New Microsoft Office Word Document
New Microsoft Office Word Document
New Microsoft Office Word Document
a loosely related set of approaches in various fields of philosophy that (1) emphasizes the role of gender in the formation of traditional philosophical problems and concepts, (2) analyzes the ways in which traditional philosophy reflects and perpetuates bias against women, and (3) defends philosophical concepts and theories that presume women's equality.
There were some early attempts in the history of philosophy to address issues of concern to women, including Mill's The Subjection of Women, which argued for woman suffrage, and Simone de Beauvoir's The Second Sex (1949), which showed how prevailing notions of femininity served male interests. Still, feminist philosophy from the 1970s was no less indebted to the practices and positions originally developed in women's consciousness-raising groups (groups dedicated to raising awareness of women's issues). The tenets that feminist philosophy extracted from those sources included the following. 1. Genderthe complex of psychological traits and dispositions that characterize a person as either masculine or feminineas well as the relations between genders, are socially constructed (the product of socialization according to culturally variable norms), not biologically or genetically determined. 2. Independence and self-determination for women can be achieved only by speaking in one's own voicei.e., only by thinking and acting in ways that genuinely reflect one's perspectives, experiences, feelings, and concerns as an individual. 3. The domination or subordination of women in any social setting or in any walk of life is a political issue, not a private one. 4. Because knowledge is produced by societiesi.e., knowledge is the result of collaboration among and validation by a community of inquirersthe standards used to evaluate knowledge claims and to identify legitimate topics of inquiry are socially determined, not absolute. 5. One's upbringing and social situation affect how one frames questions and what one is likely to understand. Those themes underlie contemporary feminist scholarship in all fields of philosophy.
The traditional political philosophies of liberalism and Marxism generally ignored sexual and family issues; in contrast, feminist philosophers made them the focus of political theory. Eventually three major schools of feminist political theory arose, each emphasizing a distinctive subset of issues: liberal feminism, socialist feminism, and radical feminism. Liberal feministse.g., Susan Moller Okinpointed out the many ways in which gender discrimination defeats women's aspirations, and they defended reforms designed to make women's equality a social and political reality. Noting that differences in the ways in which girls and boys are raised served to channel women and men into different and unequal social roles, they advocated gender-neutral forms of education and child rearing. They particularly focused on protecting and extending the rights that enabled women to pursue self-chosen goals, such as reproductive rights (including the right to legally obtain an abortion) and rights to full educational and economic opportunities. Whereas liberal feminists applied the core liberal values of freedom and equality to address women's concerns, the socialist feminists Alison Jaggar and Iris Marion Young appropriated Marxist categories, which were based on labour and economic structures. Criticizing traditional Marxism for exaggerating the importance of waged labour outside the home, socialist feminists insisted that the unpaid caregiving and homemaking that women are expected to perform are equally indispensable forms of labour and that the sexual division of labour that assigns most domestic work to women is exploitative. They also objected to the double day of work that burdens most women who have children and who work outside the home. Likewise, they condemned the economic dependency and insecurity of stay-at-home mothers and the low salaries of child-care workers. Last, the school of radical feminism turned women's attention to sexuality and to the disparities of power that pervade heterosexual relationships in patriarchal cultures. According to radical feminists, male heterosexuality objectifies the female body and makes the domination and degradation of women a source of erotic stimulation. Such assertions were the basis of Catharine MacKinnon's and Andrea Dworkin's campaigns in the 1980s and '90s against sexual harassment and pornography. Likewise, those assertions provided the basis of Marilyn Frye's endorsement of separatist feminist practices. Liberal, socialist, and radical feminism continue to challenge standard philosophical assumptions about the scope of politics and the nature of justice. Yet, arguably, each of them rests on a flawed conception of gender. As Elizabeth V. Spelman, Mara Lugones, and Judith Butler claimed, none adequately takes into account the ways in which gender is influenced by and interacts with sexual orientation, race, ethnicity, class, age, and ability, and none explicitly addresses how those factors affect the needs of diverse groups of women. Moreover, as Uma Narayan argued, none comes to grips with the complexities of advancing women's rights internationally or with the obstacles to coordinating feminist agendas in a globalized economy. Much current work in feminist social and political philosophyspecifically in black feminist theory, queer theory, and feminist human rights theorytakes on these urgent problems. Yet, despite advances in these fields, controversy persists between Luce Irigaray's view that gender is an ontological reality and Judith Butler's contention that it is an ontological illusion.
Feminist ethics
Whereas feminist social and political philosophy arose from consciousness-raising groups, feminist ethics was initially developed by women who were or had been full-time homemakers or mothers and who felt excluded (and in some cases offended) by the women's movement's emphasis on dismantling barriers to professional careers for women. These women's moral worlds were less concerned with rights and justice and instead revolved around caregiving and maintaining networks of relationships. Inspired by Carol Gilligan's work on care ethics, early projects in feminist ethics shifted the focus of ethics from relations between citizens or strangers to close relationships rooted in emotional attachments, including friends, lovers, and mothers and children. In those intimate relationships, the parties respond to each other as unique individuals, not merely as typical human beings. Although they are vulnerable to each other in many of the same ways that strangers are, they are far more vulnerable to insensitivity, indifference, unkindness, and the threat of abandonment. Moreover, personal relationships are not always reciprocal. Because one of the individuals may be temporarily or chronically dependent on the other for sustenance, the other may shoulder a greater share of the burdens of the relationship. In those contexts, then, moral reciprocity is not reducible to equal respect or equal contribution. The focus on interpersonal morality showed that general moral rules, which some traditional ethical theories strove to develop, were rather crude instruments for conducting a moral life. Consequently, feminist ethical philosophersnotably Sara Ruddick, Virginia Held, and Annette Baiersought to explicate virtues and values suitable to everyday sociability. They questioned the tenability of basing moral relations on an implied social contractin which individuals promise to behave morally toward others on the condition they behave morally toward them and they demonstrated the critical role of trust in establishing an environment conducive to moral interaction. Although they did not repudiate the rational calculation of consequences in evaluating actions, they saw empathy and emotional responsiveness as vital to moral judgment. That general approach came to be known as the ethics of care. Because the demands of caregiving often prevented women from pursuing other projects and goals, striking a proper balance between caring for others and caring for oneself became a key problem for feminist ethics. In work since the 1990se.g., by Margaret Walkerthe concerns addressed by the ethics of care have been reframed in sophisticated accounts of the social processes through which individuals consolidate their moral identities, enter into and sustain relationships, and negotiate responsibilities.
settings that were in some respects inimical to their interests. A prime motivation for all feminist scholarship was the knowledge that institutions and practices throughout human history have subordinated womenalbeit in different ways and to different degrees at different times and in different places. Because children assimilate cultural norms and form interpersonal bonds long before they are able to assess the desirability of these life-shaping influences, it is to be expected that many women will be predisposed to accept a subordinate social position. Thus, when opponents of feminist principles and initiatives pointed out that most women willingly comply with prevailing feminine norms, feminist philosophers replied that women might well choose to live differently were it not for the omnipresence of traditional heterosexual role models and media representations, not to mention the disadvantages of nonconformity. The problem of women's agency was thus inextricable from the theme of voice. What was at issue was how to discern when women are speaking in their own voices and doing what they really want to do. There was considerable consensus among feminist philosophers regarding the criteria that a feminist theory of agency must satisfy, but there was also heated controversy about which theory best meets those criteria. At a minimum, a feminist theory of agency must explain how it is possible for women in male-dominated societies to live in ways that reflect their genuine needs and concerns, and it must explain how it is possible for women to develop critiques of sexist social and political institutions and to mount active resistance. Moreover, it must accomplish both of those tasks without pretending that people are capable of stepping outside their own socially determined viewpoints to attain a God-like perspective. Building on the consciousness-raising model of the 1970s, Nancy Hartsock held that women discover their own values and gain authentic agency only through acts of solidarity with feminist protesters and dissenters. Sandra Bartky pointed to the usefulness of discovering contradictions within the gender norms imposed upon womene.g., women are supposed to dedicate themselves to being beautiful and attractive to men but then are derided for being narcissistic. Such conflicts, they held, provide a basis for questioning prevailing notions of the proper role of women in society and the home. Another approach invoked narration to account for agency. Hilde Lindemann urged that individuals articulate their sense of themselves by telling stories. Since the narrative form opens up the possibility of reinterpreting past events as well as of devising different continuations of a story in progress, it enables women to mobilize creative powers and thereby to reshape their lives. For example, by identifying some customary behaviours in the workplace as sexual harassment, women workers validated the anger and humiliation they felt, which in turn enabled them to envisage ways of combating those discriminatory practices. Finally, an approach to agency that complemented those views focused on the epistemological question of how individuals can distinguish desires, values, and the like that are truly their own from those that they have merely absorbed from their social environments. The proposed solution was that agency requires a well-developed repertoire of skills in self-discovery, selfdefinition, and self-direction. By using those skills, individuals may identify beliefs, desires, projects, and so forth that promote their own flourishing as well as that of others and disavow beliefs, desires, and projects that they deem unfair and detrimental.