morality of con-
cord’ also had more explicitly political consequences (Bonazzi 2006a). ‘Concord’ is one of the
central terms in the heated ideological and political debate that raged in the years of the
Peloponnesian War, so much so that it became one of the key terms that moderates and oligarchs
invoked against democratic nomos. Likewise, for Antiphon the concept of ‘concord’ does not
amount to a generic call to collective reconciliation, but rather serves to trace the profile of true
wise men, who alone ought to govern, since ‘nothing is worse for human beings than lack of
rules (anarchias)’ (87B61 D.-K. = 37D63 L.-M.). Concord, then, emerges as the capacity to
take care of oneself and others by curbing violent and irrational impulses. Obviously, a thesis of
this sort potentially applies to all people, but it is easy to see how the concept could be exploited
by the oligarchic faction as a powerful way to criticize the alleged freedom of the democrats:
according to oligarchic propaganda – as illustrated by the anonymous author of the Constitution
of the Athenians – democracy is a system which justifies the unruliness of the masses, which allows
the masses to yearn for and achieve more and more, thereby laying the ground for the outbreak of
increasingly violent conflicts. When set in its context, this praise of self-control and privileging
of intelligence over law lose much of their apparently generic quality and prove closely reminiscent
of the typically aristocratic themes that characterize pro-Spartan polemics. Regrettably, the limited
number of surviving fragments of On Concord do not allow us to further investigate this hypothesis.
Be that as it may, the fact that considerations of this sort could be exploited for political and espe-
cially anti-democratic purposes is confirmed by the theses of another opponent of (democratic)
nomos, the oligarch Critias: see e.g. H. Patzer 1974 and Bonazzi 2018: 33–41.
more aware of what they are and of what they do, so as to assign priority
to what truly matters: the exercising of one’s own intelligence, since
‘thought (gnome) leads the body, for all humans, toward health and dis-
ease and toward everything else’ (87B2 D.-K. = 37D1b L.-M.). When
it comes to the issue of happiness, therefore, Antiphon once again
proves himself to be a subtle thinker who exemplifies what is arguably
the most distinctive and interesting aspect of sophistry, namely its cap-
acity to rethink the foundations and assumptions of the Greek tradition,
through a subtle dialectic of correction and transformation.
18
Xenophon, Memorabilia, 2.1.21–34 (= 84B2 D.-K. = 34D21 L.-M.). Recently, Dorion 2008
has denied that the passage from Xenophon is a reliable testimony on Prodicus, arguing that the
apologue is used to investigate ethical issues addressed by Xenophon’s Socrates. This is an intri-
guing hypothesis, which highlights some interesting affinities between Socrates and Prodicus, but
which fails in its attempt to disprove Prodicus’ authorship. Certainly, this text is not to be taken as
a word-by-word quotation (as suggested instead by Sansone 2004, criticized by Gray 2006);
rather, in the light of the introductory expressions used by Xenophon, it is more reasonable to
assume that what we have is a summary of Prodicus’ argument: see now Mayhew 2011: 201–21.
19
Momigliano 1930: 102–3. The frequency of ethical terms among Prodicus’ synonyms has
also been noted by many other scholars: see esp. De Romilly 1986, Dumont 1986, Tordesillas
2004, and Wolfsdorf 2008a. However, in many cases it is difficult to establish whether we are deal-
ing with reliable testimonies (as in the case of 84A19 D.-K. = 34D6a L.-M.) or mere parodies (as
is probably the case with 84A15 D.-K. = 34D22 and 23–5 L.-M.). A testimony by Galen (84B4
D.-K. = 34D9 L.-M.), concerning phlegma (inflammation), shows that Prodicus was not exclu-
sively interested in ethical terms.
sophists on the one hand and sophists open to tradition on the other.
We have already noted how immoralism resulted more from a negative
interpretation of their views by their detractors (Aristophanes, Plato,
and others) than a position which was actually upheld by the sophists.
It is a matter now of reassessing Prodicus’ and Hippias’ theses with
respect to traditional knowledge and values, and of verifying that
some apparent banalities20 conceal interesting insights, which can be
fruitfully compared with what has been noted with regard to other
sophists. The freedom and heterogeneity of the sophists does not
exclude a range of common interests and ideas.
Given the almost complete absence of any information on Hippias’
discourse, we should focus our attention on Prodicus. Undoubtedly,
his discourse complied with the civic ideology that assigned glory to
those who had committed themselves to the public good, resisting
the temptation of immediate gratification (84B2.28 D.-K. =
34D21.28 L.-M.). Still, we must be careful to avoid drawing a clear-cut
contrast between pleasure and virtue, as though these were two incom-
patible concepts. Prodicus’ aim is not to teach contempt for pleasure
and encourage the virtues of toil and hard work, but rather to show
that true pleasure, the kind of enjoyment which can accompany a per-
son throughout their life, often stands in opposition to immediate grati-
fication, which can soon turn into pain and affliction. It is not a matter,
then, of drawing a contrast between pleasure and hard work, but of
knowing what is truly good and hence what really brings pleasure
and happiness:
A life entirely focused on eating before being hungry, on sleeping. . .because one has
nothing to do, on pursuing sexual enjoyment without feeling any sexual urge or need
is certainly not a pleasant life. What Virtue champions, then, is not the negation or con-
demnation of pleasure: it is not a matter of seeking out pleasures in themselves. . .but,
on the contrary, of only indulging in them when this means meeting the vital needs of
man, for only then do they truly bring enjoyment.21
20
Guthrie 1971: 277–8.
21
Casertano 2004: 78. Some very interesting observations on this hedonistic perspective may
be found in Capra 1997: 289–98.
sacrifice ourselves for the public good, but shows that, ultimately, a life
of commitment will prove more enjoyable and convenient; and it is for
this reason, on account of its usefulness, that it is preferable.22 No
doubt, in his exhortations Prodicus does not oppose traditional morality,
but rather draws upon many of its ideas (cf. Hesiod, Works and Days,
286–97; Simonides, fr. 386 Page). But this does not imply a clear
break with respect to the other sophists: Prodicus’ emphasis on personal
advantage and the centrality of the individual, just like his interest in the
issue of pleasure, is undoubtedly reminiscent of Antiphon.23 In other
words, like Antiphon, Prodicus would appear to adopt a nuanced stance
with respect to traditional morality, which is not rejected (he does not
deny the importance of honour, just as Antiphon does not deny the
importance of wealth) but is rather reassessed according to a different
hierarchy of values (where the individual comes before the community).
To further clarify the complexity of Prodicus’ approach to tradition,
we should not overlook the self-promotional tone of his discourse: the
purpose of a discourse, of a public epideixis, is not simply to convey an
argument but to advertise a teacher.24 Significantly, the distinctive fea-
ture of the discourse, as it has reached us, is not so much the fact that
Heracles chooses the path of virtue as the fact that he does so after
debating two opposing theses.25 In such a way, the discourse implicitly
yet quite clearly opposes the traditional conception of education, which
was often seen as consisting in the passive learning of precepts and
norms of conduct: on the contrary, true education must prepare us
for making distinctions and assessments. This, in turn, highlights the
central importance of the teacher, who alone can teach us how to rea-
son and argue correctly. Heracles was an ambiguous figure, known for
having rid the world of monsters (Pindar, Nemean 3) but also for yield-
ing to anger, desire, and pleasure (consider, for instance, Euripides’
Alcestis, Sophocles’ Women of Trachis, and Aristophanes’ Frogs). This
makes him the ideal pupil for a sophist, and Prodicus can portray
22
In this respect, it has been observed that the criterion of usefulness appears to have played a
part even in the case of linguistic distinctions: in other words, it is reasonable to suggest that the
primary aim of the distinction drawn between positive and negative terms was to identify what
course of action one ought to follow. See Dumont 1986 and Tordesillas 2004: 61–3.
Notwithstanding the reservations expressed in n. 19 above, this is an intriguing hypothesis.
23
Significantly, Prodicus would appear to share Antiphon’s dualist psychology, if De Romilly
1986: 6 is correct in noting that his linguistic distinctions are always based on a contrast between
terms associated with the spheres of irrationality and rationality.
24
See the crucial analysis provided by Morgan 2000: 106–15.
25
Dorion 2009b: 536 n. 34.
himself as the perfect teacher, whose merit lies not in his conformity to
traditional values (something expected in public performance), but in
his capacity to teach one how to put forward reasons for each matter
at issue and adequately assess them. Once again, what distinguishes
the sophists’ discourse is its dynamic relation with tradition, which
combines the borrowing of certain ideas and a degree of conformity
(Heracles ultimately chooses virtue) with certain changes. This is all
the more true given that the tale of Heracles at the crossroads was
invented by Prodicus himself, who thereby adapted myth to suit his
own educational purposes.26
The same kind of tension is also to be found in Hippias’ Trojan
Discourse (86B5 D.-K. = 36D5 L.-M.), where the protagonist’s choice
is even more indicative of the provocative character of the sophists’
message. Whereas Heracles remained an ambiguous figure,
Neoptolemus was an infamous one, insofar as during the siege of
Troy he had killed the elderly Priam, who had taken refuge at the
altar of Zeus. The dramatic context of Hippias’ speech is therefore highly
revealing, because it is precisely after the seizing of Troy, which is to say
just after Neoptolemus’ terrible crime, that Nestor addresses words of
advice to the young man. Neoptolemus’ case is even more problematic
than that of Heracles, but it is also better suited to the world of the
second half of the fifth century, a world that was experiencing a dramatic
war and crisis; and Hippias, like a new Nestor capable not only of edu-
cating the young but of leading them to success, can present himself as
an ideal master for these tumultuous times.27 Like Prodicus, he applies a
subtle strategy of appropriation of tradition and its values: he does not
criticize its assumptions or principles, but exploits them for his own pur-
poses. If we think of the way in which Protagoras and Gorgias had
engaged with poetic lore (see Chapter 3), here too the divergence from
the other sophists turns out to be less marked than what at first appeared
to be the case. All sophists, each in his own way, present themselves as
masters of virtue; and this is why Plato criticized them so harshly, in
the belief that their teaching, far from leading one to the true good,
only exacerbated the defects of traditional morality.
26
Kuntz 1993.
27
In this respect, it is interesting to note that, in the Protagoras, Plato parodies Hippias in the
figure of Nestor: see Brancacci 2004. Nestor is certainly a paradigmatic figure, also apparently
evoked by Gorgias (82B14 D.-K. = 32D52 L.-M.) and Antiphon (87A6 D.-K. = 37P9 L.-M.).
1
Muir 1985:193–5.
2
Kahn 1997: 250–3.
3
In the ancient world, the term ‘atheist’ did not only describe someone who denies the exist-
ence of the gods, but also someone who scorns the gods or has been abandoned by them (see
Winiarczyk 1990). In the following pages, the term will mostly be used in its modern sense. In
general on ancient atheism, see now Sedley 2013, Whitmarsh 2015, and Gourinat 2019.
4
Usually these lists included the names of Prodicus, Diagoras, Critias, Theodore of Cyrene,
Euhemerus of Messene, and – with some reservations – Protagoras: see Gigon 1985: 423.
explains the violent reactions to their teachings in Athens. Given the free-
dom with which the problem of the divine was investigated from the most
ancient times, one might have expected to find a certain degree of toler-
ance towards debates and criticism even in the fifth century.5 Instead,
the opposite was the case, especially in the second half of the century,
when war raged between Athens and Sparta. While Dodds may have
gone too far in describing this as a period of resurgent irrationalism,
excesses occurred in both directions.6 Probably in 437 BC, Diopeithes’
decree was issued to denounce those who did not believe in the existence
of the gods or spoke on celestial matters (ta meteora).7 On the opposite side
of the spectrum, we know that, a few years later, a club of kakodaimonists
(‘companions of the evil daemon’) was founded, whose members would
meet to enjoy a banquet on what were regarded as unlucky days. Finally,
we have the case of the Hermocopids (those who smashed the Hermes sta-
tues in Athenian streets) and the profanation of the Mysteries in 415 BC.
Within this context, it appears that many representatives of the new cul-
ture were brought to trial.8 Then, of course, we have the most famous
trial of all: we should not forget that one of the two charges in the trial
which led to Socrates’ death was that the philosopher did not respect
the traditional gods and had introduced new deities. The sophists appear
to have been both a symptom and a cause of this climate of unrest.9 Much
of their fame, and of the hatred they attracted, depends precisely on their
provocations in this field.
Protagoras’ agnosticism
5
Betegh 2006: 625.
6
Dodds 1951: 188–95.
7
The authenticity of this decree has been repeatedly disputed; a recent defence of its historicity
is in Whitmarsh 2015: 117–19.
8
Trials have been recorded for Anaxagoras, Diagoras, Protagoras, Prodicus, Euripides,
Phidias, and Aspasia. However, in particular with regard to Protagoras and Prodicus, it seems
that the sources are not always reliable: see the overview provided by Ostwald 1986: 528–36,
and Bonazzi 2018: 43–7.
9
Burkert 1985a: 311–17.
10
At present, it is still difficult to establish the relation between this text and the Truth. What is
more interesting to note is that the sources also credit Protagoras with a treatise On What Is in
Hades (80A1 D.-K. = 31D1 L.-M.), which would appear to confirm his interest in the topic.
About the gods I am able to know neither that they exist nor that they do not exist nor of
what kind they are in form: for many things prevent me for knowing this, its obscurity
and the brevity of man’s life. (80B4 D.-K. = 31D10 L.-M.)11
For a recent and very detailed analysis of this fragment, see Corradi 2017 with further
bibliography.
11
On the text, see Di Benedetto 2001.
12
On Protagoras and the Magi, see Gigon 1985: 427–30.
13
See Corradi 2012: 31–43.
14
Barnes 1979: ii.449–50.
15
Drozdek 2005: 41.
16
See Kerferd 1981a: 165–9.
17
See Di Benedetto 2001.
18
Kahn 1973: 302.
19
Barnes 1979: ii.450.
20
Mansfeld 1981: 41–2.
21
It is interesting to note that a statement similar to Protagoras’ has been attributed to
Parmenides’ pupil Melissus, who was a polemical target of the sophists: ‘He said that we ought
not to make any statements about the gods, for it was impossible to have knowledge of them’
(D.L. 9.24).
22
Sassi 2013; see also Corradi 2017: 456–61. Alternatively, Protagoras may have been referring
to the repeated transformations of the gods in Greek myths: this too militated against the possibil-
ity of saying anything definite about their form (Drozdek 2005: 42).
23
On the relation between this passage from Herodotus and Protagoras, see Burkert 1985b,
who has emphasized the dependence of the former on the latter, and the words of caution voiced
by Sassi 2013.
24
Mansfeld 1981: 43.
discussed not the problem of the gods in itself, but rather the issue of
what they represent for human beings, thereby inaugurating an
anthropological and sociological approach that considers religion in
terms of its function for human civilization and society.25 This is no
doubt a noteworthy suggestion. What is less convincing is the way in
which this hypothesis has been developed. From Jaeger onwards, scho-
lars have believed that, while leaving the problem of the actual existence
of the gods open, Protagoras celebrated their importance for human
civilization.26 Given the silence of fragment B4, this hypothesis is
based on the myth that Protagoras relates in the dialogue named after
him. Yet, even leaving aside the problem of the Protagorean origin of
this page of Plato’s (a far from trivial problem27), what may be inferred
from the myth is in fact the very opposite. In the myth, Protagoras
acknowledges the importance of belief in the gods as something specif-
ically and universally human; but the very moment that he acknowl-
edges the presence of the religious dimension, he de facto limits its
importance by implying that this belief (or fear) is not enough to pro-
vide a foundation for human society. What ensures that people can
live together in cities is rather politics, which is the object of the soph-
ists’ teaching. Protagoras’ agnosticism is therefore instrumental for his
radical humanism.28
25
Jaeger 1947: 176. See also Corradi 2012: 169–70, on the basis of Plato, Cratylus, 400d–401a.
26
In addition to Jaeger, consider for instance Schiappa 1991, pp. 141–148 or, more recently,
Drozdek 2005.
27
See Bonazzi 2011.
28
As further confirmation of this humanism, one might recall the ideas on crime and punish-
ment that Plato puts into Protagoras’ mouth in the dialogue named after him (Prot. 323c–324d;
however, it is difficult to establish whether these are ideas that may historically be traced back
to Protagoras: see Saunders 1981). The underlying thesis – that a just punishment must not be
a reprisal, but must rather serve as a means of correction and deterrent – stands out insofar as
it aims to investigate the problem of injustice and evil among human beings without invoking,
or confiding in, any corrective action on the gods’ part.
perspective, the gods are a human product, insofar as people have cho-
sen to regard as ‘divine’ that which has proven useful to their lives: at
first, things such as the sun and moon, rivers and fruits; later, ‘as
human wit entered into competition with nature’,29 this was also
extended to those people who had distinguished themselves with inven-
tions that were particularly useful for the well-being of humanity.30
According to Henrichs’ reconstruction, a transition was essentially
made from an impersonal stage, in which beneficial objects were deified
(e.g. bread or wine), to a personal stage, in which the object of deifica-
tion were those people to whom the invention could be attributed, or
who at any rate had taught others how to correctly employ useful things
(as in the case of Demeter and Dionysus31). The gods and religion,
then, are merely a human product resulting from humans’ attempt to
make sense of the environment in which they live.32 Undoubtedly,
the boldness of these ideas, which ‘make the gods come down from
their pedestal’;33 the parallel reassessment of the human world, which
is capable of making sense of reality; and the emphasis on usefulness
as the distinguishing criterion to understand and guide one’s actions
make this theory a typical testimony to the sophists’ way of reasoning.
Not unlike in Protagoras’ case, the limited number of testimonies we
have prevents us from precisely reconstructing the context of Prodicus’
theories on the matter. It cannot be ruled out that somehow – and,
once again, as in Protagoras’ case – this discussion concerning the
gods constituted a prelude to an analysis of human civilization.34 Yet,
as far as we can infer from a passage by Themistius (a rhetor from
the age of Imperial Rome: 84B5 D.-K. = 34D17 L.-M.), Prodicus
would appear to have stressed the importance of agriculture rather
than politics, as Protagoras did in the Platonic dialogue. It might be
hypothesized, therefore, that
29
Henrichs 1975: 111.
30
Guthrie 1971: 238–42 voiced some reservations with regard to the two-phase reconstruction
of Prodicus’ theory (which entails first the deification of inanimate objects and then that of particu-
larly distinguished human beings), by arguing that the available sources allow us to attribute to
Prodicus only the deification of inanimate objects and not of humans as well (the same view is
taken by Gomperz 1912: 113 n. 251). However, an oft-neglected testimony, a papyrus fragment
from a treatise On Piety by the Epicurean Philodemus (PHerc. 1428 = 84B5 D.-K. = 34D15
L.-M.), has made it possible to cast these reservations aside and to attribute the whole theory to
Prodicus: see Henrichs 1975: 112–23; Mayhew 2011: 180–3.
31
See Untersteiner 1947.
32
Henrichs 1975: 112.
33
Dorion 2009a: 348.
34
Nestle 1936.
35
Soverini 1998: 105. Further developing his hypothesis, Nestle 1936 had set these doctrines in
relation to the famous testimony on Heracles’ choice (see Chapter 5, pp. 106–110): indeed, this
argument was featured in a text entitled Horai (84B1 D.-K. = 34D19 L.-M.), and it may reasonably
be assumed that the term referred to the seasons, and therefore that Prodicus celebrated Heracles as
a symbol of the world of farmers as well. According to this view, then, the Horai provided a praise of
agriculture, a theory on the origin of religion connected to agriculture, and an exhortation to virtue
(something necessary for agricultural life), embodied by the figure of Heracles at the crossroads.
This hypothesis – an intriguing one, yet difficult to prove – may find some confirmation in the
testimonies from Aristophanes (Clouds, 360–2, and Birds, 690–2 = 84A5 D.-K. = Dram. T22 L.-M.)
and Timon (fr. 18 Di Marco). These present Prodicus as a meteorosophist, an expert on celestial matters:
the reference here would not be to cosmological phenomena, but to atmospheric ones such as rain and
wind, which Prodicus claimed to know much about (see Soverini 1998: 90–114). However, it is also
worth noting that, while certainly important, the connection with agriculture did not exhaust the rich-
ness of the apologue on Heracles, which could equally well apply to the world of the polis – indeed, it
especially referred to this.
36
Muir 1985: 204. Besides, Antiphon too is credited with a treatise On Agriculture (87B118
D.-K., not in L.-M.), and often the sophists are regarded as experts on celestial matters (meteora;
see preceding footnote): see e.g. Protagoras 80A11 D.-K. = Dram. T18a and Gorgias 82A17 =
32P35 L.-M.
37
Henrichs 1976; Willink 1983; Mayhew 2011.
38
See Kerferd 1981a: 171.
39
Dihle 1977 is the main champion of this new attribution, which has attracted much consen-
sus: see e.g. Scodel 1980: 124; Ostwald 1986: 281; Kahn 1997. However, we also find some cham-
pions of the Critias attribution: see e.g. Centanni 1997: 144–59 (very useful on the other tragedies
possibly written by Critias); Bultrighini 1999: 213–50; Scholten 2003: 238–57 and Alvoni 2017.
character – and not a great one either, given the sinister reputation sur-
rounding Sisyphus, the deceiver par excellence.40 In other words, this
long fragment counts as a document that attests to the ideas circulating
at the time rather than to any independent theory.41
The fragment reconstructs the history of humanity by dividing it into
three crucial stages: (1) in its first stage, humankind’s life was dis-
orderly and bestial, dominated as it was by brute force (lines 1–4);
(2) to remedy the situation, human beings established laws ensuring
justice and peace, and yet these laws only partially attained the result
that was sought after: while they regulated public actions, underhanded
acts of violence continued (5–11); (3) someone, ‘a man who was
shrewd and wise in his planning’ (12), then invented the gods: immor-
tal, omniscient, and omnipotent beings capable of reading human
beings’ thoughts and of acting upon this knowledge – and fear of the
gods finally made city life possible (11–42). What we have here is a
first attestation of the theory of religion as an instrumentum regni, a the-
ory destined to enjoy great popularity, first in Rome and then in the
modern world.
Even though it is impossible to establish any direct links, it is
interesting to note that this passage stands in contrast to the theories
of Prodicus and Protagoras that I have just discussed. Unlike
Prodicus, the author of these verses traces the origin of the belief in
the gods back not to usefulness, but to fear.42 Even more marked is
his divergence from Protagoras and democratic ideology. While
Protagoras celebrates the superiority of politics (and the nomos) over
religion precisely because of its capacity to regulate the social life of
humans, the very opposite is the case in the Sisyphus: it is religion,
understood as fear of the gods, which safeguards human life. But the
real point of divergence does not concern so much the analysis of soci-
ety as the anthropological conception which this analysis implies:
whereas Protagoras stresses a ‘collaborative’ anthropology, which
underlines the political and social dimension of human life, the
Sisyphus passage entails a very different kind of anthropology, which
emphasizes the irremovable nature of the passions and of the instinct
40
Sutton 1981.
41
Kahn 1997: 249–50.
42
An interesting parallel here is with Democritus, 68A75 D.-K. = Atom. D207 L.-M.; see too
Euripides, Helen, 743.
One issue which had always been debated in relation to the gods was
what in the modern age came to be referred to as the problem of ‘the-
odicy’, which is to say the problem of the justification of divine justice
vis-à-vis the existence of evil. Faith in the gods entailed confidence in a
corrective action on their part, as had constantly been stressed by the
greatest poets, from Hesiod (Works and Days, 267–73) and Solon
(fr. 1, 25–32 D.) onwards. In the second half of the fifth century BC,
the Greeks started voicing more and more doubts, reservations, and
objections with regard to the effectiveness of this divine intervention,
in some case denying its very existence. As a counterpart to
Aeschylus’ censuring of those who dared to claim ‘that the gods did
not deign to concern themselves / with such mortals’ (Agamemnon,
369–72), it is possible to adduce some verses from Euripides that
clearly reflect the anxiety felt by the people of his day: ‘if the gods are
<sensible>, you, just man that you are, will be rewarded. And if not,
why should we toil?’ (Iphigenia in Aulis, 1034–5). Besides, this was
the implicit moral of the Sisyphus: ‘the truth would be that there are
no gods and that no unjust man has anything to fear insofar as he
can escape the human guardians of law and order’.45 Protagoras, too,
had dealt with this issue in an original way, by attempting to solve
the problem of justice without invoking the gods. It is perfectly reason-
able to assume, then, that the sophists contributed to this climate of
anxiety through the views they expressed.
Other testimonies confirm this, in addition to the ones already
discussed. Consider, for instance, the following statement by
Thrasymachus:
43
Evident affinities are instead to be found with Antiphon: see Chapter 4, pp. 84–89. This sort
of polemic becomes even more interesting when we consider the fact that another target might
have been Socrates’ intellectualism. However, it is difficult to agree with Santoro 1997 that the
wise inventor of the gods is to be identified precisely with Socrates (more reasonably, Palumbo
2005 suggests the name of Xenophanes – but, again, it is difficult to draw any definite
conclusions).
44
Nestle 1948. On this, see now Balla 2018.
45
Burkert 1985a: 315.
‘The gods do not notice human affairs: for otherwise they would not have failed to take
notice of what is the greatest good for humans, justice. For we see that humans do not
practice this’ (85B8 D.-K. = 35D17 L.-M.).
46
Untersteiner 1954: 325; Romeyer-Dherbey 1985: 77; and Guthrie 1971: 297 respectively.
47
Bonazzi 2008.
48
See also Chapter 2, pp. 40–41. Some difficulty, in this case, might be raised by fragment
87B10 D.-K. = 37D9a L.-M. (‘that is why he lacks nothing and receive nothing from anyone,
but is unlimited and unlacking’), which many scholars believe to be referring to god. Other solu-
tions are possible, however, because the subject might be the cosmos, the intellect, or nature: see
the discussion in Pendrick 2002: 256–9.
Melos. Regrettably, not much is known about him, and the little infor-
mation we have consists of trivial anecdotes which do not really help us
to reconstruct his ideas.49 So it is impossible to establish whether – as
hypothesized by Guthrie50 – Diagoras may be the source of theses of
the sort we find in a fragment from Euripides’ Bellerophon:
49
The testimonies were brought together in Winiarczyk 1981 and 2016.
50
Guthrie 1971: 236; but see now the more detailed treatment in Whitmarsh 2015: 109–13.
51
Translated Barnes 1979.
52
See Barnes 1979: ii.455–6 for an analysis of the merits and limitations of this argument.
53
From the few testimonies we have about Diagoras’ life, it seems as though he was charged
with impiety and forced to flee Athens precisely in 415/414 BC: see Winiarczyk 2016: 54–59. A
scholium to Aristophanes would appear to establish a correlation between his impiety (and in par-
ticular his profanation of the Eleusinian Mysteries) and the Melos event (Scholia in Aristoph. Aves,
1073); see also Brisson 1994. However, Diagoras’ atheism had long been known: see Ostwald
1986: 275–7. As far as Euripides’ Bellerophon is concerned, it can be dated between 430 and
426 BC.
pages by another great author of the fifth century; once again, this is not
a sophist but a writer deeply influenced by the sophists: Thucydides.
When introducing the Melos episode in Book 5 of his History,
Thucydides imagines a dialogue between the Athenian ambassadors
and the representatives of Melos to discuss the surrender of the
‘small city’ to the imperial power of Athens. The structure of what is
often referred to as the ‘Melian Dialogue’, arranged according to
opposite theses, clearly reflects the influence of sophistic antilogies,
as does the content of the arguments: scholars have, for instance,
repeatedly observed that the Athenians defend the same notion of just-
ice as the one that Plato attributes to Thrasymachus in the Republic,
namely the idea that justice comes from might. By contrast, scholars
have often failed to note that the dialogue also includes a most interest-
ing variation on the theme of the divine and of theodicy.
Towards the end of the dispute, when it is clear that any settlement
between the two parties is impossible, the Melians openly accuse the
Athenians of injustice, while voicing their faith in a providential inter-
vention of the gods (who are expected to somehow force the
Spartans – whose colonists the Melians are – to come to their aid):
Melians: We, too, be well assured, think it difficult to contend both against your power
and against fortune, unless she shall be impartial; but nevertheless we trust that, in
point of fortune, we shall through the divine favour be at no disadvantage because
we are god-fearing men standing our ground against men who are unjust. . .
Athenians: Well, as to the kindness of the divine favour, neither do we expect to fall
short of you therein. For in no respect are we departing from men’s observances regard-
ing that which pertains to the divine or from their desires regarding that which pertains
to themselves in aught that we demand or do. For of the gods we hold the belief, and of
men we know, that by a necessity of their nature wherever they have the power they
always rule. And so in our case since we neither enacted this law nor when it was
enacted were the first to use it, but found it in existence and expect to leave it in exist-
ence for all time, so we make use of it, well aware that both you and others, if clothed
with the same power as we are, would do the same thing. And so with regard to the
divine favour, we have good reason not to be so afraid that we shall be at a disadvantage.
(Thucydides, 5.104–5)
While one might disagree with the Athenians’ words, their originality
can hardly be disputed: to defend themselves, they did not simply reject
the belief that any providential divine intervention was possible, as
Thrasymachus might have done, for instance; neither did they deny
the existence of the gods, like the Bellerophon or Diagoras; nor yet
did they endorse an agnostic stance like Protagoras. On the contrary,
54
Significant similarities may be found in Book 10 of the Laws: ‘All this, my friends, is the
theme of experts – as our young people regard them – who in their prose and poetry maintain
that anything one can get away with by force is absolutely justified. This is why we experience out-
breaks of impiety among the young, who assume that the kind of gods the laws tell them to believe
in do not exist; this is why we get treasonable efforts to convert people to the “true natural life”,
which is essentially nothing but a life of conquest over others, not one of service to your neighbor
as the law enjoins’ (Pl. Leg. 10.890a–b). On the possible references to Antiphon in this passage, see
above and Chapter 2, pp. 40–41. It is interesting to note that in antiquity Antiphon was regarded as
one of Thucydides’ masters: the hypothesis that these passages from the Melians’ dialogue betray
the sophist’s influence is intriguing, but impossible to demonstrate based on the available
testimonies.
55
Crane 1998: 6.
Protagoras of Abdera
1
In certain cases, these profiles draw and expand upon the introductory notes provided by
Bonazzi 2007 (on Protagoras, see too Bonazzi 2009b). Other detailed presentations may be
found in Kent Sprague 1972, Kerferd 1981a: 42–58, Guthrie 1971: 261–319, and Pradeau
2009a. With regard to the Platonic figures, Nails 2002 is also very useful. On ancient philosophers
more generally, I will refer to Goulet 1989–2018.
appointment of this sort implies that the two men shared the same pol-
itical views). This connection with Pericles can also be confirmed by
the upheavals that marked the last years of Protagoras’ life: the crisis
of Periclean politics seems to find a counterpart in the downfall of
Protagoras, who – like other personalities close to the statesman –
was reportedly put on trial.
But the information we have here becomes very hazy. Some sources
report that, after a public reading of his text on the gods, Protagoras was
charged with impiety and fled Athens, while his books were burned. By
the same account, the sophist died in a shipwreck during his flight.
However, this is very questionable; in particular, it differs from what
Plato writes in his dialogues, where he speaks of Protagoras as though
he had died as a universally esteemed figure in old age, with no refer-
ences to any trials or flights. From Plato we know that Protagoras
lived approximately seventy years (other sources state ninety), which
would place his death at around 420 BC.
Diogenes Laertius attributes many works to Protagoras, but a com-
parison with the other sources reveals that his list is incomplete. Worse
still, what are missing from Diogenes’ list are precisely the most import-
ant and controversial works, such as Truth and On the Gods. One pos-
sible explanation is that these two texts constituted individual entries of
the Antilogiae (Opposing Arguments, mentioned by Diogenes), which
were possibly also known as Kataballontes logoi (The Overthrower
Arguments or, better, The Knockdown Arguments: see Appendix 2).
Yet, as in other cases, any attempt at reconstruction is destined to
remain a mere hypothesis, given the dearth of available fragments.
Indeed, apart from the title of Protagoras’ work, all we have are a few
authentic fragments and many interpretations. Ever since antiquity,
his provocative theses have elicited interest and criticism from his read-
ers. As a result, different reconstructions of his thought are available,
which are not always reliable and are often clearly shaped by dispara-
ging intentions.
The first and most important tradition stretches back to Plato, who
devoted two dialogues to the theses of the sophist of Abdera, the
Protagoras and the Theaetetus. Many of the later testimonies, starting
with Aristotle’s, appear to depend on Plato’s discussion, and this
must be taken into account when examining the information from
our sources. Alongside the Platonic tradition, another tradition proved
influential in antiquity, namely the one that highlighted the sceptical
implications of Protagoras’ thought. However, little is known about
Gorgias of Leontini
Palamedes, which are among the few sophistic works to have survived; a
long fragment from a Funeral Oration delivered in Athens, or at any rate
written for an Athenian public; and the fragments of other orations
delivered in various places in Greece. Gorgias may also have been the
author of a treatise on The Art of Rhetoric, and of another text, On the
Opportune Moment (kairos).
The names of many of Gorgias’ pupils have been recorded:
Alcidamas of Elea, Callicles of Acharnae, Isocrates of Athens,
Licymnius of Chios, Meno of Larissa, Polus of Acragas, Protarcus of
Athens, Proxenus of Thebes, and probably Lycophron too.
Thucydides and Critias are also said to have been influenced by
Gorgias, as was Aspasia, Pericles’ hetaira.
2
For an initial overview, I will refer to Bonazzi 2007: 52–6. Significantly, the two recent mono-
graphs by Hourcade 2001 and Gagarin 2002 favour the unitary reading; see also Decleva Caizzi
1969, Narcy 1989, and now Laks and Most 2016, vol. ix. Nevertheless, it is important to note
with Woodruff 2004 that, however widespread this interpretation may be, it is not universally
accepted: Pendrick 2002 once again supports the arguments of the separatists.
(of Rhetoric) and with some Prologues. The most interesting works
among the surviving orations are On the Murder of Herodes, Against
the Stepmother for Poisoning, and On the Choreutes. We also have a frag-
ment of what was probably the speech he gave to defend himself after
the 411 BC coup. Finally, some sources identify the sophist Antiphon
with another Antiphon, an author of tragedies: but this identification
is made more problematic by the information that the poet was mur-
dered by orders of the tyrant of Syracuse, Dionysius.
Xeniades of Corinth
Prodicus of Ceos
We know that Prodicus came from the island of Ceos in the Cyclades.
The sources make no mention of his date of birth but nonetheless pre-
sent him as a contemporary of Democritus, Socrates, Hippias, and
Gorgias, which would suggest sometime around 460 BC. Like other
sophists, Prodicus made repeated visits to Athens (where by 423 BC
he was already well known) and other Greek cities, either as an emissary
or to deliver speeches or lectures. One of the main reasons for his fame
lies in his linguistic interests, and particularly in his ability to correctly
distinguish the various meanings of terms, clarifying their nuances. Not
without some irony, the importance of this research was acknowledged
by Socrates (who at times went so far as to describe himself as a pupil of
Prodicus) and Plato. These linguistic distinctions are based on the
assumption that language can adequately reflect the variety of things:
the correct use of names is therefore the precondition for an adequate
evaluation of reality.
Prodicus also took an interest in natural problems (a record survives
of a treatise On Nature), although he stands out for his humanistic
emphasis, as is shown by his rationalist criticism of religion, according
to which humans first deified all the natural forces on which their exist-
ence depended – such as the sun, the rivers, and the sea – and then the
great benefactors who had contributed to the progress of civilization
(for instance, Demeter and Dionysus for bread and wine). Finally,
we know about the contents of a declamation entitled The Choice of
Heracles,3 in which the choice between vice and virtue provided an
avenue to celebrate the freedom of human beings, who forge their
own destiny. In the eyes of several interpreters, from Xenophon to
George Grote, this call to sacrifice and virtue constitutes the most strik-
ing refutation of the charge of immorality directed against the sophists.
According to a late tradition, Prodicus died in Athens when he was
charged with corrupting the young and forced to drink a cup of hem-
lock. Modern scholars have often dismissed this as an unreliable
account; however, other sources report that he was expelled from a
gymnasium for having addressed inappropriate words to the young:
‘it is not impossible that he did have to face the kind of opposition
which Protagoras spoke of as the common lot of all sophists’.4
Thrasymachus of Chalcedon
3
Possibly part of the broader work entitled the Seasons (Horai): see p. 118, n. 35.
4
Kerferd 1981a: 46.
Hippias of Elis
Critias of Athens
elegies and other poetic compositions, which were well suited to sym-
posia. Critias also composed some tragedies, although in some cases
their authorship is uncertain. He can probably be credited with the frag-
ments from the Tennes, Rhadamanthys, and Pirithous, which appear to
have explored the sharing – out of love and friendship – ‘of the ultimate
dangers, death or exile’ – dangers whose full weight Critias bore in his
own life.5 The case of the satyr-play Sisyphus is more problematic,
because it can also be attributed to Euripides.
Philostratus featured Critias in his Lives of the Sophists: for this rea-
son, perhaps, Diels chose to include him in his edition; and since
then he has always been reckoned among the sophists. However, if
we rule out the fragments from the Sisyphus, there seem to be no cogent
reasons to regard Critias as a sophist: he was not a teacher and appears
to have championed a kind of old-fashioned, pro-Spartan education,
essentially hostile to the teachings of the sophists (although some points
of convergence between the two may be found). The importance that
Critias assigned to poetry also seems to be at odds with the sophists’
positions. Finally, even if one were to attribute the Sisyphus to him,
this work is a theatrical text that cannot be taken to present doctrines
personally endorsed by Critias. At most, like many other young
Athenian nobles, he may be regarded as a pupil of the sophists (and
of Socrates), but he can hardly be considered to have been a sophist
himself.
Lycophron
5
Centanni 1997: 178.
generation of sophists. Our sources do not even record the titles of his
works, although from the few testimonies we have it is possible to infer
that he had a good command of the problems tackled by the most fam-
ous sophists – from the issue of language to the opposition between
nomos and physis. This makes the lack of reliable information about
him all the more regrettable.
Callicles of Acharnae
All we know about Callicles is what Plato tells us in the Gorgias. Some
scholars have gone so far as to suggest that he is a fictional character.
More reasonably, Dodds defended the opposite thesis, suggesting
that Callicles truly existed but died young, thus leaving little memory
of himself.6 As far as we can judge from Plato’s dialogue, he is remin-
iscent of another Athenian aristocrat, Critias. Like Critias, he is to be
considered not so much a sophist as a pupil of the sophists – and
Plato arguably used the figure of Callicles to illustrate the dangers of
their theses.
Most of the information that we have about these figures comes from
Plato’s Euthydemus; other testimonies from the Cratylus and Aristotle
confirm that they were genuine historical figures. As far as we can
tell, the distinctive feature of their work lies in their interest in soph-
isms, of which they make bold use in the Platonic dialogue. Ever
since antiquity, this focus on paradoxical arguments has suggested a
comparison with the Megarian School. Yet, there is no need, perhaps,
to hypothesize, as Dorion 2009a does, that the two figures belonged to
this school, thereby severing all links with the sophistic tradition.
Rather – at any rate according to Plato’s testimony – they represent
the worst version of sophistry, the eristic type whose only goal was
to win debates.
6
Dodds 1959: 12–15. The hypothesis of a premature death is based on a prophecy post
eventum, at Gorgias, 519a.
Alcidamas of Elaea
7
Kerferd 1981a: 54.
8
Mazzarino 1966: 285–6.
9
See also T. Robinson 1979 and Maso 2018.
10
A succinct overview of the other anonymous treatises attributed to sophists may be found in
Kerferd and Flashar 1998: 97–107.
1
See Soverini 1998: 90–114; and Chapter 6, n. 34.
not at a point, but as Protagoras said it did, in his refutation of the geometers [that is
along a line]).
(80B7 D.-K. partly reproduced by L.-M. as 31D33)2
The presence of two key terms, the verbs kataballo and antilego, clearly
suggests a Protagorean context. The Kataballontes logoi, therefore, are
2
Let us also consider Philodemus’ testimony: ‘the <things> are not knowable, <the> words are
not acceptable, <as> Protagoras indeed [sc. said] about ma<thematics>’ (PHerc. 1676 = 80B7a
D.-K. = 31D34 L.-M.). As regards the meaning of the polemic against geometry, we might
posit (with Barnes 1979: ii.546) that in this case too Protagoras exploited his method of two con-
trasting logoi: geometry hinges on physical objects; now, if it does not deal with physical objects, all
it amounts to is an insignificant verbal game; on the other hand, if it does deal with physical
objects, it is subject to empirical evaluation; but any empirical evaluation is bound to offer different
results from those provided by a priori analyses; thus even in relation to the apparent certainties of
mathematics we find that for the same object there are two opposite logoi. Arguments of this sort
were probably also used in the treatise On Mathematics (or On the Sciences) mentioned by Diogenes
Laertius (80A1 D.-K. = 31D1 L.-M.). Besides, even in the Protagoras the sophist does not show
himself to be very keen on the mathematical sciences (318d–e, 80A5 D.-K. = 31D37 L.-M.).
3
See Jori 1996: 333–57.
4
Fait 2007: xli.
those speeches or arguments that have the power to defeat one’s oppon-
ent; and putting pupils in the condition to compete against anyone was
the aim of antilogies.
An analysis of testimonies about the sophists’ engagement with spe-
cialist forms of knowledge once again confirms their agonistic approach:
through such polemics, they sought to present their teaching as superior
to that of other specialists, be they poets, scientists, or philosophers.5
This ‘architectural’ vocation – to quote an Aristotelian expression – of
sophistic knowledge vis-à-vis all other forms of knowledge finds an
exemplary expression in a statement attributed to Gorgias: ‘Gorgias
the orator said that those who neglect philosophy6 but dedicate them-
selves to the ordinary disciplines (ta enkuklia mathemata) are similar to
the suitors, who desired Penelope but slept with the maidservants’
(82B29 D.-K. = 32P22 L.-M.) If we consider the ideological value
that technai possessed in fifth-century democratic Athens, we once
again realize just how provocative the sophists’ activity was.
A reaction from the sophists’ opponents, however, was not long in
coming. The Hippocratic treatise The Art has already been mentioned;
see for instance Chapter 1:
Some there are who have made an art of vilifying the arts, though they consider, not that
they are accomplishing the object I mention, but that they are making a display of their
own knowledge. . . .To be eager to bring shame through the art of abuse upon the
discoveries of others, improving nothing but disparaging before those who do not
know the discoveries of those who do, seems to me to be not the ambition and work
of intelligence, but the sign of a nasty nature, or of want of art.
To this one may add other texts from the Corpus hippocraticum (e.g. On
the Nature of Man, 1–8) or certain passages from Plato (from the Sophist
and Euthydemus) and Aristotle (especially from the Sophistical
Refutations). Indeed, the specious nature of these polemics contributed
to fuel the suspicion that the sophists were incompetent and merely
eristic (from the Greek eris, ‘discord’) debaters: they were incompetent
because they did not really grasp the things they were talking about, and
merely eristic because they were only interested in winning debates. In
certain cases, at least, it is difficult to dismiss these charges.
5
In Protagoras’ case, it seems as though a more open position was adopted in relation to music
(or at any rate the musical theories of Damon, who was a representative of the ‘new culture’): see
Brancacci 2008.
6
Evidently, the term ‘philosophy’ here refers to the kind of activity in which rhetors and soph-
ists engaged.
Barnes, Jonathan (ed.) 1984. The Complete Works of Aristotle. 2 vols. Princeton, NJ,
Princeton University Press.
Bonazzi, Mauro 2007. I sofisti. Milan, Rizzoli.
Cooper, John (ed.) 1997. Plato. Complete Works. Indianapolis, IN, and Cambridge,
Hackett Publishing Company.
Diels, Hermann, and Kranz, Walter 1951–2. Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. Sixth
edition, Berlin, Weidmann.
Dillon, John, and Gergel, Tania 2003. The Greek Sophists. London, Penguin.
Freeman, Kathryn 1948. Ancilla to the Pre-Socratic Philosophers. A Complete Translation
of the Fragments in Diels’ ‘Fragmente der Vorsokratiker’. Oxford, Blackwell.
Kent Sprague, Rosamund (ed.) 1972. The Older Sophists. Columbia, SC, University
of South Carolina Press.
Laks, André, and Most, Glenn W. 2016. Early Greek Philosophy. 9 vols.
Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.
———, and ——— 2016. Les débuts de la philosophie. Des premiers penseurs grecs à
Socrate. Paris, Fayard.
Pradeau, Jean-François (ed.) 2009. Les sophistes. With the assistance of M. Bonazzi,
L. Brisson, M.-L. Desclos, L.-A. Dorion, A. Macé, and M. Patillon. 2 vols. Paris,
Flammarion.
Untersteiner, Mario 1949–62. I sofisti. Testimonianze e frammenti. With the assist-
ance of A. M. Battegazzore. 4 vols. Florence, La Nuova Italia.
2. Works cited
Alvoni, Giovanna 2017. ‘Die Rhesis des Sisyphos über den Ursprung der Religion
(Kritias, Fr. 19 Sn.-K.)’, Paideia 72: 467–81.
Apfel, Lauren J. 2011. The Advent of Pluralism. Diversity and Conflict in the Age of
the Sophists. Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Arrighetti, Graziano 1998. Esiodo. Opere. Turin, Utet.
Balaudé, Jean-François 2006. ‘Hippias le passeur’, in Sassi 2006: 287–304.
Balla, Chloe 2018. ‘πέwυκε πλεονεκτεῖν? Plato and the Sophists on Greed and
Savage Humanity’, Polis 35: 83–101.
——— 2004. ‘Il logos di Ippia: Plat. Prot. 337c–338b’, in G. Casertano (ed.), Il
Protagora di Platone. Struttura e problematiche. Naples, Loffredo: 390–401.
——— 2008. ‘Protagora, Damone e la musica’, in Musica e filosofia da Damone a
Filodemo. Florence, Olschki: 21–33.
Brisson, Luc 1994. ‘Diagoras de Mélos’, in Goulet 1989–2018: ii.750–7.
——— 2009. ‘Critias’, in Pradeau 2009a: i.391–442, 545–58.
Brunschwig, Jacques 1984. ‘Hippias d’Élis, philosophe-ambassadeur’, in Greek
Philosophical Society 1984: 269–76.
——— 2002. ‘Democritus and Xeniades’, in Caston and Graham 2002: 159–67.
Buchheim, Thomas 1989. Gorgias von Leontinoi. Reden, Fragmente, und
Testimonien. Hamburg, Meiner.
Bultrighini, Umberto 1999. ‘Maledetta democrazia’. Studi su Crizia. Alessandria,
Edizioni dell’Orso.
Burkert, Walter 1985a. Greek Religion. London, Blackwell (first published
Stuttgart 1977).
——— 1985b. ‘Herodot über die Namen der Götter: Polytheismus als historisches
Problem’, MH 42: 121–32.
Burnyeat, Myles 1976. ‘Protagoras and Self-Refutation in Later Greek
Philosophy’, PhR 85: 44–69.
Calogero, Guido 1932. Studi sull’Eleatismo. Florence, La Nuova Italia.
Canfora, Luciano 2001. Storia della letteratura greca. Rome and Bari, Laterza.
Capra, Andrea 1997. ‘La tecnica di misurazione del Protagora’, ASNP, 4th series,
2: 273–327.
——— 2005. ‘Protagoras’ Achilles: Homeric Allusions as a Satirical Weapon
(Plat. Prot. 340A)’, CPh 100: 274–7.
Casertano, Gianni 1971. Natura e istituzioni umane nelle dottrine dei sofisti. Florence
and Naples, Il tripode.
——— 1986. ‘L’amour entre “logos” et “pathos”: quelques considérations sur
“l’Hélène” de Gorgias’, in Cassin 1986: 211–20.
——— 2004. Sofista. Naples, Guida.
Cassin, Barbara 1980. Si Parmenide. Le traité anonyme De Melisso Xenophane et
Gorgia. Lille, Presses universitaires de Lille.
——— (ed.) 1986. Positions de la sophistique. Paris, Vrin.
——— 1995. L’effet sophistique. Paris, Gallimard.
Castagnoli, Luca 2010. Ancient Self-Refutation. The Logic and History of the
Self-Refutation Argument from Democritus to Augustine. Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press.
Caston, Victor 2002. ‘Gorgias on Thought and Its Objects’, in Caston and
Graham 2002: 205–32.
——— and Graham Daniel W. (eds.) 2002. Presocratic Philosophy. Essays in Honour
of A.P.D. Mourelatos. Aldershot, Ashgate.
Centanni, Monica 1997. ‘Atene assoluta. Crizia dalla tragedia alla storia’, Padua,
Esedra.
Denyer, Nicholas 2013. ‘The Political Skill of Protagoras’, in Harte and Lane
2013: 155–67.
De Romilly, Jacqueline 1973. ‘Gorgias et le pouvoir de la poésie’, JHS 93:
155–72.
——— 1975. Magic and Rhetoric in Ancient Greece. Cambridge, MA, Harvard
University Press.
——— 1986. ‘Les manies de Prodicus et la rigeur de la langue grecque’, MH
43: 1–18.
——— 1988. Les grands sophistes dans l’Athènes de Périclès. Paris, Éditions du
Fallois.
——— 2005. La legge nel pensiero greco. Dalle origini ad Aristotele. Milan, Garzanti
(first published as La loi dans la pensée grecque. Des origines à Aristote. Paris, Les
Belles Lettres, 1971).
Detienne, Marcel 2006. Les maîtres de vérité dans la Grèce archaïque. Second edi-
tion, Paris, Librairie Générale Française (first published 1967).
Di Benedetto, Vincenzo 1955. ‘Il Περὶ τοῦ μὴ ὂντος di Gorgia e la polemica contro
Protagora’, RAL 10: 287–307.
——— 2001. ‘Contributo al testo del frammento di Protagora sugli dei’, RCCM
43: 345–6.
Diels, Hermann 1884. ‘Gorgias und Empedokles’, Sitzungsberichte der Königlich
Preußischen Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin: 343–68 (reprinted in C. J.
Classen (ed.), Sophistik. Darmstadt, Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft,
1976: 351–83).
Dihle, Albrecht 1977. ‘Das Satyrspiel Sisyphos’, Hermes 105: 28–42.
Dodds, Eric R. 1951. The Greeks and the Irrational. Berkeley, CA, University of
California Press.
——— 1959. Plato. Gorgias. A Revised Text with Introduction and Commentary.
Oxford, Oxford University Press.
——— 1973. ‘The Sophistic Movement and the Failure of Greek Liberalism’, in
The Ancient Concept of Progress and Other Essays on Greek Literature and Belief.
Oxford, Clarendon Press: 92–105.
Dorion, Louis-André 2008. ‘Héraclès entre Prodicos et Xenophon’, PhilosAnt
8: 85–114.
——— 2009a. ‘Euthydème et Dionysodore’, in Pradeau 2009a: ii.63–80, 179–87.
——— 2009b. ‘Prodicos’, in Pradeau 2009a: i.343–72, 525–39.
Drozdek, Adam 2005. ‘Protagoras and the Instrumentality of Religion’, AC 74:
41–50.
Dumont, Jean-Paul 1986. ‘Prodicos: de la méthode au système’, in Cassin 1986:
221–32.
Edmunds, Lowell 2006. ‘What Was Socrates Called?’, CQ 56: 414–25.
Ehrenberg, Victor 1957. Sophocles and Pericles. London, Blackwell.
El Murr, Dimitri 2019. ‘Platon contre (et avec) Thrasymaque’, in Collette,
Gavray, and Narbonne 2019: 343–64.
Fait, Paolo 2007. Aristotele. Le confutazioni sofistiche. Rome and Bari, Laterza.
Harte, Verit, and Lane, Melissa (eds.) 2013. Politeia in Greek and Roman
Philosophy. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
Heinimann, Felix 1945. Nomos und Physis. Herkunft und Bedeutung einer Antithese
im griechischen Denken des 5. Jahrhunderts. Basel, Schweizerischen Beiträge zur
Altertumswissenschaft.
Henrichs, Albert 1975. ‘Two Doxographical Notes: Democritus and Prodicus on
Religion’, HSCPh 79: 93–123.
——— 1976. ‘The Atheism of Prodicus’, CErc 6: 15–21.
Hobbs, Angela 2000. Plato and the Hero. Courage, Manliness and the Impersonal
Good. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
Hoffmann, Klaus F. 1997. Das Recht im Denken der Sophistik. Stuttgart and
Leipzig, Teubner.
Horky, Phillip S. 2006. ‘The Imprint of the Soul: Psychosomatic Affection in
Plato, Gorgias, and the “Orphic” Gold Tablets’, Mouseion 6: 383–98.
Hourcade, Annie 2001. Antiphon d’Athènes. Une pensée de l’individu. Brussels,
Ousia.
——— 2006. Sophistique et atomisme. Brussels, Ousia.
Iannucci, Alessandro 2002. La parola e l’azione. I frammenti simposiali di Crizia.
Bologna, Edizioni Nautilus.
Ioli, Roberta (ed. and trans.) 2010. Gorgia. Su ciò che non è. Zürich and New York,
Olms.
——— 2013. Gorgia. Testimonianze e frammenti. Rome, Carocci.
Isnardi Parente, Margherita 1969. ‘Il pensiero politico greco dalle origini alla sofis-
tica: Socrate e Platone’, in L. Firpo (ed.), Storia delle idee politiche, economiche e
sociali. Vol. I. Turin, Utet: 127–289.
——— 1977. Sofistica e democrazia antica. Florence, Sansoni.
Jaeger, Werner 1947. The Theology of the Early Greek Philosophers. Oxford,
Clarendon Press.
Jori, Alberto 1996. Medicina e medici nell’antica Grecia. Saggio sul peri technes ippo-
cratico. Bologna, Il Mulino.
Kahn, Charles 1973. The Verb ‘Be’ in Ancient Greek. Dordrecht, Reidel.
——— 1981. ‘The Origins of Social Contract Theory’, in Kerferd 1981b: 92–108.
——— 1997. ‘Greek Religion and Philosophy in the Sisyphus Fragment’, Phronesis
42: 247–62.
Kennedy, George A. 1963. The Art of Persuasion in Greece. Princeton, NJ,
Princeton University Press.
Kerferd, George B. 1955–6. ‘Gorgias on Nature or What is Not’, Phronesis 1:
3–25.
——— 1981a. The Sophistic Movement, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
——— (ed.) 1981b. The Sophists and Their Legacy. Wiesbaden, Steiner Verlag.
——— 1984. ‘Meaning and Reference: Gorgias and the Relation Between
Language and Reality’, in Greek Philosophical Society 1984: 215–22.
——— 1985. ‘Gorgias and Empedocles’, Syculorum Gymnasium 38: 595–605.
——— and Flashar, Helmut 1998. ‘Die Sophistik’, in F. Überweg and H. Flashar
(eds.), Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophie. Die Philosophie der Antike, vol. 2.1:
Sophistik, Sokrates, Sokratik, Mathematik, Medizin. Basel, Schwabe: 1–137.
Kuntz, Mary 1993. ‘The Prodikean “Choice of Herakles”: AReshaping of Myth’,
CJ 89: 163–81.
Lapini, Walter 1997. Commento all’Athenaion Politeia dello pseudo-Senofonte.
Florence, Dipartimento di Scienze dell’Antichità ‘Giorgio Pasquali’.
Lee, Mi-Kyoung 2005. Epistemology After Protagoras. Responses to Relativism in
Plato, Aristotle, and Democritus. Oxford, Clarendon Press.
Lloyd, Geoffrey E. R. 1979. Magic, Reason and Experience. Studies in the Origins and
Development of Greek Science. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
——— 1987. The Revolutions of Wisdom. Studies in the Claims and Practices of
Ancient Greek Science. Berkeley, CA, University of California Press.
Long, Anthony A. 1984. ‘Methods of Argument in Gorgias’ Palamedes’, in Greek
Philosophical Society 1984: 233–41.
——— 2015. Greek Models of Mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Macé, Arnaud 2008. ‘Un monde sans pitiè: Platon à l’échole de Thasymaque de
Chalcédoine’, PhilosAnt 8: 33–60.
——— 2009. ‘Thrasymaque’, in Pradeau 2009a: ii.7–28, 149–66.
Mansfeld, Jaap 1981. ‘Protagoras on Epistemological Obstacles and Persons’, in
Kerferd 1981b: 38–53.
——— 1985. ‘Historical and Philosophical Aspects of Gorgias’ “On What Is
Not”’, SicGymn 38: 243–71.
——— 1986. ‘Aristotle, Plato, and the Preplatonic Doxography and
Chronography’, in G. Cambiano (ed.), Storiografia e dossografia nella filosofia
antica. Turin, Tirrenia Stampatori: 1–59.
——— 1988. ‘De Melisso Xenophane Gorgia: Pyrrhonizing Aristotelianism’, RM
131: 239–76.
Manuwald, Bernd 2013. ‘Protagoras’ Myth in Plato’s Protagoras: Fiction or
Testimony?’, in Ophuijsen, Van Ralte, and Stork 2013: 163–77.
Maso, Stefano 2018. Dissoi logoi. Rome, Edizioni di storia e letteratura.
Mayhew, Robert (ed. and trans.) 2011. Prodicus the Sophist. Texts, translations,
and commentary. Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Mazzara, Giuseppe 1999. Gorgia. La retorica del verosimile. Sankt Augustin,
Akademia Verlag.
——— 2005. ‘La rhétorique éléatico-gorgienne d’Alcidamas chez Diogène Laërce
(IX, 54) et le quatre fonctions fondamentales du λόγος’, AC 74: 51–67.
Mazzarino, Santo 1966. Il pensiero storico classico, vol. 1. Bari, Laterza.
Momigliano, Arnaldo 1930. ‘Prodico di Ceo e le dottrine sul linguaggio da
Democrito ai Cinici’, Atti della Regia Accademia delle Scienze di Torino 65:
95–107.
Morgan, Kathryn 2000. Myth and Philosophy from the Presocratics to Plato.
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
Most, Glenn W. 1986. ‘Sophistique et herméneutique’, in Cassin 1986: 233–45.
Schiappa, Edward 1991. Protagoras and Logos. Columbia, SC, University of South
Carolina Press.
Scholten, Helga 2003. Die Sophistik. Eine Bedrohnung für die Religion und Politik der
Polis? Berlin, Akademie Verlag.
Scodel, Ruth 1980. The Trojan Trilogy of Euripides. Göttingen, Vandenhoek &
Ruprecht.
Sedley, David 2013. ‘The Atheist Underground’, in Harte and Lane 2013: 329–48.
Segal, Charles 1962. ‘Gorgias and the Psychology of Logos’, HSCPh 66: 99–155.
Sihvola, Juha 1989. Decay, Progress, the Good Life? Hesiod and Protagoras on the
Development of Culture. Helsinki, Societas Scientiarum Fennica.
Solmsen, Friedrich 1931. Antiphonstudien. Untersuchungen zur Enstehung der
attischen Gerichtsrede. Berlin, Weidmann.
——— 1975. Intellectual Experiments of the Greek Enlightenment. Princeton, NJ,
Princeton University Press.
Soverini, Luca 1998. Il sofista e l’agora. Sapienti, economia e vita quotidiana nella
Grecia classica. Pisa, Pubblicazioni della Scuola Normale Superiore.
Spatharas, Dimos G. 2001. ‘Patterns of Argumentation in Gorgias’, Mnemosyne
54: 393–408.
Striker, Gisela 1996. ‘Methods of Sophistry’, in Essays in Hellenistic Epistemology
and Ethics. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press: 3–21.
Sutton, Dana 1981. ‘Critias and Atheism’, CQ 31: 33–8.
Tell, Håkan 2011. Plato’s Counterfeit Sophists. Washington, DC: Center for
Hellenic Studies.
Thomas, Rosalind 2003. ‘Prose Performance Texts: Epideixis and Written
Publication in the Late Fifth and Early Fourth Centuries’, in H. Yunis (ed.),
Written Texts and the Rise of Literate Culture in Ancient Greece. Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press: 162–88.
Tinsdale, Christopher W. 2010. Reason’s Dark Champions. Constructive Strategies of
Sophistic Argument. Columbia, SC, University of South Carolina Press.
Tordesillas, Alonso 1986. ‘L’instance temporelle dans l’argumentation de la
première et de la seconde sophistique: la notion de kairos’, in B. Cassin
(ed.), Le plaisir de parler. Paris, Les éditions de minuit: 31–61.
——— 2004. ‘Synonymique, éthique, philosophie (note sur Prodicos de Ceos)’, in
J.-P. Cometti (ed.), L’éthique de la philosophie. Paris, Éditions Kimé: 55–75.
——— 2008. ‘Gorgias et la question de la responsabilité d’Hélène’, in F. Alesse
et al. (eds.), Anthropine sophia. Studi di filologia e storiografia filosofica in memoria
di Gabriele Giannantoni. Naples, Bibliopolis: 45–54.
Tortora, Giuseppe 1985. ‘Il senso del kairos in Gorgia’, SicGymn 38: 537–64.
Trabattoni, Franco (ed. and trans.) 2000. Gorgia – Platone. Parola e ragione. Milan,
Unicopli.
Untersteiner, Mario 1947. ‘La storia dell’umanità e la soluzione dell’antitesi
nomos-physis in Prodico di Ceo’, RSF 2: 117–22.
——— 1954. The Sophists. transl. by K. Freeman. Oxford, Blackwell (first pub-
lished in Italian 1949).
Vegetti, Mario 1989. L’etica degli antichi. Rome and Bari, Laterza.
——— 1998. ‘Trasimaco’, in M. Vegetti (ed.), Platone. La Repubblica. Vol. I. Libro
I. Naples, Bibliopolis: 233–56.
——— 2018. ‘Antropologie della pleonexia: Callicle, Trasimaco e Glaucone in
Platone’, in Il potere della verità. Saggi platonici. Rome, Carocci: 195–210.
Verdenius, Willem J. 1981. ‘Gorgias’ Theory of Deception’, in Kerferd 1981b:
116–28.
Versenyi, Lazslo 1962. ‘Protagoras’ Man-Measure Fragment’, AJPh 83: 178–84.
Vitanza, Victor 1997. Negation, Subjectivity, and the History of Rhetoric. New York,
State University of New York Press.
Vlastos, Gregory 1956. ‘Protagoras’, in M. Ostwald (trans.) and G. Vlastos (ed.),
Plato. Protagoras. New York, Bobbs-Merrill Company: vii–xxiv.
Wardy, Robert 1996. The Birth of Rhetoric. Gorgias, Plato and Their Successors.
London, Routledge.
Wedgwood, Ralph 2017. ‘The Coherence of Thrasymachus’, OSAP 53: 33–63.
White, Stephen A. 1995. ‘Thrasymachus the Diplomat’, CPh 90: 307–27.
Whitmarsh, Tim 2015. Battling the Gods. Atheism in the Ancient World. New York,
Knopf.
Willink, Charles W. 1983. ‘Prodikos, “Meteorosophists” and the “Tantalos”
Paradigm’, CQ 33: 25–33.
Winiarczyk, Marek (ed.) 1981. Diagorae Melii et Theodori Cyrenaei reliquiae.
Leipzig, Teubner.
——— (ed.) 1990. ‘Methodisches zum antiken Atheismus’, RM 133: 1–15.
——— (ed.) 2016. Diagoras of Melos. A Contribution to the History of Ancient
Atheism. Berlin, De Gruyter.
Wolfsdorf, David 2008a. ‘Hesiod, Prodicus, and the Socratics on Work and
Pleasure’, in Brad Inwood (ed.), Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy XXXV:
Winter 2008. Oxford, Oxford University Press: 1–18.
——— 2008b. ‘Prodicus on the Correctness of Names: The Case of τέρψις, χαρά
and εὐwροσύνη’, JHS 35: 1–18.
Woodruff, Paul 1999. ‘Rhetoric and Relativism: Protagoras and Gorgias’, in A. A.
Long (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy. Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press: 290–310.
——— 2004. ‘Antiphons, Sophist and Athenian’. OSAP 26: 323–36.
——— 2013. ‘Euboulia as the Skill Protagoras Taught’, in Ophuijsen, Van Ralte,
and Stork 2013: 179–93.
Yunis, Harvey 1997. ‘Thrasymachus B1: Discord, Not Diplomacy’, CPh 92:
58–66.
Zeller, Eduard 1923. Die Philosophie der Griechen in ihrer geschichtlichen
Entwicklung. Fifth edition, Leipzig, Reisland.
Zilioli, Ugo 2013. ‘Protagoras Through Plato and Aristotle: A Case for the
Philosophical Significance of Ancient Relativism’, in Ophuijsen, Van Ralte
and Stork 2013: 233–57.
To place an order from within the United States, Canada and Mexico For information on subscribing or submitting to the journal, please visit
please contact Cambridge Customer Services toll free via +1 800 872 7423 journals.cambridge.org/gar
or by email via information@cup.org/. For orders outside of North America
please call + 44 (0)1223 325566 or email via ukcustserve@cambridge.org/.
BY Mauro Bonazzi
From Socrates and Plato onwards, the Sophists were often targeted by the authoritative
philosophical tradition as being mere charlatans and poor teachers. This book, translated
and significantly updated from its most recent Italian version (2nd edition, 2013), challenges
The Sophists
these criticisms by offering an overall interpretation of their thought, and by assessing the
specific contributions of thinkers like Protagoras, Gorgias and Antiphon. A new vision of the
Sophists emerges: they are protagonists and agents of fundamental change in the history of
Ancient Philosophy, who questioned the grounds of morality and politics, as well as the nature
of knowledge and language. By shifting the focus from the cosmos to man, the Sophists
inaugurate an alternative form of philosophy, whose importance is only now becoming clear.